Elements of Spacetime Geometry: Hands-On Exercise: Manifolds and Coordinate Patches
Elements of Spacetime Geometry: Hands-On Exercise: Manifolds and Coordinate Patches
Elements of Spacetime Geometry: Hands-On Exercise: Manifolds and Coordinate Patches
55
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Columbia University Libraries, on 21 Aug 2018 at 13:10:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511755811.004
56 Elements of spacetime geometry
one another. According to everything that we’ve learned about the propagation of
light, space and time must transform into one another, and so rather than existing
in space that evolves in time, with space and time distinct phenomena, we exist
in spacetime, with space and time mixing with one another, time able to turn into
space and space able to turn into time through the Lorentz transformation, which
in two spacetime dimensions looks like
τ̃ = γ τ − γβx
x̃ = −γβτ + γ x. (3.1)
It’s more than just a cliché to say that this relativity of the phenomena of space
and time has enormous implications. In this chapter, however, we will ignore the
enormous implications and delve into the nuts and bolts of spacetime, to look into
spacetime geometry from the dry exacting perspective of mathematics, to see what
makes spacetime tick, so to speak.
Coordinates in space
Before we get to spacetime, let’s first clarify what we mean by space. Let’s start
from the abstract concept of a manifold.
To make a manifold M, we start with a well-behaved set of points, that is, a set
of points fulfilling two requirements regarding how the points in M can be divided
into open subsets or neighborhoods. First, near any point p in M, we should be
able to find some open subset of points U ( p) that is near p. Second, any two points
p and q in M can be put into different open subsets U ( p) and U (q) of M that
don’t intersect.
For any point p in M, points in an open neighborhood U ( p) near p should
be describable by D real numbers (x 1 , x 2 , . . . , x D ) representing the values of D
coordinates in a Euclidean space E D in D dimensions. These coordinates define a
distance lAB between any two points pA and pB given by
lAB = (xA1 − xB1 )2 + (xA2 − xB2 )2 + · · · + (xAD − xBD )2 (3.2)
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Columbia University Libraries, on 21 Aug 2018 at 13:10:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511755811.004
Space and spacetime 57
U(q)
U(p)
Fig. 3.1. A manifold M with two locally Euclidean coordinate patches U ( p) and
U (q). The intersection U ( p) ∩ U (q) is the shaded area. The local coordinates in
the two neighborhoods are related by a coordinate transformation.
the same as (3.2) but with x → w. In the intersection U ( p) ∩ U (q) of these two
neighborhoods, points can be described by either local coordinate system, with
a smooth coordinate transformation relating the two coordinate systems given by
transition functions
wi = wi (x 1 , . . . , x D ), i = 1, . . . , D. (3.3)
This mapping from one set of local coordinates to another is one-to-one if the
Jacobian
∂wi
J = det M, M ij = (3.4)
∂x j
is everywhere nonzero. If M can be covered by a union of such coordinates
patches, with the overlapping local patches of E D related to one another as above,
then M is a manifold of dimension D.1
The surface of the LSO in the exercise above is an example of a manifold, if we
idealize it so that it is smooth at all distances scales, even the subatomic scale. Any
point p on the surface of the LSO can serve as the origin of a local E2 coordinate
patch, let’s call it U ( p), with local coordinates (x, y) measured on the axes you
made with the two rulers, with their origins located at p. Any nearby point P on the
LSO could be described in terms of coordinates (x P , y P ) on the two axes located
at p. But if P is too far from p, the curvature of the LSO becomes important, and
the location of P can’t be described by coordinates on the axes located at p.
The way out of this problem is to define another local coordinate patch U (q) at
some other point q that is close to P, and then define transition functions that tell us
1 The name differentiable manifold is also used. The transition functions define a differentiable structure on the
manifold.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Columbia University Libraries, on 21 Aug 2018 at 13:10:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511755811.004
58 Elements of spacetime geometry
how the two coordinate patches at p and q are related in the regions U ( p) ∩ U (q)
on the LSO where they overlap. We can cover the whole LSO with coordinate
patches and transition functions, and then have a way to find the coordinates of
any point on the LSO.
On the LSO, the local set of axes twists and turns when it is moved from point
to point on the LSO, and there isn’t a simple way to patch them together and still
have a rectangular coordinate system with one fixed set of axes. This is because
the surface of the LSO is a curved surface. In differential geometry, the curvature
can be computed from the way the local Euclidean coordinate system twists and
turns from one patch to another. When there is no curvature, so that the local
Euclidean coordinate system doesn’t twist or turn from one patch to another, the
whole manifold can be covered globally by a single Euclidean coordinate patch,
and then we say that this manifold is flat.2
On the top of a desk or table, any point P can be described in terms of coordi-
nates along the axes located at some point p, if we imagine the axes extended in
either direction as far as necessary. We really only need one coordinate patch of
E2 to specify the coordinates of any point q on the desk. This is because the desk
is flat.
A flat space can be covered by Euclidean coordinates, but it’s still flat when
described in terms of any other coordinates. For example, flat space in three di-
mensions can be described in rectangular coordinates (x, y, z), or in spherical co-
ordinates (r, θ, φ), related by the coordinate transformation
x = r sin θ cos φ
y = r sin θ sin φ
z = r cos θ, (3.5)
with 0 ≤ θ ≤ π and 0 ≤ φ < 2π . In these coordinates, the metric
dl 2 = d x 2 + dy 2 + dz 2 (3.6)
becomes
2 Note that this definition of flatness assumes that the manifold is infinite, or is finite with a boundary. There
are flat manifolds that cannot be covered globally by one set of Euclidean coordinates because of topological
issues such as periodic boundary conditions. A torus T D in D dimensions is one such case.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Columbia University Libraries, on 21 Aug 2018 at 13:10:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511755811.004
Space and spacetime 59
Coordinates in spacetime
What happens if we add a time dimension to the flat space described above, and
get flat spacetime? All of the definitions above can be recycled if we just substitute
Minkowski space Md for Euclidean space E D . The local coordinate patches have d
spacetime coordinates (x 0 , x 1 , x 2 , . . . , x D ), where x 0 ≡ τ = ct, and any two
points pA and pB in the local neighborhood U ( p) are separated by the Minkowski
interval sAB , given by
sAB
2
= −(τA − τB )2 + (xA1 − xB1 )2 + · · · + (xAD − xBD )2 . (3.8)
two events, because it can be negative. But if it’s not the distance between events,
then what does this interval signify? It tells us about the causal structure of the
spacetime – which event can be the cause of another event, and which cannot.
Normally, without taking special relativity into account, we would just use time
to decide the question of causality, assuming that the time between two events is
absolute and the same for all observers. If event E A occurs at time tA and event E B
occurs at time tB , if tA < tB , then event E A could be the cause of, or have influence
on, event E B , but if tB < tA , then the causal relationship is reversed. But this view
doesn’t take into account the speed of light, which is finite and the same for all
observers. When we take into account the speed of light, we lose absolute time
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Columbia University Libraries, on 21 Aug 2018 at 13:10:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511755811.004
60 Elements of spacetime geometry
τ Timelike future
E5 E2
Spacelike
E4
Spacelike E0 Null
x
E3
E1
Timelike past
Fig. 3.2. The sign of s 2 divides the spacetime around any event E 0 into regions
of timelike, null and spacelike separation. Events E 3 and E 4 take place on the
null light cone L of E 0 , shown above by dashed lines. Event E 2 takes place at a
timelike interval to the future of E 0 , and event E 1 takes place at a timelike interval
to the past of E 0 . Event E 5 happens at a spacelike interval from E 0 , too soon for
light to travel from E 0 to the location where E 5 happens. Event E 0 can only cause
or influence events to the future of E 0 with a timelike or null separation from E 0 .
The principle of causality is encoded in the geometry of spacetime in a Lorentz
invariant manner.
and learn that time is relative, that two inertial observers will not agree when two
events occur at the same time.
So what happens to causality when the passage of time is relative? The answer
is encoded into the spacetime geometry by the sign of the Minkowski interval,
which is unchanged by a Lorentz transformation, and hence the same for all iner-
tial observers. There are three possibilities for the sign of sAB2 , and these three
possibilities divide up the spacetime around each point into the three Lorentz in-
variant regions described below:
(i) sAB2 > 0: Events E and E are separated by a spacelike interval. There exists a
A B
Lorentz boost at some velocity β to a frame where events E A and E B happen at the
same time, but there exists no Lorentz transformation to a frame where the two events
happen at the same place.
(ii) sAB2 = 0: Events E and E are separated by a lightlike or null interval. This is the
A B
path a beam of light or a massless particle would take to get from event E A to event
E B . There exists no Lorentz transformation at any velocity β to a frame where events
E A and E B happen at the same time or the same place.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Columbia University Libraries, on 21 Aug 2018 at 13:10:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511755811.004
Space and spacetime 61
τ τ% x%
x
E0
Fig. 3.3. In this spacetime diagram, the coordinates (τ̃ , x̃) are related to the coor-
dinates (τ, x) by a Lorentz boost. The dashed lines represent curves of constant
s 2 from event E 0 = (τ0 , x0 ). These curves are hyperbolas, which degenerate to
straight lines through the origin in the limit s 2 → 0. All of the dashed lines on
this diagram represent Lorentz invariant submanifolds of Minkowski spacetime.
The invariant submanifold with s 2 = 0 is the light cone of event E 0 .
(iii) sAB2 < 0: Events E and E are separated by a timelike interval. There exists a
A B
Lorentz transformation at some velocity β to a frame where events E A and E B happen
at the same place, but there exists no Lorentz transformation to a frame where the two
events happen at the same time.
The set of spacetime events that satisfy s 2 = 0 divides the timelike region of the
spacetime of any event E 0 from the spacelike region of that event. In d spacetime
dimensions, this set forms a submanifold of Md whose coordinates satisfy the
condition
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Columbia University Libraries, on 21 Aug 2018 at 13:10:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511755811.004
62 Elements of spacetime geometry
τ τ%
τ1 E1
τ%0 = τ%1
E0 τ0
x%
x
Fig. 3.4. Event E 1 is separated by a spacelike interval from event E 0 , whose light
cone L is shown by the dashed lines. In the S frame with coordinates (τ, x), events
E 0 and E 1 occur at different times, with τ0 < τ1 . In the S̃ frame, with coordinates
(τ̃ , x̃) related to (τ, x) by a Lorentz boost at some velocity β = β0 , events E 0
and E 1 occur at the same time τ̃0 = τ̃1 . If β > β0 , then E 1 happens before E 0 .
The time ordering of two events separated by a spacelike interval depends on the
motion of the observer.
is invariant under a Lorentz transformation. We will show below that the light cone
of an event serves as a boundary between the past and future of that event that is
the same for all inertial observers.
The set of events in Md with a timelike separation from an event E 0 satisfy the
condition
λ2 = (τ − τ0 )2 − |
x − x0 |2 , (3.10)
(τ − τ0 )2 = λ2 + |
x − x0 |2 (3.11)
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Columbia University Libraries, on 21 Aug 2018 at 13:10:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511755811.004
Space and spacetime 63
ρ 2 = |
x − x0 |2 − (τ − τ0 )2 , (3.12)
where ρ 2 > 0. As with λ in the timelike region, every value of ρ defines a different
Lorentz-invariant submanifold of Md in the spacelike region of E 0 . For d = 2, we
get submanifolds of M2 that are the hyperbolas that cross the x axis at x = ρ,
shown as dashed lines in the spacelike regions of Figure 3.3.
In the spacelike region of E 0 , τ − τ0 can pass through zero for x = x0 , for any
value of ρ = 0. This is opposite from the situation in the timelike region. In the
spacelike region of E 0 , it makes no sense to say whether any event is to the future
or the past of event E 0 . There is always a Lorentz boost from a frame S where
τ > τ0 to some other frame S̃ where τ̃ ≤ τ̃0 , and vice versa.
Notice that for any event in the spacelike region of E 0 , | x − x0 |2 ≥ ρ 2 , with
equality only for τ = τ0 . This means that |ρ| measures the proper distance between
the event and E 0 . It also means that it is not possible in the spacelike region of E 0
to find a Lorentz boost to a frame where | x − x0 |2 vanishes. In the timelike region
of E 0 , it is always possible to find a frame where a given event in the region takes
place at x0 . The spacelike and timelike regions of an event are in a sense dual to one
another. Differences in location can be transformed away in the timelike region of
an event, and differences in time can be transformed away in the spacelike region
of an event.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Columbia University Libraries, on 21 Aug 2018 at 13:10:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511755811.004
64 Elements of spacetime geometry
τ̃ = γ τ − γβx 1
x̃ 1 = −γβτ + γ x 1
x̃ i = x i , 2 ≤ i ≤ D. (3.13)
When drawn in the (τ, x 1 ) plane, the τ̃ axis makes an angle of φ = π/2 −
2 tan−1 β with the x̃ 1 axis, so the angle between the axes goes to zero for β → 1.
The Lorentz boost squeezes the time and space coordinate axes into one another,
as shown in Figure 3.3. That’s not how a rigid body transforms. The Lorentz
boost (3.13) could be said to shear the spacetime in the (τ, x 1 ) plane, which tells
us that spacetime behaves more like an elastic medium than a rigid one.
There is a thought experiment that exemplifies this difference, in a situation that
appears paradoxical according to the reasoning that we learn in rigid time and
space, but which is not paradoxical at all once we understand special relativity.
This experiment features a pole being moved through a barn. The pole and the
barn both have proper length L 0 . The pole is being carried on a rocket moving at
velocity β through the barn, which has doors on the front and rear. Before the pole
enters the barn, the front door is open but the rear door is closed. After the rear end
of the pole passes the front door, the front door closes. When the front end of the
pole is about to hit the rear door, the rear door opens.
According to observers in the rest frame S of the barn, the pole is Lorentz-
contracted
from its proper length L 0 to length L P = L 0 /γ , where γ =
1/ 1 − β as usual. The distance between the two barn doors is L B = L 0 . Since
2
L P < L B , the pole easily fits inside the barn with both doors closed.
When we look at this same sequence of events in the rest frame S̃ of the pole,
however, a problem arises. According to observers in the pole frame, the pole
and the rocket are at rest, and the barn comes rushing at them with velocity −β.
The barn is Lorentz-contracted to length L̃ B = L 0 /γ , while the pole has length
L̃ P = L 0 . According to observers in this frame, L̃ P > L̃ B , in other words,
the pole is longer than the barn, so the pole cannot possibly fit inside the barn
with both doors closed.
This appears to violate both common sense and the symmetry that is supposed
to be inherent in the principle of relativity. There shouldn’t be one frame where the
pole can be trapped inside the barn, and another frame where it crashes through
the doors.
The key to this mystery is that it is spacetime, not space or time individually,
that does the stretching and contracting. The length of each object is measured in
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Columbia University Libraries, on 21 Aug 2018 at 13:10:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511755811.004
Space and spacetime 65
τ E4 τ%
x%
E3
E2
E1 x
pole
barn
Fig. 3.5. The pole moving through the barn, plotted in coordinates (τ, x) in the
rest frame of the barn.
the rest frame of the object, by comparing both ends of the object at the same time.
But in special relativity, simultaneity is relative, and time ordering can be relative,
if there is a spacelike separation between two events.
The sequence of events under examination is shown in Figure 3.5 in the rest
frame of the barn, and in Figure 3.6 in the rest frame of the pole and rocket. In
Figure 3.5, the coordinate axes (τ, x) represent the rest frame of the barn, and the
coordinate axes (τ̃ , x̃) represent the rest frame of the pole, moving at velocity β in
the +x direction. The sequence of events according to the time τ in the barn rest
frame is:
E1: The front end of the pole enters through the front door of the barn.
E2: The rear end of the pole enters through the front door of the barn.
E3: The front end of the pole leaves through the rear door of the barn.
E4: The rear end of the pole leaves through the rear door of the barn.
Between times τ2 and τ3 , the pole, of length L 0 /γ , is completely inside the barn,
which in this frame has length L 0 .
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Columbia University Libraries, on 21 Aug 2018 at 13:10:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511755811.004
66 Elements of spacetime geometry
τ E4 τ%
x
E2
E3
x% E1
pole barn
Fig. 3.6. The pole moving through the barn, plotted in coordinates (τ̃ , x̃) in the
rest frame of the pole.
In Figure 3.6, the coordinate axes (τ̃ , x̃) represent the rest frame of the pole, and
the coordinate axes (τ, x) represent the rest frame of the barn, moving at velocity
−β in the +x direction. The sequence of events according to the time τ̃ in the pole
rest frame is:
E1: The front door of the barn passes the front end of the pole.
E3: The rear door of the barn passes the front end of the pole.
E2: The front door of the barn passes the rear end of the pole.
E4: The rear door of the barn passes the rear end of the pole.
In the pole frame, the sequence of events E 2 and E 3 is the opposite from what
they were in the barn frame. This is possible because these two events – the rear
end of the pole entering the front door of the barn, and the front end of the pole
leaving the rear end of the barn – occur at a spacelike separation. (Proof of this
fact will be left to the reader as an exercise.)
The pole can’t be contained within the barn between times τ̃2 and τ̃3 , because
τ̃2 > τ̃3 . According to observers for whom the pole is at rest and the barn is mov-
ing, the front end of the pole is already out of the rear door of the barn before the
rear end of the pole has entered through the front door of the barn. According to
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Columbia University Libraries, on 21 Aug 2018 at 13:10:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511755811.004
Vectors on a manifold 67
the sequence of events as measured according to clocks in the rest frame of the
pole, the pole is never completely contained within the barn at any time. And that
is perfectly consistent with the pole, with length L 0 , being longer than the barn,
which in this frame has length L 0 /γ .
If you feel reassured by this, then don’t be! How do we normally define any
object that exists in nature, such as a pole or a barn? We normally define an object
to exist in space at distinct moments in time. A pole is supposed to have extent in
space, not extent in time. But in special relativity, objects have extent in space and
time. That’s what spacetime means. The measurement of space is connected to the
measurement of time. An object exists in spacetime, and the measurement of its
length depends on a measurement of both space and time.
In Figures 3.5 and 3.6, the pole and barn are represented by the areas they sweep
out as they move in time. These areas are called the world sheets of the pole and
barn, for the one-dimensional representation of the pole and barn we’re using here.
In real life, the pole and barn sweep out world volumes in spacetime.
The pole at any moment in time is represented on the diagram by a slice of the
world sheet of the pole at that time. But the time slices will be at different angles,
depending on the angle of the time axis of the observer relative to the time axis in
the rest frame of the pole. A slice of the pole world sheet at some time τ in the
rest frame of the pole reveals a pole that has length L 0 . A slice of the world sheet
of the pole at some time τ̃ in the barn rest frame reveals a pole that has length
L 0 /γ .
So what do we mean by a rigid object such as a pole or a barn? Is an object that
we see in space just a particular time slice of the world volume of that object in
spacetime? Is there really such a thing as a rigid object in relativity at all? We will
ponder this question again in later chapters.
The basis vectors (êx , ê y , êz ) in the set are mutually orthogonal and have unit mag-
nitude, everywhere in space, for all values of the parameter t. If we have N such
objects, each with mass m i and position vector xi (t), then we can talk about the
collective motion of the whole ensemble by looking at the trajectory of the center
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Columbia University Libraries, on 21 Aug 2018 at 13:10:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511755811.004
68 Elements of spacetime geometry
In introductory physics it is taken for granted that all of the above mathematical
operations make sense. We can define vectors by the displacements in a coordinate
basis, the basis vectors are the same everywhere, we can add and subtract vectors,
multiply them by numbers, and check whether they are orthogonal, anywhere in
this space with no problem. In other words, we assume that we are living in a
vector space where all of these operations can be defined.
Newtonian physics makes sense because the physical space we are employing as
a model for nature has the structure of a vector space, namely E3 , Euclidean space
in three dimensions. On a general manifold, a vector space can only be defined at
each point in the manifold. In flat space and spacetime, it’s possible to get away
with ignoring this fact, but in this section, we will not ignore it, and we will show
how vectors in spacetime are properly defined on a general manifold, before we
make use of the convenient fact that the manifold we’re dealing with is flat.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Columbia University Libraries, on 21 Aug 2018 at 13:10:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511755811.004
Vectors on a manifold 69
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Columbia University Libraries, on 21 Aug 2018 at 13:10:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511755811.004
70 Elements of spacetime geometry
used with spherical coordinates (r, θ, φ) in E3 . Commuting the first two of these,
we get
∂ 1 ∂f 1 ∂ ∂f 1 ∂f
− =− 2 = 0. (3.24)
∂r r ∂θ r ∂θ ∂r r ∂θ
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Columbia University Libraries, on 21 Aug 2018 at 13:10:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511755811.004
Vectors on a manifold 71
The basis vectors (3.23) do not commute, so they form what is called a non-
coordinate basis for T p (E3 ).
In flat spacetime in four dimensions, with coordinates (τ, x, y, z), the coordi-
nate basis for T p (M4 ) is (∂τ , ∂x , ∂ y , ∂z ). But it’s not the act of adding an extra
coordinate and calling it time that makes spacetime different from space. The dif-
ference between geometry in space and in spacetime has to do with the metric. To
understand the metric, we also need to look at the other geometrical objects that
can be defined on a manifold in addition to vectors.
ω̄ = ωi d x i . (3.27)
Combining (3.27) with (3.26) gives us the inner product of a vector v = v i ∂i and
a form ω̄ in terms of their components
v, ω̄
= v i ωi . (3.28)
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Columbia University Libraries, on 21 Aug 2018 at 13:10:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511755811.004
72 Elements of spacetime geometry
We want a geometrical object that maps two vectors in T p (M) into a real num-
ber. Such an object is called the metric tensor. A tensor T is a generalization of a
vector that we will discuss in greater detail later. The metric tensor g takes two vec-
tors as arguments, and produces a real number. So it is a map from two copies of
the tangent space g : T p (M) ⊗ T p (M)
→ R. In a coordinate basis, using (3.26)
and (3.27) we can write
g = gi j d x i ⊗ d x j , (3.29)
where here d x i means the one form and not the infinitesimal line element. The
components of the metric tensor are
∂ ∂
gi j = g , . (3.30)
∂xi ∂x j
The metric product of two vectors u and v can then be written
g(u, v) = gi j u i v j . (3.31)
It is common to call the metric product the inner product. We will call it the
scalar product, because its value is a scalar quantity. The scalar product is related
to the inner product because the metric gives us a way to associate components of
vectors in the tangent space with components of forms in the cotangent space. If
we define the operation of lowering an index on a component as
u i = gi j u j , (3.32)
then the component u i with the lowered index could be thought of as a component
of a form in the cotangent space. The scalar product of two vectors can then be
written in terms of components as
g(u, v) = gi j u i v j = u i v i . (3.33)
Note that this is identical to the result we get from the inner product
v, ω̄u
(3.34)
ω̄u = u i d x i . (3.35)
making ω̄u the one form associated with the vector u through the metric g.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Columbia University Libraries, on 21 Aug 2018 at 13:10:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511755811.004
Vectors on a manifold 73
The operation (3.32) is invertible using the inverse metric, which in a coordinate
basis has components that satisfy the equation
g i j g jk = δki . (3.37)
So the metric operating on vectors in the tangent space also gives the line element
on the manifold.
x̃ i = x̃ i (x 1 , x 2 , . . . , x D ). (3.41)
∂ x̃ i j
ṽ i = v , (3.42)
∂x j
then v i is a vector.
In the modern view, the vector v, expanded in a coordinate basis as
∂
v = vi , (3.43)
∂xi
is a fundamental geometrical object that remains unchanged by a change in
coordinates. The components {v i } of the vector change according to (3.42), and
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Columbia University Libraries, on 21 Aug 2018 at 13:10:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511755811.004
74 Elements of spacetime geometry
∂x j
ω̃i = ωj, (3.47)
∂ x̃ i
and the object ω̄ stays the same.
The action of a coordinate transformation on the components of the metric ten-
sor can be deduced from
g̃i j d x̃ i ⊗ d x̃ j = gi j d x i ⊗ d x j
∂xi ∂x j
= gi j k l d x̃ k ⊗ d x̃ l . (3.48)
∂ x̃ ∂ x̃
The scalar product of two vectors is a coordinate invariant object, because the
coordinate transformation of the components of the metric cancel the transforma-
tion of the components of the two vectors, as
i
∂ xk ∂ xl ∂ x̃ ∂ x̃ j m n
ṽ2 = g̃i j ṽ i ṽ j = gkl v v
∂ x̃ i ∂ x̃ j ∂xm ∂xn
k
∂ x ∂ x̃ i ∂ x l ∂ x̃ j
= gkl v m v n
∂ x̃ i ∂ x m ∂ x̃ j ∂ x n
= δm δn gkl v m v n = gkl v k vl = v2 .
k l
(3.49)
scalars, because what they yield is just a real number, which is the same when
evaluated in any coordinate system.
Some classes of coordinate transformations leave the metric invariant because
they represent symmetries of the spacetime. For example, Euclidean space in any
dimension is the same in all directions, at every point. It is isotropic (same in all
directions around some point) and homogeneous (the same at every point in some
given direction). Isotropy means the Euclidean metric is invariant under rotations
of the coordinate system. In D = 2 this takes the form
x̃ = cos θ x − sin θ y
ỹ = − sin θ x + cos θ y, (3.50)
where θ is a constant. Homogeneity means the Euclidean metric is invariant under
translations of the coordinates by constants
x̃ i = x i + ci . (3.51)
In both cases, the line element is the same in the new coordinates as it is in the old
coordinates
d x̃ 2 + d ỹ 2 = d x 2 + dy 2 , (3.52)
so the metric components in this basis are the same, g̃i j = gi j .
A coordinate transformation that leaves the metric unchanged is called an isom-
etry. Isometries in spacetime give rise to conserved quantities in physics, as we
shall see later in this book.
L 0̃0 = γ
L i0̃ = −γβ i
L ĩ0 = −γβ i
βi β j
L ĩj = (γ − 1) + δi j , (3.54)
β2
ṽ µ = L µ̃ ν
ν v . (3.55)
The metric tensor g of flat spacetime has coordinate basis components gµν =
ηµν , where
η00 = −1
η0i = ηi0 = 0
ηi j = δi j . (3.56)
The metric serves as a map between the tangent space T p (Md ) and the cotan-
gent space T p∗ (Md ). In a coordinate basis this means index raising and lowering
via
vµ = ηµν v ν
ωµ = ηµν ων . (3.57)
D
µ ν
u · v = ηµν v u = −v u + 0 0
vi u i . (3.58)
i =1
D
D
ηµν v µ u ν = −v 0 u 0 + v i u i = −ṽ 0 ũ 0 + ṽ i ũ i . (3.59)
i =1 i =1
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Columbia University Libraries, on 21 Aug 2018 at 13:10:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511755811.004
Vectors in spacetime 77
The minus sign in the metric presents us with three options for the metric prod-
uct of a vector with itself:
D < 0 timelike
µ ν
v = ηµν v v = −(v ) +
2 0 2
(v )
i 2
= 0 null (3.60)
i =1 > 0 spacelike.
Since v2 is a scalar and hence the same for all observers, a timelike vector is
timelike, a null vector is null, and a spacelike vector is spacelike, in all coordinate
systems and in all inertial frames.
Timelike vectors
A rotation in space of the Euclidean coordinate axes can change the direction in
space in which a vector points, so that a vector pointing in the +x direction be-
comes a vector pointing in the −x direction. But a Lorentz transformation in space-
time cannot change the direction in time in which a timelike vector points, so that
a vector pointing into the future becomes a vector pointing into the past.
Let’s assume that the direction of increasing coordinate τ is the future. With that
convention, a timelike vector
∂ ∂
v = v0 + vi i , v2 < 0 (3.61)
∂τ ∂x
we will call future-pointing if v 0 > 0, and past-pointing if v 0 < 0. A future-
pointing timelike vector cannot be transformed by a continuous Lorentz transfor-
mation into a past-pointing timelike vector. Consider the action of a Lorentz boost
with spatial velocity β of the time component of v
ṽ 0 = L 0̃0 v 0 + L i0̃ v i
= γ v 0 − γ δi j β i v j
= γ v 0 − γ β · v. (3.62)
v 0 ≤ β · v, (3.63)
where the last term comes from the Schwarz inequality in flat space
(
v · u)2 ≤ (
v · v) (
u · u). (3.65)
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Columbia University Libraries, on 21 Aug 2018 at 13:10:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511755811.004
78 Elements of spacetime geometry
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Columbia University Libraries, on 21 Aug 2018 at 13:10:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511755811.004
Vectors in spacetime 79
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Columbia University Libraries, on 21 Aug 2018 at 13:10:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511755811.004
80 Elements of spacetime geometry
If the curve C (λ) is a path of a particle or object in spacetime, then the tangent
vector must represent a spacetime generalization of velocity. Normally in Newto-
nian physics the momentum is p = m v. If we generalize this to flat spacetime in
d dimensions, then we should write
p = mu, (3.79)
p2 = ηµν p µ p µ = −( p 0 )2 + | p |2 = −m 2 . (3.80)
Technically speaking, momentum is a one form, and properly lives in the cotangent
space T p∗ (Md ). However, because the spacetime metric provides an isomorphism
between T p (Md ) and T p∗ (Md ), it’s usually okay to treat momentum as a vector.
Note that we have absorbed the speed of light into the coordinate system by
using τ = ct as a time coordinate with units of length, so that we can write the
time–time component of the Minkowski metric as η00 = ητ τ = −1 rather than
η00 = ηtt = −c2 , with the inverse being η00 = ητ τ = −1 rather than η00 = ηtt =
−1/c2 . With this choice of coordinates, spacetime velocity is dimensionless, be-
cause the proper time λ comes in units of length as well. However, this convenient
choice for the metric components introduces an issue for the units of other physical
quantities, as we shall see below.
The time and space components of p are
p0 = γ m
p = γ m β. (3.81)
E = mc2 , (3.83)
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Columbia University Libraries, on 21 Aug 2018 at 13:10:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511755811.004
Vectors in spacetime 81
ũ 0 = L 0̃0 u 0 + L i0̃ u i
= γ u 0 − γ β · u
= γ γu (1 − β · βu ). (3.87)
Since ũ 0 = γ̃u , we see that the Lorentz boost rule for γu is
γ̃u = ũ 0 = γ γu (1 − β · βu )
(1 − β · βu )
= . (3.88)
1 − |βu | 1 − |β|
2 2
ũ i = L ĩ0 u 0 + L ĩj u j
β · u i
= u i − γβ i u 0 + (γ − 1) β. (3.89)
β2
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Columbia University Libraries, on 21 Aug 2018 at 13:10:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511755811.004
82 Elements of spacetime geometry
In this form it’s hard to see that this is a Lorentz boost. For simplicity let’s work in
d = 3 with β = β êx , so that β · u = βu x . We then get
β · u
ũ x = u x − γβu 0 + (γ − 1) β
β2
= γ u x − γβu 0 = γ γu ((βu )x − β)
ũ y = u y = γu (βu ) y , (3.90)
which is the usual formula for a Lorentz boost in one dimension (here in the
x direction). The components of the transformed velocity become
ũ x (βu )x − β
(β̃u )x = =
ũ 0 1 − β · βu
ũ y (βu ) y
(β̃u ) y = 0 = . (3.91)
ũ γ (1 − β · βu )
Notice that although the relative motion between frames S and S̃ is constrained
to the x direction, the object’s velocity in the y direction is changed by the trans-
formation. In Galilean relativity, the components of velocity orthogonal to the rel-
ative motion between the frames are not changed, but in special relativity they are.
This is necessary for the speed of light to be preserved by the Lorentz transfor-
mation. The equations in (3.91) tell us that in the limit β → 1, (β̃u )x → −1 and
(β̃u ) y → 0. The component in the y direction ought to vanish if we’re boosting the
x direction by the speed of light, and the Lorentz transformation guarantees that it
does.
Null vectors
The limit m → 0 of (3.84) gives a null momentum vector with time component
p 0 = E = ±| p |. Null vectors are traditionally labeled by letters from the middle
of the alphabet, so let’s call this null vector k. A massless object has null momen-
tum, and so travels at the speed of light. A null vector is tangent to the world line of
an object traveling at the speed of light. But that world line can only be a straight
line, as will be left for the reader to prove as an exercise. So a null vector is a very
constrained object, unlike a timelike or a spacelike vector.
A null vector k is orthogonal to itself, because k · k = 0. Suppose there is some
other null vector l orthogonal to k. If k · l = 0, then
|l| = k · l.
|k| (3.92)
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Columbia University Libraries, on 21 Aug 2018 at 13:10:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511755811.004
Tensors and forms 83
Spacelike vectors
Spacelike vectors are tangent to curves that are not the world lines of objects trav-
eling in time. A timelike vector points in a definite direction in time, past or future,
but a spacelike vector can point to the past or future depending on the Lorentz
frame of the observer. The time component of a spacelike vector v can be got-
ten rid of entirely by a Lorentz boost at some velocity β. To get rid of the time
component, we need to satisfy the equation
v 0 = β · v. (3.93)
Squaring this equation and applying the Schwarz inequality tells us that
(v 0 )2
2 < 1,
≤ |β| (3.94)
|
v |2
which can be satisfied if and only if v is a spacelike vector.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Columbia University Libraries, on 21 Aug 2018 at 13:10:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511755811.004
84 Elements of spacetime geometry
ω̄ = ᾱ ∧ β̄ ≡ ᾱ ⊗ β̄ − β̄ ⊗ ᾱ. (3.95)
ω̄ = αµ βν (d x µ ⊗ d x ν − d x ν ⊗ d x µ )
= α µ βν d x µ ∧ d x ν
1
= (αµ βν − αν βµ ) d x µ ∧ d x ν
2
1
= ωµν d x µ ∧ d x ν . (3.97)
2
The components of a two form are antisymmetric, ωµν = −ωνµ . Note that the
most general two form is not a product of two one forms, but any two form ω̄ can
be expanded in a coordinate basis as
1
ω̄ = ωµν d x µ ∧ d x ν , (3.98)
2
with ωµν = −ωνµ . A two form that you will become deeply acquainted with in
Chapter 5 is the electromagnetic field strength F̄, known in spacetime component
notation by Fµν . Electric and magnetic field vectors in T p (E3 ) do not give rise
to electric and magnetic field vectors in T p (M4 ). The electric and magnetic fields
are instead components of the two form field strength F̄. This will be discussed in
much greater detail in Chapter 5.
We can keep using the antisymmetric direct product on the coordinate basis one
forms {d x µ } until we run out of coordinates. If we take an antisymmetric product
of p basis forms, then we get the basis for a p form, also called a form of degree
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Columbia University Libraries, on 21 Aug 2018 at 13:10:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511755811.004
Tensors and forms 85
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Columbia University Libraries, on 21 Aug 2018 at 13:10:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511755811.004
86 Elements of spacetime geometry
L 00̃ = γ
L i = γβ i
0̃
0
L ĩ = γβ i
βi β j
L ij̃ = (γ − 1) + δi j , (3.108)
β2
as can be verified by matrix multiplication. The components ωµ1 µ2 ···µ p of a p form
ω̄ transform as
ν
ω̃µ1 µ2 ...µ p = L νµ˜11 L νµ˜22 . . . L µ˜pp ων1 ν2 ...ν p , (3.109)
where, as usual, all pairs of repeated upper and lower indices are to be summed
over all spacetime dimensions.
What is a tensor?
We can take as many copies as we want of the tangent space T p (M) and
the cotangent space T p∗ (M), take the direct product T p (M) ⊗ . . . ⊗ T p (M) ⊗
T p∗ (M) . . . ⊗ T p∗ (M), and use this as a space for defining the bases of geometrical
objects of the manifold M. Such objects are called tensors. If we take a direct
product of m copies of the tangent space T p (M) and n copies of the cotangent
space T p∗ (M), then we have a space for defining what is called a rank (m, n)
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Columbia University Libraries, on 21 Aug 2018 at 13:10:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511755811.004
Tensors and forms 87
tensor. A vector is a rank (1, 0) tensor and a one form is a rank (0, 1) tensor. A
scalar, that is, a number, can be considered to be a rank (0, 0) tensor.
A rank (m, n) tensor T can be expanded in a coordinate basis as
∂ ∂
T = Tνµ1 ···ν
1 ···µm
µ
⊗ · · · ⊗ µ ⊗ d x ν1 ⊗ · · · ⊗ d x νn . (3.110)
n
∂x 1 ∂x m
We learned previously that a one form ω̄ = ωµ d x µ ∈ T p∗ (M) can be thought of
as a map that operates on a vector v = v µ ∂µ ∈ T p (M) to produce a coordinate
invariant scalar v µ ωµ ∈ R. A rank (m, n) tensor T can be thought of as a map
(T p∗ (M))m ⊗ (T p (M))n
→ R, taking as arguments m one forms and n vectors to
produce a coordinate invariant scalar
T(ω̄1 , . . . , ω̄m , v1 , . . . , vn ) = Tνµ1 ...ν
1 ...µm ω
n
ν1 νn
µ1 . . . ωµm v . . . v . (3.111)
When there is a metric tensor defined on the manifold, there is an isomorphism
between the tangent space and the cotangent space at each point, which is ex-
pressed in a coordinate basis through the operation of index raising and lower-
ing. This operation extends naturally from vectors and forms to tensors of any
rank. The metric tensor used in this way can turn a rank (m, n) tensor into a rank
(m − 1, n + 1) tensor by lowering one of the lower indices. For example,
T µν κ = gκλ T µνλ . (3.112)
The inverse metric operates on a rank (m, n) tensor to produce a rank (m + 1,
n − 1) tensor by raising an index, for example
T µνκ = g κλ T µν λ . (3.113)
The metric tensor operates on two vectors to give a coordinate invariant scalar,
so it is a map T p (M) ⊗ T p (M)
→ R. Therefore the metric tensor can operate on
a rank (m, n) tensor to produce a rank (m − 2, n) tensor, for example
T κ = gµν T µνκ . (3.114)
The inverse metric yields a rank (m, n − 2) tensor, for example
T κ = g µν T κ µν . (3.115)
The study of tensors in full generality is a big subject. In physics we are usually
only concerned with certain types of tensors. In spacetime physics, we’re con-
cerned with the behavior under Lorentz transformations. A general tensor can be
reduced into parts, each of which transforms into itself under a Lorentz transfor-
mation. When we can no longer reduce the tensor any further, we say that the
individual parts are irreducible tensors. Part of this story involves symmetry and
antisymmetry, as will be explained below.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Columbia University Libraries, on 21 Aug 2018 at 13:10:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511755811.004
88 Elements of spacetime geometry
When we discussed p forms, we defined the exterior product of two one forms
as their antisymmetric direct product. This is meaningful as a definition because
the direct product T p∗ (M) ⊗ T p∗ (M) can be divided into antisymmetric and sym-
metric subspaces, and this division is coordinate-independent. The antisymmetric
subspace of T p∗ (M) ⊗ T p∗ (M) is spanned in a coordinate basis by
d x µ ∧ d x ν = d x µ ⊗ d x ν − d x ν ⊗ d x µ. (3.116)
The components of a two form, or antisymmetric tensor of rank (0, 2) are anti-
symmetric under exchange of indices, so that Tµν = −Tνµ . Under a coordinate
transformation, an antisymmetric tensor remains antisymmetric, so this subspace
of the direct product space transforms into itself.
There is also a symmetric subspace of T p∗ (M) ⊗ T p∗ (M), spanned in a coordi-
nate basis by
d x µ ⊗ d x ν + d x ν ⊗ d x µ. (3.117)
The components of a tensor defined in this subspace are then symmetric under
exchange of indices so that Tµν = Tνµ . Under a Lorentz transformation, a sym-
metric tensor remains symmetric, so this subspace of the direct product space also
transforms into itself.
If we look at tensors as represented by their components in a coordinate basis,
then any general rank (0, 2) tensor Tµν is the sum of its symmetric and antisym-
metric parts.
Tµν = T(µν) + T[µν]
1
T(µν) ≡ (Tµν + Tνµ ) symmetric
2
1
T[µν] ≡ (Tµν − Tνµ ) antisymmetric. (3.118)
2
But this is not yet the full reduction of the tensor into its irreducible parts. The
trace T = Tµν g µν of a rank (0, 2) tensor is a real number, a coordinate invariant,
and hence trivially transforms into itself under a coordinate transformation. The
symmetric part of a rank (0, 2) tensor is the sum
1
T(µν) = T{µν} + gµν T
d
1 1
T{µν} ≡ (Tµν + Tνµ ) − gµν T traceless symmetric
2 d
κλ
T ≡ g Tκλ trace (3.119)
of the traceless symmetric part and the trace.
A symmetric tensor has zero antisymmetric part, and an antisymmetric tensor
has zero symmetric part. The electromagnetic field strength tensor F is the primary
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Columbia University Libraries, on 21 Aug 2018 at 13:10:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511755811.004
The Principle of Relativity as a geometric principle 89
example of an antisymmetric tensor of rank (0, 2) used in physics, while the metric
tensor g is the symmetric (0, 2) tensor with which physicists and mathematicians
tend to be the most familiar.
The symmetrization and anti-symmetrization process can be extended to ten-
sors of any rank (m, n). A tensor can be symmetric in some pairs of indices and
antisymmetric in others, or symmetric or antisymmetric in all pairs of indices.3
Examples will be left to the reader as an exercise.
ṽ µ = L µ̃ ν
ν v , (3.120)
transforming the components of a general tensor of rank (m, n) is simple. You just
apply vector transformations on the m upper indices, and apply one form transfor-
mations on the n lower indices to get
1 ... µm = L µ˜1 . . . L µ˜m L λ1 . . . L λn T κ1 ... κm .
T̃νµ1 ... (3.122)
νn κ1 κm ν˜1 ν˜n λ1 ... λn
(i) All physical laws valid in one frame of reference are equally valid in any other frame
of reference moving uniformly relative to the first.
(ii) The speed of light (in a vacuum) is the same in all inertial frames of reference, regard-
less of the motion of the light source.
The rich geometric structure of flat spacetime grows out of those two simple
postulates if we follow them to their logical conclusions. In order for all physical
laws to be equally valid in frames of reference moving relative to one another, the
physical laws have to be expressed in a form that allows such a transformation to
3 There are also more subtle permutation symmetries, which are neither symmetric nor antisymmetric. They are
best analyzed using the mathematical theory of the symmetric group.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Columbia University Libraries, on 21 Aug 2018 at 13:10:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511755811.004
90 Elements of spacetime geometry
be defined, and that structure is a manifold with a tangent space and a cotangent
space.
In order for the speed of light to be the same in all inertial frames of reference,
space and time cannot be absolute and independent. Relativity of simultaneity,
time dilation and length contraction are what we get when we follow the sec-
ond postulate to its logical conclusions. The invariance of the speed of light leads
us to a unified picture of spacetime. The spacetime coordinate transformations
that leave invariant the speed of light are Lorentz transformations and spacetime
translations.
In this chapter we surveyed the fundamentals of geometry in flat spacetime. In
Chapter 4 we will put this geometry to work when we examine relativistic me-
chanics in flat spacetime.
Exercises
3.1 The following pairs of numbers represent the (τ, x) coordinates of events
in a spacetime of two dimensions. Using grid paper or your favorite
plotting software, plot these events on a spacetime diagram similar to
Figure 3.2. Using the invariant interval between each set of events, de-
termine which events have timelike, null or spacelike separations from the
other events.
E 0 = (0, 0)
E 1 = (1, 3)
E 2 = (−2, 5)
E 3 = (3, 0)
E 4 = (1, −3).
On the same grid, draw a pair of straight lines with slope ±1 that intersect
at event E 0 . In what way does this pair of lines relate to the sign of the
invariant interval between some other event and E 0 ? What does this pair
of lines represent?
3.2 Suppose that the S̃ frame with coordinates (τ̃ , x̃) is moving at velocity
β relative to the S frame with coordinates (τ, x), with the events (0, 0)
coinciding in both frames. On the same grid as in the previous exercise,
draw the (τ̃ , x̃) axes for β = 1/5, 1/2, 4/5.
3.3 On a (τ, x) coordinate grid, plot the curves
−τ 2 + x 2 = n 2 (E3.1)
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Columbia University Libraries, on 21 Aug 2018 at 13:10:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511755811.004
Exercises 91
−τ 2 + x 2 = −n 2 (E3.2)
ds 2 = −dτ 2 + d x 2 + dy 2 . (E3.3)
(a) Rewrite this metric using coordinates (u, v, y), where u = τ + x and v =
τ − x.
(b) Forgetting about the y direction, on a piece of grid paper or using your favorite
computer software, plot the (u, v) axes in (τ, x) coordinates.
(c) What type of world line is represented by a line of constant u or v?
Coordinates such as (u, v) are known as null coordinates, or light-cone
coordinates. If one wants to learn string theory, it is a good idea to become
familiar with light cone coordinates.
3.6 Consider the pole in the barn scenario discussed in this chapter. Prove that
in the case where the pole and barn have the same proper length L 0 , the
events E 2 and E 3 always have a spacelike separation. Suppose the barn
and pole have different proper lengths. Under what conditions, if any, can
the separation between events E 2 and E 3 be timelike? In such a case, is
there any contradiction in the time ordering between the two events in the
pole frame and the barn frame?
3.7 Consider a thin pole of proper length L 0 at rest in the S frame, with one
end at x = 0, y = 0 and the other end at x = L 0 , y = 0. Suppose we are
looking at this pole in a universe with three spacetime dimensions with
coordinates (τ, x, y).
(a) Find the equation for the world line of each end of the pole in frame S.
(b) Consider an observer in frame S̃ with coordinates (τ̃ , x̃, ỹ) moving at velocity
β x = 0, β y = β relative to frame S. Using (3.54), compute the equations for
the world lines of the ends of the pole in terms of (τ̃ , x̃, ỹ). What is the length
of the pole according to the observer in frame S̃?
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Columbia University Libraries, on 21 Aug 2018 at 13:10:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511755811.004
92 Elements of spacetime geometry
√
(c) Suppose frame S̃ moves instead with velocity β x = β y = β/ 2. Us-
ing (3.54), compute the equations for the world lines of the ends of the pole
in terms of (τ̃ , x̃, ỹ) in this case, and compare with your answer above. What
is the length of the pole according to the observer in frame S̃?
3.8 Using (3.54), write the Lorentz transformation for four spacetime dimen-
sions (d = 4) as a 4 × 4 matrix, and calculate the determinant.
3.9 Consider the pole in the barn scenario discussed in this chapter. Imagine
a pole with proper length L 0 = 10 m heading towards a barn with proper
length L 0 = 10 m at speed β = 4/5. Let’s call the frame in which the barn
is at rest S with coordinates (τ, x), and label the frame in which the pole
is at rest by S̃ with coordinates (τ̃ , x̃). Suppose that the leading edge of
the pole passes the front door of the barn at time τ = τ̃ = 0. Find the total
amount of time τi that the pole is completely inside the barn. What do
you learn when you try to calculate the corresponding interval τ̃i ?
3.10 Picture a rigid pole at rest according to an observer in frame S with space-
time coordinates (τ, x). One end is at x = 0 and the other is at x = L 0 .
(a) Draw the world sheet of the pole between τ = 0 and τ = L.
(b) On the same plot, draw a line representing the path of a flash of light at τ =
x = 0 aimed along the pole in the +x direction.
(c) Suppose the end of the pole at x = 0 is sharply tapped at τ = 0. On your plot,
identify the set of events on the world sheet of the pole that could possibly
be influenced by the tap at the end of the pole, according to special relativity.
Identify the set of events on the world sheet of the pole that could not possibly
be influenced by the tap at the end of the pole, according to special relativity.
(d) Suppose the tap at the end x = 0 is forceful enough to make the pole move at
speed β = 1/5. On a new plot, again using the (τ, x) coordinate system, draw
a possible world sheet for the accelerating pole from time τ = 0 to τ = 2L 0 .
Make sure that this world sheet is consistent with special relativity.
(e) What conclusion would you draw from this exercise about the nature of a
rigid body in spacetime?
3.11 The metric for flat space in three dimensions can be written using Eu-
clidean coordinates (x, y, z) as
ds 2 = d x 2 + dy 2 + dz 2 . (E3.4)
x = u cos w
y = u sin w
z = v, (E3.5)
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Columbia University Libraries, on 21 Aug 2018 at 13:10:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511755811.004
Exercises 93
x = u cos w sin v
y = u sin w sin v
z = u cos v. (E3.6)
3.12 Consider two flat space dimensions, with Euclidean coordinates (x, y).
Let’s write the metric in tensor form as
g = d x ⊗ d x + dy ⊗ dy. (E3.7)
(a) Rewrite this metric in polar coordinates x = r cos φ and y = r sin φ.
(b) Write the basis vectors (êr , êφ ) = (∂/∂r , ∂/∂φ) in terms of the basis vectors
(êx , ê y ) = (∂/∂ x, ∂/∂ y). Is the basis (∂/∂r , ∂/∂φ) a coordinate basis?
(c) If some set of basis vectors êi is an orthonormal basis, then g(êi , ê j ) = δi j . Is
the basis (∂/∂r , ∂/∂φ) an orthonormal basis?
∂
(d) Is the basis (∂/∂r , r1 ∂φ ) an orthonormal basis? Is it a coordinate basis?
(e) Is the basis (∂/∂ x, ∂/∂ y) an orthonormal basis? Is it a coordinate basis?
3.13 Consider four flat spacetime dimensions, with Minkowski coordinates
(τ, x, y, z). Let’s write the metric in tensor form as
α = αµ d x µ β = βµ d x µ
γ = γµ d x µ δ = δµ d x µ (E3.9)
where, as usual, the repeated Greek index implies a sum over all d
spacetime dimensions, compute α ∧ β, α ∧ β ∧ γ and α ∧ β ∧ γ ∧ δ for
d = 2, 3, 4.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Columbia University Libraries, on 21 Aug 2018 at 13:10:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511755811.004
94 Elements of spacetime geometry
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Columbia University Libraries, on 21 Aug 2018 at 13:10:11, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511755811.004