Conio 2015 Occupy A People Yet To Come
Conio 2015 Occupy A People Yet To Come
Conio 2015 Occupy A People Yet To Come
Conio
Occupy
A People Yet to Come
Edited by Andrew Conio
Occupy
Occupy
A People Yet to Come
Edited by Andrew Conio
London
2015
Open Humanities Press is an international, scholar-led open access publishing collective whose mission is to make leading works of contemporary critical thought freely available worldwide. More at
http://openhumanitiespress.org
Contents
Preface
Claire Colebrook
Introduction
23
Andrew Conio
67
88
97
Giuseppina Mecchia
John Protevi
Rodrigo Nunes
4. Resistance to Occupy
125
5. Preoccupations
158
172
191
203
Claire Colebrook
David Burrows
225
238
Bios
269
Eugene Holland
Andrew Conio
Acknowlegements
I would like to thank Claire Colebrook for her generous and steadfast support during the writing of this book; the contributors, Andrew Stapleton,
Sigi Jttkandt and my many friends at Occupy and the Economics
Working Group especially David, Tim, Clive, Mary, Ellena, Omar, Janos,
Peter, Mike, Obi, Schlack, Nick and Vica whose commitment to finding
ways to create a better world prompted the writing of this book.
Preface
I
At the time of this book going to press, amidst all the diverging political theories and commentaries regarding how the twenty-first century
might cope with the intertwined complexities of climate change, collapsing global finance, wars on terror that are also wars on freedom, potential
viral pandemics and increasing disaster scenarios (with increased vulnerability to disaster for the less fortunate) one thing seems clear enough:
end the occupation. The attacks by Israel on Gaza have not received
unanimous condemnation; there are still those, especially in the United
States, who for all the disproportionate suffering inflicted on those
trapped in Gaza still see Israel as having some right to defend itself, and
still maintain that conflict was instigated by Hamas and therefore not
subject to any critique outside the right of Israel to respond. Regardless
of the competing histories, narratives, conflicting allegiances and complexities, it nevertheless seems clear that ending the occupation would be
the best and quickest way to end widespread and ongoing violence.
Why does ending occupation, amidst all this complexity, appear to
be such a clear and just thing to do? There are two identities the State
of Israel and the Palestinians in Gaza both of whom can lay claim to
having suffered displacement and both of whom can seem to ask quite
legitimately for a territory of their own. In the ongoing demands for a stable and peaceful future, perhaps one would support a two-state solution,
10
Claire Colebrook
Preface
11
12
Claire Colebrook
Wall Street was the site for a people finance, banking and yes, this site
was overtaken and occupied by protestors. The logic was not, this is our
space and we have a right to this space because of who we are what we
represent and because we stand for humanity in general. On the contrary,
the occupation began and then certain motifs of proportion or statistics
were made quite explicit: to say we are the 99% is less a claim of identity,
property and right and more a claim of assembling. And if Wall Street
was based on a deterritorialized system of owning space because some
system other than occupation was at work (real estate, property, colonization of space), the Occupy movement was based on higher deterritorialization. Rather than right or ownership or taking back what was owed
to us, there was no us or we outside the event of occupation.
I would suggest that the same applies to Israel and Gaza: the Israeli
defense force is adopting majoritarian or molar occupation, appealing to
a narrative of nation, right, security, constituted peoples and property.
Tragically, those abandoned in Gaza, cannot appeal to any straightforward conception of nation but Gaza is where they are. All they have is
their occupation of space, a space that has then been occupied by a force
that does not simply counter-occupy but places the competing claims to
space as some grand narrative of security, nation, legitimacy and right. It
might seem quixotic, and violently so, to suggest that rather than respond
with a counter-narrative of right and nation one imagines a world of
occupation without right. Such a new earth would not set the occupation of a territory within a moral framework but would instead begin
with occupation the assembling across a space that generates a people,
and then enables certain narratives of rights to be formed ex post facto.
Such a call for a radically immanent politics might be navely wishful, but
here I would quote Isabelle Stengers and Philippe Pignarre who affirmed
the possibility that was articulated at the Seattle protests (prior to the
Occupy movements) that another world would be possible:
Becoming the child of an event: not being born again into
innocence, but daring to inhabit the possible as such, without the adult precautions that make threats of the type what
will people say?, who will they take us for? or and you think
that is enough? prevail. The event creates its own now to
which the question of a certain acting as if , which is proper
Preface
13
14
Claire Colebrook
Preface
15
16
Claire Colebrook
asking the question not of what this thing is for me, but what this thing or
being is as such.
It is in a moment of disorientation, or a certain loss of world, that
one might start to think not of a world that is always already human but
an earth (the forces from which the human world are composed). We
might say that what Deleuze and Guattari refer to elsewhere as the war
machine, or an agonistics that has not been captured by opposing sides
(such as political parties, nations, identified groups or communities), is
only possible when there is no actual war: in a state of war one holds on
to who one is, where one is, what one stands for and what one believes.
Doing so reduces the intensity of the war machine to stabilized terms and
oppositions; the war machine would be destructive of such a terrain. In
this respect Deleuze and Guattaris philosophy, like Heideggers, is not at
all easy because it abandons the negotiation of a field, abandons settlement among terms and instead aims for a higher deterritorialization: in
both cases one thinks the relation between world (constituted meaning) and earth (the plane that renders such constitution possible but
also fragile). Heidegger argued both that one can ask questions and begin
to think only because one has a world (a horizon of meaning, concern,
care, others, history and ownness) and that one becomes aware of the
having of a world when the world breaks down. Authenticity is therefore
not so much attachment to the projects and horizons that make us who
we are, but a sense that while all we do and think emerges from the lifeworld, what is truly worth thinking about is that there is a world, and that
it might not be. This does not mean that living authentically is liberation
from any identity, history, project or tradition, but that having a world or
tradition is something one takes on with a radical sense of decision. We
can only take up a free and decisive relation to a world that was not of our
own deciding, and nothing legitimates that world other than that world
itself. And here, of course, is where things start to become not at all easy
as a Heideggerian. One might not only say that there are certain material
and geopolitical conditions for adopting ones world freely and decisively,
and that for Heidegger these conditions were tied to a German National
Socialism that aimed to eradicate anything that appeared as too inert
or unthinking to embrace radical self-becoming. One might also point
out, as Jacques Derrida has done, that a certain notion of contemporary
Preface
17
18
Claire Colebrook
Preface
19
20
Claire Colebrook
for democracy or the debates and wars between and among identities
that are constituted in a capitalist milieu of geopolitical borders produced
by markets, trade agreements, and histories of appropriative nation states
tied to warring territories constituted by trade competition needs to be
displaced by a mode of thinking in which no-one has a prima facie right,
whatever the history, to occupy. What needs to be thought are less the
molar categories of the people, and the nation, and instead the micropolitical potentials that might open a new people and a new earth.
Rather than think of molar politics and minor politics as an opposition, it might be best to think of oppositional narratives versus narratives
devoid of scale. That is to say, one could start to approach the Israel
Gaza conflict through the history of anti-Semitism, the horrors of the
Holocaust and the desperate need for state security as a response to terror, or one could adopt a history of the Palestinian people and Hamas
and the insecurity of Muslim culture in a Middle Eastern zone increasingly tied towards alignment with the interests of the US, capital, energy
markets and other affiliations that have little to do with the survival of
the people who are supposedly represented by governments, parties and
brotherhoods. Molar politics focuses upon a history of nation and party
formation, and geopolitical border disputes; such competing narrations
enable debates over the proper nature of scale: should the IsraelGaza
conflict be framed by the specter of the Holocaust and anti-Semitism, or
by the other history of displacement of the Palestinian people? Deleuze
and Guattaris micro-politics is not opposed to the molar, but pulverizes
any such identity: any nation, party, people or brotherhood has as its condition of emergence thousands of years of a taming of the earth (including oil and other lines of capital), and no dispute over borders has a natural or proper scale. Rather than the banal claim that beneath religious,
political, tribal or ethnic conflicts we are all human which of course is
the violent imposition of a humanity of recognition and would demand
that we all become liberal and distanced from the affiliations that mark
out our territories Deleuze and Guattari see difference as multiplying rather than weakening in micro-political analysis. Neither the Israeli
defense forces nor Hamas can contain the proliferation of differences
and identities that both sides violently seek to represent. So rather than
a democratic politics that would negotiate one people versus another,
Preface
21
or that would reconcile the rights of people over territories, one might
think beyond persons, beyond the demos, beyond the polity. One might
start to consider how the earth not the world might generate a people to come, a people without right, ownership or propriety. Such a call
for a world in common without propriety, without identity and without
nations and that would be beyond the world by thinking the forces of the
earth would not be easy. It would risk, as so many people have objected
with regard to Deleuze and Guattaris work, a celebration of statelessness
and impersonal life precisely when the worlds most fragile people are
seeking a territory and state of their own. But we need to ask, today, both
when climate change and environmental collapse have been ignored as
viable political concerns because states are concerned with their own survival, and when as the Occupy movement demonstrated, states represent corporations rather then people whether the ideals of personhood
and nation are not more risky. Do not concepts of right and nation risk
generating higher degrees of catastrophe than a possible future where
there are not territories and peoples, but a new people and a new earth,
no longer bound by the macro-narratives of the world and polities.
The heightened Israeli violence against Gaza occurs just as the earth
not the world but the earth (or the geological strata from which philosophy and various forms of humanity formed itself) is poised at a singular
point or threshold that would render all human life in its current mode
untenable. Rather than extending capitalist democracy a democracy
that represents persons as private consumers with the right to self-determination perhaps a better path would be to intensify the forces from
which diverse peoples emerge, beyond states, markets, territories and
right. The assaults on Gaza and the use of the figure of Hamas to destroy
the lives of civilians is perhaps one of the more violent and flagrant events
that have allowed the borders of states, markets, nations and molar identities to reduce the complex differences of people who do not have a state
or a territory.
If it is not that easy being Heideggerian or Deleuzo-Guattarian, then
one might insist that such difficulties are minor very minor when
compared with the struggle to live in the occupied territories. Rather
than see the means of violence the state as a right that should be
extended, a minor politics would intensify forces that are irreducible to
22
Claire Colebrook
the state, disentangling Judaism in all its forms from Israel, and differentiating Islam from Hamas and the Muslim Brotherhood, and in turn
disentangling life and the earth from the striated space of East and West.
Works Cited
Deleuze, Gilles and Flix Guattari. 1994. What is Philosophy?. Trans. Hugh Tomlinson
and Graham Burchell. London: Verso.
Derrida, Jacques. 1994. Force de loi: Le Fondement mystique de lautorit (Paris:
Galile). English translation: Force of Law: The Mystical Foundation of
Authority. Trans. Mary Quaintance. Cardozo Law Review 11 (1990): 9191045.
Derrida, Jacques. 2005. The Politics of Friendship. Trans. George Collins. London:
Verso.
McClintock, Anne and Rob Nixon. 1986. No Names Apart: The Separation of Word
and History in Derridas Le Dernier Mot du Racisme. Critical Inquiry 13 (1):
140154.
Stengers, Isabelle and Philippe Pignarre. 2011. Capitalist Sorcery: Breaking the Spell.
Trans Andrew Goffey. London: Palgrave.
Introduction
Andrew Conio
24
Andrew Conio
be it phallogocentrism, colonialism, or sexism, controls the flow differently, hence there can be no crude economic determinism. As Conley2
observes, by:
advocating an ever-unfinished, non-dialectical, and nonhierarchical model of constructive dissent, [Deleuze and
Guattari] do away with the Marxian notion of class structure to consider social conflict in terms of mobile micro- and
macro-cosms, ever shifting lines, rhythms and harmonics.
Under neoliberalism, as it reaches ever further into the fabric of life,
capital determines far more than it ever did. The global economic and
political elite is commandeering the human genome and the building
blocks of life as well as the ontological and epistemological horizons of
thought. The central paradox is that while capitalism seeks to command
flows, capital itself is the strongest force of irrepressible desire to escape
all limits. As neoliberalism tightens its grip, Deleuze and Guattaris AntiOedipus (1972) takes on even greater prescience:
the prime function incumbent upon the socius has always
been to codify the flows of desire, to inscribe them, to record
them, to see that no flow exists that is not properly dammed
up, channeled, regulated. (Deleuze and Guattari 2000: 33)
Such insights support Colebrooks claim that Anti-Oedipus might be recognized as one of the twentieth centurys most important works.3
Release, capture, flow, systolic and diastolic rhythms, and the processes necessary to control these pulsations are to be found in all things,
in flows of women and children, flows of herds and seed, sperm flows,
flows of shit, menstrual flows (Deleuze and Guattari 2000: 112). The
paths of flows are always machinic: mouthbreast, sunphotosynthesis,
cameraluxlumen, and the production of subjectivity itself is a machinic
process. Production is primarily desiring production, far in excess of the
economic system: social life is machinic [and] may be conceived as a
global system of desire and destiny that organizes the production of production, the productions of recording, and productions of consumption
(Deleuze and Guattari 2000: 142). There are, however, two valences to all
things block or flow, production or anti-production. Anti-production is
not necessarily the opposite of creative production. In anti-production
Introduction
25
26
Andrew Conio
that Occupy and the political ontology of Deleuze and Guattari demand
of each other.
The combination of precision and subtlety to be found in Deleuze and
Guattaris concepts accounts for the worldwide multi-discursive interest
in their formulations. Recent politically-engaged Deleuzian scholarship,4
the financial crisis, and the emergence of widespread social conflict following the collapse of the self-certainties of the BlairBush era have made
their work seemingly indispensible in the struggle to transform capitalism. Whilst Deleuze and Guattari have many mediators and interpreters in political theory, most notably Michael Hardt and Antonio Negri,
readers are increasingly attracted by the force of Deleuze and Guattaris
own conceptual apparatus and the ways in which it reveals the immanent dynamics of capitalism in the the pure flow of deterritorialization,
of money and labor brought together in a conjunction of flows which is
actualized in private property (Holland), and the axiomatics that hold
this system in place. Also fundamental to their analysis is an understanding of economic production as part of a much larger field of desiring production that produces the subjectivities and social relations upon which
the economic system ultimately depends. Deleuze and Guattaris political concepts have the capacity to resolve many of the contradictions left
unaddressed by other accounts of the machinery of capitalism. For example, their presentation of the immiserating, sadistic, world-destroying
tendencies of capitalism is no barrier to their appreciation for capitalisms
dynamic potential and boundless creativity. Their formulation of capitalist axiomatics provides a way to understand how capitalist systems, supported by a war machine of stupendous proportions, have the appearance
of inviolable natural laws, and yet are constantly modified by capitalisms
own inherent dynamism, the pressure of the multitude, and outright
resistance. Deleuze and Guattari share with Marx the view that capitalism is the handmaiden of its own eventual demise. The construction of
the contemporary subject is such that it is both the measure of capitalisms capacity for freedom and its primary mode of capture. In sum: the
brilliance of Deleuze and Guattaris thought lies precisely in their ability
to capture the multi-dimensional nature of social and life forces in such a
way that (through the construction of a matrix of extremely sophisticated
concepts) bifurcations, contradictions, and dialectics do not become
Introduction
27
28
Andrew Conio
Introduction
29
condition), whereas for Deleuze it gives rise to sense (it is senses condition). Far from involving a multiplicitous dynamic interplay of cognitive,
semantic and affective forces of the type outlined by John Protevi in
this volume for Badiou the event moves on and produces the subject
who is also (again following Lacan) barred from her own subjective formation by the event itself.
Events are such an important feature of Deleuzes conceptual landscape because he is a philosopher of transformation. These transformations are changes in both matter and sense, both corporeal and incorporeal, so that when changes become infinitely extended and ongoing
processes they also become events. Buchanan clarifies that events are
not necessarily matters of scale:
the event for Deleuze and Guattari is not measured by a
change in the state of things a large crowd gathering in a
public square in Cairo or camping out in New York City is
not intrinsically an event in Deleuze and Guattaris thinking.
It only becomes recognizable as an event if it brings about a
transformation of thought itself, if it yields a new idea, a new
way of acting.
For example, when the genocide of the American first peoples is properly understood, then Americas whole sense of itself is undone. Most
importantly, for Deleuze, matter is evental; as Verena Conley puts it:
changes can occur autopoietically, unbeknownst to the subject, before
she or he even opens to the environing world. The inward rush of the
sea has a sense, a life-sense as Buchanan helpfully phrases it. We might
talk of crowds contracting, expectations growing, balance sheets expanding, blood levels rising, global digital signals pulsating across networks
around a Champions League football match. Organic or urban, in relation to the moon, the molluscs, the pier and the bather (Williams 2008:
8), sense is dispersed and flows in waves through and across bodies. The
sea and the moon provide a picturesque example, but the application of
the same concepts to the retreating, collapsing, rising, and dispersing of
flows in the stock market helps us to understand that markets are only
rational within the sublime irrationality of the capitalist economic system, that they are affairs of animal spirits which are most often wolverine
30
Andrew Conio
as they hunt in packs. It is a Deleuzian commonplace that there is no difference in nature between the economic infrastructure and the libidinal
economy: desire belongs to the infrastructure, not to ideology, desire
is in production as social production, just as production is in desire as
desiring-production (Deleuze and Guattari 2000: 348).
Many of the features of Deleuzes embodied/engaged (schizoanalytic) subject are marshalled in Mecchias third defence of Deleuzes work
(after her considerations of Badiou and Rancire) against the criticisms
of Peter Hallward, whom she contends recasts and radicalizes Badious
critique of Deleuzian politics. Here Deleuze is again accused of aloofness,
his vitalism is considered a major flaw, and his commitment to a particular theorization of the virtual is taken to have left his theory devoid
of agency or of any sense of a determinant material force that might act
upon the world. Stephven Shukaitis summarizes Hallwards argument:
this results in a politics that can only lead out of this world, because the
potential of the actualized world is always compromised in comparison to the virtual (Shukaitis 2010). Ambrose phrases a pithy riposte to
this contention:
It is never merely a question of attempting to break out of
the world that exists, but of creating the right conditions
for the exposition of other possible worlds, the heterocosmic to break in in order to introduce new variables
into the world that exists, causing the quality of its reality/
actuality to undergo modification, change and becoming.
(Ambrose 2006)
There are significant problems, in particular, with Hallwards understanding of the virtual. In The Logic of Sense (1969) Deleuze shows that the
incorporeal is as real as the corporal. It is not the case that the virtual is
some kind of unreality outside of the real; rather, the virtual is real, just
not actualized. As Buchanan says in his contribution to this volume: the
virtual is fully real, as real as an idea, an image, and an innovation, is real.
It is real because its effects are real. Think of the infinite variety of forms
the wheel has taken, from prayer wheel to clock to waterwheel and propeller. Deleuze and Guattari suggest that there is an infinite multiplicity of
potential in everything, only a minuscule portion of which is actualized
Introduction
31
32
Andrew Conio
Introduction
33
34
Andrew Conio
In the former, equal status is afforded to all and the crowd is organized;
it moves as one, chants together, and there is a uniformity of function.
Packs are not secondary groupings emerging from the crowd; they are
the elemental ground of the mass and are formed out of alogical orders,
consistencies and compatibilities. As was seen first-hand at Occupy,
packs or multiplicities continually transform themselves into each other,
and cross over into each other, through processes of alliance or contagion. As Deleuze puts it: Schools, bands, herds, and populations are not
inferior social forms; they are affects and powers, involutions (Deleuze
and Guattari 2000: 241).
In their different ways Nunes, Protevi, Conley and Mecchia each find
solutions to the problems inherent to the tendency to objectification, or
the ways in which historically sedimented practices impede becoming.
Protevi captures the process as follows:
You dont combat [the shame of unemployment] by trying to
change individual peoples minds, one by one, with information about unemployment trends; you combat it by showing
your face, by embodying your lack of shame, by putting a face
on unemployment or homelessness. You thus counteract the
existing collective affect by creating a positive affect of, shall
we say, joyful solidarity. Shame isolates (you hide your face);
joyful solidarity comes from people coming together.
For Nunes, in the body of the collective one gains access to the complex
process of becoming-imperceptible, which, far from being an act of selfdenial is a becoming-more through allowing oneself to be exposed, to
take a risk, and to trust that one can be formed by and, can help form, collective assemblages. Nunes shares with Conley a concern to place becoming-collective at the heart of the process of undoing subjectivation. He
outlines how becoming-imperceptible should be understood as becoming more realistic about oneself and the real potentials and limitations to
a process. It requires the shedding of selfhood (the vanguard, the revolutionary), undermining pre-given divisions (self/other), finding differences that exist in potential, and the capacity to create new continuities.
The sense that the novel and spontaneous is diffused in a web of practices
and sensibilities that have been a long time in the making is shared by
Introduction
35
Thoburn, who also places the evental quality of life at the imperceptible
center of processes of social formation: the ungraspable and often highly
seductive character of a formation whose directions remain unmapped,
indeterminable, full, as Deleuze has it, of virtuality.
For Deleuze, only some of the virtual potentials existent in the world
are actualized as we are moulded by macro and microscopic affects and
sensations that pass through us and which can be cosmological in extension.5 We must think of contraction and dilation, release and flow, rupture and slice, entropy and clamor, as pure intensities: the world floods
through us in a cacophony of multiplicities and singularities fused in an
indeterminable concoction of affects and percepts across multiple landscapes of psychic, social and physiological geographies in the backwards
and forwards of time in multiple durations.
IV. Deconstruction and Occupy
In her contribution, Colebrook discusses the continued relevance of
deconstruction, addressing a body of work that has considerable traction
in contemporary political philosophy, and whose influence may be seen
in the refusal by contemporary political activists to adopt an unassailable
and inviolable stance of purported truth from which to declare the correctness of their position. Colebrook discusses the difficulties inherent in
claiming either a pre-existing place of purity, innocence or natural justice,
or a futural justice yet to come from which resistance to an invading or
occupying force might be mounted. Implicit in the language of Occupy,
explicit in its structure and modus operandi, and suffused throughout its
culture, was the question, how do you criticize capitalism without setting yourself up as the uniquely privileged defender of an imagined
purity or innocence against some evil external power? More specifically,
how do you defend a cause or mount a critique without repeating the
same binary oppositions that sustain capitalism and which substitute
underlying terms of exclusion and dominance for other equally determinant terms? How do you create change without being either fascist
or Leninist, or navely accepting capitalisms claim that its leading terms
such as freedom, equality, democracy and autonomy are somehow not
complicit in the violence inherent in their constitution? These are the
36
Andrew Conio
reasons Occupy steadfastly refused to assert a claim to a single overarching truth, knowing that one claim to truth is a potential violence against
another. Diversity is a strategy, a methodology and an objective; any
attempt to impose a master narrative is seen as a type of violence done
to the myriad micro-struggles represented in the lived struggles of the
movements members. The question often put to the occupiers, What
exactly do you want?, is thus viewed as illegitimate, an attempt to delegitimize, belittle and close minds.
Colebrook explores the relevance of the works of Jacques Derrida and
Paul de Man to these debates, and in so doing outlines the weaknesses in
some interpretations of the deconstructive approach to politics (which
saw deconstruction contributing to a politics of nihilism, relativism and
cynicism), whilst highlighting some features that remain not just pertinent but necessary. First, in line with many of the arguments in this volume, and with its repeated theme of embodiment, Colebrook outlines
how deconstruction arose out of both developments in the history of
ideas and Derridas tortured response to the Nazi occupation of France,
where the occupation of language and citizenship led to a sense that the
material occupation of a territory and the immaterial occupation of language and subjectivity were violences of the same order.
For Colebrook, what began in material, historically specific circumstances provided the impetus for what became deconstructions quasitranscendental claim that neither the self-authoring presence of the
citizen/subject nor languages representational certainties, nor indeed
any binary opposition between inside or outside, innocent or contaminated, can be cited as non-compromised or non-complicit sites of resistance uncontaminated by the very logic of exclusion they were fighting
against. Paul de Man, whom Colebrook says captures deconstructions
conception of politics at its most rigorous, shows how there is no place
where language and the real can find a seamless relation. Each side of the
binary, the beautiful soul and totalizing power, resists a transcendental
structure of impossibility and undecidability. Both are party to an oppositional dialectic or binarism and are marked by the failure to accept the a
priori truth of the never assimilable, ungraspable outside, which places
all claims for truth under erasure. This is true of any type of Marxism
that might seek to ground resistance in some kind of system of techne
Introduction
37
38
Andrew Conio
dominance. Such concerns have been overtaken by an era in which market, choice, opportunity, autonomy and equality in the market place are
now caricatures unable to conceal a logic of market ruthlessness. We are
now in the grip of a flagrant neo-feudalism that no longer even pays lip
service to liberal ideology. We need to look elsewhere to explain how
certain axioms have come to dominate and overtake the previous configuration: how did capital manage to escape difference and allow one
axiom to overcode all others? (These questions are further attended to
by Holland and myself).
For Colebrook, instead of attempting to find a putative place of otherness we should think within system, techne and difference, critiquing
capitalism from within. There is no outside to capitalism; becoming
minor within a pre-existing language, economy and ontology is not only
theoretically valid but can create a series of heterogenic economies and
political systems, and a return to multiplicities of difference. In response
to the question what do you want? Occupy answers: ongoing reflection,
an authentic relation not to life but to becoming minor and a revitalized
commitment to difference.
V. Subjectivity and Aesthetics
Deleuze and Guattari oppose notions of an originating, proprietorial or
intentional subjectivity. It is not unreasonable to say that their entire oeuvre amounts to a profound and relentless anti-humanism, where humanism is the conception that humanity somehow stands above or straddles
life or nature. In fact, life precedes, envelopes and supersedes all that
human beings are the lived body is a paltry thing in comparison with
a more profound and almost unlivable power of life (Deleuze 2003: 44).
Deleuze and Guattari do not claim that their model of trans-monadic
becoming supersedes or supplants the present system, but rather that it
is already what we are. We are already packs; the body is impressed with
bodies of knowledge, medical bodies, juridical bodies and a myriad of
collective assemblages of enunciation. Perception is already cinematic
and memory photographic.
Nunes brings these themes neatly together by highlighting the correlation between event and subject taking place at Occupy. [The] subject
Introduction
39
is not an autonomous, sovereign agent, but the way in which the event
expresses itself. It exists to the extent that it affirms the event, as much
as the event exists only because it expresses itself in this subject. [T]he
event creates a new existence, it produces a new subjectivity (Deleuze
and Guattari 2003: 216), but not as an external cause; it is in producing
such transformations that the event events. That the subject is crafted
by rather than master of events is also crucial to Conleys argument. As
Guattari asserts, changes can occur autopoietically, unbeknownst to the
subject, before she or he even opens onto the environing world.
For Conley, Occupy presents an opportunity to revisit the promise of
new forms of subjectivity outlined in A Thousand Plateaus, a work which,
for her, marks a significant turning point in Deleuzes political thought.
After the exuberance, almost delirium, of Anti-Oedipus, and after the
defeats of the left and capitalisms resurgence, a more sombre and pragmatic approach was needed. As Conley notes, A Thousand Plateaus is far
from being the vague and indeterminate series of loose assemblages of
ideas it is sometimes taken to be, but is rather a series of territories held
together by affective intensities made possible as a specific moment in
history from which, in the present (for the authors in the aftermath
of 1968) they think and write. There is something so consistent about
Deleuzes approach that it almost amounts to a methodology: from the
indeterminate ground, the flux and flow of change, consistencies emerge;
depending on the context these are fashioned as territories, assemblages,
milieus or plateaus. Conley attunes us to the subtlety of Deleuzes use of
plateaus to describe the creation of territories or planes of consistencies
out of the profusion of complex multilayered social dynamics, semiologies and intensities. She writes of shifts in subjectivity, changes in relations and expectations, the dynamics of voyaging smoothly with awareness, of crossing thresholds, of the making of rhizomatic connections
that happen way beyond the egotistic and outside of the world reduced
to systems of economic, juridical and scientific signs. She affirms that in
voyaging one can invite change by shifting to a new subjectivity, perspective or language, or taking a line of flight, and she finds plenty of evidence
of such soft subversions effected by artists, educators, and cultural creators. Considering the slippery nature of desire, Buchanan (2011) notes
that changing the composition of desire is itself revolutionary, and as
40
Andrew Conio
recent events have shown the transformation of desire on both an individual and collective level is not something that necessarily requires
planning. Conley also asks, most positively of all, whether Occupy has
not also put the dominant discourses of state, democracy, space into
variation: is Occupy another plateau?
In keeping with the spirit of this volume, Thoburn explores Deleuzes
concepts not in order to illustrate or represent the themes and issues of
Occupy but to create a dialogue between the two with the aim of facilitating their further development: Its a recursive relation, for reflection
upon Occupys themes or problems should also help extend Deleuzian
concepts, lending them a contemporary vitality. For Thoburn, the
minoritization of politics has found expression in the shift away from
identitarian and representational politics as part of long-term changes
in the structure of capitalist development and the concomitant production of the multitude. The minor brings contestation, argument and
problematization to the fore. This is exemplified by Occupys single most
important statement: Let these Facts be Known the Declaration of the
Occupation of New York City.
Lets acknowledge the reality: the future of the human race
requires the cooperation of its members. Our increasingly
interconnected world obscures the underlying truth that all of
our grievances are connected.
Adding extra dimensions to this and echoing the autonomist Marxist tradition, Thoburn draws our attention to how willed poverty and a form
of boundary limitation are actively affirmed as a means of resistance
by the multitude. He shows how the range of economic structures and
plethora of social relationships thrown up by the push and pull between
these co-determining dynamics offers no fixed route, system or structure.
He also presents a warning that seeing the multitude in this way might
mean avoiding perhaps the most urgent task of all: creating a strategically
planned, coherently organized, well-prepared and organized body able to
win a fearsome class war.
Thoburn also pursues a thought experiment by thinking of democracy as a grid a series of lines, intersections and spaces, something
like a diagram, imposed upon the virtual multiplicities of the socius. He
Introduction
41
marshals Deleuze: Elections are not a particular locale, nor a particular day in the calendar. They are more like a grid that affects the way we
understand and perceive things. Everything is mapped back on this grid
and gets warped as a result (Deleuze 2007: 143). For Thoburn, democracy imposes a status quo that inherently excludes the problems of
inequality and exploitation. This state of affairs is normalized and treated
as a natural condition that liberal democratic systems are best suited to
resolve, rather than being imbricated in the very structures that bring
these iniquities about. The grid democracy is thus a matrix of principles,
ideals, and structures into which people are expected to fit even when
the inner logic of the system results in unelected technocrats taking control of the levers of power, as in Greece and Italy. Indeed, the idea that
an unproblematized majority might somehow stand for the will of the
people is itself a form of dictatorship. Its not that Deleuze and Guattari
are anti-democratic, far from it; rather, they seek a far more intensive
democracy, a becoming democratic in everything everywhere.
To this end, Thoburn suggests that the grid Occupy can be seen as
a means of multiplying points of antagonism. For example, the slogan we
are the 99% (asserting that the vast majority of humanity is suffering at
the expense of the few), may have captured world-wide attention, but
we should recall that Occupy London took down the talismanic banner
Capitalism is Crisis because it accentuated a single theme. The fact that
Occupy distinguishes itself relationally the 99% versus the 1% means,
writes Colebrook, that it does not present itself as somehow positioned in
a pure outside, occupying its own self-referential ground. It is a relation,
it labels a mass not an identity. The 1% has no identity other than that
of its situation within an already distributed terrain. In this way Occupy
both reclaims capitalisms claim of universality a system of the greater
good and names a number and not an identity such as the workers or a
class, a vanguard or a method of socialism.
For Deleuze a majority is like a dictatorship, or a weapon, a false
abstraction imposed upon myriad forces, identities and singularities;
indeed, counting, for Buchanan, even a headcount of a million protestors, is not the same as that which transforms history. A majority is false
because it adheres to number and not the dynamic multiplicities evolving in the will of the people. For Badiou, the majority is an empty set, a
42
Andrew Conio
set that is determined by force, the terms of which majority might count
having already been decided. The question, Would you prefer a society
in which all people share of the common wealth equally? is positioned
as nonsense.
Contrariwise, historical transformation involves rather the irruption
of immanence and a change in consciousness irrespective of number.
Buchanan provides two examples to illustrate how such transformation
can be both conceptual and historical. An idea whose time has come is
a clear manifestation of the minor, it isnt concerned with results, with
counting in the here and now, what it awakens is the force of history itself.
A raggle taggle of disaffected anarcho-political activists who numbered
no more than a few hundred placed into world-wide public consciousness the idea that we might imagine the total transformation of society.
Buchanan also writes of the creation of smooth space and the mobility
it affords being the key resource in battles for territory, technology, minds
and ideas. However, elsewhere he is careful, in employing Deleuzes exact
phrasing, to caution against an uncritical valorization of the term:
it all depends on a careful systematic use were trying to say
you can never guarantee a good outcome (its not enough just
to have a smooth space, for example, to overcome striations
and coercion, or a body without organs to overcome organisations. (Deleuze 1995: 32)
Thoburn likewise observes that a kind of smooth space is necessary to
undo the illusions of democracy, but he fills this with layers of antagonism. Hence, the grid Occupy seeks is to encourage a problematics
of contestation and critique, and the development of divergent positions in an extension and intensification of the problematic in concrete
circumstances.
As well as emphasizing the contested and conflictual modality of
Occupy, Thoburn explores the aesthetic dimension of political struggle.
He references Deleuzes anthropological/ethological approach wherein
animal, natural and human traits are interlaced in a social form that is
indispensably aesthetic. We find in Occupy expressions of territoriality that are not just markers and signifiers of boundary lines but have
an expressive sensory quality. As in the numerous ethological examples
Introduction
43
44
Andrew Conio
illustrate but to be applied along with Occupys practical tools and methods, not least in various approaches to the question of space.
Buchanan for instance observes how smooth space amounts to a
commons. He argues that Occupy opened up a new way, a new space, for
thinking and acting, creating a radical break with the normal continuity of things, interrupting and causing a counter flow to the usual flow
of daily life. Articulating the increasing interest in the common, the
commons movement and commoning at Occupy, he suggests that the
common, conceived as social relations, can be understood as a smooth
space. We must bear in mind that neither Buchanan nor Thoburn equates
smooth space with a flattening or an absence of conflict. Buchanan borrows from David Harvey:
The common is not to be constructed, therefore, as a particular kind of thing, asset or even social process, but as an unstable and malleable social relation between a particular welldefined social group and those aspects of its actually existing
or yet-to-be-created social and/or physical environment
deemed crucial to its life and livelihood. There is, in effect, a
social practice of commoning. (Harvey 2012: 73)
For Hardt and Negri the common is the basis for the existence of the
multitude; the two are indivisible since the common is:
that which allows the multitude to communicate and act
together the common does not refer to traditional notions
of either the community or the public the common is
what configures the mobile and flexible substance of the multitude and social life depends on the common. (Hardt and
Negri 2006: 9, 10, 212)
The common is a space that allows for the greatest degree of singularity, it
is composed of a set of singularities and by singularity here we mean a
social subject whose difference cannot be reduced to sameness. Beyond
all else, the common is the virtual space of pre-individual singularities,
where flows of affects and percepts, ideas and processes, and the ground
of all human life (Graeber 2012: 101) discussed by all the contributors
to this volume, are to be found.
Introduction
45
46
Andrew Conio
between what we already know from French intellectual writing after May
1968 which broadly accepted the idea that power is not simply a matter of coercion or repression the product or the expression of a powerful ruling elite exercising influence over a powerless majority (Buchanan
2008: 21) and contemporary conditions on the ground suggesting the
emergence of a transcendent neoliberal war machine of debt and perpetual war against people, communities and life.
We should also be wary of investing in the notion of the sovereignty
of an empire or despot as a terrifying behemoth, lest we both misunderstand it and create a monster that can only be challenged by matching
its scale and its weapons, in turn affording it even greater power. Instead,
we should think with Hardt and Negri:
Empire creates a greater potential for revolution than did the
modern regimes of power because it presents us, alongside
the machine of command, with an alternative: the set of all
the exploited and the subjugated, a multitude that is directly
opposed to Empire, with no mediation between them. (Hardt
and Negri 2000: 393)
Capitalism is, in and of itself, decentered and deterritorialized; it is endlessly creative. It creates fluid networks, multiple hybrid identities, and
demands new subjectivities. Its axiomatics create borders and inhibit
flows, and yet it also cannot tolerate borders; indeed, we might argue that
capitalist production cannot tolerate the unproductiveness of racism,
sexism and homophobia, and certainly decoding and deterritorialization have immense emancipatory potential. According to Virno (2004)
the capitalist mode of production in the transition from Fordism to postFordism was driven by the multitudes demands for new socialities, new
working practices, and the development of new desires, relations, sexualities and attitudes to hierarchy that have subsequently been capitalized.
Given the inherent dynamism of capitalism, it is hardly surprising
that the multitude takes on equally amorphous forms of expression. But
the multitude is not simply a consequence of new forms of production;
it emerges from the autopoietic drive of the resourcefulness of life of
difference as the driving force behind new forms of capitalist production. Its force also emerges from disjunctive and conjunctive accidents
Introduction
47
48
Andrew Conio
Introduction
49
1987: 2419, 2679, 278, 3667, 384, 39093) rather than strict obligation or duty, although, he warns, there is nothing that can be considered
decisive about this modus operandi in itself, since the Tea Party movement, and indeed the stock exchange, share many of these features of
the war machine. Notwithstanding this caveat, when looking to understand Occupys potential for social transformation the concept of the war
machine provides an invaluable tool. Historical change does not come
only through violent revolution or sudden ruptures but also through slow
developments in thought, affects and perception, through the shifting
and sliding of subjectivities and communities. As we are seeing today, the
potential for a revolution in consciousness is observable in the exceedingly clear political bifurcation that is taking place between diametrically
opposed political ontologies, the furthest poles of which being exemplified by Occupy and the Tea Party.
Refusal is also central to Hollands analysis. He suggests that a slowmotion general strike (a strike against everything) may be taking place
in the widespread subtraction of our collective and individual experience
from the machinery of neoliberal capitalist production. It is clear that vast
numbers of people are either reduced to exhaustion and dismay by capitalisms rage against love, community, and social solidarity, or are enraged
by informed analyses of climate change, wealth distribution, people
trafficking, the prisonindustrial complex, modern-day slavery and so
forth, and emboldened by experience in resistance movements across
the globe. It takes time to create new networks and new subjectivities,
and taking back time is both the method and objective of many of these
disparate political groupings. Holland leaves open the question as to
whether this will prompt a sudden irruption of the political unconscious
or will continue in slow motion. Either way, the hoary old reformrevolution conundrum does not become an issue because neither is negated
in the open-ended political utopianism of Occupy.
VII. Money and Debt: Towards a Minor Marxism
Anti-Oedipus is a difficult read. It is Deleuze and Guattari at their most
infuriating and perplexing, and yet it may be their most prescient text.
For Holland it provides an indispensible anatomization of how the
50
Andrew Conio
conversion of wealth into capital and work into dependent wage labor is
central to the development of capitalism, and charts a path through different conceptualizations of money, debt, control societies and capitalist
axiomatics to arrive at what appears to be capitalisms essence, the conjunction of three flows of decoding consisting of:
The decoding of land flows, under the form of the constitution of large private properties, the decoding of monetary
flows, under the form of the development of merchant fortunes, the decoding of a flow of workers under the form of
expropriation, of the deterritorialization of serfs and peasant
landholders. (Deleuze 1971)
The conjunction of the deterritorialized flows of abstract capital and
abstract labor and their reterritorialization in the form of private property forms the center of the many factitious reterritorializations of capitalism. In turn, private property functions to alienate the wage laborer
whose so-called free labor serves as their only property, removed from
their material and incorporeal reproduction of worlds, selves and the
socius. Only as a consequence of these conjunctions could capitalism stabilize and endure.
In Anti-Oedipus we find that whilst critiquing all forms of arborescent thought, particularly Freudianism and Marxism, Deleuze and
Guattari assert that capitalism has an archetypal structure. At first blush
this appears to be a contradiction, but we should consider the difference
between seeking to determine the essential nature of a thing and analyzing a historically contingent organization of forces. Indeed, there is
a mood of exhaustion in contemporary Deleuzian scholarship, and the
proliferation of Deleuzian aesthetics, the various alibis for rhizomatic
absentmindedness and the championing of the liberating potential of
desire and schizoid expressivity. This reading (clarified in some detail in
this volume by Mecchia) has led to attempts to articulate a more careful and coherent Deleuzian political philosophy, achieved not least by
the works of Ian Buchanan. A useful introduction to the basic principles
of Deleuze and Guattaris political, social and economic thought can be
found in Buchanans 2008 Deleuze and Guattaris Anti-Oedipus (88116),
which concerns a particular section of Anti-Oedipus (pages 139262).
Introduction
51
52
Andrew Conio
Central to the transition from the primitive/territorial to the despotic epoch was the role played by the development of money. In the
primitive/territorial age, goods were exchanged according to a system
of barter.8 Credit and debt were measured using various fungible, finite
recording systems criss-crossing a palimpsest of social and familial registers which laid the foundation of the development of thought (where
thought is taken to include shared beliefs, alliances and filiations, inherited myths, social practices, recognitions and scales of values, affects,
soma, and so forth), and social obligations. Money was not introduced to
facilitate barter but imposed by the despot to secure his power and exact
tribute. This, along with the development of abstract labor and capital,
laid the foundations for the development of capitalism. The conjunction of these great forces of decoding were exacted through the figure
of money, which retained the imprint of its originative incarnation as a
power of command.
My own chapter shows how money, while its infinite variety of uses
may be impossible to fully theorize, should be understood in terms
of the originative division, forged in the transition from the primitive
to the despotic age, between its dual functions as credit and exchange.
The self-same coin acts according to two valences as credit, which allows
for accumulation, the extraction of tribute and the power of command,
and exchange, which facilities both invention, creativity and the multitudinous expression of desire. Exchange money is impotent and turns
us into slaves of the social machine of production and consumption
wherein all desires are decoded and recoded into the general equivalence
of money: under capitalism, all the flows of desire, and all of the intensities of life become grounded on one single flow: the quantifiable medium
of capital and exchange (Colebrook 2006: 50).
There is then a profound ambivalence at the heart of money. It facilitates the creative potentials of unlimited exchange and it also allows for
quantitative exchange as a substitute for the time-consuming, socially
complex and never quite concluded palimpsest of different mechanisms of trade.
Quantitative measurement as a substitute for rational value
judgment confers supreme moral security and intellectual
comfort: the Good becomes measurable and calculable;
Introduction
53
decisions and moral judgments can follow from the implementation of a procedure of impersonal, objective, quantifying calculation and individual subjects do not have to
shoulder the burden [of decision making] anxiously and
uncertainly. (Gorz 1989: 121)
However, these extraordinary freedoms are curtailed as money becomes
the supreme, indispensible criteria and single measure of value of all
things. These values and criteria are largely determined by the manner
in which is money is issued and the purposes to which it is put. These
ambivalences and contradictions at the heart of money are fundamental,
and Philip Goodchilds project is to show how thinking and reason are
grounded in the same processes. Looking across the epochs we can question whether the great advances in trade and social development would
have been possible without the cooperation and coordination introduced
by the single quantifying measuring scale provided by money. Likewise,
would the industrial revolution have been possible without credit?
These contradictions may explain why moneys other side, its power
of command and extraction through rent and tribute, remains unhindered and leads to chronic overproduction, breathtaking inequality and
wastefulness of human potential, and an inescapable, incessant schiz-flow
of creative invention and destruction rather than revolution. What is hidden is the simple fact that moneys ability to facilitate the expression of
lifes potential is severely curtailed by its issuance as credit money by the
banks. Indeed, the appearance of a primary equilibrium of prices leads to
a belief in an underlying principle of equality that conceals entirely functional and fundamental inequalities. As Goodchild, one of the foremost
interpreters of Deleuzian economic theory, notes:
Since money is created as debt, and debt must be repaid in
the form of money and more debt, and debt becomes the
supreme principle of theoretical knowledge, practical conduct, and mutual trust, then this perspective of evaluation is
not chosen but imposes itself. (2013: 53)
Taking up the challenge of making Deleuze relevant to policy formation and institution building, I ask whether the practical policy formulations of the political campaign group Positive Money (whose agenda
54
Andrew Conio
Introduction
55
the form of obligation and mutuality, dependence and merit, was realized
through the practices of theft and gift.
Deleuze and Guattari detail how in the primitive/territorial age the
destruction of surplus production in rituals or potlatch not only used
excess to create a filiative lineage of social adhesion but also allowed
obligations to remain, as the absence of wealth held in reserve necessitated continued social dependency. Mecchia reports on Pierre Clastres
view that many world populations were not frugal and stateless because
of scarcity and political primitivism, but as a consequence of an explicit
political decision, notably the unwillingness to engage in labor contracts
and political representations. Celebrations and expenditure to demonstrate excess, along with enactments of rituals and inscriptions, are all
forms of gift that are very different from just simply giving something
away, or from messy reciprocal gift-giving; they are commitments to the
social bond. Buchanan (2008) explains that the chief doesnt exchange
his wealth for allegiance; rather, through these practices he converts
wealth into allegiance. Gift is also a form of trade, and to give often
implies a power relation as the gift bestows power in the form of reputation, rank and sociability, which implies its mirror in the form of allegiance. By giving, credit is accrued, but also life force is expended, and by
expending is in turn increased; the gift is the spending of energy not for
the sake of return, indeed ones force is increased the more one spends
(Colebrook 2006: 126).
To a large extent to steal is to be, and very often the gift is indistinguishable from theft as elaborate feasts and gift-giving become a way
of converting goods into prestige and allegiance: to prevent this from
becoming an exchange the ritual of gift giving must make the gift seem
like a theft (Deleuze and Guattari 2000: 203). Before there is an economy allowing for the exchange of property, and before there is anything
like scarcity, need or interest, Deleuze and Guattari argue for a milieu of
forces that is neither the rapacious world of capitalist acquisitiveness and
theft, nor a benign moral nature attuned to social harmony and benevolence. Once social systems are formed from a war machine that is a play
of forces before interests and property, then a milieu of rivalry, envy and
rank inevitably follows precisely because of establishing the single force
of the proper or of ownership.
56
Andrew Conio
Introduction
57
The requirement of the socius was therefore that potency, agency, leverage and force create relatively stable terms, and intensive difference is
a pre-requisite for a genuine calculation to be made regarding who has
taken what. Such calculation, as I show, is taken by Nietzsche to be the
foundation of thought.
In the primitive/territorial epoch we see an assemblage of adjunctive
and disjunctive relations and collective territorialization occurs when the
tribe is marked by processes [that] allow organs such as the eyes, penis,
breast or head to be experienced collectively (Colebrook 2006: 144).
This collectivism also leads to a proto-individualism, as only in a form of
territorialization can the body take itself as an individual; and individual
memory, or a sense of self existing in time, is dependent upon collective
memory. As Holland, Colebrook and I all make clear, fundamental to this
process is debt and the ability to live up to a promise. As I argue:
Certainly, without rational thought, anticipation and prediction, man would not survive; but memory is more than that.
It lays the foundation for the formation of will by the creation
of a link between I will and the actual manifestation of the
will in action. In this way an infallible psychological law leads
to predicable subjects who, in turn, provide the infrastructure
for the social bond.
Also emergent from this process is accumulation achieved not through
expropriation but as a result of harboring and storing and the process of
exchange, which together form the conditions for a nascent capitalism.
Economic and subjective differences, a this is mine and that is yours or
non-exchangeable and non-substitutable singularities between two discernable persons, are pre-requisites for trading. The emergence of capitalism was a consequence not of determining laws of history, nor of an
underlying human nature, nor of a law of struggle or economic production, but of a specific historically contingent assemblage of forces.
VIII. Deterritorialization, Reterritorialization, and Smooth Space
Deleuze and Guattari are often presented as being in thrall to the deterritorializing effects of capitalism. Fueling this perception, Anti-Oedipus
58
Andrew Conio
Introduction
59
60
Andrew Conio
Introduction
61
62
Andrew Conio
Introduction
63
tolerate its own plenitude. In response, rather than following the Deleuze
popularized in some circles of accelerated difference we need to find or
invent, with Occupy, difference-affirming machines. Occupys Let these
Facts be Known captures the myriad forms of minoritarianism that
allow for contradictory, antagonistic, connective, rhizomic differences.
Recognizing that our urgent times do not afford us the luxury of absolute
deterritorialization or fantasies about an outside to capitalism, Occupy
is intensely pragmatic all of its groups and assemblies are charged with
experimenting with questions of how to devise practical solutions to the
problems of the state, democracy, economy and social relations. In the
end, both Occupy and Deleuze are rooted in practical analysis, and both
reject the stifling alternative reform or revolution, because both understand that the question [of revolutions] has always been organisational
(2007: 143): the organization of flows into autopoietic and highly relational structures.
Works Cited
Ambrose, Darren. 2006. Deleuze, Philosophy, and the Materiality of Painting.
Symposium 10 (1): 191211.
Badiou, Alain. 2000. Deleuze: The Clamor of Being. Minneapolis: University of
Minesotta Press.
Badiou, Alain. 2012. The Rebirth of History: Times of Riots and Uprisings. London:
Verso.
Buchanan, Ian. 2008. Deleuze and Guattaris Anti-Oedipus: A Readers Guide. London:
Continuum.
Buchanan Ian. 2011. Desire and Ethics. Deleuze Studies 5 (Supplement): 720.
Colebrook, Claire. 2006. Deleuze: A Guide for the Perplexed. London: Continuum.
Choat, Simon. 2009. Deleuze, Marx and the Politicisation of Philosophy. Deleuze
Studies 3 (Supplement): 827.
Conio, Andrew. 2012. The Ontogenesis of Language. Journal of Literary, Cultural and
Language Studies 3 (2012): 4462.
64
Andrew Conio
Introduction
65
66
Andrew Conio
Notes
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
7.
As Anne Pettifor points out: real wealth should be seen not in terms of the
tangible stuff (homes, money land) but in terms of the intangible stuff the
economic power that wealthy people are able to exercise by virtue of the fact
they have got assets, those assets enable them to borrow and leverage their
wealth at a rate that is unprecedented in human history. For example the
Glazier brothers bought Manchester United using very little of their own
money, they used borrowed money. They had some collateral but the real
collateral was Manchester United football team itself, and its supporters
and its streams of revenue. They were about to purchase a football club and
make others pay for the debt, through buying tickets, televisions rights,
tee-shirts. Those revenue streams are paying down the debt incurred by the
Glazier families is an exact example of how the rich are further enriched
by the enforced indebtedness of others. See Boom Bust (June 5, 2014),
RT America. Accessed April 25, 2015 from: https://www.youtube.com/
watch?v=1Yqalvi5jUM
8.
The first coinage by the Lydian or Phrygian despots in the Greek colonies on
the Aegean around 680 BC, probably for fiscal, military and political purposes
rather than for trade; coinage only acquired a use in trading between cities
in the following century in the main Greek trading ports, such as Athens.
(Goodchild 2008: 28).
Chapter 1
68
Giuseppina Mecchia
in this chapter. In the following pages, I will argue that Gilles Deleuze and
Flix Guattari left us with basic elements of an ethico-political stance that
can best let us understand the political discourses and practices that saw
in the Occupy movements their most recent instantiation. In particular,
their common work on schizoanalysis will help me propose the concept
of the anthropos as a dynamic, material figure of political subjectivity.
Defined as the psychosocial subject of the schizoanalytic unconscious,
such a figure can help us conceive not only capitals current grip on global
forms of life, but also and most importantly the limits of such a hold and
the spaces that can still be reclaimed for anthropolitical projects of liberation and affective redirection.
Before going any further, a few words about schizoanalysis are in
order. While the limits of this chapter dont allow me to go into the more
technical details of their presentation, let us remember that Deleuze and
Guattari introduced the concept in Anti-Oedipus as a political response
to some contemporary trends in psychoanalytic thought. We should
remember how, in the early 1970s, Lacans pessimism about the movements of May 1968 when he famously claimed that the students were
simply looking for another master was becoming increasingly influential in intellectual circles, and was later promptly adopted in the reactionary atmosphere of the 1980s. The Lacanian unconscious cares little about
history and political change: deeply rooted mechanisms of physical and
mental dependency internal to the human physiology and familial structures remain constant, and beside stoic acceptance and analytic lucidity,
little or no space is left for any serious questioning of ones determinations. Political revolt is largely presented as an ultimately insignificant
smoke-screen, behind which an immutable tale of suffering and neurosis
continues to unfold. To this pessimist narrative always liable to become
a socially conservative political stance Deleuze and Guattari opposed
a revised version of the Lacanian unconscious, at once less chronically
despondent and more politically satisfying. In the chapter entitled A
Materialist Psychiatry, we read that contrary to Lacanian orthodoxy, the
productions of desire are real, and are borne by the machinic investments
expressed by constantly created bodies and minds:
If desire produces, its product is real. If desire is productive, it
can be productive only in the real world and can produce only
On Anthropolitics
69
reality. Desire is the set of passive syntheses that engineer partial objects, flows and bodies, and that function as units of
production. (Deleuze and Guattari 2009: 26)
The task of schizoanalysis is then progressively made clear: intervening
in the passive syntheses that constitute the partial objects of desiring
production, responding to the suffering caused by deadly investments in
oppressive and stunting processes be it familial entrapments, capitalist cooptation or statist bureaucracies with an effort to follow decoded
schizzes, defined as the desiring chains working toward the continual
detachments (Deleuze and Guattari 2009: 39) of disjunctive moves
against pre-determined, ready-made individualized significations.
Refusing the normative call to individualization and the injunction to
name oneself as attached to a specific desire, those who follow the schizzes resist filling the space of the I understood as the isolated subject of a
reified identity:
There are those who will maintain that the schizo is incapable
of uttering the word I, and that we must restore his ability to
pronounce this hallowed word. All of which the schizo sums
up by saying: theyre fucking me over again. (Deleuze and
Guattari 2009: 23)
Deleuze and Guattari are careful to contextualize their rethinking of the
psychoanalytic unconscious in relation to a critique of capitalism, through
the different social mutations of private property and accumulation, since
it is this form that produces the capitalist field of immanence, the capitalist, the worker [and that] produces a vast conversion of this world
by attributing to it the new form of an infinite subjective representation
(Deleuze and Guattari 2009: 303). Only by perceiving ones subjective
representation as the result of an oppressive, even deadly, assignation can
one try to redirect ones energies in a less nefarious manner.
The Occupy movements, in this respect, were profoundly schizoanalytic: supported by non-proprietary and anonymous cultural forces such
as Adbusters or Anonymous itself, and by individuals whose identities
of workers/unemployed/students/producers became the asignifying
numeric symbol of the 99%, the people involved in these actions were
70
Giuseppina Mecchia
able to defy and physically contradict at least for a time the capitalist
subsumption of their mental and social energies.
On Capitalist Crises and Insurrectional Responses
Although I intend to formulate a critique of the present with a focus on
the Occupy movements, there is no better introduction to my main argument than a very old quotation taken from A Thousand Plateaus:
Doubtless, the present situation is highly discouraging. We
have watched the war machine grow stronger and stronger, as
in a science fiction story; we have seen it assign as its objective a peace still more terrifying than fascist death; we have
seen it maintain or instigate the most terrible of local wars as
parts of itself; we have seen it set its sights on a new type of
enemy, no longer another State, or even another regime, but
the unspecified enemy Yet the very conditions that make
the State or the World War Machine possible, in other words,
constant capital (resources and equipment) and human variable capital, continually recreate unexpected possibilities for
counterattack, unforeseen initiatives determining revolutionary, popular, minority, mutant machinesthe unassignable
material Saboteur or human Deserter assuming the most
diverse forms (Deleuze and Guattari 1987: 422).
The second installment of the diptych Capitalism and Schizophrenia was
originally published in 1980, eight years after the publication of AntiOedipus and as a result of about ten years of cooperation between the two
co-authors. It is, of course, very difficult to reconstruct with any accuracy
the historical context of what they then called the present situation.
Nonetheless, the policies adopted by a number of Western powers in the
late 1970s to counter internal and external threats were the source of the
discouragement felt by many activists at that time.
A few, certainly insufficient, reminders do in fact allow us to reconstruct some aspects of the books present, in a highly interdependent
international context: the escalation of the AmericanRussian conflict in
Iran and Afghanistan at the end of Jimmy Carters presidency in the US;
On Anthropolitics
71
72
Giuseppina Mecchia
On Anthropolitics
73
potentially revolutionary situations? Is it possible to affirm, socially, psychologically and philosophically, that figures such as saboteurs, deserters,
strikers and occupiers are indeed possible, even when they appear historically doomed, without resorting to the abstract and factually inadequate
principles of liberal democracies, such as human equality and freedom of
speech? In the rest of this essay, it will be my contention that yes, there
is a way to think the immanent potentialities of the social subject, and
that it may be present, more than anywhere else, precisely in the kind of
thought that is present in Capital and Schizophrenia, and more specifically
in the conceptual configuration of the schizoanalytic subject. It is this
new anthropolitical figure that I will try to delineate in the remainder of
this paper, taking a little pre-emptive detour through the objections that
have been raised against it.
One More Effort, If You Want to be Materialist!
After decades of controversies, it is inevitable that before articulating the
outlines of what I consider to be the innovative conception of subjectivity that emerges from the combination of Deleuzes brand of materialist
thought and the analytic, practical anthropology that he elaborated with
Flix Guattari, I should address some of the objections that have been
raised against its politics, because they are extremely useful to the articulation of the affirmative moments of my argument. I focus on the issue
of materialism because the stakes of this appellation are still quite high
when one wants to position ones critique within the Marxist legacy of
the political critique of capital.
First of all, the highly interdisciplinary and somewhat unruly philosophical lexicon of Capitalism and Schizophrenia, with its concomitant
revision and expansion of classically Marxist categories and fields of
inquiry, certainly contributed to its muted political reception in many
leftist academic circles, in France and abroad. Additionally, the unorthodox theoretical credentials of Flix Guattari, joined to what is considered
a more bourgeois, classical practice of philosophy on the part of Gilles
Deleuze prior to their collaboration, have determined several thinkers to
either completely ignore the books the two co-authored during the last
twenty years of their lives, or to simply focus on the indictment of the
74
Giuseppina Mecchia
On Anthropolitics
75
76
Giuseppina Mecchia
On Anthropolitics
77
78
Giuseppina Mecchia
from what Bateson once called the ecology of the mind, that is, the environmental milieu that supports our brain function. Similar objections
could be levied against the Italian philosopher Paolo Virno, who, like
Rancire, seems to be too dependent on Aristotelian and formal linguistics to engage in a genuinely materialist critique of psychosocial structures and physical determinations.
Both Badiou and Rancire and more recently Paolo Virno have
found an eager audience in British and North American academia. As a
concrete and remarkable case of derivative theory, I will reference here
Peter Hallward, a much younger, Canadian political philosopher, who
is greatly indebted to both philosophers and shares several of their basic
theoretical moves. Hallward, however, maintains a strong Leninist background that leads him to the formulation of a political voluntarism even
more radical than the apostolic fidelity requested of the Badiouan subject of truth. And like Badiou, he is staunchly anti-Deleuzian. His 2006
book, tellingly entitled Out of This World: Deleuze and the Philosophy of
Creation, recasts and radicalizes Badious critique of Deleuzian politics, most notably in the methodological exclusion of the volumes
co-authored with Flix Guattari and the accusation of Stoic, even aristocratic, detachment linked, once again, to a naturalistic vitalism considered incapable of formulating a political critique of contingent forms of
power. Hallward proposes nothing less than a neo-Leninist vanguardist
practice for the engaged intellectual, predicated on a strict one might
say ascetic adherence to certain principles, or truths. This is almost
paradoxical, since Hallward had already reproached both Deleuze and
Guattari for formulating a non-specific theory of singularity in his earlier text, Absolutely Post-Colonial (2001), while at the same time he himself was rejecting the inscription of the political subject in his or her own
sociohistorical determinations. The political subject appears as process
of relational de-specification, always consciously embraced by a responsible agent (Hallward 2002: 50). It is true that in his work on Haiti,
Hallward devotes unrelenting attention to the economic, cultural and
social specificities of that particular community; however, his inflexible,
transcendental conception of political subjectivity puts him in a difficult
double bind when thinking about issues of political agency. This is a difficulty that he shares most clearly with Badiou, but also, I would contend,
On Anthropolitics
79
with the kind of linguistic understanding present in Rancires conception of equality and democracy.
My critique should not be interpreted as hostile: I do appreciate the
fact that all of these thinkers remain steadfast in their opposition to present and past forms of capitalist and bureaucratic domination. However, I
think that all of them, and maybe most notably Hallward, who explicitly
declares his own inscription in MarxismLeninism, need to operate an
exceedingly difficult intellectual torsion in order to maintain their theoretical presuppositions. They all engage with but ultimately reject materialist empiricism maybe the most concise definition of Deleuze and
Guattaris thought as viable foundation for political critique in general
and for the description of the political subject in particular. To a certain
extent, even the ultimate Marxist legacy, which remains the critique of
political economy, is tossed to the side. Their political unconscious, to
quote Jameson, is entangled in the formal positions attributed to it by
psychoanalytic and linguistic representation. Whether such representation is true or false is not, of course, what is at stake here. Rather,
what needs to be questioned is the impossibility, for them, of theoretically accounting for the here and now of political constitution. What
Deleuze and Guattari allow us to think is the materiality of such constitutions, in their transversal crossing of the striated spaces of social organization. It is in the empiricist or even Stoic articulation of materiality
and autonomy, of singularity and immanent collective connectivity that
the most precious contribution of Deleuze and Guattari to political
philosophy is to be found, as I will argue in the rest of this chapter. In the
articulation of the schizoanalytic subject as anthropolitical agent we can
find maybe the most faithful rendition of the occupier, a figure that is as
material as it is complex, embedded in the deepest recesses of contemporary forms of subjective formation.
From Anthropological Abjection to Anthropolitical Autonomy
It is not by chance that I evoked Hallwards 2001 book on post-coloniality: in fact, powerful objections to the political content of Deleuze and
Guattaris two volumes on capitalism and schizophrenia have also come
from scholars deeply engaged in post-colonial studies, although others
80
Giuseppina Mecchia
On Anthropolitics
81
economic and social subjects, organized around the two axes of space
and time. This is in fact the mode that organizes the project of Capital
as narration. Therefore, when Paul Patton says that Deleuze and Guattari
engage in a neo-Marxist universal history (Patton 2000: 88), it is important to introduce an essential modification: while Marx relegates the
primitive mode of production to a historical past that conceives the modern capitalist mode of production as the inevitable telos of modern forms
of progress, Deleuze and Guattari adopt a slightly different universal
perspective. For them, capital and the state apparatus are both present
and absent in all societies, either as accepted realizations or, more importantly, as rejected virtualities.
In their treatment of primitive and despotic societies in Anti-Oedipus,
and later in the separate but interconnected chapters of Thousand Plateaus
devoted to nomadology and the war machine, segmentarity, and apparatuses of capture, they give us a way to conceive different world populations in their respective social inscriptions. What emerges from these
pages, densely populated with more or less realistic characters, is a world
crisscrossed by innumerable political striations, where nothing is truly
impossible or, inversely, absolutely necessary. This is why not only history, but also anthropology, have been essential to the formulation of the
political theses of Capitalism and Schizophrenia. Far from being primitivist, the recourse to anthropology is essential in trying to assess the psychosocial constitution of todays collective becomings, such as those that
prompted a people to occupy public spaces in the Occupy movements.
Of course, one has to be careful: we are not talking here of the structural anthropology of Levi-Strauss, which is still excessively dependent
on an unrepresentable center the incest taboo, for instance for the
subsequent representation of family and social segmentarity emanating from it, but rather an account mediated to Deleuze and Guattari
by Pierre Clastres, a friend and contemporary of Flix Guattari and an
assiduous participant in Deleuzes seminars at Vincennes in the mid1970s. Before his premature death in 1978, Clastres had furthered in his
fieldwork some of Marshall Sahlins earlier discoveries: most notably, in
Stone Age Economics (1972), the Marxist anthropologist had reported
that many world populations were not frugal and stateless because of
scarcity and political primitivism, but as a consequence of an explicit
82
Giuseppina Mecchia
political decision, notably the unwillingness to engage in labor contracts and political representations. These were societies of abundance,
although they appeared destitute to bourgeois ethnocentrism (Sahlins
1974: 3). Sahlins arguments extended to politics: in these societies, the
political sphere is often unrecognizable to us simply because the political
function has not been reified by a bureaucratic apparatus, but has been
retained by the social body itself.
Clastres pushed Sahlins argument a step further: it is precisely
because the primitive society refuses the alienation of power that it also
prevents the accumulation of wealth on the part of one or several of its
members. Some primitive societies, therefore, invest their psychosocial
affects and productive energies in ways that are not pre- but anti-modern.
They are, in sum, fully communist, both economically and politically,
even if such a definition can appear Western-centered and anachronistic.
Furthermore, Clastres recognizes the very profound political motivation for the immense amount of technical and human effort that primitive societies devote to war. In many respects, war defines the community and, among other things, ensures one of the most common social
axiomatics, the one that defines specific gender roles. Additionally, war
allows the primitive subject to deal with death and other forms of natural
and cultural exteriorities.
Against all odds and maybe counter-intuitively, it is through war that
social subjects reaffirm themselves as free and autonomous within the
bounds of their collective organization and biological determinations.
Such an affirmation does not need to concern itself with the reality of
its claims: it just works, insofar as it ensures a certain kind of collective
organization. Even more importantly, Clastres shows how the primitive
socius was perfectly able to modulate its own apparently rigid dichotomies, such as male/female, warrior/mother, and so on. In certain cases,
he observed that some male subjects refused the ultra-masculine association with warrior societies, adopting a more domestic, village-bound
existence. Same-sex physical relations were also widely present, and were
accommodated in different manners, allowing for men to actually dress
as women and share in their occupations.
In other words, far from being rigid, blind, limited, anti-statist,
and anti-capitalist, communities were even able to decode their own
On Anthropolitics
83
84
Giuseppina Mecchia
On Anthropolitics
85
86
Giuseppina Mecchia
was and is about, and in this respect, if Capitalism and Schizophrenia can
indeed teach us anything, I deem it to be a good lesson.
Works Cited
Aug, Marc. 1999. An Anthropology for Contemporaneous Worlds. Stanford: Stanford
University Press.
Badiou, Alain. 2009. Logics of Worlds. London: Continuum.
Badiou, Alain. 2010. The Idea of Communism. In The Idea of Communism. Ed.
Costas Douzinas and Slavoj iek. London: Verso: 114.
Berardi, Franco Bifo. 2008. Interview with Giuseppina Mecchia, July 11 2005. In
Flix Guattari: Thought, Friendship and Visionary Cartography. London: Palgrave
2008: 14168.
Clastres, Pierre. 1989. Society Against the State: Essays in Political Anthropology.
Brooklyn: Zone Books.
Clastres, Pierre. 2010. Archeology of Violence. New York: Semiotext(e).
Deleuze Gilles and Guattari, Flix. 1987. A Thousand Plateaus: Capitalism and
Schizophrenia. Minneapolis and London: University of Minnesota Press.
Deleuze Gilles and Guattari, Flix. 2009. Anti-Oedipus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia.
London: Penguin Books.
Hallward, Peter. 2002. Absolutely Post-Colonial: Writing Between the Singular and the
Specific. Manchester: Manchester University Press.
Hallward, Peter. 2006. Out this World: Deleuze and the Philosophy of Creation. London:
Verso.Miller, Christopher L. 1993. The Post-Identitarian Predicament in the
Footnotes of A Thousand Plateaus: Nomadology, Anthropology and Authority.
Diacritics 23 (3): 635.
Patton, Paul. 2000. Deleuze and the Political. London: Routledge.
Rancire, Jacques. 2010. Communists Without Communism?. In The Idea of
Communism. Ed. Costas Douzinas and Slavoj iek. London: Verso: 16777.
Sahlins, Marshall. 1972. Stone Age Economics. Chicago: Aldine-Altherton.
Spivak, Gayatri. 1988. Can the Subaltern Speak?. In Marxism and the Interpretation
of Culture. Ed. Lawrence Grossberg and Cary Nelson. Urbana and Chicago:
University of Illinois Press: 271313.
Viveiros de Castro, Eduardo. 2010. The Untimely, Again. Introduction to Archeology
of Violence. Pierre Clastres. New York: Semiotext(e).
On Anthropolitics
87
Virno, Paolo. 2002. Quando il verbo si fa carne: Linguaggio e natura umana. Torino:
Bollati Boringhieri.
Notes
1.
The acronym for Lesbian, Bisexual, Gay and Transgendered people did not
exist at the time. However, it is in the late 1970s and in the 1980s thanks in
part to another crisis, the AIDS health emergency that these groups entered
the sociopolitical scene on the footsteps of the receding feminist wave.
2.
3.
Chapter 2
Housecleaning
The Occupy movement shows us how the semantic, pragmatic, and affective meaning, action, and feeling are intertwined in all collective practices. The intertwining of the semantic and the pragmatic what we say
and what we accomplish in that saying has been a topic of interest in the
humanities and the critical social sciences for almost 50 years, since its
thematization by Austin and its codification in speech act theory; widespread interest in affect has been more recent, but the interplay of its twin
roots in Tompkins and Deleuze producing a sort of evo-neuro-Spinozism has been usefully explored in The Affect Theory Reader (Gregg and
Seigworth 2010). Its now time to bring speech act theory and affect theory together in understanding the role of political affect (Protevi 2009)
in the Occupy movement.
To do that, well need some housecleaning. The first thing that needs
to go is the concept of ideology. Deleuze and Guattari say in A Thousand
Plateaus: Ideology is a most execrable concept concealing all of the
effectively operating social machines (Deleuze and Guattari 1987: 68).
I take that to mean that we have to thematize political affect to understand effectively operating social machines. From this perspective, the
real German ideology is that ideas are where its at, rather than affect. Its
political affect that makes men fight for their servitude as stubbornly as
though it were their salvation.
89
90
John Protevi
a different social ontology would have to start from the presumption that
there is a shared condition of precarity that situates our political lives.
A brief excerpt from the beginning of Butlers Venice talk sets out
some of the main lines of thought that would go toward this different
social ontology:
assembly and speech reconfigure the materiality of public
space, and produce, or reproduce, the public character of that
material environment. And when crowds move outside the
square, to the side street or the back alley, to the neighborhoods where streets are not yet paved, then something more
happens. At such a moment, politics is no longer defined as
the exclusive business of public sphere distinct from a private
one, but it crosses that line again and again, bringing attention
to the way that politics is already in the home, or on the street,
or in the neighborhood, or indeed in those virtual spaces
that are unbound by the architecture of the public square.
(Butler 2011b)
But in the case of public assemblies, we see quite clearly not only that
there is a struggle over what will be public space, but a struggle as well
over those basic ways in which we are, as bodies, supported in the world
a struggle against disenfranchisement, effacement, and abandonment.
The role of the body in social ontology need not be limited to shared
precarity, however, as important as that is to emphasize in order to break
down notions of individuals as disembodied bundles of rights. We can
also think the positive affective contribution of public assemblies. In this
case, the city government of New York unwittingly helped OWS tap into
the affective potential of collective bodies politic. Im talking here about
the human microphone, which works, quite literally, to amplify the constitution of political space by assembled bodies.
The human microphone thus offers an entry into examining political
affect in the enacting of the phrase We the People at OWS. It shows us
how direct democracy is enacted by producing an intermodal resonance
among the semantic, pragmatic, and affective dimensions of collective
action. It also shows how the production of contemporary neoliberal subjects (homo economicus as self-entrepreneur, as individual rational utility
91
92
John Protevi
(collective rhythm). In her Venice talk Butler analyzes the Tahrir Square
chant translated as peacefully, peacefully in these terms:
Secondly, when up against violent attack or extreme threats,
many people chanted the word silmiyya which comes from
the root verb (salima) which means to be safe and sound,
unharmed, unimpaired, intact, safe, and secure; but also, to
be unobjectionable, blameless, faultless; and yet also, to be
certain, established, clearly proven. The term comes from the
noun silm which means peace but also, interchangeably and
significantly, the religion of Islam. One variant of the term
is Hubb as-silm which is Arabic for pacifism. Most usually,
the chanting of Silmiyya comes across as a gentle exhortation: peaceful, peaceful. Although the revolution was for the
most part non-violent, it was not necessarily led by a principled opposition to violence. Rather, the collective chant was
a way of encouraging people to resist the mimetic pull of military aggression and the aggression of the gangs by keeping in mind the larger goal radical democratic change. To
be swept into a violent exchange of the moment was to lose
the patience needed to realize the revolution. What interests
me here is the chant, the way in which language worked not
to incite an action, but to restrain one. A restraint in the name
of an emerging community of equals whose primary way of
doing politics would not be violence. (Butler 2011b)
This is an insightful, eloquent analysis of the pragmatics and semantics
of the chant. So its not to undercut it that I call attention to the material
dimension of the resonating bodies that accompany the semantic content
and pragmatic implications of this chant. Its to point to the way in which
an analysis of material rhythms reveals the political affect of joyous collectivity, and the intermodal (semantic, pragmatic, affective) resonance
such chanting produces.
93
94
John Protevi
95
Ostrom, Elinor. 2005. Policies that Crowd out Reciprocity and Collective Action.
In Moral Sentiments and Material Interests: The Foundations of Cooperation in
Economic Life. Ed. Herbert Gintis, Samuel Bowles, Robert Boyd, and Ernst Fehr.
Cambridge: MIT Press: 25375.
Protevi, John. 2009. Political Affect: Connecting the Social and the Somatic. Minneapolis:
University of Minnesota Press.
Protevi, John. 2010. Adding Deleuze to the Mix. Phenomenology and the Cognitive
Sciences 9 (3): 41736.
Ristic, Igor. 2011. The Human Microphone #OccupiesWallStreet.
Communicationblog.net. Accessed November 5, 2011 from: http://igorristic.
wordpress.com/2011/10/11/the-human-microphone-occupieswallstreet/
Trevarthen, Colwyn. 1979. Communication and Cooperation in Infancy: A
Description of Primary Intersubjectivity. In Before Speech: The Beginning of
Interpersonal Communication. Ed. Margaret Bullows. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Notes
1.
There are many ways of relating cognition and emotion, without even
bringing in the relations of this analytic vocabulary with that of the
Husserlian noesis/noema scheme. Still, I hope this will suffice just to get some
traction on the problem.
2.
When I was unemployed, some 15 years ago, for six months, I was often
overcome with shame, no matter how often I reminded myself of the objective
factors, the nonsensical nature of the affect, etc. But where did I pick up this
shame? I cant see how it was transmitted to me by another actual instance
of shame. You could say I had been socialized so that I carried a latent
disposition to shame that became occurent in the right circumstances. But
thats hardly less metaphysical than an account of virtual or environmental
collective affective with shamed selves crystallized out of that. I dont think
well escape metaphysics that easily; theres a lot of potential versus actual
metaphysics to be worked out there in the latent versus occurent disposition
scheme, as I try to do in Protevi 2010.
3.
Another topic for analysis would be the bike generators being set up at OWS.
In another possible blunder, recalling that of the banning of bullhorns, the
city confiscated gasoline generators prior to the late October snowstorm. The
brilliant OWS response was to acquire bicycle generators. Will there be an
analogous affective supplement from taking turns on the bikes to generate
electricity?
96
John Protevi
4.
5.
6.
Many thanks to The New APPS Blog, authors and commenters alike, for help
with this essay.
Chapter 3
The issue of leadership is one of several overlaps that have been spotted
between the thought of Deleuze and Guattari and the movements that
arose in 2011 a heady year that began in late 2010 with the English student movement, saw the emergence of the Arab Spring, Spains 15M, the
English riots, Occupy Wall Street, and continued into 2012 with Mexicos
Yo Soy 132 movement, among others. Whether it is because of a debt
to anarchism (Graeber 2011), because networking and web 2.0 are like
second nature to most participants, or because their acute awareness of
the crisis of representative politics spills over into distrust of any form of
representation, these movements have tended to eschew leaders, spokespeople and fixed structures beyond open assemblies and working groups.
In doing so, they have been widely perceived as subscribing to a logic that
Deleuze and Guattari describe as rhizomatic (open, mutable, horizontal,
spontaneously organized) as opposed to arborescent (closed, fixed, vertical, structured).
In what follows, I argue that this is not the whole picture. As much
as a closer reading of Deleuze and Guattari makes any simple opposition between rhizomatic and arborescent more complex, a more attentive examination of these movements shows that they are not entirely
free from phenomena of leadership and representation. This does not
mean that they are at fault in any way, failing to meet some standard of
openness and horizontality, or are somehow disingenuous. On the contrary, it is the idea of such a standard, or the notion that organization and
98
Rodrigo Nunes
organizational form necessarily denote hierarchies and vertical structures, that Deleuze and Guattari can help us put into question. Rather
than disproving the overlap between their philosophy and these movements, then, we can actually discover a deeper, more complex connection that helps shed light on how these movements work and some ways
in which they could transform their practice.
This essays first two parts are dedicated to showing how phenomena of leadership, vanguard and representation manifest themselves in
contemporary movements, arguing that these are not just residues of a
representative politics to be overcome, but an unavoidable aspect of politics itself. In particular, I will draw on Deleuze and Guattaris distinction
between the crowd and the pack to argue that these movements, rather
than leaderless, display what could be called distributed leadership. In the
third, I will develop some consequences of this by showing how the relation between spontaneity and organization must be rendered complex,
and how distributed leadership calls for thinking organization in terms
of complementarity. In the last section, I argue that Deleuze and Guattaris
concept of becoming-imperceptible offers a key with which to think the
organizational and strategic tasks facing these movements today.
I. Synecdoche Wall Street
One of the reasons why movements like the Arab Spring, 15M and
Occupy are seen as bypassing representation and leadership lies in their
relation to mass organizations. For much of the nineteenth and twentieth
centuries, mass organizations were a pillar of radical or progressive politics. Forming, maintaining and perfecting them were indispensable steps
towards social transformation; their development was both a condition
for, and the material substrate of, the historical movement of social transformation itself. Mass organizations were burgeoning class consciousness
in externalized, materialized form; what gave that consciousness a visible
face and a cadre that could spread it. Mass organizations were something
like a collective memory device, whose very body registered its development: the tactics that worked, the mistakes that cost dearly, the victorious lines, the individuals who had acquired greater experience and prestige. As such, they were indispensable to a collective learning process that
Pack of Leaders
99
proceeded towards ever greater unification: organization by trade leading to organizations uniting workers across trades, and then to a party
through which the class could represent itself politically, in parliament
and outside it.
By contrast, most important mass movements since the late 1990s
have gone without or even against mass organizations, or involved
them in minor roles. This is partly because of the historical crisis of leftwing parties and trade unions, and the broader crisis of representative
politics. While the emancipatory movements of really existing socialism
became exploitative and oppressive regimes, parties and trade unions in
countries where socialism did not win not only manifested the same
problems to variable degrees (authoritarianism, lack of accountability,
bureaucratization), they often effectively worked to stymie social mobilization and radical demands. This process, already visible in the post-war
welfare state and national liberation struggles, became more acute with
the neoliberal restructuring from the late 1970s onwards.
This is where the crisis of representation in the left opens onto the
crisis of representative politics in general, in response to which protesters
around the world have risen in recent years. Most mature democracies
have effectively become two-party systems where both parties represent
essentially the same interests, so that the key political antagonism today is
between the overrepresented (the 1% with disproportionate economic
and political clout) and the under- or unrepresented (everyone else, the
99%). Whereas from the 1940s to the 1970s the welfare state was, in the
global North at least, the gravitational center of politics, and the political system offered a more or less accurate representation of the two key
opposing forces capital and (stable, Fordist, industrial, unionized) labor
neoliberalism functions less as a point of equilibrium than as a naturalized, almost invisible background. As a result, the options on the table
tend to be only slight variations on the same formula, tailored to cater for
the small interest groups which, in a context of indifference generated by
the lack of real options, decide whether an election goes this or that way.
While no doubt far from the extremes of Egypt or Tunisia, even the best
Western democracies are mired in cronyism and elite rule. This is what
has been dramatically laid bare by the crisis begun in 2008. It is hardly
surprising that contemporary movements should bypass, even avoid
100
Rodrigo Nunes
mass organizations, when the parties and unions that historically represented the working class are equally implicated in the crisess causes and
results, helping usher the bailouts and austerity measures with which
governments have made populations pay the ransom exacted by finance.
This subjective rejection is, however, not a sufficient cause for how
they have developed. We must add to it an objective condition, the widespread access to means of production and diffusion of information, of
which the material substrate is above all the internet. It may be true that
drums, fires, incendiary tracts, running down the backstreets, word-ofmouth, ringing bells (Badiou 2011: 39) were for centuries what mobilized masses of people; but just hurriedly dismissing Facebook and other
such nonsense of alleged technical innovation (Badiou 2011: 39) we risk
missing the quantitative and qualitative differences that our technological conditions represent.
Quantitatively, they vastly increase both the potential reach of calls to
action and the information on which they are based, as well as the speed
of their spread across networks; not only do they generate more instant
connections among a greater number of people, they create connections among people and groups that are distant from each other, to some
extent transcending the requirement of physical proximity. Qualitatively,
they create a continuous background of exchange of information, participation and collaboration beyond the limits of physical proximity (neighborhoods, workplaces, countries) and belonging (to a political organization, a movement, an ethnicity). Under certain special conditions, this
can scale up in unpredictably big and fast ways, and move from the virtual
environment into the real world.1 For that same reason, social technologies also provide a sort of continuous schooling in networked organization, so that it appears as the natural organizing logic for most people
living in the landscape created by these technological transformations.
Consequently, less open and flexible, less collaborative and participatory
logics will tend to be seen with suspicion.
If we abstract too quickly from specifics in search of universal, transhistorical constants we end up treating material media as indifferent and
interchangeable, as if the internet and drums were just instruments to do
the same thing, and our materialism becomes impoverished. However,
we can find a first approach to questions of leadership in one of the eternal
Pack of Leaders
101
102
Rodrigo Nunes
Pack of Leaders
103
part (communists) that shows others the way (other working-class parties); yet this movement or process, taken as a whole, expands by attracting those around it (the great mass of the proletariat and fractions of
other classes).
While retaining these two different moments, vanguard is used here
in a way that differs from the orthodox Marxist idea in a crucial aspect. So
as to get to this difference, let us first go through Deleuze and Guattaris
analysis of two different logics of group function identified, following
Elias Canetti, as the crowd and the pack.4
The crowd is characterized by large quantity, the divisibility and
equality of number, concentration unitary hierarchical direction, the
organisation of territoriality or territorialisation; the pack, in turn, by
small or restricted numbers, dispersion qualitative metamorphoses,
inequalities as remainders or thresholds, the impossibility of a fixed totalisation or hierarchisation, the Brownian variation of directions, the lines
of deterritorialisation (Deleuze and Guattari 2004: 46).5 The distinction
between the two is projected directly onto that between the arborescent
and the rhizomatic and, as with the latter,
[t]he point is not to oppose the two types of multiplicities
() according to a dualism that would not be worth more
than that of One and multiple. There are only multiplicities of
multiplicities that constitute a single assemblage, that operate
in the same assemblage: packs in crowds, and vice-versa. Trees
have rhizomatic lines, but the rhizome has points of arborescence. (Deleuze and Guattari 2004: 47; italics in the original).
In other words, these are oppositions in thought that in reality only ever
occur in a mixed state (Deleuze and Guattari 2004: 593). They indicate
two tendencies present in every assemblage, and two frames of reference
according which to analyse them, depending on whether we look at them
from the point of view of already given differences (and identities) or
understand [them] in intensity (Deleuze and Guattari 2004: 44). And
while Deleuze and Guattari (2004: 31) oppose the arborescent and the
rhizomatic not as two models, but as something acting as a model
even if it produces its own flights, and something acting as an immanent
process that upsets the model even if it produces its own hierarchies,
104
Rodrigo Nunes
Pack of Leaders
105
298) call the cutting edge of deterritorialisation of a situation or grouping that part which, having started to function in a different way, opens
a new direction that, after it has communicated to others, can become
something to follow, divert, resist (or imitate, oppose and adapt, as per
Gabriel Tardes three social laws).6 The vanguard-function is objective in
the sense that, once the change it introduces has propagated, it can be
identified as the anomalous cause behind a growing number of effects.
Yet it is not objective in the traditional Marxist sense of a deterministic
or transitive relation between an objectively defined position (class, class
sector etc.) and the occurrence of a subjective political breakthrough
(event), itself underpinned by a conception of history as following necessary laws. Where a process starts, which direction it takes, who steers or
diverts it, what is its course these can be determined retrospectively,
but never in advance. While it is no doubt possible to hazard more or
less educated guesses (depending on how well one can read the symptoms announcing potential events), there are no laws behind this. It is
only in this objective but non-transitive sense that the Arab Spring, 15M,
Occupy etc. can be called vanguards.
We can now extend this concept beyond the synecdoche between
these movements and the rest of society to its second moment, the
vanguard (or vanguards) within the vanguard. What changes the packs
course is an animal pulling the group in one direction and the rest suddenly following it, changing the groups shape and structure as they do.
It is not the case that the pack is leaderless, then, but the opposite: every
member is a potential leader. And this, rather than an ideal of horizontality that would amount to no less than absolute equality, is what best
defines the way in which the movements of the last few years organize.
Distributed leadership, not assemblies or horizontality, is their defining
trait.7 If the pack is the degree zero of collectivity, and distributed leadership is the kind of organization proper to it, we can conclude that distributed leadership is the degree zero of organization. That would no doubt
be true; at the same time, it is important that we appreciate the extent
to which contemporary communication technology expands the potential for it.
When crowd and pack are contrasted according to large and small
numbers, as Deleuze and Guattari do, this should be understood less in
106
Rodrigo Nunes
Pack of Leaders
107
108
Rodrigo Nunes
the occasional leader of the pack is said to be a vector of deterritorialization, itself following a movement that was already present at least in
potential, a creator or originator only in being the first to grasp it. In
order to better understand this, it is worth taking the time to unpack what
Deleuze and Guattari mean by events, the generic term that they ascribe
to such spontaneous changes in direction.
Events have a complicated structure. The same event happens on different levels and, in a way, more than once; it is at once a discontinuity
concentrated on a point and a continuous process, an eventing that happens over time. To begin with, for any event there will be several layers
of causality at play; these will be, for example, a series of long-held grievances, a history of collective frustrations and personal humiliations, etc.
At this point, however, those under the effect of these causes will still
be operating within a pre-defined space of possibilities that constrains
what reactions are imaginable: the situation itself cannot be overcome,
although there may be individual routes of negotiating it (small acts of
transgression, escapist compensation, episodes of acting out, opportunistic collaboration, etc.). Something boils under the surface, but there is
no way it could emerge; acting on it does not even appear as a possibility
yet. Then, however, a new cause may act as a catalyst, focusing the existing layers of causality on a point, and a virtual threshold is crossed new
dispositions and potentials emerge, accompanied by a transformation in
sensibility: the situation is now perceived as intolerable. In a sense, the
event has already happened; the field of possibilities expands, and even
rational calculations change just yesterday you were wondering how
long you could extend a cigarette break, now you are asking yourself how
to organize a walk out.
The event is a rupture, firstly, because it is an excess over its causes,
a break with linearity, a bifurcation, a deviation in regard to laws, an
unstable state (Deleuze and Guattari 2003: 215). It is unpredictable in
advance and only appears as possible after the fact: as much as one can
and must assign in the causal series the objective factors that made such a
rupture possible only what belongs to the order of desire and its irruption can account for the reality that [this rupture of causality] acquires at
that moment, in that place (Deleuze and Guattari 2005: 453). Secondly,
it creates new possibilities, which in a sense makes it a necessary given for
Pack of Leaders
109
what comes afterwards: an event can be countered, repressed, recuperated, betrayed, it nonetheless cannot be surpassed: it is an opening of
possibles (Deleuze and Guattari 2005: 453).
This is the event as pure becoming, a virtual transformation
abstracted or subtracted from actual states; but the event is not just a
pure becoming, it is also a becoming something else. A virtual mutation
must be followed by an actualising mutation (Zourabichvli 2000: 344),
which is the means through which a shift in sensibility is given a form:
new words, acts, behaviors, the actual and perceptible inscription of a virtual and sensible change in bodies and assemblages. It is through them
that the event actually takes place, transforming the world around it, and
is communicated. It may be that only a few have crossed the threshold, but
once they change, that change can be shared.
This is how the event, which has already happened once in a virtual
mutation and twice in the creation of new individuations, can happen
many more times as it spreads. But this means that spontaneity is not,
as is often thought, the absence of any form; on the contrary, the events
actualizing side is precisely the passage from formlessness to (new) form.
Gilbert Simondon (2005: 549), whose philosophy of individuation profoundly influenced Deleuze, draws an explicit comparison between a
metastable state of supersaturation, in which an event is ready to take
place, or a structure ready to emerge, and a pre-revolutionary one: all
it takes is for a structural germ [germe structural] to appear. An actualizing mutation (a perceptible change in behavior, practices, relations) is
such a structural germ: a new form that spreads across a field that is ripe
for the event even if, while the event is still eventing, not exhausted
in its potential, this new form is far from fixed, and rather than being a
model to be consciously imitated or rejected, it is communicated and
propagates through changes in sensibility.10 Here we see the correlation
between event and subject: it is when history tips over into meaninglessness, literally breaks the norm and creates something new, that the
subject comes onto the scene, bringing everything into doubt and producing a new utterance, an operation of the signifier as expression of a
meaning, a possible split in a given order, a breach, a revolution, a cry
for radical reorientation (Guattari 1984: 175). Yet this subject is not an
autonomous, sovereign agent, but the way in which the event expresses
110
Rodrigo Nunes
itself. It exists to the extent that it affirms the event, as much as the event
exists only because it expresses itself in this subject. [T]he event creates
a new existence, it produces a new subjectivity (Deleuze and Guattari
2003: 216), but not as a cause external to its effects; it is in producing such
transformations that the event events. The subject is therefore what constitutes itself around the feeling that a rupture has taken place (it cannot go on like before), and must respond to the event by forming new
collective assemblages that correspond to the new subjectivity (Deleuze
and Guattari 2003: 216).
Thus, if we still speak of spontaneity a discontinuity, an excess over
causes, a break with existing constraints and the previously mapped
space of possibilities it is neither as a free creation nor as an absence of
form. The event expresses an expansion of freedom and contingency, not
an elimination of all constraints, and is inseparable from the structural
germs that, in giving it viable forms, actualize it.11 We can therefore see
why there is no contradiction in speaking of spontaneity and distributed
leadership. In fact, we can easily track the emergence of recent movements by observing how a few spontaneously created forms, in propagating across networks, brought those very movements into existence: the
protests in Sidi Bouzid around Mohamed Bouazizis suicide mushrooming into protests across Tunisia, as the first cries of Step down, Ben Ali
were heard; the camps that spread from Tahrir Square to the Maghreb and
Mashreq, then to Spain, Israel, the US and around the world; the original
Adbusters Occupy Wall Street meme, taken seriously by activists who
started organizing around the idea, until its replication across the US.
What these examples also show is that, even if there is a sense in which
the event is a rupture out of the blue, in its becoming, it escapes history (Deleuze and Negri 2007: 231), there is nothing magical or ethereal about it. On the contrary, it demands work; to say that propagation
happens at a virtual or sensible level does not make its conditions any
less material. The examples above make it evident that the various vanguards (several of them for each movement) had to spend a fair amount
of time honing their messages, building alliances, creating the necessary
channels and platforms (face-to-face meetings, Facebook pages, websites,
Twitter and Youtube accounts etc.), organizing protests, producing and
circulating videos, images, texts, memes.12 There is a much more complex
Pack of Leaders
111
interplay between spontaneity and organization than a simple opposition between the two would allow. On the one hand, the tactics that succeeded in producing large-scale outbursts generally did so because they
were sufficiently open-ended, inclusive and adaptable to allow people to
become involved in their own terms and through progressive steps, rather
than having to conform to a predefined activist style and identity overnight. Some have described this as open code activism in comparison
to open code software.13 On the other hand, if it were not for a backbone
of committed activists working from the early days, many of which had
years of political experience behind them and belonged to pre-existing
groups and networks, these movements would not have turned out the
way they did. The fantasy of thousands of entirely unconnected individuals magically turning up at the same place at the same time is simply a
myth; the reality is closer to a continuous eventing in which small vanguards slowly built up (and others no doubt withered), until the event
irrupted in full force on the streets. A series of small, ever growing synecdoches, leading to that sudden, exponentially larger synecdoche that
Badiou calls contraction.
If we understand spontaneity as formlessness, it is easy to slip into
imagining organization as its total opposite the fixation of a rigid form,
the party. It is certainly common that unreconstructed Leninists pay lip
service to a certain right to spontaneity in a first moment (Deleuze 2004:
278), but only as a transitional manifestation that must be left behind for
a superior phase, marked by the setting-up of centralist organisations
(Guattari 1984c: 66). But the problem also works the other way round: a
paranoid fear of organization, too sharp a distinction between the good,
spontaneous moment (which belonged to everyone) and the bad,
transcendent one (in which some people tried to take control) can
block the way to necessary new creations. Understanding spontaneity as
the creation and propagation of new form, on the other hand, poses a different set of problems than any binary choice between either spontaneity or organization: what forms to propose, what forms to select, which
forms to connect to.
There are, of course, many steps between selecting some incipient forms that manifest themselves in actions, conducts, discourses
etc., and developing organizational consistency (more clearly defined
112
Rodrigo Nunes
Pack of Leaders
113
114
Rodrigo Nunes
Pack of Leaders
115
the Guy Fawkes mask worn by Alan Moores V, a sort of fictional forerunner of Marcos.
At the same time, it is clear that one cannot be anonymous forever.
Even if we do not know Marcos face, he is still identifiable as an EZLN
leader, and while the individuals in Anonymous may remain anonymous,
the collectivity called Anonymous itself cannot. If the vanguard-function leads, it inevitably becomes recognizable, even if only as something
like a Twitter alias. Besides, there is an important difference between the
localized kind of intervention that acts as a catalyst for a protest and the
more continuous, long-term work of a campaign or group. In the latter
case, becoming identifiable is unavoidable, and it is more likely that, however informal an organizational format might be, internal structures and
leadership figures will emerge.
Another of Deleuze and Guattaris concepts may help us think beyond
the limits of invisibility and anonymity: becoming-imperceptible.24 At
first, the three may seem synonymous, or becoming-imperceptible can
sound like the opposite of acting or leading. I would like to suggest, however, that it offers ways of thinking how to act and lead better, rather than
not at all. The first thing to stress about the concept is that it refers to
a kind of action. Although initially defined as becoming like everyone/
the whole world [tout le monde] (Deleuze and Guattari 2004: 342), it
is poorly understood if treated as mere inaction or going with the flow.
To begin with, one actively strives to become imperceptible, choosing
to suppress everything that prevented us from slipping between things
(Deleuze and Guattari 2004: 344); one takes a step back from a constituted position (my group, my beliefs, myself) facing other constituted
positions so as to become attuned to their common background: their
virtual or unconscious conditions and the potentials present in the situation. It is a striving to place oneself in the position of the anomalous element that is a packs vector of deterritorialization, of which Deleuze and
Guattari (2004: 299) say that it is neither an individual nor a species
and has neither familiar nor subjectified feelings, nor specific or significant characteristics, but only affects.
This means neither an elimination of the self nor the attainment of
an objective, Gods-eye perspective on the whole. It is true that Deleuze
and Guattari (2004: 348) speak of a plane of consistency or immanence
116
Rodrigo Nunes
Pack of Leaders
117
118
Rodrigo Nunes
that of maintaining continuity, let alone assuming or producing homogeneity. Divisions exist between the 1% and the 99%, the over- and
the under-represented, white and non-white, majorities and minoritarian
becomings etc. , and overcoming them will more often than not require
asserting their existence and creating new ones.
To the extent that events are ruptures, and that one seeks potentials
in order to elicit and propagate events, becoming imperceptible is part
of intervening so as to create ruptures; it is a moment in the hard work of
eventing. The question is what ruptures to produce, and how where to
draw the lines, in which direction to move, how to retain enough openness, where to be divisive and where inclusive, when to go with the flow
and when to interrupt it. Sometimes, attempting to push things beyond
the vaguest agreement will result in a process implosion or ones own
isolation; if new ruptures are to be created, one will have to wait, to be
flexible, to read the mood. In other cases, a spontaneous action that initially garnered little consensus can produce a widely shared qualitative
change for example, the way in which the storming of Conservative
party headquarters in London galvanised the UK student movement of
2011 (cf. The Free Association 2011).
This shows that neither maintaining continuity or asserting division
can be turned into categorical imperatives for political action. Whether
continuity or division is preferable is a badly posed problem. Properly
political (that is, practical) problems are always a matter of what continuity, what division, when, how, how much. The experimental character
of becoming-imperceptible, its reference to a specific process or situation, highlights this. By the same token, it indicates that the point of an
intervention is not itself, but what it does: one intervenes not in order to
assert oneself or the correctness of ones position, but in order to produce
effects. There is no advantage to respecting differences if that only means
that existing differences will remain the same; nothing is gained from
asserting division if all it does is divide us from everyone else. It is key
to the idea of an open code activism that revolutions should be come
as you are affairs; but they will not have been revolutions if they do not
result in leaving as you were not. The whole point of political practice is
what happens in the middle, and how to make it happen.
Pack of Leaders
119
Works Cited
Badiou, Alain. 2011. Le Rveil de lHistoire. Paris: Lignes.
Brighenti, Andrea Mubi. 2010. Tarde, Canetti, and Deleuze on Crowds and Packs.
Journal of Classical Sociology 10: 292315.
Canetti, Elias. 1981. Crowds and Power. Trans. Carol Stewart. New York: Continuum.
Comit Invisible. Nos Amis. Paris: La Fabrique.
Dean, Jodi. 2012. The Communist Horizon. London: Verso.
Deleuze, Gilles. 2004. Trois problmes de groupe. In LIle dserte. Textes et entretiens
19521974. Paris: Minuit: 270284.
Deleuze, Gilles and Flix Guattari. 2003. Mai 68 na pas eu lieu. In Deux rgimes de
fous. Textes et entretiens 19751995. Paris: Minuit: 21520.
Deleuze, Gilles and Flix Guattari. 2004. Mille Plateaux. Paris: Minuit.
Deleuze, Gilles and Flix Guattari. 2005. LAnti-Oedipe. Paris: Minuit.
Deleuze, Gilles and Tony Negri. 2007. T Contrle et devenir. In Pourparlers. Paris:
Minuit 2007: 22939.
Deleuze, Gilles and Claire Parnet. 2004. G comme gauche. In Abcedaire. Paris:
Montparnasse.
The Free Association. 2011. On Fairy-dust and Rupture. Accessed May 2, 2015
from: http://freelyassociating.org/on-fairy-dust-and-rupture/
Graeber, David. 2004. The Twilight of Vanguardism. In World Social Forum:
Challenging Empires. Ed. Jai Sen and Peter Waterman. New Delhi: Viveka
Foundation: 32935.
Graeber, David. 2011. Occupy Wall Streets Anarchist Roots. Al Jazeera.
Accessed May 3, 2015 from: http://www.aljazeera.com/indepth/
opinion/2011/11/2011112872835904508.html
Guattari, Flix. 1984. Molecular Revolution: Psychiatry and Politics. Trans. David
Cooper and Rosemary Sheed. Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Guattari, Flix. 2006. The Anti-Oedipus Papers. Ed. Stphane Nadaud. Trans. Klina
Gotman. Los Angeles/New York: Semiotext(e).
Guattari, Flix. 2009a. Institutional Intervention. In Soft Subversions: Texts and
Interviews 19771985. Ed. Sylvre Lotringer. Trans. Emily Wittmam. Cambridge:
Semiotext(e)/MIT Press: 3363.
120
Rodrigo Nunes
Guattari, Flix. 2009b. The Unconscious is Turned Towards the Future. In Soft
Subversions: Texts and Interviews 19771985. Ed. Sylvre Lotringer. Trans. Arthur
Evans and John Johnston. Cambridge: Semiotext(e)/MIT Press: 17783.
Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm. The Principles of Philosophy, or the Monadology, In
Philosophical Essays. Ed. and trans. Roger Ariew and Daniel Garber. Indianapolis:
Hackett: 213-25.
Malo, Marta. 2011. Sol, o Cuando lo Imposible Se Vuelve Imparable.
Madrilonia. Accessed May 3, 2015 from: http://madrilonia.org/2011/05/
sol-o-cuando-lo-imposible-se-vuelve-imparable/
Marx, Karl and Friedrich Engels. 2001. The Communist Manifesto. In Karl Marx:
Selected Writings. Ed. David MacLellan. Oxford: Oxford University Press: 24572.
Nunes, Rodrigo. 2013. Notes Towards a Rethinking of the Militant. In Communism
in the Twenty-First Century, vol. 3. Ed. Shannon Brincat. Santa Barbara: Praeger.
Nunes, Rodrigo. 2014. Organisation of the Organisationless. Collective Action after
Networks. London: Mute/PML Books.
Nunes, Rodrigo. Forthcoming 2016. The Network Prince: Leadership between
Clastres and Machiavelli. International Journal of Communication 10.
Simondon, Gilbert. 2005. Forme, Information, Potentiels. In Lindividuation la
lumire des notions de forme et dinformation. Grenoble: Jerme Millon: 53151.
Tarde, Gabriel. 2002. Les Lois Sociales. Paris: Institut Synthlabo,
Thoburn, Nick. 2010. Weatherman, the Militant Diagram, and the Problem of
Political Passion. New Formations 68: 12340.
Toret, Javier. 2013. No es la revolucin Facebook o Twitter, es una nueva capacidad
tecnopoltica. Madrilonia. Accessed May 3, 2015 from: http://madrilonia.
org/2013/04/no-es-la-revolucion-facebook-o-twitter-es-una-nueva-capacidadtecnopolitica-entrevistamos-a-toret/
Viveiros de Castro, Eduardo. 2009. Mtaphysiques cannibales. Paris: PUF.
iek, Slavoj. 2009. The Parallax View. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Zourabichvili, Franois. 2000. Deleuze e o possvel (sobre o involuntarismo na
poltica). In Gilles Deleuze: uma vida filosfica. Ed. Eric Alliez. So Paulo: Editora
34: 33355.
Pack of Leaders
121
Notes
1.
Javier Toret (2013) notes that, while the nodes more connected to the
explosion of the movement became weaker, a remarkable flow of interaction
and daily work has remained, being occasionally reactivated by the
connection with circles that are less internal to the process through new
(even if smaller) events that make social malaises transversal with network
processes, and thus are re-actualisations of the 15M DNA. This leads him to
distinguish four moments of the 15M process: gestation, explosion and birth
of the network-system, globalisation (including Occupy and the October 15,
2011 day of action) and evolution, development and mutation.
2.
Pays profond, in the sense that one speaks, for example of the United States
deep south.
3.
This helps explain the appeal that activists of a radical libertarian and
egalitarian bent sometimes find in a certain millenarianism: thinking
a radical change that happens at once (brought about, for example, by
ecological collapse) allows us to bypass all the dangers (the formation
of leaders and hierarchies, compromise) and the daunting work of a
transformation taking place over time.
4.
5.
122
Rodrigo Nunes
(Deleuze and Guattari 2005: 470 et seq.). Later in his life, Guattari (2009a:
48) would claim: I no longer have much faith in the specificity of the group,
and I would even say that I believe less and less in the existence of the group
as an entity I would like to start from a much more inclusive, perhaps more
vague, notion of assemblage. Cf. also Guattari (2009b: 179): Ive changed
my mind: there are no subject-groups, but arrangements of enunciation,
of subjectivization, pragmatic arrangements that do not coincide with
circumscribed groups.
6.
7.
8.
Again, this does not mean that people are always really free under control,
but that the constraints put on their actions (which elicit and modulate as
much as repress and prohibit them) never fully determine their content. It is
to the extent that their actions are underdetermined that they are free, not
only to operate under those constraints but also, under certain conditions, to
change the constraints themselves.
9.
While I am staying close to the animal metaphor here, it should be clear that
this need not be an individual; the cutting edge of deterritorialization could
be a group, a new material relation, a human/non-human assemblage etc.
10. Cf. Simondon (2005: 544): There can be no taking of form [prise de
forme] without two conditions coming together: a tension of information,
contributed by a structural germ, and the energy imprisoned by the milieu
that begins to take form; the milieu must be in a metastable, tense state,
like a solution in supersaturation or superfusion, so as to pass into a stable
state by liberating the imprisoned energy through the structuring work of the
structural germ.
11. Guattari (1984: 1723) introduces the concept of coefficient of transversality
to speak of the degree of freedom and contingency, or openness and
indeterminacy and the capacity to become aware of and manage them in a
group or institutional situation.
12. This point is further developed in Nunes (forthcoming).
13. I have heard the expression on three separate occasions from friends involved
in the Spanish 15M movement.
14. On organization thought as a continuum, cf. Nunes (forthcoming).
15. That initiatives should be based on political wagers means that they
should arise from strategic appraisals of the situation rather than mere
personal preference. Cf. Dean (2012: 228): fearful of excluding potential
opportunities, Occupy tried early on to avoid confronting fundamental
divisions within the movement. () The effect, though, was to reduce
Pack of Leaders
123
division to forking (in other words, to sublimate it). People pursued their own
projects, perpetually splitting according to their prior interests and expertise.
16. Other forms of implicitly teleological discourses that exist in the orbit of
contemporary movements include a certain historical and technological
optimism that places contemporary movements in a struggle between
the old (representative democracy, rigid structures, hierarchy, monopoly,
proprietary code) and the new (real democracy, networks, decentralization,
participation, open code), in which the victory of the new over the old would
be assured by the arrow of time, rather than seen as the very object of the
struggle; and an appeal to a generic humanity seen not as the outcome of a
struggle to overcome social antagonisms, as in the Marxist account, but as
an underlying reality veiled by divisions, ideologies, antagonisms etc., and
therefore the object of a spontaneous self-reflexive awakening. Once the veils
are lifted, the idea goes, it is inevitable that we see ourselves as essentially
equal, and so inevitably bound to agree on the basics of how society is to be
run. I develop the critique of positing a transcendence of the process over
agents in Nunes (2013).
17. The problem of organization appears then as profoundly Leibnizian:
obtaining as much variety as possible, but with the greatest order possible
(Leibniz, 1989, 58).
18. Deleuze and Guattari never had any illusions, however, that this tension can
be indefinitely sustained stasis always wins in the end, as it is inevitable
events exhaust themselves in their eventing, eventually consuming their
potentials or being captured by strata. This does not mean that they return
us to the same place, which would make them mere blips in a constant
underlying order, but that there is no final, perfect state, and at one point
new potentials will have to be harnessed to go beyond the forms created by
previous events in that sense, movement always wins in the end. This is
what leads Deleuze (with Parnet 2004) to jest but who did ever believe
that revolution turn out well? All revolutions fail. Everyone knows it
That revolutions fail, that revolutions turn out bad, that has never stopped
people from becoming revolutionary What people have to do in a situation
of oppression or tyranny is effectively to become revolutionary, for there is
nothing else to do.
19. At around the same time, Guattari (1984: 65) comments on May 1968: it is
true that problems are now seen differently, but, equally, there has been no
real break. This is undoubtedly because there is no large-scale machine for
revolutionary war. We have to recognize that certain dominant images are
still perpetrating their destructive effects even within revolutionary groups
themselves.
20. An example of the incapacity (or fear) of abandoning the position in which
the vicissitudes of political experience can always be blamed on others would
124
Rodrigo Nunes
be the Invisible Committees (2014: 75) critique of the notions constituent
power, democracy and government which sounds woefully inadequate in
its suggestion that the defeat of uprisings such as the one in Egypt would have
resulted from failure to deprive power of its legitimacy, make it acknowledge
is arbitrariness, when they were actually interrupted by the arbitrariness of
sheer force.
21. I borrow this explanatory short-circuit from Viveiros de Castro (2009: 239).
22. Interestingly, Guattari (1984: 202) comments that one should still be a
Leninist, at least in the specific sense of believing that we cannot really
look to the spontaneity and creativity of the masses to establish analytical
groups in any lasting way though Leninist is perhaps an odd word to use
when one remembers that the object at this moment is to foster not a highly
centralized party, but some means whereby the masses can gain control of
their own lives.
23. Treating psalo (the pass it on tag tacked to the end of emails and text
messages calling for actions) as the unpredictable actor behind the
movement of the indignados in Spain, Marta Malo (2011) observes that, as
the son of decades of political disaffiliation, psalo is wary, especially of
organised groups; when the latter attempt to use the same mechanism of viral
spread, their initiatives fall flat.
24. Nicholas Thoburn (2010: 137) emphasizes Deleuze and Guattaris affirmation
of becoming imperceptible as a political figure, aptly characterizing it as
not a sublime end-point of spiritual inaction, but the immanent kernel of a
militant political composition, and departing from a clear disarticulation of
political practice from the construction of coherent collective subjectivities,
but in a fashion that bypasses the anti-group position with an orientation
toward the discontinuous and multilayered arrangements that traverse and
compose social or, indeed, planetary life.
Chapter 4
Resistance to Occupy
Claire Colebrook
I
The title of my chapter indicates two senses of the concept of resistance,
and two senses of the concept of occupation. The two contrary tendencies of the concept of resistance take us to the heart of Deleuze and
Guattaris political philosophy. There is no authentic proletariat to whom
one might appeal in political protests. Rather than think of a populaces
resistance to power or the state, in terms of opposition, one needs to
think of political resistance at the molecular level: how might some forces
forces that compose us and what we take to be our interests produce
new formations that are not those of the standard political identities that
make up political analysis? We might think of standard (molar) political
resistance as to use Foucaults terms too bound up with sovereign
conceptions of power, as a repressive power over, or as a top-down
power, against which life and liberty would be set. By contrast, Deleuze
and Guattari theorize a sense of multiple and genuinely political resistance: it is not a question of life resisting power, but of thinking within
each body of resisting forces. In his book on Leibniz Deleuze describes
the play of forces that would generate a relatively unified body. On such
an account, for a body to resist would not be to appeal to natural desire or
interests, but to have a feeling for the multiple tendencies that would then
yield an inflection:
I hesitate between staying home and working or going out
to a nightclub: these are not two separable objects, but two
126
Claire Colebrook
Resistance to Occupy
127
each individual deciding for herself because only she can determine
her own good a collective politics might generate alternating relations
of clarity and distinction. While Occupy may have been characterized
by indistinction never clear just who or what the movement represented, coming into being prior to any formation of an end or aim its
force and presence were clear (clear but indistinct), and as the movement
grew in size it became capable of different and varying amplitudes. The
political nature of Occupy cannot be understood by way of the subject,
whose finite knowledge would determine a range of expertise, but does
make sense according to Deleuze and Guattaris sense of perception as a
form of occupation and resistance: one perceives and knows according
to where one is, and what impedes or enhances ones range. This is not
just to say that Occupy managed to generate a broad, indistinct but clear
perception of its own force by gradually gaining self-perception by way of
social media, but also that within each Occupy site there were moments
of relative distinction where divergent demands of racial, ethnic, sexual
and gendered justice came into relative conflict. It was occupation, or the
assembling together of bodies, that generated multiple lines of resistance
both resistance to Occupys outside the 1% and within Occupy.
The use of relative quantities to name relations of resistance is closer
to a Deleuzian politics of the monad rather than the subject: rather than
a self who perceives its outside, political resistance is achieved by shifting and constantly redistributed relations of force. There are not subjects
who occupy and then resist; rather, there is an assembling of force, the
formation of a territory, and then the self-perception of that force by way
of its relative range of clarity and confusion. From the stable monad, a
being defined by it locus and force of perception, Deleuze and Guattari
argue for the nomad: a range of perception and force that is constantly
shifting (Deleuze and Guattari 1987: 5734).
Deleuze and Guattaris work therefore manages to weave together two
contrary senses of resistance. The political concept of resistance is oppositional as in the French resistance and is a resistance to an occupying power. Deleuze and Guattaris micro-politics intertwines oppositional resistance, especially in Anti-Oedipus, with the psychoanalytic
concept of resistance: what stops a body, force or desire from doing what
it wants to do? If one wants to resist politically, and oppose a power, then
128
Claire Colebrook
one needs to ask about the powers within every body and every perception that impede or enhance its amplitude. Let us say that the political
concept of resistance, captured in the historical moment of the French
resistance (but also more broadly in anti-colonization movements), was
that of opposing an occupying power, and that such a concept of oppositional resistance has been increasingly problematized by another notion
of resistance articulated by psychoanalysis: how is it that desire resists
itself? It was this sense of immanent (rather than oppositional resistance)
that Paul de Man deployed in the notion of resistance to theory: rather
than imagine theory as something that could be easily achieved, such
that we might step back from a field of forces and relations and grasp its
higher logic, de Man argued that theory or the gaze of wise distance was
not something that could ever be fully achieved. Resistance or a certain immanent impossibility of fulfillment is constitutive of any event
of reading, or any attempt to grasp the sense of what one encounters.
Blindness is constitutively coupled with insight, just as for Deleuze and
Guattari all perceptions are distinct and confused, clear and indistinct.
A body occupies a field and encounters its resistances with counter-resistance. The theoretical desire is at once necessary to break with relations
as already constituted, but always remains as a desire, never a final object
(de Man 1982).
When Deleuze and Guattari write about micro-facisms, they focus
the question of resistance and opposition at the level of desire (Deleuze
and Guattari 1987: 31). If there is fascism, or the social-political organization of all force towards a single transcendent end the state, the people,
the party this is not because there is something that simply opposes
desire; rather, desire itself has a tendency towards becoming resistant to
its own tendencies:
You may make a rupture, draw a line of flight, yet there is
still a danger that you will reencounter organizations that
restratify everything, formations that restore power to a signifier, attributions that reconstitute a subject anything you
like, from Oedipal resurgences to fascist concretions. Groups
and individuals contain microfascisms just waiting to crystallize Good and bad are only the products of an active and
Resistance to Occupy
129
130
Claire Colebrook
Our only points of disagreement with Foucault are the following: (1) to us the assemblages seem fundamentally to
be assemblages not of power but of desire (desire is always
assembled), and power seems to be a stratified dimension
of the assemblage; (2) the diagram and abstract machine
have lines of flight that are primary, which are not phenomena of resistance or counterattack in an assemblage, but cutting edges of creation and deterritorialization. (Deleuze and
Guattari 1987: 531)
Placing their work in context one might say that the French resistance,
and then the political milieu prior to May 1968, relied on a dichotomous
notion of occupation and resistance: in the Nazi occupation of France,
an outside had invaded the inside or the territory, and this outside must
be resisted. But Deleuze and Guattaris political theory, well before the
Occupy movement, precluded any simple sense of an inside/outside of
political territories. It is not the case that there is something like a territory a marked out and defined space that is then occupied: this is the
myth of nations, or the notion that space and place have some intrinsic
proper being. Rather, it is by way of occupation, or by filling a zone or
moving across a field, that something like a space or territory is formed.
This primary nomadism always occurs in relation (and by way of contestation). In the beginning is the potential for occupying a space, and the
mapping out of a territory; but the territory is therefore the outcome of
deterritorialization: forces of desire enter into relation, producing a certain quality or space. Property is occupation, or the taking up of a space
and of marking or signing it as ones own. There is something like a quality that is desired; there is a desiring, and it is from this tendency to take
up a quality that a territory is formed:
The expressive is primary in relation to the possessive; expressive qualities, or matters of expression, are necessarily appropriative and constitute a having more profound than being
No sooner do I like a color that I make it my standard or placard. One puts ones signature on something just as one plants
ones flag on a piece of land. A high school supervisor stamped
all the leaves strewn about the school yard and then put them
Resistance to Occupy
131
back in their places. He had signed. Territorial marks are readymades. And what is called art brut is not at all pathological or
primitive; it is merely this constitution, this freeing, of matters
of expression, in the movement of territoriality: the base or
ground of art. (Deleuze and Guattari 1987: 316)
Here, Deleuze and Guattari articulate a politics of occupation and resistance that is improper; in the beginning is the chance taking up of what is
not ones own as ones own. It would follow from this theory of original
occupation that it is not the case that there is a proper space of ones own,
that might then be taken over or occupied, and that this occupation must
be resisted by some proper or innocent outside of power. Rather, desire
encounters resistance, and in so doing generates a space of ownness or
an occupation. Occupation is the outcome of resistance, which in turn
is dependent upon a desire that has no proper home or being. I would
argue that there is something necessarily appropriative about the mode
of Deleuze and Guattaris political theory: not only do they see the notion
of the proper and property as dependent upon the seizing of a quality,
their very style of thinking about politics transforms how we think about
political theory. Rather than politics following on from an idea, rationale
or decision a commitment to freedom, the market, the individual or
even justice they commence with aesthetics in the strictest sense: a
quality is seized. The notion that this quality is then a sign of ones own
identity or territory or property is a consequence of a certain reversal. In
this respect their own theory is not only an overturning of Platonism (by
placing ideas as effects of sensations) but also an overturning of a certain conception of resistance that would focus on a politics of good ideas:
rather than demystifying or informing the masses of what they ought to
desire, and rather than focusing on a politics of good thinking, they stress
the event of occupation. Take up a space; write a placard, and sign it as
your own. Philosophically, we might say that Deleuze and Guattari insist
on internal relations: there are not qualities that enter into relation, but
there are powers that have tendencies to establish certain styles of relation. This is to say that rather than a matter that is neutral and that is then
differentiated from outside, there are tendencies to establish relations by
way of matters inflections. Matter is not blank quantity without quality.
Along with the commitment to internal relations, Deleuze and Guattari
132
Claire Colebrook
Resistance to Occupy
133
there are two very different types of relations: intrinsic relations of couples involving well-determined aggregates or
elements (social classes, men and women, this or that particular person), and less localizable relations that are always
external to themselves and instead concern flows and particles eluding those classes, sexes and persons. (Deleuze and
Guattari 1987: 196)
I would suggest that the first wave of French post-structuralism, or the
first uptake of French post-structuralism, stressed external relations: a
system of differences (such as langue) was the condition for some point
of stability or sameness. It would follow, then, that politics might depend
on solicitation or disturbance of a system from within, given that there
would be nothing (or no thing) outside the constitutive differences that
enable points of seeming identity. By contrast, Deleuze and Guattari
combine internal relations (a forces desire or tendency) with external
relations, or the constituted differences that generate stable points.
We might think, then, of the genealogy of French post-structuralism as an initial phase focused on the resistance to occupation. Nazi
occupation of France was, ostensibly, the intrusion or installation of a
foreign and pernicious body into a democratic polity; the French resistance directed against occupation relied upon the rebellion and refusal
by a polity that could conceive itself as other than the invading forces.
Deconstructions ongoing response to this notion of occupation as intrusion or contamination by an external evil has increasingly been one of a
politics of auto-immunity: there is no innocent body politic that is accidentally or tragically overtaken by forces of violence, terror and totalizing power, for in order to constitute any we or body proper there
must have been some violent and homogenizing event of recognition
that established the purity of the border and the putative innocence of
the we. Put in an overly simple way we might say that in an age of selfsatisfied democracy and good feeling where violence and terror appear
to be located elsewhere it would be theoretically requisite to point out
that our supposedly democratic and inclusive body politic was always
already contaminated by violence, terror and exclusion. From Derridas
early work on Levinas (where he argues that some domestication of the
other is necessary to avoid a worse violence of absolute exclusion) to
134
Claire Colebrook
Resistance to Occupy
135
136
Claire Colebrook
Resistance to Occupy
137
138
Claire Colebrook
that constitute relatively stable terms, and that one cannot step outside
difference (deconstruction); then one takes the next step and starts to
think about just what force, life or matter it is that generates difference
(Deleuzism). Even in terms of literary history there is the high postmodernism of quotation, linguistic and textual self-reflexivity, and then a shift
to local and multiple narratives focused on perception, feeling and the
body. One can think here of Don Delillos classically postmodern White
Noise (1985) with its reference to simulacra, media, spectacle and clich, and then the same writers later Body Artist (2001) or Point Omega
(2010) concerned far more with the visible and the sensible. Similarly,
feminism seemed to be dominated by constructivist or linguistic conceptions of gender, subsequently displaced by a turn to the body; more
often than not the same texts were involved but were read differently.
Historically or critically (at least for the English-speaking world) the high
era of deconstruction was in the 1980s and 1990s, and was then followed
by a series of turns away from a perceived textualism or overly literary
post-structuralism towards a more vital, material and engaged Deleuzism.
This sequence coincides, I would suggest, with different political
problems. For deconstruction one needed to problematize liberal antifoundationalism; it is not sufficient to say that in the absence of any
determined law one must decide for oneself, for one is always already
complicit, determined and within the domain of difference that enables
one to think and speak. There is no pure outside, and no site of good conscience. The liberal individual simply substitutes rather than displaces the
onto-theology of the West, and needs to be deconstructed by insisting
on ones inescapable location within difference. Deleuzism, from a similar genealogy, is less about demystifying origins and instead remystifying: how do some figures seem to rigidify or reterriorialize, despite our
cynicism? Or, why is it that despite capitalism and cynicism desire is still
enslaved to Oedipal, familial and personal rigidities? How did capital
manage to escape difference and allow one axiom to overcode all others?
More specifically, how in this era of late capitalism and the supposed
liberation of all exchange from moral conceptions of justice and fairness
were some entities (banks, money, and economic wisdom) deemed to
be too important to be exposed to the contingency of force and survival?
The problem is no longer the ideology of capitalist individualism and its
Resistance to Occupy
139
140
Claire Colebrook
Resistance to Occupy
141
opposites (the linguistic focus of deconstruction versus Deleuzes materialism and vitalism), and sometimes seen as a sequence, with Deleuze
taking the problem of difference further, beyond language and humans.
Sometimes this is how Deleuze and Guattari present themselves in relation to deconstruction, and how Deleuze thinks about his own relationship to writers like Foucault (Deleuze 2006: 62). One way to read Deleuze
today is to see him as having picked up on a Spinozist tradition of politics
and Marxism that has been overshadowed by French Hegelianism and
that is being rethought today. But to state the relation and sequence this
way is to think at the level of the history of ideas, and to think that ideas
have a semi-autonomous history (which is itself a MarxistHegelian
notion). But what if ideas are expressive, and what if the DeleuzianSpinozist-materialist turn were an unfolding of new potentialities and
forces of life? I want to suggest that this is indeed the case and that the
vogue for a Deleuzian mode of politics is enabled by a positive sense of
occupation and a mode of politics that is less attuned to resistance; by the
same token I want to suggest that deconstruction was broadly focused on
the positivity of resistance in opposition to occupation.
Thinking about the shifting sense of occupation is not merely an
observation in the use of a word or what it means to occupy so much
as a different mode and style of political force. If occupation once figured
the imposition of illegitimate power in an otherwise democratic polity,
then it would make sense to question as Derrida does the supposed
purity and integrity of the putatively innocent democratic state. If, as is
increasingly the case, it is no longer a question of a state presenting itself
as democratic by excluding and abandoning a few, then one needs to
reconsider how concepts such as democracy have increasingly less force.
This is what I mean by referring to a new feudalism: rather than promoting the free and open market that accidentally leaves a few at the bottom,
it is now widely accepted that the few at the top will do all they can to
maintain wider and wider difference; the very concept of banks that are
too big to fail reinstalls a power that exists by fiat rather than right. A
few the 1%, who now flagrantly name and mark themselves as exceptional by means of bonuses and stately architecture (such as Manhattans
Trump Tower) have abandoned any pretension of the good polity. How
does political critique proceed when bourgeois liberalism is no longer
142
Claire Colebrook
Resistance to Occupy
143
144
Claire Colebrook
Resistance to Occupy
145
Derrida will insist on a politics that does not yearn for some space
outside the limits of law, but that uses the logic of law to think a justice
that will always remain to come. Resistance, thought in terms of psychoanalysis, names the subjects own stifling of the truth: their symptom is
not an affliction from without but something taken on such that they can
imagine themselves suffering from an outside. If we accept constitutive
resistance then justice will not be what the other destroys by way of occupying my proper terrain of citizenship, for there is no proper, no justice
and no terrain of ones own. Resistance is first and foremost a resistance
to the very forces of non-presence, negativity and non-identity; these
differential forces, though precluding pure presence are nevertheless
capable of generating justice, if there is such a thing. Writing on Foucaults
attempt to (as Derrida sees it) find a historical space outside the rationalization and incarcerating logic of modernity, Derrida responds with a
perpetual threat that will always destroy the logic of opposition:
For, in principle, all these determinations are, for the historian, either presences or absences; as such, they thus exclude
haunting; they allow themselves to be located by means of
signs, one would almost say on a table of absences and presences; they come out of the logic of opposition, in this case,
the logic of inclusion or exclusion, of the alternative between
the inside and the outside, and so on. The perpetual threat,
that is, the shadow of haunting (and haunting is, like the
phantom or fiction of an Evil Genius, neither present nor
absent, neither positive nor negative, neither inside nor outside) does not challenge only one thing and another, the very
logic of exclusion or foreclosure, as well as the history that is
founded upon this logic and its alternatives. What is excluded
is, of course, never simply excluded, not by the cogito nor by
anything else, without this eventually returning and this
is what a certain psychoanalysis will have also helped us to
understand. (Derrida 1994b: 242)
For Derrida, then, psychoanalysis is both about internal resistance, or a
self that cannot confront its internal occupation, its own non-presence to
itself. For Paul de Man, certainly not speaking in psychoanalytic terms,
146
Claire Colebrook
Resistance to Occupy
147
climate change, because we are waiting for all the acts to come in. We suffer today not from doubt and relativism, but from a literalist notion
that there is a truth and that there is one system that grants us access to
the world: the new positivism of finance. So when Deleuze insists in his
books on cinema that we have stopped believing in the world, and when
(with Guattari) he describes capitalism as a dominance of cynicism, this
needs to be understood alongside the theory of the despotism of the
signifier: it is as though there is at one and the same time an abandonment of the distance between sign and world, and a simple acceptance
of the single system of signs that compose the shrill certainty of the
world as it is, capitalism as we know it in its flagrant just so. The value
of de Mans insistence on theory and Deleuze and Guattaris insistence
on minor politics is that rather than aim to disturb language from within,
one accepts the non-coincidence of linguistic systems with other strata,
and refuses the privilege accorded to any single system that would present itself as the code of all codes, the narrative of all narratives. This is not
simply another form of liberalism whereby the absence of ultimate truth
places us in a position of deliberation and ongoing communicative reflection: for there will always be some sort of appropriation of one strata
by another, and a laziness that resists the complex multiplicities that go
beyond any single polity. Resistance is constitutive; there will always be
some refusal of the blank stare of theory that abandons hope of grasping some innocent outside (de Man), always a resistance to immanence
as such that is not immanent to any transcendence (Deleuze). But there
are two ways of thinking radical immanence or non-transcendence. What
the absence of any privileged outside meant for the time of deconstruction in the 1980s and 1990s was that capitalism should not be opposed in
any simple way. There has always been techne and alienation. It is not the
case that we might step outside ideology and find the truth for the very
notion of an original truth that some sign system might grasp is ideology.
Resistance to the necessary distance of signs and the banality of inscription is ideology; that resistance is neither avoidable nor capable of being
reformed. Instead, all we have is a tireless war on all the modes of transcendence that might present themselves as good or benevolent outsides.
In response to this we might want to ask: was not the 2008 global
financial crisis precipitated precisely by just this abandonment of
148
Claire Colebrook
reference? But things are not so simple, for while it is the case that
futures, derivatives, hedge funds and the selling on of toxic assets enabled
an ungrounded and uncontrolled system that went into free fall, the
problem was neither unbridled exchange nor the absence of real value,
but some ongoing notion that exchange was grounded in assets and that
there would ultimately be a way of translating numbers back into material wealth (if there is such a thing). There is nothing at all valid in the
notion that post-structuralisms critique of representation plays a role in
nihilism, relativism and capitalist cynicism. On the contrary, it is still the
case that incontrovertible truths are asserted without any sense of the
impossibility of determination; we are now referring to corporations as
individuals, assuming that these entities are real, bounded and agential.
Indeed, the 2008 crisis was possible precisely because some myth of
reference precluded examination of an essentially virtual network: supposedly, at the base of it all, there were commodities, homes attached
to mortgages, speculation about buyers and sellers all real and material things. The problem lay in the notion that financial circulation was
ultimately grounded on things, or that financial speculation wasnt the
entirely fictional enterprise that it was. The very idea that banks operated
as some necessary structure that was so significant as to be too big to fail
did not come from a postmodern notion that reality is untethered, quite
the contrary.
What is required, then, is not some nave reaction that turns us back
to reality, and that expels deconstruction as a sign of the times of late
capital. Rather, the next question or problem after we accept anti-foundationalism, is how deterritorialized, groundless, unnatural, and open
exchange gets reterritorialized into some manufactured or hallucinated
center? How is that in all this free-floating speculation some bodies came
to be foundational, and eventually too big to fail? How did certain bodies, faces and persons maintain the prestige that enabled them, after the
2008 US election, to suspend social policies for emergency bail-outs, as
though crisis rendered certain forms of expertise more powerful? The
problem is not nihilism, decentering and lack of foundations and values;
it is the failure to render nihilism active, for it was the experience of crisis
and ungrounding that allowed for a seizing of autocratic authority and an
ongoing practice of disaster ethics: in an age of volatility and precarious
Resistance to Occupy
149
life we are told we cannot afford to be too relativist, and need to turn
back to management and expertise. Should we really be thinking that in
a time of crisis we need to buoy up some sites of concentrated capital
in order to keep the rest of the field in play? Or, would it not be a question without any illusion of stepping outside of capitalism of exposing points of theft? When Deleuze and Guattari insist that the social field
begins with theft not exchange, they do not so much oppose capitalism as
they create an idea of powerfully destructive excessive capital. If life were
simply free exchange then there would be no basic stability, but if force is
originally stored, taken, harbored and then squandered, one site in the
field appears as powerful and even structural. It is not from scarcity that
political assemblages are formed, but from excess and theft: a body seizes
and stores force, and from that pooling of force an organized or deterritorialized reference point is constituted. Political life occurs as the repression of exchange, not because exchange is foundational but because radically unimpeded flows of exchange would destroy the relatively stable
points achieved by marking out quantities or properties as ones own:
desire begins not from a stable point that one might then establish as a
site of exchange, but from a seizing of force that establishes a stability
(territorialization), and that enables a system of exchange that in turn
is never fully free but always referred to a locus (deterritorialization).
One steals therefore one becomes. It is only by impeding an absolutely
deterritorialized flow that anything like a territory is assembled:
It is theft that prevents the gift and the countergift from entering into an exchangist relation. Desire knows nothing of
exchange, it knows only of theft and gift
Will it be said that, if desire knows nothing of exchange,
it is because exchange is desires unconscious? Will this be
explained by the exigencies of generalized exchange? But
what entitles one to declare that shares of debt are secondary
compared with a totality that is more real ? Yet exchange is
known, well known in the primitive socius-but as that which
must be exorcised, encasted, severely restricted, so that no
corresponding value can develop as an exchange value that
would introduce the nightmare of a commodity economy.
The primitive market operates through bargaining rather
150
Claire Colebrook
Resistance to Occupy
151
good old-fashioned dose of truth and reality. Think of how futures and
hedging worked, or the ways in which speculation enabled persons who
were nothing more than agents of exchange (day traders, brokers); this
system of exchange was made possible only by way of the lure that there
was some ultimate reality or substance to what was being exchanged.
Ostensibly, hedge funds bet on future outcomes, just as mortgages are
originally debts attached to property, but are subsequently circulated and
repackaged. Money markets also function on the lure of substitution, or
that money is the sign of value. There is, in the world of unbridled finance
no shortage of realist fictions. The crisis was enabled precisely by what
de Man referred to far more broadly as aesthetic ideology: the notion
that the figures that captivate our attention are signs of an underlying and
amenable reality. One needs to criticize speculation not because it takes
its gaze off reality and starts to bet wildly on what has no substance, but
because it deploys a language (or tropology) of substance and reality.
What is really occurring is the creation of power by way of the illusion of
substance in the hands of a few who are stealing the practice of exchange.
On the surface the numbers being circulated in the years leading up to
the crisis were signs of peoples savings, houses and futures; but as pyramid and Ponzi schemes disclosed, there was no pyramid, no base that
was big enough to support the heights of financial fantasy.
IV
What does this mean for thinking about theory and politics today? First,
I would suggest that what Deleuzian or Deleuzo-Guattarian modes of
politics offer is an intensification, rather than reversal, of the positive
sense of resistance and occupation. Their use of the term desire is the
very opposite of the desires of consumers for products; desire is revolutionary directly because it is without anchor in identities or investments (Deleuze and Guattari 1983: 113). What is resisted and repressed
is desire, and desire is not a quality so much as a quantity without quality:
Capitalism institutes or restores all sorts of residual and artificial, imaginary, or symbolic territorialities, thereby attempting, as best it can, to recode, to rechannel persons who have
been defined in terms of abstract quantities. Everything
152
Claire Colebrook
Resistance to Occupy
153
154
Claire Colebrook
Resistance to Occupy
155
156
Claire Colebrook
Resistance to Occupy
157
Deleuze, Gilles and Flix Guattari. 1987. A Thousand Plateaus: Capitalism and
Schizophrenia. Trans. Brian Massumi. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Deleuze, Gilles and Flix Guattari. 2004. Anti-Oedipus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia.
Trans. Robert Hurley, Mark Seem, and Helen R Lane. London: Continuum.
de Man, Paul. 1982. The Resistance to Theory. Yale French Studies 63: 320.
Derrida, Jacques. 1978. Writing and Difference. Trans. Alan Bass. London: Routledge.
Derrida, Jacques. 1994a. Specters of Marx. Trans. Peggy Kamuf. London: Routledge.
Derrida, Jacques. 1994b. To Do Justice to Freud. Trans. Pascale-Anne Brault and
Michael Naas. Critical Inquiry 20 (2): 22766.
Derrida, Jacques. 1998. Monolingualism of the Other; or, The Prosthesis of Origin. Trans.
Patrick Mensah. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Latour, Bruno. 2014. Beyond Belief: On the Forms of Knowledge Proper to
Religious Beings. Religion and Plurality of Knowledge (May 12). Groningen.
Accessed May 4, 2015 from: http://sggroningen.nl/en/evenement/beyond-belief
Protevi, John. 2013. Life, War, Earth: Deleuze and the Sciences. Minneapolis: University
of Minnesota Press.
Chapter 5
Preoccupations
Verena Andermatt Conley
Preoccupations
159
of 1968, where the Sorbonne was occupied for days and nights on end,
the revolt having for a first time united students and workers? If so, and
if it has political mettle, what is its future? Or is it simply a ritual celebration that as Roland Barthes stated long before the fact in Mythologies
(1957), a collection of studies of popular culture depoliticizes itself
in the pleasure of its performance? Slavoj iek, a sympathetic critic,
warned the participants of Occupy of the risks of turning their movement into a narcissistic festival in place of a manifestation of dissensus. He
asked participants not to become enamored with themselves:
The danger [is] that [the protesters] will fall in love with
themselves, with the nice time they are having in the occupied places. Carnivals come cheap the true test of their
worth is what remains the day after, how our normal daily life
will be changed. We spend a pleasant moment together here.
But remember, carnivals are cheap. Of importance is the day
after, when people go on with their everyday lives. Thats the
moment to ask whether anything has changed? (iek 2012)
Other philosophers and cultural theorists have been less critical. Judith
Butler argues that Occupy is a bodily outcry and a demand for a physical
and mental space in which to live:
When bodies gather as they do to express their indignation
and to enact their plural existence in public space, they are
also making broader demands. They are demanding to be recognized and to be valued; they are exercising a right to appear
and to exercise freedom; they are calling for a livable life.
These values are presupposed by particular demands, but they
also demand a more fundamental restructuring of our socioeconomic and political order. (Butler 2011)
Michael Hardt and Antonio Negri, in turn, in a pamphlet entitled
Declaration write that as a movement of revolt Occupy is symptomatic
of dominant forms of subjectivity produced in the context of the current
social and political crisis. [They] engage four primary subjective figures
the indebted, the mediatized, the securitized, and the represented all of
which are impoverished and their powers for social action are masked or
mystified (Hardt and Negri 2012). When iek cautions against slogans
160
and Butler calls for a life worth living; or when Hardt and Negri urge
humans who are immobilized and infantilized by the media to go beyond
a threshold of revolt, we can read in filigree many of the Gilles Deleuze
and Flix Guattaris reflections on resistance. Often in similar terms, on
the heels of 1968, denouncing the state of the world under capitalism in a
phase of rampant and destructive expansion, they urged students, readers
and listeners to pry open spaces within its sphere that might enable the
beginnings of a greater reinvention and recomposition.
What are the links between the philosophers preoccupations and
those both of Occupy Wall Street and of Occupy in general? It is well
known that the two philosophers consider concepts to be both intellectual and political instruments carried in a toolbox. What can be drawn
from their toolbox, Deleuzes metaphor for the arsenal that can be put
to the use of rearranging inherited configurations of life? In addition to
practical concepts, what is the dynamism and force of conviction that we
can lift from their writings to help Occupy thrive? While iek, Butler
and especially Hardt and Negri (the most Deleuzian of the chosen list)
try to address todays problems, I propose first to go back to the philosophers pronouncements and then to see if and how they can be articulated with Occupy today.
The call to occupying the street rather than holding the fort runs
through Deleuze and Guattari both literally and metaphorically. The philosophers emphasize change through movement and flow, be it of people,
desire, affects or thought. Advocating an ever-unfinished, non-dialectical,
and non-hierarchical model of constructive dissent, they do away with
the Marxian notion of class structure to consider social conflict in terms
of mobile micro- and macro-cosms, ever-shifting lines, rhythms and harmonics. Already in 1975, in the French version of their first co-authored
book, Kafka, Toward a Minor Literature, Deleuze and Guattari emphasize
the need to put a dominant idiom into a condition of variation. Never
stable, a dominant language, a common and unquestioned lingua franca
that generally controls subjectivity, is modulated where popular use of
dialects, vernaculars, verbal aberrations and multilingualism alters its
unilateral (and clearly monolingual) character. When used tactically,
minor languages instill into dominant rhythms cadences of stunning
variety (Deleuze and Guattari 1987: 100110). In 1976, in Rhizome:
Preoccupations
161
162
Preoccupations
163
164
Sympathetic and possibly in accord with Virilio, notably after the fall of
the Iron Curtain, Deleuze and Guattari did not join the chorus of those
praising the event as the triumph of liberalism. Without nostalgia or
despair, each in turn Guattari in 1989 and Deleuze 1990 denounced
the new state of the world (Dosse 2007: 4589). Deleuzes outlook
became bleak. At the end of Negotiations (1990), first in an interview
with Negri titled Control and Becoming and then in a short addendum,
entitled Postscript on Control Societies, he notes without nostalgia
that we have lost the world (Deleuze 1995: 16782). It has been taken
from us. No real resistance is possible when money, not affect, neither
variation nor pulsation, is the currency of life. Because it wafts in the
flow of capital, he speculates, even art, that had once produced singularities and made possible invention and creativity, can no longer be countenanced. Perhaps the only thing left is the opening of small vacuoles
from and within which to think otherwise. At the time of his suicide in
1995 Deleuze was rumored to have said that mentally and physically he
was finished.
In The Three Ecologies (1989), Guattari for his part decried the loss
of the subject and of human relations in an age that is in the grip of
infantilizing media in collusion with omnipotent corporate control of
the state. In the post-Fordist era, consumerism, he argued, transforms
humans into market samples and collectivities into molar aggregates. He
called for a reconstruction of the subject on his terms: by emphasizing
singularities, in the making of rhizomatic connections, and by advocating a collective solidarity. Building on an existential vocabulary, Guattari
notes the fragility of the subject as a for-itself opposed to the in-itself,
immobilized by debt and lobotomized by the media and its capacity
to change. Crucial for our purposes is that Guattari asserts on the one
hand that changes can occur autopoietically, unbeknownst to the subject,
before she or he even opens onto the environing world. In either case,
something suddenly affects the subject that leads to a preoccupation of
sorts, an event which produces a change in the individual or in the social
body. Even among large aggregates of given populations spontaneous
change and types of recomposition are possible. Singularities or groups
move about and across striated spaces under the impetus of a different
affect, without colliding head-on with the group or territory they are
Preoccupations
165
166
Preoccupations
167
168
long-term transformation. As Deleuze and Guattari put it, the becomings that it seeks are difficult to obtain and their results always uncertain.
Over the last few years, a preoccupation, however faint, that reintroduces
idealism has become perceptible. In addition to the occupation of microspaces, it is in fields such as education, urbanism, architecture and the
environment that a shift has become noticeable among a newer generation seeking to redirect its thoughts and energies for the sake of social
justice, the rights of fauna and flora or simply put, for a life worth living
and a habitable world. These issues are often local and require coordination of analysis and careful exercise of militancy by which preoccupation becomes occupation occupation such that new affects generate
percepts and concepts.5 In this light, Occupys aphorism of action has to
be carried out in the accompaniment of an ongoing question on how to
occupy a space, that is, how to open and distribute it, and how to develop
a different sensibility and intelligence that, although situated within capitalism, runs against its grain. A different sensibility calls for ways of existing that both embrace singularity and collectivity and recognize both
transversality and interdependence. It thinks change from todays conditions, from the standpoint of a global scale and from that of locales in
their many-faceted and ever-changing conditions. A different intelligence
does not measure the state of things in terms of profit alone. Its condition
of difference seems at times difficult to generate in the present climate,
notwithstanding Occupys success that is yielding hints of what it can be.
As Deleuze and Guattari had argued, a kind of preoccupation that rises
spontaneously, autopoietically, is the pre-condition of the creative intelligence of singular and collective occupation. In addition, those who are
in a position to affect subjectivities share the responsibility of introducing a wedge in peoples thinking and open spaces for charting new lines
of inquiry.6
The question Occupy asks today is how to reorient social, economic
and artistic production for collective benefit. And for the two philosophers artistic did not mean a vaguely creative act (that, in fact, they
dismissed as vitamin induced, or bien vitamin). They noted then what
needs to be noted now: in a state of occupation in the economy in which
it is born, art has to do with invention and experimentation and not just
with testing and bigger markets. In the wake of Deleuze and Guattari and
Preoccupations
169
the artists they championed, we can say that Occupy aims to produce a
different type of singular and collective existence. Retrospection tells us
that they ask to create an oikos or habitat in dynamic process. The type of
occupation for which Deleuze and Guattari had virtually argued would
change awareness. To be preoccupied is to be aware of occupation before
occupation takes place. Preoccupation is a situated place at the level of
affect, a sense of something that stirs, turns into a percept and eventually
becomes a concept. As the philosophers had underscored over and again,
a new sensibility is fostered under the influence of other forms of intelligence; added to the intuitive sort of the artist, are those of scientists and
philosophers who too create new plateaus and new dynamisms.
Occupy thrives on creativity in an era of new modes of communication, but also on creatively passive militancy. It is hopefully part of a longterm projection that can be measured in terms of duration. Occupy began
with a sudden and contagious preoccupation, that has inspired a desire to
occupy space otherwise. Like the philosophers of 1968 before them and
with their tools refashioned for use in the twenty-first century, occupiers of mettle are those who rethink and refashion space by means of new
distributions and redistributions: who value nomos against logos; who,
refusing refuge in the fort, circulate in both real and electronic streets.
Occupation always begins with an event, a rupture, a sudden surge of
affect. It begins with preoccupation.
Works Cited
Barthes, Roland. 1972. Mythologies. Trans. and ed. Annette Lavers. New York: Hill
and Wang.
Butler, Judith. 2011. Precarity, Embodiment and the Politics of Public Space. Tidal
(December 12). Accessed January 1, 2013 from: http://occupytheory.org/
Tidal_7.html
Deleuze, Gilles. 1995. Negotiations 19721990. Trans. Martin Joughin. New York:
Columbia University Press.
Deleuze, Gilles and Flix Guattari. 1983a. On the Line. Trans. John Johnston. New
York: Semiotext(e).
170
Deleuze, Gilles and Flix Guattari. 1983b. Anti-Oedipus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia.
Trans. Robert Hurley, Mark Seem and Helen R Lane. Minneapolis: University of
Minnesota Press.
Deleuze, Gilles and Flix Guattari. 1986. Kafka, Toward a Minor Literature. Trans.
Dana Polan. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Deleuze, Gilles and Flix Guattari. 1987. A Thousand Plateaus: Capitalism and
Schizophrenia. Trans. Brian Massumi. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Doherty, Gareth and Moshen Mostafavi (Eds). 2010. Ecological Urbanism. Baden:
Editions Mller.
Dosse, Franois. 2007. Gilles Deleuze et Flix Guattari: Biographie croise. Paris:
ditions La Dcouverte.
Guattari, Flix. 1986. Les annes dhiver, 19801985. Paris: Barrault.
Guattari, Flix. 2000. The Three Ecologies. Trans. Ian Pindar and Paul Sutton. London:
Athlone.
Guattari, Flix. 2009. Soft Subversions: Texts and Interviews 19771985. Ed. Sylvre
Lotringer. New York: Semiotext(e).
Guattari, Flix. 2012. Un amour dUiq. Ouvrage dirig par Silvia Maglioni and
Graeme Tomson; avec la collaboration dIsabelle Mangou. Paris: ditions
Amsterdam.
Hardt, Michael and Antonio Negri. 2013. Declaration. Jacobin Magazine. Accessed
May 4, 2015 from: https://www.jacobinmag.com/2012/05/take-up-the-baton/
Harvey, David. 2000. Spaces of Hope. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Khatibi, Kate, Margaret Killjoy and Mike McGuire. 2012. We Are Many, Reflections on
Movement Strategy from Occupation to Liberation. Oakland: AK Press.
iek, Slavoj. 2012. Occupy Wall Street: What is to be Done Next?. The Guardian.
Accessed May 5, 2015 from: http://www.theguardian.com/commentisfree/
cifamerica/2012/apr/24/occupy-wall-street-what-is-to-be-done-next
Notes
1.
In the Cage is included in MD Zabel (Ed.), Henry James: Eight Tales from
the Major Phase (New York: Norton, 1969). Deleuze and Guattari make little
mention of the cage as a prison, composed of crisscrossed wires, in which
the female is traditionally (and iconically) confined. One set of lines is thus
opposed to that of another, the heroines that crosses the barrier.
Preoccupations
171
2.
3.
4.
5.
If after what was perceived as the Arab Spring and the protests in Spain
and Greece, the widespread and sudden success of Occupy suggested the
beginning of another worldwide wave of protest as in the nineteen-sixties, the
movement has, for the time being, often been more immediately successful at
the local levels. For example, in Occupy Utica, Occupying a Small Rustbelt
City, the authors show how for reason of its precise, concrete and attainable
demands that include local school programs, extension of social services (of
which a psychiatric clinic would be a part) and even the organization of a May
parade in honor of labor, Occupy was successful and produced change. The
members involved realized the importance of moving past the celebratory
moment of occupation and toward an active occupying of a space (Khatib,
Killjoy and McGuire 2012, cited in Le Monde diplomatique, January 2013).
6.
Chapter 6
173
law courts shift up a gear in the discipline, punishment, and brutalization of student demonstrators, anti-cuts activists, and the young people
involved in the 2011 riots a move undoubtedly driven by concern that
the normalization of this grotesque inequality cant hold indefinitely.
In repurposing the vacant UBS office and abandoned school, Occupy
London spun such critical threads as these through neoliberalism, cuts,
housing, and the city, and did so in ways both analytical and practical.
But the Bank then School of Ideas also had a distinct pedagogical dimension. In Chile, California, Britain, and elsewhere, direct action against
neoliberal education policy has been a leading edge of the current cycle
of struggles. These education struggles have been largely defensive, fighting for the last remnants of a model of liberal education that is far from
perfect, albeit that it is vastly superior to the emerging neoliberal model
of debt-financed vocationalism. But the composition of this struggle
has also been characterized by new critical knowledges and solidarities,
as funding cuts in tertiary and higher education, creeping privatization
of educational institutions, student debt, the casualization of academic
labor, and graduate unemployment have drawn together a diverse range
of actors that have interrogated the forms, functions, and possibilities
of education at a new level of intensity. The School of Ideas, like other
autonomous educational endeavours, was interlaced with these developments, as participants in various struggles cycled through the building
and shaped it in their own ways. But it was also something that stood
up on its own, to make use of an expression I discuss below. Equal
parts co-learning school, workshop, community center, organizational
base, public interface, and home, one might say that the School of Ideas
amplified (not isolated) the critical intellectual function and culture of
Occupy London, and it was in that context that a sizeable group gathered
on a bright winters morning to discuss Deleuze, Guattari and the politics of Occupy.
Minor Politics
With the UK government itching to criminalize squatting, its a real pleasure to be speaking in a building that is undergoing public repossession,
so Id like to thank Andrew Conio for organizing this workshop and the
174
Nicholas Thoburn
School of Ideas for hosting us.4 What I want to do in this talk is work
through three of Deleuze and Guattaris concepts that are helpful in
thinking about Occupy. What do I mean by helpful? My aim is deliberately not to try and explain Occupy, to sew it up in a theory that for
Deleuze would be to negate what is inventive in a movement, but also to
lose the inventive quality of theory, making it merely a representation of a
state of affairs. Instead my approach will be to use theory to reflect upon
certain themes or problems in Occupy, looking at how these problems
can be approached with Deleuzian concepts in a way that may help shed
light upon them and aid their further development. Its a recursive relation, for reflection upon Occupys themes or problems should also help
extend Deleuzian concepts, lending them a contemporary vitality.
Given that this workshop is concerned in equal measure to bring
Deleuze and Guattaris concepts into relation with Occupy and to offer
an introduction to Deleuze and Guattari as political thinkers, Im going
to try and strike a balance between concept and Occupy, leaving space for
us to expand upon the points I make about Occupy in the discussion. The
concepts and problems that I address in turn are: minor politics and the
99%; territory, expression, and occupation; and fabulation and agency.
I will start with minor politics and fold in some comments about
the 99% though bear with me, the relation may not at first be apparent.
Running throughout Deleuze and Guattaris philosophy is a notion that
politics arises not in the fullness of an identity a nation, a people, a collective subject but, rather, in cramped spaces, choked passages, and
impossible positions; on the condition, that is, that the people are missing (Deleuze and Guattari 1986: 1516; Deleuze 1989: 216; Deleuze
1999: 133). To understand how this anti-identitarian formulation works,
we need to consider their concepts of the majoritarian and minoritarian.
As Deleuze and Guattari have it, majority describes a system of identities that are constituted and nurtured by social relations to the extent
that the social milieu serv[es] as a mere environment or a background
(Deleuze and Guattari 1986: 17). The minoritarian condition, on the
other hand, is one where social relations no longer facilitate coherent identity, for they are experienced as riven with competing imperatives and constraints. As such, the social ceases to be mere background
and floods individual experience, as life becomes a tangle of limits or
175
impossibilities lets say, the experience of poverty, precarity, debt, racism, but also the spatial arrangements of the city, the gendered divisions
of labor, the partitions of public and private, dominant linguistic forms,
in their myriad combinations in each particularity. It is a condition that
forces each individual intrigue to connect immediately to politics, for
without an autonomous identity, even the most personal, individual situation is always already comprised of social relations. And vice versa: this
immanent relation to the social is not a flattening of particularity, quite
the contrary. For the mesh of complex and contradictory social relations
in every particularity is such that [t]he individual concern thus becomes
all the more necessary, indispensable, magnified, because a whole other
story is vibrating within it (Deleuze and Guattari 1986: 17). Particularity,
then, is constituted by and interlaced with social relations, and it is on
this condition, not some kind of minority identity, that minor politics is
founded. So, what Deleuze and Guattari call major or molar politics
expresses and constitutes identities that are nurtured and facilitated by a
social environment, whereas minor politics is a breach with such identities, when the social environment is experienced as constraint, as perception is opened to what is intolerable in social relations (Thoburn 2003).
Deleuze uses an appealing image to convey a sense of this minor condition. He says that to be on the Right is to perceive the world starting
with identity, with self and family, and to move outward in concentric circles, to friends, city, nation, continent, world, with diminishing affective
investment in each circle, and with an abiding sense that the center needs
defending against the periphery. On the contrary, to be on the Left is to
start ones perception on the periphery and to move inwards. It requires
not the bolstering of the center, but an appreciation that the center is
interlaced with the periphery, a process that undoes the distance between
the two (Deleuze and Parnet 2012).
It is clear thus far that the minoritarian is a structural condition. And it
is one that is very much entwined with developments in global capitalism.
For the imperative of capital to set and overcome limits (an appreciation
of which is the basis of Deleuze and Guattaris Marxism)5 has produced
an ever more fragmented, variegated, and mutable patchwork of unequal
exchange, exploitation, and poverty, where the identity structures of
Fordism no longer hold and peripheral zones of underdevelopment
176
Nicholas Thoburn
177
178
Nicholas Thoburn
substantial identity; rather, it at once names and cuts the social relations of
exploitation, among those who feel cramped by these relations, feel their
intolerable pressure.
This naming and breach in capital is of course very general, without
immediate purchase on concrete particularities. And here lies the risk
of a tendency toward identity, as the generality is mistaken as naming
a coherent group of people, a political subject. But We are the 99% is,
rather, something like a formula or, to use a term with more spatial connotations, a grid. It lays out the abstract principle that can be taken up
and extended by any person or collective that would embody or express
it in their concrete experience; indeed, it is an abstract principle that only
has any meaning or purchase insofar as it is expressed in particular circumstances. In order to see how this grid functions, I want to compare
it to one that Occupy is more or less directly opposed to, the grid of parliamentary democracy. Parliamentary democracy is, for Deleuze, a grid
laid out across social space that seduces and channels political activity
through its specific forms and structures:
Elections are not a particular locale, nor a particular day in
the calendar. They are more like a grid that affects the way we
understand and perceive things. Everything is mapped back
on this grid and gets warped as a result. (Deleuze 2007: 143)
Politics in this way gets warped, as he puts it, because everything is
reduced to and formatted by the status quo, to the perpetuation of that
which gave rise to politics in the first place. A fundamental aspect of this
warping is the exclusion of problems of inequality and exploitation from
the realms of political interrogation. This was of course Marxs insight,7
but the condition is currently so acute that it has widespread, even popular recognition, as Greece and Italy have unelected technocrats imposed
on the populace to force through hitherto unknown assaults on living
standards, as the ConDems slice up the National Health Service while
claiming that it matters not one jot whether it is run by the state or private capital.8 This is why Occupys much remarked upon refusal to make
demands is so important and so much a product of our times. A demand
is a mechanism of seduction into the grid of democratic politics, a means
179
of channelling the political breach with capital right back into the institutions that perpetuate it.
In contrast, the grid that is constituted by the slogan We are the
99% is very different. Rather than a mechanism of seduction into the
status quo, it is a means of multiplying points of antagonism, or, in more
Deleuzian terms, it extends the process of perceiving the intolerable and
politicizing social relations. As I said, this does not occur in general, but
from peoples concrete and situated experience it is a variegated field,
where the points of problematization are housing repossession, the laying waste of public services, privatization of common resources, debt,
police violence, workfare, and so on, and the tactics range from occupying social space, through the Oakland general strike, to direct actions
against eviction from foreclosed housing, non-payment of debt, the
hacking activities of Anonymous, or public repossessions as we have in
this building. Put another way, the grid is a catalyst across the social, not
an aggregating body extending ever-outwards from Zuccotti Park but a
zigzag, a discontinuous and emergent process. Again, its not a catalyst
because people come to recognize themselves in it as an identity even
a collective identity but because they come to embody and express its
abstract problematic in concrete circumstances.
Before moving on I want to directly address two points that are
implicit in what Ive said so far. First, it is not infrequently said by those
involved in Occupy that it in some sense is creating the new world in the
shell of old; that practices of collective decision, direct action, cooperation and care, global association, and so on, are a kind of communism in
miniature. Certainly, all of these collective practices are crucial to understanding the unfurling of Occupy, to its effectivity and affective consistency, to the complex pleasures and pains of being a part of it. But from a
minor political perspective, the risk with this formulation is that Occupy
turn inwards, valorizing its own cultural forms at the expense of selfproblematization and an ever-outward engagement in social relations.
Occupys vitality lies in its extension and intensification of the problematic of the 99% through an open set of sociopolitical sites and events,
in what is of course a highly segmented and stratified terrain (where, to
return to my earlier point, the fact of segmentation negates any notion
that the we of the 99% could designate a coherent subjectivity). For it is
180
Nicholas Thoburn
in and through these sites and events that the worlds population exists,
and from which an unknown set of possible futures will emerge. To identify those futures with the cultural forms discovered in Occupy camps
would be nave at the least, and risks a conservative reduction of the
movements minor political potential, a reduction to identity.
Second, refusing to make demands is not a refusal to speak to formulate and express our anger, hopes, and desires, to name the particular problems of which we are concerned and to seek practical effects.
On the contrary, to work through the problems of Occupy requires an
incessant production of critical knowledge and practice, knowledge and
practice that needs to be circulated in the extension and development of
these problems. The point is that this critical production is immanent to
Occupy, or to the social relations that Occupy politicizes, not a pleading
for recognition from an external power or a transposition of its problems
into the grid of parliamentary democracy. We have seen Occupy developing slogans and concrete decisions that move toward defining what the
movement wants, as part of reflection on how it may get it and this of
course is encouraging. But such formulations need to have a minor political efficiency, as Guattari has it, they must be adequate to the specific
and mutating problems of Occupy and its world, not reproduce themselves at the level of clich: either a minor language connects to minor
issues [which should not be taken to mean small or exclusively local
issues], producing particular results, or it remains isolated, vegetates,
turns back on itself and produces nothing (Guattari 1995: 37). All this
knowledge production will involve critique, contestation, and the development of divergent positions. Deleuze and Guattari are certainly interested in the way group consistencies emerge from distributed decision
lets say, the process of consensus in Occupys General Assemblies
but a good problem is not best extended in thought and practice by
pretending that we all agree: The idea of a Western democratic conversation between friends has never produced a single concept (Deleuze and
Guattari 1994: 6).
181
182
Nicholas Thoburn
are apparent, for example, in the art of the Bowerbird, whose courtship
rituals involve the production of elaborate decorated structures.
What are the components of this constructed territory? Well, they
are drawn from the environment, from existent materials in the case of
the Bowerbird, twigs, berries, bottle-tops but they are also qualities and
forms that emerge in the process of construction:
This emergence of pure sensory qualities is already art, not
only in the treatment of external materials but in the bodys
postures and colours, in the songs and cries that mark out
the territory. It is an outpouring of features, colours, and
sounds that are inseparable insofar as they become expressive.
(Deleuze and Guattari 1994: 184)
The St Pauls occupation is very much this kind of constructed territory.
It comprises practical materials, the tent of course, items of furniture,
cooking equipment but also placards and signs, books, newspapers,
drums, assemblies, hand signals, the peoples mic, photographic images,
livestreams, YouTube clips, the OccupyLSX website and Twitter feed,
and so on. My point is not to proclaim that Occupy is art exactly, but to
suggest that alongside the practical tactics of occupation, the construction of territory through these functional components also includes an
expressive, sensory quality that becomes an inseparable aspect of the occupation.9 This is one explanation, for instance, of the production of newspapers at the Occupy camps, when online production and distribution is
clearly more practicable. As well as being an object of news, discussion,
and practical politics, the newspaper in this regard is also a bloc of sensation, an aesthetic expression of Occupy.
Tent as Monument
You might ask, Whats the relation between this sensory or expressive
quality of Occupy and its meaning or explicit politics? For Deleuze and
Guattari the two are different modalities of composition that come into a
mutually sustaining encounter. They sometimes use a surprising word for
these works of art or works of territory they call them monuments:
183
184
Nicholas Thoburn
(Deleuze and Guattari 1994: 105).11 With the tent, then, we see something of the tactical or practical aspect of Occupy interlaced with its sensory or expressive quality: a tactic, and a sensory bloc both, for Deleuze
and Guattari, are constitutive of its territorial form.
The nomadic tent this production of a movable and moving ground
orients our attention to a final aspect of the territorial form of Occupy.
In constituting its territory, Occupy needs to remain open to a strong
degree of deterritorialization of its own. Indeed, the relation should be
reversed Occupys reterritorializations need to play only a secondary
role to the onward and open process of deterritorialization if it is not to
become blocked, bogged down, identified in its new territory (Deleuze
and Guattari 1988: 508). Deterritorialization in this way lends an evental
quality to a social formation, the ungraspable and often highly seductive
character of a formation whose directions remain unmapped, indeterminable, full, as Deleuze has it, of virtuality. But what does deterritorialization mean in more practical terms? You can think of deterritorialization here as the spatial dimension of that minor political opening to the
social that I began with, the process of warding off identity and problematizing social relations. It is a central problem of Occupy, as well expressed
in one editorial of The Occupied Times:
[The eviction of Occupy Wall Street from Zuccotti Park] triggered a period of self-examination about how the Occupy
movement might best move forward beyond its signature
tents and into communities, enacting the movements core
message through practical action rather than symbolism.
It is a journey that has seen American occupiers leave tents
behind in favour of defending the homes of those about
to be foreclosed Thanks to equal measures of adroitness
and serendipity, Occupy Londons initial encampment at St
Pauls Churchyard has now far outlived Zuccotti Park in duration It would be a bitter irony and a failure of enormous
proportions if we allowed our comparative security to stop
us seeing some of our more distinctive tactics for what they
are: a tool to be employed only for as long as they remain
useful. Useful tactics generate change. They inspire others
185
186
Nicholas Thoburn
187
fabulation. Its a word you might have noticed earlier in the quotation
about the monument. Fabulation or myth-making occurs when the shock
of an event be it an earthquake, a work of art, a social upheaval produces visions or hallucinatory images that substitute for routine patterns
of perception and action and come to guide the event. In Deleuze and
Guattaris reading, fabulation is a weapon of the weak, a means of fabricating giants, as they put it germinal agents with real world effects in
the service of political change (Deleuze and Guattari 1994: 171). What
is perhaps most appealing in the context of Occupy is that these fabulations or myths are not so much located in individual people the cults of
personality, for instance, of Lenin, Mao, Churchill, what have you but
have a desubjectified or anonymous quality, generated and held in the fragmented bits of events, stories, medias, affects, material resources, and are
associated as much with mediocrity as with the grandiose (Deleuze and
Guattari 1994: 171). In this way Deleuze describes myth as a monster, it
has a life of its own: an image that is always stitched together, patched up,
continually growing along the way (Deleuze 1989: 150; Deleuze 1997:
118; Thoburn 2011).
Occupy has had something of this mythical quality, an agential power
of its own that exists among and between us, and that pulls its particularities along. Ill end by pointing to one small (and by no means unproblematic) artefact in this myth: the Guy Fawkes mask. Think how different
these two images of political myth are. Mao, a concentrated myth centered, in demagogic fashion, on an individual and the truth of his infallible thought. And the Guy Fawkes mask, an anonymous, distributed
power a part of the myth of Occupy, open to anyone, signifying a resistance to closure in a leader, vaguely menacing, a little bit silly, mediocre
even, and pop-cultural to boot. The masks impersonal mythical power is
well expressed in a cartoon in The Occupied Times, a cartoon that takes its
words from Subcomandante Marcos (and Thomas Mntzer in turn) and
so forms a red thread across to another political myth of our time: its not
who we are thats important, but what we want: everything for everyone (The Occupied Times 2011: 2).
188
Nicholas Thoburn
Works Cited
Gilles Deleuze. 1989. Cinema 2: The Time-Image. Trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Robert
Galeta. London: Athlone.
Deleuze, Gilles. 1997. Essays Critical and Clinical: 19681990. Trans. Daniel W Smith
and Michael A Greco. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Gilles Deleuze. 1999. Negotiations 19721990. Trans. Martin Joughin, New York:
Columbia University Press.
Gilles Deleuze. 2007. Two Regimes of Madness: Texts and Interviews 19751995.
Ed. David Lapoujade. Trans. Ames Hodges and Mike Taormina. Los Angeles:
Semiotext(e).
Deleuze and Flix Guattari. 1986. Kafka: Towards a Minor Literature. Trans. Dana
Polan. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Deleuze, Gilles and Flix Guattari. 1988. A Thousand Plateaus: Capitalism and
Schizophrenia. Trans. Brian Massumi. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Deleuze and Guattari. 1994. What Is Philosophy?. Trans. Hugh Tomlinson and
Graham Burchill. London: Verso.
Deleuze, Gilles with Claire Parne. 2012. Gilles Deleuze: From A to Z. Dir. Pierre-Andr
Boutang. Trans. Charles Stivale. Los Angeles: Semiotext(e).
Gentleman, Amelia. 2012. Housing Benefit Cap Forces Families to Leave
Central London or be Homeless. The Guardian (February 16). Accessed
May 4, 2015 from: http://www.guardian.co.uk/society/2012/feb/16/
housing-benefit-cap-families-central-london
Guattari, Flix. 1995. Chaosophy. Ed. Sylvre Lotringer, New York: Semiotext(e).
Kafka, Franz. 1999. The Diaries of Franz Kafka: 19101923. Ed. Max Brod. Trans.
Joseph Kresh and Martin Greenberg. London: Penguin.
Marx, Karl. 1975. Early Writings. Trans. Rodney Livingstone and Gregor Benton.
Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Marx, Karl. 1976. Capital. Trans. Ben Fowkes. Harmondsworth: Penguin.
The Occupied Times. 2011. The Occupied Times 6. Accessed May 4, 2015 from:
http://issuu.com/theoccupiedtimes/docs/ot_issue_6_issuu/1?e=0
The Occupied Times. 2012. The Occupied Times 8. Accessed May 4, 2015 from:
http://issuu.com/theoccupiedtimes/docs/ot_8_issuu/5?e=0
OSullivan, Simon. 2006. Art Encounters Deleuze and Guattari: Thought Beyond
Representation. London: Palgrave.
189
Notes
1.
2.
See Simon Rogers, Occupy protests around the world: full list visualised,
The Guardian (November 14, 2011), available at: http://www.guardian.co.uk/
news/datablog/2011/oct/17/occupy-protests-world-list-map#data
3.
See Patrick Collinson, Budget 2012: Earning 1m? Your Tax Cut Will Pay for
a Porsche, The Guardian (March 21, 2012), available at: http://www.guardian.
co.uk/uk/2012/mar/21/budget-2012-earning-1m-tax-cut-pay-for-porsche
4.
Since this talk took place, the ConDem administration has enacted what Tory
regimes have long threatened, making squatting in residential properties
a criminal offence. The government and media bogeyman, as ever, was the
squatter who moves into an occupied family home; a clear ruse to deflect
from the disgraceful situation where people sleep on the streets when 610,000
homes lie empty in England alone. See Empty Homes Agency, Statistics
(October 2014), available at: http://www.emptyhomes.com/statistics/
Attacking working class housing on another front, central government has
set rents for local authority and housing association tenants to rise to 80% of
those in the private rental sector, a move that in many parts of the country
effectively brings to completion the destruction of council housing that began
with Margaret Thatchers policy of right to buy.
5.
Flix Guattari and I have remained Marxists, in our two different ways,
perhaps, but both of us. You see, we think any political philosophy must turn
on the analysis of capitalism and the ways it has developed. What we find
most interesting in Marx is his analysis of capitalism as an immanent system
thats constantly overcoming its own limitations, and then coming up against
them once more in a broader form, because its fundamental limit is capital
itself (Deleuze 1999: 171).
190
Nicholas Thoburn
6.
The critique of the formulation of the 99% is well made in Clinical Wasteman,
No Interest but the Interest of Breathing, Mute, Available at: http://www.
metamute.org/editorial/articles/no-interest-interest-breathing
7.
It is worth sketching Marxs thesis here, and keeping in mind Deleuze and
Guattaris distinction between major and minor politics while doing so, for
the correspondence is striking indeed. Rather than engage with the human
as social animal as species being in all the socioeconomic complexities
and antagonisms of its production bourgeois politics abstracts an isolated
individual a partial being, the individual withdrawn into himself,
his private interest and his private desires and devotes all its energies
to securing this subjectivity. Here, the whole of society is there only to
guarantee each of its members the conservation of his person, his rights and
his property, and, as such, the political sphere in which man behaves as a
communal being [Gemeinwesen] is degraded to a level below the sphere in
which he behaves as a partial being. This is not a mere ideological ruse, but
a structural feature of the inverted subjectivity of capital, where the worker,
who is wholly a product of capitalist social relations, experiences life as an
individual free to sell her labor-power on the open market. It is upon these
conditions that Marx can proclaim with every reason and some irony that
capital, for all that it comes dripping from head to toe, from every pore, with
blood and dirt, is indeed a very Eden of the innate rights of man (Marx 1975:
2301; Marx 1976: 926, 280).
8.
See To be honest I dont think it should matter one jot whether a patient is
looked after by a hospital or a medical professional from the public, private or
charitable sector, Tory health minister Lord Howe, quoted in Nick Triggle,
Private Sector Have Huge NHS Opportunity, BBC News (September 7,
2011), available at: http://www.bbc.co.uk/news/health-14821946
9.
The bowerbird is certainly not the last word on art in Deleuze and Guattari.
I should point out that despite possible indications to the contrary here,
their writing on art is not best viewed through the avant-garde lens of the
subsumption of art and everyday life, for they invest considerable import in
the exacting forms and techniques of modernist practice, in painting and
cinema especially (see OSullivan 2005; Zepke 2005).
10. See the Occupy London Homelessness Statement, available at: http://
occupylondon.org.uk/homelessness-statement/
11. Many thanks to John Bywater for pointing out this passage on the English
taste for camping, which helps counter any Orientalism in Deleuze and
Guattaris concept of nomadic dwelling.
Chapter 7
192
Ian Buchanan
193
194
Ian Buchanan
195
by their own inviolable purity of principle (We dont talk to people with
power, because to do so would be to acknowledge the legitimacy of their
power). I do not want to suggest that the occupiers should somehow
be seen as immune to criticism. But I do want to suggest that the political frameworks in place today are in many ways conceptually inadequate
to deal with events like Occupy Wall Street, which falls outside most
peoples standard paradigms for understanding political interactions
between the manifestly powerful and the apparently powerless. Usually
power is equated with violence and more especially the control of the
right to violence. The fact that non-violent movements like Occupy Wall
Street challenge that very idea, indeed that basic assumption, that politics
ultimately boils down to who has the best weapons and the most troops
is in many ways the most overlooked (in the media, I mean) aspect of
political activism today.
Conceptual advances are, in this sense, political acts in themselves,
because they open a space, or more precisely, create the form of the
expression for new political ideas (as the content of the expression) and
thereby enable political voices to be heard that would otherwise be presumed silent or adjudged irrelevant.
This is one of the key reasons that the concept of the event has
been so central a preoccupation for critical theory for the past decade
or more; it is starting point for any inquiry about what happened? Of
the several philosophers who have given thought to the concept of the
event, the most influential in critical theory, at least are undoubtedly
Alain Badiou and Gilles Deleuze. The event is a crucial concern for
both, but they each approach it quite differently. At the risk of grossly
oversimplifying their respective arguments, I will try to generalize the
difference between them as follows. For Badiou the event gives rise to
truth (it is truths condition), whereas for Deleuze it gives rise to sense
(it is senses condition). Badious event, as a truth-event, demands our
commitment it therefore hovers on the border between conscious and
unconscious, voluntary and involuntary, that which we choose to do and
that which we feel compelled to do. Our commitment to a particular
truth is not so much a rational decision based upon the weighing up of
evidence as a lightning strike, an epiphany that hits us and in an instant
reshapes our view of the world. Badiou tends to give mathematical
196
Ian Buchanan
examples to explain what he means by truth because for him the real
quality of a truth is its inarguable nature: a triangle has three sides, a
square has four, and so on. Similarly, one could look to physics, and the
various laws formulated there: gravity means everything must fall. It is
an open question, it seems to me, whether any political idea can attain a
comparable status, but for Badiou this is what conviction would mean in
a political context: the unshakeable belief in the rectitude of a particular
idea and the concomitant clarity of perception this conviction affords
(Badiou 2012: 6061).
For Deleuze, too, the event is a kind of lightning strike, but it demands
only that we adapt to it. It does not demand our conviction, or even our
belief. The event for Deleuze is an eruption of immanence, if you will,
a bursting forth of a kind of immanent time-space continuum in which
something transcendent (sense) appears. In a late essay, published after
his death, Deleuze even called this type of eruption of immanence life
(Buchanan 2006). In his work with Guattari, space was usually referred
to as smooth space (but it had other names as well the body without
organs, the plane of immanence, the plane of composition, the plateau
and so on). This life-sense as we may perhaps call it (to distinguish it
from ordinary or semantic sense) has a structuring effect inasmuch as it
gives shape to the world as we live and experience it. F. Scott Fitzgeralds
notion of the crack is, for Deleuze and Guattari, something of a
touchstone example of what they mean by the event. It is a kind of mental
clean break, a brain snap as some people say, after which nothing is the
same. Examples of cracks might include the realization that ones job
is worthless and not deserving of the effort you put into it, or that you
arent as talented as you once thought (which was Fitzgeralds feeling),
and so on (Deleuze and Guattari 1987: 198200). This is by no means at
odds with anything Badiou says about the event, except that for Deleuze
this eruption of immanence (the opening up of a smooth space in other
words) does not necessarily correlate with an idea of truth. It is also
worth noting that the event for Deleuze and Guattari is not measured
by a change in the state of things a large crowd gathering in a public
square in Cairo or camping out in New York City is not intrinsically an
event in Deleuze and Guattaris thinking. It only becomes recognizable as
an event if it brings about a transformation of thought itself, if it yields a
197
new idea, a new way of acting.5 And I would argue that is precisely what
Occupy did: it opened up a new space of thought.
In contrast to Badious truth-event, Deleuze and Guattaris smooth
space of thought, or life-sense, is not universal or universalizable. The
crack Fitzgerald experiences is a truth for him, but not for anyone else,
not even Zelda Fitzgerald, who experienced her own crack. It is his sense
of his world, not anyone elses. Thats why we call it his life. And even if we
empathize with his outlook on things and feel that it somehow describes
our own world too, that it has something to say about our own life, it is
a not a truth we can be faithful to in Badious sense (as he applies it to
ideological worldviews like communism, for instance). I can believe in
the existence or occurrence of the crack (clean break, brain snap, etc.)
in someones life, but only in a formal sense. The specific content of
someone elses crack will always elude me because as Tolstoy more or less
said were all unhappy, that is to say, broken or cracked, in our own way.
What pushes me over the edge does not have to be the same as whatever
pushes another person over the edge for us to both say weve experienced
a crack. Yet for that very reason our respective experiences of cracking
are only comparable in an abstract way. This is not to say that for Deleuze
and Guattari there are no such thing as collective events, or events that
affect more than one person, but it does mean that universality cannot be
one of its defining criteria, as it is for Badiou. The other difference is that
for Deleuze and Guattari the life-sense event is involuntary Fitzgerald
doesnt choose to accept or adhere to the crack, it comes up upon him
without him knowing about it in advance and leaves him a changed man
in its wake. For Badiou, in contrast, the event requires our fidelity, we
have to choose to believe in it and place it at the center of our lives.
The event for Deleuze and Guattari is a radical break with the normal
continuity of things that at once interrupts the usual flow of daily life
and initiates its own counter-flow.6 This was precisely what Occupy Wall
Street did: it brought about a radical break with the normal continuity of
daily life, not just in lower Manhattan, but globally, as the whole world
stopped to see what was happening there. That it could do so without
violence or even the threat of violence is remarkable, particularly in an
era that is in many ways defined by the so-called War on Terror, which
had its beginnings Ground Zero a short distance from Zuccotti Park.
198
Ian Buchanan
Having said that, it is important to see that Occupy Wall Streets nonviolent approach, the so-called passive resistance it exercised, is anything
but passive. It is a misnomer that robs the non-violent approach to
protest of its core, namely the galvanizing effect of a desire for change. As
Perry Anderson writes, Ghandi himself translated satyagraha as truthforce rather than passive resistance. Inspired by Tolstoy, Ghandi coined
this neologism himself to conceive a vision of non-violent resistance
infused with a religious idea of transcendence (Anderson 2012: 6).7 For
Badiou, this is precisely how an event like Occupy Wall Street works.
It ignites what he calls a truth process it makes apparent to all that
human animals are capable of bringing into being justice, equality,
and universality (the practical presence of what the Idea can do). It is
perfectly apparent that a high proportion of political oppression consists
in the unremitting negation of this capacity (Badiou 2012: 87).
The fact that people take the trouble to interrupt their own lives
to commence and participate in an occupy movement and do so in
substantial numbers is living proof that in the words of the anti-WTO
protesters from the decade before Occupy Wall Street, another world is
possible. What counts is the act, the willingness to disrupt ones own life
and beyond that the lives of others, and beyond that the life of the social
machine itself. As Badiou puts it, speaking of the occupation of Cairos
Tahrir Square in January 2011, which sparked the Arab Spring: even if
the occupiers are a million strong, that still does not represent many of
the 80 million Egyptians. In terms of electoral numbers it is a guaranteed
fiasco! But this million, present in this site, is enormous if we stop
measuring the political impact (as in voting) by inert, separated number
(Badiou 2012: 58). Deleuze and Guattari call this space one occupies
without counting smooth space, which they contrast to striated space.
In what follows I will argue that Occupy Wall Street can usefully be
thought of as having created a new kind of smooth space. Ironically, it
is perhaps Badiou who, while severely critical of Deleuzes attachment to
the concept of the virtual, gives us the most useful illustration of precisely
what is meant here by smooth space. Speaking of Spains indignados, the
loose social movement which arose in response to the austerity measures
the Spanish government was forced to impose by the European Central
Bank as a condition of its debt relief (following the global financial crisis
199
of 2007 and the resulting meltdown of the euro), Badiou argues that as
noble as their cause is, because it is fuelled only by negative emotions a
desire for real democracy to replace the bad democracy they have to
live with their movement isnt as powerful or as sustainable as it would
be if it were underpinned by an affirmative Idea (Badiou 2012: 97). The
Idea, Badiou says, is blind to the self-evidence of what is before it the
local defeats, as in the case of Occupy Wall Street, which was rousted out
of Zuccotti Park after only two months and far-sighted concerning the
future that no-one else has eyes to see it isnt concerned with results,
with counting in the here and now, what it awakens is the force of History
itself, the certainty that nothing not even capitalism is forever (Badiou
2012: 989).
Now, I would not want to say that smooth space is identical with
Badious conception of the Idea, but I do want to make the point that it
is both conceptual and historical in nature. Take for example Deleuze
and Guattaris key exhibit, Paul Virilios concept of the fleet in being.
At a certain point in history, naval commanders arrived at the idea that
the ocean could be dominated by the superior mobility of forces and the
power to interdict the mobility of others rather than through the control
of fixed positions. This idea, which was fully an event in both Badious
and Deleuzes terms, was communicated from sea to land to air to space.
Now war in all its modalities is informed by this idea. There have been
moments when this idea has seemed out of step with history. Germanys
Schlieffen Plan to sweep across Western Europe came horribly unstuck
in 1914 when their planned war of mobility was unseated by the twin
powers of the machine gun and barbed wire and turned into a standstill
war of attrition claiming the lives of millions. But almost as soon as the
first trenches were dug the opposing forces began scheming to regain
the power of mobility and within the space of a few years solutions were
found: tanks and airplanes rendered the gridlocked space of the battlefield smooth all over again. In this way a new pattern of action was set in
motion: striated space was to be defeated by technological advancement.
But within a few decades, by the time of the Vietnam War, if not sooner,
this model was also brought unstuck. Today, the incredible mobility
of high-tech weapons is countered by the fluidity of the identity of the
enemy. The unseen and unknown enemy compels the one who seeks
200
Ian Buchanan
them to give up at least some of their mobility for the apparent security
of checkpoints and surveillance procedures. In each instance, the Idea
of space dominated by mobility remains very much alive (Deleuze and
Guattari 1987: 480).
It is this power the power of an Idea as a force that shatters or cracks
the status quo and lets in a new kind of light, one that hasnt shone there
before that is the key to understanding Deleuze and Guattaris concept
of smooth space. Let me offer a different example that will hopefully
bring it into even sharper relief. I would claim that smooth space is comparable to David Harveys conception of the urban commons. He argues
that the 2011 occupations of Syntagma Square in Athens, Tahrir Square
in Cairo, and the Plaa de Catalunya in Barcelona transformed these public places into latter day variations of the medieval idea of the commons.
Importantly, although these spaces are all physical places that one can go
and visit, the urban commons itself is not, it is a social relation, and that
is precisely how smooth space should be understood I believe. Harvey
writes: The common is not to be constructed, therefore, as a particular
kind of thing, asset or even social process, but as an unstable and malleable social relation between a particular well-defined social group and
those aspects of its actually existing or yet-to-be-created social and/or
physical environment deemed crucial to its life and livelihood. There is,
in effect, a social practice of commoning (Harvey 2012: 73). The key to
commoning, as Harvey sees it, is that it removes the relation between a
group and a space from commodity exchange: the commons is off-limits
to the market. This amounts to saying the commons is a virtual space as
Deleuze and Guattari would put it and that the virtual space of the commons is produced by the occupiers of that space, which is an important
clarification of what Deleuze and Guattari mean by smooth space.
Virtual does not mean unreal, as Deleuze and Guattari often remind
us. The virtual is fully real, as real as an idea, an image, and an innovation, is real. It is real because its effects are real. Here one might think of
Jamesons frequently made point about the need to keep alive what he
calls the utopian imagination: without bold ideas for the future, that is,
ideas which envisage a break a disruption, as Jameson calls it with the
present state of affairs we are condemned to simply let things continue as
they are. And this, as Walter Benjamin rightly said, is the real emergency.
201
The smooth space may not suffice to save us, as Deleuze and Guattari
caution, but it does at least apply the handbrake to history and that may
just be enough.
Works Cited
Anderson, Perry. 2012. Ghandi Centre Stage. London Review of Books ( July 5): 311.
Badiou, Alain. 2012. The Rebirth of History: Times of Riots and Uprisings. Trans.
Gregory Elliott. London: Verso.
Buchanan, Ian. 2008. Deleuze and Guattaris Anti-Oedipus. London: Continuum.
Buchanan, Ian. 2006 Deleuzes Life Sentences. Polygraph 18: 12947.
Greenberg, Michael 2011. In Zuccotti Park. The New York Review of Books
(November 10). Accessed May 4, 2015 from: http://www.nybooks.com/articles/
archives/2011/nov/10/zuccotti-park/?pagination=false
Greenberg, Michael. 2012a. New York: The Police and the Protesters.
The New York Review of Books (October 11). Accessed May 4, 2015
from: http://www.nybooks.com/articles/archives/2012/oct/11/
new-york-police-and-protesters/?pagination=false
Greenberg, Michael. 2012b. What Future for Occupy Wall Street?. The New York
Review of Books (February 922): 468.
Harvey, David. 2012. Rebel Cities: From the Right to the City to the Urban Revolution.
London: Verso.
Mills, Nicholaus. 2011. Occupy Wall Street: A Primer. The Guardian (November
7). Accessed May 4, 2015 from: http://www.guardian.co.uk/commentisfree/
cifamerica/2011/nov/07/occupy-wall-street-primer
Rancire, Jacques. 1999. Disagreement: Politics and Philosophy. Trans. Julie Rose.
Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Notes
1.
202
Ian Buchanan
2.
3.
4.
5.
As they observe, following Gabriel Tarde, the French revolution began when
peasants stopped doffing their caps to the aristocracy, not when the heads
began to roll (Deleuze and Guattari 1987: 216).
6.
7.
In an interesting twist of history, the Phillip Glass opera based on the life of
Ghandi, Satyagraha, was playing at the Lincoln Center in New York for much
of the period of Occupy Wall Streets tenancy at Zuccotti Park. See Greenberg
(2012b: 46).
Chapter 8
Suck My Kutzs1
With the first cuts, the first voids appear. The first negative spaces appear.
A window in Londons Milbank is kicked repeatedly, cracks radiate from
a hole filmed and photographed by much of Britains news media. The
following day, footage of a fire extinguisher dropped by a student from
the roof of the Conservative Partys HQ is uploaded to YouTube. The fire
extinguisher scatters ranks of police who survive unscathed except for
minor injuries. Nervous systems are stimulated by the first day of mass
protest against plans to charge full fees for undergraduate education in
England and Wales. The mass media twitch and pulse anticipating the
conflict to come.
Day X. The stepson of a millionaire rock star out of his mind on
LSD, whiskey and valium swings on a flag poll at the Cenotaph in
Whitehall, London. Kettles are sprung like traps on unsuspecting protestors. Some though are prepared. The Book Bloc batter police lines
with scaled-up cardboard replicas of Our Word is Our Weapon (2002) by
Marcos, End Game (1957) by Beckett, One Dimensional Man (1964) by
Marcuse and Just William (1921) by Compton. Others improvising with
metal barriers join them and punch holes in the cordon at Parliament
Square. As evening descends, the government votes to increase university
fees for home and European students and confrontation between protestors and police escalate. Television news leads with stories of violence in
the streets of Westminster, an attempted storming of the Treasury and a
204
David Burrows
group of students sitting in the National Gallery, refusing to leave, surrounded by millions of pounds worth of paintings. Later, a chaufferdriven Rolls-Royce limousine in Londons West End is splattered with
paint. One of the vehicles windows is breached and an aristocrat sitting in
the back seat of the car is poked with a stick.
On an overcast day in March, swarms of protestors peel off the Trade
Union Congress (TUC) march to Hyde Park in London to occupy
Oxford Street. A giant, ramshackle horse representing the TUC lumbers
towards the center of Oxford Circus and is sacrificed. The pantomime
horse is set on fire. Dense, black plumes of smoke are visible for miles
around and the smell of melting tar fills the air. As does the sound of
whirring electric motors closing shutters, signalling the area is closed for
business. Rather than join the zombie-shuffle from point A to point B
(the prearranged rallying point from which a message to the powerful is
to be sent), a few thousand protestors transform the West End into a carnival of refusal. UK Uncut occupy the luxury goods shop Fortnum and
Mason and police form a ring around the store, serving as a membrane
for a vacuole of discontent.
At first, the UKs news media equated protests against austerity measures with violent confrontation the sought-after photograph was a
smashed window. Soon another tale emerged, told by journalists close
to the action: the birth of a new kind of protestor, the networked individual connected through social media. This declaration was followed
by another: a new kind of protest movement was identified by commentators, presented as an alliance forged through weak links, rapid collective decision-making and organization without hierarchies. But there is
another story to be told about this period of unrest and protest. As with
other manifestations of refusal around the world in 2010 and 2011, protesting against the coalition governments austerity measures involved
producing the space for protest. This took the form of occupations, protest swarms, teach-ins and gatherings; collective actions that rejected representational politics and embraced pragmatism and protocols and tactics
developed by anti-globalization activists. All of which contributed to the
production of protest as an occupation of space and time different to that
sanctioned by orthodox political organizations and traditions. Protestors
experimented with producing negative spaces that traversed and bored
205
holes into the representations of organized politics and the mass media.
By 2011, for many the issue of education fees was succeeded by a focus
on the 1% whose spiritual home is the square mile governed by the City
of London Corporation, targeted by Occupy London. By then, opposing
austerity was no longer equated with violence in the UK, rather it was
equated with a group of people who met daily on the steps of St Pauls
Cathedral, experimenting with ways of living in tents in a small patch of
ground in the heart of the capital.
This essay is concerned with this recent period of unrest and opposition to student fee increases in London, in particular the occupations,
teach-ins and gatherings that not only manifested protest but the space
of protest. It is an account that draws upon my involvement with Arts
Against Cuts during this period, and thus will be a partial account and
include an assessment of the role art played in producing the negative space of protest, experiments named here as negative space war
machines. In this, the essay is specifically concerned with three interrelated problems.
1. Saying no. Protestors said no or expressed refusal in different
ways, something mirrored in the discussions concerning negativity, refusal and affirmation that took place during this period
of protest in various scenes or circles, many of which overlapped. Often views were polarized; actions and discussions
included a militant rejection of affirmation as well as an exploration of the relationship of dissent and affirmation. A constellation of names, that include Marx, Deleuze, Negri, Marcos and
Badiou, plotted different, competing political and philosophical ideas circulating during this period of unrest. However, to
frame this period of protest with a political or philosophical
concept or name would be unwise. Better to view recent protests as a testing ground for competing orientations, better to
focus on the modes of operation employed than present the
concepts and ideas of philosophers as providing meaning for
events. To that end, this essay charts various instances of refusal
and reflects upon the relevance of philosophical concepts and
orientations. Two orientations in particular are addressed: (a)
total refusal to produce anything that might hinder collapse or
206
David Burrows
207
208
David Burrows
precious thing had already been lost before the man was visited by this
disturbing dream or perhaps the precious thing was only ever an elusive
idea of a thing yet to be produced.
Many involved in the protests have voiced similar feelings of disquiet.
It is not that a precious thing has been lost exactly; rather, it is the feeling that the act of saying no, an act that should be simple and straightforward, is more complex than it once was. No doubt, this is due in
part to many lacking a faith in any politics of representation. No doubt
too, globalization has made opposing or reforming capitalism, the goal
of many protestors in UK, a much harder task. During the print union
and miners strikes in the UK in the 1980s, the unions identified a clear
goal and course of action: stop the transportation of newspapers or coal
by drawing a line, a picket line, across a gate or road. Action was envisaged as taking place on a local scale and having a national impact. In the
1990s and 2000s different spatial configurations were produced. Anticapitalist movements traveled the world and converged on the gathering
points and summits of global powers within various cities. In response,
governments created secure lines or corridors between protected cordons or sealed vacuoles, so as to allow business to be conducted without interruption. The protestors actions, though often spectacular and
confrontational, had little effect or influence. In recent times, occupation
rather than confrontation has become prevalent, leading some to declare
Bartleby, the Scrivener (1853) by Herman Melville to be the model for
a new kind of protestor, and the first occupier of Wall Street.2
Bartleby, the Scrivener is a strange tale of a man staying put and
refusing to do anything. Whenever his employer makes a request, including asking the scrivener to vacate the attorneys office in Wall Street,
Bartleby replies, I prefer not to. When asked about a change of employment or environment he indicates he would prefer not to as he is not
particular; that is, he has no specific desire to do anything in particular.
What is confusing for the attorney, who means the scrivener well, is that
Bartlebys statement I prefer not to, as Gilles Deleuze (1998: 68) argues,
is asymmetrical grammar or agrammatical; it is the affirmation of a negative that withdraws from dialogue.
Paul Mason, in Why its Kicking Off Everywhere (2011), continually
remarks upon how, in his encounters with European protestors, he rarely
209
encountered anyone willing or concerned with identifying with a political ideology or set of demands. It might be the case that he didnt try
hard enough (the recent protests brought many class warriors out of the
shadows and the websites of various protest collectives carry numerous
statements and lists of demands); but Masons observation was echoed
in oft-heard criticism of the movements refusal to identify as one mass or
group promoting an agreed political doctrine, program or set of demands.
When asked to articulate the political doctrines of various protest movements many replied I prefer not to. Mason understood something that
others critical of the protestors lack of identification with a named or
historic political position did not. The refusal to identify is a refusal of
representation, a refusal of the modes and organizations of mainstream
media and politics mentioned earlier. Speak with us, not for us, as the
popular refrain goes.3 And this approach is effective to a point; without
a head to speak to or a name to cite or negotiate with, the conventions of
representational politics fails.
Comparing Bartlebys acts of refusal with recent protest might not
be inappropriate though. The scrivener ends his days in a prison or asylum refusing to eat and rejecting all assistance and kindness. Eventually
he dies: a sad end but, as suggested by the narrator, perhaps one ensuring Bartlebys freedom or sovereignty until his last breath. Perhaps this
is where the analogy of Bartleby as contemporary protestor seems limited, the scriveners silence and inactivity towards death would have been
out of place in the camps occupying the steps of St Pauls Cathedral in
London and Zuccotti Park in New York. Bartlebys asymmetrical grammar and occupation of space is, however, a compelling example of a
refusal that forecloses exchange and dialogue. Such refusal is relevant
when analyzing recent dissent and also when differentiating between
protests that demand the powerful accommodate or afford specific interests from the refusal that does not afford representation or dialogue, and
declines accommodation by the powerful. In this latter mode of protest,
the refrain we prefer not to plays out in many different ways.
The voices that articulated the most militant forms of refusal argued
that creative solutions and actions addressing the crisis of capitalism do
nothing more than breathe life into the failing organizations and economies of capitalism. To explore this idea I turn to perhaps a surprising
210
David Burrows
211
212
David Burrows
create organizations with fixed and hierarchical roles in favor of gatherings convened by facilitators. These gatherings proceeded through spontaneous organization producing weak links between groups and individuals and consensus voting (allowing people to opt out of actions).
The role of facilitator was often taken up or adopted by individuals
in relation to the demands of a situation or event on the understanding
that the role lasted for the duration of that event. Not only this, events
and gatherings were arranged without a set program or agenda. At such
events, the order of activities and items for discussion were decided on
the day or through open space technology.5 The use of facilitators and
open space modes of programming expressed an ambition to avoid fixing
symbolic mandates and to produce a political movement that was multiple, flexible and peripatetic in action and word.
To further develop this discussion of movements that are not only
nomadic in thought and deed but that foreclose dialogue with the powerful, the thoughts of Gilles Deleuze are helpful. Deleuze, in conversation
with Toni Negri, argued that it was better to produce a vacuole of noncommunication, to produce circuit breakers, to prefer not to communicate rather than connect (Deleuze 1990: 175). For Deleuze, creating
was something different from communication. He argued that resistance
and communism has nothing to do with minorities or masses speaking
out, not least because speech and communication, which has become
corrupted by money and unable to evade control, has to be hijacked
(Deleuze 1990: 175).
What is a vacuole of non-communication? Perhaps it is merely a noisy
arrangement, or a piece of nonsense? In the same conversation, Deleuze
allows us to understand the potential genesis of this vacuole when he discuses the term war machine, a term that has nothing to do with waging war as such (Deleuze 1990: 172). Rather, it is a term that refers to a
particular occupation of space, an experiment within space and time, an
invention of space and time. Deleuze makes this term concrete by suggesting that the way the Palestinian Liberation Organization (PLO) had
to invent space-time in the Arab context has been underestimated. To
do so, the PLO became a war machine, marking out a territory where
previously none existed, opening up gaps and negative spaces in the
213
214
David Burrows
dividual, is a connection between other connections; dividuals can articulate and be articulated by an organization, such as
electronic media.7
3. Refusal through producing nothing. Refusal as an act that is
not affordable (for an individual or others) and that welcomes
the collapse or suspension of existing organizations without
proposing anything but the destruction of existing relations: a
refusal of affirmation, solutions or production of any kind.
4. Refusal through producing something different. Refusal as
an act of dissent and as an experiment with producing a different space and time from that produced by existing organizations of relations: a refusal that is unconcerned with communicating or negotiating with existing hierarchies.
Of course, the four modes of refusal are not four different kinds of
people; they are four statements that can be articulated by the same person or group. The statements can be found in the testimonies of different
occupations, three of which, issued in 2010, are cited below.8
Slade School of Fine Art Occupation Statement: We vehemently oppose the transformation of the university system into market based model; education should be a public
debate, not a private economy. Therefore we the students of
the Slade are offering a space for the assembly of all art colleges in England in order to organise non-violent direct action
against what we view as an attack by the government on the
arts. This is not a virtual exchange, this is a physical assembly.
We are demonstrating the value of physical space for art education through the continuation of our day-to-day activity, as
well as by inviting other colleges to participate in open events,
lectures and workshops. Our occupation is not designed to be
disruptive, nor will it engender any damage to the building.
Rather, we want to highlight the value of intellectual and cultural exchange within art courses. This is not a boycott, it is an
act of support (Slade Occupation 2010).
215
216
David Burrows
down our society? Fine, well shut it down. And not just for a
few moments, or for a day, but for as long as it takes to reverse
their decision to axe our services, our jobs, and our futures.
(Goldsmiths Occupation 2010b)
Three statements, three negative spaces, three different expressions of
refusal. The first and most affirmative statement proposes an occupation
in which the university remains open but is run by the students as a platform for national resistance and as a space to experiment with what the
university could become. The last statement is damning of most of the
actions carried out by the majority of protestors at this time and proposes
that all universities, and society itself, should be shut down as a means
of striking at the government. We can discuss who is right and wrong,
which statement is the more idealistic, and whose actions are more symbolic or pragmatic but this would require a second piece of writing. In citing these statements, the intention here is to draw attention to the ways in
which space became the material of protest, and how the production of
negative space became a means of resistance.
By examining the statements produced by the occupations we can
see how refusal relates not just to the political and ethical orientations
but the production of space. This should not be a surprise. First, the protests addressed the problem of who can afford to attend the institutions
of education and culture, and which people and logics administer and
organize these spaces. Secondly, protestors, by marching and occupying,
discovered or confirmed that much so-called public space was constantly
surveyed and policed in London, if not run by or owned by private companies. Kettling, the restraint of groups of people as a means of containing protest or as a means of intimidation by the police, turned out to be a
defining and politicizing experience for many. Finally, protest (in producing the space and time of protest) necessitated the occupation of space
through swarms, teach-ins, disruption of business and the staging of
spectacles. All of which required preparation time and space that for
groups such as Arts Against Cuts and their fellow travelers took the form
of direct action planning weekends at various student unions. For many,
these were the encounters that mattered. Contrary to commentators
who have focussed critically on the use of social network technology by
protestors, face-to-face meetings in physical space were the medium that
217
218
David Burrows
is the most likely result. Clearly, though, Berardi points to how we have
evolved from the postmodern primitives described by Jameson, but to
do so we have evolved into networked individuals dividuals continually making connections. The use of social network media by the occupations, while never fully cutting out the middle man of mass media broadcasters and communications corporations as some claimed, allowed
networked individuals to plug into collective culture and space, and to
broadcast from and about the actual spaces that they affected, controlled
and transformed through action. This radicalization of the dividual went
far beyond the act of creating Facebook pages. Two key examples of the
knotting together of cyberspace and physical space to produce the negative space of protest are the creation of the smartphone application Sukey,
developed by University College London students, to track the movement of the police through gathering Twitter information and the use
of text messages and other social media to amass and disperse swarms
and occupations at rapid speed. Whilst remaining dividuals (connecting,
circulating information and responding to messages) the protestors used
cyberspace to physically manifest negative spaces within the city.
Mise en abyme
To address the role of art as negative space war machines during this
period of protest it is important to clarify further what the term negative space refers to in the context of art. The term is borrowed from an
art school exercise that encourages abstract thinking and drawing. This is
not a process of opposition or of producing opposites; drawing the space
of the negative is different from developing a piece of film as a negative
for a positive photographic print. Rather a negative space drawing counters figuration, habits of seeing and thinking, and our perceptions of what
exists. Negative space is produced through a process of experimenting
with composition, a process that begins with observation (of things and
the unoccupied space around things), but produces new and abstract
arrangements (though a drawing might still bear the trace of the observed
or recognizable world that has all but disappeared in the final image). By
drawing empty space, by drawing nothing rather than things, the transcription of outlines and spaces onto a two-dimensional surface creates
219
220
David Burrows
221
222
David Burrows
Works Cited
Arts Against Cuts. 2010. The Nomadic Hive Manifesto (December 9). Accessed
8 May, 2015 from: https://artsagainstcuts.wordpress.com/2010/12/10/
after-the-national-gallery-teach-in/
Berardi, Franco. 2009a. Communism is Back But We Should Call the Therapy of
Singularization. Generation Online (February) Accessed May 4 2015, from: http://
www.generation-online.org/p/fp_bifo6.htm
Berardi, Franco. 2009b. Precarious Rhapsody: Semiocapitalism and the Pathologies of the
Post-alpha Generation. Ed. Erik Empson and Stevphen Shukaitis. Trans. Arianna
Bove, Michael Goddard, Giuseppina Mecchia, Antonella Schintu and Steve
Wright. London: Minor Compositions.
Curtis, Adam. 2011a. All Watched Over by Machines of Loving Grace. Episode one.
BBC2 (May 23).
Curtis Adam. 2011b. Untitled paper. The Story Conference at Conway Hall (February
20). London: Storythings. Podcast available on iTunes at: https://itunes.apple.
com/gb/podcast/storythings/id439627244?mt=2#
Deleuze, Gilles. 1990. Negotiations 19721990. Trans. Martin Joughin. New York:
Columbia.
Deleuze, Gilles. 1998. Bartleby; or, The Formula. In Essays Critical and Clinical:
19681990. Trans. Daniel W Smith. London and New York: Verso.
Deleuze, Gilles and Flix Guattari. 2003. Treatise on Nomadology War Machines.
In A Thousand Plateaus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia. Trans. Brian Massumi.
London: Continuum: 387467.
Foucault, Michel. 1974. The Archaeology of Knowledge. Trans. AM Sheriden Smith.
London: Tavistock.
Goldsmiths Occupation. 2010a. Goldsmiths Occupation Statement. Mute
(December 7). Accessed May 9, 2015 from: http://www.metamute.org/
community/your-posts/goldsmiths-occupation-statement
Goldsmiths Occupation. 2010b. Statement on the Goldsmiths Occupation.
Mute (December 8). Accessed May 9, 2015 from: http://www.metamute.org/
community/your-posts/statement-goldsmiths-occupation
Jameson, Fredic. 1991. Postmodernism, or, the Cultural Logic of Late Capitalism.
London and New York: Verso.
Land, Nick. 1997. Organisation is Suppression: Interview by James Flint. In Wire
(February). Accessed April 1, 2013 from: http://dialspace.dial.pipex.com/town/
park/di21/art_tech_ec_files/land.htm
223
Land, Nick. 2011. Machinic Desire. In Fanged Noumena: Collected Writings 1987
2000. Cornwall: Urbanomic: 34041.
Mason, Paul. 2012. Why Its Kicking Off Everywhere. London and New York: Verso.
Platonov, Andrei. 1978. Chevengar. Trans. Anthony Olcott. Michigan: Ardis.
Slade Occuption. 2010. Our Statement. Accessed 8 May, 2015 from: https://
sladeoccupation.wordpress.com/our-statement/
Notes
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
224
David Burrows
6.
7.
Mason (2012: 79) describes another (mythical) figure in the same book,
sitting in Starbucks, face colored blue from the reflected light of a laptop.
She may be facebooking, designing, gaming, tweeting or planning protest
and revolution, or all of these things at once. Mason suggests that this marks
a shift in culture from a generation steeped in collectivism to a generation
concerned with the expansion of the individual.
8.
9.
See Arts Against Cuts, Arts Against Cuts: The Long Weekend (December
2, 2010), available at: http://artsagainstcuts.wordpress.com/2010/12/02/
arts-against-cuts-the-long-weekend/
Chapter 9
226
Eugene Holland
227
was the initial French student protest), it very quickly grew beyond the
bounds of anything they had imagined, and certainly grew far beyond
anything they could control. Yet the fact that OWS can be said to have
taken the form of a mutation machine does not make it a panacea: the
contemporaneous right-wing Tea Party movement operated according
to quite similar dynamics although it did benefit from funding by the
likes of the Koch brothers and from media hype provided by the likes of
Fox cable news. As Deleuze and Guattari point out, the Nazis operated
as an autonomous war machine before they took power and integrated
that machine into the apparatus of state rule. Ultimately, then, the form
of organization or of the social dynamics of a given group says relatively
little about the content of their positions or activities. The value of the
concept of the war machine is rather that it directs our attention to the
manner in which these social groups or movements actually operate. And
in OWS and the Tea Party movements, we have chosen rather extreme
examples: it may be that elections in so-called liberal or representative
democracies are always won or lost on the basis of which party can mobilize more numerous and more energetic war machines operating on its
behalf from student volunteers going door-to-door, to volunteer housewives stuffing envelopes, to donors and campaign operatives themselves.
Much like the stock market, electoral politics depends far more than is
usually recognized on the kind of enthusiasm and contagion that are key
elements of the war machine.
Since war machines operate on the Right as well as the Left, and everywhere in between, the fact that OWS took that form, or started out that
way, cannot be considered decisive in evaluating its impact. But the same
was true of the events of May 1968 for Deleuze and Guattari: within the
span of a few months, the French movement had been re-absorbed into
macro-politics as usual, with President de Gaulle receiving broad-based
and strong support in the ensuing elections. But that doesnt mean nothing changed on the level of micro-politics. Deleuze and Guattari describe
deep-seated effects on countless individuals, for one thing in a portrait
that might just as well suit a generation of young Americans who would
soon participate in OWS:
The children of May 68, you can run into them all over
the place, even if they are not aware who they are, and each
228
Eugene Holland
229
230
Eugene Holland
231
we will discuss below. But it poses some problems for the politics of the
war machine, as discussed above. How do you make political action that
is not obviously revolutionary into something contagious? How does the
felt need for social change become urgent? In the 1960s United States, it
was anti-war protest, and the prospect of dying in a war we didnt believe
in, that lent the counter-culture movement its sense of urgency; in 1960s
France, however, there was no such focal point, and yet the French student movement proved far more contagious than its American counterpart, and ended up mobilizing a far greater proportion of the French
people than were mobilized by the American counter-culture and antiwar movements combined. The Occupy movement certainly became
contagious, but despite the name Occupy, it never had concrete longterm ambitions: what will become of Occupy 2.0 is a pressing question
that so far remains unanswered. One of the unfortunate difficulties of the
war machine and non-linear history is that they are so unpredictable
practically by definition. It is just as impossible to produce enthusiasm
or solidarity at will as it is to predict the timing or extent of a bifurcation
point in advance. But it was certainly no accident that ground zero for
the Occupy movement was none other than Wall Street.
The Minor
And it may be just as revealing that the single most enduring, significant
and vigorous off-shoot of the Occupy movement has been the (inaptly
named) Occupy Student Debt movement. To help explain why this
might be so, we can turn to Deleuze and Guattaris adaptation of Marxs
analysis of capital, which I call their minor marxism (Holland 2011).
The key difference between most major or dialectical Marxism and this
minor or structural marxism is that while the former focuses on the results
of the dialectical process of capital accumulation, the latter focuses on the
structural preconditions for capital accumulation also known as primitive accumulation. The watchword of major Marxism follows from the
dialectical precept of the negation of the negation: expropriate the expropriators; confront the power of accumulated capital head-on, and wrest
it from its illegitimate private owners by force. The approach of a minor
marxism is different: address the structural preconditions for capital
232
Eugene Holland
233
234
Eugene Holland
decision in every minute of every day, 24/7/365: for those in debt, each
and every moment of their entire life must enter a calculus of whether it
reduces, merely defers, or actually increases their debt burden.
But modern debt itself takes several different forms. Modern debtfinanced capital investment, of course, dates back to the early days of
mercantile capitalism, and continues unabated under industrial capitalism. The public debt [was] one of the most powerful levers of primitive
accumulation from early on, according to Marx (1887: Chap. 31 Para.
15). But as capitalist production develops and massifies, the realization problem emerges, as we have seen, and debt-financed consumption
arises alongside debt-financed production. Indeed as long as profit gets
extracted from the entire sum of exchanges between wages and commodity prices, capitalism requires debt-financed consumption in order
to survive. But debt-financed consumption itself takes two very different
forms. The first was the great Keynesian-New-Deal-Fordist-welfare-state
gambit, whereby states would go into debt in hard times to bail out capital
through deficit spending, with the expectation, supposedly, that the debt
would be repaid in good times. Except that, as we know, the debt never
does get repaid; instead, it continues to grow and grow and eventually
goes through the ceiling until or unless the ceiling itself is conveniently
moved, as it has been repeatedly by bipartisan acts of Congress. But the
debt ceiling cant be moved forever, at least not without exposing the
whole capitalist accounting system as a massive hoax or Ponzi scheme.
The inevitable conclusion is that capitalism has been living on borrowed
time for at least the last 83 years or on borrowed money, which as we
know is more or less the same thing. Nation states around the world, and
not just the United States, face this long-term sovereign debt crisis, as it
is called Argentina, notoriously, a decade ago; Greece, Italy, Spain, and
Ireland more recently with no final solution in sight. As the Occupy
movement spread around the world, it often focused on this form of debt.
But in the United States, the original OWS focused on the other form of
debt, which we can call neoliberal debt or indentured debt peonage the
kind that Deleuze associates with what he calls control society (Deleuze
1995: 177822). In this form, some of the debt required to keep capitalism afloat gets displaced from sovereign states onto private individuals
(home mortgages, car loans, student loans, credit card retail debt, and so
235
on). While private consumer debt is hardly new, the scale of predatory
abuse of consumers perpetrated by finance capital, including most notably in home mortgages and student loans, went through the roof, and
were a key motivation for OWS, and for the choice of Wall Street as the
place to occupy in the first place.
Minor marxism offers another kind of explanation for OWS choosing Wall Street as its prime target, which has to do with the nature of
debt to begin with. Marx likens the role of so-called primitive accumulation in bourgeois political economy to that of original sin in theology:
it is crucial to everything that follows, but it itself remains unexamined
and/or unexplained. Deleuze and Guattari offer a very different account
of primitive accumulation: on their account, pre-capitalist accumulation is responsible for the appropriation of surplus-labor long before
the rise of capitalism, and the consolidation of capitalism as a mode of
production entails the transfer of what had been an infinite debt from
gods or despots to capital itself. What had been owed to them in various forms of tribute or taxation is henceforth owed to capital in the form
of interest. This means that finance capital has not just a historical precedent (as most Marxists will admit, from the period of mercantile capitalism), but a theoretical precedence as well. For major Marxism, credit
becomes possible because of, and out of, the surplus generated by capitalist production; the dialectical account occupying the first few hundred
pages of Capital, Volume One shows how through a process of increasing
abstraction money emerges from in-kind exchange, and then how the
commodification of labor-power enables money to become capital, and
finally how interest on money represents a share of the surplus-value generated through the production process owed to finance capital. Deleuze
and Guattari, by contrast, insist that finance capital is prior to industrial
capital not just at the historical emergence of capitalism, but in principle
and throughout the history of capitalism. This is so in principle because
Deleuze and Guattari follow Nietzsche in understanding money to be
primarily a vehicle for debt and the establishment and enforcement of
unequal power relations rather than a vehicle for the exchange of equivalents among equal parties. For minor marxism, then, ownership of capital
is first and foremost the power to create value ex nihilo, if only for the
purpose of subsequently introducing it into the production process in
236
Eugene Holland
237
Works Cited
Deleuze, Gilles. 1995. Negotiations 19721990. New York: Columbia University
Press.
Deleuze, Gilles. 2006. Two Regimes of Madness: Texts and Interviews 19751995. Los
Angeles: Semiotext(e).
Deleuze, Gilles and Flix Guattari. 1987. A Thousand Plateaus: Capitalism and
Schizophrenia. Trans. Brian Massumi. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Gibson-Graham, JK. 1996. The End of Capitalism (As We New It): A Feminist Critique
of Political Economy. Cambridge: Blackwell Publishers.
Holland, Eugene W. 2011. Nomad Citizenship: Free-Market Communism and the SlowMotion General Strike. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Marx, Karl. 1887. Capital, Volume One. Trans. Samuel Moore and Edward Aveling.
Accessed May 8, 2015 from: https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/
works/1867-c1/index.htm
Patton, Paul. 2000. Deleuze and the Political. London and New York: Routledge.
Chapter 10
Savage Money1
Andrew Conio
The process by which banks create money is so simple that the
mind is repelled.
JK Galbraith (1975: 29)
Banks create money. That is what they are there for Each
time a Bank makes a loan new Bank credit is created
brand new money.
Graham Towers, Governor of the Bank of Canada 1935 to 1955
Savage Money
239
This single feature impacts upon every aspect of economic and political life. First, it is difficult to overstate the role that bank money played
in the creation of the housing bubble. The rise in house prices was not a
supply and demand issue: over the last 20 years US housing stock grew
by 16%, meaning that the number of houses grew faster than did the
number of people, whilst mortgage lending grew by almost 600% over
the same period. Subprime mortgage lending increased from $30 billion
a year to $600 billion a year in 10 years, leading to an effective doubling
of house prices.
This endogenous form of money creation has distorted the UK
national economy and cannot be disassociated from the gigantic Ponzi
scheme that brought the world economy to its knees. It was the transformation of debt into tradable securities that made possible the invention
of securitization and the armory of financial weapons of mass destruction, as Warren Buffet dubbed them.
Bank-created money provided the base fuel for unrestrained money
creation taking into account the $1.5 quadrillion derivatives market, it
is safe to say that in effect money creation became infinite. This is a system whereby so-called fiat money, money that is not backed by reserves
of another commodity, became virtual.
In a speech to the Committee on Monetary and Economic Reform,
Michael Rowbotham (2013) dissects most clearly how a debt-based
economy squeezes disposable income; it also squeezes the profit margins
of businesses creating the need for cheaper and cheaper products and
higher levels of mass production, which in turn creates increased impoverishment of the labor force, thousands of tons of cheap and disposable
goods, and the unpayable social and environmental costs of production
and distribution. Money creation is the main driver behind the imperative for growth that is in essence the driver of ecological destruction.
As Ross Jackson notes, the most important single factor that is driving our civilization toward ecological collapse is the promotion of great
per capita consumption as the primary goal of every nation state at a time
when we are already over-consuming (2012: 73). The stark reality is that
if we continue to pursue the economic growth required to pay off the
debts then runaway climate change is all but guaranteed.
240
Andrew Conio
When banks create money they realize the stuff of wizards and legends. The magical power to create your own money in the form of an
asset out of thin air is expressed by Paul Fisher (2013) thus:
When you start printing money, you create some value for
yourself. If you can issue a thousand pounds worth of IOUs to
everybody, youve got a thousand pounds for nothing.
From 2003 to 2013 the banks created 1trillion, netting
interest of between 108bn to 217bn every single year. The
financial system has effectively held the political system hostage. As banks create money they have the power to shape the
economy and decide the economic priorities of the nation.
With little bearing on any sensible measure of what counts as economic
development and wealth creation, between 1980 and 2007 the assets of
the banking sector grew from $2.5 trillion to $40 trillion. In 1980 banking assets were worth 20 times the then global economy; by 2006 they
were worth 75 times (according to the UN). Due to this wizardry banks
have an undue influence on the development of the economy. Assetstripping, off-shoring and speculative trading are now favored over the
steady growth that emerges out of a commitment to manufacturing and
long-term business-development. As a result, new money is often more
likely to be channelled into property and financial speculation than into
small businesses and manufacturing, with profound economic consequences for society.4 Given that five banks control 85% of the money in
the UK economy, a total of 87 board members (or 30 to 40 key decision
makers) have effective control over the nations money supply.
Government has to gear its policies to keeping the money (debt) supply working, and because the banks are essentially responsible for that
supply, when they get into trouble, government that is, taxpayers
have to bail them out. We have no choice. We find ourselves in a position where the banks lending is higher than all government spending.
Further, each and everyone of us now has to shoulder the burden of this
debt; the natural human propensity to take responsibility for oneself, to
shoulder ones burden, is exploited and masochistically internalized as
we take upon ourselves the costs and risks of the economic and financial disaster.
Savage Money
241
Financial markets became integral to the administration of public debts, accompanied by an expansion of their logic, their rules, their
imperatives and interests. This implies, finally, the shifting of the reserves
of sovereignty. The financialization of government structures, the mediation between public and private debts have mechanized political decisions as market-driven decisions; the markets themselves have become a
sort of creditor-god, whose final authority decides the fate of currencies,
social systems, public infrastructures, private savings, etc. (Vogl 2012: 5)
The overall effect of this cycle was a colossal transfer of wealth from
the poor to the rich. Far from creating jobs, and prompting the miraculous trickle down effect, this wealth concentration created a restriction
of real demand. The owners of assets (property, stocks and shares, private equity, complex financial products, works of art, race horses, etc.)
were able to use easy credit to inflate the value of those assets. By these
means were they obscenely enriched. Those without assets and therefore
without access to easy credit were correspondingly impoverished. Thus
did the rich get richer, and the poor poorer. The repugnant effects spread
across household, regional and global scales as debt repayment was used
to justify outcomes that would be intolerable in other circumstances: an
avalanche of people losing their homes, who also can no longer afford
healthcare; countries losing their economic sovereignty and devastating
their social provision; cancellation of healthcare programs leading to the
deaths of tens of thousands and, on a global scale, the hunger, even starvation, of vast numbers and the immiseration of millions.
The link between the housing bubble and money creation is clear, as
is the relationship between the creation of the shadow banking system,
the huge swathes of predatory products, and the vulture, voodoo or
downright quasi-criminal speculative trading schemes that brought the
world economic system to the brink of collapse. Bank credit provided the
fuel, deregulation the environment, and algorithms the velocity required
to create colossal sums and to some extent shield the players from their
responsibilities.
For the Positive Money campaign group, the effect endogenous
money has had on the banking sector betrays the structural flaw at the
heart of the financial system in the form of ceding control of the nations
finances to private interests. What has become clearer is the central role
242
Andrew Conio
money creation has played in this, along with the staging of a financial
coup dtat by the financial services industry. A rogue, predatory industry, bereft of moral values, has been bolstered by an idiotic idiom that
models only objective illusions (Goodchild 2013: 55) perpetuated by
an economics profession that has captured the debate to the exclusion of
any consideration of the values of life, ethics, species, planet, community,
compassion, or the future of life itself.
However, whilst from the perspective of mainstream (neoliberal)
economic theory, Positive Moneys thesis may be considered unorthodox, from a philosophical or anthropological perspective they rely on a
set of conventional and unexamined predicates, particularly around the
nature of money, which they take to be relatively colorless or frictionless
instead of originativily and structurally riven with power relations. With
regard to the history, nature and function of money this paper questions
whether there exists an unbridgeable methodological, ethical or ontological divide between speculative philosophy and political economy.
To answer this question, I propose a journey from the empirical policy-driven world of Positive Money to the experimental empiricism of
Gilles Deleuze and Flix Guattari, in order to test one against the other.
I will examine the theory of money presented in Anti-Oedipus, which is
coming to be regarded as a prescient and prophetic reading of contemporary capitalism.
In conclusion, I suggest that the philosophical speculations of Deleuze
and Guattari and Positive Moneys empirical approach to debt-based
money can, despite emerging from wholly different epistemologies and
methodologies, be overlaid, one atop the other like tracing paper, each
ultimately saying the same thing. The political, economic, and philosophical consequences of this are far reaching. Not least in the identification
of a potential meeting place for the most intensive critiques of capitalism
as a totalizing abstract machine and the political demands of policy formation and reform.
Credit and Debt
The following discussion is framed by four works that have the strongest
purchase on the issues at hand: Friedrich Nietzsches On the Genealogy
Savage Money
243
of Morality (1887), David Graebers Debt: The First 5000 Years (2011),
Deleuze and Guattaris Anti-Oedipus, and Maurizio Lazzaratos The
Making of Indebted Man (2011). The first three books each delineate
differently the same formative period in the development of humanity
before the emergence of societies that were structured chiefly through
the interaction of church, money and state. The period is outlined with
different emphases but with substantive details in common as the The
Axial Age5 (Graeber), Primitive Society (Nietzsche), or Primitive/
Territorial Society6 (Deleuze and Guattari). Lazzaratos work offers a
reading of a new stage of capitalist development (contemporary finance
capital) and the concomitant emergence of a new subject, the indebted
man, by way of the Nietzsche-inspired thoughts of Deleuze and Guattari.
Graeber accumulates extensive anthropological and historical evidence going back millennia to take issue with the conventional view
that money emerged in order to expedite barter and to demonstrate that
coins were used in the Agrarian Age7 which preceded the Axial Age but
were made to suit the needs of small city states, and acted as a currency
of last resort when informal credit systems became too unwieldy. They
had few of the features which we would today associate with money.
This concurs with Deleuze and Guattaris description of primitive
territorial societies where debt was plural, finite and based on systems of
alliance. Indeed, in a recent International Monetary Fund (IMF) paper
Benes and Kumhof (2012: 12) pull together an even wider range of
accounts which in their different ways show that money did not develop
out of the need to trade or as a way of measuring equivalences.
Nietzsches thesis in the Genealogy of Morals can be expressed in short
order: man is innately aggressive, he expresses enmity, cruelty, joy in pursuit, in attack, in destruction, and to think otherwise is navely to divorce
man from his animal nature. In primeval times, within the original tribal
cooperatives, relations were principally relations of judgment and measure rather than cooperation and mutuality. Nietzsche (1998) outlines in
his book On the Genealogy of Morality that man is an inherently calculating animal, and selling and buying, together with their psychological
attributes, are the oldest forms of social organization.
The character of the system for the measurement and collection
of debts determined the logic of social exchange and relations. With
244
Andrew Conio
Savage Money
245
246
Andrew Conio
Savage Money
247
memory and accounting tools, but did not have the functions normally
associated with money as exchange value, stores of wealth, or commodity. Money in the form we know it today emerged out of conquest. It was
the form in which the conqueror could extract tribute and/or facilitate
expansion. A single currency replaced a myriad of logical currencies
some of which were metal-based coinage. Here is Graeber:
Coinage, certainly, was not invented to facilitate trade. It
appears to have been first invented to pay soldiers, probably
first of all by rulers of Lydia in Asia Minor to pay their Greek
mercenaries. Carthage, another great trading nation, only
started minting coins very late, and then explicitly to pay its
foreign soldiers. (2009)
After the violence of conquest, populations were enslaved and tribute
extracted, not least to pay for the campaign and to create a market in
which the conquerors were sole controllers of a currency invented precisely for purpose of control and domination.
The credit systems of the Near East did not crumble under commercial competition; they were destroyed by Alexanders armies armies that
required half a ton of silver bullion per day in wages. The mines where
the bullion was produced were generally worked by slaves. Military campaigns in turn ensured an endless flow of new slaves. Imperial tax systems,
as noted, were largely designed to force their subjects to create markets,
so that soldiers (and also, of course, government officials) would be able
to use that bullion to buy anything they wanted (Graeber 2009).
The despot would impose his currency on the society, while local currencies were downgraded in relation to a single representative of value,
which served as the measure of power relations, hierarchy, social control
and obligations.
Graeber puts this into sharp relief when he asks why the ruler created
coins when he owned all the gold and silver mines anyway. The answer
is that coins became not only the most efficient way of paying the troops
and buying supplies, but also the main way of supplicating the population in bondage who were required to pay their taxes in coins, which
were exchanged for the produce they made. A relationship of disequilibrium thus becomes exquisitely efficient, and a hierarchical form of social
248
Andrew Conio
Savage Money
249
250
Andrew Conio
from bonds, class and the exhilarating freedom of all things to shed limiting meanings, purposes, uses or values. This is a tremendously productive
development in human relations. To be able to borrow without sticky
social or kinship obligations is an attribute of individual autonomy and
existential capacity.
Moneys emergence does mean that there is a tendency for personal,
finite (that is, dischargeable) compassionate indebtedness, the binding
among people borne out of mutual reliance, to give way to alienated and
commodified relations, but the opposite is also the case; money can also
be used to express love and compassion, to appease and facilitate human
relations and forge the social bond.
Unquestionably, money creates hierarchies, changes the nature of
obligation, monetizes relations and changes the value of everything, particularly subjective, social and ecological relations. But this type of thinking must not shelter ressentiment towards the innovations, entrepreneurial
risks and expansion that capitalism affords. Money also creates new alliances, new soma, affects, desires and thoughts; polyplurient life is facilitated through money as pure flow. Capitalism forces us to be free, and
this is an axiom, but, without question, millions of people find contentment through the opportunities, freedom and security that capitalism
and the inherent ease of money affords. However, as Goodchild (2010:
33) points out, a specific historical process has taken place, from money
as universal equivalent and exchange value to money as speculative capital, until finally money replaces itself as a differential, reflexive flow.
Money has so many dimensions it is little wonder that no definitive
theory of it exists. Such rhetorical statements as in capitalism the debt
becomes infinite because one is submitted to a law and a system, but this
law does not demand a particular body so much as empty and formal
submission (Colebrook 2006: 130) need to be balanced by the fact that
the deterritorialization facilitated by exchange enables the transcendence
of all bodies including God, the despot, the nation state, Oedipus, and
class. Money is both capture and release: the deepest diastolic and systolic movements of the psyche and the bowels are manifested in the flows
of the financial markets. The desolate capitalist system is also creative,
innovative and facilitative of human needs and multiple layers of expression and joy. It is nothing short of arrogant to dismiss the hard creative
Savage Money
251
252
Andrew Conio
Savage Money
253
It is much more than a coincidence that the New York Stock Exchange
topped 15,000 for the first time ever just as it was announced that the
atmosphere had absorbed 400 ppm CO2. Such is the ruin that the only
recourse open to it appears to be a return to much more savage social
formations as increasingly modern capitalist and socialist states take on
the characteristic features of the primordial despotic state (Deleuze and
Guattari 2000: 220). Think of drone strikes, the prisonindustrial complex and direct tribute in the form of quantitative easing. It is more than
a note in passing to comment that for Deleuze and Guattari history is not
teleological, as primitive, despotic and civilized capitalist machines coexist in contemporary society.
The world as represented by capitalism is therefore seen through the
wrong lens. Instead of a world of production, wealth, values, and social
relations, the world as represented increasingly manifests the exclusive
requirements of the monetary system, the first requirement of which is
the production of more money. Labor processes and general production
that were once the heartbeat of society are now used to produce only capital. The deployment of this quotation from Marx in Anti-Oedipus illustrates why Deleuze and Guattari refer to themselves as Marxists: Capital
is dead labour that vampire-like, only lives by sucking living labour, and
lives the more, the more labour it sucks (Marx 1887: 160).
However, and this is the real matter at hand, such is the nature of
money that any discussion of its historical development and the amorphousness of its form bears yet further contradistinction in a seemingly
endless movement between adversative conjunctions such as also,
but and however that is logically unavoidable. This is not a problem
because the defining feature of any Deleuzian analysis is its capacity to
take into account the contradictions inherent in any issue. Deleuze,
across his entire corpus, whether on painting or cinema, philosophy or
science, develops systems that create dynamic relations between what
other systems would treat as irreconcilable contradictions, paradoxes
or dialectics. Hence, we live under the axiomatics of capitalism, yet life
retains its vitalism; the society of control regulates social relations, yet
across A Thousand Plateaus unexpected speeds and slowness traverse the
machinic, human and organic, in expressions of social life composed of
melodic refrains.
254
Andrew Conio
Savage Money
255
is the same as that amassed by the billionaires. But the stability provided
by the idea that money is a determinate quantity entered on bank statements and balance sheets is based only on faith, as are the distortions,
specious premises, bogus methodologies and mathematical tautologies
of the dismal science known as economics. Economic rationality only
makes sense within a system that is irrational and is divorced from other
measures that would include rudimentary values for life.
Everything is rational in capitalism, except capital or capitalism itself.
The stock market is certainly rational; one can understand it, study it, the
capitalists know how to use it, and yet it is completely delirious; its mad
(Deleuze and Guattari 2001: 215).
The other objective part to this system is the sense that money is the
fabric of life that we all have equal access to. It is approachable: it exists
right there in front of you, not actually outside of you but as part of your
very constitution; your processes are exactly the processes you have
inherited. Hence:
this principle of convertibility which is enough to ensure
that the desire of the most disadvantaged creature will invest
with all its strength, irrespective of any economic understanding or lack of it, the capitalist social field as a whole. Flows,
who doesnt desire flows, and relationships between flows,
and breaks in flows? (Deleuze and Guattari 2000: 229)
Accordingly, an appearance is given of a medium of exchange that is fair,
and able to provide a quantitative determination of all things as a price;
yet in and of itself, it is neutral. Moreover, we can position ourselves
wherever we wish in relation to it, and should take responsibility for
our autonomous choices. Yet the effects of the price mechanism are also
pernicious, it creates an illusion of a primary equivalence at the heart of
society, and inurs us to a fundamental disequilibrium, as Shaviro (2011:
8) observes: The price system continually forces us into debt. And
thereby it confines, restricts, and channels our behavior far more rigidly,
and effectively, than any compulsion based upon mere brute force would
be able to do.
256
Andrew Conio
Savage Money
257
way, 2,700 companies get to pocket the money paid by their employees
in tax. Five-and-a-half billion dollars has been diverted from workers
paychecks in this way. US pipeline companies are exempt from corporate income tax but they are allowed to include the tax on the rates they
charge customers. Energy customers are thus paying a tax that does not
exist and this increases the ultimate return to the owners of these pipelines by as much as 75%. Recent research shows that in the UK welfare
support functions as a failure to pay a living wage subsidy to the employers of 5.5 million workers, and private sector housing benefit serves as a
direct transfer of public funds to property owners and banks. This shift
from profit to rent is also noted by Lofgren (2012), who writes that the
super rich aim to create a tollbooth economy, whereby more and more
of our highways, bridges, libraries, parks, and beaches are possessed by
private oligarchs who will extract a toll from the rest of us.
All of the accounts discussed above confront us with the same question: are we dealing with an anthropological invariant or a historically
specific assemblage of forces? The answer is that the disequilibrium
inherent to relations of exchange, which came to be expressed in money,
is the originative paradigm of the social, and that the debt paradigm has
displaced or superseded other forms of capitalist development (cognitive
capital, financial capital, and so on). The neoliberal form is a specific form
of debt relation in which this paradigm of capture, predation and extraction forms the very basis of social life. The creditordebtor relationship
constitutes specific relations of power that entail specific forms of production and control of subjectivity a particular form of homo economicus the indebted man (Lazzarato 2012: 778). Thus, in neoliberalism,
the creditordebtor relationship encompasses all other relations: capital/
labor, business/customer, workers/consumers. Everyone is a debtor,
accountable and guilty before capital. Capital has become the Great
Creditor, the Universal Creditor.
The question arises as to the relationship between an abstraction,
a seemingly amorphous ubiquitous indebtedness, and specific material acts such as the invention of new financial products, new computer
algorithms, and the pre-crash wave of deregulation. The question often
directed to Deleuzes articulation of the society of control (and to his
wider politics) similarly concerns the relationship between the indefinite
258
Andrew Conio
and the specific. In answer we should note that a significant feature of the
Deleuzean and Guattarian political landscape is their tendency to avoid
giving specific examples of (and indexes to) even their most productive
and worthwhile political concepts capitalist axiomatics, schizoanalysis,
the war machine requiring the reader to experiment with them each
time they are used. To prevent ossification concepts must remain mobile,
work in multiple circumstances and be brought into relations with other
concepts in the manner of creating new understandings and potentials
for political thought, and have an inherent resistance to subsumption and
clich. Most importantly, though, is that a level of abstraction must operate as a necessary counter-force and weapon: we must rise to this level of
abstraction and deterritorialisation if we want to avoid being swept away
or crushed by the Great Creditor (Lazzarato 2011: 161).
Exchange Money, Credit Money
Accepting, indeed welcoming, all the paradoxes inherent to this statement: Deleuze and Guattaris identification of a profound dualism at the
heart of money is the rock bottom of all of the matters at hand. For them
we cannot underestimate:
the extreme importance in the capitalist system of the dualism
between the formation of means of payment and the structure of financing, between the management of money and
the financing of capitalist accumulation, between exchange
money and credit money (2000: 229).
Credit money and exchange money are tendencies; the multiple interactions between the two use the same coin, and banks facilitate both financing and payment transactions with one continually flowing into the other.
Even so, the fundamental difference between the two is of inestimable
importance. There is a profound dissimulation of the dualism of these
two forms of money, payment and financing the two aspects of banking
practice (Deleuze and Guattari 2000: 229). In this sense, it is decidedly
not the same coin that is counted as credit on the balance sheet and in the
pocket of the wage earner. Credit money is where the flow of exchange is
Savage Money
259
arrested, where values are assigned, and divinations of purpose, rent and
ownership are made according to the axiomatics of capitalism.
On the one hand, exchange money has no value in and of itself: it is
an impotent sign of exchange value, it could be a theatre token, a shell
or a notch. On the other hand, credit money traverses a particular circuit
where it assumes, then loses, its value as an instrument of exchange and
where the conditions of flux imply conditions of reflex, giving the infinite
debt its capitalist form. It is here that Deleuze and Guattari predict the
impact of credit money: bank credit effects a demonetisation or dematerialization of money, and is based on the circulation of drafts instead
of the circulation of money (Deleuze and Guattari 2000: 229). Drafts
here correspond only in part to the 97% bank-issued money identified by
Positive Money; in reality they include the trillions of dollars conjured
up by the shadow banking system. In short: the capitalist field of immanence is sustained by the circulation of credit money (Kerslake 2009),
and through credit the archetype of violence and savagery is forcibly
built into the nature of money, and money is a precondition for existence
in any part of the globe (Shaviro 2011). This credit-and-exchange-money
binary solves a residual problem with the Marxist theory of money.
It is unfortunate that Marxist economists too often dwell on the mode
of production, and on the theory of money as the general equivalent as
found in the first section of Capital, without attaching enough importance to banking practice, to financial operations, and the specific circulation of credit money (Deleuze and Guattari 2000: 230).
At this stage of the argument, it should be clear that trying to establish the essence or truth of money, trying to pinpoint its role and function, should give way to the problem of forces. What counts is less the
essential nature of money than what it does. Capitalism is sustained by
the great paradoxes between its dynamism and destructiveness; invention and despotism, freedom and servitude, the implacability of its axioms and demand to constantly revolutionize them, these can be understood in terms of this essential dualism and how the irrepressible creative
charge and rhizomic flow of capital is essentially underpinned by credit
money, or more importantly, how exchange money comes into existence
as credit money:
260
Andrew Conio
Savage Money
261
where success is to be found where their policies have been ignored, yet
all the while they have magnificently convinced the world that capitalism and not just capitalism, but exactly the financialized, semi-feudal
capitalism we happen to have right now is the only viable economic
system (Graeber 2013). Thus banks not only have the capacity to control
investment and interest, most importantly they control the relationship
between credit and exchange money that becomes the principal feature
of the capitalist mode of production itself.
This is Deleuzes first axiomatic of capitalism that it must be presented as common sense, irrefragable and transcendental in its immanence; that it insists there is no other way of controlling the schiz/flow,
credit money/exchange money, credit/debt whilst concealing its chronic
wastefulness and iniquity and the inherent power relations: therein; and
that it inhibits human creativity largely through the issuance of money.
Through the system of debts, money imposes an immense
and irresistible system of social control on individuals, corporations, and governments, each of whom are threatened by
economic failure if they refuse their obligations to the money
system. (Kerslake 2009)
In this way, neoliberalism is the control society we are controlled by and
submit to its values as it insists that alternatives to its immanence are
crushed. Kerslake is right, Anti-Oedipus was prophetic:
There is always a monotheism on the horizon of despotism:
the debt becomes a debt of existence, a debt of the existence
of the subjects themselves. A time will comewhen the creditor has not yet lent while the debtor never quits repaying.
(Deleuze and Guattari 2000: 197)
Here we can recognize the phenomenological struggle of the mind to
take in the colossal sums of bank credit, the quadrillions produced by
the financial services industry as assets, securities and virtual credit, that
exist alongside the flows and intimacies of everyday life facilitated by
exchange money. Whilst they may be expressed in the same coin their
functions are so dissimilar as to make it impossible to conceive of them as
the same thing. Today, consumption, production and the production of
subjectivity are geared to provide the surplus value needed to give these
262
Andrew Conio
Savage Money
263
Todays money has become the primary agent of capital accumulation and an aggressive catalyst of dispossession that, in
order to feed itself, uses enormous leverage to parasitically
prey on life and energy in general, insatiably consuming emergent, biological and processual forms of life and matter in
order to feed that which both keeps it alive and expanding:
debt. (Tiessen 2012)
In the meeting of Positive Money, and Deleuze and Guattari there is no
need to posit contradictions between philosophical and anthropological
speculations and the objective political policies and programs of political
economy. Controlling the banks issuance of money is a specific weapon,
perhaps the most urgently needed of our age. A range of currencies serving different purposes is also needed. Such a range already exists.9 The
coexistence of a range of currencies with a state-issued currency may
be the first of a series of experiments wherein the philosophical work of
Deleuze and Guattari might find practical concrete application. As would
a combination of reforms that piece-by-piece may gain the consistency
of a counter-aggregate sufficient to cause the capitalist abstract machine
to lose its potency. Like much of the Occupy movement worldwide, the
OccupyLSX Economics Working Group (EWG), of which the author is
a member, is discussing a range of specific policy initiatives and reforms
to the monetary system. The three main foci of these discussions for the
EWG in London are thus: reform of the issuance of money; reform of
the structure of land ownership and rent; and reform of wage structures
along the lines of guaranteeing a minimum income to all citizens regardless of status or employment. It is striking how much of this chimes with
Deleuzes description of the three main decodings that came together to
create the capitalist system:
These decodings of all kinds consisted in the decoding of land
flows, under the form of the constitution of large private properties, the decoding of monetary flows, under the form of the
development of merchant fortunes, the decoding of a flow of
workers under the form of expropriation, of the deterritorialisation of serfs and peasant landholders. (Deleuze 1971)
264
Andrew Conio
Works Cited
Benes, Jaromir and Michael, Kumhof. 2012. The Chicago Plan Revisited. IMF Working
Paper, WP/12/202. International Monetary Fund.
Coghlan, Andy and Debora Mackenzie. 2011. Revealed The Capitalist Network
that Runs the World. New Scientist 2835. Accessed May 8, 2015 from: http://
www.newscientist.com/article/mg21228354.500-revealed--the-capitalistnetwork-that-runs-the-world.html#.UidCblNvk0w
Colebrook, Claire. 2006. Deleuze: A Guide for the Perplexed. London: Continuum.
Savage Money
265
266
Andrew Conio
Savage Money
267
Notes
1.
2.
Over 600,000 YouTube views of their video 97% Owned (as of March 4,
2014); 30,000 visits per month to http://www.positivemoney.org
3.
4.
5.
6.
Deleuze and Guattari identify three different social machines: The primitive
territorial machine of savage society; the imperial despotic machine of
barbarian society; and the capitalist immanent machine of civilized society.
7.
8.
268
Andrew Conio
each other. The map of power also uncovers a wider set consisting of a core
group of 1,318 companies which controlled 60% of global revenues (Coghlan
and Mackenzie 2011). This concentration is the result of both preferential
connectiveness motivated by existing power relations (players gravitate
towards the most powerful groups, networks or individuals) and naturally
occurring structures relating to systems characterized by complexity.
So, the architecture of the network of power showing the characteristics
associated with small-world networks together with the kind of business
companies do, and the shared assumptions about the economy that unite
decision-makers into a coherent hub, combine to establish the super-entity
determining the fate of the global economy. It means a small elite the
1%? wields enormous power which can by-pass democratic control and
regulations.
9.
In the form of: time banks; air miles (United Airlines in the USA used to
pay their entire worldwide PR account in frequent flyer points); electronic
barter currencies (Trade Dollars Northwest) and international currency
(universal); herocards in Minneapolis, Local Economic Trading Schemes;
and, loyalty cards (Boots loyalty card has space on it for various different
loyalty currencies).
Bios
Ian Buchanan is Professor of Cultural Studies at the University of
Wollongong. He is the author of the Dictionary of Critical Theory (OUP)
and the editor of Deleuze Studies (EUP).
David Burrows is an artist, writer and lecturer based in London and
working at Slade School of Fine Art, UCL. He exhibits and presents performances in the UK and abroad, working independently and in collaboration to produce the performance fiction Plastique Fantastique.
Claire Colebrook is Edwin Erle Sparks Professor of English at Penn
State University. She has written books and articles on Literary Theory,
Feminist Theory, Queer Theory, Contemporary European Philosophy
and the visual culture. Her most recent books are the two-volume Essays
on Extinction (Open Humanities Press, 2013). She is currently completing Fragility: Species, Planet, Earth for Duke University Press.
Andrew Conio is an artist, writer and activist. He organised public
debates and gatherings at Occupy St Pauls in London, worked on the
information tent and served as a member of the Occupy Economic
Working Group until 2014. Andrew teaches at the School of Music
and Fine Art, Kent University, and has published on a range of subjects
including language, the moving image, architecture, painting, institutional critique and creativity.
Verena Andermatt Conley teaches in Comparative Literature and
Romance Languages and Literature at Harvard University. She writes on
issues of ecology and technology. Her recent publications include Spatial
Ecologies (Liverpool, 2012) and Nancy Now (Polity, 2013), co-edited
with Irving Goh.
270
Bios
Bios
271
Philosophy/Political
Conio
Occupy
A People Yet to Come
Edited by Andrew Conio