Discover millions of ebooks, audiobooks, and so much more with a free trial

From $11.99/month after trial. Cancel anytime.

Inconsistencies
Inconsistencies
Inconsistencies
Ebook204 pages1 hour

Inconsistencies

Rating: 0 out of 5 stars

()

Read preview

About this ebook

Meditations, aphorisms, maxims, notes, and comments construct a philosophy of thought congruent with the inconsistency of our reality.

Those who continue to think never return to their point of departure.
Inconsistencies

These 130 short texts—aphoristic, interlacing, and sometimes perplexing—target a perennial philosophical problem: Our consciousness and our experience of reality are inconsistent, fragmentary, and unstable; God is dead, and our identity as subjects discordant. How can we establish a new mode of thought that does not cling to new gods or the false security of rationality? Marcus Steinweg, as he did in his earlier book The Terror of Evidence, constructs a philosophical position from fragments, maxims, meditations, and notes, formulating a philosophy of thought that expresses and enacts the inconsistency of our reality.

Steinweg considers, among other topics, life as a game (“To think is to play because no thought is firmly grounded”); sexuality (“wasteful, contradictory, and contingent”); desire (”Desire has a thousand names; It's earned none of them”); reality (“overdetermined and excessively complex”); and world (“a nonconcept”). He disposes of philosophy in one sentence (“Philosophy is a continual process of its own redefinition.”) but spends multiple pages on “A Tear in Immanence,” invoking Nietzsche, Heidegger, Sartre, and others. He describes “Wandering with Foucault” (“Thought entails wandering as well as straying into madness”) and brings together Derrida and Debord. He poses a question: “Why should a cat be more mysterious than a dog?” and later answers one: “Beauty is truth because truth is beauty.” By the end, we have accompanied Steinweg on converging trains of thought. “Thinking means continuing to think,” he writes, adding “But thinking can only pose questions by answering others.” The question of inconsistency? Asked and answered, and asked.

LanguageEnglish
PublisherThe MIT Press
Release dateOct 13, 2017
ISBN9780262343558
Inconsistencies

Related to Inconsistencies

Titles in the series (18)

View More

Related ebooks

Philosophy For You

View More

Related articles

Related categories

Reviews for Inconsistencies

Rating: 0 out of 5 stars
0 ratings

0 ratings0 reviews

What did you think?

Tap to rate

Review must be at least 10 words

    Book preview

    Inconsistencies - Marcus Steinweg

    Untimely Meditations

    1. The Agony of Eros

    Byung-Chul Han

    2. On Hitler’s Mein Kampf: The Poetics of National Socialism

    Albrecht Koschorke

    3. In the Swarm: Digital Prospects

    Byung-Chul Han

    4. The Terror of Evidence

    Marcus Steinweg

    5. All and Nothing: A Digital Apocalypse

    Martin Burckhardt and Dirk Höfer

    6. Positive Nihilism: My Confrontation with Heidegger

    Hartmut Lange

    7. Inconsistencies

    Marcus Steinweg

    8. Shanzhai: Deconstruction in Chinese

    Byung-Chul Han

    Inconsistencies

    Marcus Steinweg

    translated by Amanda DeMarco

    The MIT Press

    Cambridge, Massachusetts

    London, England

    © 2017 Massachusetts Institute of Technology

    Originally published as Inkonsistenzen in the series Fröhliche Wissenschaft by Matthes & Seitz Berlin: © Matthes & Seitz Berlin Verlagsgesellschaft mbH, Berlin 2015. All rights reserved.

    All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced in any form by any electronic or mechanical means (including photocopying, recording, or information storage and retrieval) without permission in writing from the publisher.

    This book was set in PF Din Text Pro by Toppan Best-set Premedia Limited. Printed and bound in the United States of America.

    Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data

    Names: Steinweg, Marcus, 1971- author. | DeMarco, Amanda, translator.

    Title: Inconsistencies / Marcus Steinweg ; translated by Amanda DeMarco.

    Other titles: Inkonsistenzen. English

    Description: Cambridge, MA : The MIT Press, 2017. | Series: Untimely meditations | Includes bibliographical references.

    Identifiers: LCCN 2017009920 | ISBN 9780262534352 (pbk. : alk. paper)

    eISBN 9780262343534

    Subjects: LCSH: Inconsistency (Logic) | Philosophy, German--21st century.

    Classification: LCC BC199.I45 S7413 2017 | DDC 193--dc23 LC record available at https://lccn.loc.gov/2017009920

    ePub Version 1.0

    d_r0

    Le plus beau serait de penser dans une forme qu’on aurait inventée.

    —Paul Valéry

    Table of Contents

    Series page

    Title page

    Copyright page

    Epigraph

    Acrobatics

    Game

    Arché

    Self-Transcendence

    Sexuality

    Samurai

    Violence

    Reality

    Tiger

    Distance

    Stage

    Vector

    Integrity

    Hegel

    Philosophy

    Contemporary Art

    Sensitivity

    Strength

    A Tear in Immanence

    Hand

    World

    Self-Objectification

    Drift

    Duras

    Excess

    Element

    Floating Architecture

    Wandering with Foucault

    Toxic Concepts

    Crazy?

    Leap

    Critical?

    Derrida with Debord

    Stupidity

    Self-Implication

    Fragmentary

    Parrot

    Fantasy of Consistency

    Subject

    Body Intelligence

    For Instead of Against

    Vision

    Love

    Extreme

    Incommensurability

    Assertion

    Harmlessness

    The Texture of Facts

    Culture

    Cat

    Beauty

    Cliché

    Finance Romanticism

    Dream

    A View from Space

    Evidence

    Tumbling

    Meaning

    Truth

    Virginity Fantasy

    Break

    Contingency

    Fact Esotericism

    Beginning

    Politics

    Sex

    Exile

    Hiatus

    A Question of Perspective?

    Subobject

    Arrow

    Artwork

    Journey

    Suspension

    Deconcentration

    Badiou with Derrida

    Desubjectification

    Decision

    Eros

    Hurrah-Negativism

    Transgression

    Antigone

    The Obscuring of Evidence

    Suicide

    Infinitesimal

    Ontological Poverty

    Equality

    Sun

    Rift

    Definition

    There Is No Right-Leaning Thought

    Celan

    Outside

    Consensus

    Hyperbole

    Reality

    Diaphora

    Active Nonthought

    Blindness

    Why?

    Moral

    Ethics

    Vanitas

    Definition of Art

    Naive Thought?

    Sex with Hegel

    Breathing Freely

    Spinoza

    Ghost

    Writing

    Gentle

    Panther

    Background

    Reason

    Nihilism

    Emotion

    Critical

    Self-Loss

    Hegel with Kierkegaard

    Glue

    Creatio Ex Nihilo

    Naturally?

    Consistency

    Ideology

    Immanence Idiots

    Desire

    Contemporaries

    Ground

    Nothingness

    Definition of Art

    Abstraction

    Heterology

    Gadamer and Derrida with Hegel

    Continuing to Think

    Desert

    Doing Nothing

    ACROBATICS

    The acrobatics of thought includes leaps and somersaults. You could say that it allows the subject to leave the ground of reflection. But doesn’t this very term imply a motion that drags reason behind it, threatening to rupture it? Reflection has nothing to do with taking secure steps on stable ground. The conditions of reflection guarantee that thought cannot be guaranteed. The subject’s only guarantee is that it borders on an abyss, which it cannot bridge. And yet it itself is a sort of bridge—one that reaches into the unknown.

    GAME

    If it’s true as Georges Bataille claims, that for Friedrich Nietzsche life was in essence a game, then what kind of game is it? Bataille is right to associate it with war insofar as war itself is a game or exercise, before it becomes brutal, violent politics.¹ Gilles Deleuze would say that Nietzsche mounted a war machine that caused the collapse of established values and certainties. The subject qua subject is martial in the sense that it mounts a resistance to the zeitgeist’s muster and commands in order to commit itself to a contingent future. Openness to contingency can only be playful, as it is openness to the world as a game that knows no determination. Heraclitus, Nietzsche, Martin Heidegger, Eugen Fink, Kostas Axelos, and Deleuze developed the category of the world game into a model in which the cosmos is a game with inconsistent rules. To think is to play because no thought is firmly grounded.² The fathomlessness of thought perforates the subject by inscribing an irreducible contingency within it. It sets it on the path of coincidence, which it attempts to answer with provisional consistency. Each of these attempts at consistency is indebted to engagements with ontological-mathematical inconsistency, which as Daniel Heller-Roazen writes, the Pythagoreans defined as unspeakable (arrhetoi), irrational (alogoi), or incommensurable (asummetroi).³ When confronted with its own fathomlessness, logos becomes playful. You could say that it emancipates itself from myth by integrating myth’s ludic qualities into itself. The logification of myth cannot be logified. It arises from a game that it simultaneously opposes. Nietzsche is just one example of this conflict. He stands at the beginning of logos-metaphysics’ impossible end. His undertaking consists in showing metaphysics its own inconsistency by playing with it. Perhaps, said Bataille, he didn’t completely abstain from philosophy, but he definitely passed over the opportunity to become a philosopher, preferring to devote himself to writing, which allowed him to constantly play with what he wrote.⁴ But it is a game that demands the utmost concentration from its player. The game of thought demands such force and such rigor that in comparison the force and the rigor demanded by construction can give the impression of laxity. The free-floating acrobat is subject to stricter rules than a mason standing on solid ground.⁵ Nietzsche’s game with logos, metaphysics, and their conceptual culture reflects the game of a world without ultimate meaning: He protests against the fact that we assign a purpose to things and to the world. For him, the world has no purpose, and we have no choice but to laugh at that which is.⁶ To laugh at the world as a game that pulls the ground out from under the subject, leaving it to float over the abyss of ontological inconsistency, is to play a game whose meaning remains suspended. A person who is playing the game always finds the power to overcome those horrors that the game entails.⁷ This is ultimately what Nietzsche calls life, actively participating in a game whose meaning proves to be the impossibility of meaning.

    ARCHÉ

    By translating the ancient Greek word αρχή with the words origin and command, Giorgio Agamben makes the claim that there is no αρχή for command—that is, logos ex nihilo—because the command itself is αρχή—or at least because it takes the place of the origin.⁸ In this, Agamben approaches the ontological axiomatics of two philosophers whose thought culminates in the repudiation of a positively formulated origin (αρχή): Ludwig Wittgenstein and Jacques Derrida. In his notes titled On Certainty, Wittgenstein states, It is so difficult to find the beginning. Or, better: it is difficult to begin at the beginning. And not try to go further back.⁹ What Wittgenstein calls the beginning is logos (language or meaning), which assumes the position of the origin. To begin at the beginning doesn’t mean going back to the absolute origin. Wittgenstein’s late thoughts revolve around the absent origin—the missing αρχή—in whose stead a sort of assertion arises that is the architecture of logos, and that Wittgenstein describes as a language game or form of life.¹⁰ It is a construction perched over the abyss of ontological inconsistency. It generates the milieu of consistency that we call reality. But that means that reality is a groundless ground, an entity that itself is not grounded. Its grounding—the level of logos; the system of organization and reference that we call reality—remains groundless. The origin is without origin. This is why Derrida spoke of a prosthesis of origin, which must be believed all the same, whether believable or not.¹¹ Here he approaches the slogan from Wittgenstein’s late work: What I know, I believe.¹² In another proposition, Wittgenstein says, The difficulty is to realize the groundlessness of our believing.¹³ Can it be said that the thought of Wittgenstein, Derrida, and Agamben all share a structural homology in which the origin, the αρχή, appears as an element that cannot be made logical?

    But that would mean that a certain floating and lightness is proper to thought. It indicates a logos that totters with precision. Would that be the logos of art and philosophy?

    SELF-TRANSCENDENCE

    Philosophy entails opening to the dimension of the exterior, which Jacques Lacan labeled the real. One could—along with Nietzsche as well as Deleuze and Félix Guattari—also speak of chaos. In any case, it’s the experience of a resistance that cannot be internalized, and that drives thought to its limits.¹⁴ The experience of the limit implies that the thinking subject hazards self-transcendence. If there is a subject, then it is a subject of originary self-transcendence that knows itself to be affected by forces that traverse and codify its body of knowledge. In the act of thought, the subject identifies itself

    Enjoying the preview?
    Page 1 of 1
    pFad - Phonifier reborn

    Pfad - The Proxy pFad of © 2024 Garber Painting. All rights reserved.

    Note: This service is not intended for secure transactions such as banking, social media, email, or purchasing. Use at your own risk. We assume no liability whatsoever for broken pages.


    Alternative Proxies:

    Alternative Proxy

    pFad Proxy

    pFad v3 Proxy

    pFad v4 Proxy