_O-POSITIONS :The Oppositions of Autonomy and History
K. Michael Hays
‘Naturally our respective concerns as individuals for for-
mal, socio-cultural and political discourse will make them-
selves felt in our joint editing of Oppositions.”: Thus did
the three founding editors stake out three primary the-
‘matic domains that, through their own writings and those
of other contributors, would be presented and debated
throughout the history of Oppositions—that extraordinary
apparatus for the production of architecture theory.
‘Therein Peter Eisenman's research into immanent formal,
operations and notations, Kenneth Frampton's eritique of
the modern and contemporary culture industries, and
Mario Gandelsonas’s ideological/semiotic analysis of con-
temporary practices—to which would later be added
(beginning with volume 6) Anthony Vidler’s institutional
and typological studies and (beginning with volume 12)
Kurt Forster's materialist historiography—swirled around
the vortex of architecture's “meaning.” But because of the
editors’ personal associations and the unfolding of
Opposition’ international network, the pages of the jour-
nal would also become saturated with, conflieted with, and
haunted by the presences of Colin Rowe and Manfredo
‘Tafuri—the rock and the hard place, the light and the dark,
between which Oppositions's discourse, at least implicitly,
‘was often eondueted.
1 will not here historicize this most important little maga-
zine (though that is surely the most important work to be
done and, perhaps, to be prompted by the issue of this
reader), but rather consider just one—I believe the domi-
nant one—of the themes that gathers up much of the work
of the editors and what they published. For the essential
contradiction between architecture's autonomy—its self-
‘organization into a body of formal elements and operations,
that separate it from any particular place and time—and
s eontingeney on, even determination by, historical forces
beyond its control subsumes all the “formal, socio-cultural
and political” concerns into an all-embracing dialectic. The
conflets of formalism and determinism of the Oppositions
decade, indeed, seem almost symptomatic of a deeper,
social pathology one would want to query more closely. One
should ask not whether architecture is autonomous, or
\hether it ean willfully be made so, but rather how it ean
be that the question arises in the first place, what kind of ix
ituation allows for architecture to worry about itself to
this degree.
In “Design versus Non-Design,” Diana Agrest gives a pre
ise description of the conditions of autonomy that most
architecture theorists of the period would have endorsed:
Design, considered as both a practice and a produc, is in
effect a closed system—not only in relation to culture as a
whole, but also in relation to other cultural systems such
as literature, film, painting, philosophy, physies, geome-
try, ete. Properly defined, it is reductive, condensing and
crystallizing general cultural notions within its own dis-
tinet parameters, Within the limits of this system, however,
design constitutes a set of practices—architecture, urban
design, and industrial design—unified with respect to cer
tain normative theories. That is, it possesses specific char-
acteristics that distinguish it from all other cultural prac-
tices and that establish a boundary between what is design.
and what is not. (p. 383 of this collection)
[As Agrest goes on to argue, the very concept of autonomy
requires us to step outside our own design culture and
grasp its relationship to other cultural codes as well as its,
difference from them by means of some vaster historical
and cultural mode of analysis. But as one pulls back to view
the social life out of which autonomization emerges—in,
particular, after the assimilation and banalization of even,
the most radical of modern formal conventions into post-
war commercial building, and the penetration of architec-
ture’s “closed system” by degraded information and
images—then what she ealls the “specificity” of the eonsti-
tutive differences of architecture becomes harder to
detect. For what is increasingly the ease after the 1950s, as,
media culture develops into an all-encompassing system, is,
the very lack of distinction among media practices, includ-
ing the design of form and space.
‘What is more, though the problematie of autonomy is prop-
erly part of the ideology of modernism, by the 1960s the
collateral modernist doctrine of functionalism—the inter-x section of brute facts of utility with objective design pro-
cedures and standardized means of produetion—had given
rise to the renewed, largely British and North American
positivist inquiries of the behavioral sciences, operations
research, systematic design methodologies, and objective
technologies, all of which sought to quantify architecture's
characteristies and trade its specificity for a generalized
scientism, Among the equipment available for mobilization
against this positivism stood Colin Rowe's emergent
Gestalt formalism (enunciated as early as his 1947
“Mathematies of the Ideal Villa” and available to
Oppositions readers since his “Neoclassicism and Modern
Architecture” in the first issue). Rowe was perhaps the
dominant influence on the early Institute of Architecture
and Urban Studies (founded in 1967) up until its contact
with, and importation and transformation of, European
phenomenological and structuralist criticisms through
Gandelsonas and Vidler, as well as Agrest and, just later,
Aldo Rossi and Manfredo Tafuri. With these last, the
European discourses of Marxism and structuralism began
tomingle with Anglo-American formalism, and the context
for the pas de deus of autonomization and historiezation
was set.
‘Three Oppositions editorials broached the theme more or
less directly. Gandelsonas’s “Neo-Functionalism” (volume
5; pp. T-8 of this collection) categorized dialectically, for the
first time, the position epitomized by the work of Robert
‘Yenturi—‘neo-realism”—and that represented by Aldo
Rossi, Peter Eisenman, and John Hejduk—‘neo-rational-
n"—and posited, as a possible third term, “neo-funetion-
alism,” a redefinition of modernist functionalism’s under-
developed concern with the problem of meaning, which
Gandelsonas understood in the structuralist sense of dif-
ferentiation and signification within a closed system.
Vidler's apologia for Rossi and the Tendenza, “The Third
‘Typology” (volume 7; pp. 13-16), identified the “ontology of
the city”—a corollary of the autonomy thesis that empha-
sized the iterability and portability of generative types—
as a possible basis for the restoration of a critical role to
architecture. While Eisenman’s “Post-Funetionalism” (vol-
ume 6; pp. 9-12) gathered up his preoccupations with
structural linguisties, conceptual art, and avant-garde
autotelie procedures, and outlined a position that would
recognize architecture's epistemological status as a kind of
entitlement granted by modernist thought.
Eisenman’s editorial is paradigmatic of the diffieult opposi-
tion of autonomy and history viewed within the limitations
of modernism. Eisenman saw modernist forms not as sim-
ple derivatives of functional needs, but as delineations of
the immanent, self-referential properties of architecture
itself, as searches for objective knowledge that lies outside
both the architectural agent's intentions and the building's
uses, and inside the very materials and formal operations
of architecture. Such research discovered the new in the
given “language” through an artieulation and redistribu-
tion of its elements; it fused the practice of architecture
with the eritique of architecture and replaced the fune-
tional object with a theoretical one, Moreover, Eisenman
historieized such concerns as part of a new episteme, a
posthumanist paradigm heralded by Kasimir Malevich and
Piet Mondrian, James Joyce and Guillaume Apollinaire,
Arnold Schoenberg and Anton Webern, Hans Richter and
Viking Eggeling, evidenced in the sheer accumulated
weight of relativity and uncertainty principles in modern
science and philosophy, and theorized in the antihumanism
of Michel Foucault and Claude Lévi-Strauss. And so
Eisenman’s effort to push architecture into this new era is
driven by a felt historical imperative: to represent. the
inner logic of the object in the object itself is necessary not
because of some subjective decision to exclude other con-
siderations but because of a historical evolution erucial, if
not unique, to the discipline of architecture, which delegit-
imizes older meanings, demands that the cultural eontent
of an older functionalism migrate into an autonomous ar-
chitecture, and concludes that the true revolutionary artist
of our time is not Karel Teige or Hannes Meyer (see
George Baird's introduction to the Teige/Le Corbusier dis-
pute, pp. 585-588) but the seemingly apolitical logothete of,
an “atemporal, decompositional mode” (p. 12).
One need look no further than the same Oppositions vol:
‘ume 6 for an apparent counter-argument. In his “Robert,