Philosophical Methodology: The Ohio State University
Philosophical Methodology: The Ohio State University
Philosophical Methodology: The Ohio State University
Kevin Scharp
Analytic philosophy goes through phases of being obsessed with its own methodology; it is
currently in the midst of one. It seems that there are at least the following six major kinds of
experience) or analytic (i.e., true by virtue of their content alone) connections between some
concept and other concepts. Often it is seen as doing even more: specifying the conceptual
constituents of some complex concept. For example, a conceptual analysis of the concept
of bachelor might be that bachelors are unmarried human males. In this case, it seems as
though the concept analyzed is more complex than the concepts used in the analysis.
However, one need not adhere to this basic/complex view of analysis. Conceptual analysis
came in for some blistering attacks in the mid 20th century2, but despite that, it seems to be
(i.e., the item to be explained) is wholly subsumed under the explanans (i.e., the items in
1 This classification is very rough—the list is not exhaustive and the descriptions are in no way definitive; see
the cited works for more detailed treatments.
2 See Quine (1951, 1960), Putnam (1962, 1971, 1975), and Kripke (1972) for examples.
3 The most influential contemporary defense of conceptual analysis is certainly Jackson (1998); see also Jackson
(2001a, 2001b), Balog (2001), Stich and Weinberg (2001), Stalnaker (2001), and Williamson (2001, 2008). See
also Lewis (1994).
kind of reductive explanation according to which every genuine phenomenon can be
reduced to the phenomena studied by the hard sciences (and often to fundamental physics).
Reductive naturalists hold that all genuine phenomena are, at root, physical phenomena.
This includes consciousness, moral properties, mental states, and so on. There are versions
of reductive explanation that are not naturalistic; for example, reductive phenomenalism
reduces all genuine phenomena to experience.4 The reduction of all genuine phenomena to
the explanans class can be accomplished by translation (e.g., a reductive naturalist might say
that all claims about legitimate phenomena can be translated into the vocabulary of particle
physics), but it need not; a laxer reductive explanation appeals to apriori entailment instead of
translation (e.g., a reductive naturalist of this stripe might claim that all true claims about
legitimate phenomena are entailed apriori by true claims about the nature and behavior of
fundamental particles).5 The former is closely connected to conceptual analysis, while the
3. Quietism is a method that avoids proposing and defending philosophical theories, and
instead sees philosophical problems as the result of confusions that are often caused by
ideas (or perhaps just remind us of things we already knew) in a way that exposes the
4 See Carnap (1928), Quine (1951), and Sellars (1963) for more on phenomenalism.
5 Even weaker reductions are familiar as well; e.g., the technical relation of supervenience is sometimes used—I
discuss it in Chapter Three.
6 See the papers in Hohwy and Kallestrup (2008) on reductive explanation; see Chalmers (2010) for much more
on the “apriori entailment” version of reductive explanation. See also Block and Stalnaker (1999), Chalmers
and Jackson (2001), and Gertler (2002) on conceptual analysis and reductive explanation. See the papers in de
Caro and Macarthur (2004) for criticism of reductive naturalism.
2
Contemporary quietism is heavily influenced by Ludwig Wittgenstein; John McDowell is
4. Experimental Philosophy is new on the scene; although it has historical precursors,8 in its
current form it is just a decade or so old. Experimental philosophy eschews the kind of
armchair reflection and intuitions that other philosophical methods, especially conceptual
theory about the source of those intuitions, and that theory is then used to support or attack
various philosophical views that depend on those intuitions. Attitudes toward this new
analysis and reductive explanation, but it seeks a synthesis of the latter two methods with the
reductive explanation focuses, analytic pragmatism looks to relations between how words are
used and the concepts those words express. The goal of an analytic pragmatist project is to
specify relations between the concepts used to describe how some words are used and the
concepts those words express. Although there are plenty of precursors, analytic pragmatism
7 See Wittgenstein (1953), Zangwell (1992), Wright (1992: ch. 6, 1998), McDowell (1994, 2009), Pettit (2004),
Rorty (2007), and Kuusela (2008) for discussion of quietism. Note that the term ‘quietism’ has come to have a
negative connotation in the hands of philosophers like Blackburn (see his 1998); for this reason, one might
prefer the term ‘therapeutic’. However, I intend no such implication.
8 Naess (1938) for example, which bears particular relevance to the topic of this book.
9 See the papers in Knobe and Nicholas (2008) for more on experimental philosophy.
3
as a philosophical methodology is new, and its primary expositor and defender is Robert
Brandom.10
emphasize the similarity or continuity between science and philosophy; they suggest that
philosophical problems should be approached by using the methods of the sciences and that
philosophical theories should, like scientific theories, not only offer explanations, but be
empirically testable. Beyond that, there is very little agreement on how to pursue
performing experiments on philosophical topics (e.g., there is no laboratory where one can
study the properties of propositions) cause problems for methodological naturalist projects.12
10 See Brandom (2008) for the presentation of analytic pragmatism. I take the projects in Kripke (1982),
Davidson (2001), Stanley (2005), Kukla and Lance (2008), and Capellen and Hawthorne (2009) to be instances
of analytic pragmatism.
11 The qualifier ‘as a philosophical method’ is meant to distinguish it from the view in philosophy of science,
which sometimes goes under the same name, that one of the criteria for science is that it rejects supernatural
explanations.
12 See Papineau (2007) for an overview of methodological naturalism. See Wilson (2006) and Maddy (2008) for
examples. See also Price (forthcoming) for what he calls subject naturalism, which I take to be very similar.
See the papers in Braddon-Mitchell and Nola (2009) for a discussion of the relation between conceptual
analysis and naturalism.