Rice University ECO 501: Microeconomic Theory I - Lecture 1: Preference
Rice University ECO 501: Microeconomic Theory I - Lecture 1: Preference
Rice University ECO 501: Microeconomic Theory I - Lecture 1: Preference
1 Consumption Set
In the …rst part of these lectures, we consider the consumer decision
problem in a market economy, where goods are o¤ered at posted prices.
Most of our attention will be on the primitive approach that starts with
"rational" individual preferences and derives optimal choices for given
prices and endowments. We will also look at connections with the
"revealed preference" approach that makes assumptions directly about
choices.
Let there be L di¤erent commodities. A consumption bundle is a list
x1 ; x2 ; : : : ; xL of quantities of each commodity, represented by a vector
2 3
x1
6 7
x = 4 ... 5
xL
in the commodity space RL .
Note that RL includes consumption bundles that list negative quantities
of some goods. These can be interpreted as debts or giving some of one’s
endowment to others.
1
Any two items that could sell at di¤erent prices should be modeled as
distinct commodities. Strictly speaking, the description of a commodity
may have to include detailed context information, such as "a diet coke
can from a vending machine at Grand Central Station in the summer
of 2008."
The de…nition of the commodity space tells us what kind of object a
consumption bundle is. It may be the case that not all such objects
(i.e. not all vectors) can be feasibly consumed, or we may wish to
impose restrictions in a particular model. Physical constraints include:
we need time to consume, and time is limited; we cannot consume in
two places simultaneously; we have to consume enough of certain things
(food, shelter) to survive.
A restriction we will impose for modeling purposes is that the set of
feasible consumption bundles, or the consumption set, is convex. That
is, if x and y are feasible, then any mixture z = x + (1 ) y with
2 (0; 1) is also feasible. This assumption rules out indivisible com-
modities.
Example. Suppose the commodities are time (in minutes) spent watch-
ing television, and time (in minutes) spent in a rollercoaster car on "The
Beast" (Kings Island near Cincinnati), a ride which takes approximately …ve
minutes. It is possible to watch no television and ride "The Beast" once (call
this bundle x), and it is also possible to watch television for one hour and
not ride "The Beast" (call this bundle y). But one cannot watch television
for half an hour and ride "The Beast" for two-and-a-half minutes (unless it
is a one-period model ....). Since this bundle (call it z) is a mixture of x and
y, the consumption set for these two commodities is not convex.
2
Most of the time, we will assume that the consumption set X contains
all bundles with only non-negative quantities:
which is convex.
2 Rational Preference
The …rst step in analyzing individual choices from the consumption
set is to de…ne preference over its elements. For the moment, we can
think of X more generally as a choice set, where the elements may in
particular be consumption bundles. Or they may be something else
one can express a preference about, for example sports teams.
% (x) fa 2 X s.t. a % xg
- (x) fb 2 X s.t. x % bg :
The intersection of the upper and lower contour sets is the indi¤erence
set at x:
(x) fb 2 X s.t. x bg :
x y i¤ x % y and not y % x
x y i¤ x % y and also y % x:
3
De…nition. Preference % is rational i¤
(i) % is complete: 8x; y 2 X, x % y or y % x (or both).
(ii) % is transitive: 8x; y; z 2 X, x % y % z =) x % z.
3 Utility Functions
To apply tools from calculus in analyzing choices, it is useful to repre-
sent the preference relation by a function.
4
De…nition. The function u : X ! R is a utility function that represents
preference relation % if 8x; y 2 X,
x % y () u (x) u (y) :
non-unique.
On the other hand, a utility function may fail to exist. It never exists
for a preference that is not rational.