0% found this document useful (0 votes)
117 views5 pages

Five Rules For The Evolution of Cooperation: C C C C C C C C C C C C C C

Beautiful

Uploaded by

Culo
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
117 views5 pages

Five Rules For The Evolution of Cooperation: C C C C C C C C C C C C C C

Beautiful

Uploaded by

Culo
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 5

REVIEW

observe cooperation between unrelated indi-


viduals or even between members of different

Five Rules for the Evolution


species. Such considerations led Trivers (10) to
propose another mechanism for the evolution of
cooperation, direct reciprocity. Assume that
of Cooperation there are repeated encounters between the same
two individuals. In every round, each player has
Martin A. Nowak a choice between cooperation and defection. If I
cooperate now, you may cooperate later. Hence,
Cooperation is needed for evolution to construct new levels of organization. Genomes, cells, it might pay off to cooperate. This game theoretic
multicellular organisms, social insects, and human society are all based on cooperation. Cooperation framework is known as the repeated Prisoner’s
means that selfish replicators forgo some of their reproductive potential to help one another. But Dilemma.
natural selection implies competition and therefore opposes cooperation unless a specific mechanism But what is a good strategy for playing this
is at work. Here I discuss five mechanisms for the evolution of cooperation: kin selection, direct game? In two computer tournaments, Axelrod
reciprocity, indirect reciprocity, network reciprocity, and group selection. For each mechanism, a simple (11) discovered that the “winning strategy”
rule is derived that specifies whether natural selection can lead to cooperation. was the simplest of all, tit-for-tat. This strat-
egy always starts with a cooperation, then it
volution is based on a fierce competition well-mixed populations needs help for establish- does whatever the other player has done in the

E between individuals and should therefore


reward only selfish behavior. Every gene,
ing cooperation. previous round: a cooperation for a coopera-
tion, a defection for a defection. This simple

Downloaded from http://science.sciencemag.org/ on October 28, 2017


every cell, and every organism should be de- Kin Selection concept captured the fascination of all enthu-
signed to promote its own evolutionary success When J. B. S. Haldane remarked, “I will jump siasts of the repeated Prisoner’s Dilemma.
at the expense of its competitors. Yet we ob- into the river to save two brothers or eight Many empirical and theoretical studies were
serve cooperation on many levels of biolog- cousins,” he anticipated what became later known inspired by Axelrod’s groundbreaking work
ical organization. Genes cooperate in genomes. as Hamilton’s rule (1). This ingenious idea is that (12–14).
Chromosomes cooperate in eukaryotic cells. natural selection can favor cooperation if the But soon an Achilles heel of the world
Cells cooperate in multicellular organisms. There donor and the recipient of an altruistic act are champion was revealed: If there are erroneous
are many examples of cooperation among ani- genetic relatives. More precisely, Hamilton’s rule moves caused by “trembling hands” or “fuzzy
mals. Humans are the champions of cooperation: states that the coefficient of relatedness, r, must minds,” then the performance of tit-for-tat de-
From hunter-gatherer societies to nation-states, exceed the cost-to-benefit ratio of the altruistic act: clines (15, 16). Tit-for-tat cannot correct mis-
cooperation is the decisive organizing principle takes, because an accidental defection leads to a
of human society. No other life form on Earth is r > c/b (1) long sequence of retaliation. At first, tit-for-tat
engaged in the same complex games of cooper- was replaced by generous-tit-for-tat (17), a strat-
ation and defection. The question of how natural Relatedness is defined as the probability of egy that cooperates whenever you cooperate,
selection can lead to cooperative behavior has sharing a gene. The probability that two brothers but sometimes cooperates although you have
fascinated evolutionary biologists for several share the same gene by descent is 1/2; the same defected [with probability 1 − (c/b)]. Natural
decades. probability for cousins is 1/8. Hamilton’s theory selection can promote forgiveness.
A cooperator is someone who pays a cost, became widely known as “kin selection” or Subsequently, tit-for-tat was replaced by
c, for another individual to receive a benefit, “inclusive fitness” (2–7). When evaluating the win-stay, lose-shift, which is the even simpler
b. A defector has no cost and does not deal fitness of the behavior induced by a certain gene, idea of repeating your previous move when-
out benefits. Cost and benefit are measured in it is important to include the behavior’s effect on ever you are doing well, but changing other-
terms of fitness. Reproduction can be genetic kin who might carry the same gene. Therefore, wise (18). By various measures of success,
or cultural. In any mixed population, defectors the “extended phenotype” of cooperative behav- win-stay, lose-shift is more robust than either
have a higher average fitness than cooperators ior is the consequence of “selfish genes” (8, 9). tit-for-tat or generous-tit-for-tat (15, 18). Tit-
(Fig. 1). Therefore, selection acts to increase for-tat is an efficient catalyst of cooperation in a
the relative abundance of defectors. After some Direct Reciprocity society where nearly everybody is a defector,
time, cooperators vanish from the population. It is unsatisfactory to have a theory that can ex- but once cooperation is established, win-stay,
Remarkably, however, a population of only plain cooperation only among relatives. We also lose-shift is better able to maintain it.
cooperators has the highest average fitness,
whereas a population of only defectors has
the lowest. Thus, natural selection constantly
C C C C C D
reduces the average fitness of the popula-
C C
Mutation
C
Selection
D C Selection
D D D
tion. Fisher’s fundamental theorem, which
C C C
states that average fitness increases under
C C D D D D D
constant selection, does not apply here be-
cause selection is frequency-dependent: The
fitness of individuals depends on the fre- Declining average fitness
quency (= relative abundance) of cooperators in Fig. 1. Without any mechanism for the evolution of cooperation, natural selection favors defectors. In a
the population. We see that natural selection in mixed population, defectors, D, have a higher payoff (= fitness) than cooperators, C. Therefore, natural
selection continuously reduces the abundance, i, of cooperators until they are extinct. The average
fitness of the population also declines under natural selection. The total population size is given by N. If
Program for Evolutionary Dynamics, Department of Or-
ganismic and Evolutionary Biology, and Department of there are i cooperators and N − i defectors, then the fitness of cooperators and defectors, respectively,
Mathematics, Harvard University, Cambridge, MA 02138, is given by fC = [b(i − 1)/(N − 1)] − c and fD = bi/(N − 1). The average fitness of the population is given
USA. E-mail: martin_nowak@harvard.edu by ‾f = (b − c)i/N.

1560 8 DECEMBER 2006 VOL 314 SCIENCE www.sciencemag.org


REVIEW
The number of possible strategies for the reciprocity also leads to the evolution of morality a certain size, it can split into two. In this case,
repeated Prisoner’s Dilemma is unlimited, but (30) and social norms (21, 22). another group becomes extinct in order to con-
a simple general rule can be shown without The calculations of indirect reciprocity are strain the total population size. Note that only
any difficulty. Direct reciprocity can lead to the complicated and only a tiny fraction of this uni- individuals reproduce, but selection emerges
evolution of cooperation only if the probability, verse has been uncovered, but again a simple on two levels. There is competition between
w, of another encounter between the same two rule has emerged (19). Indirect reciprocity can groups because some groups grow faster and
individuals exceeds the cost-to-benefit ratio of only promote cooperation if the probability, q, split more often. In particular, pure cooperator
the altruistic act: of knowing someone’s reputation exceeds the groups grow faster than pure defector groups,
cost-to-benefit ratio of the altruistic act: whereas in any mixed group, defectors re-
w > c/b (2) produce faster than cooperators. Therefore, se-
q > c/b (3) lection on the lower level (within groups) favors
Indirect Reciprocity defectors, whereas selection on the higher level
Direct reciprocity is a powerful mechanism Network Reciprocity (between groups) favors cooperators. This model
for the evolution of cooperation, but it leaves The argument for natural selection of defection is based on “group fecundity selection,” which
out certain aspects that are particularly impor- (Fig. 1) is based on a well-mixed population, means that groups of cooperators have a higher
tant for humans. Direct reciprocity relies on where everybody interacts equally likely with rate of splitting in two. We can also imagine a
repeated encounters between the same two everybody else. This approximation is used by model based on “group viability selection,”
individuals, and both individuals must be able all standard approaches to evolutionary game
to provide help, which is less costly for the dynamics (31–34). But real populations are not
donor than it is beneficial for the recipient. well mixed. Spatial structures or social net-
But often the interactions among humans are works imply that some individuals interact

Downloaded from http://science.sciencemag.org/ on October 28, 2017


asymmetric and fleeting. One person is in a more often than others. One approach of cap-
position to help another, but there is no possi- turing this effect is evolutionary graph theory
bility for a direct reciprocation. We help strangers (35), which allows us to study how spatial struc-
who are in need. We donate to charities that do ture affects evolutionary and ecological dy-
not donate to us. Direct reciprocity is like a barter namics (36–39).
economy based on the immediate exchange of The individuals of a population occupy the
goods, whereas indirect reciprocity resembles the vertices of a graph. The edges determine who
invention of money. The money that fuels the interacts with whom. Let us consider plain
engines of indirect reciprocity is reputation. cooperators and defectors without any strategic
Helping someone establishes a good reputa- complexity. A cooperator pays a cost, c, for
tion, which will be rewarded by others. When each neighbor to receive a benefit, b. Defec-
deciding how to act, we take into account the tors have no costs, and their neighbors receive
possible consequences for our reputation. We no benefits. In this setting, cooperators can
feel strongly about events that affect us directly, prevail by forming network clusters, where
but we also take a keen interest in the affairs of they help each other. The resulting “network
others, as demonstrated by the contents of reciprocity” is a generalization of “spatial rec-
gossip. iprocity” (40).
In the standard framework of indirect rec- Games on graphs are easy to study by com-
iprocity, there are randomly chosen pairwise puter simulation, but they are difficult to analyze
encounters where the same two individuals mathematically because of the enormous num-
need not meet again. One individual acts as ber of possible configurations that can arise.
donor, the other as recipient. The donor can Nonetheless, a surprisingly simple rule deter-
decide whether or not to cooperate. The inter- mines whether network reciprocity can favor
action is observed by a subset of the popu- cooperation (41). The benefit-to-cost ratio must
lation who might inform others. Reputation exceed the average number of neighbors, k, per
allows evolution of cooperation by indirect individual:
reciprocity (19). Natural selection favors strat- Fig. 2. Evolutionary dynamics of cooperators
egies that base the decision to help on the b/c > k (4) and defectors. The red and blue arrows indicate
reputation of the recipient. Theoretical and em- selection favoring defectors and cooperators,
pirical studies of indirect reciprocity show that Group Selection respectively. (A) Without any mechanism for the
people who are more helpful are more likely to Selection acts not only on individuals but also evolution of cooperation, defectors dominate. A
receive help (20–28). on groups. A group of cooperators might be mechanism for the evolution of cooperation can
Although simple forms of indirect reciprocity more successful than a group of defectors. There allow cooperators to be the evolutionarily stable
strategy (ESS), risk-dominant (RD), or advanta-
can be found in animals (29), only humans seem have been many theoretical and empirical studies
geous (AD) in comparison with defectors. (B)
to engage in the full complexity of the game. of group selection, with some controversy, and
Cooperators are ESS if they can resist invasion by
Indirect reciprocity has substantial cognitive recently there has been a renaissance of such defectors. (C) Cooperators are RD if the basin of
demands. Not only must we remember our own ideas under the heading of “multilevel selection” attraction of defectors is less than 1/2. (D)
interactions, we must also monitor the ever- (42–50). Cooperators are AD if the basin of attraction of
changing social network of the group. Language A simple model of group selection works as defectors is less than 1/3. In this case, the fixa-
is needed to gain the information and spread the follows (51). A population is subdivided into tion probability of a single cooperator in a finite
gossip associated with indirect reciprocity. Pre- groups. Cooperators help others in their own population of defectors is greater than the in-
sumably, selection for indirect reciprocity and group. Defectors do not help. Individuals re- verse of the population size (for weak selection).
human language has played a decisive role in produce proportional to their payoff. Offspring (E) Some mechanisms allow cooperators to domi-
the evolution of human intelligence (28). Indirect are added to the same group. If a group reaches nate defectors.

www.sciencemag.org SCIENCE VOL 314 8 DECEMBER 2006 1561


REVIEW
where groups of cooperators are less likely to go measures of evolutionary success. Suppose a A mechanism for the evolution of cooper-
extinct. game between two strategies, cooperators C and ation can ensure that cooperators become
In the mathematically convenient limit of defectors D, is given by the payoff matrix ESS, RD, or AD (Fig. 2). Some mechanisms
weak selection and rare group splitting, we ob- even allow cooperators to dominate defectors,
tain a simple result (51): If n is the maximum C D which means a > g and b > d.
group size and m is the number of groups, then C a b
group selection allows evolution of cooperation, D g d Comparative Analysis
provided that We have encountered five mechanisms for the
The entries denote the payoff for the row evolution of cooperation (Fig. 3). Although the
b/c > 1 + (n/m) (5) player. Without any mechanism for the evolution mathematical formalisms underlying the five
of cooperation, defectors dominate cooperators, mechanisms are very different, at the center of
Evolutionary Success which means a < g and b < d. A mechanism for each theory is a simple rule. I now present a
Before proceeding to a comparative analysis of the evolution of cooperation can change these coherent mathematical framework that allows
the five mechanisms, let me introduce some inequalities. the derivation of all five rules. The crucial idea
1) If a > g, then cooperation is an evo- is that each mechanism can be presented as a
lutionarily stable strategy (ESS). An infinitely game between two strategies given by a 2 × 2
Kin selection large population of cooperators cannot be in- payoff matrix (Table 1). From this matrix, we
vaded by defectors under deterministic selec- can derive the relevant condition for evolution
tion dynamics (32). of cooperation.
1 r 2) If a + b > g + d, then cooperators are For kin selection, I use the approach of
risk-dominant (RD). If both strategies are inclusive fitness proposed by Maynard Smith

Downloaded from http://science.sciencemag.org/ on October 28, 2017


Direct reciprocity ESS, then the risk-dominant strategy has the (31). The relatedness between two players is r.
bigger basin of attraction. Therefore, your payoff multiplied by r is added
3) If a + 2b > g + 2d, then cooperators are to mine. A second method, shown in (53), leads
advantageous (AD). This concept is important to a different matrix but the same result. For
for stochastic game dynamics in finite pop- direct reciprocity, the cooperators use tit-for-tat
ulations. Here, the crucial quantity is the fix- while the defectors use “always-defect.” The
Indirect reciprocity ation probability of a strategy, defined as the expected number of rounds is 1/(1 − w). Two
probability that the lineage arising from a tit-for-tat players cooperate all the time. Tit-for-
single mutant of that strategy will take over tat versus always-defect cooperates only in the
the entire population consisting of the other first move and then defects. For indirect rec-
strategy. An AD strategy has a fixation proba- iprocity, the probability of knowing someone’s
bility greater than the inverse of the popu- reputation is given by q. A cooperator helps
lation size, 1/N. The condition can also be unless the reputation of the other person in-
expressed as a 1/3 rule: If the fitness of the in- dicates a defector. A defector never helps. For
Network reciprocity vading strategy at a frequency of 1/3 is greater network reciprocity, it can be shown that the
than the fitness of the resident, then the fix- expected frequency of cooperators is described
ation probability of the invader is greater than by a standard replicator equation with a trans-
1/N. This condition holds in the limit of weak formed payoff matrix (54). For group selection,
selection (52). the payoff matrices of the two games—within

Table 1. Each mechanism can be described by a simple 2 × 2 payoff matrix, which specifies the
interaction between cooperators and defectors. From these matrices we can directly derive the nec-
essary conditions for evolution of cooperation. The parameters c and b denote, respectively, the cost
for the donor and the benefit for the recipient. For network reciprocity, we use the parameter H =
Group selection [(b − c)k − 2c]/[(k + 1)(k − 2)]. All conditions can be expressed as the benefit-to-cost ratio
exceeding a critical value. See (53) for further explanations of the underlying calculations.

Cooperation is…
Payoff matrix
C D ESS RD AD
Kin C (b c)(1 r ) br c b 1 b 1 b 1
r…genetic relatedness
selection D b rc 0 c r c r c r
Cooperators Defectors

Fig. 3. Five mechanisms for the evolution of Direct C (b c) /(1 w) c b 1 b 2 w b 3 2w w…probability of next round
reciprocity D b 0 c w c w c w
cooperation. Kin selection operates when the
donor and the recipient of an altruistic act are
Indirect C b c c(1 q) b 1 b 2 q b 3 2q q…social acquaintanceship
genetic relatives. Direct reciprocity requires re- reciprocity D b(1 q ) 0 c q c q c q
peated encounters between the same two individ-
uals. Indirect reciprocity is based on reputation; a Network C b c H c b b b
helpful individual is more likely to receive help. reciprocity k k k k…number of neighbors
D b H 0 c c c
Network reciprocity means that clusters of coop-
erators outcompete defectors. Group selection is b n b n b n n…group size
Group C (b c)(m n) (b c)m cn 1 1 1
the idea that competition is not only between selection c m c m c m m…number of groups
D bn 0
individuals but also between groups.

1562 8 DECEMBER 2006 VOL 314 SCIENCE www.sciencemag.org


REVIEW
and between groups—can be added up. The correlation. Therefore, kin selection theory also 32. J. Hofbauer, K. Sigmund, Evolutionary Games and
details of all these arguments and their limi- provides an approach to compare different mech- Population Dynamics (Cambridge Univ. Press, Cambridge,
1998).
tations are given in (53). anisms for the evolution of cooperation (69, 70). 33. J. Hofbauer, K. Sigmund, Bull. Am. Math. Soc. 40, 479
For kin selection, the calculation shows that The two fundamental principles of evolution (2003).
Hamilton’s rule, r > c/b, is the decisive criterion are mutation and natural selection. But evolution 34. M. A. Nowak, K. Sigmund, Science 303, 793 (2004).
for all three measures of evolutionary success: is constructive because of cooperation. New 35. E. Lieberman, C. Hauert, M. A. Nowak, Nature 433, 312
(2005).
ESS, RD, and AD. Similarly, for network rec- levels of organization evolve when the compet- 36. R. Durrett, S. A. Levin, Theor. Popul. Biol. 46, 363
iprocity and group selection, we obtain the ing units on the lower level begin to cooperate. (1994).
same condition for all three evaluations, name- Cooperation allows specialization and thereby 37. M. P. Hassell, H. N. Comins, R. M. May, Nature 370, 290
ly b/c > k and b/c > 1 + (n/m), respectively. promotes biological diversity. Cooperation is the (1994).
38. C. Hauert, M. Doebeli, Nature 428, 643 (2004).
The reason is the following: If these con- secret behind the open-endedness of the evolu- 39. R. M. May, Trends Ecol. Evol. 21, 394 (2006).
ditions hold, then cooperators dominate defec- tionary process. Perhaps the most remarkable 40. M. A. Nowak, R. M. May, Nature 359, 826 (1992).
tors. For direct and indirect reciprocity, we aspect of evolution is its ability to generate co- 41. H. Ohtsuki, C. Hauert, E. Lieberman, M. A. Nowak, Nature
find that the ESS conditions lead to w > c/b operation in a competitive world. Thus, we 441, 502 (2006).
42. G. C. Williams, D. C. Williams, Evolution 11, 32 (1957).
and q > c/b, respectively. Slightly more strin- might add “natural cooperation” as a third fun-
43. D. S. Wilson, Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 72, 143
gent conditions must hold for cooperation to be damental principle of evolution beside mutation (1975).
RD or AD. and natural selection. 44. P. D. Taylor, D. S. Wilson, Evolution 42, 193 (1988).
45. A. R. Rogers, Am. Nat. 135, 398 (1990).
Conclusion 46. R. E. Michod, Darwinian Dynamics (Princeton Univ. Press,
References and Notes Princeton, NJ, 1999).
Each of the five possible mechanisms for the 1. W. D. Hamilton, J. Theor. Biol. 7, 1 (1964). 47. L. Keller, Ed., Levels of Selection in Evolution (Princeton
evolution of cooperation—kin selection, direct 2. A. Grafen, in Oxford Surveys in Evolutionary Biology, Univ. Press, Princeton, NJ, 1999).

Downloaded from http://science.sciencemag.org/ on October 28, 2017


reciprocity, indirect reciprocity, network reci- vol. 2, R. Dawkins, M. Ridley, Eds. (Oxford Univ. Press, 48. J. Paulsson, Genetics 161, 1373 (2002).
Oxford, 1985), pp. 28–89. 49. P. B. Rainey, K. Rainey, Nature 425, 72 (2003).
procity and group selection—can be described
3. P. D. Taylor, Evol. Ecol. 6, 352 (1992). 50. E. O. Wilson, B. Hölldobler, Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A.
by a characteristic 2 × 2 payoff matrix, from 4. D. C. Queller, Am. Nat. 139, 540 (1992). 102, 13367 (2005).
which we can directly derive the fundamental 5. S. A. Frank, Foundations of Social Evolution (Princeton 51. A. Traulsen, M. A. Nowak, Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A.
rules that specify whether cooperation can Univ. Press, Princeton, NJ, 1998). 103, 10952 (2006).
evolve (Table 1). Each rule can be expressed 6. S. A. West, I. Pen, A. S. Griffin, Science 296, 72 52. M. A. Nowak, A. Sasaki, C. Taylor, D. Fudenberg, Nature
(2002). 428, 646 (2004).
as the benefit-to-cost ratio of the altruistic act 7. K. R. Foster, T. Wenseleers, F. L. W. Ratnieks, Trends Ecol. 53. See supporting material on Science Online.
being greater than some critical value. The Evol. 21, 57 (2006). 54. H. Ohtsuki, M. A. Nowak, J. Theor. Biol. 243, 86
payoff matrices can be imported into standard 8. R. Dawkins, The Selfish Gene (Oxford Univ. Press, Oxford, (2006).
frameworks of evolutionary game dynamics. 1976). 55. M. A. Nowak, Evolutionary Dynamics (Harvard Univ.
9. E. O. Wilson, Sociobiology (Harvard Univ. Press, Press, Cambridge, MA, 2006).
For example, we can study replicator equations Cambridge, MA, 1975). 56. R. L. Riolo, M. D. Cohen, R. Axelrod, Nature 414, 441
for games on graphs (54), for group selection, 10. R. Trivers, Q. Rev. Biol. 46, 35 (1971). (2001).
and for kin selection. This creates interesting 11. R. Axelrod, The Evolution of Cooperation (Basic Books, 57. A. Traulsen, H. G. Schuster, Phys. Rev. E 68, 046129
new possibilities for the theory of evolutionary New York, 1984). (2003).
12. R. Axelrod, W. D. Hamilton, Science 211, 1390 58. V. A. Jansen, M. van Baalen, Nature 440, 663 (2006).
dynamics (55). (1981). 59. C. Hauert, S. De Monte, J. Hofbauer, K. Sigmund, Science
I have not discussed all potential mechanisms 13. M. Milinski, Nature 325, 434 (1987). 296, 1129 (2002).
for the evolution of cooperation. An interest- 14. L. A. Dugatkin, Cooperation Among Animals (Oxford 60. T. Yamagishi, J. Pers. Soc. Psychol. 51, 110 (1986).
ing possibility is offered by “green beard” mod- Univ. Press, Oxford, 1997). 61. E. Fehr, S. Gaechter, Nature 415, 137 (2002).
15. D. Fudenberg, E. Maskin, Am. Econ. Rev. 80, 274 62. E. Fehr, U. Fischbacher, Nature 425, 785 (2003).
els where cooperators recognize each other via
(1990). 63. C. F. Camerer, E. Fehr, Science 311, 47 (2006).
arbitrary labels (56–58). Another way to obtain 16. R. Selten, P. Hammerstein, Behav. Brain Sci. 7, 115 64. Ö. Gürerk, B. Irlenbusch, B. Rockenbach, Science 312,
cooperation is making the game voluntary rather (1984). 108 (2006).
than obligatory: If players can choose to cooper- 17. M. A. Nowak, K. Sigmund, Nature 355, 250 (1992). 65. K. Sigmund, C. Hauert, M. A. Nowak, Proc. Natl. Acad.
ate, defect, or not play at all, then some level of 18. M. A. Nowak, K. Sigmund, Nature 364, 56 (1993). Sci. U.S.A. 98, 10757 (2001).
19. M. A. Nowak, K. Sigmund, Nature 393, 573 (1998). 66. R. Boyd, H. Gintis, S. Bowles, P. J. Richerson, Proc. Natl.
cooperation usually prevails in dynamic oscil- 20. C. Wedekind, M. Milinski, Science 288, 850 (2000). Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 100, 3531 (2003).
lations (59). Punishment is an important factor 21. H. Ohtsuki, Y. Iwasa, J. Theor. Biol. 231, 107 (2004). 67. S. Bowles, H. Gintis, Theor. Popul. Biol. 65, 17 (2004).
that can promote cooperative behavior in some 22. H. Brandt, K. Sigmund, J. Theor. Biol. 231, 475 68. M. Nakamaru, Y. Iwasa, Evol. Ecol. Res. 7, 853
situations (60–64), but it is not a mechanism for (2004). (2005).
23. O. Leimar, P. Hammerstein, Proc. R. Soc. London Ser. B 69. L. Lehmann, L. Keller, J. Evol. Biol. 19, 1365 (2006).
the evolution of cooperation. All evolutionary 268, 745 (2001). 70. J. A. Fletcher, M. Zwick, Am. Nat. 168, 252 (2006).
models of punishment so far are based on un- 24. M. Milinski, D. Semmann, H. J. Krambeck, Nature 415, 71. Supported by the John Templeton Foundation and
derlying mechanisms such as indirect reciprocity 424 (2002). the NSF-NIH joint program in mathematical biology
(65), group selection (66, 67), or network reci- 25. M. A. Fishman, J. Theor. Biol. 225, 285 (2003). (NIH grant 1R01GM078986-01). The Program for
26. M. D. Hauser, M. K. Chen, F. Chen, E. Chuang, Proc. Evolutionary Dynamics at Harvard University is
procity (68). Punishment can enhance the level of R. Soc. London Ser. B 270, 2363 (2003). sponsored by J. Epstein.
cooperation that is achieved in such models. 27. K. Panchanathan, R. Boyd, Nature 432, 499 (2004).
Kin selection has led to mathematical the- 28. M. A. Nowak, K. Sigmund, Nature 437, 1291 (2005). Supporting Online Material
ories (based on the Price equation) that are 29. R. Bshary, A. S. Grutter, Nature 441, 975 (2006). www.sciencemag.org/cgi/content/full/314/5805/1560/DC1
30. R. D. Alexander, The Biology of Moral Systems SOM Text
more general than just analyzing interactions (de Gruyter, New York, 1987). References
between genetic relatives (4, 5). The interacting 31. J. Maynard Smith, Evolution and the Theory of Games
individuals can have any form of phenotypic (Cambridge Univ. Press, Cambridge, 1982). 10.1126/science.1133755

www.sciencemag.org SCIENCE VOL 314 8 DECEMBER 2006 1563


Five Rules for the Evolution of Cooperation
Martin A. Nowak

Science 314 (5805), 1560-1563.


DOI: 10.1126/science.1133755

Downloaded from http://science.sciencemag.org/ on October 28, 2017


ARTICLE TOOLS http://science.sciencemag.org/content/314/5805/1560

SUPPLEMENTARY http://science.sciencemag.org/content/suppl/2006/12/05/314.5805.1560.DC1
MATERIALS

RELATED http://science.sciencemag.org/content/sci/314/5805/1555.full
CONTENT

REFERENCES This article cites 58 articles, 14 of which you can access for free
http://science.sciencemag.org/content/314/5805/1560#BIBL

PERMISSIONS http://www.sciencemag.org/help/reprints-and-permissions

Use of this article is subject to the Terms of Service

Science (print ISSN 0036-8075; online ISSN 1095-9203) is published by the American Association for the Advancement of
Science, 1200 New York Avenue NW, Washington, DC 20005. 2017 © The Authors, some rights reserved; exclusive
licensee American Association for the Advancement of Science. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. The title
Science is a registered trademark of AAAS.

You might also like

pFad - Phonifier reborn

Pfad - The Proxy pFad of © 2024 Garber Painting. All rights reserved.

Note: This service is not intended for secure transactions such as banking, social media, email, or purchasing. Use at your own risk. We assume no liability whatsoever for broken pages.


Alternative Proxies:

Alternative Proxy

pFad Proxy

pFad v3 Proxy

pFad v4 Proxy