Markov I 2012
Markov I 2012
Markov I 2012
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/
info/about/policies/terms.jsp
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content
in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship.
For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
University of Illinois Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Illinois Classical Studies.
http://www.jstor.org
This content downloaded from 192.54.242.155 on Thu, 24 Dec 2015 17:08:33 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Lucretius 3.9781023 and the Hellenistic
Philosophical Polemics against the Grammarians
Daniel Markovi
In his comments on Lucretiuss treatment of the fear of death in book 3, the aging
Bailey confirmed his position on the question that troubled Lucretian scholars at
the beginning of the 20th century: On the whole I remain of the opinion, which
I previously expressed,2 that the fear of punishment in death was more prevalent
in Epicuruss Greek world than in the Roman world of the 1st century B.C., and
agree with Sellar3 and Regenbogen4 that Lucretius, taking over the Epicurean
tradition, has to some extent exaggerated the fears of his contemporaries.5 De-
spite its modern guise, this critical observation goes back to antiquity. Cicero and
Seneca regard Epicuruss campaign against the stories about the Underworld as
mere shadowboxing: Cicero points out that not even an old wife would be sense-
less enough to believe in these stories; Seneca dismisses them as simply childish.6
1.I would like to thank the anonymous referee, Antony Augoustakis, and Charles Campbell
and Marcus Heckenkamp for their helpful suggestions in revising the first draft of this paper. Any
remaining errors are mine alone.
2.Bailey (1932) 220.
3.Sellar (1881) 272.
4.Regenbogen (1932) 4977.
5.Bailey (1950) 2.995.
6.Cf. Cic. Tusc. 1.10, 48; N.D. 1.86; 2.5; Sen. Ep. 24.18. Seneca, who objects that the fear is
too childish, nevertheless explains in one of his later letters that the fear of darkness is one of the
main psychological reasons why death appears to us as an evil (Ep. 82.1516).
143
This content downloaded from 192.54.242.155 on Thu, 24 Dec 2015 17:08:33 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
144 Illinois Classical Studies 3536 (20102011)
This content downloaded from 192.54.242.155 on Thu, 24 Dec 2015 17:08:33 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Daniel Markovi 145
This content downloaded from 192.54.242.155 on Thu, 24 Dec 2015 17:08:33 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
146 Illinois Classical Studies 3536 (20102011)
As the following analysis will show, the process consists of a careful selection
and recontextualizing of certain keywords:16
atque ea nimirum quaecumque Acherunte profundo
prodita sunt esse, in uita sunt omnia nobis.
nec miser inpendens magnum timet aere saxum
Tantalus, ut famast, cassa formidine torpens;
sed magis in uita diuom metus urget inanis
mortalis, casumque timent quem cuique ferat fors.
nec Tityon uolucres ineunt Acherunte iacentem
nec quod sub magno scrutentur pectore quicquam
perpetuam aetatem possunt reperire profecto.
quamlibet immani proiectu corporis exstet,
qui non sola nouem dispessis iugera membris
obtineat, sed qui terrai totius orbem,
non tamen aeternum poterit perferre dolorem
nec praebere cibum proprio de corpore semper.
sed Tityos nobis hic est, in amore iacentem
quem uolucres lacerant atque exest anxius angor
aut alia quauis scindunt cuppedine curae. (Lucr. 3.97894)
And surely whatsoever things are fabled to exist in deep Acheron, these
all exist for us in this life. Wretched Tantalus does not, as the story goes,
fear the great rock that hangs over him in the air, frozen with vain terror;
rather it is in this life that the futile fear of gods oppresses mortals without
cause, and the fall they fear is any that chance may bring. Nor is Tityos
lying in Acheron rummaged by winged creatures, nor can they actually
find in eternity anything at all to dig for deep in that vast breast. Wide as
you will, let that huge body be spread forth, enough to cover not nine acres
only with the outstretched limbs, but the whole globe of earth; yet he will
not be able to bear pain forever, nor to provide food from his own body
always. But our Tityos is here, the man who, as he lies in love, is torn by
winged creatures and devoured by agonizing anguish or rent by anxieties
through some other passion.
The first two lines establish the connection between Acheruns and our life and
prepare the ground for the transfer of the images of mythical sinners from one
realm to another. The next two segments are diptychs. They display the same
image against two different backgrounds, that of the fictitious Underworld on
one hand and that of real life on the other. In the first segment the transfer from
16.More comprehensive accounts of the fireworks in this section can be found in West (1969)
97103 and Kenney (1971) 22232. Text and translation are taken from Smith (1992), both slightly
revised.
This content downloaded from 192.54.242.155 on Thu, 24 Dec 2015 17:08:33 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Daniel Markovi 147
the first, fictitious setting to reality is established through the idea of falling; the
casus implied in the image of the inpendens saxum over the head of Tantalus is
in the second part of the diptych interpreted as the casus of chance in real life.
The central ideas in the second segment are those of lying supine and suffering:
the diptych juxtaposes the image of Tityos, iacens in the Underworld, his liver
eaten by winged birds, with the image of our Tityos, a lover, also iacensas the
tradition of amatory poetry has ithis emotions stirred by the winged Erotes.
Sisyphus in uita quoque nobis ante oculos est,
qui petere a populo fasces saeuasque secures
imbibit et semper uictus tristisque recedit.
nam petere imperium quod inanest nec datur umquam,
atque in eo semper durum sufferre laborem,
hoc est aduerso nixantem trudere monte
saxum quod tamen e summo iam uertice rursum
uoluitur et plani raptim petit aequora campi.
deinde animi ingratam naturam pascere semper
atque explere bonis rebus satiareque numquam
quod faciunt nobis annorum tempora, circum
cum redeunt fetusque ferunt uariosque lepores,
nec tamen explemur uitai fructibus umquam
hoc, ut opinor, id est, aeuo florente puellas
quod memorant laticem pertusum congerere in uas,
quod tamen expleri nulla ratione potestur. (Lucr. 3.9951010)
Sisyphus also appears in this life before our eyes, athirst to solicit from the
people the lictors rods and cruel axes, and always retiring defeated and
full of gloom: for to solicit power, an empty thing, which is never granted,
and always to endure hard toil in the pursuit of it, this is to push labori-
ously up a hill the rock that still rolls down again from the very top, and in
a rush recovers the levels of the open plain. Then to be always feeding an
ungrateful mind, yet never able to fill and satisfy it with good thingsas
the seasons of the year do for us when they come round bringing their fruits
and manifold charms, yet we are never filled with the fruits of lifethis,
I think, is meant by the tale of damsels in the flower of their age pouring
water into a riddled urn, which, for all their trying, can never be filled.
This content downloaded from 192.54.242.155 on Thu, 24 Dec 2015 17:08:33 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
148 Illinois Classical Studies 3536 (20102011)
connotations of the phrases containing the verb petere, but also by the political
connotations of the word campus. Trying to fill, explere, an ungrateful mind in
vain in this life, a thing that we are not able to do, nec ... explemur, is mirrored
in the Underworld by the futile labor of the Danaids who fetch water with jars
that cannot be filled (expleri).
Cerberus et Furiae iam uero et lucis egestas,
Tartarus horriferos eructans faucibus aestus
qui neque sunt usquam nec possunt esse profecto.
sed metus in uita poenarum pro male factis
est insignibus insignis scelerisque luella
carcer et horribilis de saxo iactu deorsum,
uerbera carnificis17 robur pix lammina taedae;
quae tamen etsi absunt, at mens sibi conscia factis
praemetuens adhibet stimulos torretque flagellis,
nec uidet interea qui terminus esse malorum
possit nec quae sit poenarum denique finis,
atque eadem metuit magis haec ne in morte grauescant.
hic Acherusia fit stultorum denique uita. (Lucr. 3.101123)
Cerberus also and the Furies and the withholding of light, and Tartarus
belching horrible fires from his throatthese neither exist anywhere nor in
truth can exist. But in this life there is fear of punishment for evil deeds, fear
as notorious as the deeds are notorious, and atonement for crimeprison,
and the horrible casting down from the Rock, lashing, the executioners
cross, pitch, red-hot plates, firebrands; and even if these are absent, yet the
guilty conscience, terrified before anything can come to pass, applies the
goad and scorches itself with whips, and meanwhile does not see where
can be the end to its miseries or the final limit to its punishment, and fears
that these same affections may become heavier after death. Hell for the
fools at the end exists on earth.
This content downloaded from 192.54.242.155 on Thu, 24 Dec 2015 17:08:33 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Daniel Markovi 149
images, but to recontextualize and thus appropriate them for his own purposes.19
He accomplished this goal through skillful exploitation of the double mean-
ing of the selected keywords, reinforced by repeated emphasis on the meaning
they have for us. The closest parallel I could find to Lucretiuss technique of
recontextualization of selected words comes from the writings of Senecaone
of the critics of the Epicurea cantilena (Epicurean refrain). In his Letter 88,
attempting to reverse the principle of non uitae sed scholae discimus (we do not
acquire knowledge for life, but for the classroom),20 Seneca converts a series
of questions typical of the grammarians school into their philosophical coun-
terparts. Each step in his revision is based on recontextualization of a selected
keyword, in some cases enhanced by the shift of focus to the first-person and to
this life. Here are the examples:
quaeris Vlixes ubi errauerit potius quam efficias ne nos semper erremus?
(Ep. 88.7)
Do you raise the question, Through what regions did Ulysses stray?
instead of trying to prevent ourselves from going astray at all times?21
doces me quomodo inter se acutae ac graues consonent, quomodo neruorum
disparem reddentium sonum fiat concordia: fac potius quomodo animus
secum meus consonet nec consilia mea discrepent. monstras mihi qui sint
modi flebiles: monstra potius quomodo inter aduersa non emittam flebilem
uocem. (Ep. 88.9)
You teach me how high- and low-pitched sounds are in accord with one
another, and how, though the strings produce different notes, the result is
a harmony; rather bring my soul into harmony with itself, and let not my
purposes be out of tune. You are showing me what the mournful keys are;
show me rather how, in the midst of adversity, I may keep from uttering
a mournful voice.
metiri me geometres docet latifundia potius quam doceat quomodo metiar
quantum homini satis sit. ... scis rotunda metiri, in quadratum redigis
quamcumque acceperis formam, interualla siderum dicis, nihil est quod in
mensuram tuam non cadat: si artifex es, metire hominis animum, dic quam
magnus sit, dic quam pusillus sit. scis quae recta sit linea: quid tibi prodest,
si quid in uita rectum sit ignoras? (Ep. 88.1013)
19.Cf. Gigandet (1998) 37385, who identifies three different levels of displacement or transfer
of meaning in this passage: (1) from the space of the Underworld to the space of this world; (2)
from the realm of physical to the realm of moral distress; and (3) from the external to self-imposed
punishments.
20.Sen. Ep. 106.12.
21.Text is taken from Reynolds (1965); translation is slightly revised from Gummere (1925).
This content downloaded from 192.54.242.155 on Thu, 24 Dec 2015 17:08:33 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
150 Illinois Classical Studies 3536 (20102011)
These passages from Seneca echo the line of criticism against traditional
education typical of Hellenistic popular philosophy, or, to use the traditional
term, diatribe.22 Recontextualization or transfer of a keyword from the realm of
schola to that of uita is a common feature in these passages. A sentence from
Bion of Borysthenes, quoted by Stobaeus, provides a good example:23
. (Stob. 3.4.52 = Kindstrand 5a)
Bion said that grammarians who inquire into the wanderings of Odysseus do
not examine their own, nor do they discern that they are themselves wander-
ing astray on this very point, viz., that they are following useless pursuits.
The same feature is preserved in another version of the sentence, from the Gno-
mologium Parisinum (320 = Kindstrand 6a). The thought has also been attributed
to Diogenes the Cynic, who might have been Bions model (D.L. 6.2728).
Of course the technique of recontextualization of the same word is too ubiqui-
tous to make any particular instance necessarily relevant for DRN 3.9781023.24
But the conjunction of the technique and content in Seneca and his Hellenistic
models suggests a deeper connection. The example of the wanderings of Odys-
seus and the transfer of its significance from the school of grammarian to real
life has, mutatis mutandis, a close parallel in Lucretiuss treatment of the poetic
accounts about the sinners of the Underworld. Both authors promote the idea
that a cure for the true anxieties of human lifesuch as Lucretiuss reversals of
fortune, passion of love, political ambition, dissatisfied mind, or greedcannot
be found in the study of poetry, but only in the study of philosophy. Seneca makes
the point explicit; Lucretius implies it by the choice of material and manner
of interpretation, leaving the conclusion to the reader. The formal similarity
22.The influence of Hellenistic diatribe on Lucretius 3 is discussed by Wallach (1976) 8391,
but the passages from Seneca are not mentioned.
23.This and the following parallel are adduced by Stckelberger (1965) ad Sen. Ep. 88.7. Bions
fragments and translation are taken from Kindstrand (1976).
24.We should note that recontextualization of keywords occurs naturally in rationalizing inter-
pretations of myth. Cf. for example Palaephatus, passim.
This content downloaded from 192.54.242.155 on Thu, 24 Dec 2015 17:08:33 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Daniel Markovi 151
between the two sets of passages is not a coincidence. Both advance the same
argument, originally developed in the context of the philosophical critique of
traditional education.
It is well known that Epicurus was one of the leading figures in the campaign
against traditional literary education, based on study of poetry.25 But it should be
noted that he did not altogether avoid references to authors such as Homer. In
the spirit typical of Hellenistic literature in general Epicurus sought to redefine
and revive Greek culture through a polemic dialogue with the classical literary
tradition:26 even in his famous exhortation to Pythocles ,
, (hoist your sail, dear boy, and run away
from all culture)Epicurus warned against the maelstrom of traditional poetry
alluding to Homer and Odysseuss encounter with the Sirens.27 Our evidence sug-
gests that Epicurus discussed the punishments of the sinners in the Underworld in
one of his works,28 and we also know that he was criticized for using Od. 9.511
in order to promote pleasure as the philosophical .29 In Letter 88.5, Senecas
claim that some make Homer an Epicurean most likely alludes to these passages.
Such interpretations were certainly not included in Epicuruss technical works such
as , but rather in his exoteric writing. Likewise, Lucretius placed his
interpretation of the myths in the nontechnical, closing part of book 3.
Lucretiuss elaborate reworking of the stories found in Ennius and Homer
turns out to be a more complex matter than it seemed before. In light of the
comparison made above, the poets rhetorical goals in DRN 3.9781023 can be
described as twofold. His first, apotreptic goal30 was to remove the erroneous
general belief implied in the mythical punishments described by the poets (as
expressed by Pliny the Elder). In order to achieve this goal, the poet admirably
manipulated the language of his vivid visual descriptions to turn the traditional
poetic tableaux into icons of the new, Epicurean belief.31 His second, ultimate
25.D.L. 10.6 and Athen. 588a = Arrighetti 43. For a list of known Epicurean works against
, see Blank (1998) xxxxxxi.
26.For a recent discussion of Epicuruss work in the context of the Hellenistic literary milieu,
see Erler (2011) 1014.
27.D.L. 10.6. Cf. Plut. Mor. 15d and 1092e1096c.
28.Besides Sen. Ep. 24.18, cf. Cic. Fin. 1.60 and Lact. Inst. 3.17.4142; 7.7.13.
29.This was demonstrated by Bignone (1936) 1.29193. For further evidence and discussion
see Asmis (1995) and Beer (2009) 7577.
30.Kenney (1971) 222 notes that a denial of the torments of hell is appropriate to a consola-
tioan apotreptic genre par excellence.
31.The procedure is typically Lucretian, according to Hardie (1986) 18: Lucretius is an efficient
predator, who digests those parts of his victim which are beneficial to his system and ostentatiously
rejects the indigestible.
This content downloaded from 192.54.242.155 on Thu, 24 Dec 2015 17:08:33 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
152 Illinois Classical Studies 3536 (20102011)
goal, can be defined as protreptic: to suggest that the only adequate guide for
living is Epicurean philosophy.
University of Cincinnati markovdl@ucmail.uc.edu
Works Cited
Asmis, E. 1995. Epicurean Poetics. In D. Obbink, ed., Philodemus and Poetry: Poetic
Theory and Practice in Lucretius, Philodemus, and Horace, 1534. Oxford: Oxford
University Press. Repr. in A. Laird, ed., Oxford Readings in Ancient Literary Criticism,
23866. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006.
. 1999. Epicurean Epistemology. In K. Algra et al., eds., The Cambridge His-
tory of Hellenistic Philosophy, 26094. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Bailey, C. 1932. Phases in the Religion of Ancient Rome. Berkeley: University of Cali-
fornia Press.
. 1950. Titi Lucreti Cari De Rerum Natura Libri Sex. Oxford: Clarendon.
Beer, B. 2009. Lukrez und Philodem: Poetische Argumentation und poetologischer Dis-
kurs. Basel: Schwabe.
Bignone, E. 1936. LAristotele perduto e la formazione filosofica di Epicuro. Firenze:
La Nuova Italia.
Blank, D. L. 1998. Sextus Empiricus against the Grammarians I. Oxford: Clarendon.
Burke, K. 1973. Literature as Equipment for Living. In Philosophy of Literary Form:
Studies in Symbolic Action, 293304. 3rd ed. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Erler, M. 2011. Autodidact and Student: On the Relationship of Authority and Autonomy
in Epicurus and the Epicurean Tradition. In J. Fish and K. R. Sanders, eds., Epicurus
and the Epicurean Tradition, 928. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Gale, M. R. 1994. Myth and Poetry in Lucretius. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Gigandet, A. 1998. Fama deum: Lucrce et les raisons du mythe. Paris: Vrin.
Gummere, R. M. trans. 1925. Seneca: Epistles. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press.
Hardie, P. R. 1986. Vergils Aeneid: Cosmos and Imperium. Oxford: Clarendon.
Jocelyn, H. D. 1986. Lucretius, His Copyists, and the Horrors of the Underworld: De
Rerum Natura 3.9781023. AClass 29: 4356.
Kenney, E. J., ed. 1971. De Rerum Natura III. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Kindstrand, J. F., ed. 1976. Bion of Borysthenes: A Collection of the Fragments with
Introduction and Commentary. Uppsala: Almqvist & Wiksell.
Mayhoff, C., ed. 1906. C. Plini Secundi Naturalis Historiae Libri XXXVII. Leipzig:
Teubner.
Regenbogen, O. 1932. Lukrez, seine Gestalt in seinem Gedicht. Leipzig: Teubner.
Reinhardt, T. 2004. Readers in the Underworld. JRS 94: 2746.
Reynolds, L. D., ed. 1965. L. Annaei Senecae Ad Lucilium Epistulae Morales. Oxford:
Clarendon.
Sellar, W. Y. 1881. Roman Poets of the Republic. Oxford: Clarendon.
This content downloaded from 192.54.242.155 on Thu, 24 Dec 2015 17:08:33 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Daniel Markovi 153
Smith, M. F., and W. H. D. Rouse, trans. 1992. Lucretius: De Rerum Natura. 2nd ed.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Stckelberger, A. 1965. Senecas 88. Brief: ber Wert und Unwert der freien Knste.
Heidelberg: Winter.
Veyne, P. 1988. Did the Greeks Believe in Their Myths? An Essay on the Constitutive
Imagination. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Wallach, B. P. 1976. Lucretius and the Diatribe against the Fear of Death: De Rerum
Natura III 8301094. Leiden: Brill.
West, D. A. 1969. The Imagery and Poetry of Lucretius. Edinburgh: Edinburgh Uni-
versity Press.
This content downloaded from 192.54.242.155 on Thu, 24 Dec 2015 17:08:33 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions