The Epistemology of Metaphor - Paul de Man
The Epistemology of Metaphor - Paul de Man
The Epistemology of Metaphor - Paul de Man
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless
you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you
may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.
Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at .
http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=ucpress. .
Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed
page of such transmission.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
The University of Chicago Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Critical
Inquiry.
http://www.jstor.org
The Epistemology of Metaphor
Paul de Man
13
14 Paul de Man The Epistemologyof Metaphor
But when, having passed over the original and composition of our
ideas, I began to examine the extent and certainty of our knowledge,
I found it had so near a connexion with words that, unless their
force and manner of signification were first well observed, there
could be very little said clearly and pertinently concerning knowl-
edge, which, being conversant about truth, had constantly to do
with propositions. And though it terminated in things, yet it was,
for the most part, so much by the intervention of words that they
seemed scarce separable from our general knowledge. At least they
interpose themselves so much between our understandings and the
truth which it would contemplate and apprehend that, like the
medium through which visible objects pass, their obscurity and dis-
order does not seldom cast a mist before our eyes and impose
upon our understandings. [Bk. 3, chap. 9, pp. 87-88]
Since wit and fancy finds easier entertainment in the world than
dry truth and real knowledge, figurative speeches and allusions in
language will hardly be admitted as an imperfection or abuse of it. I
confess, in discourses where we seek rather pleasure and delight
than information and improvement, such ornaments as are bor-
rowed from them can scarce pass for faults. But yet, if we would
speak of things as they are, we must allow that all the art of
rhetoric, besides order and clearness, all the artificial and figurative
application of words eloquence hath invented, are for nothing else
but to insinuate wrong ideas, move the passions, and thereby mis-
lead the judgment, and so indeed are perfect cheat; and therefore
however laudable or allowable oratory may render them in ha-
rangues and popular addresses, they are certainly, in all discourses
that pretend to inform or instruct, wholly to be avoided and,
where truth and knowledge are concerned, cannot but be thought
a great fault either of the language or person that makes use of
them. What and how various they are will be superfluous here to
take notice, the books of rhetoric which abound in the world will
instruct those who want to be informed; only I cannot but observe
how little the preservation and improvement of truth and knowl-
edge is the care and concern of mankind, since the arts of fallacy
are endowed and preferred. It is evident how much men love to
deceive and be deceived, since rhetoric, that powerful instrument
of error and deceit, has its established professors, is publicly
taught, and has always been had in great reputation; and I doubt
not but it will be thought great boldness, if not brutality, in me to
have said thus much against it. Eloquence, like the fair sex, has too
prevailing beauties in it to suffer itself ever to be spoken against.
And it is in vain to find fault with those arts of deceiving wherein
men find pleasure to be deceived. [Bk. 3, chap. 10, pp. 105-6]
epistemological problems since the nominal and the real essence of the
species designated by the word coincide; since the idea is simple and
undivided, there can in principle be no room for play or ambivalence
between the word and the entity, or between property and essence. Yet
this lack of differential play immediately leads to a far-reaching conse-
quence: "The names of simple ideas are not capable of any definitions
." (bk. 3, chap. 4, p. 26). Indeed not, since definition involves distinc-
tion and is therefore no longer simple. Simple ideas are, therefore, in
Locke's system, simpleminded; they are not the objects of understand-
ing. The implication is clear but comes as something of a shock, for what
would be more important to understand than single ideas, the cor-
nerstones of our experience?
In fact, we discourse a great deal about simple ideas. Locke's first
example is the term "motion," and he is well aware of the extent to which
metaphysical speculation, in the scholastic as well as in the more strictly
Cartesian tradition, centers on the problem of the definition of motion.
But nothing in this abundant literature could be elevated to the level of a
definition that would answer the question: What is motion? "Nor have
the modern philosophers, who have endeavored to throw off the jargon
of the Schools and speak intelligibly, much better succeeded in defining
simple ideas, whether by explaining their causes or any otherwise. The
atomists,who define motion to be a passagefrom one place to another, what
do they more than put one synonymous word for another? For what is
passage other than motion?And if they were asked what passage was, how
would they better define it than by motion?For is it not at least as proper
and significant to say passage is a motionfrom one place to another as to say
motion is a passage, etc. This is to translate and not to define .. ." (bk. 3,
chap. 4, p. 28). Locke's own "passage" is bound to continue this per-
petual motion that never moves beyond tautology: motion is a passage
and passage is a translation; translation, once again, means motion, piles
motion upon motion. It is no mere play of words that "translate" is
translated in German as "iibersetzen"which itself translates the Greek
"metaphorein" or metaphor. Metaphor gives itself the totality which it
then claims to define, but it is in fact the tautology of its own position.
The discourse of simple ideas is figural discourse or translation and, as
such, creates the fallacious illusion of definition.
Locke's second example of a word for a simple idea is "light." He
takes pains to explain that the word "light" does not refer to the percep-
tion of light and that to understand the causal process by which light is
produced and perceived is not at all the same as to understand light. In
fact, to understand light is to be able to make this very distinction be-
tween the actual cause and the idea (or experience) of a perception,
between aperception and perception. When we can do this, says Locke,
then the idea is that which is properlylight, and we come as close as we can
come to the proper meaning of "light." To understand light as idea is to
18 Paul de Man The Epistemologyof Metaphor
understand light properly. But the word "idea" (eide), of course, itself
means light, and to say that to understand light is to perceive the idea of
light is to say that understanding is to see the light of light and is there-
fore itself light. The sentence: to understand the idea of light would then
have to be translated as to light the light of light (das Licht des Lichtes
lichten), and if this begins to sound like Heidegger's translations from the
Pre-Socratics, it is not by chance. Etymons have a tendency to turn into
the repetitive stutter of tautology. Just as the word "passage" translates
but fails to define motion, "idea" translates but does not define light and,
what is worse, "understand" translates but does not define understand-
ing. The first idea, the simple idea, is that of light in motion or figure,
but the figure is not a simple idea but a delusion of light, of understand-
ing, or of definition. This complication of the simple will run through
the entire argument which is itself the motion of this complication (of
motion).
Things indeed get more complex as one moves from simple ideas to
substances. They can be considered in two perspectives: either as a col-
lection of properties or as an essence which supports these properties as
their ground. The example for the first model of a substance is "gold,"
not unrelated, in some of its properties, to the solar light in motion. The
structure of substances considered as a collection of properties upsets
the convergence of nominal and real essences that made the utterer of
simple ideas into something of a stuttering idiot but, at least from an
epistemological point of view, a happy one. For one thing, properties are
not just the idea of motion, they actually move and travel. One will find
gold in the most unexpected places, for instance in the tail of peacock. "I
think all agree to make [gold] stand for a body of a certain yellow shining
colour; which being the idea to which children have annexed that name,
the shining yellow part of a peacock's tail is properly to them gold" (bk.
3, chap. 9, p. 85). The closer the description comes to that of metaphor,
the more dependent Locke becomes on the use of the word "properly."
Like the blind man who cannot understand the idea of light, the child
who cannot tell the figural from the proper keeps recurring throughout
eighteenth-century epistemology as barely disguised figures of our uni-
versal predicament. For not only are tropes, as their name implies,
always on the move-more like quicksilver than like flowers or butterflies
which one can at least hope to pin down and insert in a neat
taxonomy-but they can disappear altogether, or at least appear to dis-
appear. Gold not only has a color and a texture, but it is also soluble.
"For by what right is it that fusibility comes to be a part of the essence
signified by the word gold, and solubility but a property of it? . . . That
which I mean in this: that these being all but properties, depending on its
real constitution, and nothing but powers either active or passive in
reference to other bodies, no one has authority to determine the sig-
nification of the word gold (as referred to such a body existing in nature)
Critical Inquiry Autumn 1978 19
move from the mere contiguity between words and things in the case of
simple ideas to the metaphorical correspondence of properties and
essences in substances, the ethical tension has considerably increased.
Only this tension could account for the curious choice of examples
selected by Locke when he moves on to the uses and possible abuses of
language in mixed modes. His main examples are manslaughter, incest,
parricide, and adultery-when any nonreferential entity such as mer-
maid or unicorn would have done just as well.5 The full list of
examples-"motion," "light," "gold," "man," "manslaughter," "par-
ricide," "adultery," "incest"-sounds more like a Greek tragedy than the
enlightened moderation one tends to associate with the author of On
Government.Once the reflection on the figurality of language is started,
there is no telling where it may lead. Yet there is no way not to raise the
question if there is to be any understanding. The use and the abuse of
language cannot be separated from each other.
"Abuse" of language is, of course, itself the name of a trope: cata-
chresis. This is indeed how Locke describes mixed modes. They are
capable of inventing the most fantastic entities by dint of the positional
power inherent in language. They can dismember the texture of reality
and reassemble it in the most capricious of ways, pairing man with
woman or human being with beast in the most unnatural shapes. Some-
thing monstrous lurks in the most innocent of catachreses: when one
speaks of the legs of the table or the face of the mountain, catachresis is
already turning into prosopopeia, and one begins to perceive a world of
potential ghosts and monsters. By elaborating his theory of language as a
motion from simple ideas to mixed modes, Locke has deployed the
entire fan-shape or (to remain within light imagery) the entire spectrum
or rainbow of tropological totalization, the anamorphosis of tropes
which has to run its full course whenever one engages, however re-
luctantly or tentatively, the question of language as figure. In Locke, it
began in the arbitrary, metonymic contiguity of word-sounds to their
meanings, in which the word is a mere token in the service of the natural
entity, and it concludes with the catachresis of mixed modes in which the
word can be said to produce of and by itself the entity it signifies and that
has no equivalence in nature. Locke condemns catachresis severely: "he
that hath ideas of substances disagreeing with the real existence of things,
so far wants the materials of true knowledge in his understanding, and
hath instead thereof chimeras..... He that thinks the name centaur stands
for some real being, imposes on himself and mistakes words for things"
(bk. 3, chap. 10, p. 104). But the condemnation, by Locke's own argu-
5. In the general treatment of mixed modes, Locke lists "adultery" and "incest" (p.
34). In the subsequent discussion of the abuses of language, he returns to the problem of
mixed modes and gives as examples manslaughter, murder, and parricide, as well as the
legal term often associated with manslaughter, "chance medley." Mermaids and unicorns
are mentioned in another context in bk. 3, chap. 3, p. 25.
22 Paul de Man The Epistemologyof Metaphor
ment, now takes all language for its target, for at no point in the course
of the demonstration can the empirical entity be sheltered from
tropological defiguration. The ensuing situation is intolerable and makes
the soothing conclusion of book 3, entitled "Of the Remedies of the Fore-
going Imperfections and Abuses [of Language]," into one of the least
convincing sections of the Essay. One turns to the tradition engendered by
Locke's work in the hope of finding some assistance out of the predica-
ment.
6. Condillac, Essai sur l'origine des connaissanceshumaines (1746), ed. Charles Porset
(Paris, 1973), bk. 1, sec. 2, p. 194. All further references will be from bk. 1, chap. 5 and will
appear in the text; here and elsewhere, my translation.
Critical Inquiry Autumn 1978 23
reflect
on nothing .. " To reflect is an analytical act that distinguishes
differences and articulates reality; these articulations are called abstrac-
tions, and they would have to include any conceivable act of denomina-
tion or predication. This is also the point at which an act of ontological
legerdemain enters the system: the subject (or mind) depends on some-
thing which is not itself, here called "modifications" ("certain sensations
of light, color, etc., or certain operations of the soul .. ."), in order to be
at all, but these modifications are themselves as devoid of being as the
mind--cut off from its differentiating action, they are nothing. As the
other of the mind, they are devoid of being, but by recognizing them as
similar to itself in this negative attribute, the mind sees them, as in a
specular reflection, as being both itself and not itself at the same time.
The mind "is"to the extent that it "is like" its other in its inability to be.
The attribute of being is dependent on the assertion of a similarity which
is illusory, since it operates at a stage that precedes the constitution of
entities. "How will these experiences, taken abstractly, or separately,
from the entity [the mind] to which they belong and to which they
correspond only to the extent that they are locked up in it, how will these
experiences become the object of the mind? Because the mind persists in
considering them as if they were entities in themselves. The mind
....
contradicts itself. On the one hand, it considers these experiences with-
out any relation to its own being, and then they are nothing at all; on the
other hand, because nothingness cannot be comprehended, it considers
them as if they were something, and persists in giving them the same
reality with which it at first perceived them, although this reality can no
longer correspond to them." Being and identity are the result of a re-
semblance which is not in things but posited by an act of the mind which,
as such, can only be verbal. And since to be verbal, in this context, means
to allow substitutions based on illusory resemblances (the determining
illusion being that of a shared negativity) then mind, or subject, is the
central metaphor, the metaphor of metaphors. The power of the tropes,
which Locke sensed in a diffuse way, is here condensed in the key
metaphor of the subject as mind. What was a general and implicit theory
of tropes in Locke becomes in Condillac a more specific theory of
metaphor. Locke's third personal narrative about things in the world be-
comes here the autobiographical discourse of the subject. Different as
the two narratives may be, they are still the allegory of the same
tropological aporia. It now also becomes more directly threatening since
we, as subjects, are explicitly inscribed within the narrative. One feels
more than ever compelled to turn elsewhere for assistance and, staying
in the same philosophical tradition, Kant would seem to be the obvious
place.
*c *c *
26 Paul de Man The Epistemologyof Metaphor
Kant rarely discusses the question of tropes and rhetoric directly but
comes closest in a passage from the Critiqueof Judgment that deals with
the distinction between schemata and symbolic language. He starts out
from the term "hypotyposis" which, used, as he does, in a very inclusive
way, designates what, after Peirce, one might call the iconic element in a
representation. Hypotyposis makes present to the senses something
which is not within their reach, not just because it does not happen to be
there but because it consists, in whole or in part, of elements too abstract
for sensory representation. The figure most closely akin to hypotyposis is
that of prosopopeia; in its most restricted sense, prosopopeia makes
accessible to the senses, in this case the ear, a voice which is out of earshot
because it is no longer alive. In its most inclusive and also its etymological
sense, it designates the very process of figuration as giving face to what is
devoid of it.
In section 59 of the Critique of Judgment ("Of the Beautiful as a
Symbol of Public Morality"), Kant is primarily concerned with the dis-
tinction between schematic and symbolic hypotyposes. He begins by ob-
jecting to the improper use of the term "symbolic" for what we still call
today symboliclogic. Mathematical symbols used in algorithms are in fact
semiotic indices. They should not be called symbols because "they con-
tain nothing that belongs to the representation [Anschauung]of the ob-
ject." There is no relationship whatever between their iconic properties
and those of the object, if it has any. Things are different in the case of a
genuine hypotyposis. A relationship exists but it can differ in kind. In
the case of schemata, which are objects of the mind (Verstand),the corre-
sponding aperception is a priori, as would be the case, presumably, for a
triangle or any other geometrical shape. In the case of symbols, which
are objects of reason (Vernunft) comparable to Condillac's abstractions,
no sensory representation would be appropriate ("angemessen,"i.e., shar-
ing a common ratio), but such a similarity is "understood" to exist by
analogy ("unterlegt,"which could be translated by saying that an "under-
lying" similarity is created between the symbol and the thing sym-
bolized). Kant then illustrates at some length the distinction between an
actual and an analogical resemblance. In an analogy, the sensory prop-
erties of the analogon are not the same as those of the original, but they
function according to a similar formal principle. For example, an en-
lightened state will be symbolized by an organic body in which part and
whole relate in a free and harmonious way, whereas a tyranny will be
properly symbolized by a machine such as a treadmill. Everyone under-
stands that the state is not a body or a machine but that it functions like
one, and that this function is conveyed more economically by the symbol
than by lengthy abstract explanations. We seem at last to have come
closer to controlling the tropes. This has become possible because there
seem to be, for Kant, tropes that are epistemologically reliable. The
denominative noun "triangle," in geometry, is a trope, a hypotyposis
Critical Inquiry Autumn 1978 27
As Kant just taught us, when things run the risk of becoming too
difficult, it is better to postpone the far-reaching consequences of an ob-
servation for a later occasion. My main point stresses the futility of
trying to repress the rhetorical structure of texts in the name of un-
critically preconceived text models such as transcendental teleologies or,
at the other end of the spectrum, mere codes. The existence of literary
codes is not in question, only their claim to represent a general and
exhaustive textual model. Literary codes are subcodes of a system,
rhetoric, that is not itself a code. For rhetoric cannot be isolated from its
epistemological function however negative this function may be. It is
absurd to ask whether a code is true or false but impossible to bracket
this question when tropes are involved-and this always seems to be the
case. Whenever the question is repressed, tropological patterns reenter
the system in the guise of such formal categories as polarity, recurrence,
normative economy, or in such grammatical tropes as negation and
interrogation. They are always again totalizing systems that try to ignore
the disfiguring power of figuration. It does not take a good semiotician
long to discover that he is in fact a rhetorician in disguise.
The implications of these parallel arguments for literary history and
for literary aesthetics are equally controversial. An historian caught in
received models of periodization may find it absurd to read texts that
belong to the Enlightenment as if one were reading Nietzsche's Uber
Wahrheit und Liige im aussermoralischenSinn or Jacques Derrida's La
Mythologieblanche. But if we assume, just for the sake of argument, that
these same historians would concede that Locke, Condillac, and Kant
can be read as we have here read them, then they would have to con-
clude that our own literary modernity has reestablished contact with a
"true" Enlightenment that remained hidden from us by a nineteenth-
century Romantic and realist epistemology that asserted a reliable
rhetoric of the subject or of representation. A continuous line could then
be said to extend from Locke to Rousseau to Kant and to Nietzsche, a
line from which Fichte and Hegel, among others, would very definitely
be excluded. But are we so certain that we know how to read Fichte and
Hegel in the properly rhetorical manner? Since we assume that it is
possible to coordinate Locke and Nietzsche by claiming that their simi-
larly ambivalent attitudes toward rhetoric have been systematically over-
30 Paul de Man The Epistemologyof Metaphor