Fuller-Morality of Law
Fuller-Morality of Law
Fuller-Morality of Law
Volume 40 | Issue 2
Winter 1965
This Book Review is brought to you for free and open access by the Law
School Journals at Digital Repository @ Maurer Law. It has been accepted
for inclusion in Indiana Law Journal by an authorized administrator of
Digital Repository @ Maurer Law. For more information, please contact
wattn@indiana.edu.
Article 5
BOOK REVIEWS
THE MORALITY OF LAW.
American society since the early 1930's has been subjected to the
stresses and strains which are inherent in a widespread modification of
long adhered to tenets of legal doctrine. Within the last decade the rapidity of change appears to have gained momentum. By the beginning
of the 1960's, change rather than consistency seems to have become one
of the characteristics of the American legal system. Many of the changes
have had an especially stunning impact upon the thinking of individuals
who had previously supported the role assigned to law in American society. A large number of Americans have experienced a great deal of
unpleasantness in adapting to the harsh realization that principles which
they had regarded as fundamentally correct and immutable have been
swept away. In their place stand novel ideas not tested by mankind's
experience but promising a better tomorrow. In this setting it is not surprising to find that one of the nation's foremost legal philosophers has
turned his attention to the formulation of a set of standards which he
believes can be employed in determining the propriety of our current and
future rules governing human activity.
In an era when Kierkegaard's fear that " 'statistics' (majority vote)
would replace ethics"' may in fact become a reality, Lon Fuller in The
Morality of Law2 has proposed a set of principles which he asserts should
be used to decide the propriety of legal doctrines, popular will to the contrary notwithstanding. Instead of arguing for expanded acceptance of
the techniques offered by the proponents of jurimetrics and the utilization of the tools of the physical scientists in the formulation of legal rules,
Fuller calls for increased recognition of the idea that law is basically a
technique of balancing mankind's conflicting objectives. He asserts that
law cannot be evaluated in terms of absolutes. When administrators,
legislators, or judges are called upon to announce a rule of law, Fuller
asks that they keep in mind the fact that, whatever principle they may
1.
2. "This book is based on lectures given at the Yale Law School in April 1963."
FULLER, THE MORALITY OF LAW v. (1964) [hereinafter cited as FULLER]. Fuller states
that he preserved in this book the lecture form; and accordingly, he writes, the reader
is exposed to the congenial lecture form which permits an informal and argumentative
presentation.
BOOK REVIEWS
ultimately accept, in most instances it was but one of several available
alternatives. He requests that the arbiter not lose sight of the fact that
in the course of arriving at his decision he was compelled to engage in a
process of compromise and accommodation of conflicting objectives. His
final judgment should not be viewed as the only possible solution. Properly, it should be regarded as nothing more than the most desirable when
tested by the standards used by the decision maker. It is in this context
of picking and choosing from among a number of possible alternatives
that Fuller calls for the consideration of the standards which he has formulated to guide the lawmakers in their promulgation of legal principles.
Early in his book Fuller comes to grips with the question of the relationship between law and morality. He elects to subdivide the term
morality into four different categories, lumping them into what can be
described as two different sets of morality, each set having two opposite
components. One set contains the "morality of aspiration" and the
"morality of duty."3 The components of this division are somewhat comparable to the approach employed by other authors in their attempt to distinguish the terms morality and ethics. They have used the term morality
to describe the standards actually followed by human beings at a particular time and place, while the word ethics has been employed to connote a desired norm of human conduct independent of any consideration
of actual current human activities.4 Fuller's "morality of aspiration!' is
comparable to the foregoing concept of ethics while his "morality of
duty" is similar to the meaning ascribed to the term morality. In spite of
the resemblance between Fuller's terms and the approach of other writers,
the "morality of aspiration" and the "morality of duty" cannot in every
instance be used interchangeably with the foregoing definitions of morality and ethics.'
Fuller's second set of moralities contains what he calls the "external
morality of law" and the "internal morality of law." The "internal
morality of law" is essentially concerned with the procedure of making
law. It is the technique used by the lawmaker in deciding which rule of
3. This breakdown is similar to the approach of Henri Bergson. Bergson wrote
that morality may result from pressure or aspiration and he described what he called the
law of pressure and the law of aspiration. Bergson saw each of these giving rise to
distinct forms of morality. Fuller sees the "morality of aspiration" and the "morality
of duty" giving rise to different standards of prescribed conduct. Bergson's thinking
appears in THE Two SOURCES OF MORULITY AND RELIGION (1956). Bergson's approach
is explored by Jacques Maritain in MORAL PHmosoPHY (1964).
4. E.g., PATTERNS or ETHics IN AMERICA TODAY (Johnson ed. 1960).
5. A different concept of the relationship between ethics and morality is expressed
in the following statement: "Ethical principles and moral ends acquire whatever weight
or importance they appear to possess as a result of certain human decisions." SwANs,
AN ANALYsIs OF MORALS 36 (1960).
Fuller is patently a proponent of a conservative approach to the proliferation of legal mandates in relation to the regulation of human endeavor, especially in those areas which were previously free from the
commands of the law. There are ways and means to attain society's ends
other than by resort to law, this legal philosopher insists. He claims that
the lawmakers must realize this if they are to make the most efficient use
6. An excellent examination of the natural law thinking as to which commands are
to be regarded as law appears in CAHN, THE SENSE OF INJUSTIcE 3-50 (1949).
7. A similar subdivision was made by Edmund Cahn in THE MoRAL DECiSION
(1955), wherein Cahn distinguished law and morality in the following manner: Law is
a device to enforce the minimum standards of moral behavior which are indispensable
for the existence of the community while morality deals with standards which are suitable for the action of an ideal human being. Law, according to Cah, governs the
external conduct of a reasonable or generic man while morality relates to subjective intentions. Id. at 38-46.
BOOK REVIEWS
of the law as an instrumentality in the ordering of our society. Fuller
asserts that those who make law should exercise restraint in establishing
laws directed at regulating the conduct of individuals. He admonishes
the lawgiver not to confuse the "morality of aspiration" with the "morality of duty." In what might be described as a laissez-faire attitude, Fuller
declares that for the most part law should be directed basically at the
"morality of duty." rather than the "morality of aspiration." Excessive
emphasis on the latter, he believes, would prevent the proper utilization
of the law. Conceding that the "morality of duty" does draw upon the
"morality of aspiration," he calls for a constant awareness of the fact
that too great a concern with the aspirations of mankind can result in the
promulgation of unsatisfactory legal principles.
The author expresses a fear that if too much attention is paid to the
"morality of aspiration" society may establish a body of law which will
prescribe too many do's and do not's in too many areas of human activity.
Such a legal system, he believes, can prevent the individual from developing to the full potential of his capabilities. Too many do not's, he says,
can stifle experimentation, prevent a person from exercising his creative
talents, and prevent the freedom of action which is necessary to advance
the best interests of mankind. Laws which demand too much of the human being can result in a rigidity which in practice can frustrate the attainment of society's sought after goals.
Fuller rejects the positivist approach to the law. Contrary to the
thinking of the legal positivists, he asserts that not all mandates of those
who possess the power to compel compliance with their directions can
rightfully be classified as law. He excludes the requisites of authority
to command and the power to force compliance from his thinking as to
what in fact constitutes law. In reading Fuller's assertion that the bare
existence of a directive of a sovereign is not of itself law since its presence does not insure obedience, one cannot help but think of the antigambling statutes, Sunday laws, and other types of prohibitory legislation
which in many instances not only are constantly violated by the individuals
against whom they are directed but also are constantly being flouted by
those persons who are charged with their enforcement. A classical illustration of the proposition that law as prescribed is not in all instances the
measure of human conduct is the people's response to the command embodied in the eighteenth amendment to the Constitution.
Having exposed the reader to the concepts of natural law thinking
and the existence of a base against which to test the propriety of rules
directed at regulating human conduct, Fuller proceeds to a study of the
"internal morality of law." For a principle to be acceptable as a law, he
BOOK REVIEWS
enforcing the law, then the law in Fuller's opinion lacks "internal
morality."
By calling for "internal morality" of our legal system in terms of
the foregoing criteria, is Fuller calling for a fundamental change in
American jurisprudence? Are these concepts foreign to current legal
thinking in the United States? Both of these questions call for a negative
response. In setting forth these eight rules Fuller has explained, explored, and clarified what is substantially the practice presently being
observed by most of our jurists. There is a great deal of similarity between what Fuller has written and the approach of the Supreme Court of
the United States in reference to the procedural requirements demanded
by the fifth and fourteenth amendments to the federal constitution.
Traditionally, common-law principles have been couched in general
terms. This is brought home to the neophyte student of the law when he
first comes in contact with the concept of reasonableness in the law of
contracts and torts. Perhaps Fuller is seeking to express his concern over
the great proliferation of statutory law which has stressed individual differences rather than similarities. Specification, according to Fuller, if
overemphasized, is undesirable. Indicative of the fact that the fundamental technique of our legal system is generality rather than specificity
is the Constitutional prohibition relating to bills of attainder.' The "egalitarian drive" manifested by the Supreme Court and of late the Congress
is patently an expression of the concept to have, to the greatest degree
possible, all persons treated in an equal manner unless there are meaningful differences between them.'
Fuller does not state which one of his eight postulates should be
given preference over any other. lie does not rank them in any order of
importance. How, then, should they be applied? He calls for a conscious
balancing and the recognition of the need to accommodate each of these
objectives which, he admits, at times may conflict with one another. Depending on the circumstances, one or more of the proposed standards
might at any one time have to be subordinated to the demands of another
if a particular societal goal is to be attained. Fuller asks that the lawmaker consider each of these eight tests in arriving at his determination
in the particular factual setting in which he is compelled to operate.
Fuller emphasizes that the judge, the legislator, and the executive must
appreciate the necessity of making a choice in considering the use of his
S. U.S. CONST. art. I, 9, prohibits the Congress from enacting bills of attainder
and contains a similar prohibition on state activity. U.S. CoNsT. art. I, 10.
9. For a discussion of what has been depicted as the "Egalitarian Revolution," see
Kurland, The Supreme Court 1963 Term, 78 HARv. L. Rxv. 143 (1964).
BOOK REVIEWS
tions among individuals and cultures which must be taken into account in
formulating legal doctrines.
In the final chapter of his book, Fuller throws open the question of
the techniques which should be employed in order to evaluate the propriety of substantive rules of law. He asks if substantive rules of law can
be neutral, that is, devoid of any relationship to morality. His answer is
apparently no. Unfortunately he does not formulate any desiderata for
this area of the law. Instead, he writes in terms of fundamental objectives. He states that substantive rules, to be moral (that is, satisfy the
demands of "external morality"), must promote the objectives of mankind. He maintains that "external morality" does not preclude change.
Law must be sufficiently fluid to adjust to the dynamic nature of the
human being. A rule of conduct cannot be moral if it fails to take into
consideration the nature of man.
In relation to certain areas of human activity he maintains that the
government has no role to play, arguing that other means exist which can
more appropriately be utilized to attain desired objectives. Fuller viewed
Baker v. Carr" as a limited intrusion by the law into an area best left to
other forms of regulation. He classified representation in the legislative
branch of government as an issue too complex for the tools available to
the judicial process. He concluded that the Supreme Court would refrain
from extending Baker v. Carr. In a series of decisions which were delivered in the course of the 1963 term of the Court, the Court took a
position diametrically opposed to Fuller's approach to the role of the
judiciary in this area." By arguing that the nation would best be served
by having the people use means other than the law to effect a change in
legislative representation, Fuller seems to have underestimated the willingness of the current members of the Supreme Court to apply the judicial process to difficult and controversial spheres of public concern. 2
In terms of the effective use of the law, Fuller's attitude may in time
prove to be more acceptable than the present Court's manner of resolving
this particular question. For the present, however, the Court has indicated a willingness to use the law to resolve what some may still classify
as an essentially political question.
Fuller carries forward his proposition that the lawmaker must distinguish the "morality of duty" from the "morality of aspiration" into
the substantive segment of the law. If the law is to play its proper role,
10. 369 U.S. 186 (1962).
11. See Wesberry v. Sanders, 376 U.S. 1 (1964), and Reynolds v. Sims, 377 U.S.
533 (1964).
12. The Court had previously adopted Fuller's attitude in Colegrove v. Green, 328
FuLLER at
186.
BOOK REVIEWS
entitled, "Appendix: The Problem of the Grudge Informer," raises a hypothetical problem for which he offers five different solutions. To select which of the alternatives is most appropriate one must decide the
extent to which he accepts Fuller's philosophy of law. I would suggest
that the reader examine the Appendix before studying the preceding
chapters and write down the alternative he views as appropriate. He
should also make a brief statement as to why he chose the particular
solution rather than any other. Many readers, I believe, will approach
the posed problem in a different manner after they have read what precedes it.
One should not feel surprise if having finished reading Fuller's
book, he experiences the following two sensations:
(1) He will henceforth pay greater attention to the idea that the
law is just one of the means available to mankind to solve its problems.
The next time the reader hears someone say: "There ought to be a law,"
he will have to go through the throes of a personal evaluation of alternative remedies before he answers, "I agree."
(2) He will want to do a great deal of studying in the areas dealing with morality, ethics, natural law, existentialism, and sociology. Action of this nature should enhance the value of the law as a problem solving device whether the reader is a student, a lawyer, a judge, a legislator,
an administrator, a member of the executive branch of government, or
one of those persons against whom laws are directed.
Fuller has done a great deal of analyzing, rejecting, formulating,
and evaluating in the preparation of the material contained in this comparatively thin volume. For the beginner as well as the seasoned student
of legal philosophy, The Mllorality of Law contains an excellent assortment of ideas demanding further thought. I suggest that this philosophical offering be examined very soon. The sooner one completes his reading of this book, the sooner he will turn his attention away from thinking
exclusively in terms of "what is the law in this case" and will instead
ponder: "Is the present legal principle satisfactory; if not, why not; and
what are the available alternatives?" The greater the number of people
who engage in this kind of thinking, the closer mankind will come to
attaining desirable human objectives.
EDWIN W.
TUCKERt