Baggini 2002
Baggini 2002
Baggini 2002
Philosophical Autobiography
Julian Baggini
To cite this article: Julian Baggini (2002) Philosophical Autobiography, Inquiry, 45:3, 295-312,
DOI: 10.1080/002017402760258141
Article views: 74
Philosophical Autobiography
Julian Baggini
The Philosophers’ Magazine
recountin g of one’s own life is almost invariabl y a form of extended speech act of
self-revelation . When a philosophe r is the autobiographer , this self-revelatio n
illuminates the interplay between thought, life, and personality . Understandin g how
this works allows us to address three problem s of biograph y raised by Honderich:
how to give an account of something as large and complex as a human life; how a
life-story is also a judgment; and how we can justify identifyin g one part of a causal
circumstance as ‘the cause’. There is also a new ethical problem raised about the
autobiographer ’s right to make public details of a shared private life.
I. Introduction
In his recently published autobiography, Ted Honderich writes:
In my stubbornness, though, I am one with most philosophers, who for the most part
are impervious to argument. There is a truth about philosophy in this. At the bottom of
philosophy are things underdescribed as commitments. They are better described as
grips that the world gets on us early. 1
In this article, I argue that what Honderich says here is broadly, if not
exactly, correct. I argue this case and fully explain how it cashes out by
examining some of the main characteristics of philosophical autobiography. It
is my contention that philosophical autobiographies of philosophers give us
valuable insights into what philosophy is and enable us to understand better
how personal judgment and prejudice work alongside rational argument. If I
am right, then philosophical autobiography has an important role to play in
the study of metaphilosophy. But even if I am wrong, the mere existence of
the issues and problems that I discuss and raise suggests that philosophical
autobiography deserves more attention than it has received.
Since philosophical autobiography is a somewhat neglected genre, I map
some of the territory as well as put forward speci c arguments. This means
What makes something a philosophical biography needn’t be that it’s the biography of
a philosopher, just somebody where there is some dynamic, an interaction to reveal
and describe, between somebody’s preoccupation with ideas and their life.3
found Eichmann had no real preoccupation with ideas at all that could create a
dynamic with his life.
What Monk describes may best be seen as a particular species of
philosophical biography, one where the interaction between the life and ideas
is that between one person’s life and their own ideas. This is just one example
of a broader category of philosophical biography where some kind of relation
between a person’s life and any philosophical ideas can be drawn out and
examined, even if those ideas are not part of the mental furniture of the
biography’s subject.
It is not my concern here to formulate a full de nition of philosophical
biography. The point of this brief discussion is merely to draw attention to the
Downloaded by [ECU Libraries] at 23:17 16 September 2015
also attend to such factors as the manner of their interruption, who they
choose to interrupt and who they leave unmolested, what kind of interruptions
they make and so on. Similarly, when a person offers an opinion, we know a
little more about them. When we hear a range of their opinions we get a much
fuller understanding of their character.
There is certainly an issue here about how much of what we reveal of
ourselves depends upon how honest and open we are. However, this can be
overstated. In a sense we do nd out more about a person who reveals every
detail of their private life than we do about someone who is less forthcoming.
But in another sense, both people reveal their characters equally: one as a
person drawn to confession and the other as a more private individual. Not
Downloaded by [ECU Libraries] at 23:17 16 September 2015
saying much about our private thoughts tells others a great deal about what
kinds of people we are.
In this way, language functions as a revealer of character. For this reason,
we can talk about the revealing of character as a form of extended speech act.
The label may seem incongruous, as acts are usually thought of as short and
discrete, whereas this kind of speech act is extended and open-ended. But by
‘acts’ all we mean are things we do, and there are many such extended, open
acts: building a career, searching for happiness, looking for the perfect
cappuccino. If acts can be temporally extended and open-ended, and if by
‘speech act’ we mean something in particular we do with words, then
revealing personality can accurately be described as a speech act.
If we accept that such speech acts exist, that is that we do reveal our
personalities through the words we utter, we can see how there is an important
distinction between biography and autobiography. In a biography, the writer
can succeed or fail to reveal truths about the subject. Although biographies
rarely contain many factual errors, many do fail to paint an accurate portrait
of their subjects. In autobiographies, however, the writers almost inevitably
reveal something of themselves. That is because the mere act of talking or
writing reveals personality. One can adopt a formal tone when writing about a
subject which can very much mask personality (more than one can when one
is speaking about the same thing). However, when the subject of one’s writing
is oneself, such masking is more dif cult. It seems to be a matter of fact rather
than any logical necessity that the coincidence of writer with subject means
that the way in which the subject’s life is related is almost bound to tell you
something about that subject.
Consider, for example, two very contrasting autobiographies by philoso-
phers which were published around the same time. Ted Honderich’s
Philosopher: A Kind of Life is extremely confessional.7 Honderich sets out
to hide nothing and present himself warts and all. Mary Warnock’s A Memoir,
however, is very different.8 There is nothing confessional about this book at
all and its polite reminiscences include nothing one wouldn’t ordinarily relate
to someone one was meeting for the rst time. Yet it is not the case that one
300 Julian Baggini
Even in an extreme case, where the author seems to reveal nothing about
their inner lives, a personality emerges. Take, for example, W. V. O. Quine’s
autobiography. 9 The book is a relentless catalogue of travels and events
which is remarkably unengaging. Quine just does not present any kind of
inner life. But that doesn’t mean we learn nothing about Quine from reading
the book. The fact that Quine attends so little to feelings and emotions cannot
but say something about the man. This is reinforced by certain patterns of
behaviour that are consistent with people who are often – perhaps too
judgmentally – described as being towards the autistic end of the personality
scale. For instance, Quine liked to keep count of how many states he had
visited and would make diversions merely to tick another off his list, wanting
to complete the set. This concern for mental order and tidiness combined with
an apparent disinterest in the emotional side of life does surely re ect
something real and important about Quine’s personality, even though it is a
portrait of the philosophe r that emerges seemingly without the author ever
consciously trying to paint it.
It seems then that in the case of autobiography, part at least of the writer’s
personality will out. In contrast, a biography can fail completely to reveal
personality. The main reason for this, as I have suggested, is that revealing
ourselves through the use of our own words is a particular kind of extended
speech act, one that it seems we cannot fail to perform if the subject of our
words is ourselves.
This is in itself an interesting philosophical point about language use in
autobiography. However, if it is true, it is true of all autobiography. Is there
anything special about philosophica l autobiography?
I suggest there is, once again on empirical rather than logical grounds.
Reading through various philosophers’ autobiographies, one is struck by how
often what is revealed of their personalities sheds light on how they thought
as philosophers. Again, there is no logical necessity here. It is more than
possible that a philosophe r could write an autobiography which left you
none the wiser about how they philosophized. But as a matter of fact,
such autobiographies seem to be rare. An autobiography of a philosopher is
Philosophical Autobiography 301
which have nothing to do with the people who produce them. Philosophy is in
an important sense a personal pursuit and we do not undertake it with an
impersonal faculty called ‘reason’. Rather, how we reason is coloured by who
we are and the commitments we already have. One might want to go even
further and endorse Wittgenstein’s belief that: ‘Work in philosophy . . . is
really more work on oneself. On one’s own conception. On how one sees
things.’ 14
I have said that philosophica l autobiography provides evidence in support
of the stronger and the weaker of the above claims. It does not force us to
accept either or both. The evidence is strong and demands a response none the
less. Anyone who wished to maintain, in the face of this evidence, that
Downloaded by [ECU Libraries] at 23:17 16 September 2015
A human life, any human life that has lasted a while, has a fullness that can seem
greater than that of any other single subject-matter. It is possible to think there is no
thing or problem in philosophy and no subject in science that challenges perception
and judgment, so challenges summary. Nothing else is, so to speak, life-size. 16
Philosophical Autobiography 303
Here, Honderich’s point is simply that a life is such a complex and large
thing that it de es explanation and summary. This does seem to be justi ed by
more than just an exceptionalism which reserves human nature as the one part
of the universe which science cannot explain. It just does seem true that
human lives are too large and messy to be completely explained. When one
considers that even in the physical sciences a subject such as meteorology is
so complex that weather and climate cannot be accurately predicted or
retrospectively understood, the claim that human lives resist complete
explanation is not too fanciful.
Honderich’s second problem is that accounts or summaries of a life ‘are not
summaries called up by the facts, but also and inevitably attitudes to a life,
Downloaded by [ECU Libraries] at 23:17 16 September 2015
the situation and thought processes just before the action we have their entire
life to date and their inherited characteristics. Yet in understanding a life we
feel the same urge to praise causes. Indeed, many philosophers have done so
without apparently considering it to be a problem. For example, Russell
recounts ve minutes that, in his mind, completely changed his life, when he
saw the sick Mrs Whitehead in extreme pain. ‘At the end of those ve
minutes, I had become a completely different person’, he recalled.19 The
impact was political as well as personal: Russell claims that in those ve
minutes he went from being an imperialist to a pro-Boer paci st. It seems
certain that this change cannot be fully explained without reference to a
causal circumstance that extends far beyond those ve minutes. Yet Russell
Downloaded by [ECU Libraries] at 23:17 16 September 2015
nds no problem in singling out that short time as the cause of his change of
heart.
explanation that appeals to fewer factors will not be complete. So the choice
is between saying we should never provide an explanation-by-cause or
accepting that an explanation-by-cause will never be a full causal
explanation.
The rst possibility must be rejected, since we cannot do without
explanations-by-cause . We are often required to give such an explanation
where an explanation-by-causal-circumstance would not do in its place. If, for
example, I want to know the cause of a car crash, there is a sense in which the
right answer would be ‘faulty brakes’. Although, qua philosophers, we may
not be able to give a satisfactory account of why this component of the causal
circumstance should be identi ed as ‘the cause’, we cannot deny that to thus
Downloaded by [ECU Libraries] at 23:17 16 September 2015
that, ‘[t]he accounts I have given of [people I have known] are partial in every
sense of the word. I have not attempted to describe them completely; and I
have written about them as they appeared to me, from my particular point of
view.’22 Both responses to the problem of partiality hit upon truths re ected
in Nagel’s account of objectivity: Warnock’s that partiality is unavoidable
and has to be accepted, Honderich’s that we should, at least on some
occasions, struggle to remove as much partiality from our accounts as
possible.
In a sense I am suggesting no more than that we accept what Honderich
himself said in the quote at the start of this article: that at bottom philosophy is
about ‘commitments’ or ‘grips the world gets on us early’. It is slightly
Downloaded by [ECU Libraries] at 23:17 16 September 2015
puzzling that Honderich accepts this and yet thinks it a philosophical disgrace
that we talk about explanation-by-cause when such explanations inevitably
re ect our commitments, purposes, or values. For Honderich, it seems,
philosophy is not what it ought to be. But perhaps philosophy is how it is and
we would be misguided to think it ought to be otherwise. We need to learn to
live with what we have, not hope for something more objective which we
cannot have.
that it should be minimal. The fact that philosophy cannot dispense with
judgments does not mean that it is reduced to a clash of opinions. Philosophy
may not be fully determined by objective facts and logic, but it is very much
constrained by them. In Nagel’s schema, philosophy may not be able to be
purely objective but objectivity is where it strives. The point is that whenever
we make a judgment we should be appealing as far as is possible to facts,
arguments, and reasons that are as objective as possible and which rely on
individual opinions as little as possible. We accept the need for judgment, but
we always strive to rely as little as possible on it. Judgment lls the gaps left
by facts and logic, it does not replace either.
What is interesting is that accepting this place for the role of judgment in
Downloaded by [ECU Libraries] at 23:17 16 September 2015
philosophy.
my life or his life, but also part of our life. When the other person writes about
this, they are thus making use of something which in a sense they do not
wholly own. This raises a moral issue: what right does the autobiographer
have to make use of something essentially shared without the permission of
the co-owner?26 The biographer has the moral problem of what they are
entitled to nd out and then what they are entitled to reveal. But in both cases
the question is about what the biographer may use of other people’s lives
when the biographer is not a participant in those lives. The autobiographer
does not have the problem of what they are entitled to nd out, but their
problem of what to reveal differs from that of the biographer since they are
participants and thus are on the same footing as others who have an equal,
Downloaded by [ECU Libraries] at 23:17 16 September 2015
greater, or lesser stake in the events being described. So whereas all the
people discussed in a biography are in the same boat – all are subjects for the
somewhat detached biographer – there is an asymmetry, and imbalance,
between the author of an autobiography and the other people such a work
describes.
There are at least two responses to this problem. One is to reject it and
argue that there is no shared ownership of personal histories and that therefore
the moral problems for the autobiographer are the same as those for the
biographer. To me this does not appear a plausible option. Even in journalism,
for example, there are moral codes governing when one uses information
from a certain source and when consent is or is not needed. It seems to me that
in almost all cases the people an autobiographer shares a life with did not do
so on any kind of understanding that what they did together could be told to a
wider public. So there is at the very least a potential problem of breach of
trust, if nothing else.
It therefore seems more fruitful to accept that the problem is real and to
examine further what the special responsibilities of the autobiographer are.
This would be beyond the scope of this article but is a question which I hope
some at least will consider worth attention.
VIII. Conclusion
Quine began his autobiography with the sentence, ‘My birth in a modest
frame house on Nash Street in a south-east-central quarter of Akron on Anti-
Christmas, June 25, 1908, brought the population of that industrial city to a
gure in the neighbourhood of sixty thousand.’27 Quine is more concerned to
give us facts about his life, perhaps more than we need, than many of his
fellow autobiographers. But in launching straight into an account of his life
without pausing to consider if the very attempt to do so raises any
philosophical issues, his memoir is typical of those of other philosophers.
Ayer, for instance, features in Honderich’s autobiography, but whereas that
Philosophical Autobiography 311
volume does examine the purpose, scope, and limitation of the genre, Ayer
managed to write two volumes of autobiography without even scratching
these issues.28 The neglect is to be regretted, since, as I have argued,
philosophical autobiography provides a particularly well-focused medium for
the examination of the interplay between life and thought and the need to
accept and understand the role of personal judgment in philosophizing. It also
presents a particular ethical problem. This article has identi ed some issues
involved in these and hopefully made some progress in thinking about others.
The topic deserves more and if that case at least has been made here then my
discussion will have been worthwhile.
Downloaded by [ECU Libraries] at 23:17 16 September 2015
NOTES
R E FE R E NC E S
Austin, J. L. 1961. How to Do Things with Words. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Ayer, A. J. 1977. Part of My Life. London: Collins.
Ayer, A. J. 1984. More of My Life. London: Collins.
Baggini, J. and Stangroom, J. (eds) 2002. New British Philosophy: The Interviews. London:
Routledge.
Cohen, G. A. 2001. If You’re an Egalitarian , How Come You’re So Rich? Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press.
De Beauvoir, Simone 1993. All Said and Done. Trans. Patrick O’Brian. New York: Paragon
House (originally published 1972).
Feyerabend , P. 1995. Killing Time. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Honderich, Ted 2001. Philosopher : A Kind of Life. London: Routledge.
Mill, J. S. 1989. Autobiography. London: Penguin (originally publishe d 1873).
Downloaded by [ECU Libraries] at 23:17 16 September 2015
Monk, R. 1990. Ludwig Wittgenstein: The Duty of Genius. London: Jonathan Cape.
Monk, R. 1996. Bertrand Russell. Volume 1: The Spirit of Solitude. London: Jonathan Cape.
Monk, R. 2000. Bertrand Russell, Volume 2: The Ghost of Madness. London: Jonathan Cape.
Nagel, T. 1986. The View From Nowhere. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Quine, W. V. O. 1985. The Time of My Life. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Rousseau, Jean-Jacque s 1996. The Confession s. Ware, Herts: Wordsworth (originall y
publishe d 1781).
Russell, Bertrand 2000. Autobiography. London: Routledge (originall y publishe d 1967, 1968,
1969).
Warnock, Mary 2001. A Memoir: People and Places. London: Duckworth.
Wittgenstein , Ludwig 1980. Culture and Value (ed. Georg Henrik Von Wright). Oxford:
Blackwell.
Julian Baggini, The Philosophers ’ Magazine, 18 Hyde Grove, Sale, M33 7TE, UK. E-mail:
editor@philosophers.co.uk