Neo-Classical Sociology - The PR - Alain Caille PDF
Neo-Classical Sociology - The PR - Alain Caille PDF
Neo-Classical Sociology - The PR - Alain Caille PDF
Alain Caillé
Université Paris-Nanterre, Paris, France
Frédéric Vandenberghe
Rio de Janeiro State University, IESP-UERJ, Rio de Janeiro, Brazil
Abstract
This article calls for a new theoretical synthesis that overcomes the fragmentation,
specialization and professionalization within the social sciences. As an alternative to
utilitarianism and the colonization of the social sciences by rational choice models, it
proposes a new articulation of social theory, the Studies and moral, social and political
philosophy. Based on a positive anthropology that finds its inspiration in Marcel Mauss’s
classic essay on the gift, it recommends a return to classical social theory and explores
articulations between theories of reciprocity, care and recognition.
Keywords
anti-utilitarianism, care, French theory, general social theory, the gift, Mauss, postcolonial
studies, recognition
Il n’y a pas des sciences sociales, mais une science des socie´te´s.
Marcel Mauss (1969: 51)
Sociology is entering its Second Century. It is a young discipline, but it is growing old.
Our question is whether it was merely, like anthropology, a discipline of the twentieth
century or whether it can continue for another two centuries. The numbers of sociolo-
gists, sociology teachers and sociology students are increasing around the world, but for
Corresponding author:
Frédéric Vandenberghe, Rio de Janeiro State University, IESP-UERJ, 82 Rua da Matriz, Botafogo, 22260-100,
Rio de Janeiro, Brazil.
Email: frederic@iesp.uerj.br
several reasons, it is not clear that this seemingly favourable situation will last, nor that
the discipline will survive for a long time in its current form. Not that sociology is in
crisis. It is not. All things considered, that is what we find most worrying. With its
increasing professionalism, it courts the risk of becoming irrelevant. There are numerous
investigations of local social problems, from drunken driving in Alabama to bullying on
the Internet and discrimination of Brazilian transsexuals in Paris. About the global eco-
nomic crisis, however, sociology has hardly anything special to say. When its contribu-
tions are not couched in obscure jargon or impenetrable maths that give them a scientific
semblance, its observations remain so close to common sense and everyday life that one
wonders what distinguishes sociology from sociography or even from (realist) literature.
Both in its expert and common-sense versions one finds a lot of moral posturing and
ideological positioning. As if denunciations of global capitalism and sympathy with the
downtrodden could possibly change the system!
In a money-driven world that admits only the measure of immediate profitability,
the usefulness of sociology is indeed challenged. The discipline may not be in crisis, it
nevertheless displays increasing uncertainty about its identity, its project and its legiti-
macy. The ritual invocation of Marx, Weber and Durkheim as ‘founding fathers’ of
sociology does not restrain the disorientation and fragmentation of the discipline.
While it constructs an illusionary continuity between the past and the present, it pre-
cludes an exploration of continuities with the older traditions (natural law, philosophy
of history, the humanities, moral and political philosophy, political economy). The
canonization of the classics checks disciplinary drift, but it only does so by relegating
other authors to the periphery of the discipline. Who still reads Comte, Spencer or
even Parsons?
In this article, we propose a series of integrated reflections on the current state of the
social sciences. Our aim is to contribute to the development of a general social theory
along anti-utilitarian lines. The article contains four sections. In the first section, it opens
with a brief analysis of a quadruple fragmentation within the social sciences: the auton-
omization of theory and research; the fragmentation among theories; the separation of
sociology and the Studies; as well as between the social sciences and moral, social and
political philosophy. As an alternative to the rational choice models of neo-classical eco-
nomics, in the second section, it develops the contours of neo-classical sociology and
calls for a new synthesis of social theory, the Studies and moral and political philosophy.
Through an articulation of metatheory, social theory and sociological theory, in the third
section, it advances a loose integration of theories of social action, order and social
change and spells out the minimal requirements of a pluralist position. Finally, in the
fourth section, in dialogue with theories of care and recognition, it presents and proposes
the gift paradigm as a general social theory that, with a little help from our friends, is able
to translate the other theories. Tentatively, we suggest that it offers the best platform for a
new synthesis within the social sciences.
Four fragmentations
When we look at the current situation of sociology, we see four fragmentations: two
internal ones and two external ones.
The first fragmentation within sociology is that between teaching and research, theory
and methodology, concepts and techniques, abstractions and operationalizations. On the
one hand, we have the teaching of classical and contemporary sociological theory (SOC
101: Marx, Weber, Durkheim, Simmel; SOC 201: Bourdieu, Giddens, Habermas, some-
times also Luhmann, though, granted, his work is definitely more difficult to teach). The
introductory courses are given at the beginning of the curriculum to students who are
generally too young to grasp its significance. The result is rather predictable: Sociology
is identified with a positivist, objectivist and determinist account of society (culled from
the first chapter of Durkheim’s The Rules of Sociological Method), an iron-cage-vision
of modernity (extracted from the final pages of The Protestant Ethic) and a trenchant, yet
stereotyped critique of neo-liberal capitalism (inspired by the Communist Manifesto). On
the other hand, there is hands-on training for empirical research, both qualitative (parti-
cipant observation, interviews, life histories, etc.) and quantitative (multiple regression,
correspondence analysis, geodata, etc.), which is required from both researchers and
research apprentices alike. Increasingly, the access to data defines the identity of its prac-
titioners. In many countries, but above all in France, the USA, less so in the UK, Ger-
many and Brazil, empirical research has become a conditio sine qua non to be even
recognized as a sociologist.
The question, therefore, arises: What or who is a sociologist? He or she is a profes-
sional who practises a cult of commemoration of the ‘founding fathers’, quotes Marx,
Durkheim and Bourdieu, does specialized work in one of the many ‘fields’ of sociology
(sociology of health, education, sports, social movements, etc.), applies research meth-
ods and techniques (participant observation, discourse analysis, factor analysis) to gather
and analyse the empirical data and does not eschew moral and political evaluation of the
social situation that is investigated.
Those who define themselves primarily as empirical researchers (ethnographers and
stats people) are not really bothered by theoretical and conceptual issues anyway. All too
often, theories have a merely decorative use and conceptual issues are quickly resolved
and dissolved through a series of obligatory references to a few contemporary schools of
thought that are far from reaching unanimity within the discipline: critical realism, neo-
Marxism, actor-network theory, pragmatism, symbolic interactionism, ethnomethodol-
ogy, etc. – all these scholarly references function more as ‘badges of identification’
(Berthelot, 2000: 72) than as genuine pointers of conceptual elaboration.
Hence, the second fragmentation. It results from the conflicts and tussles between
anathematizing sociological schools (cultural sociology vs. structural sociology, critical
theory vs. systems theory, rational choice vs. neo-institutionalism) that are unable to
come to a minimum consensus about the very essence of sociology. What we would call
‘multiple paradigmatasis’ has now become so acute that it is hard to see what the nano-
approach of discourse analysis has in common with the mega-approach of world systems
theory. Apart from a nominal adherence to sociology, within the discipline, there is not
even a minimum consensus about the unit of analysis, basic ontology or elementary con-
cepts. At best, there is mutual indifference and tolerance; at worst, confrontation and
agonistics.
To those two divisions within the discipline itself, we should add two others that
emerge at the boundaries of sociology and its environment. The third fragmentation
To clear the way for investigations that are at the intersection of sociology, the
Studies and philosophy, we will quickly review some developments in contemporary
moral, social and political philosophy. Following the debate between liberalism and
communitarianism of the 1990s, itself a result of the massive international reception
of John Rawls’s landmark publication in 1971 of A Theory of Justice, moral philoso-
phy has sought to move beyond the narrow, formal and procedural framework in
which John Rawls’s concept of justice as fairness and Jürgen Habermas’s discourse
ethics have locked the normative and ethical thinking for almost fifty years. Be it
through a return to Aristotle, Augustine, Spinoza, Hume, Hegel, Nietzsche or Heideg-
ger, philosophers have increasingly explored the ethical questions that Kantian deon-
tology and utilitarian consequentialism had neglected and pushed to the margins:
solicitude (Levinas), care (Gilligan), trust (Baier), empathy (Irigaray), hospitality
(Derrida), authenticity (Taylor) and recognition (Honneth).1 The rehabilitation of
practical philosophy, the rediscovery of virtues and moral sentiments, the ethical turn
within post-structuralism and feminist theory have dislocated the normative emphasis
from the basic structure of well-ordered societies to intersubjectivity, alterity and pri-
mary sociability (Sayer, 2011).
If moral philosophy encounters micro-sociology, macro-sociology encounters critical
theory and social philosophy. Complementing classical theories of modernity with an
investigation of the normative foundations of social critique, social philosophy critically
investigates developmental tendencies of society. It does not hesitate to characterize
them as ‘social pathologies’ when they threaten social integration and jeopardize the
social conditions of the personal realization of the ‘good life’ (Honneth, 2000: 11–69;
Fischbach, 2009). Understood as a systematization of the diagnoses of the present
(Zeitdiagnose) that one finds in the work of Hegel, Marx and Nietzsche or, closer to
us, of Arendt, Castoriadis and Habermas, social philosophy not only analyses social
developments, but it also evaluates and judges them. Joining thus analysis to diagnosis,
social philosophy stands at the intersection of moral and political philosophy.
While contemporary social philosophy remains indebted to the German tradition of
critical theory, contemporary political philosophy has visibly been much more influ-
enced by French post-structuralism and deconstruction. More radical than critical theory,
it weaves post-structuralism and post-Marxism into a heady contentious brew of radical
anti-liberalism. Inspired by a leftist interpretation of Heidegger’s ‘ontological differ-
ence’, the political was introduced as a foundational moment of politics and society
(Marchart, 2007). With the rise of the Global Justice Movement around the turn of the
century and the recent return of radical anti-systemic social movements onto the scene of
world history, late- and post-Marxist philosophers of the cultural left, like Antonio
Negri, Alain Badiou, Slavoj Žižek, Ernesto Laclau or Jacques Rancière have seen in the
‘newest’ social movements in the Middle East (the ‘Arab Spring’), Western Europe (‘los
indignados’) and the United States (‘Occupy’) a rejuvenation of non-representative
forms of democracy. Their revolutionary interpretations of the ontology of the present
are not only in tune with the Zeitgeist; to the extent that their analyses are both relevant
and influential, they have also put sociology in the shadow and recast it as an ‘old
European discipline’ that harks back to foundational texts of the nineteenth century to
understand the challenges of the twenty-first century.
consciously continues moral philosophy by different means, it does not separate social
and moral life (Chanial, 2011; Vandenberghe, forthcoming). It rather seeks to investigate
their relation not only conceptually, but also empirically. Given its differentiation from
economics, it stands and falls with its opposition to utilitarianism. For a long time,
sociology was able to think of itself as the other of economics, and simultaneously also
as its extension, its critique and its Aufhebung. If sociology were to fall apart, an entire
field of thought – that which refuses the transformation of the world into a vast market –
would likewise disappear, condemning us to theoretical, ethical and political
powerlessness.
Hence, in order to organize a rationalized transmission of the achievements of modern
reflexivity, and to counter the imperialism of economics and its tendency to ‘colonize’
the social and political sciences (Archer and Tritter, 2000), there is a pressing need to
find a common denominator among all of the above-mentioned schools and streams
of thought. At this point, we would like to advance our main argument and suggest two
things (we cannot do more than suggest).
First, as an alternative to neo-classical economics, we plead for the development of
‘neo-classical sociology’ as a common platform for the dialogical synthesis of sociology,
the Studies, as well as social, moral and political philosophy. We call it neo-classical
sociology, because we believe that the contemporary understanding of sociology is much
narrower than what the founders of sociology had in mind.4 They knew that foundational
work borders on the philosophical. Their foundation of a new science and their principled
rejection of utilitarianism were inseparable from their appeal for a renewal of society. As
Durkheim famously said in his second Preface to De la division du travail social: ‘Sociol-
ogy would not be not worth a single hour’s effort if it had no more than speculative interest’
(Durkheim, 1986: xxxix). We sincerely believe that if we go back to the initial inspiration
of sociology, we can perhaps ‘re-found’ the social sciences and reformulate its remit so as
to make it more cosmopolitan, ecumenical and inclusive, so inclusive that it can integrate
sociology and anthropology, the Studies, and moral, social and political philosophy into a
common project. That, we submit, is the task of social theory, which we understand in the
broad and inclusive sense as the general theory of the social sciences or, to say the same
thing in slightly different words, the theory of societies in general.5
Moreover, and though we realize that the following affirmation may be slightly less
consensual, we also would like to suggest that the missing common denominator of the
social sciences is to be found in what we and our friends from the MAUSS (Mouvement
Anti-Utilitariste en Sciences Sociales) call the ‘gift-paradigm’.6 Indeed, thirty years of
collective, interdisciplinary reflection on the phenomenon of the gift as a total social fact
have convinced us that the concept of social relations one can deduce and extract from
Marcel Mauss’s Essai sur le don (Mauss, 1950) can and should be extended beyond the
immediate field of ethnology to all social sciences. From this foundational perspective,
Mauss’s discovery of the triple obligation of the gift – ‘to give, to accept and to return the
gift’ (Mauss, 1950: 205–14) – appears to be the basis of social life in general. The
mechanism of reciprocity, which is the motor of sociability, produces, and continues
to produce, society. Without reciprocity, no society; without generosity, neither econom-
ics, nor politics or sociology are possible. The focus on the individual and collective
capacity to initiate, create and sustain social relations allows us also to move beyond the
impasses of individualism and collectivism, liberalism and socialism, market and state.
When the dynamics of reciprocity are fully worked out into a relational, associational
and interactionist theory of society, the anthropology of the gift emerges as a fully-
fledged ‘third paradigm’ (Caillé, 2000, 2014) between individualism and holism. We
think that it not only offers an alternative to the social sciences, but also to society.
As the crucible of society, the political is the continuation of the gift by other means.
It is carried forward by non-governmental organizations, civil associations and social
movements that seek to uphold the moral economy against both the market and the state.
Such associations do not aim to abolish the state or the market; rather, moving beyond
the lib/lab formations of social democracy, they contribute to the realization of Mauss’s
dream of a cooperative or associative socialism.
We have not sufficiently recognized that through its professionalization and specia-
lization, sociology has gradually become very different from what its founders had orig-
inally envisaged it. With the exception of Georg Simmel, who developed his formal
sociology along narrow lines, all of the founders conceived of sociology as a general sci-
ence. They did not think of sociology in a narrow sense, but developed it as a general
science of society and its subsystems. From the beginning, sociology was thus more than
sociology. It was both a specialized discipline (sociology) and a generalizing discourse
(social theory); it was, as Habermas (1991: 184) says in a remarkable reflection on Wei-
mar sociology, ‘at once discipline and superdiscipline, sociology and theory of society’.
The founders envisioned their sociology as a kind of federative metadiscipline that
would unify the various social sciences (history, anthropology, sociology, political sci-
ence, political economy) under a single heading. None of them thought of it as a mere
accumulation of field surveys; rather, they devised it as an empirical social, moral and
political philosophy that would integrate social and historical research into a systematic
presentation and interpretation of the evolution of societies. The ambitions of the inven-
tor of the name, Auguste Comte, were clearly aimed at a ‘positive’ (scientific and
Romantic) philosophy of history that would investigate the empirical conditions of moral
order and progress. Was Marx an economist, a sociologist, a historian, an anthropologist
or a philosopher? Let us not forget that Max Weber, a lawyer by training, whose first
research was in history, had long regarded himself as an economist. Simmel conceived
of himself as a philosopher and considered sociology a pastime. For Durkheim, as for his
friends and collaborators of L’Anne´e sociologique, sociology was clearly intended to
unite all the specialized disciplines of the social sciences: ethnology, science of religion,
science of education, history, economy, etc. And that, with the clear ambition of giving
better answers to the questions raised by moral and political philosophers.
With Comte, we think that it is high time to overcome fragmentation and specializa-
tion through further specialization and differentiation. We need to ‘transform the study
of scientific generalities into one more grand specialty’ (Comte, 1949: 57). We need to
train and form a new class of social scientists who are interdisciplinary and not narrowly
attached to their own discipline, who study the different branches of the social sciences
and explore connections and relations between them, in order to find out what they have
in common.
Let us assume, then, that within all the disciplines that make up the humanities and the
social sciences, there are two slants: a specialized slant, centred on itself and its own
more resolutely macro and also more diagnostic in its basic approach. Given that it tries
to ‘capture its own time in concepts’ (Hegel), it comes as no surprise that it bears the
imprint of its time and is, consequently, more dated. Think about modernization theory
of the 1960s, dependency theory of the 1970s, postmodernism of the 1980s, globalization
theories of the 1990s and post-colonialism of today.
We consider that it will be easier to reach a consensus on a metatheoretical basis than
on a theoretical one. The ‘heterodox consensus’ will most probably be a normative one.
The intellectual alliances between theoretical positions will be of an ethical and political
nature. Assuming we can agree on the metatheoretical foundations of the social sciences,
we can then try to elaborate a general social theory that offers a coherent framework for
the analysis of social action, order and change. On this basis, we can then proceed, in
collaboration with the Studies, to the formulation of a historical grand narrative about
the emergence, development and global diffusion of modernity that does not remain tied
to the nation-state, but takes the world as a single unit of analysis. This analysis of the
global present will not only be descriptive, but also normative. It will be cosmopolitan
and critical, analytic and diagnostic, propaedeutic and reconstructive.
seen the light and tried to correct some of Habermas’s Enlightenment rationalism with an
insistence on the concrete other (Benhabib), recognition (Honneth), solidarity (Brun-
khorst), reflexivity (Ferrara), dialogue (Kögler), etc. belong to the dialogical constella-
tion, even if they drift off towards the neighbouring constellations.
Within the constellation of care, we do find at least three strands (Van Sevenant,
2001): Theories of ‘care of the self’ (Foucault, Hadot, W. Schmidt), existential philoso-
phies of ‘care in itself’ (Heidegger, Levinas, Derrida) and the ‘care for the other’, asso-
ciated with feminism and the ethics of care (Tronto, Gilligan, Held, Kittay).9 What all
these theories and philosophies of care, solicitude and compassion have in common is
a junction between a moral disposition to overcome indifference (care for oneself), to
decentre oneself and depersonalize one’s relation to the world (care in itself) and to
assume responsibility for the suffering of the other (care for the other). Unlike liberal-
masculine visions of the self that underscore autonomy, feminist ethics of care value and
cultivate relations of interdependence between people.
The emphasis on interconnection and reciprocity is also at the centre of the various
theories that make up the constellation of the gift, all of which find their inspiration in
Marcel Mauss’s fabulous essay on the gift.10 Readers of Mauss will remember that the
gift is in no way a simple thing. First, it is not a thing, but a triple process of obligations
(to initiate, accept and return the gift) that ties persons and collectives in communities
of exchange. Second, it is not simple, but complex. It fuses contradictory motives
(obligation and spontaneity, interest and generosity, peace and conflict) into a system
of actions and interactions that are at the root of sociability and community (Caillé,
2000, 2009). Consequently, it comes as no surprise that the reception of Mauss has
been complicated as well, with various interpretations, from Lévi-Strauss to Bourdieu,
Bataille to Baudrillard, Derrida to Marion, Sahlins to Strathern, Lefort to Caillé, that
are at odds with each other. Where some (like Bourdieu) would only see hypocrisy that
masks the tit-for-tat of exchange, others (like Derrida) would go to the other extreme
and consider the asymmetric, unilateral, hyperbolic gift with no return possible as the
only real gift. Similarly, while some (like Lévi-Strauss) see the gift as a system, others
(like Lefort) see it as action. Some (like Ricoeur) identify it as peace, others (like
Bataille) as agonism, etc.
The theory of recognition has by now sprawled into an academic cottage industry
(Guéguen and Malochet, 2012). Philosophers have offered new interpretations of the role
of Anerkennung in Hegel’s writings (from the early Realphilosophie to the Phenomen-
ologie des Geistes), though Fichte, Adam Smith and Rousseau have also been hailed
as predecessors. Without going back to the notion of anagnôrisis in Aristotle and Sopho-
cles, it is remarkable how various currents in contemporary moral and political philoso-
phy (critical theory with Honneth and Fraser, hermeneutics with Taylor and Ricoeur,
deconstruction with J. Butler and J. Tully, psychoanalysis and social psychology with
J. Benjamin and Todorov), have been able to latch onto the concept of recognition and
make it into a major asterism. The repercussions of Axel Honneth’s (1992) work and his
debate with Nancy Fraser (Fraser and Honneth, 2003) suggest that the category of rec-
ognition (and its negation: invisibility, humiliation, alienation) taps into an unnamed
reservoir of diffuse suffering among the population that deserves attention and repair
if solidarity is to be maintained.
Economics investigates what determines the value of goods and, correlatively, also the
value of subjects as either owners or producers of goods endowed with a certain value.
Sociology asks – though often without knowing it – what determines the relative value of
various social groups, independent of their ability to produce or own goods.
When asked what determines the economic value of goods or merchandise, the eco-
nomic tradition has provided two main answers: their utility (i.e. their relative scarcity),
or the average working time necessary for their production. What determines the value of
social groups and individuals? The very language we have used to describe the core
issues of the major schools of contemporary thought sufficiently indicates the direction
in which we must seek the answer. What social groups in conflict (women, former colo-
nies, subalterns, care providers, etc.) want to have recognized is the value of the gifts
they have given (or of what has been taken from them). Let us generalize: the value
of individuals and social groups comes from the recognition of the gifts they have actu-
ally given or they could potentially give and/or from the relation they maintain to some-
thing more primordial and sacred (donation (Ergebnis/Gegebenheit), grace (charisma)
and gratuity that explain why there is something rather than nothing).
Conclusion
We understand, therefore, that mutatis mutandis modern struggles for recognition are
contemporary manifestations of the struggles to give – the ‘agonistic’ gift for recognition
– as properly exhumed by Marcel Mauss (1950) in his study of archaic societies. We also
understand that history, sociology, and anthropology are closely related, because the past
informs the present, and the centre informs the periphery. And vice versa. The lesson for
sociology is that it must not only develop sociology experts, but also seek to become, as
quickly as possible, a cosmopolitan public sociology. Sociology has to become once
again a general social science, but this time without provincial blinders. To be faithful
to its heritage, it must reconnect organically with philosophy, history, ethnology and eco-
nomics and draw from it all the institutional consequences for the organization of edu-
cation and research.
To conclude, we can now characterize the contours of neo-classical sociology as we
have sought to develop it in this article. Like its illustrious forebears from Weimar and
Paris, neo-classical social theory fuses theory construction and diagnosis of the present
(Habermas, 1991). This fusion explains the continuity with other traditions of thought
(natural law, political economy, philosophy of history, moral and political philosophy),
for whom modernity itself has become a question; its interest in paradoxes, crises and
pathologies of social development, as well as in social movements and social change;
the unity of sociology and social theory in a general theory of society that gives a coher-
ent answer to the question of social action, order and change; the attempt to develop
sociology as a science of society that systematizes reflections on politics and economics,
law and culture, ethics and psychology and seeks a dialogue with moral, social and polit-
ical philosophy, as well as with the Studies; the attempt to outline a sociological theory
that is both systematic and historical and that throws light on the ontology of the present;
and, finally, the unity of theory and metatheory, not to mention the continuous philoso-
phical, theoretical and methodological self-reflection of all the proposals it puts forward.
Notes
1. We will return to these issues in the final section of the article where we will propose a rappro-
chement between neo-Hegelian theories of recognition and a neo-Maussian theory of the gift.
2. Both of the authors are sociologists by training (though Caillé also has a PhD in economics)
and social theorists by vocation. Our particular location within the discipline explains, in part,
why we privilege neo-classical sociology. Although we call for a transdisciplinary synthesis,
we are well aware that our arguments are mainly pitched to sociologists and that our article
would probably not be published in journals of anthropology, history, geography or economics,
though we hope that it will inspire our colleagues from neighbouring disciplines, and will spur
them to take on board our project and write similar articles for slightly different audiences.
3. Technically speaking, we understand by utilitarianism any theory that implicitly or explicitly
subscribes to the ‘axiomatic of interest’ (Caillé, 1986: 99–139). For a long view of the utili-
tarian tradition, from Socrates to Rawls, see Caillé et al. (2001); on the utilitarian tradition,
from Bentham to the Mills, see Halévy’s (1995) classical study of philosophical radicalism.
4. We coined the term neo-classical sociology, but we did not invent it (see Eyal et al., 2003).
Whereas their neo-classical sociology is post-Marxist and neo-Weberian, ours is post-
Marxist and neo-Maussian. Although we welcome the invitation of Eyal and Co. to return
to classical sociology to think through the challenge of a ‘world without socialism’ ironically,
we fail to see that attractions of irony.
5. For a first exploration of the possibility of a general theory of society, see Revue du MAUSS
(2004b), partially translated in European Journal of Social Theory (2007, 10, 2).
6. The Anti-Utilitarian Movement in the Social Sciences was founded by one of the authors and
gathers anthropologists, sociologists, political scientists, philosophers and heterodox econo-
mists who have a common interest in reciprocity, who feel inspired by Mauss’s seminal essay
on the gift and who publish in the Revue du MAUSS. Alain Caillé, the founder of the MAUSS
and director of its journal, is also the main theorist of the gift-paradigm. Programmatic and
synthetic statements can be found in Caillé, 2000, 2009 and 2015.
7. Let us take an example to make the argument clear: Marxism is unthinkable without
Hegel’s objective idealism. In Marx, dialectics (metatheory) undergirds historical material-
ism (social theory), which informs the theory of the class struggle under capitalism (socio-
logical theory), which orients research on the situation of the working class in Lancashire.
In our case, anti-utilitarianism is our philosophical platform (metatheory) on which we
build the gift paradigm (social theory), which informs our analysis of the role of associa-
tions in contemporary societies (sociological theory). Our argument is that if we can agree
on anti-utilitarianism, we can then work towards a loose integration of social theories (the
gift, care, recognition, etc.) and propose a theoretically informed analysis and diagnosis of
the present. To keep our options open, we develop our position at a higher and therefore
more inclusive level of abstraction.
8. Through a Heideggerian spin, which unfortunately only works in French, we can transform
recognition (reconnaissance) into natality (co-naissance), natality into gratitude (reconnais-
sance), gratitude into rebirth (re-naissance) with, through and thanks to the other’s love
(re-co-naissance: being born again with the other).
9. For an exploration of the ethics of care and its relation to the gift paradigm, see Revue du
MAUSS (2008b).
10. As a specialized journal that attends to a general public, the Revue du MAUSS is entirely dedi-
cated to the investigation and discussion of the gift in all its facets and in all disciples. While each
issue focuses on a particular theme or aspect related to the gift, some special issues (1993, no. 1;
1996, no. 8; 2010, no. 36) have been entirely devoted to Mauss’s anthropology of the gift.
11. In France, the debate over recognition theory has not been limited to disciples of Honneth
(Renault, Voirol, Haber). It has received a major impetus from the MAUSS. See Revue du
MAUSS (2004a); Caillé (2007); and Caillé and Lazzeri (2009). The contributions in Caillé
(2007) deserve a special mention. The debate is not restricted to conceptual issues, but
includes empirical research by some of France’s major sociologists (Dubet, Thévenot,
Dejours, Heinich).
References
Alexander J C (1982–1983) Theoretical Logic in Sociology, 4 vols. Berkeley: University of
California Press.
Alexander J C and Seidman S, (eds) (2001) The New Social Theory Reader: Contemporary
Debates. London: Routledge.
Archer M. and Tritter J. (eds) (2000) Rational Choice Theory: Resisting Colonisation. London:
Routledge.
Berthelot J (2000) Sociologie et ontologie. In Livet P. and Ogien R. (eds) L’enqueˆte ontologique.
Du mode d’existence des objets sociaux. Paris: EHESS (Raisons pratiques, no. 11).
Caillé A (1986) Splendeurs et mise`res des sciences sociales. Genève: Droz.
Caillé A (2000) Anthropologie du don. Le tiers paradigme. Paris: Desclée de Brouwer.
Caillé A (ed.) (2007) La queˆte de reconnaissance, nouveau phe´nome`ne social total. Paris: La Découverte.
Caillé A (2009) The´orie anti-utilitariste du don. Fragments d’une sociologie ge´ne´rale. Paris: La
Découverte.
Caillé A (2014) Anti-utilitarisme et paradigme du don. Pour quoi? Lormont: Le bord de l’eau.
Caillé A (2015) La sociologie malgre´ tout. Autres fragments d’une sociologie ge´ne´rale. Paris:
Presses Universitaires de Paris-Ouest-Nanterre-La Défense.
Caillé A and Lazzeri C (eds) (2009) La reconnaissance aujourd’hui. Paris: CNRS.
Caillé A, Lazzeri C, and Senellart M (eds) (2001) Histoire raisonne´e de la philosophie morale et
politique. Le Bonheur et l’utile. Paris: La Découverte.
Chanial P (2011) La sociologie comme philosophie politique et reciproquement. Paris: La Decouverte.
Comte A (1949) Cours de philosophie positive (Premie`re et deuxie`me leçons). Paris: Garnier.
Cusset F (2005) French Theory: Foucault, Derrida, Deleuze et cie – et les mutations de la vie intel-
lectuelle aux Etats-Unis. Paris: La Découverte.
Durkheim E (1986) De la division du travail social. Paris: PUF.
Eyal G, Szelenyi I and Townsley E (2003) On irony: an invitation to classical sociology, Thesis
Eleven, 73: 5–41.
Fischbach F (2009) Manifeste pour une philosophie sociale. Paris: La Découverte.
Fraser N and Honneth A (2003) Redistribution or Recognition? A Political-Philosophical
Exchange. London: Verso.
Guéguen H and Malochet G (2012) Les the´ories de la reconnaissance. Paris: La Découverte.
Habermas J (1981) Theorie des kommunikativen Handelns, 2 vols. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.
Habermas J (1991) Soziologie in der Weimarer Republik. In: Texte und Kontexte. Frankfurt am
Main: Suhrkamp, pp. 184–204.
Author biographies
Alain Caillé is professor emeritus of the Université Paris-Nanterre. He is the founder of the
Mouvement anti-utilitariste dans les sciences sociales (MAUSS) and chief-editor of the Revue
du MAUSS. His work on the sociology of the gift is very well known in France. His most recent
books are Anti-utilitarisme et paradigme du don. Pour quoi? (2014); La Re´volution du don, le
management repense´ (2014) and La Sociologie malgre´ tout. Autres fragments d’une sociologie
ge´ne´rale. (2015).
Frédéric Vandenberghe is Professor of Sociology at the State University of Rio de Janeiro in Bra-
zil. He has published widely in the field of social theory. His most recent books are What’s Critical
about Critical Realism? Essays in Reconstructive Social Theory (2014) and (with Jean-François
Véran and Alain Caillé) Comentários sobre a sociedade convivial (2015).