Cristina Chimisso - Bachelard Places of The Imagination
Cristina Chimisso - Bachelard Places of The Imagination
Cristina Chimisso - Bachelard Places of The Imagination
andImages ofSpace
CristinaChimisso
In The Formation of the Scientific Mind, Gaston Bachelard contrasted the alche-
mists workshop with the chemists laboratory. The former was in the private home
of the alchemist who had undisputed control over the experiments that took place
there, just as he had over his pupils. In fact, the alchemists teaching was a moral
initiation rather than transmission of rational knowledge (Bachelard 2002 [1938],
p.58). Alchemic theories for Bachelard were developed from human beings first
and most immediate image of the world; this is an image dominated by emotions
and desires. The alchemists did not see just combinations of substances, but rather
copulations from which offspring was issued; they did not see metals as inorganic,
but rather as having not only life but also souls (Bachelard 2002 [1938], Chapter 8).
In a private space, the alchemists imagination for Bachelard could rule unchecked
by peers and free from the constraints and rules of public spaces. For the alchemist
there was no distinction between his home and his workshop, between private and
public, and between nature and his private image of it.
C. Chimisso (*)
Open University, Milton Keynes, UK
e-mail: cristina.chimisso@open.ac.uk
1
The concept of epistemological obstacle, alongside with that of epistemological break, is central
in Bachelards epistemology.
2
For Bachelard, science only emerged at the end of the eighteenth century.
Gaston Bachelards Places oftheImagination andImages ofSpace 185
about. Non-Euclidean spaces are to be grasped by reason, rather than being repre-
sented by images. The places of the imagination follow the same axis in the oppo-
site direction.3 For Bachelard there are places where one can dream, and these
would be rather different from those of scientific work. There are also dreamed
spaces, which include the places we remember, although these are infused with our
dreams, just as the places about which we read are infused with the memory of the
places of our life (Fig. 1).
For Bachelard before the emergence of modern science there was a certain unity
of the human mind, as the imagination and rationality were not properly distinct. By
contrast in modern scientific times there is a dichotomy of the mind, and indeed of
life, and Bachelards life was no exception. In the unfinished book he was writing at
the end of his life, he remarked: my work life [has] two almost independent halves,
one under the sign of the concept, the other under the sign of the image... He wrote
that he lead a double life (Bachelard 1988, p.33, 34). These lines echoed those at
the end of La Flamme dune chandelle, when Bachelard emphasised that that book
only showed half of his life, and that after so many reveries, he was impatient to
learn again difficult and rigorous books thanks to which the mind constructs
and reconstructs itself (Bachelard 1961, pp.111112). These books would have
been about science and rationality.
In these quotations, Bachelard hinted at the fact that he employed different meth-
ods in his books about science and about the works of the imagination, respectively.
Whereas his philosophy of science did not change significantly, his interpretation of
the works of the imagination underwent a conscious evolution. At first, he mostly,
although not exclusively, analysed the works of the imagination from the point of
view of the diurnal man, or scientific rationality. In works such as the Formation
of the Scientific Mind, he aimed to psychoanalyse objective knowledge, or, as he
put in the Psychoanalysis of Fire, to cure the mind from its happy illusions
(Bachelard 1964 [1938], p.4). He never changed his mind about the negative role
that the imagination played in dialectic of scientific knowledge, but at the same time
3
Here I follow Bachelards view of his own investigation and indeed of our approach to objects:
from the first, immediate encounter with an object, we can follow an axis towards objectification
and science, or in the opposite direction, towards subjectivity and poetry; see (Bachelard 1964
[1938], pp.23).
186 C. Chimisso
4
The dark summers in the house suggest a house in which shatters prevent sunlight and heat from
entering, a rather geographically and culturally specific image.
Gaston Bachelards Places oftheImagination andImages ofSpace 187
p. 136), because it is rest from diurnal work, and affords us solitude. Images of
intimacy can become increasingly small and concentrated, and include wardrobes,
chests, drawers, and even small boxes, which suggest secrecy and an intuitive sense
of hiding places (Bachelard 1994 [1957], p.81).
The withdrawal and refuge that the house provides can take other forms in our
imagination, such as nests and shells. Nests for Bachelard are simple houses, and
images of rest and quiet (Bachelard 1994 [1957], p.98); they afford a special soli-
tude, but they are ambiguous, as they may simultaneously suggest refuge and dan-
ger (Bachelard 1972a [1943], p.242). Nests, and even more so shells, are closer to
nature than houses, and therefore more primitive; they can indeed be prehistoric,
as Bachelard labelled Jack Londons reverie about nests (Bachelard 1972a [1943],
p. 241). Reading and dreaming about them bring out the primitiveness in us
(Bachelard 1994 [1957], p.91). Primitiveness for Bachelard is connected with the
life of the imagination, with poetry and emotions. Unlike reason, which for him
evolves and brings about change, the imagination maintains its links with our primi-
tive self. Unlike Lucien Lvy-Bruhl, whose theory of primitive mentality had a
tremendous influence on a number of disciplines in the inter-war France, Bachelard
believed that the primitive approach to the world is not lost to modern people, but
rather survives in their imagination. This is why our dreams are populated by primal
images.
Bachelard considered the house in its multifarious versions (as room, corner,
nest, shell and others) as the image of intimacy. This is the centrality of the house.
But he also analysed the house in its verticality.5 Bachelards vertical house is a
synthesis of all other oneiric dwelling places; it has three or four storeys, each of
which is the image of a psychic state. The houses cellar roots the house in the
earth (Bachelard 1992b [1948], p.110), and in so doing it partakes of subterranean
force; descending into the cellar is a way to relive the primitivity and the specific-
ity of ones fears (Bachelard 1994 [1957], pp.1819). The ground floor is that of
common life; it comes as no surprise that Bachelard had little to say about this floor
which represents the platitude of common life (Bachelard 1992b [1948], p.110).
The interpretation of the upper floors may at first sight look rather confusing. In La
terre et les reveries du repos, Bachelard assigned sublimations to the upper floors.
In The Poetics of Space, he offered a more detailed analysis, in fact he appeared to
offer more than one. At first, he seemed to follow Carl Jungs lead, and presented a
house in which the cellar is the image of the irrational unconscious, whereas the
roof represents rationality. He employed Jungs images of the cellar and attic in
order to analyse the fears that inhabit the house. Bachelard quoted Jung as saying
that the conscious acts like a man who, hearing a suspicious noise in the cellar,
hurries to the attic, and, finding no burglars there decides, consequently, that the
noise was pure imagination (Bachelard 1994 [1957], pp.1819). Lucy Huskinson
has pointed out the discrepancy between Bachelards quotation and Jungs original,
in which the conscious acts like a man who hears a noise in the attic and goes to
5
Bachelard discussed verticality more generally in (Bachelard 1992a [1947], Chapter 12), and in
(Bachelard 1972a [1943]).
188 C. Chimisso
3 A
nother Method? TowardsaHermeneutics ofDreamed
Spaces
Bachelard did not change his mind about the imagination being an obstacle a
necessary one in the dialectic progress of science. In his books on science, he
always held the view that the scientific mind should be rectified and purified
from instincts and dreams, and that we should aim at a hortophychism (Bachelard
1970 [19341935]); (Bachelard 1986b [1949], p.48 and passim); (Bachelard 1951,
Gaston Bachelards Places oftheImagination andImages ofSpace 189
6
Bachelards use of psychoanalysis was rather eclectic from the beginning: he variously employed
Freud and Jung and above all Marie Bonaparte and Ren Allendy.
190 C. Chimisso
about how to live together in his rationalistic books. However, in his books on the
works of the imagination he did not want to tell anyone how they should live their
diurnal life. Indeed, as the father of a female philosopher who had published books
on rationality and on Husserl, he may have found it difficult to accept that a woman
would find it boring if her husband examined her on the Critique of Pure Reason,
as Jung had remarked (Jung 1928, p.177). Bachelard therefore made it clear that in
trying to indicate how the masculine and the feminine especially the feminine
help fashion our reveries, we are limiting our observations only to oneiric situa-
tions. As for the womans situation in the modern world, he left it to experts
Simone de Beauvoir and F.J. J.Buytendijk. How little Bachelard was concerned
with evaluating male and female psychology outside his own reverie is apparent by
his lumping together the author of The Second Sex with an author whose aim was to
show that there is an essential difference between men and women, a difference
in nature, capabilities, inborn qualities, abilities, talents and character, and therefore
a difference in vocation, mission and destiny (Buytendijk 1968, p.26).
It is crucial to take Bachelard seriously when he tells us that we should read his
books on reverie in anima, because they have been written in anima (Bachelard
1971 [1960], p. 212). Reading in anima for Bachelard means to suspend critical
engagement, and to receive images in a sort of transcendental acceptance of gifts
(Bachelard 1971 [1960], p.65). Bachelards topoanalysis, that is his exploration of
dreamed spaces and spaces where to dream, is not a method in the strict sense of the
world, and I agree with E.S. Casey who calls it less a method than an attitude
(Casey 1997, p.288). Not by chance, Bachelards chapter of The Poetics of Reverie
dedicated to animus and anima is about Reverie on reverie: he invited us to read
his lines as we read poetry rather than rationalist philosophy.
In the last years of his life, Bachelard gave up his former obsession with psycho-
analytical culture (Bachelard 1971 [1960], p.3), and adopted a new approach that
he called phenomenology, which he defined as the consideration of the onset of
the image in an individual consciousness (Bachelard 1994 [1957], p. xix). When
reading descriptions of places, such as a house, a nest or a corner, Bachelard was no
longer interested in the causal link that they may have with their authors psyches or
lives. This marked a sharp departure from the method he had employed in
Lautramont, where he reconstructed the poets biography and complexes from an
analysis of his work (Bachelard 1986a [1939]). Similarly, he was not interested in
these images cultural past or historical setting; no scholarship is needed for their
reception, but rather a nave consciousness (Bachelard 1994 [1957], p. xix). Like
Husserls, Bachelards phenomenology is descriptive rather than normative, and is
carried out by the individual. However, Bachelards phenomenology is neither a
method nor a science, unlike Husserls presentation of his phenomenology in his
Cartesian Meditation (Husserl 1960 [1931]). As Paul Ricoeur has emphasised, for
Bachelard there was no crisis of the sciences, as there was for Husserl, because for
the former crises take place entirely within objectivity... and can be resolved only
through the progress of the sciences (Ricoeur 2007, pp. 16162) (Husserl 1970
[1936]). For Bachelard, the sciences and rationalistic philosophy set the norms for
our objective knowledge and our collective living, whereas his phenomenology and
Gaston Bachelards Places oftheImagination andImages ofSpace 191
space, but he also discussed ontology and indeed ontogenesis when analysing sci-
entific discourse. In The Poetics of Reverie, published only two years before his
death, he emphasised that anima is not the whole of life, and expressed the wish to
write another work of animus, that is a work of philosophy of science (Bachelard
1971 [1960], p. 212). His hermeneutics of space is about the imagination and
dreams; but these make up only half of human existence. As I shall argue in the
Conclusion, he aimed to put forward a pedagogy for the nocturnal man, just as he
had done for the diurnal man in his books about science.
4 Conclusion
References
7
See for instance (Kennedy 2011).
8
For my interpretation of Bachelards philosophy of science as a pedagogical project, see (Chimisso
2001). For a defence of the enduring pedagogical value of Bachelards philosophy, see (Favre
1995).
194 C. Chimisso