Kantian Anthropology Frontlines - UNT 2015
Kantian Anthropology Frontlines - UNT 2015
Kantian Anthropology Frontlines - UNT 2015
Curry)
Over and beyond Buffon or Linnaeus, Kant, in his transcendental philosophy (e.g.,
Critique of Pure Reason), describes ways of orienting oneself geographically in space,
mathematically in space and time, and, logically, in the construction of both categories
into other sorts of consistent whole. In the Observations on the Feeling o/the Beautiful and Sublime, a work which
ought to be considered as primarily anthropological , Kant shows the theoretic transcendental
philosophical position at work when he attempts to work out and establish how a
particular (moral) feeling relates to humans generally, and how it differs between men and
women, and among different races. For example, "feeling" as it
appears in the title of the work refers to a specific refinement of character which is universally properly human: that is, belonging
to human nature as such. And we recall that for Kant "human nature" resides in the developmental expression of rational-moral
In order to assign man into a system of living nature, and thus to characterize him, no other alternative is left than this: that he has
a character which he himself creates by being capable of perfecting himself after the purposes chosen by himself. Through this,
he, as an animal endowed with reason (animale rationabile) can make out of himself a rational animal (animale rationale).
If non-white peoples lack "true" rational character (Kant believes, for example, that the character of the
Mohr is made up of imagination rather than reason) and therefore lack "true" feeling and moral sense,
then they do not have "true" worth, or dignity. The black person, for example, can
accordingly be denied full humanity, since full and "true" humanity accrues only to the
white European. For Kant European humanity is the humanity par excellence.
___. Kants belief in Black inferiority is a transcendental grounding of his moral philosophy. He believes
that reason itself demands recognizing the racial inferiority of the African such that it gives credence to
the transcendental grounding of European reason itself.
Eze1997 (Emmanuel, Professor of Philosophy @DePaul University, The Color of Reason in
PostColonial African Philosophy: A Critical Reader [Cambridge: Blackwell Publishing, 1997], 103-131
Kant's idea of the constitutively anthropological feeling thus derives from his
conception of the reality of "humanity itself," for "feeling" reveals a specific,
universal character of the human essence. Kant stated: "I hope that 1 express
this completely when I say that [the feeling of the sublime] is the feeling of the
beauty and worth of human nature." Accordingly, in his racial classifications,
when he writes in the Observations that the "African has no feeling beyond the
trifling," Kant, consistent with his earlier doctrines, is implying that the African
barely has character, is barely capable of moral action,' and therefore is less
human. Kant derived from Hume "proof' for the assignment of this subhuman
status to "the Negro":
Mr Hume challenges anyone to cite a simple example in which a Negro has shown
talents, and asserts that among the hundreds of thousands of blacks who are
transported elsewhere from their countries, although many of them have been
set free, still not a single one was ever found who presented anything great in
art or science or any other praiseworthy quality; even among the whites some
continually rise aloft from the lowest rabble, and through superior gifts earn
respect in the world. So fundamental is the difference between the two races of
man, and it appears to be as great in regard to mental capacities as in' color.
Although Kant cites Hume as the confirming authority for his view of the black,
a careful 'reading shows that Kant, as with Linnaeus' system, considerably
elaborated upon Hume by philosophically elevating Hume's literary and
political speculations about "the Negro" and providing these speculations with
transcendental justifications. For example, when Hume argues that "the
Negro" was "naturally" inferior to "the White,'~ he does not attempt a
transcendental grounding of either "nature" or "human nature," while Kant
does. "Human nature," for Kant, constitutes the unchanging patterns of specie classes
so that racial differences and racial classifications are based a priori on
the reason (Ve~unfi) of the natural scientist.
Kant's classificatory work on race, however, ought to be situated within the context of
prior works in the area, such as the descriptions of the "system of nature" that the natural
historians Buffon, Linnaeus, and the French doctor Francois Bernier had done in the
preceding years. Buffon, for example, had classified races geographically, using
principally physical characteristics such as skin color, height, and other bodily features as
indices. According to Buffon, there was a common, homogeneous human origin so that
the differences in skin and other bodily features were attributable to climatic and
environmental factors that caused a single human "specie" to develop different skin and
bodily features. In Buffon's view, the concepts of "species" and "genra" applied in racial
classifications are merely artificial, for such classes do not exist in nature: "in reality only
individuals exist in nature. Kant accepted the geographical classification of races, but he
rejected Buffon's idea that "races" were not specieclasses - in which case the distinctions
would be historical, contingent and ungrounded as logical or metaphysical necessity.
According to Kant, the geographical distribution of races is a fact, but the differences
among races are permanent and fixed, and transcend climatic or any other environmental
factors. Race and racial differences are due to original specie- or class-specific variations
in "natural endowments" so that there is a natural "germ" (Keim) and "talent" (Anlage)
for each (separate) race.
of Kant know all too well about the first part of morals, that is, the metaphysics of morals or
metaphysica pura. This first nonempirical or pure part of morals is built on necessary laws, as a result it
cannot be grounded on the particular constitution of a rational being, [such as] the human being (Moral
Mrongovius II 29: 599; cf. Gr 4: 389). But what about the second part; philosophia moralis applicata, moral anthropology, to which the
empirical principles belong (Moral Mrongovius II 29: 599)? Moral anthropology, as the term suggests, is morality applied to the human
being (Moral Mrongovius II 29:599).In
his writings and lectures on ethics, Kant repeatedly invokes the term
anthropology when describing this second, empirical part of ethics . Often, as in the previous citations, the
favored phrase is moral anthropology; sometimes it is practical anthropology (Gr 4: 388); and sometimes it is simply
anthropology (Gr 4: 412; Moral Philosophie Collins 27: 244; Moral Mrongovius I 27: 1398). This frequent employment within
the practical philosophy texts and lectures of the term anthropology as a shorthand means of conveying what the other
member of the division of practical philosophy as a whole is about gives readers who turn to the anthropology lectures a
thoroughly legitimate expectation that the myriad mysteries of Kants philosophia moralis applicata will finally be addressed in
some detail. Those who approach these lectures with ethics in mind are inevitably driven by the hope of
finally locating a missing link in Kants system of practical philosophy, a link that will give his ethics the
much needed material content and applicability to human life that critics from Hegel to Max Scheler and
extending on to contemporary descendants such as Bernard Williams, Alasdair MacIntyre, and many
others have claimed is nowhere to be found in Kant.
3. Kants moral philosophy depends on Weltkenntnis (world knowledge). Kant argues that moral
philosophy that does not investigate the nature of human beings around us, fails to be moral
philosophy. Anthropology by Kants own admission is key to applying moral philosophy to the
real world.
Robert Louden(Professor of Philosophy @ University of Southern Maine, in Essays on Kants
Anthropology, ed. Brian Jacobs [Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003], 60-84, 71-72.
In the Groundwork, Kant emphasizes that morals needs anthropology for its application to human beings (4: 412).
Morals, which here appears to refer exclusively to the rational, nonempirical part of ethical theory (cf. 4: 388),
needs anthropology in part because its a priori laws require a judgment sharpened by experience, partly to
distinguish in what cases they are applicable and partly to provide them with entry (Eingang) to the will of the
human being and efficacy for his fulfillment of them (Nachdruck zur Ausubung); for the human being is affected by
so many inclinations that, though capable of the idea of a practical pure reason, he is not so easily able to make it
effective in concreto in the conduct of his life (4: 389). In other words, human beings need Weltkenntnis in order to make morality
work effectively in their own lives. Human beings cannot simply jump unaided into pure ethics; background knowledge of
their own empirical situation is a necessary prerequisite. This necessary empirical background for moral judgment has been well
described by Barbara Herman in her discussion of rules of moral salience. Such rules, she writes, are acquired
as elements in a moral education, [and] they structure an agents perception of his situation so that what he perceives is a world with moral
features. They enable him to pick out those elements of his circumstances or of his proposed actions that require moral attention. . . . Typically
they are acquired in childhood as part of socialization; they provide a practical framework within which people act. . . . The rules of moral
salience constitute the structure of moral sensitivity.
An important part of the task of a specifically moral anthropology is thus to contribute to human beings progress
of the power of judgment (cf. KpV 5: 154). This task is carried out in the anthropology lectures through the
imparting of Weltkenntnis to listeners.
There is, then, in Kant, a clear distinction between a raw "state of naturc" and a "state of
human nature" which "man ... has now attained." Indeed, for Kant, if the "state of nature"
is a state of evil, it is "human nature," as moral nature, which offers the possibility of the
overcoming of evil.50
For Kant human nature, unlike natural nature, is, in essence, a moral naturc, so
that what constitutes human nature proper is not, as the ancients may have believed,
'Simply intelligence or reason, but moral reason - the capacity to posit oneself rationally
as a moral agent. Humans, in the state of nature, are simply animaIe rationabile; they
have to make of themselves animate rationale. The idea and the effort of "making of
oneself' is a specifically historical and moral process. Moral capacity means that humans
can posit goals and ends in their actions because they make choices.in life, and choices
are made in the function of goals. Intimately connected with the idea of moral reason,
then, is the capacity for action directed toward self-perfectibility, or the faculty of self
improvement. Kant writes that the individual "has a character which he himself creates,
because he is capable of perfecting himself according to the purposes which he himself
adopts." The "goal" of society and civilization is therefore tied to the destiny of the
species: "to affect the perfection of man through cultural progress.
Humanity is clearly demarcated away from and against the natural state and elevated to a
level where it has necessarily to construct in freedom its own culture. For Kant, it is this
radical autonomy that defines the worth, the dignity, and therefore the essence of
humanity. Pragmatic anthropology as a science has as its object the description of this
essential structure of humanity and its subjectivity. Anthropology's task is to understand
and describe "the destination of man and the characteristic of his development" as
rational, social, and moral subject. Pragmatic anthropology is meant to help "man"
understand how to make himself worthy of humanity through combat with the roughness
of his state of nature. Kant's anthropological analysis of the "essence of man,';
accordingly, starts not from a study of the notion of a prehistorical or precivilization
"primitive" human nature, but rather from the study of the nature of"man" qua civilized.
To study animals, one might start with the wild, but when the object of study is the
human, one must focus on it in its creative endeavors - that is, in culture and civilization for ",'civilization does not constitute man's secondary or accidental characteristic, but
marks man's 'essential nature, his specific character."
___.Kants practical and moral philosophy is rooted in his understanding of anthropology.
There is no separating his scientific investigations into the capacity of the human from his
moral theories. Dont let them reduce this to a historical fact; this is central to Kants
moral system.
Eze1997 (Emmanuel, Professor of Philosophy @DePaul University, The Color of Reason in
PostColonial African Philosophy: A Critical Reader [Cambridge: Blackwell Publishing, 1997], 103-131
Yet for Kant, human nature, or the knowledge of human nature, does not derive from
empirical cultural or historical studies. History and culture are inadequate to
understanding human nature because they deal only with the phenomenal, accidental,
and changing aspects of "man,'' rather than with the essential and permanent. And
"through the work of Rousseau, Kant did grasp the essential element in man: his ethical
. . . nature. " Thus, according to Kant, while physical and racial characteristics as
aspects of the physical_ .nature are studied or established by ''scientific reason, "moral
nature, or rational character, which constitutes humanity proper, is the domain of
pragmatic anthropology leading to practical/moral philosophy.
Kants anti-Black racism is more puzzling than that of many of his contemporaries because it was not directly
put to the service of a defense of slavery, the issue of his day that can most readily be understood as
necessitating the development of a racist ideology. There were relatively few voices for or against chattel
slavery in the late seventeenth century and early eighteenth century. Sla very presented certain practical
problems should slaves be baptized? Could they be freed by their masters? which touched on issues central
to the organization of a society built on slavery, but, as an institution, such justifications of slavery that existed
were not subject to scrutiny, largely because it was not at that time subject to sustained attack. The early
opponents of slavery, like Samuel Sewall of Boston in 1700, were isolated and largely ignored. There were
discussions of slavery in the standard works of seventeenth-century political philosophy, for example, in
Pufendorf and Locke, based on the idea that captives from a just war can be legitimately enslaved. John Locke
argued that, because one does not have power over ones own life, one cannot enslave oneself to anyone else,
but one can forfeit ones life by committing an act that deserves death.21 Lockes argument also clearly
excludes chattel slavery, but there is a strong possibility that it simply did not occur to Locke, who was above
all concerned with the rights of Englishmen, that the chattel slavery of Africans needed justification, even
though he was well aware of how the system operated and indeed profited from it through his investments. 22
Although slave traders did on occasion appeal to the just war theory of enslavement, it is clearly an inadequate
model to apply to the chattel slavery of Africans by Europeans, particularly the enslavement of women and
their children in perpetuity. At what point it became widely known that application of this argument to enslave
Africans was specious is not clear, but in 1735 John Atkins explicitly addressed the argument and exposed it as
false.23 Montesquieu was the first philosopher to challenge the use of African slaves by Europeans, but he did
so in an ironic fashion so that even in our own century he was not always correctly understood. The dispiriting
fact is that philosophers as a group were slow to recognize the evils of the chattel slavery in Africans and that
even Kant failed to speak out against it. Kants ethics would seem to be a perfect instrument with which to
combat chattel slavery. His remarks against serfdom and other forms of slavery leave no doubt that his
philosophy provided him with the resources for doing so. And yet he was virtually silent on this topic.
10
11
5. Turn: Kantian Cosmpolitanism leads to racial extermination. Extend our Bernasconi evidence
from the original shell. Kleingolds work depends on Kantian Cosmopolitianism as the resolution
of his racism, our Bernasconi evidence shows this idea empirically lead to genocide and the
scientization of white racial purity at the dawn of the 1800s.
12