Journal of Philosophy
Journal of Philosophy
Journal of Philosophy
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless
you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you
may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.
Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at
http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=jphil.
Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed
page of such transmission.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
Journal of Philosophy, Inc. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Journal
of Philosophy.
http://www.jstor.org
VOLUMEXLIX, No. 14 JULY 3, 1952
461
462 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY
ism, and the non-cognitive, emotive theory. The pattern of de-
bate between these schools has become more and more stereotyped.
Each school is strong in pointing out the difficulties of other posi-
tions but weak in defending its own. Recent observers have
suggested the need for a closer study of the concrete phenomena
of moral experience, and for broader concepts capable of doing
justice to these rich and complex data.2 What each school sees is
no doubt true, but none seems as yet to have penetrated to those
foundational ontological structures which lie at the root of moral
phenomena, and with reference to which the diverse subordinate
phases focused by different points of view may be fitted together
into a meaningful and non-exclusive whole.
It is most significant that many thinkers of divergent schools
agree that basic moral categories such as goodness, so far as they
can be defined at all, must be identified with fixed, determinate
qualities or properties of some kind. But this assumption seems
to lead only to reductionism, eclectic pluralism, or the dubious
doctrine of indefinability. Can it be that a more basic existential
category is being forgotten and ignored?
Let us select two pairs of related concepts, the ought and the
good, existence and value, which are worthy of a brief glance.
No recent school seems to have been able to focus the relation which
holds the members of each pair together. Hence one must be
reduced to the other, or the two must be separated by a yawning
chasm with paradoxical results in each case which have been often
emphasized. Either reductionism or disintegration. This is the
price we pay for a neglect of the concrete data and those onto-
logical concepts by which alone they may be coherently understood.
Thus if we attempt to reduce oughtness to the good conceived
as a hedonic quality, difficulties arise concerning the intrinsic
goodness of virtuous acts, and that peculiar binding power which
the ought exerts upon the individual agent. On the other hand, if
we separate the ought from factual value as two insular essences
totally divorced from each other, we are forced to say that what
we ought to do is not good, and the good is not what we ought to
do. If they have nothing in common, how then can we weigh them
against one another and compare them, as we must do in any
serious process of deliberation? Moral law is left with no factual
foundation whatsoever, and moral justification seems meaningless.
In the case of goodness and existence, as they are now ordi-
narily conceived, we are confronted with a similar dilemma. If
2 W. K. Frankena, "Main Trends in Moral Philosophy at Mid-Century,"
Philosophical Review, Vol. LX (Jan. 1951), p. 50.
TENDENCY 463
3. ONTOLOGYAND ETHICS
I shall now attempt to show very briefly that such an analysis
as we have suggested is capable of shedding light on the funda-
mental categories of ethics, and of bringing supposedly discordant
concepts into a meaningful unity. Let us begin with value and
existence. From an essentialist point of view which regards ex-
istence as something fixed and finished, value is something else,
TENDENCY 473
quite separate. Value is what ought to be. And the ought im-
plies a certain futurity and tension which cannot belong to a
finished fact. Hence value is thought of as a peculiar kind of
quality or property dwelling in its own realm apart from actual
existence. But if value is separated from existence completely,
how can it be anything at all? Surely there is some relation be-
tween the two. What is this?
Our analysis suggests a reasonableanswer to this fundamental
question. Existence, as we have seen, is tendential. Value is the
fulfilment of existential tendency. It is true that it cannot be
identified with any finished fact, except in so far as this includes
fulfilment. But in the concrete,no facts are ever finished. They
are incomplete and tendential. Hence the sense of futurity and
tension that attaches to the ought.
How then is value related to that which exists at a given
moment? That towards which an entity is essentially tending,
which will realize its nature, is good for it. This is the relation
of fitness. By value, we mean what is fit for a thing, what is due
to its nature, the further existence that will complete its basic
tendencies, and its incidental tendencies as well, so far as these
do not conflict with the former.
Can value then be deduced from fact? If by deduction we
mean the tautology of modern logic, the answer is of course no.
The fitting fulfilment of a tendency is not the same as its incipient
stages. A synthetic connection is involved. But if we mean by
synthetic, two separate items which merely succeed each other in
time with no real bond between, the answer to this again is no.
We cannot apprehend an incipient tendency with any degree of
clarity without understanding something of the gestalt deter-
mining it, and its fitting fulfilment. Thus a biologist cannot
observe a fossil skeleton without understanding something of the
fitting activities required to complete its tendencies, the requisite
environment,etc.
The tendency is not an atomic essence which we first under-
stand by itself alone, and from which we then "infer" the com-
pletion as another separate entity. It is rather a relational ac-
tivity which is either grasped all together with some degree of
clarity or not at all. In apprehendinga relation we must appre-
hend something of its terms; so in apprehending a tendency we
must grasp somethingof what it is tending towards. Thus values
are rightly said to be founded on facts.
Does this mean that value is to be identified with all existence,
and that what is, is right? By no means. Existence is tendential.
This tendency may proceedin a fitting mannertowards its natural
474 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY
fulfilment. The entity is then said to be in a sound or correct
condition. On the other hand, it may be warped and impeded,
and still go on existing. Such existence is said to be unsound and
incorrect. Goodness, therefore, is not to be identified with any
existent fact cut off from the future, nor with a non-existent prop-
erty cut off from all existence. It is an existential fulfilment, fit
for and thus founded on the essence and its essential tendencies.
Let us now turn to goodness and oughtness, which are also
tommonly separated by contemporary schools of ethics. Thus
goodness is held to be an object of cognition with no binding
power, while oughtness is a subjectively felt, compulsive tendency
to act. Hence they are divorced, as though they were fixed essences
like greenness and blueness, as though goodness ought not to be
achieved, and as though doing what I ought to do were not good.
Surely this is absurd. What then is the relation between the two?
The essential needs or tendencies of human nature may be
objectively understood, together with the fitting values or realiza-
tions founded upon them. From these values, certain modes
of required action may then be strictly deduced and stated in the
moral law of nature. In a given situation, I may see that such an
act is possible for me. I will then experience that peculiar union
of rational insight into the tendential nature of man and the law
founded on this nature, together with a subjectively felt tendency
(for I myself am human) which constitutes what we call an
obligation. If I have ever paid any attention to the factual ten-
dencies of human nature I must feel something of this sort. If
I do not feel it in a given instance, either my analysis of the ten-
dency is wrong, or I do not understand myself.
From this basic ontological point of view, I am not forced to
reduce oughtness to goodness, goodness to oughtness, or goodness
to existence. Neither am I forced to separate them into isolated,
atomic compartments. They may be fitted together as existential
categories into a meaningful structure that corresponds with the
data of moral experience. But this will require the abandonment
of essentialist prejudices very dear to the modern mind.
The first of these is the doctrine that value, if it is anything at
all, must be a peculiar quality or property. Such a view must
lead either to a reductionist ethics like hedonism and utilitarian-
ism, a chaotic view like recent moral pluralism so-called, or a flight
to ineffability like that of G. E. Moore and the so-called intuition-
ists. These are striking examples of the terrible price that must
be paid for the neglect of first philosophy. Basic concepts like
goodness and rightness can be clarified only by ontological anal-
COMMENTSAND CRITICISM 475
ysis. Unless they are so illumined, they will either be reduced and
distorted, or fade into unintelligibility.
This is not only true of the foundational concepts of ethics
but of those of the other disciplines as well. Philosophic data
are more pervasive, and richer, than the abstract data of any of
the more restricted sciences. Hence the attempt to squeeze these
data, with all their variegated content, into the limited perspec-
tives of one science, or even of all the quantitative sciences, must
always lead to reductive distortion of data, chaos, or unintelligi-
bility.
The broad concepts of ontology alone are capable of opening
up perspectives which can take account of all the immediate data of
experience without incoherence. It is our primary duty at the
present time to keep this perspective open, first of all by phe-
nomenological description, then by careful analysis of those onto-
logical data which are inaccessible to the restricted methods of
what we now call science, and finally by the formulation of ex-
planatory hypotheses which can be checked by these data. Unless
we perform these arduous functions in a disciplined manner, au-
thentic empiricism will vanish, to be replaced, as it is now being
replaced, by linguistic analysis, or as it has already been replaced
in many quarters, by a spurious, so-called empiricism which is only
a deceptive disguise for a bigoted a priori dogmatism. Meta-
physics is the foundational empirical discipline-the empirical
science par excellence. JOHN WILD
EAVARD UNIVERSITY