Classics of International Relations - Nodrm
Classics of International Relations - Nodrm
Classics of International Relations - Nodrm
Henrik Bliddal is Director of the Science and Technology Committee at the NATO
Parliamentary Assembly in Brussels, Belgium.
Edited by
Henrik Bliddal, Casper Sylvest and Peter Wilson
First published 2013
by Routledge
2 Park Square, Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon OX14 4RN
Simultaneously published in the USA and Canada
by Routledge
711 Third Avenue, New York, NY 10017
Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group, an informa business
© 2013 Henrik Bliddal, Casper Sylvest and Peter Wilson
The right of Henrik Bliddal, Casper Sylvest and Peter Wilson to be identified as the
editors of this work has been asserted by them in accordance with the Copyright,
Designs and Patent Act 1988.
All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or utilised in
any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now known or hereafter
invented, including photocopying and recording, or in any information storage or
retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publishers.
Trademark notice: Product or corporate names may be trademarks or registered
trademarks, and are used only for identification and explanation without intent to
infringe.
British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data
A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library
Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data
Classics of international relations : essays in criticism and appreciation / edited by
Henrik Bliddal, Casper Sylvest and Peter Wilson.
pages cm
Includes bibliographical references and index.
1. International relations. I. Bliddal, Henrik.
JZ1242.C54 2013
327–dc23
2012050841
1 Introduction 1
HENRIK BLIDDAL, CASPER SYLVEST AND PETER WILSON
11 Towards a liberal realism: Inis L. Claude’s Power and International Relations 109
J. SAMUEL BARKIN
18 Obligations beyond the state: Andrew Linklater’s Men and Citizens in the
Theory of International Relations 177
RICHARD DEVETAK AND JULIETTE GOUT
19 The making of IR/IPE: Robert W. Cox’s Production, Power and World Order 187
RANDALL GERMAIN
25 Restraint in the global polity, the remix: Daniel Deudney’s Bounding Power 250
BRENT J. STEELE
26 Conclusion 261
HENRIK BLIDDAL, CASPER SYLVEST AND PETER WILSON
Index 271
List of contributors
For better or worse, International Relations (IR), like all fields of academic enquiry,
gains its identity and establishes a degree of coherence by reference to tradition: its core
concerns, staple approaches, and landmark or ‘classic’ contributions. This book pro-
vides introductions to and critical engagements with classical works of IR since c. 1900;
i.e. the point when IR began to emerge as a recognizable socio-intellectual space, with
its own concerns, debates and literature, if not yet its own professional space within the
academy. At a time when the research agenda of the field is expanding and fragment-
ing, there is a growing trend to introduce IR through a combination of theory exegesis
and a return to the discipline’s founding fathers and classic books. At the same time,
the changing nature of academic learning in conjunction with the proliferation of
scholarly books and articles means that students and even some faculty rarely have the
time or the opportunity to engage properly with more than a handful of these books.
Classics of International Relations speaks to this predicament. It provides coherence by
introducing the intellectual landmarks and core concerns of the field and gives students
and scholars authoritative treatments of a considered selection of classics. Classics of
International Relations aims to contribute to the ongoing debate about the identity of
the discipline. Not shying away from the politics involved in establishing a canon, the
book’s broad and inclusive understanding of ‘the classic’ – covering inter alia the
acknowledged classic, the classic in-the-making, and the ‘alternative format’ classic – is
intended to facilitate such debate.
This Introduction has four aims. First, to provide a brief history of the idea of a
classic text. Second, to set out the broad concept of classics around which the volume is
organized. Third, to justify the purposes of the book and discuss some of the pitfalls
involved in bringing it together. The volume is inescapably involved in the process of
canonizing, engaging as it does in potentially powerful practices of inclusion and
exclusion. Fourth, to provide a brief overview of the organization of the volume and set
out the principles that have informed our selection of classics.
What is a classic?
The notion of a classic work of IR, history, sociology, politics or indeed any field of
scholarly and scientific endeavour derives from literature. It is a notion tied to the
process of secular canon-formation from the beginning. The Romans used the term
classici to distinguish citizens of the pre-eminent class, those enjoying a certain fixed
income, from the poorer citizenry beneath them, infra classem. The first writer to
employ the term classicus figuratively was Aulus Gellius in the second century AD.2 He
2 Henrik Bliddal, Casper Sylvest and Peter Wilson
used it to distinguish superior, authoritative texts, i.e. texts that could constitute a
model for future writers, from those less worthy. Since that time, the term has been used
repeatedly to distinguish the finest literary products of Western civilization from the
mass. A classic work goes beyond the merely useful, noteworthy and valuable. It is a
work that is considered in some important respects seminal or exemplary. A classic
work is required reading for a person of culture. It is a work that all such persons ought
to read or at least ‘ought to have on their bookshelves’.3 Yet it cannot be assumed that
there was ever a time when a consensus prevailed, on anything more than a very gen-
eral level, on the qualities and characteristics that define a classic. A classic work is
certainly one that to some degree has stood the test of time. It is a work that continues
to be read across the generations and in this sense is said to have ‘endured’. But how
many generations does a ‘classic’ need to cross? How long does it need to endure?
What is it, most importantly, about this classic that has enabled it to cross the genera-
tions and endure? In addition to crossing generations, a classic is often deemed to be a
work that crosses frontiers. Its appeal goes beyond the country and perhaps even the
culture of its birth, often in time being translated into many different languages. But
how many frontiers does it need to cross?
To these questions many answers have been given, with the outer boundaries of a
centuries-old debate being defined by two broad positions. The first position, which
held sway until the twentieth century, and could still be heard in the strong voices of T. S.
Eliot and Q. D. Leavis well into that century, might be termed the essentialist. The
second position, which holds sway today, though containing many disparate evoca-
tions, might be termed the sociological. The essentialist position finds one of its strongest
statements in a celebrated essay by the nineteenth-century French literary critic,
Charles Augustin Sainte-Beuve. He acknowledged at the outset that the question ‘What
is a classic?’ is delicate and different answers could be proposed ‘according to times and
seasons’. He went on to present, however, his own unequivocally essentialist account of
what a classic work entails. ‘The idea of a classic implies something that has con-
tinuance and consistence, and which produces unity and tradition, fashions and trans-
mits itself, and endures.’ It is a work that enriches the human mind, increases its
treasure, and causes it ‘to advance a step’. It discovers some ‘moral and not equivocal
truth’ and reveals ‘some eternal passion in that heart where all seemed known and
discovered’. It expresses itself in a form ‘broad and great, refined and sensible, sane and
beautiful’; and in a style peculiar to itself yet which is ‘found to be also that of the
whole world, a style new without neologism, new and old, easily contemporary with
all time’.4 The idea that a classic expresses certain timeless verities and speaks not to
this or that culture but to the whole world goes to the heart of the essentialist
position. However, the conceptual vessels ‘timeless verities’ and ‘speaking to the
whole world’ are in themselves quite empty and have been filled in a variety of ways.
Eliot, for example, contended in 1944 that the classic must display inter alia wit, mag-
niloquence, maturity and urbanity. The one work that Eliot considered to be a true
classic, Virgil’s Aeneid (according to him, Dante, Shakespeare, Racine and Milton
wrote, at best, ‘relative classics’), moreover exhibited comprehensiveness, centrality, a
sense of destiny and the gift of prophecy. But it also possessed a certain universality:
‘The classic must … express the maximum possible of the whole range of feeling which
represents the character of the people who speak that language’. Universality for
Eliot unlike Sainte-Beuve was paradoxical; it resided in this ‘comprehensiveness in
particularity’.5
Introduction 3
Such nuances in Eliot’s essay anticipate the sociological position which received its
best-known expression in Frank Kermode’s The Classic, published some three decades
later. According to Kermode, classics are ‘old books which people still read’.6 An
important factor in the making of a classic is ‘a more or less continuous chorus of
voices asserting the value of a classic’. This contrasts with what Kermode calls Eliot’s
‘imperial’ model which expresses the timeless verities of a culture or civilization.7
Rather than containing anything timeless, classic works possess ‘an openness to
accommodation which keeps them alive under endlessly varying dispositions’.8 Here,
Kermode echos Ezra Pound’s contention of the 1930s that ‘[a] classic is a classic not
because it conforms to certain structural rules, or fits certain definitions (of which its
author had quite probably never heard). It is a classic because of a certain eternal and
irrepressible freshness’.9 He also anticipates Calvino’s contention that ‘[a] classic is a
book that has never finished saying what it has to say’ and ‘[t]he classics are books that
we find all the more new, fresh, and unexpected upon reading’.10 For the essentialists, a
classic is by and large a closed book which specialized study and learning can partly
open. As late as 1969, Leavis maintained that many peripheral readings of a classic
were possible but only one central reading.11 In Kermode’s view, however, the classic is
an open text capable of generating new meanings and understandings, ideas and
interpretations. The classic signifies different things to different generations and differ-
ent people within those generations. Classic works endure not because they lack sub-
stance and are open to infinite interpretation, but because they possess substance that is
‘patient of interpretation’. Rather than express timeless verities, a work becomes a
classic because it is sufficiently complex and open-ended to enable different cultures,
generations and societies to find in it new meaning.12
From this brief exegesis one conclusion can be drawn: classic is a status we give to a
work that separates it from often worthy but professedly inferior peers. It says this is a
book one should read. It says this is a book one should prioritize over others because of
its timeless qualities or because of the high value a given society, community or culture
attaches to it. It is a term inextricably linked to the notion of a secular canon, a body of
works if not sacred and eternal then in some important respects superior and deemed
to be of continuing value and importance.
What is an IR classic?
There has been no comparable debate about what makes a classic of IR. The field has
a number of texts that are routinely referred to as classics, a number of others to which
classic status is occasionally attributed. All too often, however, the label is employed as
a loose synonym for ‘landmark’ or ‘groundbreaking’. This reflects an unsatisfactory
degree of critical self-awareness in applying the concept and an underdeveloped
appreciation of its discursive functions and possibilities. Before suggesting a typology
that will help us to heighten our consciousness and sharpen our appreciation of the IR
classic, it is important to make some preliminary distinctions regarding the use of the
prefix ‘classic’ in IR discourse.
First, it is important to distinguish a classic work, in the sense understood in this volume,
from a work of the classical tradition. The term classical tradition (also sometimes
termed ‘international theory’)13 is usually used to refer to that broad body of thought that
predates IR as a specialized and professional field of study, and to which the IR community
continuously adds by the ‘discovery’ of old works. Its originators are philosophers,
4 Henrik Bliddal, Casper Sylvest and Peter Wilson
political theorists, lawyers or publicists who have written significant, perhaps profound,
things about the international system or society, who have influenced later thought, and
whose works are deemed to be worthy of serious study. Among them can be counted
such illustrious names as Vitoria, Hobbes, Grotius, Vattel, Rousseau, Smith, Burke,
Kant, Hegel and Gentz – to cite the subjects of one well-known collection of essays14 –
though the extent to which such disparate figures may be said to constitute in any
meaningful sense a ‘tradition’ can be, and indeed has been, questioned.15
Second, it is important to distinguish a classic work from a work that employs the
classical approach. The classical approach is a term originating from and still mainly
used by those associated with the English school of IR.16 The classical approach, in
Bull’s words, signifies ‘that approach to theorizing that derives from philosophy, history,
and law, and that is characterized above all by explicit reliance on the exercise of judg-
ment’ and ‘the scientifically imperfect process of perception or intuition’.17 Bull derived
this understanding of the approach from what he took to be the analytical methods of
classical, i.e. pre-twentieth century, thinkers, thus closely linking the classical tradition
and the classical approach. He held these methods to be superior, or at least more
honest and realistic, than the behavioural, scientific or quantitative methods that were
at the time taking hold in the social sciences. Bull’s definition and his subsequent
argument are concerned with methodology and epistemology, not with the status of
any body of work or particular work. While he certainly used the word ‘classical’ to
lend gravitas to an approach he personally favoured, he was not using it to suggest that
by the very fact of being ‘classical’ it was superior to others.
The classic work as understood in this volume, therefore, has no logical connection
to the classical tradition or to the classical approach. These refer to particular types,
bodies and methods of work, not a work’s status. It is perfectly possible for classic
works to hail from the ‘scientific’ as from the ‘classical’ camp (to use Bull’s imperfect
categories). The fact that the majority of IR classics as specified here come from the
classical camp says perhaps more about the age of this camp than its intellectual
superiority. It also, however, reflects the non-positivist inclinations of the editors, our
understanding of the discipline as a conversation between competing theoretical
standpoints rather than a quest from a single standpoint for a single, universally valid,
truth – the goal of much ‘scientific’ theory.
There are, we contend, five types of classic work in the field of IR. We have arrived
at three of these types by reflecting on the works that are generally or increasingly
deemed to be classics, not through the application of any a priori conceptions or
understandings. Our approach here is therefore ‘sociological’, not ‘essentialist’, though
the possibility of arriving at some essentialist conclusions have not been ruled out. Yet
to this fairly conventional understanding of classic must be added, if we are to capture
the current IR field in all its diversity, two further types. The five types are:
(i) The acknowledged or undisputed classic. These are works such as The Twenty
Years’ Crisis and Theory of International Politics whose status as classics few in
IR would deny.
(ii) The archetypal classic. These are works seen as the best expressions of an
important school of thought, paradigm or approach. They are widely deemed
and utilized as exemplars of that approach. Examples include The Anarchical
Society (English school) and Political Theory and International Relations
(cosmopolitanism).
Introduction 5
(iii) The classic in the making. These are works published relatively recently such as
Social Theory of International Politics and Bounding Power, which show signs in
terms of their disciplinary impact of becoming classics in the future.
(iv) The overlooked classic. These are works such as Three Guineas and Bananas,
Beaches and Bases, which have a small but intense following within certain dis-
ciplinary sub-groups but which have yet to be more broadly acknowledged. A
parallel in the world of film would be the cult classic.
(v) Alternative format classic. Types (i) to (iv) generally betray a conventional
understanding of ‘text’: a published, academic book; the academic monograph.
A broader notion of text would embrace film, literature, art, music. The alter-
native format classic is a cultural reference point. While not emanating from the
discipline, it is a work that has had such an impact on the way international
relations are conceived within broader society that it has come to assume a
prominent place in teaching and in scholarly debates.
These types are not mutually exclusive. The Anarchical Society, for example, is an
acknowledged classic and an archetypal classic. Inside/outside is an archetypal classic and
a classic in the making. The types are sufficiently clear and coherent, however, to enable
us to sharpen our thinking on the IR classic and, more broadly, the canon-forming
process in IR.
Notes
1 We would like to thank Lucian M. Ashworth, Duncan Bell and Peter Marcus Kristensen for com-
ments on an earlier draft and Stefan Kristiansen for extensive help with a survey (see Note 33).
2 Charles Augustin Sainte-Beuve, What Is a Classic? Available at: http://classiclit.about.com/
library/bl-etexts/csaintebeuve/bl-csaintebeuve-classic.htm (accessed 12 September 2012), first
published as ‘Qu-est-ce qu’un classique?’, Le Constitutionnel, 21 October 1850; Frank Kermode,
The Classic: Literary Images of Permanence and Change, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press, [1975] 1983, p. 15.
3 Fay Weldon, ‘Today’, BBC Radio 4, 8 August 2012.
4 Sainte-Beuve, What Is a Classic?, pp. 1–4.
5 T. S. Eliot, What Is a Classic?, London: Faber & Faber, 1944, pp. 7–32; Kermode, The
Classic, pp. 37–38.
6 Kermode, The Classic, p. 43.
7 Kermode, The Classic, p. 117. Eliot contended that a classic is a work that becomes the voice
of something lasting, of lasting importance – as Virgil became ‘the voice of timeless Empire’.
Eliot’s understanding of Empire defies easy comprehension. It is a religio-cultural as much as
a political expression.
8 Kermode, The Classic, p. 44.
9 Ezra Pound, ABC of Reading, New York: New Directions Publishing, [1934] 2011, pp. 13–14.
10 Italo Calvino, Why Read the Classics?, London: Penguin Classics, [1980] 2009, pp. 3–10.
11 See Kermode, The Classic, pp. 133–34.
12 Kermode, The Classic, pp. 75, 121 and 134.
13 See e.g. Martin Wight, International Theory: The Three Traditions (ed. Gabriele Wight and
Brian Porter), London: Leicester University Press, 1991.
14 Ian Clark and Iver B. Neumann (eds), Classical Theories of International Relations, Basing-
stoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 1996.
15 See e.g. Tim Dunne, ‘Mythology or Methodology? Traditions in International Theory’, Review of
International Studies, 1993, vol. 19, 305–18; Ian Clark, ‘Traditions of Thought and Classical
Theories of International Relations’, in Clark and Neumann, Classical Theories, pp. 1–19.
Introduction 11
16 See Barry Buzan, From International to World Society? English School Theory and the Social
Structure of Globalisation, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004; Andrew Linklater
and Hidemi Suganami, The English School of International Relations: A Contemporary
Reassessment, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006.
17 Hedley Bull, ‘International Theory: The Case for a Classical Approach’, World Politics, 1966,
vol. 18, p. 361.
18 Constitutive practices include the kind of questions that get asked, the kind of answers con-
sidered legitimate, the range of methods deemed appropriate, and the types of sources con-
sidered valid. Regulative practices include the methods by which work gets selected for
publication, the means by which publication status is determined, the channels through which
knowledge is disseminated and reproduced, and the processes by which appointments to
professional bodies and editorships are made and research grants awarded.
19 Stephen van Evera, ‘Director’s Statement: Trends in Political Science and the Future of
Security Studies’, MIT Security Studies Program: Annual Report 2009–2010 (2010), p. 4. A
similar critique has also, of course, been levelled against various types of post-positivist
scholarship.
20 Benjamin Cohen, ‘Are IPE Journals Becoming Boring?’, International Studies Quarterly,
2010, vol. 54, 887–91, at p. 887.
21 Ole Wæver, ‘The Sociology of a Not so International Discipline’, International Organization,
1998, vol. 52, 687–727, esp. Figure 3; Ole Wæver and Barry Buzan, ‘After the Return to
Theory: The Past, Present, and Future of Security Studies’, in Alan Collins (ed.), Con-
temporary Security Studies, 2nd edn, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010, pp. 463–83.
22 See also Duncan Bell, ‘Writing the World: Disciplinary History and Beyond’, International
Affairs, 2009, vol. 85, 3–22. We return to question of the state of IR in the Conclusion to this
volume.
23 David A. Lake, ‘Why “Isms” Are Evil: Theory, Epistemology, and Academic Sects as Impe-
diments to Understanding and Progress’, International Studies Quarterly, 2010, vol. 55, 465–80;
Henry R. Nau, ‘No Alternative to “Isms”’, International Studies Quarterly, 2010, vol. 55,
487–91. See also Lucian M. Ashworth, ‘The Poverty of Paradigms: Subcultures, Trading
Zones and the Case of Liberal Socialism in Interwar International Relations’, International
Relations, 2012, vol. 26, 35–59; Duncan Bell, ‘Introduction: Under an Empty Sky – Realism
and Political Theory’, in Bell (ed.), Political Thought and International Relations: Variations
on a Realist Theme, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008, pp. 1–25.
24 Peter Wilson, ‘The Myth of the First Great Debate’, Review of International Studies, 1998,
vol. 24, 1–16; Casper Sylvest, ‘Interwar Internationalism, the British Labour Party and the
Historiography of International Relations’, International Studies Quarterly, 2004, vol. 48,
409–32; Brian Schmidt (ed.), International Relations and the First Great Debate, London and
New York: Routledge, 2012.
25 Ole Wæver, ‘Still a Discipline after all these Debates?’, in Tim Dunne, Milja Kurki and Steve
Smith (eds), International Relations Theories, 2nd edn, Oxford: Oxford University Press,
2010, pp. 297–318. See also Ole Wæver, ‘The Speech Act of Realism: The Move That Made
IR’ in Nicolas Guilhot (ed.), The Invention of International Relations Theory, New York:
Columbia University Press, 2011, pp. 97–127.
26 K. W. Thompson, Masters of International Thought, Baton Rouge, LA: Louisiana State
University Press, 1980; Iver Neumann and Ole Wæver (eds), The Future of International
Relations: Masters in the Making, London: Routledge, 1997; Filippo Andreatta (ed.), Le
Grandi Opere delle Relazioni Internazionali, Bologna: Il Mulino, 2011.
27 Ken Booth, ‘Masterdebating in International Relations’, Millennium: Journal of International
Studies, 1998, vol. 27, 141–44.
28 Steffen Kailitz (ed.), Schlüsselwerke der Politikwissenschaft, Wiesbaden: Verlag für Sozial-
wissenschaften, 2007. Kailitz uses the terms ‘key works’ (Schlüsselwerke) and ‘classics’
(Klassiker) interchangeably.
29 The case for reading works in their context has been forcefully made by the Cambridge
School of Political Thought. See primarily Quentin Skinner, Visions of Politics, Vol. I: On
Method, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002. This and other approaches empha-
sising the importance of context for meaning and understanding have made some impact in
studies of international thought during the last decade.
12 Henrik Bliddal, Casper Sylvest and Peter Wilson
30 Neumann and Wæver pointed out that they did not choose this title, since their aim was not to
‘replace the reading of primary texts by secondary ones’. Neumann and Wæver, The Future of
International Relations, p. 6; Ken Booth, ‘Master-Debating International Relations’, p. 142.
31 We thank Politik and its publisher DJØF Forlag for permission to draw on the articles on
The Great Illusion (an earlier version, Europe’s Great Illusion from 1909, was reappraised),
International Politics in the Atomic Age, Man, the State, and War and Theory of International
Politics. The special issue also contained a chapter on The Twenty Years’ Crisis but the
chapter in this volume does not draw on it.
32 Henrik Bliddal, ‘International Relations Classics Reappraised: The Nines’, Politik, 2009, vol.
12, p. 2.
33 Specifically, we sent them to all scholars in the following institutions: the Department of
International Relations, London School of Economics and Political Science (LSE); the
Department of International Politics, Aberystwyth University, UK; the Department of Poli-
tical Science, University of Copenhagen, Denmark; the Freie Universität Berlin (various
departments and centres), Germany; the Center for International Studies and Research at the
Institut d’études politiques in Paris, France; the Department of Political Science, University
of Chicago, USA; the Woodrow Wilson School of Public and International Affairs and
Department of Politics, Princeton University, USA; and the School of Politics and Interna-
tional Relations at the Australian National University.
34 As brilliantly argued in Wight, International Theory, p. 6.
2 A pillar of air? Norman Angell and
The Great Illusion
Torbjørn L. Knutsen
Few books on international relations can beat the best-selling record of Norman
Angell’s The Great Illusion (TGI).1 It was published in London, UK in 1910 and sold
around two million copies prior to World War I. It then faded from view. Why? A
common explanation is that its thesis was mistaken. Angell’s critics commonly claim
that the book’s main message, that war was now impossible, was disproved by the
outbreak of World War I in 1914. This is a deeply unfair criticism. TGI never claimed
that war was impossible. The book was, in fact, a passionate warning of the dangers of
imminent war. If the statesmen of the West did not change their ways – if they did not
come round to a more sensible view of international affairs – costly wars would erupt.
The argument that supported this message has been part and parcel of the professional
study of International Relations (IR) ever since: in an interdependent world, large-scale
war will bring economic disaster for everybody.
Angell strongly believed that war did not pay. Yet why did so many readers mis-
understand this simple message? Why has the book largely been forgotten today, rather
than hailed as a classic in interdependence theory? In order to answer these questions,
it is useful to begin with the book’s early reception. Its first reviews show that academic
commentators did not misunderstand the book’s basic message. But others did. One
reviewer, T. G. Martin, noted that the book’s most eager fans also appeared to be the
greatest distorters of its message.2 This observation, that the most committed peace activists
tended to read the book the most selectively, suggests one reason why TGI has been so
misunderstood: it is a book of many messages. Different readers have found different
points and meanings in it.
The first chapter of the book introduces the reader to the core idea around which its
argument is built: that during the second half of the nineteenth century, the industrial
states of the world went through an evolution that made them dependent on each other
for trade and finance. War among the great powers would cause this network of inter-
dependence to unravel, and bring the entire economic system down. Subsequent chap-
ters introduce other ideas that add greater complexity to the thesis. One such addition
is that language shapes our perception of the world. Upon this argument hinges the
very concept of ‘illusion’ in the book’s title. Through it Angell infers that if people were
provided with a new vocabulary better able to capture the realities of an interdependent
world, then they would also more easily understand and adapt to the political realities
of that world. This notion of ‘adaptation’ – a notion which is grafted onto a social-
evolutionary outlook – plays a crucial role in the book. Ideas such as these – inter-
dependence, adaptation and the effects of language on politics – are all central to TGI.
They are also an integral part of twentieth-century IR. In this sense, a study of TGI is
14 Torbjørn L. Knutsen
also an exercise in disciplinary history, as it involves the early use of some of the key
terms and theories in IR.
This chapter will first draw a quick sketch of the book’s author. It will then present the
structure and the argument in this important but much-misunderstood and over-
looked IR classic. The chapter will close with an examination of the three concepts
that carry the book’s argument – interdependence, adaptation and the formative effects
of language.
The author
Ralph Norman Angell Lane was born in 1872. He was an inquisitive and precocious
child and rebelled against the inhibitive conventions of Victorian society. Upon com-
pleting elementary school in England he travelled abroad. He went to secondary school
in France, returned to London to attend business school, and then spent a year in
Geneva. During his formative years he read works that exposed ‘the world’s injustices,
miseries, and follies’3 – Voltaire, Thomas Paine, J. S. Mill, Charles Kingsley, William
Morris and Herbert Spencer foremost among them.
At the age of 18 he decided that Europe was spent, so he emigrated to the New
World. In 1891 he travelled to the USA and set himself up as a homesteader in the
Wild West to lead a ‘simple life’.4 He worked at different jobs to make ends meet,
among them prospecting, cattle-herding, vine-planting, well-digging, mail-carrying and
book-keeping. He ended up as a newspaper reporter on the San Francisco Chronicle
and, later, the St. Louis Globe-Democrat.
The book
One reason for the success of the book was that it rode the wave of a burgeoning peace
movement. It greatly stimulated discussions on the causes of war and the preconditions
for peace. Another reason was Angell himself. His books may have catapulted him to
fame, but his charm, sharp wit and boundless energy sustained it. He quickly became a
peace activist of note and a public intellectual known for his lecture tours and pro-
nouncements on contemporary affairs. He lent his name to peace clubs and anti-war
16 Torbjørn L. Knutsen
organizations. Although he rode the wave of the peace movement, he also exerted a
formative force on it.
A third reason for the book’s success was that its author was backed by powerful
sponsors. One of them was Viscount Esher, the chairman of the British Committee of
Imperial Defence. He was impressed by Europe’s Optical Illusion and sent copies to
many of his influential friends. He wrote to Angell and intimated that the book might
be as important for the field of Political Science as Darwin’s Origin of Species had been
for biology.7 If Angell was willing to expand on his analysis, Esher continued, it might
be possible to provide him with financial support and some secretarial assistance.
When Angell expressed interest in the proposal, Esher asked some of England’s wealthy
industrialists to sponsor him. A fund was established in the name of one of them, Sir
Richard Garton. Backed by the Garton Foundation for Encouraging the Study of
International Policy Angell could afford to devote himself to the study of international
affairs and to write TGI.
Esher, Garton and other industrialists agreed that war was bad for business. They
were attracted to Angell’s argument because it distanced itself from the religious rea-
soning and pacifism that had traditionally dominated the anti-war movement. TGI was
not a moralist tract, but an appeal to common sense and scientific argument. It drew
on economic theories of trade and finance to procure the key concept of inter-
dependence, and it invoked current theories of social evolution to develop an argument
of adaptation. Such arguments dovetailed nicely with the orientation of the British
business community. In 1913 the Garton Foundation sponsored the establishment of War
and Peace: A Norman Angell Monthly – one of the world’s first journals of international
affairs.
The conclusion
Part One of TGI argues that war is an irrational act in an interdependent world. War is
futile. It no longer pays. Part Two adds that world’s leaders do not seem to understand
this. Instead, they persist in viewing world affairs in the obsolete and illusive terms of
power politics. They have failed to adapt to the changing realities of world affairs. Part
Three of the book assesses the political implications of these arguments and affords a
piece of good advice for the statesmen of the world – especially for British leaders, to
whom Angell proposes a more updated and sensible foreign policy agenda. The UK
may well build battleships and introduce conscription. However, this must not be pre-
sented as preparation for war, but rather as preparation to prevent war. There is always
a danger that such preparations may be misperceived and thus increase political ten-
sion. Therefore this agenda must be accompanied by a campaign to combat the ‘great
illusion’ of the age and alter the knowledge of politicians and the popular opinion.
The eponymous great ‘illusion’ is, then, a collectively held, cognitive perspective
sustained by an obsolete terminology that prevents statesmen and scholars from seeing
the world as it really is. British, French, German and US statesmen recreate or recon-
stitute this dangerous ‘great illusion’ whenever they think and talk about world affairs.
Whenever they discuss order and security in their old and obsolete terms, they
reconfirm their erroneous ideas of interstate struggles and military fitness. As a
consequence, they actually make the world less safe. This ‘illusion’ can only be dis-
pelled by education. Since human nature is plastic and malleable, humans can learn
and develop new knowledge that will change their ways and help them adapt to new
realities. If collective superstitions and falsehoods have been dispelled in the past, then
systematic education can purge present illusions and replace them with accurate,
fact-based knowledge.
Angell on adaptation
Angell’s argument of interdependence has attracted much attention. His elegant skew-
ering of social Darwinism, however, has been largely forgotten. Yet, Angell’s argument
of adaptation, more affected by Spencer than by Darwin, may be both the more ori-
ginal and the more elegant part of his book. The way Angell invoked the concept of
adaptation to demonstrate the logical inconsistency of power politics is polemically
brilliant. First, he identified the basic assumptions of traditional realpolitik – a con-
stant view of human nature and a view of politics as a power struggle. Then he
demonstrated their flaws. Finally, he presented an alternative and progressive view of
human history. His argument was simple: ‘Man’s irresistible drift away from conflict
and towards co-operation is but the complete adaptation of the organism (man) to its
environment (the planet, nature)’ (p. 163). In the distant past, war might have served
some purpose of group cohesion or the acquisition of land and loot. But no more. In
the age of industrialism and interdependence conquest and war are destructive activ-
ities for the human species. The establishment of organizations and institutions for
solidarity and cooperation, by contrast, are constructive. They increase humanity’s
chance of survival and further the evolution of the human species. Solidarity and
cooperation fuel the evolution of industry, of productive economies and of rising
wealth and prosperity. They make relations among states steadily more peaceful and
orderly.11
This was a seductive view for progressives. However, it ran into difficulties early in
the twentieth century. The outbreak of World War I showed that Angell’s view relied
on an excessively optimistic notion of unilinear progress. For although the industrial
states clearly grew more interdependent during the final quarter of the nineteenth cen-
tury, this growth did not continue into the twentieth. It unravelled during World War I.
Angell was quick to spot this flaw when war erupted in 1914 and he promptly amended
his views. Before the war, he had argued that ‘when nations realised the futility of
conquest, they would just drop the effort’.12 After the war he adopted a more practical
view. In the 1933 edition of TGI he advocated an international arrangement of collec-
tive security – a ‘conscious international organization of power’. Angell repeated the
claim in his interwar essay ‘The International Anarchy’ – where the title as well as the
text is rife with realist allusions.13
An assessment
TGI marked the beginning of Angell’s extraordinary and prolific writing career. During
the next four decades he published over 40 books on international affairs. He addressed
a variety of themes but tended to orbit the key themes of interdependence, adaptation
and the formative effect of language on politics and society. These themes provided the
core of an approach which was popularly referred to as ‘Norman Angellism’. Prior to
World War I this approach stirred debates about the causes of war and the precondi-
tions for peace. It inspired a great number of clubs and organizations. More than 100
peace groups, International Politics clubs, Norman Angell leagues and war and peace
societies sprang up in Great Britain during the years leading up to World War I. TGI
thrust Angell into the spotlight. The book was translated into at least 25 languages
over the years. It comprehensively addressed the problems of its age. It offered a new
perspective on the strife and the mounting tensions in an interdependent world. It
sustained Angell’s fame for years – it was instrumental in earning him a knighthood in
1931 and the Nobel Peace Prize in 1933. Yet, although it was republished in new edi-
tions after World War I, it steadily faded from view.
Norman Angell: The Great Illusion 21
Why has this book largely been forgotten rather than hailed as a classic? It is
tempting to borrow a line from Alan Ginsburg who explained the sudden rise and
popularity of Bob Dylan in the early 1960s, by referring to him as ‘a pillar of air’; as an
artist of striking originality, great talent and passion but with a message so general,
vague and plastic that it appealed to the tastes of many audiences and suited many
political purposes. Angell, like Dylan, produced striking and passionate work. Both
delivered many messages – some of them vague, some of them working at cross-pur-
poses, yet connected to the main issues of the age. Thus, one important reason why
TGI has been forgotten is that although the book is striking and insightful, it suffers
from prolixity. It purports to address the problem of war, but its initial analysis of the
Anglo-German arms race quickly fractures into colourful discussions of free trade,
property rights, colonialism, conquests and confiscations. It is not a laser but a prism.
The book is a veritable tour d’horizon of the international scene of its times. This was
undoubtedly part of its success. However, it was also its biggest problem. For as Angell
spun out his argument, his simple, initial notion of interdependence was pulled in many
directions.16 This made its core argument hard to pin down. Different readers came
away with different views about the prospects for war and the preconditions for peace.
Thus, the book lent itself to various interpretations.
Another reason for the book’s fading from memory is that it was quickly eclipsed by
a wave of more scholarly competitors. Following the outbreak of war in 1914, a torrent
of books was published that addressed the causes of war and preconditions for peace.
Compared to these new, more academic discussions, TGI appeared more like a
pamphlet than a sustained, scholarly analysis. Angell, like Thomas Paine, was sharp,
engaging and persuasive. However, he lacked the time, the patience and the scholarly
tools to develop careful theoretical arguments. In 1910 TGI was a fresh approach that
appealed to common sense, economic theories of trade and finance and Spencer’s
sociology of development. However, the book was written by a skilled journalist and
was hardly a work of academic scholarship. It refers to old authors like Smith and Mill
often enough, but the references are sweeping and they support the argument of inter-
dependence only in the most general of terms.17 It omits contemporary economists and
lawyers who also discuss interdependence. When Angell needed support for his argu-
ments, he invariably drew on newspapers rather than academic books and scholarly
journals. Thus, he refers to the famous journalist and editor William T. Stead who had
gauged the implications of interdependence on military affairs, but he omits any men-
tion of Ivan Bloch, upon whose original work Stead relied.18 By 1920 Angell’s lustre
faded as other authors emerged – academicians who drew on history, law and the new
social sciences and whose investigations contributed to the founding of IR as a scholarly
discipline.19
TGI played a role in this founding of IR, but it was indirect. When the book was
published in 1910, it greatly excited the international peace movement, and fuelled a
popular debate about the causes of war and the preconditions for peace. It contributed
massively to a debate that provided wide interest in and a boost to the scholarly study
of international affairs. However, Angell was a journalist and a peace activist who
worked the public sphere. He read and wrote for newspapers and popular journals and
did not really connect with the growing academic IR community. Once the new scholarly
field was established, Angell remained outside of it.
A final reason for the fading of TGI is that its argument was superseded by events.
World War I severed the trade networks that Angell relied on for his economic
22 Torbjørn L. Knutsen
argument. The Great War was succeeded by the Great Depression, which unravelled
the webs of trade and finance even further. Then came World War II. In the wake of
such events the concept of interdependence lost its purchase on world affairs and much
of its appeal. Following World War II it took a generation to rebuild the global webs of
interaction. Only during the 1970s did the world regain an international transaction
density that approached pre-World War I levels. When it did, the interdependence
argument resurfaced in IR scholarship. By then, however, its long history – and
Angell’s formative role in it – was largely forgotten.
There are many reasons why TGI was shifted onto a track towards oblivion rather
than towards the IR Hall of Fame. Some will argue that the main responsibility for this
lies with Angell, who struggled in vain to formulate a clear and parsimonious argu-
ment. Others will argue that the responsibility lies with an audience who misinterpreted
the book and misunderstood its message. That it was particularly misunderstood by its
most eager fans, may seem to give an ironic touch to the book’s impact history. In fact,
it rather confirms Angell’s central thesis – namely, that most people are set in their
ways and selective in their perceptions and would rather cleave to habit and old outlooks
than change their views.
Notes
1 Norman Angell, The Great Illusion: A Study of The Relation of Military Power in Nations to
their Economic and Social Advantage, London: William Heinemann, 1910. Page numbers
placed in parentheses in the text refer to this edition.
2 T. G. Martin, ‘The Illusions of Norman Angell’, War and Peace, 1913, vol. 1, p. 22.
3 Norman Angell, After All, New York: Farrar, Straus and Young, 1951, p. 8.
4 Angell, After All, pp. 24ff. The story of Angell’s extraordinary life is more reliably told in
Martin Ceadel, Living the Great Illusion, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009.
5 Ralph Lane, Patriotism under Three Flags, London: T. Fisher Unwin, 1903.
6 Norman Angell, Europe’s Optical Illusion, London: Simpkin, Marshall, Hamilton, Kent,
1909. See Torbjørn L. Knutsen, ‘Norman Angell and Europe’s Optical Illusion’, Tidsskriftet
Politik, vol. 12, 5–10.
7 Angell, After All, p. 163.
8 It was Herbert Spencer who coined the famous quip about ‘the survival of the fittest’ (see e.g.
Herbert Spencer, Principles of Biology. Vol. I, New York: D. Appleton & Co, [1864] 1871, pp.
444ff.). Spencer, like Angell, did not equate ‘fitness’ with ‘strength’. Angell writes mockingly
that the advocates of realpolitik use a language that may be suitable for discussions of train-
ing studios, but not to debates on evolution.
9 Torbjørn L. Knutsen, ‘A Lost Generation? IR Scholarship before World War I’, International
Politics, 2008, vol. 45, 650–74.
10 In his The Struggle for Bread (London: Bodley Head, 1912) Victor W. Germains protested
Angell’s claim that conquest never pays. William Fullerton argued that Angell entertained the
simplistic notion that war was triggered by greed and misperception (William Morton Full-
erton, The Problem of Power, New York: Charles Scribners’ Sons, 1913).
11 Angell relies on examples from Charles Darwin (Descent of Man, New York: Barnes &
Noble, [1871] 2001, p. 112) to prove his point. However, it is Spencer’s sociology that provides
the logic of his argument, and it is Spencer who is quoted to account for the transition from
militant to industrial stages of social evolution when war no longer pays (cf. Herbert Spencer,
Political Institutions, London: Williams and Norgate, pp. 208ff., 253ff.). See also Casper Syl-
vest, British Liberal Internationalism, 1880–1930, Manchester: Manchester University Press,
2009, pp. 106ff., 214ff.
12 Norman Angell, TGI, London: William Heinemann, 1933, pp. 369ff.
13 Norman Angell, ‘The International Anarchy’, in Leonard Woolf (ed.), The Intelligent Man’s
Way to Prevent War, London: Victor Gollancz, 1933, pp. 19–67.
Norman Angell: The Great Illusion 23
14 Angell, Europe’s Optical illusion, p. 41.
15 E. H. Carr, The Twenty Years’ Crisis, New York: Palgrave Macmillan, [1939] 2001, p. 28.
16 This problem increased with time, as Angell tried to clarify his arguments in a steady stream
of new editions of the book, but with little success. He had a tendency, as he recognized later
in life, to delve into ‘side issues and incidental matters arising in the course of the discussion’
and to leave the main claims either buried or underdeveloped (quoted in Ceadel, Living The
Great Illusion, p. 103).
17 TGI invoked several ‘classical’ thinkers – Aristotle, Grotius, Nietzsche and Renan to name a
few. Their names, however, are merely noted in passing. They add little to the argument of
the book and largely serve as academic décor. Angell cites Adam Smith and J. S. Mill and
other liberal classics to substantiate his theory of interdependence, but he does not cite See-
bohm or Lorimer or others who had in fact employed the term ‘interdependence’ to discuss
changes in world trade and international law a generation earlier.
18 Alfred Fried, the founder of the German Peace Society, noticed Angell’s lack of academic
rigour and scholarly connections at once. He wrote to Angell and pointed out that TGI
overlooked the works of Bloch, Novicow and other scholars whose arguments would support
Angell’s larger point. Angell was grateful for the tip, and added brief references to these
authors in later editions of his book (Ceadel, Living The Great Illusion, p. 111).
19 Among these authors were John Hobson, Leonard Woolf, G. Lowes Dickinson, Alfred Zimmern,
David P. Heatley, S. H. Allen and James Bryce (see Knutsen, ‘A Lost Generation?’).
3 A democratic critique of the state: G. Lowes
Dickinson’s The European Anarchy
Jeanne Morefield
The world is divided politically into States. These States are a kind of abstract
being, distinct from the men, women, and children who inhabit them. They are in
perpetual and inevitable antagonism to one another … That being so, war is an
eternal necessity.27
Dickinson’s parody here suggested there was nothing ‘factually’ true about the state
form. In the spirit of early twentieth-century pluralism, he both acknowledged that
states were powerful political organizations but also insisted that they were abstrac-
tions, legal fictions, real but also ‘distinct’ from the human beings that comprised
them.28 Speaking in the voice of an impatient realist, tut-tutting at the pacifist’s
inability to grasp the imperilled heart of the situation, Dickinson suggests that this
fictive form of international political organization had become so naturalized that
alternatives to its logic looked like an affront to the ‘facts’ of the world.
28 Jeanne Morefield
Dickinson’s argument in The War and the Way Out spoke volumes about the plur-
alist direction of his international thought at the very beginning of the war. However,
the argument itself was based largely on Dickinson’s intuitions about the international
climate. Dickinson himself later admitted that he had ‘made, at the time, no special
study of international relations’ and to the reader it is clear that the argument itself falls flat in
a number of places.29 This lack of rigour was a problem that Dickinson himself clearly
understood and which he spent the next two years addressing by engaging in a careful study
of the ‘circumstances and events’ that led up to the war. In the process, he took his
largely unformed ‘governmental theory’ and translated it into a more nuanced analysis
of the relationship between sovereignty and what he now termed the international anarchy.
The result was EA, which can be understood as Dickinson’s test drive of the histor-
ical methodology and conceptual apparatus he later used to write IA, a work he
described to a friend as ‘a more serious and laboured book’.30 Dickinson clearly saw
EA as his first foray into the study of international politics and as an attempt to fuse
the core intuition of his anti-war writings (that ‘Europe had long been a powder
magazine’) with a historical inquiry that focused on the events leading up to the war.31
In this spirit, Dickinson mined sources as diverse as diplomatic cables and the private
letters of foreign correspondents, from both combatants and neutral states alike, for
insight into the way domestic populations, diplomats, the press and statesmen under-
stood the build-up to the conflict.32 The goal of this inquiry was, first, to refute the
predominant nationalist interpretation that blamed the war entirely on German
aggression. More importantly, however, the book aimed to demonstrate that leaders in
the UK, France and Germany alike all believed, in the years leading up to the war,
that the intentions of other states were aggressive and that their own state’s protection
required military and territorial expansion. Dickinson’s historical dissection of avail-
able materials suggested, in contrast, that the war was a by-product of sovereign state
aggression combined with an international system constructed around sovereign states.
War emerged from the ‘normal working of the European anarchy,’ where everything
jingoistic, aggressive and violent about states went unconstrained by any higher power
or law (p. 105).
The notion of international anarchy that Dickinson developed in this text was
explicitly indebted to Hobbes. As Hobbes noted in The Leviathan, in ‘the condition of
mere nature’, self-interested and pugnacious individuals will fall into a state of ‘anar-
chy’ characterized by a perpetual ‘war of all against all’, a condition that only ends
with the creation of the forceful sovereign state.33 However, in the international realm,
anarchy never ends. ‘Persons Artificial’ remained in a state of perfect liberty in rela-
tionship to each other and therefore in a state of constant war or the threat of war
‘with their frontiers armed, and canons planted against their neighbours round
about’.34 Dickinson argued similarly that where there was an ‘aggregation of states’
relating to each other in the absence of common law and common force, then ‘there
will be what Hobbes truly asserted to be the essence of such a situation, a chronic state of
war, open or veiled’ (p. 14). For Dickinson, because the motivation behind the ideology
of statehood was the aggrandizement of the state itself, because there were no ethical
and legal limits on this aggrandizement, and because nothing succeeds like success, all
states could and eventually would fall before the logic of expansion and jingoism. ‘It is
not only the jingoism of Germany that Europe has to fear’, he argued, ‘it is the jingo-
ism that success may make supreme in any country that may be victorious’ (p. 132).
Under conditions where states have no incentive but to behave aggressively, peace itself
G. Lowes Dickinson: The European Anarchy 29
was merely ‘latent war’, during which time states armed themselves in a manner they
might argue was intended to be defensive but which was always motivated by the
underlying aggression of raison d’état. When overt war broke out ‘some one state’ might
be the ‘immediate offender’, argued Dickinson, but the ‘main and permanent offence is
common to all states. It is the anarchy which they are all responsible for perpetuating’
(ibid.).
Dickinson’s use of Hobbes here is interesting and slightly counterintuitive. He was
not a Hobbes scholar and it is clear from both his published writings and his papers
that he never wrote about Hobbes outside of EA and IA. More importantly, as a
humanist with a deep and abiding faith in people’s capacity for critical reason, Dick-
inson’s notion of human nature could not have been more different from that of
Hobbes who believed that individuals themselves were always motivated by the self-
oriented, expansive desires identical to those that Dickinson ascribes to states. By
contrast, Dickinson’s patent refusal to theorize about human nature beyond what he
saw as the basic desire of human beings to seek the good was one of the most out-
standing features of his personality and his scholarship, and perhaps what most differ-
entiated his ontological impulses from both Hobbes and those of later human nature
realists such as Morgenthau. In the words of George Santayana, Dickinson ‘prayed,
watched, and labored to redeem human life, and began by refusing to understand what
human life is’.35 In effect, this refusal to ‘understand’ human life meant that Dickinson
never believed war to be the inevitable result of something inherently violent or self-
absorbed in human nature.36 The question for Dickinson was not ‘why do people
fight?’ in a general sense but, rather, ‘how do organized political communities enable
fighting?’ We could be ‘social animals’, we could even be driven by a ‘herd’ instinct
arising from some residual, primitive sense of family. That, however, was a question
‘for biologists to settle’. All we know about people, Dickinson argued, is that they are
creators of institutions and communities that sometimes ‘shape’ individuals into forms
that can become dangerous.37 War, argued Dickinson, ‘is not a fatal product of human
nature. It is an effect of that nature when put under certain conditions’, namely, the
conditions of sovereign statehood.38
It is equally curious that Dickinson was writing about Hobbes’s understanding of
anarchy well before Hobbes had become an iconic figure of twentieth-century IR.39 So,
whence came Dickinson’s reading of Hobbes? While it is possible that he might have
been imitating a language already brought into limited circulation in the USA during
this time by scholars of international law, Dickinson did not mention such influences.40
Rather, it is more likely, given his intellectual inclinations and circles, that his reading
of Hobbes was influenced by the historical sensibilities of the English pluralists such as
Laski who identified Hobbes with the historical emergence of a particularly modern
theory of the monistic, juridical state.41
Dickinson’s use of Hobbes in EA was similarly historical and similarly critical. He
evoked Hobbes in the earliest pages of the book in the same paragraph in which he
located the origins of modern international conflict in a particular historical moment.
In a manner as grave and rhetorically bombastic as Rousseau’s claim that the origins of
inequality could be found in the actions of the first man to enclose a plot of land and
then ‘take it into his head to say this is mine’, Dickinson identified the ‘turning point’ in
the ‘great and tragic history of Europe’ with ‘the emergence of the sovereign State at the
end of the fifteenth century’ (p. 13). Dickinson labelled the theory behind this emer-
gence ‘Machiavellianism’ because it took the state as both the end and means of
30 Jeanne Morefield
politics. The combination of this state-oriented theory, Dickinson argued, with the
deepening historical involvement of European nations in expansive colonial projects
during the sixteenth century produced an international political environment char-
acterized primarily by the ‘mutual aggression and defense of beings living in a “state of
nature”’(p. 16).
There is, then, nothing transcendental or ahistorical about Dickinson’s use of
Hobbes in EA. Unlike later IR theorists, Dickinson turned to Hobbes’ description of
the ‘chronic state of war’ not to provide him with an essentialized account of the state
as it naturally is but, rather, to understand better why states – and the populations they
contain – behave the way they do under modern historical conditions. For Dickinson,
Hobbes’ observations on the anarchic nature of international politics were descriptively
correct while his ontological assumptions about human nature were wrong. Thus, the
international anarchy was never, for Dickinson, a fait accompli. Rather, it was always
potentially subject to the transformative interventions of human beings themselves.
Conclusion
While Dickinson’s critique of sovereignty and its relationship to international anarchy
in EA is highly suggestive, it should be noted that in some ways it is not entirely
coherent. For instance, Dickinson argued throughout EA that modern states were
moved by a basic ‘will to power’ and that, in the context of an international system
unable to check that power, war was inevitable. However, it is never entirely clear from
Dickinson’s writings why modern states behaved this way. For Hobbes and Mor-
genthau, states reflected the self-oriented nature of human beings, a conclusion that
Dickinson, as a humanist, rejected. By contrast, Dickinson’s analysis reversed this
causation, casting modern states as the reason why human beings acted aggressively
rather than imagining states as mirror images of human nature. Dickinson’s critique
located the aggressive tendencies of states in a particularly modern historical moment
and thus resisted attempts to naturalize either the state or human nature. However, he
never fully explained why it is that, since Machiavelli, the ideology of raison d’état has
reigned supreme. It is also not clear from his analysis how a people, thoroughly con-
ditioned by the jingoism and violence of state ideology, could purge themselves of their
‘prejudices and preconceptions’ (p. 17) and transform their politics. Thus, it is not
entirely surprising that, during the last century, IR scholars have tended to use the term
‘international anarchy’ as a place-holder for their own interpretations of the interna-
tional system rather than wrestle with Dickinson’s more internally complicated and
often conceptually messy critique of the state.
In addition, the actual policy details of Dickinson’s first solution for solving the
problems of international anarchy (the creation of international institutions) were both
far milder than, and strangely out of sync with, the audacity of his call for ‘a radical
change’ in the spirit of international politics that would broaden the ambit of demo-
cratic accountability (p. 136). Dickinson thus argued, for instance, that states must
relinquish some of their sovereignty in order to create a ‘kind of machinery for settling
their disputes and organizing their common purposes’ (p. 152), but the shape of that
machinery remained remarkably vague in EA. Indeed, this language of ‘machinery’
itself resonated squarely with the way that mainstream, liberal members of the League
of Nations Union (none of whom were interested in a radical transformation of
sovereignty) also talked about the post-war world.46 However, even the least mainstream
aspect of Dickinson’s institutional proposals – his suggestion that this international
G. Lowes Dickinson: The European Anarchy 33
body serve as ‘a real and effective counterpoise to aggression from any Power in the
future’ by maintaining international peace ‘by force’ (p. 152) – seems, oddly, to reproduce
the very problem of sovereignty on a global level. In other words, it is not clear from
Dickinson’s analysis why an interstate body with the capacity to ‘overawe’ its members
in a Hobbesian sense would behave any less aggressively or would warp human nature
any less than a body aimed at ‘overawing’ its citizens on a domestic level.
In the final analysis, then, it is not Dickinson’s specific ideas about international
institutions but, rather, his more general call for a disruption of the theory of democ-
racy that situated accountability within the inward looking purview of the sovereign
state, which makes EA both a prescient and enduringly suggestive text for our time.
Since sovereign states tended to rationalize power in their own interest and condition
their citizens to do likewise, the only real ‘guarantee of peace’ Dickinson argued, lay in
the democratization of foreign policy. Together with a few other radicals at the time
associated with the Union of Democratic Control, Dickinson argued in EA that the
sheath of sovereign authority (adumbrated by the power of secret diplomacy), which
surrounded the modern state must become more porous to the democratic will of its
citizens thus empowering these citizens to not only guide foreign policy but to hold
their own states accountable for violations of international law. Only this, he argued,
would render international law itself more than ‘a cobweb stretched before the mouth
of a cannon’ (p. 142). In this sense, Dickinson’s work prefigured that of contemporary
cosmopolitan theorists such as David Held who similarly push the notion of demo-
cratic accountability beyond the state, as well as that of pluralists like William Con-
nolly who strive to decentralize our democratic imaginary in a globalized world by
insisting upon a ‘compromise of sovereignty in both its “internal” and “external”
manifestations’.47 While, disappointingly, EA never theorized what such a ‘compro-
mise’ might look like, Dickinson’s work stands as an early gesture towards the possi-
bility of an international politics in which global citizens are able to hold individual
states to account for their actions in the world. And, in an era of WikiLeaks, when the
aggressive, non-democratic, violent practices of states are increasingly visible to all,
Dickinson’s challenge to ‘secret diplomacy’ and his push for democratic control of
international politics seems both more necessary and possible than ever. If we under-
stand a classic to be a work of enduring interest and relevance for our times, few texts
in the history of contemporary IR match EA.
Notes
1 E. M. Forster, Goldsworthy Lowes Dickinson, New York: Harcourt Brace, 1934, p. 173.
2 Goldsworthy Lowes Dickinson, The European Anarchy, London: Macmillan, 1916. Page
numbers placed in parentheses in the text refer to this edition.
3 See Ian Hall, ‘World Government as Empire: The International Historian as Theorist’,
International Affairs, 2006, vol. 82, p. 1161.
4 Memoir of Goldsworthy Lowes Dickinson published by King’s College, January 1933. See
The Papers of Goldsworthy Lowes Dickinson, King’s College, Cambridge, hereafter King’s/
PP/GLD/6/10/Bibliographia/fol.17. Thanks to King’s for allowing me access to the papers.
5 Hedley Bull, ‘Sovereignty and Anarchy in International Relations’, in Herbert Butterfield and
Martin Wight (eds), Diplomatic Investigations: Essays in the Theory of International Politics,
London: Allen and Unwin, 1966, p. 35; Hedley Bull, The Anarchical Society, New York:
Columbia University Press, 1977, p. 47.
6 Martin Wight, International Theory: Three Traditions, New York: Holmes and Meier, 1991, p. 7.
7 Kenneth Waltz, Man the State and War, New York: Columbia University Press, 1959, p. 10.
34 Jeanne Morefield
8 John Mearsheimer, The Tragedy of Great Power Politics, Chicago, IL: University of Chicago
Press, 2001, p. 21. See also B. I. Plank, ‘Goldsworthy Lowes Dickinson and the Causes of
War: A Theoretical and Historical Analysis’, PhD, LSE, 2011.
9 Bull, ‘Society and Anarchy’, p. 38.
10 G. Lowes Dickinson, The Autobiography of G. Lowes Dickinson, ed. Dennis Proctor, London:
Duckworth, 1973, p. 190.
11 G. Lowes Dickinson, The War and the Way Out, London: The Chancery Lane Press, 1914, p. 39.
12 See Henry Winkler, The League of Nations Movement in Great Britain, New Brumswich, NJ:
Rutgers University Press, 1952, pp. 16–18; George Egerton, Great Britain and the Creation of
the League of Nations, Chapel Hill, NC: University of North Carolina Press, 1978, p. 8.
13 Michael Smith, Realist Thought From Weber to Kissinger, Baton Rouge, LA: Louisiana State
Press, 1986, pp. 55–56.
14 Andreas Osiander, ‘Re-reading Early Twentieth Century IR Theory: Idealism Revisited’,
International Studies Quarterly, 1998, vol. 42, p. 413.
15 See Hedley Bull, ‘The Grotian Conception of International Society’, in Kai Alderson and
Andrew Hurrell (eds), Hedley Bull on International Society, New York: Macmillan, 2000.
16 See G. D. H. Cole, ‘The Nature of the State and Its External Relations’, Proceedings of the
Aristotelian Society, 1915–16, vol. 16; Harold Laski, ‘The Pluralist State’, The Philosophical
Review, 1919, vol. 28; Leon Duguit, Les Transformations du Droit Public, Paris: Armand
Colin, 1913.
17 G. Lowes Dickinson, Letters from a Chinese Official, New York: McClure and Phillips, 1903, p. 15.
18 G. Lowes Dickinson, Justice and Liberty; A Political Dialogue, New York: Doubleday, 1920, p. 132.
19 G. Lowes Dickinson, ‘War and Peace: A Dramatic Fantasia,’ King’s/PP/GLD/4/3/Plays.
20 Brian Schmidt, The Political Discourse of Anarchy, New York: SUNY Albany Press, 1998, p. 160.
21 Forster, Dickinson, p. 159.
22 See Isaac Kramnick and Barry Sheerman’s analysis of Cole and Laski, in Harold Laski: A
Life on the Left, New York: Penguin Press, 1993, p. 251,
23 Casper Sylvest, ‘Beyond the State? Pluralism and Internationalism in Early Twentieth-Century
Britain’, International Relations, 2007, vol. 21, p. 80.
24 Dickinson, The International Anarchy, London: Century, 1926.
25 Dickinson, Autobiography, p. 144.
26 See Catherine Cline ‘British Historians and the Treaty of Versailles’, Albion: A Quarterly
Journal Concerned with British Studies, 1988, vol. 20, p. 46.
27 Dickinson, War and the Way Out, p. 9.
28 The notion of the unified state as a fiction had already been well developed at this time by
Duguit.
29 Dickinson, Autobiography, p. 194.
30 Letter to A. J. Grant, 1926, King’s/PP/GLD/5/11/5/Correspondence/fol.8.
31 Dickinson, Autobiography, p. 194.
32 Dickinson later described his approach to writing EA in characteristically humble terms as
‘right enough, as anyone could easily be right (if that were any good) by merely standing
aloof ’ (letter to A. J. Grant, 1926, King’s/PP/GLD/5/11/5/Correspondence/fol.8).
33 Thomas Hobbes, The Leviathan, Harmondsworth: Penguin Classics, 1985, p. 395.
34 Hobbes, Leviathan, p. 266.
35 George Santayana, My Host the World, London: Cresset Press, 1953, p. 31.
36 Dickinson, Causes of International War, New York: Harcourt Brace and Howe, 1920, p. 9.
37 Dickinson, Causes of International War, p. 10.
38 Dickinson, Causes of International War, p. 16
39 On the discovery of Hobbes as an IR thinker see David Armitage, ‘Hobbes and the Foundations
of Modern International Thought’, in James Tully and Annabel Brett (eds), Rethinking the
Foundations of Modern Political Thought, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006.
40 See Schmidt, Political Discourse of Anarchy, pp. 151–88.
41 Laski, Pluralist State, p. 568.
42 See the chapters by Schmidt, Wivel, and Chong in this volume.
43 For an account of this distinction see Helen Milner, ‘The Assumption of Anarchy in Inter-
national Relations Theory: A Critique’, Review of International Studies, 1991, vol. 17, 67–85.
G. Lowes Dickinson: The European Anarchy 35
Milner does not mention Dickinson in this article and understands the idea of international
anarchy as a strictly post-war phenomenon.
44 IA, p. 27.
45 IA, p. 47.
46 Such as Gilbert Murray, Lionel Curtis, and Alfred Zimmern. For an example of the language
of ‘machinery’ see Zimmern, The League of Nations and the Rule of Law, London: Macmil-
lan, 1936.
47 In particular, see Held’s notion of the ‘most affected’ in his introduction to Global Governance
and Public Accountability, New York: Wiley-Blackwell, 2005. See also William Connolly, ‘Democ-
racy and Territoriality’, in Frederick Dolan and Thomas Dumm (eds), Rhetorical Republic:
Governing Representations in American Politics, Amherst, MA: University of Massachusetts
Press, 1993, p. 250.
4 Attacking Hitler in England:
patriarchy, class and war in Virginia Woolf’s
Three Guineas
Peter Wilson1
‘Scarcely a human being in the course of history has fallen to a woman’s rifle’.2
One of the most original essays on international politics written during the first half of
the twentieth century is not obviously about international politics. Its title, echoing with
a class twist Brecht’s Threepenny Opera,3 gives no clue to its contents. Staple issues
such as diplomacy, the League, sanctions, foreign policy and collective security are not
covered. Its starting point is a simple question: how can we go about preventing war? The
answer it gives is anything but simple: we can only begin to think about this question
once we have reflected on the society and the civilization (hierarchical, patriarchal,
acquisitive and pugnacious) we (or rather men) have constructed. As a mode of writing the
essay defies easy categorization. It is more than a polemical essay but less than a social
or political treatise. As one would expect from one of the most important novelists of the
twentieth century, it is a piece of imaginative writing. Yet it brims with facts, footnotes
and references. Froula describes it as ‘an epistolary essay, a compound public letter’.4
Themes
The subtitle of Three Guineas could be ‘Preventing War from the Woman’s Angle’.5
Interestingly, Virginia Woolf had considered ‘Men Are Like That’ as a possible title,
and the book was serialized in Atlantic Monthly under the Euripidean ‘Women Must
Weep, or Unite Against War’.6 It takes its cue from a letter from a certain gentleman
representing a certain political society asking its recipient (i.e. Woolf) to join that
society, subscribe to its funds and sign a certain manifesto. The letter contains the
question (p. 153): ‘How in your opinion are we to prevent war?’ This is the stimulus for
what follows: a series of ratiocinations on how a woman of a certain class might go
about answering that letter, ‘a letter … perhaps unique in the history of human corre-
spondence, since when before has an educated man asked a woman how in her opinion
war can be prevented?’ (ibid.). Woolf ’s correspondent is middle-aged, educated, com-
fortable, but still socially engaged having not yet settled for the ‘contended apathy of
middle life’ (p. 154). We later learn that he is a lawyer (p. 167), a member of the Eng-
lish Bar (p. 173), and an Oxford graduate (p. 189). In the process of composing her
reply, the author feels compelled to respond first to two further letters that have been
lying unanswered for some time on her desk. The first is from an honorary treasurer
appealing for money to help rebuild a ladies’ college. The second is from an honorary
secretary requesting a subscription to a society dedicated to helping young women find
Virginia Woolf: Three Guineas 37
positions in the professions.7 What on the surface appear to be separate requests are
shown to be highly interdependent. The guinea symbolizes the sum of earned income
the author is eventually prepared to conditionally grant to each.
It is impossible to do justice in a summary to the many layers of meaning and the
complex arguments within Three Guineas. It is undoubtedly the product of a highly
original mind, and part of that originality resides in Woolf ’s rejection of the conven-
tional language of politics and her desire to speak ‘not in any language known to
men’.8 For the student of International Relations (IR) the argument can be presented
in terms of a number of themes. Not all of them pertain to the subject conventionally
understood, but they are all integral to Woolf ’s conviction that war begins at home, in
the social and cultural fabric of society.
3. Power
Women had no power to prevent war. They could not join the armed forces and ‘fight
for peace’. They were not eligible to become members of the stock exchange. They were
barred from the diplomatic service and the higher reaches of the Church. They could
38 Peter Wilson
submit articles and send letters to the newspapers. However, the press was controlled by
men. Since 1919 women could enter the UK civil service and join the Bar. However,
the position of women in these professions was weak and insecure. The daughters of
educated men therefore had no power. Even refusing to work would make no differ-
ence. If men in the legal profession downed tools the country would grind to a halt. If
their female colleagues were to do so the impact would be negligible. Women were thus
weaker than men of their own class. However, they were weaker than working-class
women. At least working-class women could refuse to make shells and bombs in the
munitions factories. The daughters of educated men were the weakest of all classes:
they had no weapons available to them to enforce their will (pp. 165–68).
4. Independent influence
Only with an independent income comes independent influence. From the guinea
earned by educated men sprung all they most valued: wife, children, home and influ-
ence. With the passing in 1870 of the Married Women’s Property Act, allowing married
women to keep their own earnings and accrue capital, the 1918 extension of the fran-
chise to women over 30, and the Sexual Disqualification Removal Act of 1919, women
now had if not a guinea then a sixpence of their own – and the true influence that went
with it (pp. 172–74).
[I]f you insist upon fighting to protect me, or ‘our’ country, let it be understood,
soberly and rationally between us, that you are fighting to gratify a sex instinct
which I cannot share; to procure benefits which I have not shared and probably will
not share; but not to gratify my instincts, or to protect either myself or my country.
For … in fact as a woman, I have no country. As a woman I want no country. As a
woman my country is the whole world (p. 313).
Virginia Woolf: Three Guineas 41
Daughters of educated men could best serve the cause of peace and civilization not by
joining men’s society, in which all that is distinctive about women’s experience and
identity would be lost, but by forming their own Outsiders’ Society. This society would
have no funds, offices, committees, or secretary. It would hold no meetings or con-
ferences. It would require no oaths, but members would bind themselves not to fight
with arms, to refuse to make munitions, to refuse to nurse the wounded, and not to
incite their brothers to fight (pp. 309–10). Outsiders would also commit themselves to
earn their own living, and press for the state to provide a living wage to those whose
profession is marriage and motherhood. This, among other things, would enable the
half-man to become whole – there would be no need for him to grind out his round,
week in week out, to maintain his family. Outsiders would bind themselves to expose
all tyranny, cease all competition, eschew all capital accumulation, and refuse to join
any profession hostile to freedom. Through these means they would help to create a
civilized society that protects cultural and intellectual liberty and teaches its citizens to
hate war (pp. 316–20).
Reception
Three Guineas was published at the height of Woolf ’s lifetime fame and it received
glowing reviews. Agnes Allen described it as a logically remorseless and formidable
critique of ‘male civilization in England’.12 In the view of K. John it was ‘artful, witty
and entertaining’. There was ‘no questioning the justice of Mrs Woolf ’s demands, or the
beauty of her gospel’.13 The Times Literary Supplement described it as a ‘penetrating
discourse upon women’s position in society’ which ‘challenges every thinking mind today’.
It was a ‘brilliant and searching pamphlet’ and its author ‘the most brilliant pamphle-
teer in England’.14 For Theordora Bosanquet, Three Guineas was a ‘revolutionary
bomb of a book’, ‘provocative’, ‘controversial’, ‘visionary’ and ‘prophetic’.15
The praise, however, was not unalloyed. John contended that most women are not
and do not wish to be ‘outsiders’. They do not mind official dress, they ‘glow with
pride in their country’, they ‘love all the red on the map’, and they ‘understand the
pleasure of dominating, and the pleasure of fighting’.16 Woolf too eagerly assumed that
on becoming independent women would want the same things as she wanted. The fact
that among women could be counted anti-suffragists as well as suffragists, fascists as
well as pacifists, was conveniently overlooked. Woolf, in sum, imputed too much emo-
tional, intellectual and political unity to women, even those from the same educated
class.17 Future Poet Laureate, Cecil Day-Lewis, sensed in Woolf ’s refusal to join a
predominantly male peace society, and her call for educated women to remain ‘out-
siders’, a ‘strong whiff of intransigent feminism mingled with the laughing gas of liberal
anarchism’. He found Woolf ’s ‘feminine isolationism’ illogical. If her class was the
weakest of all classes with no weapon to enforce its will, surely it made sense for it to
join forces with working women who did possess a weapon? Moreover, if class society
and war had an economic basis, as she tacitly acknowledged, surely it made sense for
all those, men and women, who were oppressed to join forces in an anti-capitalist, anti-
fascist, and anti-war front?18 Indeed, more than a few eyebrows were raised at Woolf ’s
remedy for war, her non-cooperating and self-abnegating Outsiders’ Society. One cor-
respondent called it a ‘counsel of perfection’.19 The most damning verdict, however,
came from literary critic Q. D. Leavis. ‘Mrs Woolf is not living in the contemporary
world’, she declared. Woolf ’s knowledge of the universities was out of date. Her
42 Peter Wilson
understanding of the ‘modern woman/daughter’ no less the ‘Victorian man/father’ was
based on hearsay not research. As well as being ill-informed her argument was self-
indulgent, bad-tempered and ‘peevishly sarcastic’. Indeed, it was not an argument at all
but ‘a sort of chatty restatement of the rights and wrongs of women of Mrs Woolf ’s
class’. Any unity it possessed was emotional not rational. Her examples were selective.
Her proposals were nebulous. In sum, Three Guineas was an incoherent and irresponsible
work not worthy of serious critical attention.20
Critical legacy
Yet serious critical attention Three Guineas has received in abundance, particularly with
the (re)emergence of the feminist movement in the 1960s, ‘Woolf Studies’ in the 1970s,
and Gender Studies in the 1990s. If anything, the controversy surrounding the book
has intensified, with feminist and gender scholars seeing it as profound, insightful,
path-breaking, prescient, even realistic,21 and more conservative commentators seeing
it as incoherent, contradictory, self-indulgent, naïve and utopian.22 However, such a
binary does not do justice to the vast range of comment and criticism that Three Gui-
neas continues to provoke within these camps as well as between them. It is hard to
think of a volume in the history of social and political studies that has inspired such a
diverse range of critical engagements.
To illustrate this point, there is, in the first place, some debate over the extent to
which Woolf should be considered a political writer. According to her husband, ‘Virginia
was the least political animal that has lived since Aristotle invented the definition’.23
He did not think highly of Three Guineas. In contrast to the vision and intensity of her
novels it was marked by ‘a certain laboriousness and deadness’ and was ‘oppressed by
the weight of its facts and arguments’.24 Virginia Woolf ’s nephew-biographer considered
Three Guineas an aberration and a failure – the former because of her general indif-
ference to politics, the latter because of her tenuous attempt to connect the struggle for
women’s rights with fascism and war.25 Against this Carroll has argued that Woolf was
an intensely political writer, even (indeed especially) in terms of Aristotle’s definition.26
Her indifference was not to politics but ‘politics as usual’: party politics, ‘speechifying’,
and the world of the professional politician. She cultivated indifference to ‘politics as
usual’ as a deliberate policy. Contrary to the view that held sway until the 1970s,
Carroll contends that there is a political philosophy at work, though often in the form
of ‘serpentine insinuations’,27 in all of Woolf ’s writing. It is a political philosophy of
struggle – against an oppressive patriarchal social system. Bell’s assertion of a tenuous
connection between the struggle for women’s rights and fascism and war, betrays a
deep misunderstanding of Woolf ’s outlook on politics. In Carroll’s view the contention
that dictatorship, war and sex domination share the same ultimate source in ‘the force
of the fathers’ should not to be so complacently dismissed.28
A second engagement concerns the form of Three Guineas. There is general agree-
ment that it is a polemic, an attack on patriarchy conducted in words. However, some
contend that from Woolf ’s pen the words form pictures. The impact of her book is
visual as much as intellectual. Amy Lilly argues, for example, that Three Guineas
should be seen as an exhibition of carefully constructed and arranged images. Woolf is
as much curator as author. She guides the reader/viewer through a series of everyday
objects – newspaper cuttings, letters, biographies, photographs – and invites her/him to
scrutinize them from a different/woman’s angle. In doing so she demonstrates the
Virginia Woolf: Three Guineas 43
ubiquity and pervasiveness of patriarchal attitudes and practices, which usually tend to
be ‘seen’ only in their most extreme form, and more ‘abroad’ than ‘at home’. Woolf,
thus, employs the method of the exhibition to get her readers/viewers to see more
acutely. Three Guineas is a book about making hitherto invisible relations between
patriarchy, fascism and war ‘visible to all’.29
A third engagement concerns the place of Three Guineas in feminist writing on peace
and war. It is generally seen as a pioneering exploration of patriarchy and war. Phyllis
Lassner, for example, describes it as ‘the ur-text of feminist anti-war writing’.30 Some
scholars, however, have sought to position it more precisely in the evolution of feminist
thinking. Yael Feldman, for example, argues that feminist thinking on patriarchy and
war was already well established when Woolf came to write Three Guineas. Its impor-
tance resides not in its focus on patriarchy per se (nor in its identification of society as
androcentric) but in its constructivist understanding of patriarchy. Three Guineas was a
revolutionary work that shifted the discourse from its essentialist and ‘maternalist’
origins to a focus on the social construction of ‘male’ and ‘female’ roles. In common
with her feminist predecessors Woolf was confident that the sexes differed in their pro-
pensity to aggression, but she was reluctant to put this down to innate differences.
Rather, she focused on the socio-historical construction of values and identity. While
she did not explicitly reject prevailing ‘biological’ presuppositions, often talking for
example in quasi-Freudian terms of ‘instinct’,31 by looking at the issue sociologically
and historically she put feminist thinking on a new trajectory. Three Guineas is a
gender analysis of peace and war avant la lettre.32
An alternative IR classic?
However, the critical value of the book as disclosed in these and other engagements
should not disguise its many analytical problems. These problems, intriguingly, have
gone unnoticed in feminist IR, which has tended to treat Three Guineas as a landmark
essay or classic without going into much detail.33 From an IR perspective the following
problems are particularly salient. The book contends that competition and jealousy (as
provoked by uniforms, ceremonial dress, medals, titles and other hierarchical symbols
and differentiations) are emotions which ‘have their share in encouraging a disposition
towards war’ (pp. 181, 357). But a disposition is not an action, and having a ‘share’ is
not much use unless we know how big it is.34 It confuses causes of war, reasons for war
and morality of war (pp. 162–63). It confuses an emotional reaction (Owen’s reaction
against war) with a logical argument (the need for armaments to deter aggression).
Woolf, indeed, relies too much on Owen’s cry against war. On the strength of it she
equates being in favour of war with being uncivilized. This leads to all sorts of pro-
blems. She says for example that the professions, because of the way they are con-
structed (breeding competitiveness, jealousy and pugnacity), produce uncivilized people
and therefore war (e.g. pp. 218ff.). However, what we have here, repeated in various
ways throughout the text, is not a logical argument but a false syllogism (war is
uncivilized; the professions are uncivilized; therefore the professions are in favour of/are
connected with/cause war – the precise formulation varies throughout). Allied with this,
Woolf establishes war (and even more broadly ‘fighting’) as an exclusively male activity
primarily through repetition, e.g. of phrases such as ‘the impulses, the motives, or the
morality which leads you [men] to go to war’ (p. 164). This is less an argument than a
mantra.
44 Peter Wilson
Such lack of rigour is also apparent in the repeated association of competition, the
competitive spirit, aggression and ‘fighting’ with war. Woolf seems to be uninterested in
war as a distinct category of human behaviour. There is no recognition of the diversity
of war as a phenomenon, nor of the possibility that different kinds of war may require
different kinds of explanation. War is merely lumped together with a range of compe-
titive behaviours from empire-building to football (e.g. pp. 324–26).35 Similarly, Woolf
makes much of the desire for control, which she describes, but nowhere defines, as an
‘infantile fixation’ (pp. 345–56). However, is there not an element of ‘infantile fixation’
in the desire to subsume a range of subjectively undesirable behaviours under one uni-
form category? It is also important to note from an IR viewpoint that Three Guineas is
almost entirely a ‘second image’ analysis (see Chapter 8 in this volume). The cause of
war is patriarchy – what she called in one of her last essays ‘subconscious Hitlerism’.36
Her remedies include dismantling the arms industry, educating graduates to hate war,
and refusing to take part in any preparations for war. However, does not this pacifist
position leave the state defenceless?37 What does one do about states that are less pro-
gressive, humane and peace-loving than ‘ours’, states with no wish to mend their
patriarchal, hierarchical and bellicose ways? Woolf has no answer. This is one reason
why many of her critics dismissed the book as naïve: it assumes the possibility of some
kind of spontaneous dismantling of all the world’s patriarchal structures.
Yet it would be wrong to dwell on these analytical minuses without mentioning some
of the creative pluses. Three Guineas provides a remarkable insight into the position of
women in British society in the nineteenth and early twentieth centuries. It vividly
reveals the public implications of private subordination, and the many subtle forms
that subordination took. It shows how ill-equipped women were to understand and
contribute to public debate on war and peace as Britain approached its darkest hour.
Yet it is important to note that the women in question here are not all women but
upper-middle-class women: ‘the daughters of educated men class’. Woolf had little
understanding of working-class women and their plight and, according to some, little
sympathy for them.38 Arguably, therefore, her ratiocinations on women and the pre-
vention of war are based on the experience of a small segment of the population. That
said, Berenice Carroll has argued that Woolf ’s unflattering portrayal of working-class
or poverty-stricken characters was not a product of snobbishness or lack of sympathy
but the desire to illustrate graphically what an unforgiving, acquisitive, patriarchal
society does to its victims.39 In addition, it can be contended that Woolf ’s unwillingness
to speak for all women is a token of both her honesty and humility. It is undeniable,
however, that the tone of Woolf ’s comments on the working class and working-class life
is frequently condescending (e.g. pp. 278, 281, 287). In common with many middle-
class progressives of her age (including the English Socialist economists Sydney and
Beatrice Webb and her husband Leonard) she often speaks of the working class as if it
is a biological entity (e.g. pp. 401–02).
This sits uneasily with other more interesting things Woolf has to say about class.
The concept of class features heavily in Three Guineas but although the work replicates
a number of common interwar socialist tropes (e.g. the menace of the arms trade, the
bellicosity of capitalism), her understanding of class is far from Marxist. Indeed, one of
the contributions of the book is to de-reify the notion of social class. Woolf establishes
that both she and her correspondent hail from the same ‘educated class’ and therefore
have similar tastes, values, manners and cultural interests. However, the relative
experiences, education, career prospects and wealth of the male and female members of
Virginia Woolf: Three Guineas 45
this class differ so profoundly as to make the notion of a class little more than an
‘anthropocentric ideology’ (p. 369). Woolf in effect ‘genders’ the notion of class, show-
ing it to be a male construction serving male interests. Acts of de-reification, indeed,
collectively constitute one of the main innovations of the book. Unquestioned institu-
tions (e.g. the family), practices (e.g. the law), and sentiments (e.g. patriotism) are pro-
blematized in terms of their potential contribution to war by providing a view of them
from female eyes (e.g. pp. 155–57). The book vividly illustrates how God, nature, law
and property were invoked in defence of these things, reifying and thus legitimating the
gender discrimination at their core (e.g. pp. 248, 353, 359, 376).
Perhaps above all Three Guineas is path-breaking in feeding a series of conventional
questions (e.g. how can we go about preventing war?) through the prism of gender
awareness. In doing so it raised for the first time a series of novel questions for students
of IR: to what extent should war be seen as a male practice? Is patriotism a masculinist
ideology which legitimizes male possessiveness and dominance? What role does the
state play in the reproduction of male dominance? What is the connection between
patriarchy and war? Three Guineas does not provide convincing answers, but it was the
first book to ask these questions and make the connections.
For this reason it is right to regard Three Guineas as a classic of IR. More precisely
it is an alternative classic, not so much in view of its radical approach but its unortho-
dox form. While Woolf herself regarded it as her ‘book of facts’40 it is far from a work
of social science, even broadly defined. It engages the reader emotionally and aestheti-
cally as much as intellectually. It has more in common with The Third of May 1808,
Guernica, or (even) Et in Arcadia ego than Politics Among Nations or Theory of Inter-
national Politics. It is a pamphlet, an essay, an epistle and, above all, an ambitious and
intricate work of art.
Notes
1 This chapter began as a paper delivered at the ‘Women Thinkers of the Twenty Years’ Crisis’
workshop, University of Limerick, and the British International Studies Association (BISA)
annual conference, University of Cork, December 2006. I am grateful to all those who com-
mented on the paper and especially to Luke Ashworth and Kim Hutchings.
2 Virginia Woolf, Three Guineas, Oxford: Oxford University Press, [1938] 1992, p. 158. Page
numbers placed in parentheses in the text refer to this edition.
3 See Christine Froula, Virginia Woolf and the Bloomsbury Avant-Garde: War, Civilization,
Modernity, New York: Columbia University Press, 2005, p. 399. Unlike the humble penny,
the guinea – the unit of currency in which professional fees and prizes in horse racing were
traditionally fixed – was infused with high social status.
4 In her diary Woolf envisioned Three Guineas as a public letter condensing ‘all the articles that editors
have asked me to write during the last few years – on all sorts of subjects. Shd. Women
smoke. Short skirts. War – & c.’ Froula, Woolf and the Bloomsbury Avant-Garde, p. 260.
5 As suggested by Julia Briggs, Virginia Woolf: An Inner Life, London: Penguin, 2006, p. 311.
6 Briggs, Virginia Woolf: An Inner Life, pp. 331, 490.
7 We learn from Morag Shiach in her explanatory notes (pp. 428–31) that in 1936 Woolf signed
the manifesto of the International Peace Campaign which included the statement: ‘Modern
war and preparations for war are hostile to the arts, and most of all to writing’. In the same
year she was asked to join the committee of patrons of Newnham (women’s) College, which
was launching an appeal to fund new buildings. The society for helping young women find
positions in the professions was probably modelled on the London and National Society for
Women’s Service.
8 The quote, from To the Lighthouse, suggests recognition that not only the institutions of
society are patriarchal but language itself. See Berenice A. Carroll, ‘“To Crush Him in Our
46 Peter Wilson
Own Country”: The Political Thought of Virginia Woolf ’, Feminist Studies, 1978, vol. 4, 117–18;
Jane Marcus, Virginia Woolf and the Languages of Patriarchy, Bloomington, IN: Indiana
University Press, 1987. See also Three Guineas, p. 366 on the ‘need to find new words and
new methods’.
9 The colleges of Girton, Newnham, Lady Margaret Hall and Somerville were founded
between 1869 and 1879.
10 In a letter to E. M. Forster on the eve of the publication of Three Guineas, Woolf wrote ‘We
must attack Hitler in England’. Quoted in Briggs, Virginia Woolf: An Inner Life, p. 485.
11 By this Woolf meant loyalties to traditions, institutions, and professions vis-à-vis people.
12 Agnes Allen, ‘Still a Man’s World’, Saturday Review, 27 August 1938, p. 6.
13 K. John (John Maynard Keynes?), ‘The New Lysistrata’, New Statesman and Nation, 11 June
1938, pp. 995–96.
14 Unsigned review, ‘Women in a World of War’, Times Literary Supplement, 4 June 1938, p. 379.
15 Theodora Bosanquet, review of Three Guineas, Time and Tide, 4 June 1938 (abstracted in
Robin Majumdar and Allen McLaurin (eds), Virginia Woolf: The Critical Heritage, London:
Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1975, pp. 402–03).
16 See similar comments from among others Vita Sackville-West in Brenda R. Silver, ‘Three
Guineas Before and After: Further Answers to Correspondents’, pp. 261–62, and Naomi
Black, ‘Virginia Woolf and the Peace Movement’, p. 192, both in Jane Marcus (ed.), Virginia
Woolf: A Feminist Slant, Lincoln, NE: University of Nabraska Press, 1983.
17 John, ‘The New Lysistrata’, pp. 995–96.
18 C. Day-Lewis, ‘Virginia Woolf: Educated Man’s Daughter’, The New Masses, 9 August 1938,
pp. 22–23.
19 Quoted in Silver, ‘Three Guineas Before and After’, p. 267.
20 Q. D. Leavis, ‘Caterpillars of the Commonwealth Unite!’, Scrutiny, September 1938, pp. 203–14.
21 See e.g. Carroll, ‘Crush Him in Our Own Country’, p. 117.
22 See e.g. Theodore Dalrymple’s unremittingly hostile ‘The Rage of Virginia Woolf ’ in his Our
Culture, What’s Left of It, Chicago, IL: Dee, 2005, pp. 63–76.
23 Leonard Woolf, Downhill All the Way: An Autobiography of the Years 1919–1939, London:
Hogarth Press, 1967, p. 27.
24 Leonard Woolf, The Journey Not the Arrival Matters: An Autobiography of the Years 1939–
1969, London: Hogarth Press, 1967, p. 43.
25 Quentin Bell, Virginia Woolf: A Biography, vol. 2, St Albans: Triad and Paladin, 1976, pp.
204–06.
26 Being capable of and suited to life in the polis; having a sense of good and evil, just and
unjust (Aristotle, The Politics, London: Penguin, 1992, pp. 13, 54, 59–60).
27 Woolf ’s self-description of her approach to conventional politics.
28 Carroll, ‘Crush Him in Our Own Country’, pp. 99–131. For a slightly different take on
Woolf ’s indifference see Hermione Lee, Virginia Woolf, London: Chatto & Windus, pp. 681–82.
29 Amy M. Lilly, ‘Three Guineas, Two Exhibits: Woolf ’s Politics of Display’, Woolf Studies
Annual, vol. 9, 2003, 29–54.
30 In British Woman Writers of World War II: Battlegrounds of their Own, Basingstoke: Pal-
grave Macmillan, 1998, p. 29.
31 The degree to which Woolf anticipated/borrowed/abused Freudian theory is contested. See
Yael S. Feldman, ‘From Essentialism to Constructivism? The Gender of Peace and War –
Gilman, Woolf, Freud’, Partial Answers: Journal of Literature and the History of Ideas, 2004,
vol. 2, 130–39.
32 Feldman, ‘From Essentialism to Constructivism?’, pp. 113–45.
33 See e.g. Cythia Enloe, The Morning After: Sexual Politics at the End of the Cold War, Ber-
keley, CA: University of California Press, 1993, p. 77; Maneuvers: The International Politics
of Militarizing Women’s Lives, Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, 2000, pp. 288–89.
34 See also ibid. pp. 192–93 where Woolf states that possessiveness and meanness (as bred sup-
posedly by the universities) are ‘connected’ with war.
35 Charlotte Perkins Gilman reached the same conclusion years some years previously in works
such as The Man-Made World (1911). Crime, rivalry, fighting and war were anti-social pro-
ducts of the same phenomenon: a competitive and acquisitive ‘masculinism’. See Feldman,
‘From Essentialism to Constructivism?’, pp. 119–23. On Three Guineas as a ‘psychopathology
Virginia Woolf: Three Guineas 47
of masculinism’ see Sybil Oldfield, Women Against the Fist: Alternatives to Militarism 1900–
1989, Oxford: Blackwell, 1989.
36 Woolf, ‘Thoughts on Peace in an Air Raid’, in Collected Essays, vol. 4, ed. L. Woolf,
London: Chatto & Windus, 1969, p. 174.
37 On Woolf ’s pacifism see Black, ‘Virginia Woolf and the Women’s Movement’, 186–97; Lee,
Virginia Woolf, pp. 688–98.
38 See e.g.: Chambers, The Novels of Virginia Woolf, London: Oliver and Boyd, 1947, pp. 1–3.
39 Carroll, ‘Crush Him in Our Own Country’, pp. 105–07, 122–23.
40 Quoted in Carroll, ‘Crush Him in Our Own Country’, p. 102.
5 Power, morality and the remaking
of international order: E. H. Carr’s
The Twenty Years’ Crisis
Peter Wilson
One should not see The Twenty Years’ Crisis (TYC) as a manifesto for political rea-
lism, still less a work recommending surrender to the immanence of power.1 That Carr
saw power as immanent in politics, especially international politics, there can be no
doubt. Indeed, this was not so much a matter of ‘seeing’ as ‘conceiving’. For Carr the
immanence of power in politics was true by definition. Politics is about the clash of
interests, and the clash of interests between large, powerful groups is serious politics.
While it would be inaccurate to define politics ‘exclusively in terms of power’, Carr
declared, ‘it is safe to say that power is always an essential element in politics’.2 How-
ever, the idea that Carr not only recognized the immanence of power but advocated
surrender to it is one that all careful readers of this seminal contribution to Interna-
tional Relations (IR) must dismiss. In this chapter I try to do six things: (i) set out
Carr’s intentions in writing TYC; (ii) state its central argument; (iii) outline its main
contentions; (iv) account for its classical status; (v) identify some of its shortcomings;
and (vi) conclude with some thoughts on the ‘surrender’ thesis and why TYC is likely
to remain an IR classic.
Aims
What was Carr aiming to do in TYC? In the Preface he states that his purpose is to
analyse ‘the underlying and significant, rather than the immediate and personal, causes
of the disaster’ – the disaster being the outbreak of war in 1939 (p. ix). Here we have an
immediate clue to the nature of the intellectually and historically broad-ranging study
to follow. Carr was not interested in what this statesman or that, whether Mussolini,
Briand, Hitler or Chamberlain, said or did at this or that moment (though he was
rather more interested in the sayings and doings of ‘Herr Hitler’3 than the others).
Rather he was interested in the conditions which made their sayings and doings poli-
tically significant, even possible.4 A settlement, he continued, which addressed the
immediate and personal causes and not the underlying and significant, that ‘destroyed
the National Socialist rulers of Germany’ but left untouched ‘the conditions which
made the phenomenon of National Socialism possible’, would ‘run the risk of being as
short-lived and as tragic as the settlement of 1919’ (ibid.). His next book was to be
called Conditions of Peace (1942). This one could have been called Conditions of War.
The subtitle of the book suggests another purpose. This was to provide an introduc-
tion for students to the new academic subject of IR. In 1936 Carr resigned from the
British Foreign Office, which he had served for 20 years, to take up the Woodrow
Wilson Chair of International Politics at the University College of Wales, Aberystwyth.5
E. H. Carr: The Twenty Years’ Crisis 49
His first book on this subject, International Relations since the Peace Treaties, was
published the following year. It was a book intended to be helpful to students. TYC, his
second book on the subject, could be seen in the same vein. Yet his engagement with
not only specialist academic literature – in political philosophy, history and interna-
tional relations – but also contributions to popular debate, notably by Nobel Peace
Laureate Sir Norman Angell, suggests a broader audience. One of his aims was to
provide a deeper, more critical, analytical framework for popular debate (and possibly
the intellectual substructure for the promotion of his own socialist utopia – but more
on that in a moment).
This leads to the final aim that can be deduced from the substance and tone of the
text: to reveal the folly of Versailles and the wisdom of appeasement. Carr was a junior
member of the British delegation at the Versailles Peace Conference, remaining in Paris
several years after. He was appalled by the harshness of the terms imposed on Ger-
many and the manner in which the German delegation was treated. His indignation
stayed with him for many years and goes some way to explain why his treatment of
Hitler and the Nazi regime in the pages of the TYC is so mild. He was infuriated by
the logic of Versailles, or at least the hypocritical way in which the principal status quo
Powers (France and Britain) implemented it by keeping Germany in a position of per-
manent subordination. He refused to be indignant over Hitler’s reoccupation of the
Rhineland in 1936, seeing it as a righting of a past wrong.6 Allied with his deep desire
to avoid another war this accounts fairly efficiently for Carr’s support for a policy of
active accommodation of Hitler’s demands. He welcomed the Munich agreement of
1938, describing it as ‘the nearest approach in recent years to the settlement of a major
international issue by a procedure of peaceful change’ (p. 282). With its frank recogni-
tion of power realities and its appeal to an accepted canon of international morality
(the principle of self-determination) the Munich agreement contained a wisdom lacking
in previous conceptions of peaceful change.7
Main argument
The pre-1914 order had collapsed. The attempt to rebuild it on the old nineteenth-
century foundations was doomed to failure. A new order could only be built on foundations
able to withstand the pressures of a very different world. The nineteenth century was
characterized by laissez-faire, free trade and liberal democracy. The twentieth century
was characterized by large-scale industry, mass production, the rapid development of
communications, controlled trade and mass democracy – or at least changes in the
nature and scale of production necessitated corresponding changes in political organi-
zation (i.e. towards a more ‘interventionist’ state). This is the basic contention of TYC
and the historical baseline from which Carr conducts his wide-ranging and multifaceted
analysis. Yet textbooks over the years have tended to present the work in terms of its
‘devastating critique’ of ‘utopian ideals’ such as the League of Nations and collective
security. It is certainly true that the book contains a critique in the name of ‘realism’ of
interwar ‘utopianism’, and that this critique is generally held to have had a ‘devastating
impact’ in IR.8 However, two things should be noted. First, while Carr believed this
critique to be of vital importance at the historical juncture of 1939, one should not
equate it unconditionally with Carr’s own position. Second, the meaning he gave to
these elastic terms ultimately does not make sense unless this historical baseline is
taken into account. Taking a ‘realistic’ view ultimately meant taking a view that was in
50 Peter Wilson
line with prevailing material conditions. Looked at another way, Carr gives attention to
the numerous events, theories, policies and decisions that litter the theory and practice
of international relations of the interwar period. However, these are all pressed into the
service of a broader historical-theoretical point. What, we may ask, is the crisis of the 20
years’ crisis? It is the world economic crisis, the collapse of free trade, the failure of the
League, the failure of collective security, ‘the armament crisis’, the international tensions
of 1939. Carr depicts all these things, and more, as crises. However, the real, funda-
mental crisis for Carr is ‘the final and irrevocable breakdown of the conditions which
made the nineteenth-century order possible’ (p. 303). It was the failure of the Western
Powers to recognize this breakdown and adapt their policy-making and diplomacy to the
needs and conditions of a new historical epoch. Hence his relative disinterest in the say-
ings and doings of this or that statesman. ‘The breakdown of the post-War utopia’, he
declared, ‘is too overwhelming to be explained merely in terms of individual action or
inaction. Its downfall involves the bankruptcy of the postulates on which it is based’ (p. 53).
Central contentions
An account, therefore, of the complex structure of TYC must begin with Carr’s reading
of nineteenth-century liberalism. Carr’s argument was not, as some have assumed,9 that
nineteenth-century liberalism was invalid per se but that it was able to survive and in
some cases flourish owing to a special set of material circumstances. These he described
as ‘the spacious conditions of the nineteenth century’ (p. 297) marked by the wide
availability of ‘unoccupied and unexploited territories’ and ‘a plentiful supply of cheap
labour’ (pp. 77–78). Liberal principles such as ‘the greatest good of the greatest
number’ were not universally valid. Rather they were expressions and rationalizations of
the interests of a rising commercial class. Similarly, the brilliant success of liberal democracy
in a limited number of countries was due not to ‘certain a priori rational principles
which had only to be applied in other contexts to produce similar results’ (p. 37).
Rather it was due to a ‘balance of forces peculiar to the economic development of the
period and the countries concerned’ (ibid.).
Yet at a time when the material conditions which had sustained liberalism were breaking
down everywhere an attempt was made to transplant its ‘half-discarded assumptions’
into the ‘special field of international relations’ (p. 36). Nothing better illustrated this
than ‘the Benthamite doctrine of the efficacy of rational public opinion’. According to
this doctrine public opinion could be relied on to judge rightly on any question
rationally presented to it, and once it had judged rightly it would necessarily act rightly
(p. 34). This constituted one of the main intellectual pillars of the League of Nations.
The whole conception of the League, Carr contended, was ‘closely bound up with the
twin belief that public opinion was bound to prevail and that public opinion was the
voice of reason’ (p. 45). In Manchuria and Abyssinia, however, public opinion proved
impotent. Moreover, in practice statesmen often proved to be more reasonable than the
people they represented. The ‘plain men throughout the world’ who in the opinion of
Wilson, Cecil and other League champions possessed ‘simple and unclouded views of
right and wrong’ sometimes took the form of a ‘disorderly mob emitting incoherent
and unhelpful noises’. In international affairs, according to Carr, it was undeniable that
‘public opinion was almost as often wrong-headed as it was impotent’ (pp. 42–51).
Underpinning nearly all nineteenth-century liberal ideas was the doctrine of the
harmony of interests between individual and the community. There were two major
E. H. Carr: The Twenty Years’ Crisis 51
interwar manifestations of this doctrine: the notion that no nation benefited from war,
that all nations had a common interest in peace; and the notion that economic pro-
tectionism was not in the long-term interests of any country, that all nations had a
common interest in free trade. Both of these ‘utopian’ notions were widely accepted in
the Anglo-Saxon world and for a particular reason: they were, Carr asserted, the doc-
trines of the political and economic top dogs, of the ‘haves’ against the ‘have-nots’, the
‘satisfied’ against the ‘dissatisfied’. The notion that war profited no one was easy to
accept in countries which having fought profitable wars had no desire to encourage
others to do the same. The notion that the catastrophe of 1914–18 had demonstrated
the futility of war was easier for the victors to accept than the vanquished, who tended
to blame their fears and insecurities not on ‘war’ but on the fact of losing. According to
Carr, the common interest in peace masked the fact that some nations desired to
maintain the status quo without having to fight for it, while others desired to change the
status quo without having to fight in order to do so (p. 68). The utopian assumption of
a world interest in peace masked fundamental conflicts of interest.
The same logic applied to the doctrines of laissez-faire and free trade. ‘Laissez-faire,
in international relations as in those between capital and labour, is the paradise of the
economically strong’, Carr asserted (p. 77). The implication of the harmony of interest
doctrine in the international economic sphere was the permanent relegation of weaker,
non-industrial Powers to second-class status. The notion of a universal interest in free
trade, equally favourable to all and prejudicial to none, was a mantra of League and
other international economic conferences of the 1930s. Yet it was contrary to fact that
economic protectionism was detrimental everywhere to those that practised it. While it
might make international trade as a whole weaker, and the economic interests of
Europe or the world at large might suffer, protectionism could strengthen the economy and
independence of less advantaged states (ibid.). Those who elevated ‘peace’ and ‘free
trade’ to the status of universal principles simply failed to understand the self-interested
character of their thought.
Armed with this appreciation of Carr’s understanding of liberalism, his understanding
of realism begins to make sense. His account of realism begins safely enough. Machiavelli
is described as the first important political realist (p. 81). Bodin, Bacon, Spinoza and
Hobbes are cited as major classical influences. More controversially, however, he cites
Kjellen, Spengler, Hegel and Marx as important modern influences. Hegel and Marx in
particular liberated realism from the pessimism of Machiavelli and Hobbes and made it
more historical, scientific and progressive. They rejected all notions of divine provi-
dence and contended that nothing existed outside the historical process, the laws of
which it was the job of the realist to reveal. Progress was part of the ‘inner essence’ of
this process. Mankind was moving with an ‘iron necessity towards an inevitable goal’
(Carr quoting Marx, p. 85). For Carr, therefore, realism primarily means something
like ‘acceptance of the entire historical process’, outside of which there are no stan-
dards of judgement, and the general course of which human beings are powerless to
alter (pp. 81–86). This is significant because it shows that this early account of realism
is also, in comparison with later accounts, quirky. A critic might contend that it was
not so much a product of a careful study of the history of political thought as some-
thing that followed ineluctably from his (precipitous) decision to frame his discussion in
terms of the stark opposition between ‘realism’ and a bundle of liberal ideas and
assumptions that he provocatively labelled ‘utopianism’. Realism becomes historical
and determinist precisely because utopianism is ahistorical and voluntarist (asserting
52 Peter Wilson
e.g. the existence of certain a priori principles standing outside of history, and attaching
great importance to the exercise of independent human reason).
However, as the cognoscenti of TYC know, Carr not only described realism, he also
critiqued it. Realism certainly had important tasks to perform. Carr viewed the expo-
sure by realist criticism of the hollowness of utopianism as ‘the most urgent task of the
moment in international thought’ (p. 113). This is why, as he later admitted, TYC
states its argument with ‘a rather one-sided emphasis which no longer seems as neces-
sary or appropriate as it did in 1939’.10 However, a ‘final resting place’ could not be
found in ‘pure realism’ (p. 113). Indeed, a thrust of TYC is that there are no final
resting places. This is why, despite being influenced by Marx, and using some of his
methods to great effect, in the final analysis Carr did not consider himself to be a
Marxist. He broadly accepted Marx’s analysis of the rise and fall of Western bourgeois
capitalism. Indeed, realistic or objective history for Carr meant history broadly in line
with Marx’s materialist understanding of the historical process.11 However, he did not
share Marx’s confidence in the revolutionary potential of the proletariat, nor his vision
of the culmination of the historical process in a worldwide classless society. He accepted
much of Marx’s analysis but not his teleology.12
In Carr’s view, ‘consistent realism’ lacked ‘four things that appear to be essential
ingredients of all effective political thinking: a finite goal, an emotional appeal, a right
of moral judgment and a ground for action’ (p. 113). Realism was also vulnerable to its
own insight of the conditioned nature of thought. Realism, he said, is ‘often’ as much
conditioned as any other mode of thought.13 For example, in politics the belief that
certain facts were unalterable or certain trends irresistible commonly reflected ‘a lack of
desire or lack of interest to change or resist them’ (ibid.). So we are left with the con-
clusion that the determinist reading of history may not be a true/real/objective reading
but a pragmatic one, being conditioned by the interests and circumstances of the (in
this case ‘modern realist’) reader. As well as this problem of reflexivity it is important
to note one further feature of Carr’s critique of realism. It was impossible to be a ‘pure’
or ‘consistent’ realist, he suggests, because in some respects it is ‘uncongenial or
incomprehensible to the human mind’ (ibid.). It went against, for example, one of the
most deep-rooted human beliefs, that ‘human affairs can be directed and modified by
human action and human thought’ (p. 117). So an important element of his critique of
realism, often overlooked, is that its view of the world is not so much empirically wrong
but psychologically unsustainable. The human mind, even of the most unsentimental
and scientific realist, will always rebel against it.
Carr’s dissatisfaction with realism carries over to his substantial treatment of inter-
national law, where again he charts a middle course. Realism held that law was merely
the ‘will of the state’, the ‘weapon of the stronger’ or the ‘registration of power rela-
tions’ within any given community (pp. 223–27). However, according to Carr law is
unsustainable if it relies for compliance exclusively on punishment. Laws that go
against the conscience of the community are difficult to enforce. Furthermore, while
enforcement is an essential factor in the bindingness of law, so is ‘the sense of right of
the community’ (p. 227). It was true that there was no special sanctity in ‘the rule of
law’ or its international counterpart pacta sunt servanda. This again was a utopian
fallacy and delusion. It was always important to ask: what law? whose law? Law, he
contended, is not an abstraction. The ethical content of law is always a function of the
ends it serves. However, Carr none the less held law to be an essential ingredient of
organized social life. Coherent social life was not possible without the ‘element of fixity and
E. H. Carr: The Twenty Years’ Crisis 53
regularity and continuity’, which it provided (pp. 228–31). The chief problem with
current international law was that it lacked an effective mechanism by which important
rules could be peacefully changed. With the creation of the League war had been
removed as a legitimate means of modifying the existing order. Yet no effective
mechanism had been put in its place. As a result international law had become a ‘bul-
wark of the existing order’ to an extent previously unknown (pp. 244–45). This was
the most fundamental reason, according to Carr, for the decline in respect for law.
Those states desiring to change the law had no choice, in the face of the hostility to such
changes from the status quo Powers, but to break it. For this reason their behaviour should
not be judged as any more immoral or unreasonable than the behaviour of the status
quo Powers. But crucially and contrary to the ‘pure’ realist view, Carr believed that it
was possible to devise a mechanism whereby law could be changed peacefully, in line with
what was considered ‘just and reasonable’ in the community of nations (pp. 278–84).
Indeed, he regarded this as one of the chief tasks facing, to cite the dedication of
TYC, ‘the makers of the coming peace’. Law was not inevitably a bastion of an unjust
status quo.
Given the collapse of the old order and the ‘ignominious failure’ (p. 287) of the
attempt to recreate it, where lay the future? In Carr’s view it lay in a socialist-inspired
transformation of international order. His starting point here, interestingly, is the
need for greater equality. The historical struggle between the privileged and the unpri-
vileged had been transferred from within national communities to between them.
Mitigating the inequality between nations was now the main challenge of international
order. Rising to it would involve inter alia the substantial reduction of consumption in
privileged nations, a ‘gigantic programme of economically unremunerative expendi-
ture’, the ‘increasing elimination of the profit motive from the national economy’, the
‘subordination of economic advantage to social ends’, and the extension of these ends
‘across the national frontier’ (pp. 302–07). Only by such means, and the frank
acknowledgement of the interdependence between economics and politics, national and
international welfare, could the mistakes of the past be averted and a lasting peace
built. This, too, Carr acknowledged, was utopia. However, it stood ‘more directly in the
line of recent advance than visions of a world federation or blue-prints of a more perfect
League of Nations. Those elegant superstructures must wait until some progress has
been made in digging the foundations’ (pp. 307).
Classic status
‘Digging the foundations’: in these final words of TYC resides the reason why it rapidly
became regarded as an IR. It was the first work in the field to call for unsenti-
mental and systematic analysis of the facts of international relations as the vital first step
to improve them. Stanley Hoffmann once described it as ‘the first “scientific” treatment
of modern world politics’.14 While the meaning of scientific, as Hoffmann’s inverted
commas suggest, can be debated, there can be no doubt that TYC was the first work to
grapple with a range of basic international questions – relating to the role and
relationship of law, power, morality, war and order – in the spirit of science; in the
spirit, that is, of detached social enquiry stripped of the liberal rationalist teleology
that hitherto had informed most work on the subject. In this regard, and in parti-
cular his call for an unsentimental analysis of the role of power in international politics,
Carr influenced virtually every IR scholar of significance of the next generation.15
54 Peter Wilson
Yet it is important to stress that it is not ‘facts’ and ‘power’ per se that are important but
the approach taken towards them. There is a sense in which the chief contribution of
TYC, and the main source of its classical status, is methodological. TYC is the first genu-
inely critical work of international relations. It was the first work that sought system-
atically to get behind conventional narratives, assumptions and wisdoms and ask: what
sustains them? Carr’s ‘realism’ is a critical tool, forged from the exotic metals (certainly
for IR of the time) of Marx’s concept of ideology and Mannheim’s sociology of
knowledge.16 It is the means by which he sought to expose ‘the hidden foundations of utopian
theory’ (p. 18), to unmask it as the ‘disguise for the interests of the privileged Powers’
(p. 118). For the purposes of this argument it does not matter that ‘utopianism’ is an
amalgam of not necessarily compatible liberal ideas and theories. It does not matter that
his understanding of ‘realism’ is quirky. Nor does it matter that the scholars of the subject
he influenced ignored almost to a man, and indeed a woman, the quasi-Marxist implications
of his employment of this ‘realist’ tool. What matters is that he got them to think critically
in a deep sense. To ask: why does this author/actor say the things he does in the way he
does? What interests and/or pragmatic purposes may he be serving? What events or
policies does this theory of international relations serve to rationalize or justify? What
subjective interests does this ‘objective’ voice serve? What particular interest does this
assertion of a common interest or general harmony of interest disguise or rationalize?
When it comes to assessing any idea or policy, cui bono?17 The answers that Carr himself
gave to these questions, directed at some of the most cherished political and economic
nostrums of his day, have been regarded by many as unsatisfactory. However, in asking
them he opened up a new critical vista in IR and played a decisive role in putting the
discipline on a methodologically stronger and more analytically self-conscious footing.
Shortcomings
There can be no definitive statement of the shortcomings of such a wide-ranging and
provocative work as TYC. In the following I offer five salient criticisms, not so much of
his interpretation of particular events and issues, but of the structure and coherence of
his argument. The strength and significance of these criticisms can only be judged by
the reader, from his/her particular viewpoint. However, they are criticisms that all serious
students of the book need to take into account.
First, a number of critics have objected to the moral stance of TYC, particularly
Carr’s assertion that there was essentially no moral difference between the methods and
policies of the fascist Powers and those of the Western Powers. According to Carr, Nazi
Germany was not doing anything in the 1930s that the UK and France would not have
done if they had found themselves in the same position. A country’s moral outlook was
entirely a function of its position in the balance of power. Those in a favourable posi-
tion used the slogans of law, security and peace to maintain it. Those in an unfavour-
able position used the language of justice and fairness to undermine it. Many critics,
however, found it abhorrent that law, justice and morality could be reduced to ques-
tions of self-interest in this way. The logic of Carr’s position was that there were no
moral constraints on action. Morality was purely instrumental. Only expediency mat-
tered. In addition, it implied that the domestic constitution and character of the state,
communist, democratic or Nazi, did not matter. But according to some (and who
today apart from the strict neo-realist would disagree?) this amounted to a relapse into
utopianism and wishful thinking as deep as that of any of the ‘utopians’.18
E. H. Carr: The Twenty Years’ Crisis 55
Second, Carr’s concept of peaceful change has been attacked on a number of fronts.
Some have found it intrinsically perplexing. How can ‘yielding to threats of force’ be
conceived as ‘a normal part of the process of peaceful change’ (p. 277; emphasis
added)? Some have found it unhelpful. How do we know, in the process of ‘give and
take’ between ‘haves’ and ‘have-nots’ posited by Carr, when concessions to a rising
Power should be halted lest the positions of the rising Power and the declining Power
be merely reversed? Additionally, who is to count as a ‘have’ or a ‘have-not’ Power?
Carr offers no definition but merely accepts as ‘have-nots’ those who said they were.
But was Italy, a victor in World War One, a ‘have-not’ Power because Il Duce said she
was? Was Germany, the victor in all the major diplomatic quarrels of the late 1930s, a
‘have-not’ because Hitler found it rhetorically convenient to portray her so?19 This is a
weakness in Carr’s argument than can easily go undetected because of the skilful way
in which it was constructed.
Third, Carr conceived utopianism in terms of the transplantation into international
thought of the assumptions of nineteenth-century liberalism. There are several pro-
blems with this. Carr’s understanding of ‘nineteenth-century liberalism’ tends to shift
according to his particular target. Sometimes it means liberal democracy, sometimes
classical political economy, sometimes the harmony of interests, sometimes Benthamism,
sometimes rationalism, the meaning of these things being far from fixed. Benthamism,
for example, sometimes means ‘utilitarianism’ and other times ‘the efficacy of rational
pubic opinion’. Other aspects of Bentham’s thought e.g. his call for ‘the emancipation
of all distant dependencies’,20 are conveniently ignored. What precisely was being
transplanted, therefore, is not always clear. In addition, there is more than a little
selection bias in the ideas Carr deems to be representative of a broad and barely
coherent liberal tradition.21 With regard to the principal institutional manifestation of
utopianism, the League of Nations, it may have been true that many of his proponents
had strong faith in the efficacy of public opinion to enforce its decisions, but it was not
true that they based their ideas on laissez-faire or the doctrine of the harmony of
interests. In the security field, for example, they supported the League precisely because
they felt that ‘laissez-faire/anarchic’ doctrines would no longer work.22
Fourth, Carr claimed that he was laying down the foundations for a ‘science’ or IR.
However, his twin conceptual pillars of utopianism and realism were far from stable. It
was not always clear what the ‘realities’ were that ‘realists’ vis-à-vis ‘utopians’ took into
account. Similarly, Carr sometimes opposes realism to ‘the ideal’ and sometimes to ‘the
apparent’, the former being a conservative tactic (to pursue the ideal is not only futile
but will make things worse), the latter being a radical tactic (behind the façade of
sweetness and light lies a structure of oppression, self-interest and discrimination).23
When it comes to ‘utopia’ things are even worse. Sometimes it means ‘impractical’,
sometimes ‘unverified’, sometimes ‘abstract’, sometimes ‘unprecedented’, and sometimes
‘false’. Connectedly, ‘morality’ was employed in conjunction with a staggering range of
synonyms e.g. ‘altruism’, ‘conscience’, ‘goodwill’, ‘ideals’, ‘self-sacrifice’.24 In addition
Carr’s ‘breathtaking equations’25 (e.g. utopia: reality = free will: determinism = theory:
practice = conscience: coersion = goodwill: enmity = altruism: self-seeking) suggested a
fast-and-loose approach to concepts far removed from science.
Finally, Carr can be accused of committing, in the final chapter of the book, the very
sin of which he accused the ‘utopians’: ‘couching optative propositions in the indicative
mood’ (p. 17). Carr saw his socialist scheme for the reconstruction of the international
order as a logical extension of existing historical trends: a ‘progressively emerging
56 Peter Wilson
future end’ as he later put it.26 This is what made it ‘realistic’. However, the refa-
shioning of liberalism and the recovery of capitalism after the war were soon to
demonstrate that Carr’s irresistible trends were far from irresistible. Carr turned out to
be ‘the prophet of a false collectivist dawn’.27 His ‘immanent developments’ and pre-
scriptions ‘directly in the line of recent advance’ (p. 307) look more and more like
normative preferences dressed up in the language of fact.
Conclusion
Deep down TYC is a highly normative book. This is the first conclusion to be drawn
from the preceding analysis. It is far from being a work of modern fatalism advocating
surrender to the immanence of power. In the final analysis morality for Carr is as vital
an element as power. He says, for example, that ‘the homo politicus who pursues noth-
ing but power is as unreal a myth as the homo economicus who pursues nothing but
gain. Political action must be based on a co-ordination of morality and power’ (p. 125).
He declares that ‘every solution of the problem of political change, whether national or
international, must be based on a compromise between morality and power’ (p. 265).
He contends that while ‘it is utopian to ignore the element of power, it is an unreal
kind of realism which ignores the element of morality in any world order’ (p. 302).
Those commentators who have portrayed TYC as a manifesto of power have mistaken
what Carr believed needed to be emphasized at a particular historical juncture for his
understanding of reality in toto. They have also portrayed it in a way that is consistent
with their own beliefs, disregarding inconvenient complexities, not least the dialectical
nature of the relationship between power and morality, which Carr viewed as an engine
of change, if not unequivocally of progress.28
Will the classical status of TYC endure? The first point to make is that it has not
diminished in the 70 years since it was first published. Indeed, it has acquired new
admirers since it was ‘freed from the grip of the realists’ in the 1990s.29 A new edition
with valuable additional material was published in 2001. It still regularly appears, if
problematically under ‘Realism’, on undergraduate reading lists. Its influence, baleful
or benign, assures it a prominent place in the history of the discipline. Moreover, it
remains, despite its many shortcomings, one of the most original and provocative ana-
lyses of international relations in the literature, a work of rare insight and argumentative
power. In this regard one should not conclude without mentioning the quality of the
writing in TYC. It is true that Carr employed his remarkable dexterity with the English
language to conceal flaws that would have been all too apparent in the work of a lesser
writer. But one of the reasons why TYC continues to be widely read and discussed is
that it is a work of considerable literary merit. There is something Hobbesian in the
gravity, Swiftian in the sharpness of wit, and Burkian in the combination of coolness
and passion in Carr’s writing. On the literary plane alone TYC stands comparison with
some of the finest political disquisitions in the English language.
Notes
1 The argument of Hans J. Morgenthau, ‘The Surrender to the Immanence of Power: E. H.
Carr’ in Hans J. Morgenthau (ed.), Dilemmas of Politics, Chicago, IL: Chicago University
Press, [1948] 1962, pp. 350–57. It has been echoed many times since, e.g. H. R. Trevor-Roper,
‘E. H. Carr’s Success Story’, Encounter, 1962, vol. 18, p. 75.
E. H. Carr: The Twenty Years’ Crisis 57
2 E. H. Carr, The Twenty Years’ Crisis, 1919–1939: An Introduction to the Study of Interna-
tional Relations, London: Macmillan, 1939, p. 131. Unless otherwise stated, all subsequent
page numbers placed in parentheses in the text refer to this first edition.
3 Merely ‘Hitler’ in the second edition (1946) of Carr, The Twenty Years’ Crisis, 1919–1939.
4 Carr later elevated this to a principle of historical research. While historical events were ‘set
in motion by the individual wills … the historian must go behind the individual wills and
inquire into the reasons which made the individuals will and act as they did, and study the
“factors” or “forces” which explain individual behaviour’. Quoted in R. J. Evans, ‘Introduc-
tion’, What is History?, London: Palgrave Macmillan, [1961] 2001, p. xviii.
5 For the imbroglio over Carr’s appointment see Brian Porter, ‘Lord Davies, E. H. Carr and the
Spirit Ironic: A Comedy of Errors’, International Relations, 2002, vol. 16, 77–96.
6 See Carr, ‘An Autobiography’, in M. Cox (ed.), E. H. Carr: A Critical Appraisal, London:
Palgrave Macmillan, 2000, pp. xviii–xix.
7 For the background, historical and psychological, to Carr’s support for appeasement see
Jonathan Haslam, The Vices of Integrity: E. H. Carr, 1892–1982, London: Verso, 1999,
Chapters 2 and 3.
8 See further my ‘Myth of the First Great Debate’, Review of International Studies, 1998, vol.
24, 1–15.
9 See e.g. Whittle Johnson, ‘E. H. Carr’s Theory of International Relations: A Critique’, Jour-
nal of Politics, 1967, vol. 29, 861–84. I have reviewed the secondary literature on Carr up to
2000 in ‘Radicalism for a Conservative Purpose: The Peculiar Realism of E. H. Carr’, Mil-
lennium: Journal of International Studies, 2001, vol. 30, 123–36.
10 Preface to the second edition of Carr, The Twenty Years’ Crisis, 1919–1939, p. x.
11 See Trevor-Roper, ‘E. H. Carr’s Success Story’, p. 74; Evans, ‘Introduction’, pp. xxvi–xxxviii; and
Keith Jenkins, ‘Rethinking the Value of What Is History?’ in Cox, A Critical Appraisal, pp. 304–21.
12 See Carr, ‘An Autobiography’, pp. xxi–xxii; Michael Cox, ‘E. H. Carr and Isaac Deutscher: A
Very Special Relationship’, in Cox, A Critical Appraisal, pp. 125–44.
13 The word ‘often’ is an example of the slippery use of words of which Carr has sometimes
been accused. When it came to utopianism the conditioning was ‘always’. Nowhere in TYC
does he explain how realism can sometimes be less conditioned than other modes of thought.
He returned to this question, however, in What is History? (pp. 37–38), arguing that some
degree of social transcendence was possible through critical self-awareness (which Marxists/
realists possessed but liberals/rationalists/utopians did not).
14 Stanley Hoffmann, ‘An American Social Science: International Relations’, Daedalus, 1997,
vol. 106, p. 43.
15 See further Peter Wilson, ‘E. H. Carr’s The Twenty Years’ Crisis: Appearance and Reality in
World Politics’, Politik, 2009, vol. 12, 21–25.
16 See Charles Jones, E. H. Carr and International Relations: A Duty to Lie, Cambridge: Cam-
bridge University Press, 1998, Chapter 6.
17 If not the term then the methodological stance that Susan Strange took from Carr. See her
States and Markets, London: Pinter, 1988, pp. 63, 132, 217, and Benjamin J. Cohen, Inter-
national Political Economy: An Intellectual History, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Press, 2008, pp. 44–65. For Carr’s attempt (one of the first) to map the relationship between
international politics and ecomonics (i.e. IPE), see pp. 145–68.
18 See, for example, the views of Angell, Hayek and Crossman summarized in Wilson, ‘Carr and
his Early Critics: Responses to The Twenty Years’ Crisis, 1939–45’, in Cox, A Critical
Appraisal, pp. 166–83.
19 See, for example, the views of Maddox, Hayek and Crossman, summarized in Wilson, ‘Carr
and his Early Critics’, pp. 171–83.
20 Quoted in M. J. Smith, ‘Liberalism and International Reform’, in Terry Nardin and David R.
Mapel (eds), Traditions of International Ethics, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1992, p. 204.
21 See Casper Sylvest, British Liberal Internationalism, 1880–1930: Making Progress? Manche-
ster: Manchester University Press, 2009, especially Chapter 2.
22 The view of Angell summarized in Wilson, ‘Carr and his Early Critics’, pp. 174–75.
23 See Stefano Guzzini, ‘The Different Worlds of Realism in International Relations’, Millen-
nium: Journal of International Studies, 2001, vol. 30, 118–19.
58 Peter Wilson
24 The views of, inter alia, Woolf and Stebbing summarized in Wilson, ‘Carr and his Early
Critics’, pp. 177–81. Woolf was so incensed with TYC that he wrote two replies. For an ana-
lysis see Peter Wilson, The International Theory of Leonard Woolf, New York: Palgrave
Macmillan, 2003, Chapter 8.
25 Hedley Bull, ‘The Twenty Years’ Crisis Thirty Years On’, International Journal, 1969, vol. 24,
p. 627.
26 Carr, What is History? p. 118.
27 Cox, ‘Introduction’, Twenty Years’ Crisis, reissue, London: Palgrave Macmillan, 2001, p. lvii.
28 This is well brought out in Seán Molloy, The Hidden History of Realism: A Genealogy of
Power Politics, New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2006, Chapter 3.
29 The first shot in a volley of reappraisals of Carr was fired by Ken Booth in ‘Security in
Anarchy: Utopian Realism in Theory and Practice’, International Affairs, 1991, vol. 67, 537–45.
6 A new politics for a global age: David
Mitrany’s A Working Peace System
Lucian M. Ashworth
In early 1965 Hans J. Morgenthau was contacted by Kurt Dreifuss of the Society for a
World Service Federation. During their discussions Morgenthau recommended that
Dreifuss read David Mitrany’s A Working Peace System (WPS – ‘this is the Func-
tionalist approach of Mitrany, and I agree it makes sense’). Dreifuss tried in vain to track
down a copy. Refusing to give up, he ‘phoned Morgenthau who said “it is distres-
sing but not surprising to me”’. Instead Morgenthau lent Dreifuss his own well-worn
copy.1 During the following year Dreifuss organized a republication of the original
pamphlet in a collection that included other works by Mitrany. In his Introduction to
this volume Morgenthau concluded that the very future of civilization now rested
on the ability of the functional approach to overcome an obsolete and dangerous
nationalism.2
Born in Bucharest in 1888 to a Jewish family, Mitrany left Romania at the age of 20.
Enrolling at the London School of Economics in 1912, he studied sociology under L. T.
Hobhouse and political science under Graham Wallas. Hobhouse and Wallas were to
influence the young Mitrany in different, but compatible, ways. From Hobhouse came
the idea of functions as the basis of society, while from Wallas came Mitrany’s scepti-
cism of rational plans for society that led to his emphasis on needs as an alternative
basis for social organization. Becoming a British citizen after the First World War, he
divided his time after that between Britain and the USA. His working life took him to
Harvard, Princeton, and the offices of Unilever in London.3
Mitrany’s first articulation of the functional approach to world order had come a
decade before WPS in The Progress of International Government.4 Yet, the functional
approach to government – where the institutions of government are built up around
specific functions that are perceived as being vital to the reproduction of society – was
not new. Hobhouse had used it in his formulation of a liberal approach to government
in 1911, and Mary Parker Follett used functional government in her 1918 book.5 In the
1920s H. G. Wells, R. H. Tawney, G. D. H. Cole and Harold Laski had all used a
functional approach to support a guild socialist alternative politico-economic system.6
Mitrany was not even the first to apply functional government to international rela-
tions. That distinction falls to Laski. Mitrany’s genius was to develop a comprehensive
functional approach to international order that fused ideas of both the welfare state
and international organizations that also did not ignore issues of power and national
interest. WPS was the culmination of two decades of work on the problems of modern
governance, yet it only represented a part of his larger research agenda, which included
publications on the peasant social revolution, international sanctions, the adaptation of
government to total war and the office of the ombudsman.7 WPS was originally a
60 Lucian M. Ashworth
policy document written for Chatham House’s Foreign Press and Research Section,
then part of the Foreign Office’s war effort. It was published in pamphlet form in 1943
and quickly made Mitrany’s name among international experts.
Ideologically Mitrany is hard to pin down, and he liked it that way. His writing on
peasant agriculture displayed a strong sympathy for the anarchist ideas of Proudhon
(and a dislike of the urban Marxists).8 He worked for the liberal Manchester Guardian
and was an enthusiastic member of the British Labour Party’s Advisory Committee on
International Questions. However, he was also a political advisor for Unilever.
Opposed to the national planning ideas of many labour and social democratic parties,
he was nonetheless an enthusiastic advocate of international planning.9 WPS is best
seen as a confluence of all of these positions, as well as a reaction to the failure of
collective security in the 1930s. A common mistake has been to regard the pamphlet as
having no theory of government, and consequently being merely a theory of ‘economic
integration’.10 In fact, WPS is premised on a theory of government, but it is not a
theory of state government. Indeed, Mitrany’s political theory flows from his study of the
peasant social revolution, and has strong anarchist elements to it. It is also a mistake to
regard his approach as being a theory of political integration (Mitrany always strenu-
ously denied this11). Rather, functional integration for Mitrany was primarily a means
towards the establishment of world peace. Mitrany turned to need as the basis of a
world order owing to his deep scepticism with previous world orders based on ration-
ality. Mitrany took from Wallas the view that reason was not employed by humanity
until we had used our emotions to choose the social urges and entities that we con-
sidered important. Needs, in a global context, were Mitrany’s interpretation of Wallas’
social urges and entities.12
In this chapter I first consider the argument of WPS. I follow this with an assessment
of why it is a classic, and an analysis of the reaction to it. With a few exceptions,
Mitrany’s ideas are less quoted and used in International Relations (IR) today than
they were up to the mid-1980s, and in European Union Studies he is usually read
through the prism of neo-functionalist analysis.13 Despite this, I conclude that the
success of WPS lies in its broad appeal that stretches beyond the immediate concerns
of 1943.
Yet, this fuzzy definition of both function and need hid a problem. The functional
approach was premised on the idea that needs were prior to culture, and therefore
politically uncontentious. However, there was no reason why this should be the case. In
fact, while need could rather tritely be viewed as prior to culture, the actual means by
which people satisfied need was often deeply culture-specific. For example, while we all
need to eat, the way that we cook the food we eat is the product of culture. In this
sense, the idea that functional organizations would somehow escape cultural wranglings
was naïve.22 That said, Mitrany certainly looked to existing practice for hints on the
form of functional organizations. This included a diverse range of recent experiences,
including wartime planning, the largely Berne-based Public International Unions, the
specialized agencies of the League, as well as domestic experiences such as the New
Deal or the London Transport Board. He also flagged the issue of functional repre-
sentation: that these functional bodies needed to be representative of all those involved in
a specific function, but on the flip side those who did not have a stake should not carry
undue weight. Thus, representation and democratic control should also be dictated by
the nature of the function, and not necessarily by outdated notions of constitutional
legal equality (pp. 38ff.).
David Mitrany: A Working Peace System 65
Reaction and significance
There are three reasons why I see WPS as a classic work. First, the pamphlet managed
to combine topicality with a theoretical underpinning that would be of interest to future
generations no longer animated by the immediate problems addressed by the text. This
might explain why his work survived in IR, while work by his contemporaries such as
Leonard Woolf, H. N. Brailsford and Philip Noel-Baker fared less well. Ironically, at
the time when WPS was written Mitrany would have been far less well known, both in
policy circles and to the wider public. Second, the functional approach emphasized
process over specific goals. He saw the institutional details of any proposed new world,
if they were to be practical and effective, as the work of those most actively involved in
a function. Mitrany’s goal was to lay out workable principles based on the ‘trend of the
times’. The only problem with this approach was that it left the question of the nature
of functional organization to be filled in by later theorists, and many of these reinter-
preted functional cooperation in ways that were not sympathetic to Mitrany’s own
world view. Yet, there were advantages to Mitrany’s approach. Not tied to any parti-
cular idea of functional cooperation, his ideas as process could find themselves applied
to a number of different sets of organizations. Third, his international theory repre-
sented a clear attempt to synthesize current developments in the study of domestic
politics, and apply them to international problems. Many of the Anglo-US debates
about international affairs in the first few decades of the century had revolved around
legalistic arguments. The hope was to apply the same ‘rule of law revolution’ that had
occurred in nineteenth-century domestic politics of Western states to the international
sphere. The functional approach was an attempt to develop an international theory
that took into account the shift towards service and needs that had come with the
development of the welfare state. Mitrany saw himself as reconnecting the study of
the international with the seismic shifts that had happened in the rest of politics. In
this context, Mitrany was responsible for revolutionizing the study of international
organizations.
The initial reaction to WPS among Mitrany’s centre-left colleagues was lukewarm.
Much of the criticism was based on the misperception that what Mitrany called func-
tional cooperation referred only to economic and social cooperation, and therefore was
not primarily concerned with longer-term issues of security and political cooperation.
While they saw value in functional cooperation, for them the key issue was the estab-
lishment of a new ‘political’ League organization to control security issues. Leonard
Woolf wrote that while there was a place for functional international organizations ‘the
necessity for a central world authority is absolute’.23 Noel-Baker echoed Woolf ’s posi-
tion, arguing that ‘the first and indispensable condition of either peace or economic
prosperity, is the creation of a strong international political organisation’.24 Outside of
the Labour Party advocates of a federal alternative were also critical of Mitrany’s lack
of a central political organization.25 Yet, despite these criticisms, Mitrany’s ideas of
international functionalism became widely accepted in British circles. Indeed, Wilson
has argued that the popularity of functionalism was partially responsible for the decline
in federalist thought in the UK after 1945.26
Interestingly, it was outside his circle that Mitrany often found the strongest support
for his ideas. E. H. Carr endorsed a functionalist solution to the problem of European
order, even if he failed to cite WPS.27 More direct acknowledgement and engagement
with Mitrany’s work came from realist scholars in the USA. While John Herz was
66 Lucian M. Ashworth
concerned that a functionalist approach did not always take into consideration the ubi-
quity of conflicts over power, he believed that it could contribute to solving interna-
tional problems, especially if it rested on broad public support.28 Morgenthau was far more
enthusiastic than Herz, and his work is peppered with references to functionalist solu-
tions to global problems.29 Later, Inis Claude’s study of international organization would
include a chapter-length critical analysis of the functional approach that, while scep-
tical of certain assumptions of Mitrany’s approach, acknowledged that it ‘has the great merit
of appealing both to humanitarian idealism and to national self-interest’,30 Claude had
neatly summarized Mitrany’s appeal to classical realism: that it combined a normative
approach with an (often pessimistic) acceptance of the pragmatic problems posed by
current structures of political power. Mitrany was less happy about the neo-functionalist
interpretation of his theories, and indeed many of the myths about what Mitrany stood
for stem from writers such as Ernst Haas,31 Leon Lindberg and Stuart A. Sheingold.32
Following the US republication of WPS in 1966, a fresh generation of students
adapted the functional approach to understand the new world of détente and North-
South dialogue.33 Here, functionalism became associated with technocratic organiza-
tions, especially those within the United Nations system. This shift of focus to the UN
had its roots in Mitrany’s own identification of the UN as a functional system.34 The
concentration on the UN also led to a downplaying of the role of functional democ-
racy. The functional approach continued to be a major part of the IR curriculum
during the 1980s, and was also taught as a forebear of neofunctionalism in European
Union studies for much longer. Since the mid-1990s Mitrany has become less popular
in discussions of IR theory. An exception to this has been the interest in Mitrany from
those studying the historiography of the field of IR.35 Despite this recent neglect, there
is an enduring appeal to Mitrany’s ideas. His view of the shifting basis of government,
and the challenge of an outdated state system, places change rather than continuity at
the heart of human governance. Yet, alongside this is a pessimism about our ability to
transcend our dogmatic and divisive identities.
Notes
1 Letter from Kurt Dreifuss to Louis B. Sohn, 12 March 1965, and letter from Kurt Dreifuss to
David Mitrany, 1 June 1965, Box Mitrany/2, Mitrany Papers, British Library of Political and
Economic Sciences, LSE, London.
2 Hans J. Morgenthau, ‘Introduction’, in David Mitrany, A Working Peace System, Chicago,
IL: Quadrangle, 1966, p. 11. Page numbers placed in parentheses in the text refer to the 1943
edition. David Mitrany, A Working Peace System, Oxford: Oxford University Press/RIIA,
1943.
3 For further biographical information on Mitrany, written by his research assistant, see Dor-
othy Anderson, ‘David Mitrany (1888–1975): An Appreciation of his Life and Work’, Review
of International Studies, 1998, vol. 24, 577–92.
4 London: Allen & Unwin, 1933.
5 L. T. Hobhouse, Liberalism, London: Williams and Norgate, 1911; Mary Parker Follett, The
New State, London: Longman, 1918.
6 H. G. Wells, Men Like Gods, London: Cassell, 1923; R. H. Tawney, The Acquisitive Society,
New York: Harcourt Brace, 1920; G. D. H. Cole, Guild Socialism, New York: Stokes, 1920;
Harold Laski, A Grammar of Politics, London: George Allen & Unwin, 1925. For a full
discussion of these works in relation to Mitrany’s functional approach see David Long,
‘International Functionalism and the Politics of Forgetting’, International Journal, 1993, vol.
48, 355–79.
David Mitrany: A Working Peace System 67
7 For a full summary of his work see Anderson, ‘David Mitrany (1888–1975)’. See also Lucian
M. Ashworth, International Relations Theory and the Labour Party: Intellectuals and Policy
Making 1918–1945, London: I. B.Tauris, 2007, p. 120ff.
8 For Mitrany’s work on the peasant social revolution see his ‘Marx v. the Peasant’, in T. E.
Gregory and Hugh Dalton (eds), London Essays in Economics: In Honour of Edwin Cannan,
London: Routledge, 1927; The Land and the Peasant in Rumania: The War and Agrarian
Reform, London: Humprey Milford and Oxford University Press, 1930; Marx Against the
Peasant: A Study in Social Dogmatism, London: Weidenfeld & Nicolson, 1951.
9 See David Mitrany, ‘International Consequences of National Planning’, Yale Review 1947,
vol. 37, 18–31.
10 See, for example, the presentation of Mitrany in David Mutimer, ‘Theories of Political Inte-
gration’ in H. Michaelmann and P. Soldatos, European Integration Theories and Approaches,
Lanham, MD: University Press of America, 1992, pp. 13–42.
11 See ‘Note for Ernst Haas’, 14 February 1963, from the Mitrany Papers, LSE Library
archives. Mitrany once told Charles Pentland that European integration theory was a waste
of time.
12 Graham Wallas, Human Nature and Politics, Boston, MA and New York: Houghtom Mifflin,
[1908] 1916, pp. 21, 25, and Chapter 4.
13 A notable exception to this is Ben Rosamond’s thoughtful analysis in his Theories of Eur-
opean Integration, Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2000, pp. 31–36.
14 For this see Richard Overy, The Morbid Age: Britain and the Crisis of Civilisation, 1919–
1939, Harmondsworth: Penguin, 2010.
15 See, for example, his ‘The New Deal: An Interpretation of its Origin and Nature’, Agenda,
1942, vol. 1.
16 David Mitrany, ‘Memorandum on Studies in International Relations’, unpublished paper
dated 1933–34; David Mitrany, ‘A Realistic Interpretation of Security’, Lecture to the Stu-
dent’s International Union, 16 July 1935, pp. 4–6; David Mitrany, ‘Outline for a Paper on
Pacifism’, no date, p. 1; all from the Mitrany Papers. British Library of Political and Eco-
nomic Sciences, LSE, London. Mitrany, Progress of International Government, p. 42.
17 For a discussion of these debates see Peter Wilson, ‘The New Europe Debate in Wartime
Britain’ in Philomena Murray and Paul Rich (eds), Visions of European Unity, Boulder, CO:
Westview, 1996, pp. 39–62.
18 See also David Mitrany, ‘The Functional Approach to World Organization’, International
Affairs, 1948, vol. 24, 351–53; David Mitrany, ‘The Prospects of Integration: Federal or
Functional?’, in A. J. R. Groom and Paul Taylor (eds), Functionalism. Theory and Practice in
International Relations, New York: Crane Russak, 1975, p. 62.
19 See, for example, Alec Stone Sweet and Wayne Sandholtz, ‘Integration, Supranational Gov-
ernance, and the Institutionalisation of European Polity’, in Wayne Sandholtz and Alec Stone
Sweet, European Integration and Supranational Governance, Oxford: Oxford University Press,
1998, p. 5.
20 Lucian M. Ashworth, ‘Bringing the Nation Back In: Mitrany and the Enjoyment of Nation-
alism’, in L. Ashworth and D. Long (eds), New Perspectives on International Functionalism,
Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 1999.
21 See Ashworth, ‘Bringing the Nation Back In?’ Inis Claude was also critical of the extent to
which functional organizations would attract loyalties. See his Swords into Plowshares: The Pro-
blems and Progress of International Organization, 4th edn, New York: Random House, [1956]
1971, p. 355.
22 See Lucian M. Ashworth, Creating International Studies. Angell, Mitrany and the Liberal
Tradition, Aldershot: Ashgate, 1999, pp. 101–03.
23 Leonard Woolf, International Post-War Settlement, London: Fabian Society/Victor Gollancz,
1944, p. 7.
24 Philip Noel-Baker, ‘Notes on Mr Dalton’s Outline Sketch of the Principles Upon Which a
Delcaration of Post-War International Policy Should Be Based’, Labour Party International
Department memo, November 1943, p. 5. William Gillies papers, Labour Party Archives,
John Rylands Library, Manchester, UK.
25 See, for example, Lionel Curtis’s comments in David Mitrany, ‘The Functional Approach to
World Organization’, International Affairs, 1998, vol. 24, 362–63.
68 Lucian M. Ashworth
26 Wilson, ‘The New Europe Debate in Wartime Britain’, pp. 57–58.
27 E.H. Carr, Nationalism and After, London: Macmillan, 1945, pp. 47–74. Carr’s use of
Mitrany is mentioned in Ashworth, Creating International Studies, p. 113, and William
Scheuerman, ‘The (Classical) Realist Vision of Global Reform’, International Theory, 2010,
vol. 2, 260. See also Wilson, ‘The New Europe Debate in Wartime Britain’, pp. 42–44.
28 John H. Herz, International Politics in the Atomic Age, New York: Columbia University
Press, 1959, 327–29. See also Scheuerman, ‘(Classical) Realist Vision’, pp. 264–66 and Casper
Sylvest, ‘Realism and International Law: The Challenge of John H. Herz’, International
Theory, 2010, vol. 2, 436.
29 See also Scheuerman, ‘(Classical) Realist Vision’, 262–64.
30 Claude, Swords into Plowshares, p. 386
31 For Mitrany’s objection to Haas’s interpretation see ‘Note to Ernst Haas’, 14 February 1963,
From the Mitrany Papers, British Library of Political and Economic Sciences, LSE, London.
For Haas’s views of functionalism and neofunctionalism see Ernst B. Haas, The Uniting of
Europe: Political, Social and Economic Forces, 1950–57, London: Stevens, 1958, and Beyond
the Nation-State: Functionalism and International Organization, Stanford, CA: Stanford Uni-
versity Press, 1964.
32 Leon N. Lindberg and Stuart A. Scheingold, Europe’s Would-Be Polity, Englewood Cliffs,
NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1970, pp. 6–7.
33 James Patrick Sewell, Functionalism and World Politics: A Study Based on United Nations
Programs Financing Economic Development, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1966;
A. J. R. Groom and Paul Taylor, Functionalism: Theory and Practice, London: University of
London Press, 1975. Mark F. Imber, ‘Re-Reading Mitrany: A Pragmatic Assessment of
Sovereignty’, Review of International Studies, 1984, vol. 10, 103–23.
34 Mitrany, ‘The Functional Approach to World Organization’.
35 Cornelia Navari, ‘David Mitrany and International Functionalism’, in David Long and Peter
Wilson (eds), Thinkers of the Twenty Years’ Crisis, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995;
Anderson, ‘David Mitrany’; Ashworth, Creating International Studies; Ashworth and Long
New Perspectives on International Functionalism; and Wilson, ‘The New Europe Debate in
Wartime Britain’.
7 Politics between and beyond nations: Hans J.
Morgenthau’s Politics Among Nations
Nicolas Guilhot
What goes under the name of ‘theory’ in PAN is thus a phenomenology of power, a casuistic
exercise aiming at ‘detecting’ or ‘distinguishing’ political phenomena rather than
articulating them under eternal laws. The book is replete with nomenclatures, typolo-
gies, taxonomies and other types of distinctions – between sources of power, between
imperialisms, etc. This phenomenological acuity, which consists in recognizing, within
the uninterrupted jetstream of events, the basic ‘underlying forces’ that determine it, is
a talent that belongs to the scholar as much as to the seasoned politician. The theory of
international politics, as Morgenthau understood it, could be not separated from the
exercise of sound political judgement, and thus from a given historical context.
Hans J. Morgenthau: Politics Among Nations 71
Against the positivistic and scientistic readings of realism and against ambiguous
formulations owing to Morgenthau himself, it is important to emphasize that PAN
does not purport to turn international politics into a science.10 If what is called for is
‘creative imagination’ rather than the detached calculations of the scientist, it is because
for Morgenthau each historical situation is ‘unique’, and cannot be derived from an
axiomatic set of principles. The antiscientific thrust that provides the basso continuo of
PAN stems from the powerful echoes that Weimarian Wissenssoziologie finds in Mor-
genthau’s work. If there cannot be a scientific knowledge of history – and, for that
matter, of politics – it is because knowledge itself is historical, as Morgenthau never tired
of repeating.11 While the cornerstone of science in the 1950s was its value-neutrality,
‘no study of international politics … can be disinterested in the sense that it is able to
divorce knowledge from action and to pursue knowledge for its own sake’ (p. 7), since
the observer is also a participant existentially engaged in the situation he describes.
Knowledge is historically situated and indexed to a specific situation.12 Of course, the
kind of knowledge offered in PAN is no exception, and it too is rooted in a particular
historical configuration, as the book’s explicit purpose is ‘to reflect on international
politics in the United States, as we approach the mid-twentieth century’ (p. 8). The
adoption of Morgenthau as the tutelary figure of a discipline eager to pass as a social
‘science’ has made us forget that its founding text was explicitly claiming its historical
situatedness.
Conclusion
It is probably impossible to pronounce a summary judgement about PAN, because of
the scope of the book, but also because Morgenthau’s purpose was not to build a sys-
tematic theory. As a result, he was able to weave together strands of thought that were
not always congruent and reflected the superposition of different contexts and different
intellectual traditions. In the luxuriance of the book, just as in the complexity of
Morgenthau’s biography, it is possible to find a mixture of elements that can be inter-
preted in one way or another: a critique of nationalism, but also a critique of democ-
racy and its deleterious effects upon foreign policy; an appeal to the ‘rational element’
in IR, but also a sustained rejection of rationalism; reformist ideas, but also an
unrestrained amor fati, which is the unmistakable mark of all conservative thought and
always legitimates the authority of tradition (‘what exists must have something to be
said in its favor; otherwise it would not exist’, p. 63). As a result, Morgenthau’s realism
has been alternatively described as a reconstruction of liberalism (Michael Williams), a
conservative theory of politics (Martti Koskenniemi), or an extension of Weimarian
progressive culture into international affairs (William Scheuerman in his most recent
Hans J. Morgenthau: Politics Among Nations 77
work) – when it has not just been pigeonholed into a simplistic version of power poli-
tics. In the end, it is highly implausible that the interpretation of Morgenthau’s politics
and of his vision of IR will ever command agreement among scholars. The question
may simply be undecidable, and the meaning of PAN, as with any other ‘classic’, can
be recovered only through the careful study of its reception and its uses. In the mean-
time, the interpretation of Morgenthau and PAN will remain the turf upon which the
battles over the identity of the discipline are fought, and a good indication of its current
state and future direction.
Notes
1 Robert Jervis, ‘Hans Morgenthau, Realism, and the Scientific Study of International Rela-
tions’, Social Research, 1994, vol. 61, 853–54, at p. 853.
2 Hans J. Morgenthau, Politics among Nations: The Struggle for Power and Peace, New York:
Knopf, 1948. Unless otherwise stated page numbers placed in parentheses in the text refer to
this first edition.
3 Christoph Frei, Hans J. Morgenthau: An Intellectual Biography, Baton Rouge, LA: Louisiana
State University Press, 2001, p. 73. Besides Frei and Scheuerman, see also Alfons Söllner,
‘German Conservatism in America: Morgenthau’s Political Realism’, Telos, 1987, vol. 72,
161–72.
4 Waldemar Gurian, ‘Reviews – International Politics’, The Review of Politics, 1949, vol. 11,
255–59, at pp. 255–56.
5 The evolution of Morgenthau’s thinking about nuclear war is analysed in Campbell Craig,
Glimmer of a New Leviathan: Total War in the Realism of Niebuhr, Morgenthau, and Waltz,
New York: Columbia University Press, 2003.
6 For a few examples of this current Morgenthau revival, see for instance Anthony F. Lang
(ed.), Political Theory and International Affairs: Hans J. Morgenthau on Aristotle’s the Politics,
Greenwood, CT: Praeger, 2004; A. J. H. Murray, ‘The Moral Politics of Hans Morgenthau’,
The Review of Politics, 1996, vol. 58, 81–107; William Scheuerman, ‘Was Morgenthau a
Realist? Revisiting Scientific Man vs. Power Politics’, Constellations, 2007, vol. 14, 506–30;
William Scheuerman, Hans Morgenthau: Realism and Beyond, Cambridge: Polity Press, 2009;
Vibeke Schou Tjalve, Realist Strategies of Republican Peace: Niebuhr, Morgenthau, and the
Politics of Patriotic Dissent, New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2008; Michael C. Williams,
‘Why Ideas Matter in International Relations: Hans Morgenthau, Classical Realism, and the
Moral Construction of Power Politics’, International Organization, 2004, vol. 58, 633–65;
Michael C. Williams (ed.), Realism Reconsidered: The Legacy of Hans J. Morgenthau in
International Relations, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007. I analyse some of the reasons
behind this revival in the Introduction to Nicolas Guilhot (ed.), The Invention of International
Relations: Realism, the Rockefeller Foundation and the 1954 Conference on Theory, New
York: Columbia University Press, 2011.
7 PAN is composed of 32 chapters divided into ten sections. Section I (‘Theory and Practice of
International Politics’) clarifies the approach followed by Morgenthau and distinguishes it
from the social scientific ideal of reducing politics to a social physics. Section II focuses on the
concept of power and on the expression of power politics in the international arena (status
quo, imperialism, policy of prestige). The book then explores the predominant – i.e.
national – form that power takes in the contemporary world (Section III), and the different
devices that have been used to contain national power: the balance of power (Section IV),
international morality and public opinion (Section V); international law (Section VI). Section
VII is an intermezzo taking stock of the state of world politics after 1945 and of the paralysis
of the traditional limitations of power. Sections VIII and IX concentrate on Morgenthau’s
devastating critiques of the various means to achieve peace through law, from disarmament
conferences to the UN, or peace through transformation, from the utopias of the world state
to the cultural activism of UNESCO. The last section, focusing on ‘peace through accom-
modation’, advocates the restoration of traditional diplomacy as the most promising, albeit
imperfect, way to ensure a modicum of peace and stability.
78 Nicolas Guilhot
8 On the anti-scientific drive of early realism, see Nicolas Guilhot, ‘The Realist Gambit: Post-
war American Political Science and the Birth of IR Theory’, International Political Sociology,
2008, vol. 2, 281–304.
9 This dimension is not entirely absent from the ‘Six Principles’: while Morgenthau compares a
rational theory of IR to a ‘portrait’, he still mentions that it will never overlap perfectly with
the ‘photographic picture’ of reality (pp. 7–8, fourth edition)
10 One could object to the title of Chapter 2, ‘The Science of International Politics’. However,
under this misleading title, the chapter is essentially a reflection upon the limits of rational-
ism, and it is entirely possible that Morgenthau deliberately chose to misrepresent his argu-
ment in order to surf the enthusiasm of the times for the social science project. As he had
acknowledged earlier, ‘no political thinker can expect to be heard who would not, at least in
his terminology, pay tribute to the spirit of science’. Hans J. Morgenthau, Scientific Man vs.
Power Politics, Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 1946, p. 31. A similar reading of
PAN can be found in Oliver Jütersonke, ‘The Image of Law in Politics among Nations’, in
Williams, Realism Reconsidered, pp. 93–117.
11 For a discussion of realism’s uneasy relation to science, see ‘The Realist Gambit’.
12 On this issue, see Peter Wilson’s chapter on Carr and Casper Sylvest’s contribution on Herz in
this volume.
13 Immediately after the previous quotation, Morgenthau adds a beautiful and incisive conclu-
sion: ‘Little do they know that they meet under an empty sky from which the gods have
departed’.
14 On this theme, see Roger Epp, ‘The Ironies of Christian Realism: The End of an Augustinian
Tradition in International Politics,’ in Eric Patterson (ed.), The Christian Realists: Reassessing
the Contributions of Niebuhr and His Contemporaries, Lanham, MD: University Press of
America, 2003, pp. 199–232; Nicolas Guilhot, ‘American Katechon: When Political Theology
Became IR Theory’, Constellations, 2010, vol. 17, 224–53. The influence of Niebuhr on both
Morgenthau and IR in general is important. See Daniel Rice, ‘Reinhold Niebuhr and Hans
Morgenthau: A Friendship with Contrasting Shades of Realism’, Journal of American Stu-
dies, 2008, vol. 42, 255–91. On Niebuhr and Morgenthau’s vision of politics after 1945, see
Tjalve, Realist Strategies of Republican Peace.
15 On this point, see in particular Richard Little, ‘The Balance of Power in Politics among
Nations’, in Williams, Realism Reconsidered, pp. 137–65, as well as the discussion in
Scheuerman, Hans Morgenthau.
16 See the discussion about the ‘uncertainty of the balance’ (p. 151).
17 The non-mechanistic nature of Morgenthau’s theory of the balance of power is also under-
scored by Michael Williams, ‘Why Ideas Matter in International Relations’, pp. 651–52.
18 Hans J. Morgenthau, ‘Positivism, Functionalism, and International Law,’ American Journal
of International Law, 1940, vol. 32, 260–84, at p. 275.
19 Stanley Hoffmann, ‘Notes on the Limits of Realism’, Social Research, 1981, vol. 48, 653–59,
at p. 657.
20 Jütersonke, ‘The Image of Law’, p. 109.
21 In particular Scheuerman, Hans Morgenthau, and Williams, Realism Reconsidered.
22 According to Stefano Guzzini, its reception was initially rather ‘one-sided’ and overlooked its
anti-Hobbesian aspects. Guzzini, Realism in International Relations and International Political
Economy, London: Routledge, 1998, p. 24.
23 Scheuerman, Hans Morgenthau.
24 While writing the sections of PAN dedicated to world government, Morgenthau had certainly
on his mind the United World Federalists, led by Cord Meyer, and the more utopian Com-
mittee to Frame a World Constitution based at the University of Chicago.
25 On this issue, see Martti Koskenniemi, The Gentle Civilizer of Nations: The Rise and Fall of
International Law, 1870–1960, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002; Hans-Karl
Pichler, ‘The Godfathers of “Truth”: Max Weber and Carl Schmitt in Morgenthau’s Theory
of Power Politics’, Review of International Studies, 1998, vol. 24, 185–200; William Scheuer-
man, Carl Schmitt: The End of Law, Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, 1999; Williams,
‘Why Ideas Matter in International Relations’.
26 Carl Schmitt, The Concept of the Political, Chicago, IL: Chicago University Press, 2007, p. 54.
27 Gurian, ‘Reviews – International Politics’, p. 257.
Hans J. Morgenthau: Politics Among Nations 79
28 Hans J. Morgenthau, ‘What the Big Two Can, and Can’t Negotiate’, The New York Times,
20 September 1959, quoted in Craig, Glimmer of a New Leviathan, p. 107.
29 Hans J. Morgenthau, University of Maryland address, March 1961, quoted in Craig, Glim-
mer of a New Leviathan, p. 108. On the issue of the world state, see in particular Hidemi
Suganami, The Domestic Analogy and World Order Proposals, Cambridge: Cambridge Uni-
versity Press, 1989 and Danilo Zolo, Cosmopolis: Prospects for World Government, Cam-
bridge: Polity Press, 1997.
8 The enduring logic of the three images:
Kenneth N. Waltz’s Man, the State,
and War
Brian C. Schmidt
There is little need to belabour the question of whether Kenneth Waltz’s Man, the
State, and War: A Theoretical Analysis (1959, MSW) is a classic text of International
Relations (IR).1 No matter how one defines the term, MSW unequivocally is a classic.
Although much of Waltz’s fame derives from his landmark book, Theory of Interna-
tional Politics (1979),2 establishing structural realism or neo-realism as a dominant
paradigm, Waltz’s exposition of the ‘third image’ – the anarchy among states – in his
earlier book lays the foundation for the systemic theory of realism that he develops
later. Waltz himself attributes the durability of MSW ‘to the continuity of international
politics’, which he argues is best explained by the enduring ‘anarchic structure of
international politics’ (p. xi). The fact that MSW not only remains in print, but con-
tinues to be widely read by both undergraduate students and senior scholars is a testi-
mony to the significant contribution that the book makes to the study of international
politics. By developing three distinct images or, if you like, three distinct levels of ana-
lysis, for investigating the cause of war, Waltz makes a profound and lasting contribu-
tion to the field and it is incredibly difficult to imagine how IR would have evolved if he
had not written this book.
The chapter begins with a short overview of the main arguments and content of
MSW. The overview provides additional justifications for designating the book a classic
work of IR. Next, I situate the text within the disciplinary history of IR and highlight
the unique contribution that Waltz makes to the field. While a greater appreciation of
the significance of the text can be gained by situating it in the history of IR, its status
as a classic is strengthened further by the fact that it continues to serve as a foundation
for new research in the field. In the last section, I consider some of the critiques of
Waltz’s MSW.
the third image describes the framework of world politics, but without the first and
second images there can be no knowledge of the forces that determine policy; the
first and second images describe the forces in world politics, but without the third
image it is impossible to assess their importance or predict their results (p. 238).
by his hasty rejection of the usefulness of the behavioural sciences, and his heavy
reliance upon the traditional political philosophers, Waltz seems to succumb to,
and strengthen, such taboos, thus inhibiting his own search for the answers that he
posed in Man, the State, and War.12
Notes
1 Kenneth N. Waltz, Man, the State, and War: A Theoretical Analysis, New York: Columbia
University Press, [1959] 2001. Page numbers placed in parentheses in the text refer to this
edition.
2 See also Anders Wivel’s chapter in this volume.
3 J. David Singer, ‘The Level-of-Analysis Problem in International Relations’, in Klauss Knorr
and Sidney Verba (eds), The International System: Theoretical Essays, Princeton, NJ: Prin-
ceton University Press, 1961, pp. 77–92.
4 Stanley Hoffman, ‘International Relations: The Long Road to Theory’, World Politics, 1959,
vol. 11, 346–77.
5 Nicolas Guilhot (ed.), The Invention of International Relations Theory, New York: Columbia
University Press, 2011.
6 Martin Wight, ‘Why Is There No International Theory?’, International Relations, 1960, vol.
2, 35–48.
7 Brian C. Schmidt, ‘The Rockefeller Foundation Conference and the Long Road to a Theory
of International Politics’, in Guilhot (ed.), The Invention of International Relations Theory,
pp. 79–96.
8 Kenneth N. Waltz, ‘Political Philosophy and the Study of International Relations’, in William
T. R. Fox (ed.), Theoretical Aspects of International Relations, Notre Dame, IN: University of
Notre Dame Press, 1959, pp. 51–67.
88 Brian C. Schmidt
9 Hans J. Morgenthau, Scientific Man Versus Power Politics, Chicago, IL: University of Chi-
cago Press, 1946.
10 Paul Y. Hammond, review of Kenneth N. Waltz, Man, the State, and War, in Political Sci-
ence Quarterly, 1960, vol. 75, 448–50, at p. 449.
11 J. David Singer, ‘International Conflict: Three Levels of Analysis’, World Politics, 1960, vol.
12, 453–61, at p. 455.
12 Singer, ‘International Conflict’, p. 461.
13 Hidemi Suganami, ‘Understanding Man, the State, and War’, International Relations, 2009,
vol. 23, 372–88, at p. 386.
14 Kalevi J. Holsti, Peace and War: Armed Conflicts and International Order 1648–1989, Cam-
bridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991.
15 Daniel S. Geller and J. David Singer, Nations at War: A Scientific Study of International
Conflict, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998, p. 2.
16 John A. Vasquez (ed.), What Do We know about War?, Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield,
2000.
17 Suganami, ‘Understanding Man, the State, and War’, p. 382.
18 Suganami, ‘Understanding Man, the State, and War’, p. 380.
19 Daniel L. Byman and Kenneth M. Pollack, ‘Let Us Now Praise Great Men: Bringing the
Statesman Back In’, International Security, 2001, vol. 25, 107–46, at p. 112.
20 Jack S. Levy, ‘Domestic Politics and War’, in Robert I. Rotberg and Theodore K. Rabb (eds),
The Origin and Prevention of Major Wars, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989, p. 79.
21 Kenneth N. Waltz, Theory of International Politics, New York: Random House, 1979, p. 18.
22 Robert O. Keohane (ed.), Neorealism and its Critics, New York: Columbia University Press,
1986.
23 See e.g. Helen Milner, ‘The Assumption of Anarchy in International Relations: A Critique’,
Review of International Studies, 1991, vol. 17, 67–85.
9 The conditions and consequences of globality:
John H. Herz’s International Politics
in the Atomic Age
Casper Sylvest
Columbia University Press published not one but two classics of International Rela-
tions (IR) in 1959. The best-known is undoubtedly Kenneth N. Waltz’s Man, the State
and War, which fleshed out the three images that generations of scholars and their
students have since deployed to make sense of war and international politics. Despite
its popularity and favourable reception at the time, the second book has not achieved
quite the same status. International Politics in the Atomic Age (IPAA) by John H. Herz
(1908–2005) is nevertheless a classic by virtue of its groundbreaking analysis of the
nuclear revolution and its impact on the theory and practice of world politics.1
Whereas Waltz’s work foreshadowed a new systematic and social scientific brand of
(neo-)realism, IPAA was the first sustained and durable attempt to ponder what realism
might mean in the atomic age.
In the early twenty-first century classical realism is back in vogue. For a variety of
reasons, including the perceived sterility of neo-realism, the need for a refined critique
of ideological crusading, and a push to reorientate IR theory and realism towards some
of the most pertinent political, democratic and normative challenges of contemporary
global politics, a growing literature harks back to the rich and tension-ridden analyses
of international politics formulated by realists during the mid-twentieth century.2 As
part of this development the social and political thought of Herz has been accorded
more attention in recent years.3 Like other contemporary realists, the starting point for
Herz was an understanding of international politics as conflictual and hostile to liberal
programmes for reform. This involved developing sophisticated theories and strategies
for understanding and navigating the perilous waters of international politics; strategies
which respected the workings of politics and guarded against its pitfalls while also,
significantly, sketching the imperfect ways in which some progress might after all be
achieved. Working with the forces of social life and not against them, judiciously
combining moderation and power for socially useful purposes, and respecting the value
of diplomacy and the Fingerspitzengefühl (intuition) of practical experience were (and
are) some of the mantras of this brand of realism.
Although post-war realists prided themselves on their useful concepts and theoretical
insights, in our modern vocabulary of (US) social science, realism of this sort was as
much vision or ideology as theory. The 1950s and 1960s was a crucial period in the
development and eventual bifurcation of US political science into a behavioural and
eventually rationalist standard and the increasingly isolated domain of political theory.
With realists at the helm, IR tried for some time to avoid being steamrolled by the
move to science.4 This was ultimately a futile project as the defensive tone of Herz’s
preface to IPAA testifies. Here he characterized the book as ‘old-fashioned’ and
90 Casper Sylvest
sardonically admitted that he had not used IBM machines, conducted interviews or sur-
veys, and that the text was free from graphs, diagrams and statistical figures: ‘It is
simply the product of the application to problems and subject matter at hand of
whatever intelligence was available’ (p. v). Armed with these old-fashioned tools, Herz
embarked on an analysis that deserves its classics label precisely by virtue of its ability
to connect a realist analysis with humanist, liberal values under the condition of
‘globality’ (p. 317) that nuclear weapons inaugurated but which have since been rein-
forced by a range of crises related to climate change, environmental degradation,
population growth and energy.
This chapter seeks to make this case by first providing a brief introduction to Herz,
his German-Jewish background and to his best-known contribution to IR theory: the
concept of the security dilemma. I then turn to a summary of IPAA, its structure and
arguments, before ending with a discussion of the reception of the book and its
contemporary relevance.
The diagnosis
Writing in the late 1950s, any sound analysis of international politics, according to
Herz, had to begin from and try to make sense of the nuclear revolution and its impact
on humanity, social life and political organization. IPAA was designed and written
with this objective in mind. In essence the argument of the book is that some of the
fundamental characteristics of the international system, particularly territoriality and
the notion that (great power) war is winnable, are fundamentally challenged and
transfigured by the invention of thermonuclear weapons and intercontinental delivery
vehicles. In this context, the concept of the national interest became (even more)
unstable and mysterious, if not empty. The atomic age literally meant a globalization of
human existence – a contraction of time and space – that in turn globalized threats to
security and liberty. Consequently, the structure of international politics was under-
going a dramatic change.10 Universal destructivity undermined the claims of almost
any political authority to offer protection and security. Humanity was placed in a new,
precarious and potentially catastrophic condition, which was only exacerbated by the
ineptness of traditional analytical and political tools, including the time-honoured
92 Casper Sylvest
perspective and practice of power politics. The double task thrown up by these devel-
opments was to analyse, assess and conceptualize the nature, extent and consequences
of this change in international politics and to begin the task of charting possible routes of
escape.
The structure of IPAA reflects this argument. The first two parts of the book deal
with the rise of traditional international politics from the seventeenth century and with
the challenge of this system provided by the H-bomb, and the ‘accumulated and accu-
mulating effect’ of modern science and technology (p. 12). The penetration of the atom
led, in short, to the perforation of the ‘hard shell’ of the state, because there were no
appropriate means of defence against nuclear weapons. This in turn invalidated the
security contract (see below) on which this form of authority was based. The third and
final part of IPAA was Herz’s attempt to confront this predicament and the reconfigured
security dilemmas it involved.
The account of the rise of modern international politics placed much emphasis on
the concept of territoriality, which emerged as a specific solution to a political problem
during the seventeenth century: how could the more than 300 states in the Holy Roman
Empire – structures of political authority that technically were under the suzerainty of
the nominal unity of Pope and Emperor – be considered sovereign? How, in other
words, could sovereignty be defined in a way that accommodated the hotchpotch of
juridical and political allegiances in the Holy Roman Empire and respected the de facto
authority of ‘states’? Herz found the answer in a short essay by G. W. Leibniz (1646–
1716), which summarized some of the most important findings of Caesarinus Für-
stenerius (1677). According to Leibniz, sovereignty may not be absolute in the Hobbesian
sense, but it did signify ability to participate in European affairs and (more impor-
tantly) de facto control of a territory. This sociological formula bound sovereignty,
independence and power to ‘an underlying pattern of statehood’ without compromising
the ethereal majesté of the Holy Roman Empire. Territoriality gradually turned states
into hard, impenetrable shells, while their interaction made them part of a larger col-
lective structure. This was, according to Herz, the bedrock of modern international
politics.
Informing this conception of the state was a version of the social contract: protection
and security was the currency that made citizens obey state authority. Seen in con-
junction with the development of modern science and technology (what Herz was later
to term the civilizational process),11 the trend towards ever larger units could be
understood in terms of persistent recalibrations of the relationship between technolo-
gies of destruction and the protection offered by the predominant forms of political
authority. Just like the gunpowder revolution challenged the small state and city-states,
the nuclear revolution spelled the end of the security contract on which the nation state
was based. Herz did not argue that territorially based states did not, in fact, continue to
play an important role in international politics, only that their underlying rationale had
been eroded with the development of the H-bomb. What distinguished this situation
from earlier adjustments to the balance between protection, political authority, the size
of units and increased technology-based destructivity was that the end of the cycle had
been reached (p. 13). In effect, the world had closed. The dangers of Cold War ten-
sions, based on the nation state system and extended territoriality, could perhaps logically
be countered by a world state, but that appeared decidedly impractical at the height of
superpower confrontation. Other means of stabilizing and reforming the world (of
states) had to be identified.12
John H. Herz: International Politics in the Atomic Age 93
In advancing this argument, Herz idealized, romanticized even, the limited but fun-
damentally important norms that buttressed and moderated international politics in
the passing age of territoriality. Like Morgenthau’s analysis of the golden age of the
balance of power or the English school’s perspective on the institutions that are essen-
tial for the stability and reproduction of an international society,13 Herz’s conception of
power politics went far beyond the mechanical. At the same time, idealizing the power
politics of a bygone age was also a rhetorical strategy that served to underline the
radical nature of the change that Herz sought to identify. Here lies a key strength of
IPAA. While some of its arguments about the obsolescence of hard security shells or
the omnicidal character of nuclear weapons appear as second nature to us, in the late
1950s with the Cuban Missile Crisis lurking in the future such arguments struggled to
advance beyond the one-worldist slogans of the peace movement (‘one world, or
none’). Herz trod a fine line between pointing to the essential unpredictability, indefi-
niteness and hectic flux beneath the apparently stable order of international politics,
while insisting that something fundamental was being transformed. Indeed, Herz
argued that these developments amounted to ‘the most radical change in the nature of
power and the characteristics of power units since the beginning of the modern state
system or, perhaps, since the beginnings of mankind’ (p. 22).
A perspective that took into account the apparent stability, new challenges and an
underlying, conceptual systemic crisis was characteristic of Herzian analysis. Indeed,
the messy world of real international politics only reinforced the acute danger of the
situation, since outmoded analytical tools prevented scholars and policy-makers from
grasping change. In this context Herz shrewdly examined the preconditions and logics
of bipolarity and deterrence, accepting their apparent stability while warning against
their underlying fragility. The Herzian analysis of (ideological) bipolarity as stable, qua
being ‘a rigid and perpetually endangered equipoise’ (p. 166) that only faintly resem-
bled a balance of power system, in some ways anticipated Kenneth Waltz’s later ana-
lysis but also took much more seriously the danger of nuclear weapons.14 Similarly,
drawing on Robert Oppenheimer’s famous image of ‘two scorpions in a bottle’ (p. 14),
Herz foreshadowed critiques of deterrence as being capable of achieving stability within
narrowly defined parameters but also as ultimately unreliable as a general principle of
international order.15 The reasoning behind this verdict was (and is) that effective
deterrence requires at least ‘a minimum of rationality, self-restraint, and ability to
subordinate immediate “national” interests to overall world interests in the avoidance
of destruction on the part of the powers’ (pp. 209–10). Fear and uncertainty make this
kind of rationality implausible. People and politics enter the equation, and with that a
never-ending game of second-guessing intentions. Stability becomes mere hope. The
overall effect of these insights was to underline the seriousness of the situation and the
limited visibility of observers and practitioners. To Herz it was, then:
[n]o wonder that international politics, not only in its actualities but also in its
concepts and terminologies, is confused, and that present-day man in the world
exists as in a maze. At no time in modern history has security meant so much to
him; at no time has there seemed less hope of retrieving it (p. 223).
However, if security is so decisive in the atomic age, why can it not be provided? The
answer is simple: the security dilemma. Fear, uncertainty about the intentions of others
and the offensive capability lodged in every claim for necessary defensive military
94 Casper Sylvest
measures, can easily conspire to produce mistrust and suboptimal outcomes. In fact,
the security dilemma reached its most poignant manifestation in the pinched ideologi-
cal bipolarity of the Cold War (p. 241).
Paths to survival
And yet, IPAA was more than a doomsday scenario of realism. The fact that in the atomic
age ‘power can destroy power from center to center’ (p. 108), gave fear and worst-case
scenarios a special place in the configuration of international politics. Living on the
knife-edge of fear could result in preventive warfare and quests for world hegemony.
However, here the poignancy of the security dilemma produced a paradox that allowed
a ray of light into the otherwise grey mental landscape of nuclear winter: not only was
the attempt to achieve security from attack or dominance often counterproductive, it
was potentially self-destructive, since the means to security could eradicate the end and
then some. The alternative to mutual accommodation was mutual destruction (p. 243).
It was against this background that Part III of IPAA offered a two-tiered sketch of
how international politics could be brought back from the brink of auto-destruction.
The first and most immediate task was to conduct ‘a holding operation’, which mobilized
the entire edifice of classical realist virtues. The aim was to create a balance – a modus
vivendi – between the two superpowers, and that entailed a recognition of the impurity
of politics, the need for quid pro quos, and an acceptance that some (containable)
realms of ‘low-intensity’ or proxy conflicts had to be left to themselves as safety valves.
Apart from this it was diplomacy, statesmanship, empathy, gradual build-up of trust
and a sober assessment of power relations – the cardinal virtues of classical realism –
that carried the burden (Chapter 11). One discerns parallels to other realist aphorisms
here: to Carr’s notion that stability in human affairs is like the stability of the bicycle or
the spinning top, to Kissinger’s formula of acting as if your intuition was already
experience or, more mysteriously, to Morgenthau’s equation of political wisdom and
fortuity.16
The second and much more extensive task was to rethink our options in the shadow
of the nuclear threat. This was dependent on (what became known as) détente and an
amelioration of security concerns. Few and certainly not Herz, expected this to happen
in 1959. In fact, Herz often characterized himself as an ingrained pessimist. He felt a
duty to investigate how a more constructive and lasting peace could be envisaged in the
atomic age, and it was this sense of duty, apparently, more than any expectation about
the prospects of this project materializing, that powered the most controversial chapters
of the book. The straw that Herz held on to was a frail, positive element hidden in the
threat of universal destruction. On the other hand, Herz seems to have got carried
away just a little during the research process. He came to argue, indeed, that a liberal
internationalist project could no longer, in the new circumstances, be dismissed as
prima facie utopian. And while the starting point of this analysis was nuclear weapons,
other problems quickly pointed in the same direction – the population explosion and
its consequences for resource depletion and the earth’s environment also contributed to
the condition of globality (pp. 316–19). Arguably, the third part of IPAA evinces the
case of the professional realist, for whom distancing himself from utopianism is so
customary, that when he gradually warms to solutions that are traditionally associated
with one-worldism, he relabels them or takes shelter in the uniqueness of the nuclear
age (e.g. p. 309).
John H. Herz: International Politics in the Atomic Age 95
In the wake of the nuclear revolution, the project of universalism was based on a
realization that in the long run national interest and universal idea(l)s were inseparable.
It was based, in short, on an ethics of survival: despite competing value claims among
humans, survival is a truly universal value. To many readers (past and present), this
prompts questions about what, if anything, realism can then mean. Again, it is worth
directing attention to the red thread running through Herz’s oeuvre: the attempt to
harness realist insights for more sophisticated attempts to realize the values of humanist
liberalism. The conceptualization of the security dilemma as a social condition made
this possible. The nuclear revolution and the identification of ‘the combined population-
resources problem’ (p. 316) did not spell an end to this vision; if anything, and to the
disappointment of some realist colleagues, it intensified Herz’s liberal longings. In
the first instance this was a case for ‘divesting nations of their nuclear power’, a move
(perhaps the only one) that could potentially restore the impermeability and future of
the nation state (p. 339). In the long run, however, IPAA was the first step towards
broadening the concept of security to include issues relating to the environment, cli-
mate, poverty and resource depletion. For Herz, discovering globality and the oneness
of the world permanently upset the balance between the real, the possible and the
necessary.
Notes
1 John H. Herz, International Politics in the Atomic Age, New York: Columbia University
Press, 1959. Page numbers placed in parentheses in the text refer to this edition. On Waltz,
see Brian C. Schmidt’s chapter in this volume.
2 For a good overview, see Duncan Bell, ‘Introduction: Under an Empty Sky – Realism and
Political Theory’, in Bell (ed.), Political Thought and International Relations: Variations on a
Realist Theme, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008, pp. 1–25.
3 See, in particular, International Relations, 2008, vol. 22, special issue commemorating the
centenary of the birth of Herz, as well as Peter Stirk, ‘John H. Herz: Realism and the Fragi-
lity of the International Order’, Review of International Studies, 2005, vol. 31, 285–306;
John H. Herz: International Politics in the Atomic Age 97
Christian Hacke and Jana Puglierin, ‘John H. Herz: Balancing Utopia and Reality’, Interna-
tional Relations, 2007, vol. 21, 367–82; Ken Booth, Theory of World Security, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2007; William E. Scheuerman, ‘Realism and the Critique of
Technology’, Cambridge Review of International Affairs, 2009, vol. 22, 563–84; Casper Syl-
vest, ‘Realism and International Law: The Challenge of John H. Herz’, International Theory,
2010, vol. 2, 410–45; Jana Puglierin, John H. Herz: Leben und Denken zwischen Idealismus
und Realismus, Deutschland und Amerika, Berlin: Duncker and Humblot, 2011; Casper Syl-
vest, ‘Technology and Global Politics: The Modern Experiences of Bertrand Russell and John
H. Herz’, International History Review, 2013, vol. 35, 121–42.
4 See particularly Nicolas Guilhot, ‘The Realist Gambit: Postwar American Political Science
and the Birth of IR Theory’, International Political Sociology, 2008, vol. 2, 281–304. For
general discussion of the development and competing identities of political science, see John
G. Gunnell, The Descent of Political Theory, Chicago, IL: Chicago University Press, 1993;
Emily Hauptmann, ‘Defining Theory in Postwar Political Science’, in George Steinmetz (ed.),
The Politics of Method in the Human Sciences, Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 2005,
pp. 207–32; Ira Katznelson, Desolation and Enlightenment, New York: Columbia University
Press, 2003.
5 Eduard Bristler, Die Völkerrechtslehre des Nationalsozialismus, Zürich: Europa, 1938. The
dissertation was written in English and later published (under pseudonym in German). See
also John H. Herz, Vom Überleben, Düsseldorf: Droste, 1984.
6 John H. Herz, Political Realism and Political Idealism, Chicago, IL: Chicago University
Press, 1951; John H. Herz, ‘Idealist Internationalism and the Security Dilemma’, World Pol-
itics, 1950, vol. 2, 157–80. See also Robert Jervis, ‘Cooperation Under the Security Dilemma’,
World Politics, 1978, vol. 30, 167–214; Charles L. Glaser, ‘The Security Dilemma Revisited’,
World Politics, 1997, vol. 50, 171–201; Ken Booth and Nicholas J. Wheeler, The Security
Dilemma: Fear, Cooperation and Trust in World Politics, Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan,
2008; Shiping Tang, ‘The Security Dilemma: A Conceptual Analysis’, Security Studies, 2009,
vol. 18, 587–623.
7 The most prominent defender of offensive neorealism, John J. Mearsheimer, does pay tribute
to Herz’s structural argument. See John J. Mearsheimer, The Tragedy of Great Power Politics,
New York: Norton, 2001, e.g. p. 36.
8 E. H. Carr made a very similar point in The Twenty Years’ Crisis. See Peter Wilson’s chapter
in this volume.
9 Herz, Political Realism and Political Idealism, p. 143.
10 In Herzian vocabulary, structure was shorthand for the fundamental characteristics of inter-
national politics in a given era, whereas the system referred to the ways in which the units of
this domain organized their relations (p. 7).
11 John H. Herz, ‘The Civilizational Process and its Reversal’, in Herz, The Nation-State and
the Crisis of World Politics, New York: McKay, 1976, pp. 195–225.
12 These considerations led Herz to modify the thesis about the territorial state that informed
IPAA. It was first advanced in John H. Herz, ‘Rise and Demise of the Territorial State’,
World Politics, 1957, vol. 9, 473–93, and revised in John H. Herz, ‘The Territorial State
Revisited – Reflections on the Future of the Nation-State’, Polity, 1968, vol. 1, 11–34.
13 See the chapters by Nicolas Guilhot and Andrew Hurrell in this volume.
14 See Kenneth N. Waltz, ‘The Stability of a Bipolar World’, Daedalus, 1964, vol. 93, 881–909;
Kenneth N. Waltz Theory of International Politics, New York: McGraw-Hill, 1979. See also
the critique in Campbell Craig, Glimmer of a New Leviathan: Total War in the Realism of
Niebuhr, Morgenthau, and Waltz, New York: Columbia University Press, 2003.
15 IPAA, Chapter 8, which also includes a sceptical analysis of graduated deterrence and ideas
about limited nuclear war (pp. 200–3). See also Nicholas J. Wheeler, ‘“To Put Oneself into the
Other Fellow’s Place”: John Herz, the Security Dilemma and the Nuclear Age’, International
Relations, 2008, vol. 22, 493–509.
16 E.H. Carr, Conditions of Peace, London: Macmillan, 1942, p. xxiii; Henry Kissinger, A World
Restored: Metternich, Castlereagh and the Problems of Peace 1812–1822, Boston, MA:
Houghton Mifflin, 1957, p. 328; Hans Morgenthau, Scientific Man versus Power Politics,
Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 1946, p. 187.
17 Herz, Vom Überleben, p. 169.
98 Casper Sylvest
18 The sales figures explain the publisher’s failed attempt to publish a new, second edition in the
late 1960s and early 1970s. Herz was unhappy with his terms and royalties. Time constraints
also played a part. The detailed sales figures and related correspondence can be found in John
H. Herz Papers, M. E. Grenander Department of Special Collections and Archives, State
University of New York at Albany, Box 40, Folder: ‘Correspondence with Publishers,
1957–75’ (the papers are uncatalogued; the reference is to the temporary organization of the
papers).
19 August Heckscher, ‘The Old Order Changeth – But Old Ways of Thinking Remain’, New
York Times, 29 March 1959; see also Charles C. Price, ‘Permeability on a Bipolar Planet’,
Saturday Review, 28–29 March 1959, pp. 29–30.
20 C. A. W. Manning, Review of IPAA, International Affairs, 1960, vol. 36, p. 75.
21 See, for example, Campbell Craig, ‘The Resurgent Idea of World Government’, Ethics and
International Affairs, 2008, vol. 22, 133–42.
22 Martin Wight, Review of IPAA, American Political Science Review, 1960, vol. 54, p. 1057.
See also Erich Hula, Review of IPAA, Social Research, 1960, vol. 27, 323–24; Arnold Wol-
fers, Review of IPAA, Political Science Quarterly, 1959, vol. 74, 437–38.
23 Daniel H. Deudney, Bounding Power: Republican Security Theory from the Polis to the
Global Village, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2007.
24 See particularly Craig, Glimmer of a New Leviathan.
25 In these debates the problems as well as the solutions vary widely. See e.g. Luis Cabrera,
‘World Government: Renewed Debate, Persistent Challenges’, European Journal of Interna-
tional Relations, 2010, vol. 16, 511–30; W.E. Scheuerman, The Realist Case for Global
Reform, Cambridge: Polity, 2011.
26 See particularly Craig, Glimmer of a New Leviathan, p. xv; Sylvest, ‘Realism and Interna-
tional Law’; Scheuerman, The Realist Case. Dan Deudney’s republican security theory points
in some of the same directions but is largely dismissive about Herz’s contribution. Deudney,
Bounding Power, pp. 249–52 and the critique in W.E. Scheuerman, ‘Deudney’s neorepu-
blicanism: One-world or America first?’, International Politics, 2010, vol. 47, 523–34. See also
Brent J. Steele’s chapter on Bounding Power in this volume.
27 John H. Herz, ‘On Human Survival: Reflections on Survival Research and Survival Policies’,
World Futures, 2003, vol. 59, 135–43, at pp. 140, 139.
10 Realism meets historical sociology:
Raymond Aron’s Peace and War
Bryan-Paul Frost
Henry Kissinger claimed that Raymond Aron’s Peace and War: A Theory of Interna-
tional Relations had established a ‘new standard’ in the field.1 While acknowledging
that no ‘book on such a vast subject can be final’, he nonetheless predicted that ‘hen-
ceforth, international theorizing will require reference to Aron’. Malheureusement, this
was one of Kissinger’s statements that did not prove prophetic.2 First published in
1962, Peace and War generally received critical acclaim throughout France. This was
no mean feat given Aron’s decidedly conservative and anti-communist credentials.
Once the book made it across the Atlantic and onto US shores, however, its reception
had markedly cooled.3 This is perhaps best illustrated in a review by another classic
author, Hans J. Morgenthau: while admitting that the book contained ‘political analy-
sis of the very first order,’ he more or less politely dismissed it as a ‘contribution to the
advancement of theoretical knowledge’.4 Certainly Peace and War is mentioned in
perfunctory footnotes listing famous and/or influential books in the tradition of classical
realism, but to all intents and purposes, John Hall’s comment about the work remains
as true today as it was when he wrote it in 1981: ‘one suspects that [Peace and War] is
more quoted than read.’5 In other words, Aron’s magisterial, 800-page tome is cited,
but not studied.
Although there are likely many reasons that account for this neglect, Stanley Hoff-
mann captured a large measure of the truth when he asked why Morgenthau’s classic
exercised such an enormous influence on the field of International Relations (IR)
whereas Aron’s influence was decidedly more muted:
One of the many reasons why Raymond Aron’s monumental Peace and War – a
book far more ambitious in its scope and far more sophisticated in its analyses
than Politics Among Nations – incited no comparable reaction from scholarly
readers may well have been the greater judiciousness and modesty of Aron’s
normative conclusions. Humane sceptics invite nods and sighs, not sound and fury;
and sound and fury are good for creative scholarship. Moreover, Aron’s own
scholarship was overwhelming enough to be discouraging; Morgenthau’s was just
shaky enough to inspire improvements.6
Similar remarks could be directed towards a more contemporary classic, namely Ken-
neth N. Waltz’s Theory of International Politics. Waltz criticizes both Aron and Hoff-
mann for rejecting the possibility of developing a general theory of international
relations similar to that found in economics. More specifically, Waltz argues that they
both fail to appreciate or grasp neorealism’s key insight ‘that international politics can
100 Bryan-Paul Frost
be thought of as a system with a precisely defined structure’: this is ‘neorealism’s
fundamental departure from traditional realism’. Consequently, Aron and Hoffmann
are much more likely to privilege the unit (or even individual) level of analysis when
explaining international outcomes and to downplay systemic causes: in the words of
Aron (which are cited by Waltz), ‘the principal actors have determined the system
more than they have been determined by it’ (p. 95).7 In short, we may surmise that
one of the reasons Peace and War suffers relative neglect in comparision to other
classic works in the field is because it did not ‘deliver the goods’ that so many aca-
demics were hoping for: Aron failed to construct a parsimonious, deductive and pre-
dictive theory of international politics.
It all depends on what we expect of a theory, of the model of a theory (in physics
or in economics) to which we refer. Such a conceptual analysis seems to me to
fulfil some of the functions that we can expect from a theory: it defines the essen-
tial features of a sub-system; it provides a list of the main variables; it suggests
certain hypotheses about the operation of the sub-system, depending on whether it
is bipolar or multipolar, homogeneous or heterogeneous.16
What we can say is that while Aron’s theory is not a system of interconnected
hypotheses, it does allow a theorist to enumerate the key elements of international
relations – the cause and effect phenomena – from which such hypotheses can be gen-
erated. It seems that Aron thought it more important to make certain that his analy-
tical framework helped to elicit the right questions about international relations, that it
allowed individuals to see the plurality of factors animating international politics.
Aron’s theoretical framework will suggest hypotheses, but never prescribe them.
Inis L. Claude’s Power and International Relations1 is an analysis of the role of inter-
national organization in securing peace among the great powers, particularly in a world
of bipolar confrontation and nuclear weapons. He compares three international sys-
tems for maintaining the peace: the balance of power; collective security; and world
government. He concludes that the balance of power is the most realistic, but that its
reliability as a mechanism for maintaining the peace is enhanced by being embedded in
the United Nations (UN), which provides both an institutional structure for and a
symbolism of pacific dispute resolution. As such, the argument is clearly realist in
its focus and assumptions, but more sympathetic to international institutions and
international cooperation than are most realist arguments.
A classical realist orientation with a focus on, and sympathy for, international organiza-
tions and the symbolism of cooperation is a hallmark of Claude’s work. His career
spanned the Cold War, with most of his major works published in the 1960s, and with
a core focus on the relationship among international organizations, the structure of the
international system, and the maintenance of international peace and security. Power
and International Relations fits neatly within this focus, although with a greater stress
on the international system, and less on international institutions as organizations, than
some of his other work. It was recognized at the time, and continues to be recognized,
as a classic conceptual analysis of the balance of power.
Power and International Relations is a fascinating book, and was well received at the
time of publication. Among other indicators, it won the American Political Science
Association’s Woodrow Wilson Award for best book on government, politics, or inter-
national affairs in 1963. However, in some respects it has not aged well in the half-
century since it was first published. While the title suggests a general treatment of
power in international relations, the book itself focuses on military power, and in par-
ticular on the prevention of great power, and nuclear, war. As such, much of the dis-
cussion is dated, since the security concerns at the height of the Cold War, with its
bipolar system and its persistent threat of nuclear war, are very different from those of
today. In addition, the project preceded what has been called the second great debate in
International Relations (IR), and the development of positivist methodologies.2 It is an
exercise in big thinking of the old school, focusing more on thoughtful and reasoned
argument than on methodological precision. At the same time, many of the details of
the argument remain relevant for the contemporary analysis of international security
structures, and the conclusions are prescient, foreshadowing some more recent devel-
opments both in international relations theory and in the practice of contemporary
international politics.
110 J. Samuel Barkin
The argument
Claude sets out to examine the problem of power and war in a world of intense bipolar
competition in which both superpowers, the USA and the Soviet Union, were devel-
oping sufficient nuclear forces to destroy civilization, and in which two world wars had
been fought within the past half-century. His goal is to analyse the three major schools
of thought predominant at the time regarding how to constrain national power and
restrain states from going to war, in order to determine which has the most promise.
The three schools of thought focus on the balance of power, collective security and
world government.
He begins by defining power very narrowly, much more so than many of his con-
temporary IR theorists, as military force. Power is thus for him a measure of the ability
to wage war in the short term, rather than a measure of longer-term military potential
(which would include economic potential, as Hans J. Morgenthau does3) or of the
ability to change the behaviour of others (which would include power over opinion, as
E. H. Carr does4). He sets out by asking what the three schools of thought can tell us
about how states can be restrained from using their existing military capabilities to
wage major war, given that in a nuclear world another world war could be uncon-
scionably destructive. He assumes that the nation state will remain for the foreseeable
future the core focus of political decision-making and of political loyalties, and therefore
that it will remain the central actor in international politics.
The focus on military power and on states suggests a realist analysis, and in many
ways Power and International Relations fits into the classical realist tradition (although
its focus on system structure foreshadows neorealism, in much the same way as does
Kenneth Waltz’s Man, the State, and War, published three years previously5). This fit is
reinforced by Claude’s frequent stress on the importance of politics rather than law and
formal institutional structure. However, he is much more willing than most realists to
criticize the concept of the balance of power, and is much less willing to write off as
‘utopian’ attempts to create other structural constraints on war. His is therefore a more
nuanced, liberal and internationalist version of classical realism than the works that
tend to be read as the classics of the genre today, such as Morgenthau’s Politics Among
Nations or John H. Herz’s Political Realism and Political Idealism.
Claude addresses the three schools of thought on a continuum from the least to the
greatest centralization of power, and in order of their historical development in the modern
state system. By either measure, the first to be addressed is the balance of power. His
primary criticism of the balance of power as a school of thought concerns its impreci-
sion. He identifies several potential meanings of the concept: a situation; a policy; and
a system. In any of the three meanings, furthermore, the term ‘balance’ is used both to
refer to an equilibrium, in which power across states and alliances is relatively equal, or
as a disequilibrium, in which threats to states, or to the peace, are overmatched. What
is worse, theorists of the balance of power often use these meanings interchangeably,
often without being clear about which of the meanings they refer to. (Claude in fact
gives several examples where different meanings are used within the same sentence.) In
the end, he concludes that for many IR theorists the concept of the balance of power is
a symbol of respectability rather than a term of substantive content. ‘It is a test of
intellectual virility, of he-manliness in the field of international relations.’6
The only use of the term that Claude finds useful in a discussion of the problem of
power and war is as a system, in which individual attempts to maximize power cancel
Inis L. Claude: Power and International Relations 111
each other out and result in an equilibrium of military capability. This can happen
either automatically (this is the version of the balance of power system that Waltz was
later to use as the foundation of neorealism7), or manually, as the result of policies by
specific states or statespeople designed to create equilibrium (this use being distinct
from balance of power as a specific foreign policy, in that it refers to systemic results
rather individual policy). Examples of a manually operated system include the British
self-conscious propensity in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries for keeping con-
tinental Europe divided, or the complex equilibria designed and managed by diplomats
such as Metternich.8
The problem that Claude has with the balance of power understood in this way is
that as a system it has historically not worked all that well at preventing war. He
quotes Morgenthau as arguing that the system has in the past been a success in pre-
venting the rise of a single imperial power, and then suggests that this is an ‘uncertain,
unreal, and inadequate system’ and that it is ‘necessary to take a somewhat stricter
view than Morgenthau’s of the nature of international order’.9 In response to Mor-
genthau’s claim that small nations owe their independence to the balance of power,
Claude responds that according to this argument ‘the preservation of weak states
depends upon an equilibrium, the absence of an equilibrium, or sheer luck; it can
hardly be regarded as a clear tribute to the equilibrating efficiency of a balance of
power system’.10 While his critique saves its most pointed ire for Morgenthau, it effec-
tively covers the range of realist thinking at the time of writing. He concludes that
while a balance of power system has some utility in constraining war, and has the
advantage that statespeople can draw on previous practice in operating the system, it is
prone to spectacular failures. Furthermore, the classical European balance destroyed in
World War I could no longer be reconstructed, and it was by no means clear how to
construct an effective new balance for a bipolar and nuclear world.
The second school of thought, the one to which by his own admission Claude is
most sympathetic, is collective security. He has two primary goals in his discussion of
this approach to constraining power and preventing war. The first is to debunk the
claim that collective security is an exercise in idealism that fails to take power into
account.11 This claim is often made by classical realists. More recently the claim has
become embedded in the story of the first great debate and its opposition of realism
and utopianism that has become so central to the history that IR as a discipline tells
about itself.12 Claude shows, through an extensive review of the works of scholars and
statespeople in what he calls the Wilsonian school (because President Wilson was its
most famous proponent, not its key thinker), that their work was not based on the
assumption that power could be ignored, but rather on the conclusion that the balance
of power had failed. The logic of the Wilsonian argument was that, in a world of total
war, great powers would come to recognize that any threat to the stability of the
international system was a threat to their national interest, and they needed an insti-
tutional structure through which to act on that recognition. The idea of collective
security was sold to the US public in more idealist language than this because its pro-
ponents felt that the public at large would respond better to idealist than to realist
language, not because its proponents were themselves idealists. Claude’s second goal in
his discussion of collective security is to show that a collective security system has in
fact never been tried in the modern state system. Such a system requires the participa-
tion of all of the great powers, and an agreement by those powers that collective action
will be taken against any of them that disturb the international peace. The League of
112 J. Samuel Barkin
Nations did not fit this bill, because at least two great powers did not participate at any
one time (the USA throughout, Germany and the Soviet Union for most of the Lea-
gue’s history). Furthermore, the UN, Claude argues, was never intended to oversee a
real collective security system. The veto given to permanent members of the Security
Council means that the body can never authorize action against the great powers. The
UN, therefore, was designed as a mechanism for preventing lesser powers from threatening
international security, not for replacing the balance of power as a mechanism for pre-
venting great power war. Claude’s conclusion is that collective security is a promising
system in principle, but that the requisite political conditions do not yet exist to put
such a system in place.
The third school of thought, the one to which Claude seems least sympathetic, is
world government. He argues that the logic of proposals for a supranational authority
capable of preventing war was insufficiently thought through. He criticizes proponents
of world government on three grounds. First, they have an inadequate theory of the
role of the state. The concept of world government is built on the idea of the state as
holder of the monopoly of force in a polity, but in practice states never actually hold
such a monopoly. Second, they are conceptually unclear about whether the subjects of
a world government would be individuals or states. Third, they propose systems of law
without recognizing that law cannot function purely as a deterrent, it needs to be based
on a collective political consensus. As such, Claude argues that world government in
the context of the modern state system is structurally flawed and politically implausible.
This section is the weakest in the book. Claude seems at times to be stretching to
ridicule an idea he does not like, rather than engaging in measured analysis. The discus-
sion of states and the monopoly of force is a good example. It points to several versions
of Max Weber’s definition of the state, without actually looking at Weber’s original,
with its nuanced elaboration.13 States (as opposed to governments – Claude confuses
the two in this section of the book) do in fact claim monopolies of legitimate violence
in support of a political order. A world government could presumably do the same, in a
way that limits even if it does not eliminate organized violence. Similarly, even if a
world government were not completely effective in eliminating violence among groups
(and it would probably not be), this is not the question that Claude started with. He set
out to address the question of great power war, and a world government that prevented
great powers from amassing large armies and major nuclear forces could in fact pre-
sumably prevent this specific form of organized violence. A world government capable
of doing so may create a different sort of monster, but this is not an argument that
Claude pursues.
The overall conclusion that Claude draws is that each of the three schools of thought
has something to contribute to solving the problem of power and war in international
relations. Balance of power theory recognizes that states have control over the means of
power, and will be reluctant to give it up. Collective security theory recognizes that
some increase in the political centralization of the international system is necessary in
response to the increasing destructiveness of contemporary power, while at the same
time recognizing the centrality of states to the system. World government theory, while
it does not provide an answer to the question of power and war in international relations,
usefully restates the question. It asks not how conflict among groups can be prevented,
but how it can be ‘resolved or contained by political rather than violent means’.14 He
also concludes that, rather than creating a system of collective security, the most
important aspect of the UN is taming the balance of power system, both by providing
Inis L. Claude: Power and International Relations 113
impartial dispute resolution of a kind that does not exist in a ‘pure’ state system, and
by changing what he calls the symbolism, what in the terminology of contemporary IR
would be called the norms,15 of war in the international system. This conclusion does
not appear to draw directly on the arguments made earlier in the book. Rather, it hints
at a new approach to understanding the problem of power and war, one that fore-
shadows both some of Claude’s later work,16 and the ideational turn in IR that began a
quarter of a century after Power and International Relations was written.
Contemporary relevance
In some ways Power and International Relations seems dated and of limited relevance
to the contemporary international scene, not surprising in a work that is more than half
a century old. In other ways, it does a good job of pointing out how both international
governance and academic IR have changed. The book is old enough that its predic-
tions about change in the international system have already been tested. Some have
been proved wrong, but more have been proved right. Since the depths of the Cold War
the world of international politics has changed in fundamental ways. The world is no
longer bipolar. In fact, in terms of military power it is arguably as unipolar as it has
been at any point in the modern state system. Major war among the great powers,
while not inconceivable, certainly is not high on anyone’s list of current major threats
to international security. In this sense, the basic frame for the book is, for the moment,
obsolete. Furthermore, the greatest fear motivating the book, nuclear conflagration,
has receded. The USA and Russia each individually retain the ability to destroy civilization at
the push of the button, but we no longer worry much that they will do so. This devel-
opment puts into question a core underlying premise of the book, that a focus strictly on
the built instruments of military force is an adequate starting point for understanding
key patterns in international politics.
Another premise that Claude gets wrong is with respect to arms control and dis-
armament. He dismisses the possibility that negotiated arms reductions would have
much impact on international politics as being something so unlikely that it does not
merit much discussion. While arms control treaties have certainly not been a panacea,
they are (arguably) far from irrelevant. They have functioned both to reduce nuclear
stockpiles to small fractions of what they once were, and to act as lubricants to the
improvement in superpower relations during the latter part of the Cold War.
Reading Power and International Relations is a useful reminder of how much, and in
what ways, not only international politics but also IR has changed. The book is a state-
of-the-art review of the international security literature at the time. This is true of its
substance and its style. It was written near the end of the dominance of what might be
called the diplomatic history style, and what has been called the classical approach of
IR scholarship.19 On the one hand, the style can be annoying to a contemporary
reader, inasmuch as it is replete with references to people and events that no longer
hold resonance. On the other hand, it displays a deep familiarity with the actual prac-
tice of international politics that often seems lost in the methodological focus of more
recent IR scholarship. Beyond style and method, the book is also a useful reminder
that the world in which IR is studied has changed every bit as much as the way in
Inis L. Claude: Power and International Relations 115
which we study it. Security studies as a whole has expanded considerably from the
Cold War focus on military capabilities and major power war, but the neorealism that
remains in some ways at the core of the field (rhetorically, at least) is still rooted in the
bipolarity and nuclear confrontation of the Cold War. Reading IR written in, rather
than about, the coldest of the Cold War is a useful corrective to strong claims that
international politics is much as it ever was.
Despite being set in a different era of international politics, however, Power and
International Relations effectively foreshadows some key developments both in the role
of the UN in issues of war and security, and in IR theory. Most importantly, perhaps,
the conclusion to the book, while it does not use the specific term, discusses the
development of multilateralism as an institution.20 This can be seen in Claude’s dis-
cussion both of the developing role of the UN as a forum for dispute resolution, and of
changes in the norms of war. The combination of the two has made war between states
much more exceptional than in the classical balance of power period, and has made
wars of territorial expansion rare. As multilateralism has developed it has been less
focused on the Security Council and General Assembly than Claude envisioned, and
has involved the nebulous UN system more broadly, but the core insight of his con-
clusions remains sound. This insight also informs some of his later work, such as his
work on the legitimation function of the UN.21
In part through this link, Power and International Relations additionally foreshadows
some of the recent trends in IR theory. These include the ideational and normative turn
of the past quarter of a century, associated most closely with constructivism. They also
include recent attempts to resurrect the contextual and prudential aspects of classical
realism, which collectively have been referred to as ‘reflexive realism’.22 Claude’s
attempt to take military power seriously, to focus on politics rather than institutions
and constitutions, but at the same time to question the received wisdom in realist
scholarship about the conclusions to be drawn from those premises, is one that reflexive
realists have perhaps paid less attention to than they should.
Contemporary impact
Power and International Relations has not had an enormous impact on contemporary
IR theory. The argument of the book fits broadly into the classical realist school of
thought, and seems intended to speak to that literature. However, this school of
thought has largely been displaced in security studies by more self-consciously metho-
dological and positivist work. Even the seminal works of classical realism, such as
Morgenthau’s Politics Among Nations or Carr’s The Twenty Years’ Crisis, are read,
and assigned to graduate students, less frequently than used to be the case. However,
they are often cited as the classics of the school of thought. Power and International
Relations, being an internal critique of a school of thought that is no longer at the
centre of the discipline, is therefore neither a good example of classical realism, nor a
clear departure from it. And the basic question that Claude asks in the book, about
avoiding great power nuclear war, is no longer central to security studies.
It none the less continues to be cited in the IR literature. Google Scholar identifies
approximately 600 citations, which continue at a rate between five and ten a year. It
continues to be cited for its discussion of the multiple and mutually contradictory
meanings of the balance of power. However, while Claude’s critique of the terminology
and efficacy of the balance of power literature is one of the best examples in the
116 J. Samuel Barkin
literature, it was not (as Claude notes in the book) particularly original. The more
original part of the discussion of the balance of power in Power and International
Relations is the focus on the systemic aspect, but in the contemporary literature Ken-
neth Waltz gets most of the credit for introducing a systemic model of the balance of
power to IR theory.
Power and International Relations is also cited for its discussion of collective security
from a critical but sympathetic perspective. While the book was prescient in fore-
shadowing the current literature on multilateralism and the role of norms in interna-
tional security, the contemporary literature on these subjects does not draw heavily on
it. The constructivist methodologies that these literatures generally draw on do not fit
much better with Claude’s style of argument than do the positivist claims of much of
the contemporary field of security studies. As such, Power and International Relations
is cited in the contemporary literature more for specific elements of its argument than
for it overall theme or its conclusions. Nonetheless, the book remains a valuable read.
It is accessible and engaging, and sheds some much-needed light on terms and concepts
that remain central to contemporary security studies, but that are built on assumptions
too often taken for granted. To the student of the history of the international scene,
either diplomatic or intellectual, the book is an excellent review of both international
politics and international relations and security studies theory at the height of the Cold
War. To the student of international organization, it offers an important viewpoint on
the development of the UN system from the goals of its designers to its current role in
international politics. And to the student of international security, it offers an excellent
reminder of just how much the world has changed in the past half-century.
Notes
1 Inis L. Claude, Jr., Power and International Relations, New York: Random House, 1962.
2 On the ‘great debates’ framing, see Yosef Lapid, ‘The Third Debate: On the Prospects of
International Theory in a Post-Positivist Era’, International Studies Quarterly, 1989, vol. 33,
235–54.
3 Hans J. Morgenthau, Politics Among Nations: The Struggle for Power and Peace, New York:
Alfred A. Knopf, 1948.
4 E. H. Carr, The Twenty Years’ Crisis, 1919–1939: An Introduction to the Study of Interna-
tional Relations, New York: Harper & Row, 1964.
5 Kenneth Waltz, Man, the State, and War, New York: Columbia University Press, 1959.
6 Claude, Power and International Relations, p. 39.
7 See Kenneth Waltz, Theory of International Politics, Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley, 1979;
and the Chapter by Anders Wivel in this volume.
8 See, for example, Carsten Holbraad, The Concert of Europe: A Study in German and British
International Theory 1815–1914, London: Longman, 1970.
9 Claude, Power and International Relations, p. 69.
10 Claude, Power and International Relations, p. 68.
11 A seminal version of this claim can be found in Carr, The Twenty Years’ Crisis.
12 See Brain Schmidt (ed.), International Relations and the First Great Debate, London: Rou-
tledge, 2012.
13 Max Weber, Economy and Society, Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, 1978, e.g. p. 56.
14 Claude, Power and International Relations, p. 271.
15 See, for example, Peter J. Katzenstein (ed.), The Culture of National Security: Norms and
Identity in World Politics, New York: Columbia University Press, 1996.
16 For example, Inis L. Claude, Jr., ‘Collective Legitimization as a Political Function of the
United Nations’, International Organization, 1966, vol. 20, 367–79.
Inis L. Claude: Power and International Relations 117
17 For an example of a recent volume on the balance of power theory that continues the ter-
minological pathologies that Claude discusses see T. V. Paul, James J. Wirtz, Michel For-
tmann (eds), Balance of Power: Theory and Practice in the 21st Century, Stanford, CA:
Stanford University Press, 2004. For an excellent recent analysis see Richard Little, The Bal-
ance of Power in International Relations, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007.
18 For a further discussion of this dichotomy see J. Samuel Barkin, Realist Constructivism:
Rethinking International Relations Theory, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010.
19 Hedley Bull, ‘International Theory: The Case for a Classical Approach’, in Klaus Knorr and
James Rosenau (eds), Contending Approaches to International Politics, Princeton, NJ: Prin-
ceton University Press, 1969, pp. 20–38.
20 On multilateralism as an institution, see John Gerrard Ruggie, ‘Multilateralism: The Anat-
omy of an Institution’, International Organization, 1992, vol. 46, 561–98.
21 Claude, ‘Collective Legitimization as a Political Function of the United Nations’.
22 See for example Brent J. Steele, ‘“Eavesdropping on Honored Ghosts”: From Classical to Reflexive
Realism’, Journal of International Relations and Development, 2007, vol. 10, 272–300.
12 The joke’s on you: International
Relations and Stanley Kubrick’s
Dr. Strangelove
Henrik Bliddal
Without a doubt, Stanley Kubrick’s Dr. Strangelove or: How I Learned to Stop Wor-
rying and Love the Bomb, first shown in US theatres in January 1964, is a true film
classic.1 While some conservative voices decried it as downright dangerous owing to its
characterization of US politicians and military officers as impotent, in every sense of
the word, it was widely praised and became a big box office success.2 It was nominated
for 14 awards, winning four (although none of the four Oscars for which it was nominated).
In the latest instalment of ‘100 Years … 100 Movies’, a list of the top 100 US movies,
compiled by the American Film Institute, it ranks as the 39th greatest movie of all
time, and the popular Internet Movie Database rates it as the 34th best film in movie
history.3
To include it in a volume on classics of International Relations (IR) is surely more
controversial. However, if one accepts the validity of this volume’s concept of an
‘alternative classic’, then Dr. Strangelove is, in fact, a rather uncontroversial choice. It
is extensively used in IR and Political Science classrooms around the world. I even
suspect that Dr. Strangelove finds its way more often onto IR curricula than some of
the books presented in this volume. In other words, there is no more ‘classic’ way of
introducing students to key aspects of international relations via film than with Dr.
Strangelove.
Today, the use of audiovisual and other unconventional material is becoming ever
more widespread, despite the fact that ‘traditional’ teaching and learning, with the
blackboard at the centre, still prevail in many universities. Movies provide simultaneous
stimulation of multiple senses, ground abstract concepts, engage emotions, contextualize
historical events, and, maybe most importantly, facilitate an active-learning environ-
ment, moving from an ‘instructional model’ of memorization, towards a ‘learning
paradigm’.4 In this sense, Dr. Strangelove offers ‘lessons about war, politics, and history’
and can be used as ‘a teaching aid for classes in introductory international relations, foreign
policy, defense policy, causes of war, organizational politics, and Cold War history’.5
Still, Dr. Strangelove is much more than just a tool for teaching. It is also a critical
intervention, however unorthodox. Kubrick carries the logics of the balance of power
and deterrence to their extremes (and beyond), uncovering their inconsistencies, as he
sees them. He exposes the gendered dimension of foreign policy and international
relations as well as dysfunctional in-fighting so often found in bureaucracies and
domestic politics. Kubrick does so by employing a satirical lens in this ‘nightmare
comedy’ where a runaway General sends his nuclear bombers to attack the Soviet
Union, in the end leading to the destruction of ‘all human and animal life on Earth’
(43 min.). He unsettles preconceived notions of international politics and, thus, invites
Stanley Kubrick: Dr. Strangelove 119
the viewer to engage critically with their logical foundations, in a way that still reso-
nates today.6
To show that Dr. Strangelove is both a formidable teaching and learning tool and
can be used to critically engage with prevalent themes in IR theory, this chapter will,
first, briefly summarize Dr. Strangelove’s plot, and place it in its historical, political
and IR context. Second, it will focus on two dominant themes of the movie
through the use of selected scenes and their relation to theoretical concepts: the
balance of power and deterrence. By focusing on these two themes, I do not intend to
diminish the importance of other themes and currents in the movie. It presents an
excellent opportunity to delve into discussions on bureaucratic and organizational
politics, for example. Quite frankly, I am perplexed that it took a further 20 years for
feminist IR to have an impact on the discipline, when Dr. Strangelove provided such a
poignant critique of the position of women in security politics. Where are the women,
Cynthia Enloe asks?7 In Dr. Strangelove’s 1964, they are the naïve secretaries that
warm the beds of Generals, and the playmates (‘Miss Foreign Affairs’) that adorn the
erotic magazines of nuclear bomber pilots. Nowhere are they to be seen in the ‘War
Room’. What about the men? They are the war-lusting Generals who blame their
impotence on communist plots; the officers who find their hidden desires in the nylons
and lipsticks of a B-52 survival kit and ride into orgasm on the back of a nuclear
bomb; and the national elite who cannot wait for the end of the world where they get
to rebuild the human race by breeding prodigiously on a 10-to-1 female-to-male ratio.
An important study linking Dr. Strangelove and gender studies of IR is hidden in plain
view here.8
President Muffley: ‘I’m sorry, too, Dmitri. I’m very sorry. [Premier Kissoff’s
answer, whose voice you never hear in the movie] Alright, you are sorrier than I am.
But I am sorry as well. [Kissoff’s answer] I am as sorry as you are, Dmitri. Don’t
say you’re more sorry than I am because I am capable of being just as sorry as you
are. So we’re both sorry, alright? [Kissoff’s answer] Alright (42 min.).
The costly endeavour of keeping up with the other side also provides the impetus for
the Russian leaders’ decision to build the Doomsday Machine, which to them appears
as a cheap balancing strategy in the light of ever-increasing demands from the popu-
lation for everyday commodities. The Doomsday Machine is the ultimate equalizer:
once it has been built, the Russian leadership can concentrate on its internal problems
instead of buying yet more arms. This argument is presented by the Russian ambassador
De Sadeski in the ‘War Room’:
122 Henrik Bliddal
There were those of us who fought against it, but in the end we could not keep up
in the Arms Race, the Space Race and the Peace Race. At the same time, our
people grumbled for more nylons and washing machines. Our Doomsday scheme
cost us just a fraction of what we had been spending on defense in a single year.
But the deciding factor was when we learned your country was working along
similar lines, and we were afraid of a Doomsday Gap. (48 min.)
This Doomsday Gap mirrors the hysteria of the times (and later years): the ‘bomber
gap’ of the mid-1950s; the ‘satellite gap’ after the launch of Sputnik by the Soviet
Union in 1957; and the ‘missile gap’ that helped John F. Kennedy to win the pre-
sidency. These presumed gaps all turned out to be chimerical, but only after they had
had enormous impact on US politics, triggering increased defence spending.
The viewer is shown the absurdity, in Kubrick’s mind, of such ‘gap debates’. This
culminates when it becomes clear that the last bomber will deliver its payload and
trigger the Doomsday Machine. Echoing Herman Kahn’s real-world call to use aban-
doned mines as shelters in nuclear war,20 Dr. Strangelove recommends shuffling off
several hundred thousand of the US elite into mine shafts, in order to ‘preserve a
nucleus of human specimen’ (1h 24 min.). General Turgidson, the President’s chief
military adviser in the movie, immediately jumps in ‘to look at this thing from a mili-
tary point of view’. He fears that ‘the Ruskies stashed away some big bombs and we
didn’t, [and] when they come out in a hundred years, they could take over’. He refuses
to believe that a devastated world would ‘cause a change in Soviet expansionist policy’.
Rather, the USA should ‘be increasingly alert to prevent them from taking over other
mine-shaft space in order to breed more prodigiously than us, thus, knocking us out
through superior numbers when we emerge’. At the same time, the Russian Ambassa-
dor De Sadeski proves that it is not only Turgidson who thinks about the ‘time after’,
when he proceeds to take pictures of the ‘Big Board’, where the locations of important
US military installations can be seen. In other words, in Dr. Strangelove’s world bal-
ancing is ubiquitous and ever-present, even when the world is doomed.
If the balance of power provides the backdrop, deterrence takes front and centre
place on Kubrick’s stage, and this is where the movie excels. Instead of ridiculing
deterrence outright or launching a frontal assault, Kubrick takes a decidedly more
effective and, at first, oblique tack. Indeed, the problems faced by the protagonists
could have been taken straight out of a textbook. Carol Cohn once argued that
‘learning the language [of defence intellectuals] is a transformative, rather than additive
process’ whereby you ‘enter a new mode of thinking’, leading to ‘a serious quandary’:
If we refuse to learn the language, we are virtually guaranteed that our voices will
remain outside the ‘politically relevant’ spectrum of opinion. Yet if we do learn and
speak it, we not only severely limit what we can say but also invite the transforma-
tion, the militarization, of our own thinking.21
Cohn had ‘no solutions to this dilemma’. Kubrick, at least at some level, seems to
have been at once aware of this predicament and managed to find a way out of it: satire.
Introducing the satirical element allows Kubrick to take the ideas behind the concept
of deterrence just far enough so that they crash in on themselves. Speaking the lan-
guage of deterrence, he thus provides a critical commentary that effectively undermines
deterrence as a strategy in the mind of the audience.
Stanley Kubrick: Dr. Strangelove 123
It is Dr. Strangelove who provides a definition of deterrence that would not have
been ill-placed in an IR book of the period: ‘Deterrence is the art of producing in the
mind of the enemy the fear to attack’ (49 min.). This is not too far from Glenn Sny-
der’s definition from 1961, for example: deterrence is ‘discouraging the enemy from
taking military action by posing for him a cost and risk outweighing his prospective
gain’.22 Faced with a perceived mutual threat, policy-makers in the Soviet Union as
well as in the USA made nuclear deterrence the cornerstone of their policies towards
each other in order to avoid military conflict. Although it seems hard to fathom for a
contemporary audience, the motto adorning General Ripper’s Burpelson Air Force
Base – ‘Peace is our Profession’ – was indeed the motto of Strategic Air Command (49
min.). Kubrick was terrified, like so many others, that something could go wrong, as it
nearly had during the Cuban Missile Crisis.23 How could a situation where both
sides threatened wholesale destruction, which in turn would have assured mutual
destruction, be stable? This was one of the key policy questions asked during the Cold
War.24 In the movie, stability clearly breaks down as the renegade General Ripper
takes matters into his own hands and orders a first strike on the Soviet Union in order
to push the US government into an all-out attack before the other side can react. This
scenario might seem outlandish to today’s audience. Still, the movie was prefaced with
the sentence that ‘[i]t is the stated position of the U.S. Air Force that their safeguards
would prevent the occurrence of such events as are depicted in this film’.25 While the
intention of this was certainly ironic, some in the audience were probably reassured by
this statement.
A key element in deterrence theory is credibility. Only if both sides believe that the
other means what it says can deterrence be stable. In Patrick Morgan’s words, ‘[t]o have
credibility [in the Cold War] it was necessary to be able to do unacceptable damage, to
have proper forces for that purpose, and have the opponent conclude that you had the
will to carry out your threat’.26 All else being equal, the third component of credibility
is the most critical one. To have the right capabilities to do unacceptable damage is one
thing, but to convince an opponent that you have the will to carry out the threat is
another. As Nobel Laureate Thomas Schelling pointed out in his seminal book The
Strategy of Conflict, ‘[i]n case a threat is made and fails to deter, there is a second stage
prior to fulfilment in which both parties have an interest in undoing the commitment.
The purpose of the threat is gone, its deterrence value is zero, and only the commitment
exists to motivate fulfilment’.27
Dr. Strangelove takes up the question of credibility in several scenes, but two stand
out. First, the reason why General Ripper can send his planes to the Soviet Union in the
first place is because President Muffley had devolved some command and control
functions to his base commanders under ‘Plan R’, a fact that the President seems to
have forgotten. General Turgidson therefore has to remind him that ‘Plan R is an
emergency war plan, in which a lower echelon commander may order nuclear retalia-
tion after a sneak attack if the normal chain of command has been disrupted’ (24
min.). This mechanism was put into place in order ‘to be a sort of retaliatory safe-
guard’ because ‘Senator Duff made that big hassle about our deterrent lacking cred-
ibility’. The logic behind this, of course, is that if the Russian side could take out the
President and those next in the line of command, no retaliatory strike could be made in
time, creating the slight possibility that the Russians could undertake a first ‘decap-
itating’ strike.28 The risk of a renegade General was apparently overlooked in this
scheme.
124 Henrik Bliddal
Another key event is the building of a Russian Doomsday Machine, which aims to
minimize any ‘meddling’ after a first strike. Again, Schelling was one of the first to
identify this problem:
The credibility of the threat before the act depends on how visible to the threatened
party is the inability of the threatening party to rationalize his way out of his
commitment once it has failed its purpose. It is essential, therefore, for maximum
credibility to leave as little room as possible for judgment or discretion in carrying
out the threat.29
Kubrick follows the logic of this argument to its conclusion. The Doomsday Machine
replaces discretion with automaticity. When President Muffley asks ‘how is it possible
for this thing to be triggered automatically and at the same time impossible to untrig-
ger’, Dr. Strangelove explains:
Mr. President, it is not only possible, it is essential. That is the whole idea of this
machine, you know. … [B]ecause of the automated and irrevocable decision-
making process which rules out human meddling, the Doomsday Machine is ter-
rifying, simple to understand, and completely credible and convincing (49 min.).
In other words, Kubrick wants to show the audience that the goal of absolute cred-
ibility is unachievable, and that the various policy recommendations to increase it – for
example, Kahn’s push to develop war-fighting nuclear capabilities – can never rule out
the possibility that something might go wrong.
Another important debate in the literature on deterrence revolves around communication
of threats, for ‘both the threat and the commitment have to be communicated’.30 In
deterrence strategy, an inherent tension of communicating too much or too little
exists. If one side gives away too much information about its forces, doctrine, and so
on, the adversary might think that he can outsmart the other side, creating the possibility of
a first strike. However, if too little communication is exchanged, then the other side
cannot make proper threat assessments. This problem of communication is also laid
bare in Dr. Strangelove. Had the Russians communicated to the Americans that they
had built an automatic Doomsday Machine, it would have been suicidal for General
Ripper to have sent his nuclear bombers. Dr. Strangelove himself puts the question to
De Sadeski: ‘The only one thing that I don’t understand, Mr. Ambassador, is that …
the whole point of the Doomsday Machine is lost if you keep it a secret. Why didn’t
you tell the world, eh?’ (51 min.). De Sadeski’s unfortunate answer is that ‘[i]t was to be
announced at the Party Congress on Monday. As you know, the Premier loves
surprises’.
The movie provides great springboards for other sub-themes of nuclear deterrence, for
example the debate on two main schools within deterrence thinking: the massive reta-
liation school and the war-fighting school.31 The adherents of the former believe that
the threat of massive retaliation is the best option to deter the adversary, i.e. where all-
out attack is the only option, and are exemplified in the Russians and their Doomsday
Machine. The second school is represented through the idea of getting as many people
into mine shafts as possible in order to survive a nuclear confrontation were it to occur.
In sum, it is no wonder that this movie is shown so often in classes on deterrence
theory and strategy.
Stanley Kubrick: Dr. Strangelove 125
Conclusion: the continued relevance of Dr. Strangelove
Even after Kubrick’s death in 1999, Dr. Strangelove stood out among the copious
amounts of praise heaped upon his oeuvre. James Christopher of The Times, for
example, called it his ‘most perfectly realized film’.32 Kubrick’s movies will, therefore,
certainly remain a staple of film studies and attract the continuing admiration of film
aficionados. However, two decades after the ending of the Cold War, it is an entirely
legitimate question to ask whether Dr. Strangelove will continue to be watched by IR
scholars and students.
The Washington Post’s Stephen Hunter, while acknowledging that Dr. Strangelove is
a ‘still-brilliant meditation on man’s tendencies toward self-incineration’, for one, points
out that it ‘had one small flaw: It was wrong. Or rather, MAD [Mutual Assured
Destruction] was right: The world didn’t end, we didn’t blow ourselves up, unless I
slept through the event’.33 Of course, the absence of nuclear annihilation is not necessarily
proof that MAD was right. Whether (or how much) nuclear weapons kept the super-
power confrontation cold is still a matter of considerable debate.34 In this context
alone, Dr. Strangelove remains relevant.
What is more, questions about nuclear deterrence are once again central to strategic
debates. For example, could the international community live with a ‘nuclear’ Iran, i.e. do
the tenets of nuclear stability also apply to states that, as some argue, exhibit ‘irrational’
decision patterns? Other important real-world developments have sparked renewed interest
in deterrence theory as well. In 1999 a senior NATO diplomat was quoted as saying that
the Alliance’s nuclear weapons had ‘been put in a small box somewhere in the corner, and
that is where they should stay.’35 However, in 2012 NATO published a new Deterrence
and Defence Posture Review, the result of a thorough year-long study of NATO’s deterrence
and defence needs, during which the role of nuclear weapons in NATO was hotly
debated. The issue of NATO’s planned missile defence system, and Russia’s concerns, cannot
be fully understood without referring to deterrence theory. Even the discussion between
the ‘war-fighting’ school and minimalist deterrence has re-emerged forcefully in the pages
of Foreign Affairs.36 As astonishing as it might seem, Dr. Strangelove still addresses all
of these issues. Of course, other themes have emerged in today’s deterrence literature in which
Kubrick’s movie has less to add. For example, the so-called fourth wave in deterrence
research is concerned with how to deal with asymmetric threats, such as terrorists,37
and cyber space has introduced altogether different dynamics to deterrence strategies.38
Ultimately, an overriding quality of Dr. Strangelove is that, while it is a Cold War
movie par excellence, it is so much more. If one wants to draw a parallel to the world of
books, the difference between Dr. Strangelove and other Cold War movies is akin to
the difference between books of IR theory and of ‘current events’. While the Fareed
Zakarias of this world will continue to produce best-sellers, it is unlikely that readers
will pick them up in ten years’ time (let alone 50), other than historians or people
browsing through bargain bins. Dr. Strangelove speaks to an audience whose interests
are very far from being confined to the Cold War, and thus, as long as the themes
dissected so brilliantly in the movie remain relevant, so will Dr. Strangelove.
Notes
1 Dr. Strangelove or: How I Learned to Stop Worrying and Love the Bomb, directed by Stanley
Kubrick, 95 min., Columbia Pictures and Hawk Films, 1964. References placed in par-
entheses in the text are to this movie.
126 Henrik Bliddal
2 In 1994, when it was shown in theatres again, its total lifetime gross was US $9,440,272 in
the USA (Internet Movie Datebase (IMDB)), Box Office/Business for Dr. Strangelove or:
How I Learned to Stop Worrying and Love the Bomb. Available at: www.imdb.com/title/
tt0057012/business (accessed 10 November 2011).
3 American Film Institute (AFI), AFI’s 100 Years … 100 Movies 10th Anniversary Edition
(2007). Available at: www.afi.com/100years/movies10.aspx (accessed on 10 November 2011).
IMDB, Dr. Strangelove or: How I Learned to Stop Worrying and Love the Bomb. Available
at: www.imdb.com/title/tt0057012/ (accessed on 10 November 2011).
4 Lynn M. Kuzma and Patrick J. Haney, ‘And … Action! Using Film to Learn about Foreign
Policy’, International Studies Perspectives, 2001, vol. 2, 33–50.
5 Dan Lindley, ‘What I Learned since I Stopped Worrying and Studied the Movie: A Teaching
Guide to Stanley Kubrick’s Dr. Strangelove’, PS: Political Science & Politics, 2001, vol. 3,
663–67, at p. 663.
6 Cynthia Weber uses movies to disrupt certain IR ‘myths’, i.e. the foundational assumptions
underlying theories or traditions that they rely upon to appear true. By stepping into the
world of movies, she wants to unsettle ‘common truths’ that are taken for granted in order to
expose similar ones found in IR theories. Cynthia Weber, International Relations Theory: A
Critical Introduction, 3rd edn, London: Routledge, 2009. However, Dr. Strangelove, as a
satire, is a movie that already wants to unsettle ‘common truths’ and, thus, may not suitable
for this particular move.
7 Cynthia Enloe, Bananas, Beaches and Bases: Making Feminist Sense of International Politics,
London: Pandora, 1989, p. 7. See also Alexandra Hyde and Marsha Henry’s chapter in this
volume.
8 For an example of how gendered discourse permeates the world of nuclear weapons see Carol
Cohn, ‘Sex and Death in the Rational World of Defense Intellectuals’, Signs, 1987, vol. 12,
687–718.
9 On the ‘three waves of deterrence theory’, see Robert Jervis, ‘Deterrence Theory Revisited’,
World Politics, 1979, vol. 2, 289–324.
10 James Naremore, On Kubrick, London: BFI and Palgrave Macmillan, 2007, p. 119.
11 Inside the Making of Dr. Strangelove (4 min.), found on the 2003 Collector’s Edition DVD of
Dr. Strangelove.
12 Quoted in Naremore, On Kubrick, p. 122.
13 Robert Gregg, International Relations on Film, Boulder, CO: Lynne Rienner, 1998, p. 7.
14 Quoted in Naremore, On Kubrick, p. 122.
15 Robert Brustein, ‘Out of This World’, The New York Review of Books, 5 March 1964.
Available at: www.nybooks.com/articles/archives/1964/feb/06/out-of-this-world/?pagination=fa
lse (accessed 10 November 2011).
16 Naremore, On Kubrick, p. 123.
17 Before the opening scene. Interestingly, this does not feature on the 2003 DVD.
18 Herman Kahn, On Thermonuclear War, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1960.
19 Naremore, On Kubrick, p. 124.
20 Kahn, On Thermonuclear War, pp. 88ff.
21 Cohn, ‘Sex and Death in the Rational World of Defense Intellectuals’, p. 716. Recall also
Martin Wight’s words that debates of international theory, including on nuclear weapons, are
‘constantly bursting the bounds of the language in which we try to handle it’. Martin Wight,
‘Why Is there no International Theory’, International Relations, 1960, vol. 2, 35–62, at p. 48.
22 Glenn Snyder, Deterrence and Defense: Toward a Theory of National Security, Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press, [1961] 1981, p. 35.
23 For a detailed discussion of near-disasters, see Scott D. Sagan, The Limits of Safety: Orga-
nizations, Accidents, and Nuclear Weapons, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1993.
24 Patrick M. Morgan, Deterrence Now, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003, pp. 15, 20ff.
25 Before the opening scene. This does not feature on the 2003 DVD, either.
26 Morgan, Deterrence Now, p. 16.
27 Thomas C. Schelling, The Strategy of Conflict, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press,
[1960] 1981, p. 39.
28 For a discussion on predelegated authority and devolution of authority, see Paul Bracken,
‘Delegation of Nuclear Command Authority’, in Ashton B. Carter, John D. Steinbrunner,
Stanley Kubrick: Dr. Strangelove 127
Charles A. Zraket (eds), Managing Nuclear Operations, Washington, DC: Brookings Institu-
tion Press, 1987, pp. 352–72.
29 Schelling, The Strategy of Conflict, p. 40.
30 Schelling, The Strategy of Conflict, p. 38.
31 Proponents of the massive retaliation school included leaders such as Eisenhower and
Khrushchev and analysts like Charles Glaser. War-fighting was a preferred option for policy-
makers such as James Schlesinger, Paul Nitze and Harold Brown and for analysts like
Herman Kahn and Colin Gray. See Morgan, Deterrence Now, pp. 22ff.
32 James Christopher, ‘Kubrick: A Cinematic Odyssey’, The Times (London), 8 March 1999.
33 Stephen Hunter, ‘Through a Lens, Darkly; Stanley Kubrick Looked at the Silver Screen and
Saw a Thousand Shades of Gray’, The Washington Post, 8 March 1999.
34 See, for example, Morgan, Deterrence Now, pp. 1–41.
35 The Economist, ‘Knights in Shining Armor? A Survey of NATO’, 24 April 1999.
36 See, for example, the debate in the pages of Foreign Affairs, which was started by Daryl Press
and Keir Lieber, ‘The Nukes We Need: Preserving the American Deterrent’, Foreign Affairs,
2009, vol. 88, 39–51.
37 See Jeffrey W. Knopf, ‘The Fourth Wave in Deterrence Research’, Contemporary Security
Policy, 2010, vol. 31, 1–33.
38 For an example of an analysis of how cyber security affects traditional security strategies, see
Paul Cornish, David Livingstone, Dave Clemente, and Claire Yorke, On Cyber Warfare,
London: The Royal Insititute of International Affairs, 2010.
13 The virtue of uncertain advice: Robert Jervis’
Perception and Misperception in
International Politics
Shiping Tang1
What are the causes and consequences of misperception? What kinds of perceptual
errors commonly occur in decision-making? How are beliefs about politics and
images of other actors formed and altered? How do decision-makers draw infer-
ences from information, especially information that could be seen as contradicting
their own views?
Notes
1 The author thanks Jon Mercer, Xiaoyu Pu, Jiwu Yin and, most importantly, the always
enlightening and modest Bob Jervis himself, for their critical comments. All errors and
omissions are the author’s own.
2 Robert Jervis, Perception and Misperception in International Politics, Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press, 1976. Page numbers placed in parentheses in the text refer to this edition.
3 I simply cannot resist plagiarizing Karl Popper’s words for Donald T. Campbell’s classic
paper, ‘Evolutionary Epistemology’, without citing either Popper or Campbell. For Jervis’s
fascinating reflections on his own intellectual career, see Robert Jervis with Thierry Balzacq,
‘The Logic of Mind: Interview with Robert Jervis’, Review of International Studies, 2004, vol.
30, 559–82. See also ‘Theory Talks with Robert Jervis’, Theory Talk, 12. Available at: www.
theory-talks.org/2008/07/theory-talk-12.html (accessed on 24 August 2012). For a touching
tribute to Jervis (plus Bruce Bueno de Mesquita and Peter Katzenstein) by Rose McDermott
(one of Jervis’s students), see ‘Great Mentors’, Perspectives on Politics, 2010, vol. 43, 713–15.
4 Other important contributions came from Kenneth Boulding, Joseph De Rivera, Merton
Deutsch, Alexander George, Margaret Hermann, Irving Janis, Herbert Kelman, Robert
North and Charles Osgood, none of whom can be cited here owing to space limitations.
5 For Jervis’s own take on how his thinking on policy issues and theoretical issues mutually
benefit each other, see Robert Jervis with Thierry Balzacq, ‘The Logic of Mind: Interview
with Robert Jervis’.
6 Jervis himself certainly would like to think that his former students ‘who serve in the gov-
ernment or who as academics have gone in for temporary stints understand that they may be
wrong, and are wiser for this’ (Robert Jervis, personal communication with the author, 11
October 2011).
7 By ‘systemic’, I mean an approach that considers interaction among many factors at different
levels. For a more detailed discussion about the systemic approach, see Robert Jervis, System
Effects: Complexity in Political and Social Life, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press,
1997.
8 Robert Jervis, Logic of Images in International Relations, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Press, 1970.
9 Jervis, System Effects: Complexity in Political and Social Life; and Jervis and Balzacq, ‘The
Logic of Mind: Interview with Robert Jervis’, p. 571. He reaffirmed this take in personal
communication with the author (June 2006), when he was preparing a new preface for the
Chinese translation of System Effects: Complexity in Political and Social Life.
Robert Jervis: Perception and Misperception 135
10 Thus, if you come to look for definitive answers in Jervis, Logic of Images in International
Relations, Perception and Misperception in International Politics and especially System
Effects: Complexity in Political and Social Life, you would be disappointed. Indeed, when I
first discussed System Effects: Complexity in Political and Social Life with my fellow graduate
students, they could not conceal their disbelief: ‘That book has no [specific] theory!’ My reply
was: ‘Well, System Effects is not about small theories, it is about a perspective for under-
standing the social world!’ I shall refrain from summarizing what systemic effects are here,
not only because there is no way that I can summarize what systemic effects are, but also
because I hold System Effects: Complexity in Political and Social Life to be a required read-
ing for any student of human society: There is no replacement for reading the text itself.
11 Robert Jervis, ‘Signaling and Perception: Drawing Inferences and Projecting Images’, in
Kristen Monroe (ed.), Political Psychology, Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum, 2002, pp. 293–312,
at pp. 295–96. See also Jervis and Balzacq, ‘The Logic of Mind: Interview with Robert
Jervis’, pp. 560–61.
12 Robert Jervis, ‘Cooperation under the Security Dilemma’, World Politics, 1978, vol. 30, 167–214.
13 Cognitive consistency (Chapter 4) and evoked sets (Chapter 5) operate before a decision or
behavior. Cognitive dissonance (Chapter 11) operates after a decision or behavior, especially
when the outcome turns out to be undesired. In this sense, Chapter 11 should immediately
follow Chapters 4 and 5.
14 See also Jervis, System Effects: Complexity in Political and Social Life (Chapter 4); Robert
Jervis and Jack Snyder (eds), Dominoes and Bandwagons: Strategic Beliefs and Great Power
Competition in the Eurasian Rimland, New York: Oxford University Press, 1991.
15 Amos Tversky and Daniel Kahneman, ‘Prospect Theory: An Analysis of Decision under
Risk’, Econometrica, 1979, vol. 47, 263–91; and Amos Tversky and Daniel Kahneman, ‘The
Framing of Decisions and the Psychology of Choice’, Science, 1981, vol. 211, 453–58.
16 I limit my discussion to those works that are more directly inspired by Jervis’s Logic of
Images in International Relations and Perception and Misperception in International Politics.
Not surprisingly, some of the works were written by Jervis’s former students (e.g. Barbara
Farnham, Ted Hopf, Chaim D. Kaufmann, Rose McDermott and Jonathan Mercer).
17 See Charles L. Glaser, ‘Political Consequences of Military Strategy: Expanding and Refining
the Spiral and Deterrence Models’, World Politics, 1992, vol. 44, 497–538; Ken Booth and
Nicholas Wheeler, The Security Dilemma: Fear, Cooperation, and Trust in World Politics,
New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2008; and Shiping Tang, A Theory of Security Strategy for
Our Time, New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2010, especially Chapters 2 and 3. See also
Casper Sylvest’s chapter on Herz in this volume.
18 See, for example, Barry Posen, ‘The Security Dilemma and Ethnic Conflict’, Survival, vol. 35,
27–47.
19 Shiping Tang, ‘The Security Dilemma and Ethnic Conflict: Toward a Dynamic and Inte-
grative Theory of Ethnic Conflict’, Review of International Studies, 2011, vol. 37, 511–36.
20 Charles A. Osgood, An Alternative to War or Surrender, Urbana, IL: University of Illinois
Press, 1962. Briefly, GRIT means one side takes some initial conciliatory steps to reduce
tensions between itself and another state. If the other state responds positively, then the two
states may end up in an improved relationship. In more formal terms, GRIT is based on the
logic of reassurance and costly signaling.
21 Deborah W. Larson, Anatomy of Mistrust: US-Soviet Relations during the Cold War, Ithaca,
NY: Cornell University Press, 1997; Andrew Kydd, Trust and Mistrust in International Rela-
tions, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2005; and Tang, A Theory of Security
Strategy for Our Time: Defensive Realism, Chapter 5.
22 See, for example, Glaser, ‘Political Consequences of Military Strategy’; Charles L. Glaser,
‘Realists as Optimists: Cooperation as Self-help’, International Security, 1994–95, vol. 19, 50–90;
and Tang, A Theory of Security Strategy for Our Time, Chapter 5.
23 Shiping Tang, ‘Fear in International Politics: Two Positions’, International Studies Review,
2008, vol. 10, 451–70; and Tang, A Theory of Security Strategy for Our Time. Very briefly,
defensive realism does not assume all states to be malignant. As such, a defensive realist state
does not believe that offensive strategies are the only viable security strategy: cooperation is
also a viable option.
136 Shiping Tang
24 Shiping Tang, ‘Outline of a New Theory of Attribution in IR: Dimensions of Uncertainty and
their Cognitive Challenges’, Chinese Journal of International Politics, 2012, vol. 5, 299–338.
25 Jervis with Thierry Balzacq, ‘The Logic of Mind: Interview with Robert Jervis’, pp. 559–63.
Unfortunately, whereas constructivists tend to forget that states’ identity change is nothing
peculiar, some of Jervis’s more materialist fellow realists tend to deny that state identities can
change at all or that such changes matter.
26 Richard Ned Lebow, Between Peace and War: The Nature of International Crisis, Baltimore,
MD: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1981.
27 Deborah W. Larson, Origins of Containment: A Psychological Explanation, Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press, 1985.
28 Barbara Rearden Farnham, Roosevelt and the Munich Crisis: A Study of Political Decision-
Making, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1997.
29 See also Ernest R. May, Lessons of the Past: Uses and Misuses of History, New York: Oxford
University Press, 1975. On heuristics and biases, see Amos Tversky, Thomas Gilvoch and Daniel
Kahneman (eds), Judgment under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases, Oxford: Oxford Uni-
versity Press, 1982. See also Thomas Gilvoch, Dale Griffin and Daniel Kahneman (eds),
Heuristics and Biases: The Psychology of Intuitive Judgment, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2002.
30 Yuen Foong Khong, Analogies at War: Korea, Munich, Dien Bien Phu, and the Vietnam
Decisions of 1965, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1992.
31 Dan Reiter, Crucible of Beliefs: Learning, Alliances, and World Wars, Ithaca, NY: Cornell
University Press, 1996.
32 Ted Hopf, Peripheral Visions: Deterrence and American Foreign Policy in the Third Word,
Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press, 1994. See also, Jervis and Snyder (eds),
Dominoes and Bandwagons.
33 Jonathan Mercer, Reputation in International Politics, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press,
1996. See also Jervis and Snyder, Dominoes and Bandwagons; Daryl Press, Calculating Cred-
ibility, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 2005; and Shiping Tang, ‘Reputation, Cult of
Reputation, and International Conflict’, Security Studies, 2005, vol. 24, 34–62.
34 Rose McDermott, Risk Taking in International Politics: Prospect Theory in American Foreign
Policy, Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press, 1998.
35 Jeffrey Taliaferro, Balancing Risks: Great Power Intervention in the Periphery, Ithaca, NY:
Cornell University Press, 2004.
36 Jervis with Balzacq, ‘The Logic of Mind: Interview with Robert Jervis’, pp. 564–65. Jervis, of
course, has since corrected this important omission. See Robert Jervis, Richard Ned Lebow
and Janice Gross Stein, Psychology and Deterrence, Baltimore, MD: John Hopkins Uni-
versity Press, 1985; Robert Jervis, ‘Understanding Beliefs’, Political Psychology, 2006, vol. 27,
641–62. For recent attempts of synthesizing emotion and cognition, see Jonathan Mercer,
‘Rationality and Psychology in International Politics’, International Organization, 2005, vol.
59, 77–106.
37 Of course, the expulsion of emotion from psychology in the 1950–60s was a reaction against
psychology’s earlier excessive focus on emotion.
38 For a classic statement on the ‘totalitarian’ ego, see Anthony G. Greenwald, ‘The Totalitarian
Ego: Fabrication and Revision of Personal History’, American Psychologists, 1980, vol. 35,
603–18. For motivated biases in our reasoning, see Ziva Kunda, ‘The Case for Motivated
Reasoning’, Psychological Bulletin, 1990, vol. 108, 480–98.
39 See also Jervis, Logic of Images, pp. 90–96.
40 Shiping Tang, ‘The Social Evolutionary Psychology of Fear (and Trust): Or Why Is Interna-
tional Cooperation Difficult?’, unpublished manuscript.
41 Irving Lester Janis and Leon Mann, Decision Making: A Psychological Analysis of Conflict,
Choice, and Commitment, New York: Free Press, 1977, Chapters 11 and 12. See also, Lebow,
Between Peace and War; and Jervis, ‘Understanding Beliefs’, esp. 652–57.
42 Reinhold Niebuhr, Moral Man and Immoral Society: A Study in Ethics and Politics, New
York: Charles Scribner’s Sons, [1932] 1960, xx–xxv, pp. 89–93. See also Richard Ned Lebow,
A Cultural Theory of International Relations, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2008;
and Shiping Tang, ‘Reconciliation and the Remaking of Anarchy’, World Politics, 2011, vol.
63, 711–49.
Robert Jervis: Perception and Misperception 137
43 See Jervis, ‘Cooperation under the Security Dilemma’; and P&M.
44 See Tang, A Theory of Security Strategy for Our Time.
45 Tang, ‘Reputation, Cult of Reputation, and International Conflict’.
46 See, Janice Gross Stein, ‘Building Politics into Psychology: The Misperception of Threat’,
Political Psychology, 1988, vol. 9, 245–71; Barbara Farnham, ‘Political Cognition and Decision-
Making’, Political Psychology, 1990, vol. 11, 83–111; and Tang, ‘Reconciliation and the
Remaking of Anarchy’.
47 Khong, Analogies at War; Richard Ned Lebow and Janice Gross Stein, We All Lost the Cold
War, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1994. For an earlier important discussion on
the methodological challenges of testing psychological hypotheses that addresses only part of
the broad challenge, see Chaim D. Kaufmann, ‘Out of the Lab and into the Archives: A
Method for Testing Psychological Explanations for Political Decision Making,” International
Studies Quarterly, 1994, vol. 38, 557–86.
48 Tang, ‘Reconciliation and the Remaking of Anarchy’.
49 See, for example, Ted Hopf, Social Construction of International Relations: Idendities & For-
eign Policies, Moscow, 1955 & 1999, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 2002.
50 Jervis with Balzacq, ‘The Logic of Mind: Interview with Robert Jervis’, pp. 562–63.
51 Norbert Elias, The Civilizing Process, revised edn, trans. Edmund Jephcott, Oxford: Black-
well, [1939] 1994.
52 Lebow, A Cultural Theory of International Relations; and Tang, ‘Social Evolutionary Psy-
chology of Fear (and Trust)’.
14 Probing the institutional fabric
of world politics: Hedley Bull’s
The Anarchical Society
Andrew Hurrell
Hedley Bull frequently used the term ‘classical’ in his own lectures and writings.
The term, he said, did not refer to a particular period but should rather be under-
stood in the sense proposed by Matthew Arnold, namely the degree to which a
work provided ‘most excellent exposition’ of a particular issue or of an enduring
question.1 The status of The Anarchical Society as a classic text in this sense is
clear. It provides the most systematic and powerful exposition of the view that toge-
ther states form an international society, and it develops this idea as a powerful vantage
point from which to analyse and assess the possibilities of order in world politics. At
the core of the book is the question: to what extent does the inherited political frame-
work provided by the society of sovereign states continue to provide an adequate
basis for order? The Anarchical Society does not seek to provide a purely descriptive
or narrative account of international events or developments, nor is it directly con-
cerned with the explanation of international relations. Rather, it provides an inter-
pretation of how international relations have changed and how those changes should
be evaluated from the perspective of a particular set of values, above all the pursuit of
order.2
Bull’s concern with order and institutions would seem to connect with the debates
on multilateralism, international institutions and global governance that have been so
prominent during the period since the end of the Cold War. But Bull’s focus is less on
explaining particular institutions and more on assessing and evaluating the overall
character of institutionalization in world politics, the normative commitments inherent
in different ways of governing the globe, and the adequacy of existing institutions
for meeting practical and normative challenges. The Anarchical Society remains a
fundamental teaching text. It is one of the most important and most-cited works of
the so-called English School of International Relations.3 Its pedagogical value rests on the
quality of Bull’s writing and analysis – its intellectual rigour, its clarity of exposition, and
its capacity to unsettle established and comfortable positions.
The first section of this chapter will elaborate this claim in more detail and provide a
brief overview of the main arguments of the book. The following section will consider
two other ways in which the book can be said to be a classical text: as emerging from,
and taking forward, a set of ‘classical traditions’ of thought on international relations,
and as representing a ‘classical approach’ to how international relations should be
studied. The third section explores some of the major criticisms of the book. The final
section examines the book’s contemporary relevance and considers the charge of out-
datedness.
Hedley Bull: The Anarchical Society 139
What is The Anarchical Society all about?
The central question that lies at the heart of Hedley Bull’s writing concerns the nature
and possibility of order in international life. As is well known, the intellectual frame-
work for this enquiry is provided by the concept of international society:
A society of states (or international society) exists when a group of states, con-
scious of certain common interests and common values, form a society in the sense
that they conceive themselves to be bound by a common set of rules in their rela-
tions with one another, and share in the working of common institutions (p. 13,
emphasis in the original).4
In developing this idea of international society, the book asks three kinds of questions.
There are, first of all, analytical and definitional questions: what do we mean by order
and what are the minimum conditions that would have to exist before any society could
be meaningfully so described? Then there are historical questions: how far can one
isolate an acceptance of these conditions in the historical practices of the society of
states that developed first in Europe and then became global in the course of the
nineteenth and twentieth centuries? And finally there are evaluative and normative
questions: how can this idea of international society be evaluated against other models,
ideas and proposals for international or world order and how is it to be judged in
moral terms?
Bull begins the book with an analytical discussion of the meaning of order. On the
one hand, social order can be understood in the sense of stable and regular patterns of human
behaviour. In this depiction it is contrasted with chaos, instability, or lack of predict-
ability. On the other hand, social order requires the existence of a particular kind of
purposive pattern that human beings have infused with meaning, that involves a parti-
cular set of goals, objectives and values, and that leads to a particular outcome. If order
is to be understood in terms of some purposive pattern, what sorts of purposes, goals and
objectives might be relevant to international life? Bull defined social order as ‘[a] pat-
tern [in the relations of human individuals or groups] that leads to a particular result,
an arrangement of social life such that it promotes certain goals or values’ (pp. 3–4).
His analysis of these ‘certain goals and values’ always tended to point in a con-
strained and minimalist direction. Bull’s classic study of order in world politics con-
centrated on the common framework of rules and institutions that had developed
within the anarchical society of states. It was anarchical in that there was no common
power to enforce law or to underwrite cooperation; but it was a society in so far as
states were conscious of common rules and values, cooperated in the working of
common institutions, and perceived common interests in observing these rules and
working through these institutions. It was, however, a necessarily thin and fragile
society in which the three fundamental goals of international social life were limited to
the preservation of the society of states itself, the maintenance of the independence of
individual states and the regulation – but not elimination – of war and violence among
states and societies.5
From this point of view, interstate cooperation and international law could never be
expected to provide a stable and universal peace but only to mitigate the inevitable
conflicts that would arise from the existence of a multiplicity of separate sovereign
states. The relevant question was not: how might human beings create forms of
140 Andrew Hurrell
international society or schemes of international cooperation that embodied all their
aspirations for justice or which universalized some particular conception of the good
society? It was rather: how might states and other groups do each other the least pos-
sible harm and, in an age of total war and nuclear weapons, survive as a species? So the
core goals of international social order were survival and coexistence, and the political
framework was made up of the core institutions of a pluralist international society –
international law, the concert of great powers, the balance of power, diplomacy and war.
The middle part of the book devotes a chapter to each of these ‘institutions’ of
international society. Here it is important to note the differences between Bull’s
approach and that of many other writers, especially those emerging from the realist
tradition. Take, for example, the balance of power. For realists, the balance of power is
a mechanical arrangement or a constellation of forces that pushes and shoves states to
act in particular ways from outside, regardless of their intentions.6 For Bull, it should
rather be understood as a conscious and continuing shared practice in which the actors
constantly debate and contest the meaning of the balance of power, its ground rules,
and the role that it should play. Equally, great powers are to be studied not simply in
terms of their material power or the degree to which they can impose order on weaker
states or within their spheres of influence on the back of crude coercion, but rather in
terms of the extent to which their role and their managerial functions are perceived as
being legitimate by other states.7 Power remains central to Bull’s analysis of international
relations, but power is a social attribute. To understand power we must place it side by
side with other quintessentially social concepts such as prestige, authority and legitimacy.
International society is therefore centrally concerned with norms and institutions. How-
ever, this does not necessarily lead to a cosy or cooperative Grotianism concerned solely
with the promotion of law and morality as is so often mistakenly assumed.
Contemporary relevance
For many readers The Anarchical Society is outdated.19 Bull’s emphasis on the great
powers, on the balance of power and on war as an institution of international society; his
use of the writings of Grotius, Hobbes and Kant; and his central concern with the ideas
and practices of classical European state system of the eighteenth and nineteenth cen-
turies – all this seems far removed from the study of contemporary world politics. Much
of Bull’s thinking was evidently shaped by the concerns of the Cold War, by the dan-
gers posed by nuclear weapons, and by the problems of managing nuclear deterrence.
In the latter part of The Anarchical Society he considers many of the claims made at that
time that international relations were undergoing fundamental change. He was deeply
sceptical about many of these arguments, for example that economic interdependence
was undermining the role of the state and transforming world politics. His emphasis on
continuity seemed then, and seems much more now, to downplay the dynamic forces at
work in global politics and to fail to recognize the extent to which the international
system has been moving decisively ‘beyond Westphalia’.20 For many readers the dra-
matic and far-reaching changes associated with globalization make it very difficult to
accept Bull’s prescriptive bottom line, namely that a thin pluralist international society
of states remains the best available means of upholding world order.
There is undoubtedly much in The Anarchical Society that seems hard to reconcile
with the changes that have taken place in global politics after the Cold War. Bull had,
after all, expressed little interest in formal international institutions, including the
United Nations. He believed that what he saw as the deeper ‘institutions’ of the balance
of power, war, the great powers, diplomacy and international law were of more abiding
importance.21 In The Anarchical Society he was critical of ‘Kantian’ optimism about
the spread and impact of liberal democracy – the set of claims that would develop into
democratic peace theory. The impact of economic globalization and political demo-
cratization, the increased importance of transnational civil society, the increased den-
sity, scope and range of international institutions, the multiple problems that result
from the break-up of states and ethnic self-assertion – all these factors have developed
144 Andrew Hurrell
to such a point that, for many commentators, Bull’s narrow focus on the society of
states is now wholly inadequate and outdated.
One possible response is simply to view Bull’s rather sober and sceptical conclusions
as a line in the sand against which the claims for change and transformation can be
judged. Pedagogically it makes great sense for students to read Bull alongside the many
works of the 1990s and early 2000s that stressed the idea of systemic transformation,
especially in the context of globalization. Which parts of Bull’s picture still hold?
Which do not? And why? Bull did not ignore change, and as noted the latter sections of
The Anarchical Society consider many different forms of change and many alternative
paths to world order. However, Bull did advocate sobriety in analysing change. He
argued consistently that many of the contemporary trends and features which appear
novel – from transnational corporations to the privatization of violence in the form of
terrorist groups or warlords – look more familiar when approached from a sufficiently
long historical perspective. Equally, he suggested that we can gain much from com-
paring the present with previous epochs of change – hence his suggestive, if underdeveloped,
idea about ‘neo-medievalism’. This involves the idea that, either generally or in parti-
cular regions such as Europe, we might be witnessing a return to an order character-
ized not by nation states but by multiple and overlapping authorities, jurisdictions and
identities.
We might therefore simply see The Anarchical Society as providing a classical expo-
sition of how to think about claims for change. Bull, after all, never argued that states
were the only legitimate objects of study in world politics, nor that they are, or would
necessarily remain, in ‘control’. He was in fact rather pessimistic about the prospects
for international society. Thus, in response to a reader’s comments on The Anarchical
Society, he wrote: ‘I am not sure that it is correct to say … that in the book I see “an
international society emerging”. I think I rather argue that international society exists
but is in decline.’22 The reasons for this decline have to do partly with the unprece-
dented expansion in the normative ambitions of international society, and partly with
the erosion of its political foundations. Equally, he was perfectly aware of the poten-
tially transformative nature of what has come to be called globalization. However, he
was less sure that these new elements provided an adequate basis for order (or, for that
matter, justice) within international society.
A second response is to use the conceptual categories developed in The Anarchical
Society as a means of capturing some of the major changes that have taken place in
recent international relations. Hence many within the English School have sought to
develop Bull’s distinction between pluralist and solidarist versions of international
society. They have also suggested that Bull’s own thinking on international society was
moving in a more solidarist direction towards the end of his career or that his thinking
can be interpreted in proto-solidarist terms.23 Substantively they have argued that,
contrary to the statism and the scepticism expressed in The Anarchical Society, a con-
sensus was in fact developing within post-Cold War international society around such
solidarist norms as humanitarian intervention or the responsibility to protect.24 In still
more strongly progressivist mode, but still owing much to Bull’s work, others have
explored how the changing conditions of global politics may be opening political and
moral spaces for the transformation of the political community.25
In similar vein one might pick up on the under-exploited intellectual resources of
The Anarchical Society – for example, taking on board the degree to which regionalism
has become an important characteristic of contemporary world politics but examining
Hedley Bull: The Anarchical Society 145
and comparing these ‘regional international societies’ within the framework of Bull’s
ideas and concepts. Or thinking through the notion of ‘world society’ whose impor-
tance Bull stresses but which is left underdeveloped in his work, and the complex ways
in which the international society of states and the ever denser and more politically
active world society relate to each other.26
Yet a third possibility is to argue that he was often right both in the questions he
asked about change and in many of his conclusions. Asking the right questions is often
by far the hardest element of any intellectual project. Bull, for example, was constantly
fascinated with the boundaries of international society, with the criteria for membership,
and with the idea that as society deepens so questions of membership become more
important. This led him to ask about the position of those groups that lay on or beyond
the historical boundaries of international society, such as pirates, mercenaries, heretics,
infidels and barbarians. Twenty years ago it might have seemed rather quaint to assign
a book on international politics that included discussion of such groups. Today the
importance of pirates, mercenaries, heretics and barbarians can hardly be doubted.
Clearly Bull’s arguments cannot simply be replayed and there are very important
differences of emphasis and of empirical application. Yet as the claims of the post-Cold
War period concerning globalization have been subjected to scrutiny and criticism, the
pattern of argumentation that we see both in Bull’s work as a whole and in many of his
substantive conclusions recur: that the historical novelty of current globalizing forces
has been exaggerated; that the decline in the role of the state has been overdone; and
that understandings of order built around power and the major powers have by no
means wholly disappeared from the global stage. More importantly, his emphasis on
the dual challenge of managing power and mediating between conflicting values
remains fundamental to understanding both the limits of solidarism in the con-
temporary world and the continued importance of older-style pluralist mechanisms of
order.27 Faced by more troubled times, therefore, we should recognize the continued
importance of Bull’s realism and his scepticism.
It cannot be overemphasized that Bull’s preoccupation in The Anarchical Society is
not with world politics in general, but with the nature and possibilities of international
order. As noted above, Bull never argued that states were the only legitimate objects of
study in world politics. And he was perfectly aware of the potentially transformative
nature of what has come to be called globalization. However, he was less sure that
these new elements provided an adequate basis for order (and still less for justice)
within international society. It is certainly the case that, even within its own terms,
Bull’s conception of interstate order was too starkly divorced from the social and eco-
nomic structures within which states and societies are embedded. It is also the case
that, as often noted, his work tended to downplay political economy, and his view of
the state’s capacity to control the direction and scope of either the national economy or
global capitalism was strained, even in the mid-1970s. Moreover, any contemporary
analysis of order and governance needs to place order within the state system against
the other two arenas within which all social order needs to be understood: civil society
on the one hand (including what is now termed transnational civil society), and eco-
nomic markets on the other.
Yet, it remains plausible to argue that alternative global frameworks for order are
either incoherent and contested (for example transnational civil society), or efficient but
highly unstable (as in the case of markets and the global economy). Yes, the past 35
years have seen an intensification of economic and social globalization, but the
146 Andrew Hurrell
inequalities and discontents of globalization have led to increased political strains both
internationally and within many states. In addition, they have fatally undermined any
notion that globalization will lead easily or unproblematically to shared values, resilient
institutions, or to a meaningful global moral community. Yes, the density of the norms,
rules and institutions of international society has increased tremendously, often pushing
in a liberal direction. Yet, Bull’s scepticism may still be merited: whose solidarist or
liberal order? How stable and how legitimate can a liberal order be when it depends so
heavily on the hegemony of the single superpower whose history is so ‘exceptionalist’
and whose attitude to international law and institutions has been so ambivalent? How
will international society confront its current triple challenge: a power transition driven
by the rise of new emerging powers; a structural transition in the scope of cooperation
as governments have to face a series of complex and often interconnected global chal-
lenges; and a cultural transition as both state power and the dynamics of the global
capitalist economy move beyond the West?
So we are still left with Bull’s concern with the disjuncture between the vaulting normative
ambitions of contemporary international society and its precarious power-political,
institutional and cultural foundations. Although sometimes seen as optimistic, com-
placent, or even nostalgic, Bull was constantly worried by what he called ‘premature
global solidarism’ – that too many hopes, too many demands, and too many moral
claims were being placed on the still thin fabric of international society. Contemporary
readers will disagree as to whether Bull’s own conclusions remain valid, but his ques-
tions and the framework for analysing provided by The Anarchical Society remain one
of the most important points of departure for any study of order in world politics.
Notes
1 Matthew Arnold, Culture and Anarchy (1869) in Arnold’s ‘Culture and Anarchy’ and Other
Writings, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993. For a discussion of Arnold’s notion
of culture as ‘the best that has been thought and said’, see Stefan Collini, Matthew Arnold: A
Critical Portrait, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008.
2 On this point see Edward Keene, ‘International Society as an Ideal Type’, in Cornelia Navari
(ed.), Theorising International Society: English School Methods, Basingstoke: Palgrave Mac-
millan, 2009, pp. 104–23.
3 For a succinct recent account see Tim Dunne, ‘The English School’, in Christian Reus-Smit
and Duncan Snidal (eds) The Oxford Handbook of International Relations, Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2008, pp. 267–85. For longer studies see Andrew Linklater and Hidemi
Suganami, The English School and International Relations: A Contemporary Reassessment,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006; Barry Buzan, From International to World
Society? English School Theory and the Social Structure of Globalization, Cambridge: Cam-
bridge University Press, 2004; and Richard Little and John Williams (eds), The Anarchical
Society in a Globalized World, Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2006. For a discussion of
where Bull fits within the English School see Tim Dunne, Inventing International Society: A
History of the English School, New York: St Martin’s Press, 1998. For a full bibliography see the
English School website. Available at: www.polis.leeds.ac.uk/research/international-relations-
security/english-school/ (accessed 17 December 12). For a recent collection of articles con-
centrating more directly on Bull himself see Coral Bell and Meredith Thatcher (eds)
Remembering Hedley, Canberra: ANU e-press, 2008.
4 Hedley Bull, The Anarchical Society: A Study of Order in World Politics, Basingstoke: Palgrave
Macmillan, 2012. Page numbers placed in parentheses in the text refer to this fourth edition.
5 One important influence on Bull’s understanding of order was his Oxford tutor, the legal
theorist H. L. A. Hart, and his notion of a ‘minimum content of natural law’. See H. L. A.
Hart, The Concept of Law, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1981. For a more detailed
Hedley Bull: The Anarchical Society 147
analysis of Bull’s views, see Kai Alderson and Andrew Hurrell (eds), Hedley Bull on Inter-
national Society, Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2000, Chapters 1–3; Robert Ayson,
Hedley Bull and the Accomodation of Power, Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2012.
6 See, for example, Robert Jervis, ‘A Political Science Perspective on the Balance of Power and
Concert’, American Historical Review, 1992, vol. 97, 716–24.
7 On the importance of legitimacy in the context of unequal power see Ian Clark, Hegemony in
International Society, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011.
8 Martin Wight, International Theory: The Three Traditions, eds. Gabriele Wight and Brian
Porter, Leicester: Leicester University Press, 1991. See also Hedley Bull, ‘Martin Wight and
the Three Traditions of International Relations’, British Journal of International Studies,
1976, vol. 2, 101–16.
9 Hedley Bull, ‘International Theory: The Case for the Classical Approach’, World Politics,
1966, vol. 18, 361–77.
10 Dunne, Inventing International Society, p. 271.
11 Patrick T. Jackson, The Conduct of Inquiry in International Relations. Philosophy of Science
and its Implications for the Study of World Politics, London: Routledge, 2011, p. 6.
12 Michael Mandelbaum, ‘Review of The Anarchical Society’, Political Science Quarterly, 2007,
vol. 92, 574–75.
13 See Tim Dunne, ‘The Social Construction of International Society’, European Journal of
International Relations, 1995, vol. 1, 367–90; and Christian Reus-Smit, ‘Imagining Society:
Constructivism and the English School’, British Journal of Politics and International Rela-
tions, 2002, vol. 4, 487–509.
14 See for example, Martha Finnemore, ‘Exporting the English School?’ Review of International
Studies, 2001, vol. 27, 509–13.
15 Edward Keene, ‘The English School and the British Historians’, Millennium: Journal of
International Studies, 2008, vol. 37, 387.
16 Justin Rosenberg, ‘The International Imagination: IR Theory and “Classic Social Analysis”’,
Millennium: Journal of International Studies, 1994, vol. 23, 85–108.
17 See for example, Chris Brown, Sovereignty, Rights and Justice, Cambridge: Polity, 2002.
18 See Andrew Hurrell and Terry MacDonald, ‘Ethics and Norms in International Relations’, in
Walter Carlsnaes, Thomas Risse and Beth Simmons eds, Handbook of International Rela-
tions, London: Sage, 2012.
19 For a recent example see Ian Hall, ‘Taming the Anarchical Society’, e-International Relations
(5 July 2012). Available at: www.e-ir.info/2012/07/05/taming-the-the-anarchical-society/ (accessed 9
July 2012).
20 For claims about change and transformation see David Held and Anthony McGrew (eds),
The Transformations Reader, 2nd edn, Cambridge: Polity Press, 2003.
21 For a recent critique of this position see Peter Wilson, ‘The English School Meets the Chi-
cago School: The Case for a Grounded Theory of International Institutions’, International
Studies Review, 2012, vol. 14.
22 Bull’s letter to Shaie Selzer, Macmillan Publishers. 14 November 1975. Bull’s Papers, Bod-
leian Library, Oxford.
23 See, for example, Tim Dunne and Nicholas Wheeler, ‘Hedley Bull’s Pluralism of the Intellect
and Solidarism of the Will’, International Affairs, 1996, vol. 72, 91–107.
24 See, for example, Nicholas Wheeler, Saving Strangers: Humanitarian Intervention in Interna-
tional Society, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000. Note that Bull examined the possibi-
lities of change in norms concerning intervention well before the subject became fashionable.
See Hedley Bull (ed.), Intervention in World Politics, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1984.
25 See, for example, Andrew Linklater, The Transformation of Political Community: Ethical
Foundations of the Post-Westphalian Era, Cambridge: Polity Press, 1998.
26 Both of these issues are examined in Buzan, From International to World Society. On the
former issue see also Barry Buzan and Ana Gonzalez-Pelaez (eds), International Society and
the Middle East: English School Theory at the Regional Level, London: Routledge, 2009. On
the latter issue see also Ian Clark, International Legitimacy and World Society, Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 2007.
27 See Andrew Hurrell, On Global Order: Power, Values and the Constitution of International
Society, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007.
15 A circumspect revival of liberalism:
Robert O. Keohane and Joseph S. Nye’s
Power and Interdependence
Thomas C. Walker1
Classic works in International Relations (IR) can emerge in a variety of ways. Some
classics introduce a new paradigm that explains complex phenomena better than pre-
vious efforts. Others revive neglected but important ideas and claims. Still others hit the
tenor of the times and speak to immediate challenges facing global politics. Robert O.
Keohane and Joseph S. Nye’s Power and Interdependence (PI), first published in 1977,
is indeed a classic for all of these reasons.2 Unlike some of the works discussed in this
volume, Keohane and Nye’s work was promptly hailed as a classic. Two of the leading
IR journals published article-length reviews of PI shortly after its publication. In
International Organization, Kal Holsti surmised that this book may ‘prove to be one of
the most significant writings in international relations theory of the past two decades’.3
In an extensive review published in World Politics, Stanley Michalak referred to PI as
‘a groundbreaking work … that will have a long-term impact on the ways in which
teachers and scholars conceptualize international phenomena’.4 Both of these reviewers
were prescient. The themes and puzzles presented in PI continue to shape our thinking
on globalization, international trade, regime formation and change, non-state actors as
well as the nature of power and military force in the global realm.
PI was an early collaboration between two young scholars who would both become
ranked among the most influential in the field of IR. When IR scholars were recently
asked ‘whose work has had the greatest influence on the field of IR in the past 20
years’ Robert O. Keohane was ranked first and Joseph S. Nye was ranked sixth.5 Their
high standing in the field rests in no small part on the enduring influence of PI and the
ways in which it deviated from the standard realist approach. The degree of realist
dominance in the decades prior to PI cannot be overstated. In the mid-1950s Hans J.
Morgenthau’s Politics Among Nations, the subject of Chapter 7 in this volume, was
‘used by more North American university-level instructors than all competing texts in
international politics combined’.6 The discipline’s reliance on realist theory was rigor-
ously documented by John Vasquez. Vasquez demonstrated how realist theory
informed more than 90 per cent of the hypotheses tested by IR scholars up to the
1970s.7 In this context of realist dominance, Keohane and Nye offered a timely con-
trast. The events of the 1970s seemed to shake the foundations of political realism. The
US inability to prevail in Vietnam despite overwhelming military capabilities was par-
ticularly troubling for many political realists. Power, especially military power, was not
as fungible as realists had expected. The oil embargo initiated by the Organization of
Petroleum Exporting Countries (OPEC) in 1972 further highlighted the changing
nature of power in the global system by demonstrating how militarily weak states could
still wield considerable influence. The global economic crisis brought on by the collapse
Robert O. Keohane and Joseph S. Nye: Power and Interdependence 149
of the Bretton Woods system showed that even the hegemon was vulnerable in an
interdependent world. Finally, the emergence of new issues of global environmental
management and questions of global governance of seabed resources raised a new set
of problems that realism could not address. Collectively, these real-world events posed
serious challenges to the realist paradigm. PI effectively responded to this series of
crises that beset world politics in the 1970s. In their Preface to the first edition, Keo-
hane and Nye admit that they ‘soon became uneasy about this one-sided [realist] view
of reality, particularly about its inadequate analysis of economic integration and of the
roles played by formal and informal international institutions’ (p. v). Keohane and Nye
set out to address these inadequacies by clarifying the concept of complex inter-
dependence and to show how complex interdependence contributes to the rise of
international regimes in a variety of issue areas. Their case studies examined interna-
tional monetary affairs and global management of the oceans. They also devoted
chapters to the cooperative bilateral relationships between the USA and Canada and
the USA and Australia. These cases demonstrate how growing interdependence
undermines the efficacy of military power and imposes layers of complexity on global
politics that are not acknowledged by realism.
I will begin reviewing the central claims and contentions made in PI and how these
claims challenged mainstream IR in the 1970s. I will then critically explore Keohane
and Nye’s later efforts to graft PI onto neorealist theory rather than highlighting how
their ideas challenge realist expectations. I argue that this obscures the close relation-
ship between PI and long-standing liberal internationalist themes in IR. I conclude by
exploring the significant and enduring legacy of PI in the study of IR.
Conclusion
Despite this requisite and speculative quibbling, PI stands as a true classic by virtue of
its influence and legacy in the study of IR. While PI certainly revived many neglected
aspects of liberal internationalism, it is difficult to label this as an exclusively liberal
work. As the title suggests, realist elements of power must be examined with liberal
elements of interdependence. In their Afterword, Keohane and Nye reflect on how PI
Robert O. Keohane and Joseph S. Nye: Power and Interdependence 155
‘consistently asks, without dogmatic presuppositions, under what conditions liberal or
realist theories will provide more accurate accounts of world political reality’ (p. 252,
emphasis in the original). In the end, this work provided IR with a new research pro-
gramme and new concepts which political realism had long ignored. Each of the
authors went on individually to develop ideas first put forth in PI. From their discus-
sions of power, Nye developed the concept of soft power more fully in Bound to Lead,
published in 1990. As opposed to material capabilities, soft power rests on ‘the attrac-
tion of one’s ideas or on the ability to set the political agenda in a way that shapes the
preferences that others express’.19 The origins of soft power, a concept now ingrained
in the discourse of IR, can be clearly discerned in PI. Keohane followed up their
seminal ideas of international regimes in his masterful book, After Hegemony, pub-
lished in 1984.20 This work could also merit inclusion as a classic of IR. Keohane and
Nye’s discussion of global governance working along informal and interdependent
networks sparked a generation of research on the topic, most notably Anne-Marie
Slaughter’s extensive study demonstrating how transnational networks shape global
politics across a variety of issues.21 Their focus on how trade and interdependence can
transform relations between states remains prominent in the liberal research pro-
gramme. Recent works by Michael Mousseau and Erik Gartzke provide systemic evi-
dence that supports the expectations of Keohane and Nye. Trade, as liberals have long
predicted, is strongly associated with peace, which Gartzke refers to as the Capitalist
Peace.22 Both Mousseau and Gartzke argue that the complex networks created by
trade may be a more powerful explanation for the liberal peace than democratic gov-
ernance. This claim, like many others in PI, will continue to be evaluated by students
of IR. Finally, Keohane and Nye’s influence on broad studies of interdependence and
globalization would be impossible to summarize. However, few would challenge the
claim that Keohane and Nye’s work was at the forefront. In the end, this work stands
as one of the earliest and most sustained efforts to address how multifaceted concepts
like globalization and interdependence are changing the nature of world politics. These
efforts will continue to shape the discipline and they are far more advanced due to the
contribution of Keohane and Nye’s seminal study, PI.
Notes
1 I would like to thank Robert O. Keohane and Jonathan M. DiCiccio for helpful and
insightful comments about an earlier draft of this chapter.
2 Robert O. Keohane and Joseph S. Nye, Power and Interdependence (2nd edn), Glenview, IL:
Scott, Foresman and Co, 1989. All page numbers placed in parentheses in this review refer to
the second edition, which contains all of the original 1977 text but also presents two new
concluding chapters; an Afterword in which Keohane and Nye respond directly to several
critics of the first edition and a short chapter on international regimes entitled ‘Two Cheers
for Multilateralism’. With these two exceptions, the first and second editions are identical.
3 Kal Holsti, ‘A New International Politics? Diplomacy in Complex Interdependence’, Inter-
national Organization, 1978, vol. 32, 513–30, at p. 524.
4 Stanley Michalak, ‘Theoretical Perspectives for Understanding International Inter-
dependence’, World Politics, 1979, vol. 32, 136–50, at p. 136.
5 Richard Jordan, Daniel Maliniak, Amy Oakes, Susan Peterson and Michael Tierney, ‘One
Discipline or Many? TRIP Survey of International Relations Faculty in Ten Countries’,
Teaching, Research, and International Policy (TRIP) Project, The Institute for the Theory
and Practice of International Relations, The College of William and Mary, Williamsburg,
VA, February 2009, p. 43.
156 Thomas C. Walker
6 William Scheuerman, Hans Morgenthau: Realism and Beyond, Cambridge: Polity Press, 2009,
p. 102.
7 John Vasquez, in The Power of Power Politics, New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press,
1983, showed how realism dominated up until the 1970s. For an updated analysis of realism’s
hold on the field of IR, see Thomas Walker and Jeffrey Morton ‘Re-Assessing the “Power of
Power Politics” Thesis: Is Realism still Dominant?’, International Studies Review, 2005, vol. 7,
341–56. Walker and Morton show a decline in realist influence, especially in the 1990s.
8 Stephan Haggard and Beth Simmons, ‘Theories of International Regimes’, International
Organization, 1987, vol. 41, 491–517, at p. 491.
9 Stephen Krasner, ‘Structural Causes and Regime Consequences: Regimes as Intervening
Variables’, International Organization, 1982, vol. 36, 185–205.
10 While Keohane and Nye did not coin the phrase ‘international regime’, they did popularize
it. In the Afterword to the second edition, Keohane and Nye acknowledge their debt to John
Ruggie’s earlier work published in 1975 (p. 250). See John Ruggie, ‘International Responses
to Technology: Concepts and Trends’, International Organization, 1975, vol. 29, 557–83.
11 For recent discussions of the logic of case selection, see Gary King, Robert Keohane and
Sidney Verba, Designing Social Inquiry: Scientific Inference in Qualitative Research, Prince-
ton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1994, and Alexander George and Andrew Bennett, Case
Studies and Theory Development in the Social Sciences, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2005.
12 Immanuel Kant, ‘Perpetual Peace: A Philosophical Sketch’, in Hans Reiss (ed.), Kant’s Poli-
tical Writings, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970, p. 114.
13 Thomas Paine, Rights of Man, Baltimore, MD: Penguin Books, 1969 [1791–92], p. 234.
14 Thomas Paine, ‘Letter to the Abbé Raynal’, in Daniel E. Wheeler (ed.), Life and Writings of
Thomas Paine, New York: Vincent Park and Company, [1782] 1908, p. 240. For a more
thorough overview of Paine and Kant in IR, see Thomas C. Walker, ‘Two Faces of Liberal-
ism: Kant, Paine, and the Question of Intervention’, International Studies Quarterly, 2008,
vol. 52, 444–68.
15 For a discussion of how challenges to the dominant paradigm are often dismissed in IR, see
Thomas C. Walker, ‘The Perils of Paradigm Mentalities: Revisiting Kuhn, Lakatos, and
Popper’, Perspectives on Politics, 2010, vol. 8, 433–51.
16 Cited in John Mueller, Retreat from Doomsday: The Obsolescence of Major War, New York:
Basic Books, 1989, p. 30.
17 Hans Morgenthau, Scientific Man vs. Power Politics, Chicago, IL: University of Chicago
Press, 1946, p. 81; p. 86.
18 Kenneth Waltz, ‘The Myth of National Interdependence’, in Charles Kindleberger (ed.), The
Multinational Corporation, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1970; and Kenneth Waltz, Theory of
International Politics, New York: Random House, 1979, p. 158.
19 Joseph S. Nye, Bound to Lead: The Changing Nature of American Power, New York: Basic
Books, 1990.
20 Robert O. Koehane, After Hegemony: Cooperation and Discord in the World Political Econ-
omy, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1984.
21 Anne-Marie Slaughter, A New World Order, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2004.
22 Michael Mousseau, ‘The Social Market Roots of Democratic Peace’, International Security,
vol. 33, 52–86; and Erik Gartzke, ‘The Capitalist Peace’, American Journal of Political Science,
2007, vol. 51, 166–91.
16 The politics of international theory:
reading Waltz 1979 as a classic
Anders Wivel1
No book on international relations has generated more debate over the past three
decades than Kenneth Waltz’s Theory of International Politics (hereafter TIP) pub-
lished in 1979.2 Today, the book is widely regarded as a modern classic.3 It continues to
be extensively cited in the study of international relations by admirers as well as critics,
and few university students would be able to take an introductory course on interna-
tional relations without becoming acquainted with Kenneth Waltz’s so-called neoreal-
ist – or structural realist – theory, although many will only learn about the theory
from textbooks, often written by authors critical of Waltz’s theory, and only a small
minority will read the book cover-to-cover.
TIP leaves us with no testable hypotheses about the nature or processes of interna-
tional relations. Its methodological assumptions are complex, at times foggy, and its
sparse and minimalist framework has been proven partly irrelevant and partly wrong,
even by scholars taking their point of departure in realist assumptions. Yet the book
has had an enormous impact on thinking about international relations, and it continues
to be an indispensable starting point for anyone wishing to discuss, develop or apply a
realist perspective on international relations.
Despite its continued importance to the study of international relations, the position
of Waltz’s structural realist theory within the discipline of International Relations (IR)
is changing. Neorealism no longer plays a central role in the debates regarding how to
explain and understand international relations or what the discipline of IR is or ought
to be.4 One would be hard pressed to find a recent article in any one of the top ten
journals on international relations, which uses neorealism as its analytical framework.
Instead ‘Waltz 1979’ has become a standard reference in modern realism, rather like
‘Carr 1939’, ‘Morgenthau 1948’ – or ‘Waltz 1959’: everybody knows it, few have read
it, and virtually no one uses it as point of departure for analysing international
relations.
In 1979, following a decade of political, normative and academic obscurity, TIP
marked the cool, calm and collected return of realism to the centre stage, in both
practical-political and scholarly debates about international relations. During the next
two decades neorealism played a major role in debates about how to explain and
understand international relations5 before being edged out by a new generation of
‘post-neorealist’ realists.6 The result for neorealism was, however, not margin-
alization but canonization. Attacks became fewer and further between and celebrations
of the contribution made by Waltz are now the order of the day.7 TIP has become a
classic.
158 Anders Wivel
How to write an IR classic (Don’t worry, it’s easy)
What does it take to write an IR classic? Using neorealism as a prism, it is possible to
identify five rules.
3. Challenge the orthodoxy, politically and academically, but stay safely within the
dominant discourse
Almost by definition, realism is ‘a hard sell’ in liberal societies, because of its claim that
the struggle for power, not ideological differences or ethical considerations, is at the heart
of all international relations, even for liberal democracies.13 Moreover, realism advan-
ces a pessimistic, almost fatalistic, view of international relations, which contrasts with
the expectation of both the electorate and political elites in modern societies that the
primary task of politicians is to solve problems and actively face the challenges that
confront the societies they govern. Kenneth Waltz is often applauded for his thought-
provoking ideas that go against the political and academic grain,14 and there is defi-
nitely some truth in this. Waltz has argued that the spread of nuclear weapons may
enhance peace, because the destructive power of these weapons will create an incentive
to avoid military conflict,15 that the USA is no different from other great powers and that
ideas matter little to its foreign policy,16 and that terrorism has left the basic char-
acteristics of international relations virtually untouched, because it does not threaten state
survival.17 However, compared to post-World War II realists, such as Hans J.
Morgenthau and Reinhold Niebuhr, who took their point of departure in a dis-
tinctively conservative and European conception of man and a traditionalist view of
social science, Waltz represents a realist perspective that is much more synchronized
with both political and academic discourse in the USA. Politically, TIP refrains from
explicating a particular view of man, leaving it philosophically antiseptic and compa-
tible with US liberalism.18 Academically, Waltz clearly distinguishes his own neorealist
‘theory’ from realist ‘thought’,19 thereby signalling that his own work – in contrast to
the work of past realists – meets the contemporary standards of philosophy of science
(p. 1).20 Acting as an agent provocateur within the discourse, rather than challenging the
discourse in itself, is not necessarily a bad idea. Part of the secret to TIP’s success is that
Waltz has managed to keep his provocations within the political and academic mainstream.
New ideas Waltz in: neoclassical realism and the study of foreign policy
Waltz’s insistence that TIP is strictly a theory of international politics, not foreign
policy (p. 122),37 has spurred an interest in how to combine Waltz’s assumptions on
international structure with explanatory variables such as domestic politics and the
perceptions and intentions of leaders. Today the realist perspective on international
relations is highly influenced by so-called neoclassical realists, who attempt ‘to combine
structural factors with domestic politics in order to explain foreign policy’.38 Neo-
classical realists open the ‘black box’ of the state and thereby return to a richer and
more inclusive understanding of realism found in earlier formulations of the perspec-
tive. This development is not necessarily a contrast or challenge to neorealist theory,39
but it does accentuate the need to explicate how neorealism may contribute to our
understanding of foreign policy.
How may TIP contribute to realist theorizing on foreign policy? Neorealism tells us
little about foreign policy per se but focuses instead on explaining ‘international out-
comes – phenomena that result from the interaction of two or more actors in the
international system [such as] international cooperation, arms races, crisis bargaining,
aggregate alignment patterns, and the war-proneness of the international system’.40 The
theory tells us about structural pressure, and the opportunities and limitations that
follow for state action, but it tells us little about how states actually respond to these
pressures (p. 73). Thus, TIP identifies the systemic demands on state external beha-
viour, but it does not tell us if and how these are met by the supply of foreign policy.
Still, foreign policy and international politics are not two distinct realms, ‘since for-
eign policy is a constituting element of international politics’,41 and a structural theory
is of little use if structural pressure does not affect state behaviour. Thus, it should
Kenneth Waltz: Theory of International Politics 163
come as no surprise that neorealism has led to hypotheses about foreign policy. For
instance, the imbalance of power between the USA and its allies following the Cold
War has led to hypotheses about the foreign policy of a largely unrestrained power.42
More controversially, it may be argued that the neorealist conceptions of competition
and socialization, and in particular the interaction between these processes, can lead to
hypotheses about foreign policy. As noted by Waltz, ‘competition spurs the actors to
accommodate their ways to the socially most acceptable and successful practices.
Socialization and competition are two aspects of a process by which the variety of
actors is reduced’ (p. 77). From this starting point, neorealism may be used to generate
hypotheses about the successful adaption of democratic states to systemic constraints,43
the decision of European states to strengthen the institutions of the European Union,44
and which foreign policy roles will be acceptable for particular states.45
Alternatively, TIP may be used as a minimalist starting point to which we gradually add
complexity. Neorealism remains the basic theory providing us with our most funda-
mental hypotheses (e.g. states tend to balance power in an anarchic system), but neo-
classical realism is used either to explain empirical deviations from these theoretical
expectations, or it serves as a specification of the unspecified neorealist explanations:46
structures ‘shape and shove’,47 but they do not explain foreign policy.48 By constructing
a theory, which acknowledges the primacy of the international system, while at the same
time theorizing variations in the impact of the international systemic structure on state
behaviour, i.e. the variations in ‘the relative importance of systemic versus domestic and
individual level variables’,49 we may be able to explain foreign policy in a way which
allows us to distinguish between general and context specific variations. In accordance with
neorealist logic states may be seen as the primary actors (p. 93)50 and members of the
foreign policy executive as reflecting state interests. Variations in foreign policy may stem
from domestic legislatures, interest groups, societal actors as well as external pressure
and the ability of foreign policy makers to obtain and process information about their exter-
nal environment.51 Starting from ‘a “top-down” conception of the state, where systemic
forces ultimately drive external behaviour’,52 TIP’s understanding of international
structure may be used as a starting point when adding first and second image variables
in order to explain foreign policy by gradually adding complexity to the parsimonious
starting point.53 If used in this way TIP may be instrumental in ameliorating an
‘identity dilemma’ between the equally unattractive options of either restricting relist
analysis to neorealist core assumptions and ending up with indeterminate explanations,
or combining structural factors with other variables and ending up with a collection of
ad hoc arguments which are indistinct from other theoretical perspectives.54
Notes
1 An earlier version of this chapter ‘From Cool to Classic: Learning from Waltz (1979)’
appeared in Politik, 2009, vol. 12, 42–47. A subsequent version of the paper benefited from
presentations at the International Studies Association Catalytic Research Workshop ‘Bridging
the Transatlantic Divide: European and American Realism Reconsidered’ in Montreal,
Canada, 15 March 2011, and at an International Relations research seminar at the Depart-
ment of Political Science, University of Copenhagen, Denmark, 12 April 2011. I thank all
participants at these events and, in particular, Barry Buzan, Balkan Devlen, Birthe Hansen,
Lene Hansen, Peter Viggo Jakobsen, Steven E. Lobell, Hans Mouritzen, Ulrik Pram Gad,
Alexander Reichwein, Norrin M. Ripsman, Jeffrey W. Taliaferro and Ole Wæver.
2 Kenneth N. Waltz, Theory of International Politics, New York: McGraw-Hill, 1979. Page
numbers placed in parentheses in the text refer to this edition.
3 Chris Brown, ‘Structural Realism, Classical Realism and Human Nature’, in Ken Booth
(ed.), Realism and World Politics, London: Routledge, 2011, pp. 143–57, at p. 143; cf. Ken
Booth, ‘Realism Redux: Contexts, Concepts, Contents’, in Booth (ed.), Realism and World
Politics, pp. 1–14, at pp. 3–6; Randall Schweller, ‘The Progressiveness of Neoclassical Rea-
lism’, in Colin Elman and Miriam Fendius Elman (eds), Progress in International Relations
Theory, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2003, pp. 311–47, at p. 313; Stephen M. Walt, ‘“A Few
Big and Important Things”: The Enduring Legacy of Kenneth Waltz’, Politik, 2005, vol. 8,
48–51.
4 Today, even realists taking their point of departure in neorealism are few and far between as
exemplified by Randall Schweller’s (somewhat exaggerated) claim that neoclassical realism
represents the ‘only game in town for the next and the current generation of realists’
(Schweller, ‘The Progressiveness of Neoclassical Realism’, p. 345). For a notable exception to
this trend, see Birthe Hansen, Unipolarity and World Politics, London: Routledge, 2011.
5 David A. Baldwin (ed.), Neorealism and Neoliberalism, New York: Columbia University
Press, 1993; and Robert O. Keohane (ed.), Neorealism and Its Critics, New York: Columbia
University Press, 1986.
6 Stephen G. Brooks, ‘Dueling Realisms’, International Organization, 1991, vol. 51, 445–77;
Annette Freyberg-Inan, Ewan Harrison and Patrick James (eds), Rethinking Realism in
International Relations, Baltimore, MD: The Johns Hopkins University Press, 2009; Steven E.
Lobell, Norrin M. Ripsman and Jeffrey W. Taliaferro (eds), Neoclassical Realism, The State,
and Foreign Policy, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009; Brian Rathbun, ‘A Rose
by Any Other Name: Neoclassical Realism as the Logical and Necessary Extension of
Structural Realism’, Security Studies, 2008, vol. 17, 294–321; Gideon Rose ‘Neoclassical
Realism and Theories of Foreign Policy’, World Politics, 1998, vol. 51, 144–72; and Anders
Wivel, ‘Explaining Why State X Made a Certain Move Last Tuesday: The Promise and
Limitations of Realist Foreign Policy Analysis’, Journal of International Relations and
Development, 2005, vol. 8, 355–80.
7 See e.g. the contributions to Booth (ed.), Realism and World Politics; and Andrew K.
Hanami (ed.), Perspectives on Structural Realism, Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2003.
8 Walt, ‘“A Few Big and Important Things”’, p. 49; and Kenneth N. Waltz, ‘The Origins of
War in Neorealist Theory’, in Robert I. Rotberg and Theodore K. Rabb (eds), The Origin and
Prevention of Major Wars, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988, pp. 39–52.
9 Joseph M. Grieco, Cooperation among Nations, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1990, p. 38.
10 Cf. Grieco, Cooperation among Nations.
Kenneth Waltz: Theory of International Politics 165
11 Kenneth N. Waltz, ‘Reflections on Theory of International Politics: A Response to My Crit-
ics’, in Robert O. Keohane (ed.), Neorealism and Its Critics, pp. 322–45; and Kenneth N.
Waltz, ‘Evaluating Theories’, The American Political Science Review, 1997, vol. 91, 913–17.
12 See e.g. Kenneth N. Waltz, ‘The Emerging Structure of International Politics’, International
Security, 1993, vol. 18, 44–79; Kenneth N. Waltz, ‘Structural Realism after the Cold War’,
International Security, 2000, vol. 25, 5–41; and Kenneth N. Waltz ‘The Continuity of Inter-
national Politics’, in Ken Booth and Tim Dunne (eds), World in Collision, New York: Pal-
grave Macmillan, 2002, pp. 348–53.
13 John Mearsheimer, The Tragedy of Great Power Politics, New York: Norton, 2001, pp. 22–27.
14 Hans Mouritzen, ‘Kenneth Waltz: A Critical Rationalist between International Politics and
Foreign Policy’, in Iver B. Neumann and Ole Wæver (eds), The Future of International
Relations, London: Routledge, 1997, pp. 66–89; Booth, ‘Realism Redux’; and Walt, ‘“A Few
Big and Important Things”’.
15 Kenneth N. Waltz, ‘The Spread of Nuclear Weapons: More May Be Better?’, Adelphi Papers,
171, London: International Institute for Strategic Studies, 1981.
16 Kenneth N. Waltz, ‘America as a Model for the World? A Foreign Policy Perspective’, PS:
Political Science and Politics, 1991, vol. 24, 667–70.
17 Waltz, ‘The Continuity of International Politics’.
18 Keith L. Shimko, ‘Realism, Neorealism and American Liberalism’, The Review of Politics,
1992, vol. 54, 281–301, at p. 299.
19 Kenneth N. Waltz, ‘Realist Thought and Neorealist Theory’, Journal of International Affairs,
1990, vol. 44, 21–37.
20 In contrast, Ole Wæver argues that Waltz’s view of theory contrasts with the mainstream
view, but that few have noticed, see Ole Wæver, ‘Waltz’s Theory of Theory: The Pictorial
Challenge to Mainstream IR’, in Booth, Realism and World Politics, pp. 67–88.
21 Waltz, ‘Reflections on Theory of International Politics’, p. 343.
22 Robert Gilpin, War and Change in World Politics, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1981, p. 85.
23 Waltz, ‘The Origins of War in Neorealist Theory’, p. 39.
24 Rathbun, ‘A Rose by Any Other Name’, p. 296.
25 Robert O. Keohane, ‘Theory of World Politics: Structural Realism and Beyond’, in Keohane
(ed.), Neorealism and Its Critics, pp. 158–203, at p. 159.
26 E.g. Waltz, ‘Reflections on Theory of International Politics’; and Waltz, ‘Evaluating Theories’.
27 Mouritzen, ‘Kenneth Waltz’, p. 79.
28 Cf. also Waltz, ‘The Spread of Nuclear Weapons’.
29 Cf. Baldwin, Neorealism and Neoliberalism.
30 Cf. John J. Mearsheimer, ‘The False Promise of International Institutions’, International
Security, 1994/95, vol. 19, 5–49; and Stephen M. Walt, ‘The Renaissance of Security Studies’,
International Studies Quarterly, 1991, vol. 35, 211–39.
31 Jim George, Discourses of Global Politics: A Critical (Re)Introduction to International Rela-
tions, Boulder, CO: Lynne Rienner, 1994.
32 Richard Little, The Balance of Power in International Relations, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2007, p. 190.
33 Hansen, Unipolarity and World Politics; Kenneth Waltz and James Fearon, ‘A Conversation
with Kenneth Waltz’, Annual Review of Political Science, 2012, vol. 15, 1–12, at p. 7; and
William C. Wohlforth, ‘The Stability of a Unipolar World’, International Security, 1999, vol.
24, 5–41.
34 William C. Wohlforth, ‘U.S. Strategy in a Unipolar World’, in G. John Ikenberry (ed.),
America Unrivalled, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 2002, pp. 98–118, at pp. 103–4.
35 T. V. Paul, ‘Soft Balancing in the Age of U.S. Primacy’, International Security, 2005, vol. 30,
46–71, at p. 58; cf. Robert Pape, ‘Soft Balancing against the United States’, International
Security, 2005, vol. 30, 7–45; Birthe Hansen, Peter Toft and Anders Wivel, Security Strategies
and American World Order, London: Routledge, 2009; T. V. Paul, James J. Wirtz and Michael
Fortmann (eds), Balance of Power: Theory and Practice in the 21st Century, Stanford, CA:
Stanford University Press, 2004; Stephen M. Walt, ‘Alliances in a Unipolar World’, World
Politics, 2009, vol. 61, 86–120. For a useful overview of scholarly debates on unipolarity since
the end of the Cold War, see Hansen, Unipolarity and World Politics, pp. 14–18.
166 Anders Wivel
36 Cf. e.g. Barry Buzan and Richard Little, ‘Waltz and World History: The Paradox of Parsi-
mony’, in Booth (ed.), Realism and World Politics, pp. 288–305; John G. Ruggie, ‘Continuity
and Transformation in the World Polity: Towards a Neo-Realist Synthesis’, World Politics,
1983, vol. 35, 261–85; and Ernst R. May, Richard Rosecrance and Zara Steiner (eds), History
and Neorealism, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010.
37 Cf. also Kenneth N. Waltz, ‘International Politics is Not Foreign Policy’, Security Studies,
1996, vol. 6, 54–57.
38 Wivel, ‘Explaining Why State X Made a Certain Move Last Tuesday’, p. 360.
39 Schweller, ‘The Progressiveness of Neoclassical Realism’; and Rathbun, ‘A Rose by Any
Other Name’.
40 Jeffrey W. Taliaferro, ‘Security Seeking under Anarchy: Defensive Realism Revisited’, Inter-
national Security, 2001, vol. 25, 128–61, at p. 133.
41 Hans Mouritzen, ‘Past versus Present Geopolitics: Cautiously Opening the Realist Door to
the Past’, in Freyberg-Inan, Harrison and James (eds), Rethinking Realism in International
Relations, p. 165. Cf. Colin Elman, ‘Horses for Courses: Why Not Neorealist Theories of
Foreign Policy?’, Security Studies, 1996, vol. 6, 7–53; Jennifer Sterling-Folker, ‘Realist Envir-
onment, Liberal Process, and Domestic-Level Variables’, International Studies Quarterly,
1997, vol. 41, 1–25.
42 Stephen M. Walt, ‘Alliances in a Unipolar World’; and Waltz ‘America as a Model for the
World?’.
43 Michael C. Williams, ‘The Politics of Theory: Waltz, Realism and Democracy’, in Booth
(ed.), Realism and World Politics, pp. 50–63.
44 Anders Wivel, ‘The Power Politics of Peace: Exploring the Link between Globalization and
European Integration from a Realist Perspective’, Cooperation and Conflict, 2004, vol. 39, 5–25.
45 Cameron G. Thies, ‘States Socialization and Structural Realism’, Security Studies, 2010, vol.
19, 689–717.
46 Norrin M. Ripsman, Jeffrey W. Taliaferro and Steven E. Lobell, ‘Conclusion: The State of
Neoclassical Realism’, in Lobell, Ripsman and Taliaferro (eds), Neoclassical Realism, the
State, and Foreign Policy, pp. 280–90, at p. 281; and cf. Schweller, ‘The Progressiveness of
Neoclassical Realism’.
47 Waltz, ‘Reflections on Theory of International Politics’, p. 343.
48 Colin Elman, ‘Realist Revisionism’, in Freyberg-Inan, Harrison and James (eds), Rethinking
Realism in International Relations, pp. 63–75.
49 Ripsman, Taliaferro and Lobell, ‘Conclusion: The State of Neoclassical Realism’, p. 282.
50 Cf. also Kenneth N. Waltz ‘Foreword’, in Booth (ed.), Realism and World Politics, p. xv.
51 Ripsman, Taliaferro and Lobell, ‘Conclusion: The State of Neoclassical Realism’, pp. 280–83.
52 Jeffrey W. Taliaferro, Steven E. Lobell and Norrin M. Ripsman, ‘Introduction: Neoclassical
Realism, the State, and Foreign Policy’, in Lobell, Ripsman and Taliaferro (eds), Neoclassical
Realism, The State, and Foreign Policy, 1–41, at p. 25.
53 Cf. Keohane, ‘Theory of World Politics: Structural Realism and Beyond’, p. 188; and
Schweller, ‘The Progressiveness of Neoclassical Realism’, p. 317. Cf. Hans Mouritzen and
Anders Wivel, Explaining Foreign Policy: International Diplomacy and the Russo-Georgian
War, Boulder, CO: Lynne Rienner, 2012.
54 Stefano Guzzini, ‘The Enduring Dilemmas of Realism in International Relations’, European
Journal of International Relations, 2004, vol. 10, 533–68; cf. Jeffrey W. Legro and Andrew
Moravcsik, ‘Is Anybody Still a Realist?’, International Security, 1999, vol. 24, 5–55; and John
A. Vasquez, ‘The Realist Paradigm and Degenerative versus Progressive Research Programs:
An Appraisal of Neotraditional Research on Waltz’s Balancing Proposition’, American Poli-
tical Science Review, 1997, vol. 91, 899–912.
55 Mouritzen, ‘Kenneth Waltz’, p. 77.
17 The cosmopolitan turn: beyond realism and
statism in Charles R. Beitz’s Political Theory
and International Relations
William Smith1
The normative study of international relations has gone from being a marginal concern
to a dynamic research agenda.2 This agenda – often labelled ‘international political
theory’ – focuses on ‘the moral dimension of international relations and the wider
question of meanings and interpretation generated by the discipline’.3 It not only
addresses the traditional issue of warfare, but also examines the full range of moral
duties owed by states and individuals to each other. The rise of international political
theory can be associated with a broader revival in political theory, epitomized by the
publication of John Rawls’s A Theory of Justice.4 This work defends principles of social
justice for domestic institutions that regulate social activity. The book presents only a
brief argument about international relations, with Rawls apparently rejecting the
application of these principles to the international realm. Its publication did, however,
inspire subsequent authors to explore this issue in greater depth, prompting an explo-
sion of interest in arguments for and against applying principles of social justice to
international relations.5
The insight that debates about social justice are relevant to international relations is
the chief intellectual legacy of the arguments presented by the US political theorist
Charles R. Beitz (born 1949) in Political Theory and International Relations (PTIR).6
The first edition of PTIR appeared in 1979 and a revised edition, with a new afterword
that clarifies and amends the arguments, appeared in 1999. An earlier version of the
book had been prepared by Beitz as a doctoral dissertation, under the supervision of
Thomas Scanlon and Dennis Thompson, while studying on the political philosophy
programme at Princeton University, USA.7 It is difficult to overestimate the impact
that PTIR had on subsequent debates in international political theory. This is due in
part to the way in which the book maps the hitherto uncharted terrain of the normative
literature on international relations.8 It is also, and more importantly, owing to its substantive
conclusions, particularly its extension of Rawls’s theory of justice from the domestic to
the global realm. Given the significant developments in the field since the initial pub-
lication of PTIR, its continued status as a landmark text is a testament to the originality
of its claims.9
This chapter explores the enduring significance of PTIR for reflection on the nor-
mative dimensions of international relations. The organizing theme is the book’s pre-
sentation of a cosmopolitan alternative to the realist and statist paradigms that,
according to Beitz, dominate modern thinking about international morality. The cen-
tral insight of realism is associated with the claim that states should pursue their
national interests over and above other moral principles. The central insight of statism,
or ‘the morality of states’, is that states should treat each other as autonomous entities
168 William Smith
with moral rights analogous to those of individuals. These perspectives are rejected in
PTIR in favour of a cosmopolitan theory that treats the interests of individuals as prior
to interests of states. This chapter explores PTIR’s call for a ‘cosmopolitan turn’ in
international political thought through: (i) summarizing its central arguments; (ii) sur-
veying prominent responses to it in the subsequent literature; and (iii) evaluating its
legacy as an attempt to lay the groundwork for a cosmopolitan political theory.
This characterization brings to the fore the underlying motive behind the reformu-
lation of the argument noted above. In refining his account of global interconnectivity,
Beitz hopes to achieve a closer fit between his theory and the cosmopolitan intuition that
the interests of all persons, conceptualized as free and equal, must be taken into
account in a global social contract. This move, he hopes, will lend further support to his
contention that the principles of justice selected for the global realm should be treated
as an extension of the corresponding principles selected for domestic contexts. This
commitment to the form of a cosmopolitan theory is, as he makes clear in the afterword,
a more fundamental concern for Beitz than his suggestions about the specific content of
these principles (p. 199).
The principal legacy of PTIR, to my mind, is its contribution to debates about what
a cosmopolitan view in international political thought should look like. This is reflected
in the number of authors who follow Beitz in conceptualizing cosmopolitanism as an
attempt to globalize conceptions of justice hitherto treated as limited in their scope to
domestic contexts.31 Cosmopolitanism has thus become an umbrella term for a family of
views in international political theory, which share a commitment to globalizing prin-
ciples of justice but often differ in their specific recommendations about the content of
those principles.32 The likelihood is that debates in international political theory will
continue to revolve around interpretations and criticisms of cosmopolitanism as
defined by Beitz. In terms of critical reflection on this legacy, at least two observations
should be made. The first relates to its focus on the moral contours of cosmopolitan
theory at the expense of its institutional implications. The value of this move is that it
encourages scholars to reflect with greater care on the underlying normative principles
of international relations. The concern – which Beitz has since acknowledged – is that
it risks pushing to the margins the equally pressing issue of the policies and practices that
must be established in order to realize cosmopolitan principles.33 The second relates to the
adequacy of Beitz’s definition of cosmopolitanism as a doctrine that calls for domestic
and global contexts to be governed according to the same principles of justice. The
value of this move, as noted, is that it establishes ‘clear blue water’ between cosmopo-
litan and non-cosmopolitan interpretations of liberalism. The price, though, is that we are
left with quite a narrow and, indeed, exclusionary definition, which appears to cast out
from the cosmopolitan liberal family those theories that aim to reconcile equal concern
for all persons with contrasting principles of domestic and global justice.34 These con-
cerns, however, do not detract from the achievements of PTIR as a work that has more
or less set the agenda for theorizing about global justice for the past 30 years. This
achievement lends meaning to the suggestion, explicit in the title of an essay by Chris
Brown, that current theoretical debate is, to a great extent, a ‘house that Chuck built’.35
Notes
1 I am extremely grateful to Charles Beitz for comments on earlier versions of this chapter.
Charles R. Beitz: Political Theory and International Relations 175
2 Nicholas Rengger, ‘Reading Charles Beitz: Twenty-Five Years of Political Theory and Inter-
national Relations’, Review of International Studies, 2005, vol. 31, 361–69, at p. 361.
3 Chris Brown, International Relations Theory: New Normative Approaches, New York: Har-
vester Wheatsheaf, 1992, p. 3. The introduction of Brown’s book discusses the relationship
between international political theory and International Relations.
4 John Rawls, A Theory of Justice: Revised Edition, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999. The
first edition was published in 1971.
5 Brown, International Relations Theory, pp. 8–11.
6 Charles R. Beitz, Political Theory and International Relations: Revised and with a New
Afterword by the Author, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1999. Page numbers
placed in parentheses in the text refer to this edition.
7 Beitz returned to Princeton in 2001 to take the position of Edwards S. Sanford Professor of
Politics.
8 Chris Brown, ‘The House that Chuck Built: Twenty-Five Years of Reading Charles Beitz’,
Review of International Studies, 2005, vol. 31, 371–79, at p. 371.
9 The designation of PTIR as a ‘landmark’ text is from Kok-Chor Tan, Justice Without Bor-
ders: Cosmopolitanism, Nationalism and Patriotism, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
2004, p. 57.
10 Rawls, A Theory of Justice, pp. 266–67. An accessible summary of Rawls’s theory is in Will
Kymlicka, Contemporary Political Theory: An Introduction, 2nd edn, Oxford: Oxford Uni-
versity Press, 2001, Chapter 2.
11 Rawls, A Theory of Justice, pp. 331–33. This aspect of Rawls’s argument is discussed in Chris
Brown, Sovereignty, Rights and Justice: International Political Theory, Cambridge: Polity,
2002, pp.163–67.
12 Henry Shue, ‘The Geography of Justice: Beitz’s Critique of Scepticism and Statism’, Ethics,
1982, vol. 92, 710–19.
13 Rengger, ‘Reading Charles Beitz’, p. 362.
14 Shue, ‘The Geography of Justice’, p. 712–13.
15 Brown, ‘The House that Chuck Built’, pp. 374–75.
16 Brown, ‘The House that Chuck Built’, p. 375.
17 Brown, ‘The House that Chuck Built’, p. 376.
18 For Beitz’s response to concerns about his characterization of realism, see Charles R. Beitz,
‘Reflections’, Review of International Studies, 2005, vol. 31, 409–23, at 410–11.
19 Beitz, ‘Reflections’, p. 412.
20 Michael Walzer, ‘The Moral Standing of States’, Philosophy & Public Affairs, 1980, vol. 9,
209–29; Terry Nardin, Law, Morality and the Relations of States, Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press, 1983; and Robert Jackson, The Global Covenant, Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 2000.
21 David Miller, ‘Defending Political Autonomy: A Discussion of Charles Beitz’, Review of
International Studies, 2005, vol. 31, 381–88.
22 Miller, ‘Defending Political Autonomy’, p. 385.
23 Brown, ‘The House that Chuck Built’, pp. 376–77.
24 Brown, Sovereignty, Rights and Justice, p. 171.
25 Tan, Justice Beyond Borders, Chapter 3.
26 Brian Barry, ‘Humanity and Justice in Global Perspective’, in J. Roland Pennock and John
W. Chapman (eds), Ethics, Economics and the Law of Property, Nomos 24, New York: New
York University Press, 1982, pp. 219–52. For counter-criticism of Barry, see Thomas Pogge,
Realizing Rawls, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1989, pp. 263–65.
27 John Rawls, The Law of Peoples: With ‘The Idea of Public Reason Revisited’, Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press, 1999, pp. 115–19.
28 It should be noted that Beitz’s argument does not rest on the view that natural resources are
the principal source of national wealth (p. 141). Rawls none the less appears to think that the
appeal of a resource redistribution principle is diminished if we accept the primacy of insti-
tutions and culture as sources of national wealth (Rawls, The Law of Peoples, p. 117).
29 Charles R. Beitz, ‘Rawls’s Law of Peoples’, Ethics, 2000, vol. 110, 669–96, at pp. 690–92.
30 The shift is influenced by David A. J. Richards ‘International Distributive Justice’, in J.
Roland Pennock and John W. Chapman (eds), Ethics, Economics and the Law of Property,
176 William Smith
pp. 275–99, at pp. 287–93. See Charles R. Beitz, ‘Cosmopolitan Ideals and National Senti-
ment’, Journal of Philosophy, 1983, vol. 80, 591–600, at p. 595.
31 Simon Caney, Justice Beyond Borders: A Global Political Theory, Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 2005; Pogge, Realizing Rawls; and Tan, Justice Without Borders.
32 Not all cosmopolitans follow Beitz in identifying global justice with Rawls’s principles of
justice (see e.g. Caney, Justice Beyond Borders). On this issue, see Charles R. Beitz, ‘Cosmo-
politanism and Global Justice’, Journal of Ethics, 2005, vol. 9, 11–27.
33 Beitz, ‘Reflections’, p. 423.
34 Erin Kelly, ‘Human Rights as Foreign Policy Imperatives’, in Deen K. Chatterjee (ed.), The
Ethics of Assistance: Morality and the Distant Needy, Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 2004, pp. 177–92.
35 Brown, ‘The House that Chuck Built’, pp. 371ff. The phrase, as Brown makes clear, draws a
parallel with Rawls’s influence on contemporary political theory, by reformulating the title of
A. S. Laden, ‘The House that Jack Built: Thirty Years of Reading Rawls’, Ethics, 2003, vol.
113, 367–90.
18 Obligations beyond the state: Andrew
Linklater’s Men and Citizens in the Theory
of International Relations
Richard Devetak and Juliette Gout1
The early 1980s saw the emergence of critical theories of international relations. A
small but significant number of scholars published work that challenged fundamental
premises of orthodox theories by reflecting on the relationship between knowledge and
values and championing the ideals of change and emancipation. Among the seminal
contributions to the development of critical theories of international relations are Cox’s
1981 Millennium article, Ashley’s 1981 International Studies Quarterly article, Walker’s
1981 Alternatives article, and Linklater’s 1982 Men and Citizens in the Theory of
International Relations (hereafter referred to as Men and Citizens).2 In addition to
using the term ‘critical theory’, these contributions sought to transform the discipline of
International Relations (IR) by setting out ambitious normative theory programmes
capable of challenging the intellectual hegemony of realism and liberalism and their
disavowal of normative political philosophy and philosophical history in favour of
more empirical and functional forms of ‘problem-solving’ theory.3
That, at least, is the conventional story told from the vantage point of the twenty-
first century.4 A similar story could be told of the way that Men and Citizens marked
the first instalment of a trilogy of books by the man who would become the Woodrow
Wilson Professor of Politics at Aberystwyth and the discipline’s leading proponent of
critical theory. While these narratives make sense as post facto reconstructions, they
neglect the actual intentions and motives behind these seminal contributions. In an
effort to understand and interpret the text’s meaning, this chapter begins by elucidating
the intentions and motives that led Linklater to write Men and Citizens. This will
require outlining the intellectual context to which Men and Citizens responded. The
chapter then provides a close reading of the book, highlighting its originality in for-
mulating a normative theory of international relations tailored to the recovery of uni-
versal ethical reasoning. In the third and final part, the chapter reflects on the reception
of Men and Citizens before trying to capture what makes the book a contemporary
classic of IR.
Notes
1 The authors would like to express their thanks to Andrew Linklater for his benevolent and
helpful comments on this chapter.
2 R. W. Cox, ‘Social Forces, States and World Orders: Beyond International Relations Theory’,
Millennium: Journal of International Studies, 1981, vol. 19, 126–55; Richard K. Ashley,
‘Political Realism and Human Interests’, International Studies Quarterly, 1981, vol. 25, 204–36;
R. B. J. Walker, ‘World Politics and Western Reason: Universalism, Pluralism, Hegemony’,
Alternatives, 1981, vol. 7, 195–227; and Andrew Linklater, Men and Citizens in the Theory of
International Relations, London: Macmillan, 1982. Page numbers placed in parentheses in the
text refer to this edition.
3 See Cox, ‘Social Forces, States and World Orders’.
4 See Nicholas Rengger and Ben Thirkell-White, ‘Editors’ Introduction’, special issue: Critical
International Relations Theory after 25 Years, Review of International Studies, 2007, vol. 33,
3–24, at p. 4; and Shannon Brincat, Laura Lima and João Nunes, ‘Introduction: The Life of
Critique’, in Shannon Brincat, Laura Lima and João Nunes (eds), Critical Theory in Inter-
national Relations and Security Studies, London: Routledge, 2011, pp. 1–11, at p. 5.
5 Hedley Bull, ‘Natural Law and International Relations’, British Journal of International Stu-
dies, 1979, vol. 5, 171–81, at p. 171.
Andrew Linklater: Men and Citizens in the Theory of International Relations 185
6 In the ‘Notes and References’ of Men and Citizens, see Chapter 2, footnote 44, p. 210 on
Marcuse; and Chapter 8, footnote 1, p. 218 on Habermas. Martin Jay’s The Dialectical Imagination:
A History of the Frankfurt School and the Institute of Social Research, 1923–1950 (Boston,
MA: Little Brown, 1973) remains the best account of the Frankfurt School.
7 Jürgen Habermas, Theory and Practice, trans. John Viertel, London: Heinemann, 1974, p. 42.
See Andrew Linklater, Beyond Realism and Marxism: Critical Theory and International
Relations, London: Macmillan, 1990; and Andrew Linklater, The Transformation of Political
Community: Ethical Foundations of the Post-Westphalian Era, Cambridge: Polity Press, 1998
for Linklater’s extended engagements with Frankfurt School Critical Theory and Habermas.
8 Michael Donelan, ‘Introduction’, in Michael Donelan (ed.), The Reason of States: A Study in
International Political Theory, London: George Allen and Unwin, 1978, p. 11.
9 Whether the writings of Pufendorf and Vattel are best classified as rationalist is not an issue
that need detain us here. Suffice to say that this is common to Kantian philosophical histories
which portray Kant’s philosophy as the culminating transcendence of the dialectic between
rationalism and empiricism. See Ian Hunter, Rival Enlightenments: Civil and Metaphysical
Philosophy in Early Modern Germany, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001.
10 On Vattel’s treatment of the balance of power, see Richard Devetak, ‘Law of Nations as
Reason of State: Diplomacy and the Balance of Power in Vattel’s Law of Nations’, Parergon,
2011, vol. 28, 105–28.
11 Richard K. Ashley, ‘Political Realism and Human Interest’; Cox, ‘Social Forces, States and
World Orders’; and John Maclean, ‘Political Theory, International Theory, and Problems of
Ideology’, Millennium: Journal of International Studies, 1981, vol. 10, 102–25.
12 For an account of the competing critical theory programs offered by Linklater and Cox, see
Richard Devetak, ‘Vico contra Kant: The Competing Critical Theories of Cox and Linkla-
ter’, in Brincat, Lima and Nunes, Critical Theory, pp. 115–26.
13 See also W. B. Gallie, ‘Wanted: A Philosophy of International Relations’, Political Studies,
1979, vol. 27, 484–92; and the chapter by William Smith in this volume.
14 More recently Walker has been at pains to distance himself from Linklater’s normative phi-
losophical history approach and its perceived universalism and hierarchicalism. See Walker,
‘The Hierarchicalization of Political Community’, Review of International Studies, 1999, vol.
25, 151–56; and the more obscure, R. B. J. Walker, After the Globe, Before the World,
London: Routledge, 2010, Chapter 3.
15 See R. B. J. Walker, Political Theory and the Transformation of World Politics, World Order
Studies Program, Occasional Paper No. 8, Center of International Studies, Princeton Uni-
versity, 1980, and ‘World Politics and Western Reason’.
16 Walker, Political Theory, p. 17.
17 Hedley Bull, The Anarchical Society: A Study of Order in World Politics, London: Macmil-
lan, 1977, p. 46.
18 Martin Wight, ‘Why Is There No International Theory?’, in Butterfield and Wight (eds),
Diplomatic Investigations: Essays in the Theory of International Politics, London: George
Allen and Unwin, 1966, p. 33.
19 R. B. J. Walker, Inside/Outside: International Relations as Political Theory, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1993.
20 A point noted by Hidemi Suganami, ‘Reflections on the Domestic Analogy: The Case of
Bull, Beitz and Linklater’, Review of International Studies, 1986, vol. 12, 145–58, at p. 152.
21 Andrew Linklater, Beyond Realism and Marxism: Critical Theory and International Relations,
London: Macmillan, 1990; Andrew Linklater, ‘The Problem of Community in International
Relations’, Alternatives, 1990, vol. 15, 135–53; and Andrew Linklater, The Transformation of
Political Community: Ethical Foundations of the Post-Westphalian Era, Cambridge: Polity
Press, 1998.
22 For a sample of the best interventions see Chris Brown, International Relations Theory: New
Normative Approaches, London: Harvester Wheatsheaf, 1992; Kimberly Hutchings, Interna-
tional Political Theory: Rethinking Ethics in a Global Era, London: Sage, 1999; Richard
Shapcott, Justice, Community, and Dialogue in International Relations, Cambridge: Cam-
bridge University Press, 2001; and Toni Erskine, Embedded Cosmopolitanism: Duties to
Strangers and Enemies in a World of ‘Dislocated Communities’, Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 2008.
186 Richard Devetak and Juliette Gout
23 See Andrew Linklater, ‘Realism, Marxism and Critical International Theory’, Review of
International Studies, 1986, vol. 12, 301–12; Linklater, Beyond Realism and Marxism; and
Andrew Linklater, ‘The Question of the Next Stage in International Relations Theory: A
Critical Theoretical Point of View’, Millennium: Journal of International Studies, 1992, vol.
21, 77–98; and Linklater, Transformation of Political Community.
24 This is how he puts it in a postscript to the second edition of Men and Citizens, London:
Macmillan, 1990, p. 209.
25 Linklater, Beyond Realism and Marxism, p. 164.
26 See Jim George, Discourses of Global Politics: A Critical (Re)Introduction to International
Relations, Boulder, CO: Lynne Rienner, 1994; Brooke Ackerly, ‘Uncritical Theory’, in Brin-
cat, Lima and Nunes, Critical Theory, pp. 140–49; and Jacqui True, ‘What Is Critical about
Critical Theory Revisited? The Case of Four International Relations Scholars and Gender’, in
Brincat, Lima and Nunes, Critical Theory, pp. 150–58
27 Christian Reus-Smit, The Moral Purpose of the State: Culture, Social Identity, and Institu-
tional Rationality in International Relations, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1999,
pp. 168–69.
28 Moorhead Wright, ‘Central but Ambiguous: States and International Theory’, Review of
International Studies, 1984, vol. 10, 233–37, at p. 235.
29 Beate Jahn, ‘One Step Forward, Two Steps Back: Critical Theory as the Latest Edition of
Liberal Idealism’, Millennium: Journal of International Studies, 1998, vol. 27, 613–41.
30 Jahn, ‘One Step Forward, Two Steps Back’, pp. 632–33. For a more sophisticated theoretical
critique of philosophical history, see Barry Hindess, ‘The Past Is Another Country’, Interna-
tional Political Sociology, 2007, vol. 1, 325–38.
31 Although Randall Schweller uses this phrase to describe Transformation of Political Com-
munity, there is no reason to believe that he would not also use it to describe Men and Citi-
zens. See ‘Fantasy Theory’, Review of International Studies, 1999, vol. 25, 147–50.
19 The making of IR/IPE: Robert W. Cox’s
Production, Power and World Order
Randall Germain1
The work of Robert W. Cox is indelibly associated with the fields of critical Interna-
tional Relations (IR) theory and International Political Economy (IPE). He was the
first to use the term neorealism in 1981, in an article that yielded two other phrases
now synonymous with his writings: ‘theory is always for someone and for some purpose’;
and the distinction between critical theory and problem-solving theory.2 A subsequent
article published in the same journal two years later introduced an entire generation of
scholars to the work of the Italian Marxist theoretician Antonio Gramsci, providing a
rich set of concepts for the study of IPE, including a reworked understanding of the
term ‘hegemony’ along with the ideas of ‘passive revolution’ and ‘historic bloc’.3 The
framework of historical structures, elaborated most completely in his landmark pub-
lication Production, Power and World Order (PPWO), has similarly inspired scholars
to range widely over the changing anatomy of world order.4 These seminal contribu-
tions persuaded Benjamin Cohen to include Cox as one of the ‘Magnificent Seven’
group of scholars who helped to usher in the modern rebirth of IPE.5
The principal animating force behind Cox’s scholarship is an abiding concern to
understand the changing modalities of global or world order. From his earliest writings
on executive leadership in international organizations through to his mid-career interest
in the material and ideational underpinnings of US hegemony to his late career fasci-
nation with intersubjective and civilizational mentalitiés,6 the question of how to
understand world order and its elements or layers forms the bedrock of his investiga-
tions.7 It is the problematic of world order that runs as a singular unifying theme
through his work, with each successive phase adding a new but interrelated aspect to
his investigations. Indeed, one can see in this problematic an enduring coherence that
simply uses different vantage points for its exploration. Within this context, PPWO
occupies what is perhaps a unique Archimedean point, both looking back to his formal
international organization phase while at the same time also suggestively pointing
towards his later interest in civilizations.
While PPWO is considered to be a classic text within the field of IPE, its status as a
classic text within IR might be viewed more ambiguously. After all, it does not rest its
methodological foundations on IR scholarship, preferring instead a modified and in
some ways extended Weberian formulation.8 Its ontological foundation is distinctly
historical materialist in its embrace of production and especially class as the key units
of organization and investigation. And its epistemological cues come from the tradition
of historicism as a mode of learning rather than from the standard tropes normally
associated with the social sciences as they have developed in the Western academy
(namely rationalism, positivism and recently philosophical realism).
188 Randall Germain
Nevertheless, the argument for including PPWO as a classic of IR is persuasive for
two reasons. First, its publication occurred at a seminal moment in the historiography
of IR, during the nexus of debates over the status of neorealism as a key approach to
IR theory and more empirically oriented questions about the continuation of US
dominance or hegemony. It should, thus, be included as one of a handful of texts which
defined a critical inflection point in the development of IR and IPE theory.9 Further-
more, unusually among this small number of texts, PPWO moves easily across dis-
ciplinary boundaries, providing students and scholars with a model of how scholarship
can usefully engage with multiple debates.
Second, and more importantly, PPWO stands as a testament to how historical
materialism as an approach to IR and IPE can usefully contribute to broader dis-
ciplinary debates. As a statement of this approach to IR and IPE, its coherence and
systematic completeness is unsurpassed, although not uncontested. It offers a suggestive
and sophisticated way to conceive of world order that encapsulates both the domestic
and global balance of social forces in political and economic terms. At the same time,
it recognizes that the impetus for these forces derives from fundamental social dynam-
ics associated with the way that power is generated and exercised through existing
institutional relationships, whether national or global. It also provides a useful way to
think about future possible trajectories of development. Indeed, its conclusions stand
up remarkably well even today. As I shall suggest below, its classic status thus rests on
the way that it innovates in the formulation of theory and how it integrates diverse
traditions of thought into its analysis.
Conclusion
In an essay written to commemorate an award given to Susan Strange, a long-time
friend and colleague, Cox wrote about how theorizing in academia tends to be organized
around a ‘groupie’ model where gatekeepers act to ensure the sanctity of theoretical
194 Randall Germain
developments and the acceptability of professionalization practices.27 By contrast the
‘loner’ model – which by implication he associated with Strange’s career – involved
neither the cultivation of groupies nor the stunted recounting of sacred debates, but
rather a proclivity to range widely over diverse material and a personal commitment to
intellectual integrity. Loners might influence one another and inadvertently on occasion
have groups form around them, but their vocation drives them to maintain their unique
vantage point through which to view the world. In some ways we might consider Cox
to be an exemplar of a ‘loner’, but one who nevertheless attracted considerable atten-
tion and who – inadvertently in some ways – found himself at the centre of several key
debates in a discipline into which he was neither trained nor professionalized.
PPWO is a classic text that lies at the centre of Cox’s intellectual status within the
disciplines of IR and IPE. By asking big picture questions about world order, and by
ranging widely in pursuit of historically relevant questions focused on change and
transformation, it provides us with a model of scholarship that focuses on enduring and
critical sets of complex social relationships. These relationships, the most important of
which are relations of class, state forms, interstate politics, intersubjectivity and pro-
duction, generate the basic parameters of our evolving social consciousness, which in
turn informs how we are able to respond collectively to the problems facing our com-
munities. Ultimately, for Cox as for the rest of us, responding to the pressures which the
global economy and its attendant structure of world order throw at us is among the
most important responsibilities facing scholars and citizens alike. The world may be a
seamless web of real, social relations, but for that very reason we need to range intel-
lectually as widely as we can in pursuit of the best kind of knowledge for this task. The
theoretical eclecticism and reliance on a historical mode of thought that lies at the
heart of PPWO provides a model through which we can pursue this knowledge, and for
this reason it deserves its status as a classic text of IR that will inspire future generations
of IR and IPE scholars.
Notes
1 I would like to thank Eric Helleiner for helpful comments on a previous draft.
2 Robert W. Cox, ‘Social Forces, States and World Orders: Beyond International Relations
Theory’, Millennium: Journal of International Studies, 1981, vol. 10, 126–55.
3 Robert W. Cox, ‘Gramsci, Hegemony, and International Relations: An Essay in Method’,
1983, Millennium: Journal of International Studies, 1983, vol. 12, 162–75.
4 Robert W. Cox, Production, Power and World Order: Social Forces in the Making of History,
New York: Columbia University Press, 1987. Page numbers placed in parentheses in the text
refer to this edition. This framework of historical structures was developed in close colla-
boration with Harold Jacobson, a lifelong collaborator and friend, and Jeffrey Harrod, Cox’s first
graduate student. See Robert W. Cox and Harold K. Jacobson, Anatomy of Influence, New
Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1972; Jeffrey Harrod, Power, Production, and the Unprotected
Worker, New York: Columbia University Press, 1987. The latter was written as a companion
volume to PPWO.
5 Benjamin J. Cohen, International Political Economy: An Intellectual History, Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press, 2008.
6 Cox took the term mentalitié from the ‘Annales’ school of French historians, who understood
it as the long-term and general mental frameworks which inform how people understand their
position in the world. See Fernand Braudel, ‘History and the Social Sciences: The Longue
Durée’, in Braudel, On History, trans. S. Matthews, London: Weidenfeld & Nicolson, 1980.
7 In addition to Anatomy of Influence and PPWO, see Cox, The Political Economy of a Plural
World: Critical Reflections on Power, Morals and Civilization, London: Routledge, 2002.
Robert W. Cox: Production, Power and World Order 195
8 See James H. Mittelman, ‘Coxian Historicism as an Alternative Perspective in International
Studies’, Alternatives, 1998, vol. 23, 63–92.
9 See also Kenneth Waltz, Theory of International Politics, Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley,
1979; Robert Keohane, After Hegemony, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1984;
Robert Gilpin, The Political Economy of International Relations, Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press, 1987; Susan Strange, States and Markets, London: Pinter, 1988.
10 See for example Brian Schmidt, The Political Discourse of Anarchy: A Disciplinary History of
International Relations, Albany, NY: State University of New York Press, 1998.
11 For an example of Cox’s historical approach to key concepts, see ‘Civil Society at the Turn of
the Millennium: Prospects for an Alternative World Order’, Review of International Studies,
1999, vol. 25, 3–28.
12 R. G. Collingwood, The Idea of History, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1946; E.P. Thompson, The
Poverty of Theory and Other Essays, London: Monthly Review Press, 1978. Cox also develops
his form of historical reasoning through a close reading of the work of the seventeenth-century
philologist Giambattista Vico. See Giambattista Vico, The New Science of Giambattista Vico,
trans. T. G. Bergin and M. H. Fisch, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, [1946] 1984. His
discussion of Vico can be found in Political Economy of a Plural World, Chapter 4.
13 Collingwood, Idea of History, p. 214.
14 Gramsci’s ideas had begun to be applied to understanding the neo-liberal turn in Western
Europe in the late 1970s and early 1980s, but almost exclusively in connection with individual
countries. For an overview see Michael Kenny, The First New Left: British Intellectuals after
Stalin, London: Lawrence & Wishart, 1995.
15 For an analysis of how this clash has developed, see Eric Helleiner and Stefano Pagliari,
‘Between the Storms: Patterns in Global Financial Governance’, in Geoffrey R. D. Underhill,
Jasper Blom and Daniel Mügge (eds), Global Financial Integration Thirty Years On: From
Reform to Crisis, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010, pp. 42–57; Randall Germain,
Global Politics and Financial Governance, Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2010.
16 Much of this work is the subject of Randall Germain and Michael Kenny, ‘Engaging Gramsci:
International Relations Theory and the “New” Gramscians’, Review of International Studies,
1998, vol. 24, 3–21.
17 See for example Randolph B. Persaud, Counter-Hegemony and Foreign Policy: The Dialectic
of Marginalized and Global Forces in Jamaica, Albany, NY: State University of New York
Press, 2001; William I. Robinson, A Theory of Global Capitalism: Production, Class and State
in a Transnational World, Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press, 2004; Adam D.
Morton, Unraveling Gramsci: Hegemony and Passive Revolution in the Global Political
Economy, London: Pluto Press, 2007.
18 See Timothy J. Sinclair, ‘Beyond International Relations Theory: Robert W. Cox and Approaches to
World Order,’ in Robert W. Cox with Timothy J. Sinclair, Approaches to World Order, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1996, pp. 3–18; Stephen R. Gill and James H. Mittelman (eds),
Innovation and Transformation in International Studies, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1997; Mittelman, ‘Coxian Historicism’; Michael G. Schechter, ‘Critiques of Coxian Theory:
Background to a Conversation,’ in Cox, Political Economy of a Plural World, pp. 1–25.
19 Schechter, ‘Critiques of Coxian Theory’, pp. 3–7.
20 Cohen, International Political Economy, pp. 84–87.
21 Cox, ‘Gramsci, Hegemony and International Relations’, pp. 171–72.
22 Susan Strange, ‘Preface’, in Susan Strange (ed.), Pathways to International Political Economy,
London: George, Allen & Unwin, 1984, p. ix.
23 Randall Germain, ‘Critical Political Economy, Historical Materialism and Adam Morton,’
Politics, 2007, vol. 27, 127–31, at p. 128.
24 Collingwood, Idea of History; Vico, New Science; Georges Sorel, Reflections on Violence,
trans. T. E. Hulme, New York: Peter Smith, [1906] 1941; Fernand Braudel, Civilization and
Capitalism, 15th to 18th Centuries, Volume 3: The Perspective of the World, trans., Sian
Reynolds, London: Collins/Fontana, [1979] 1984.
25 The specificity of such an ethos is illustrated in an earlier publication that examines how a
seemingly minor internal conflict over labour control and organization within states actually
marked a significant structural shift in world order. Robert W. Cox, ‘Labor and Hegemony’,
International Organization, 1977, vol. 31, 385–424.
196 Randall Germain
26 For another example see Robert W. Cox, ‘Towards a Post-Hegemonic Conception of World
Order: Reflections on the Relevancy of Ibn Khaldun,’ in James N. Rosenau and Ernst-Otto
Czempiel (eds), Governance Without Government: Order and Change in World Politics,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992, pp. 132–59.
27 Robert W. Cox, ‘Take Six Eggs: Theory, Finance and the Real Economy in the Work of
Susan Strange,’ in Cox, Approaches to World Order, 1996, pp. 174–88.
20 Gendering geopolitics, gendering IR:
Cynthia Enloe’s Bananas, Beaches
and Bases
Alexandra Hyde and Marsha Henry1
Bananas, Beaches and Bases2 was first published in 1989, towards the end of the Cold
War and the beginning of feminism’s engagement with International Relations (IR).
The book has gained iconic status and, with subsequent works on related themes,3
Enloe has achieved broad recognition as a key contributor to both feminism and IR
scholarship. A critical appraisal of Bananas, Beaches and Bases therefore has to deal
with its ambiguous position in and between the discipline of IR and the field of Gender
or Women’s Studies. Arguably any work that seeks to expose gaps in ‘traditional’ dis-
ciplines risks a very partial kind of success – appreciated somewhat selectively, as an
intriguing curiosity perhaps, but rarely absorbed into the established ‘canon’. It is
encouraging then that Bananas, Beaches and Bases has made it through to this collec-
tion of classics in IR. Like other outliers such as Virginia Woolf ’s Three Guineas4 and
Stanley Kubrick’s Dr. Strangelove,5 Bananas, Beaches and Bases intervenes in IR by
means of a different form and field of representation. More than 20 years after pub-
lication it is still original and unruly enough not to be ignored, while Enloe herself
remains a scholar who persistently uses a non-academic arsenal to challenge IR scho-
larship from within. What is striking from the start is the breadth of the book’s register,
its accessibility of tone and above all the wit with which Enloe sets out her argument
and in so doing, the stealth by which she intercepts and plays upon our preconceptions
and expectations – of IR, of feminism, and of the world around us. In such ways,
Bananas, Beaches and Bases is not simply about showing an alternative view of inter-
national relations. Drawing from feminist theory and practice, Enloe’s work requires its
readers not only to see but to think in new ways: with the situatedness of their knowledge
rather than the illusion of objectivity; with a reflexive sense of familiarity that throws
what is unfamiliar, because hidden, into relief; or to think at the intersection of multi-
ple, analytical categories such as gender, race and sexuality rather than taking a single,
linear approach. As such, Bananas, Beaches and Bases is a kind of collage that cuts up
the neatly delineated, ethnocentric fabric of IR and brings these monotone pieces
together with fragments from political and cultural reality as it is lived and experi-
enced, embodied or enacted by different people around the world. Assembled together
in this way, Enloe is able to reveal new and surprising angles from which international
relations might be understood and conceptualized.
Enloe’s demonstrative combination of the everyday and the international is key to
the impact and originality of Bananas, Beaches and Bases. Yet the same juxtaposition
of macro-level geopolitics and micro-level gender relations is also what renders it sus-
ceptible to being discounted as ‘proper’ IR. It is true that Bananas, Beaches and Bases
does not engage explicitly on an epistemological level with much of the classic
198 Alexandra Hyde and Marsha Henry
theoretical work featured in this volume, for example. Critics have agreed that Bananas,
Beaches and Bases and other works in Enloe’s inimitable style might challenge an
academic audience to take them seriously.6 As such, Enloe’s recalibration of international
relations to take account of what is personal as well as political (to use an old-fash-
ioned phrase more current at the time when Bananas, Beaches and Bases was published
than it is now) comes with the occupational hazard of being ‘easy to trivialize’.7 However,
what Enloe qualifies as the ‘desire to trivialize’8 her work within the discipline of IR, is
still an important factor in assessing whether or not the book will endure as a classic. Enloe
announces her intervention into IR by asking ‘Where are the women?’ (pp. 7, 200). It is
a simple question, and one to which Enloe has more or less adhered in many of her
subsequent monographs.9 However, surely the fact that this question still needs to be
asked shows that gender as a mode of analysis has not been fully absorbed as a
common denominator across IR research? How far has feminist IR come in its adaptation of
Enloe’s question into a suitably sharp and nuanced tool that can be incorporated into
the analytical machinery of IR as a whole? If the same question is still being asked,
then perhaps Enloe’s ultimate aim in Bananas, Beaches and Bases might be argued to
have failed. Nevertheless, feminist IR has developed at a steady rate over the past 30
years, at the same time adopting a more reflexive assessment of its own status within IR.10
As will be discussed in the second half of this chapter, an appraisal of Bananas, Beaches
and Bases as an IR classic must not only consider how far feminist IR has come, but how far
it still has to go. First, however, this chapter aims to provide some textual insights into
Enloe’s approach in Bananas, Beaches and Bases, considering both its critical reception,
and some of the ways in which it opened the door for a deeper investigation of the central
tenets of IR. We then consider some of the ways in which feminist IR has measured its
own impact in terms of integrating gender analysis alongside other ‘turns’ in critical
theory, before considering the contemporary relevance of Bananas, Beaches and Bases
and its potential to endure as a classic of both gender studies and IR.
As one learns to look at the world through feminist eyes, one learns to ask whether
anything that passes for inevitable, inherent, ‘traditional’ or biological has in fact
been made. One begins to ask how all sorts of things have been made – a treeless
landscape, a rifle-wielding police force, the ‘Irishman joke’, an all-woman typing
pool. Asking how something has been made implies that it has been made by
someone. Suddenly there are clues to trace; there is also blame, credit and respon-
sibility to apportion, not just at the start but at each point along the way (p. 3).
In other words, the different symbolic and social values that are attached to particular
identities, relations and experiences, play a direct role in determining the material and
economic conditions of people’s lives. Enloe calls attention to what she argues is the
expressly political power of factors traditionally beyond the scope of IR. These are
slippery concepts that are not only hard to define, but constantly conceal their own
effects: ‘Ignoring women on the landscape of international politics perpetuates the
notion that certain power relations are merely a matter of taste and culture’ (p. 3).
Bananas, Beaches and Bases sets out to demonstrate that suffused throughout inter-
national relations are a host of ‘cultural’ ideas pertaining to men and women that give
meaning, order and expression to the experience of social reality. Taking the example
of the tourist industry, Enloe draws attention to the ways in which flight attendants and
chambermaids provide sexualized services that are propagated by ideas about femi-
ninity. ‘Femininity’ can be sexualized when uniformed in an obligatory skirt or more
prosaically, housekeeping can be feminized as ‘natural’ and therefore unskilled labour
for women, which allows multinational hotel firms to pay their local female workforce
less (p. 34). Somewhere along this continuum of ideas about gender, labour and tourism,
Enloe plots the migration of workers from rural areas to coastal towns or cities (p. 86)
where over time, particular jobs and roles become associated with different ethnic
identities. Next, she introduces the use of some of these same towns for ‘R&R’ by US
soldiers on leave (p. 36). By this point, the growth of sex tourism appears anything but
anomalous and the social, economic and cultural assumptions that go with it are
revealed as simply another ‘strand of the gendered tourism industry’ (ibid.). The flip-
side of ‘culture’ then is that this seemingly benign, catchall concept can be used to
whitewash the role of gender in international politics by turning it into something that
is just natural, like the apparent libido of US marines or the apparent sexual availability
of Thai women, for example. Further linking tourism, masculinity and femininity to
Cynthia Enloe: Bananas, Beaches and Bases 201
the construction of national identity, Enloe argues that ‘[i]f a state is a vertical creature
of authority, a nation is a horizontal creature of identity’ (p. 46). But which nationalist
movement appropriates the oppressed chambermaid as its political symbol? None, it
turns out. Enloe wagers that the figure of the chambermaid is far less compelling as a
symbol of the corrosion of national identity than for example, the men at the core of
Caribbean nationalist movements who have been emasculated and transformed into a
‘nation of busboys’ working in white resorts (p. 34). There has been no gendered
reduction of power, no ‘unnatural’ reversal of roles in the transformation of thousands
of women into housekeepers: ‘after all, a woman who has traded work as an unpaid
agricultural worker for work as a hotel cleaner hasn’t lost any of her femininity’ (p. 36).
Only when idealized forms of femininity are compromised, however, do women finally
make it through as agents of national identity, and only then to be rescued like the
figure of the female sex worker, or protected like the figure of the veiled Muslim
woman (p. 42).
Rather than focusing on nation states as unitary actors within the international
political system, Bananas, Beaches and Bases is comprised of a vast range of empirical
snapshots, interconnected in ways that confound or decentre the analytic and geo-
graphical boundaries of IR. Enloe’s internationalist methodology draws on feminist
standpoint theory in its accommodation of a range of different – and global – per-
spectives from which social reality might be understood and experienced.11 Feminist
standpoint theory12 recognizes that knowledge (and therefore power) is situated in the
particular context of its production, be that a question or combination of academic
disciplines, free market economics, social relations, geographical locations or political
representation. Enloe’s contribution is to point out that conceptualizing international
relations as a vertical set of top-down transactions obscures the kinds of knowledge
and power that are negotiated at the margins. In other words, that it is often at the
opposite end of the scale to macro-level forms of knowledge and power that international
relations reach their material apotheosis. In Bananas, Beaches and Bases, the global
economic market for consumer goods such as designer jeans (p. 151) is examined in
terms of local conditions of production in factories in South Korea (p. 168) or Mexico
(p. 169). More recently, feminist scholars such as V. Spike Peterson and Penny Griffin
have provided valuable schemata for the relationship between gender and international
political economy.13 At the time that Bananas, Beaches and Bases was published (and
in her earlier work with Wendy Chapkis14), Enloe and other feminist scholars were
primarily concerned with making visible the role of women’s labour in ‘the new indus-
trial map of the world’.15 By focusing on the empirical effects of macroeconomics on a
micro scale, Enloe opened the door for IR to take seriously a much broader range of
power relations with respect to shifts in the international division of labour and the
‘feminization’ (p. 176) of particular kinds of employment. Importantly, Enloe’s for-
mulation of such power relations includes women’s organizing both locally (p. 170) and
transnationally (p. 173), providing a more nuanced view of women’s role in a country’s
development and their empowerment through wage labour and political consciousness
(p. 175). At the same time, Enloe’s attention to the material and experiential margins of
IR goes much deeper than the positivist/rationalist16 proposition of simply ‘adding’
women to the economic equation. If in Bananas, Beaches and Bases, Enloe chooses to
focus as much on the role of symbolic and cultural capital in shaping material and
social reality, it is because her constructivist critique of IR is concerned not only with
the ways in which women’s labour is exploited, but also the social and cultural
202 Alexandra Hyde and Marsha Henry
conditions by which women’s labour comes to be exploitable. As such, her focus on the
effects of macroeconomics yields considerable insight into their micro-level causes.
Incidentally, this includes the tendency of feminist scholars in the West to ‘collapse all
women in Third World countries into a single homogenous category’ (p. 175), or the
contradictory case of the ‘feminist domestic employer’ (p. 179). What Enloe is at pains
to point out by writing against or outside traditional ideas about productive labour, is
precisely what more conventional IR perspectives obscure: namely the gendered,
racialized or class-based structures of knowledge and power that underpin interna-
tional divisions of labour and the value attached to them. However, while alert to the
multiple political economies arising from and within the formal structure of nation
states, Enloe pays less attention to the shadow economies that operate to disrupt the
existence – and the conceptualization – of a single international political system. Here
Bananas, Beaches and Bases is out-paced by more recent work on phenomena such as
‘global care chains’,17 which accounts for gender within processes of globalization by
highlighting the counter-systems that are generated by informal or illegal markets such
as human trafficking, for example. Enloe is interested in patriarchy as a structure of
oppression and does much to illustrate its cooperation with global and local patterns of
class and ethnicity (p. 186). At the same time, however, her emphasis on the social,
cultural and collective dynamics of international relations leaves the role of individual
agency unexplored. It is not as if Bananas, Beaches and Bases is not vividly populated by
real-life politics. Rather, to fully deconstruct the superstructure of the international
system requires insight into how these relations are renegotiated or resisted on an
individual or subjective level. Bananas, Beaches and Bases was not ahead of its time in all
respects perhaps, but as we explore below no book can be all things to all people in
relation to feminism and IR.
Although Enloe’s ideas about gender, power and culture can be traced back to fem-
inist standpoint and postmodern constructivism,18 she does not offer a comprehensive
account of the mechanics of these ideas, nor their epistemological foundations. Conse-
quently the parameters of gender power – as either distinct from or mutually con-
stituted by other forms of power – can appear undefined, lending gender a singularity
and centricity that is sometimes at odds with the intersectional nature of oppression
that Enloe is keen to emphasize in other parts of the book. One might argue that
without unpicking the epistemological foundations of IR as a discipline, it is not pos-
sible to incorporate the threads of gender analysis in the comprehensive way that Enloe
claims is necessary. At the same time, the question as to whether or not a work of IR
scholarship must be founded upon or produce broad cross-cutting theories as a pre-
condition of its relevance and applicability to a broad, cross-cutting discipline is per-
haps the very point in question. Animated as it is by something of the activist’s zeal as
opposed to the academic’s constant qualification, Bananas, Beaches and Bases chal-
lenges disciplinary boundaries in form as well as content. In this sense, it remains a
breakthrough work: forthright, occasionally blunt and heavy-handed, but as its inclu-
sion in this volume attests, undoubtedly effective in clearing a space so that other
questions – more systematic and nuanced perhaps – can begin to be asked. Enloe her-
self has acknowledged that following the question ‘Where are the women?’ (pp. 7, 200),
come others such as ‘why are they there, who got them there, and what happens to your
understanding of the people you have already painted in once you see them there?’19
Feminist IR is rooted at least partially in a critical tradition that views IR as con-
structed from a Western, masculinist perspective, its production of knowledge a
Cynthia Enloe: Bananas, Beaches and Bases 203
historical instrument of domination and control over global political and economic
systems.20 Enloe does not disavow the need for ‘explanatory generalization that is
above the particular’,21 but insists that theory is inevitably tested in reality: ‘My kind of
theorizing constantly goes back and forth between general and particular because I
want to actually test my theories on the page with the reader’.22 There can be no doubt
that the accessibility of Bananas, Beaches and Bases has helped it to reach a great many
readers, with the book a common fixture of reading lists at both undergraduate and
graduate level, published in its second edition with a new preface by the author in
2000. The paradox of Bananas, Beaches and Bases and its potential stumbling block
within the ‘serious’ discipline of IR, however, is that both its content and its accessible
style are rooted in another core principle of feminist research – the importance of
considering ‘the everyday’. In other words, at the same time as Bananas, Beaches and
Bases challenges what counts as international relations, it also challenges what might
count as IR epistemology.
(Inter)disciplinary tensions
To the extent that any ‘classic’ gains its status as a placeholder for a particular school of
thought or approach, it is necessary to go beyond the individual factors that make
Bananas, Beaches and Bases relevant to both feminism and IR, and consider more
carefully some of the disciplinary tensions it provokes. Bananas, Beaches and Bases
takes its place alongside Jean Bethke Elshtain’s Women and War23 and J. Ann Tick-
ner’s Gender in International Relations to form a kind of holy trinity, canonized by
ensuing scholarship24 as the first wave of feminist IR. Enloe, Tickner, Elshtain and
others25 take up individual and sometimes overlapping positions from across a range of
theoretical and disciplinary approaches, from standpoint theory to discourse analysis
and peace studies. Since then, and perhaps inevitably for a theoretical tradition that
promotes a reflexive assessment of its own production of knowledge, feminist IR has
also turned its attention inwards, assessing its own origins and complicity with the
Western historical and intellectual traditions that were the very same foundations for
disciplines such as IR. Gender studies and its purpose or impact with regards to IR
continues to be debated by scholars.26 Even the necessity for anything called ‘feminist
IR’ has been argued to expose the failure of gender theory to reach its potential as a
common analytical category across the field as a whole.27 However, the inter-
disciplinary world of feminist scholarship is itself far from coherent, marked as Kim-
berley Hutchings has put it, by the ‘contrast and continuity’ that results from multiple
approaches combined under one banner.28 More recently, Marysia Zalewski has ques-
tioned the helpfulness of tidying up feminism to take on such institutional behemoths
as IR.29 She presents a scenario where in order to ‘undo’ IR, feminism is forced to
deny the productive tensions that result from its interdisciplinarity, tying up its loose
ends to take on the solid mass of IR as a coherent discipline.30 It is significant then that
Enloe refused the temptation to streamline her investigations in order to produce a
generalizable pattern or theory through which gender as a category of analysis might
achieve ‘universal’ applicability – and Bananas, Beaches and Bases a kind of universal
acceptance.
The push for disciplinary coherence within feminist IR also derives from a feminist
politics that seeks a social, transformative role for the knowledge it produces.31 Indeed,
if Bananas, Beaches and Bases is a ‘classic’ feminist text in any sense, it would qualify
204 Alexandra Hyde and Marsha Henry
solely on the basis of the explicit link that Enloe draws between feminist theory and
praxis, analysis and activism, and social change. Enloe is interested in the differences
between and among women, for example the differences in race, class and sexuality
between women serving in, married to or protesting against military institutions (p. 65).
Her ultimate aim is to demonstrate how the relations between women are structured
according to social orders of distinction that are co-opted in the interests of military
effectiveness, for example (p. 92) and to the detriment of women’s collective (and
transnational) political potential:
Enloe’s considerable ambitions for feminist activism might not be best suited to the
field of IR, where Adam Jones has argued that32 ‘the recognition of the importance
and politicized nature of the domestic realm does not automatically lead to a particular
set of prescriptions for conducting politics within or among states’33 Neo-feminist
scholars also highlight the failure of feminism to provide a gender analysis that is broad
enough to accommodate the relative oppressions not just between different women, but
between different women and different men. According to this viewpoint, the classical
feminist canon is outdated in only taking women’s lives as its starting point: ‘Attention
to the large mass of ordinary men in international society is not absent in Enloe’s work
(as it is in most feminist writing); but it seems disconcertingly permeated by the male-
as-power-broker stereotype.’34 An increasing attention to men and masculinities has
emerged in gender studies in recent years, with the work of theorists such as R. W.
Connell35 informing debates on the role of gender within military institutions, for
example.36 Jones’ own solution, however, is to devote his analysis to ‘concrete’ matters
and ‘real-world issues’, rather than a ‘more abstract investigation into the construction
of gender, the continuum of gender identities, and so on’ (emphasis added).37 He calls
for more examples, statistics and comparisons by ‘strictly quantitative measure’ that
will ‘outweigh the female-grounded examples’38 given by scholars such as Enloe.
However, stereotypes are not defeated simply by being outnumbered, they must first be
recognized for what they are: cultural constructions, produced and perpetuated, Enloe
would argue, by a strategic politics of representation (and yes, perhaps on occasion, by
feminist politics of representation). Counter-examples alone cannot negate the persis-
tence of particular stereotypes. This is only half the battle, and only a fraction of what
Enloe does in Bananas, Beaches and Bases. The achievement of Enloe’s approach is not
only to show what social, cultural and political forms gender takes, but also to show
how those constructions are made and how they are used. Contrary to Jones’ criticism,
Enloe’s point is that the construction of gender is a concrete matter and that gender
ideology contributes to the sharp end of social reality.
Cynthia Enloe: Bananas, Beaches and Bases 205
Conclusion
Enloe’s question: ‘Where are the women?’ (pp. 7, 200) has perhaps become an unfa-
shionable proposition during the transition in scholarship from feminist or women’s
studies to a range of disciplines with the prefix ‘Gender and … ’. But Bananas, Beaches
and Bases is not only about the impact of international relations upon women, or the
impact of women upon international relations. Enloe takes feminism’s deep-rooted
concern with the production of knowledge and questions the very process by which IR
as a discipline draws the boundaries of what counts as IR. She does this not only by
revealing the places where gender matters, but also by critiquing the gendered ways in
which our knowledge about international relations is produced.39 Enloe’s focus on the
constructedness of things, the way things are made and indeed, made to appear, would
seem to limit her analysis to a solely descriptive rather than a prescriptive role,
neglecting a ‘radical redefinition of what actually constitutes “power”’.40 However, in
reassessing the scripts, codes, modes and boundaries of this power, Bananas, Beaches
and Bases sets a clear and unequivocal mandate for a reconfiguration of IR and its
methodology. Enloe reveals that the mechanics of IR work together in a precise way,
the direction of one part being dependent on the reversal of another, so that on the face
of it the world keeps turning as before. What Enloe brings to the classical canon of IR
is the question of what international power is, if it is not constituted by its application.
One way of responding to this question is to seek to understand the profoundly gendered
and material ways in which power is exercised and experienced.
Notes
1 We are grateful to Cynthia Enloe for generous feedback on several key aspects of this chapter.
2 Cynthia Enloe, Bananas, Beaches and Bases: Making Feminist Sense of International Politics,
London: Pandora, 2000. Page numbers placed in parentheses in the text refer to this edition.
3 Including: Enloe, Maneuvers: The International Politics of Militarizing Women’s Lives, Berkeley,
CA: University of California Press, 2000; The Morning After: Sexual Politics at the End of
the Cold War, Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, 1993.
4 Virginia Woolf, Three Guineas, London: Hogarth Press, 1938.
5 Dr. Strangelove or: How I Learned to Stop Worrying and Love the Bomb, directed by Stanley
Kubrick, 95 min., Columbia Pictures and Hawk Films, 1964.
6 Cristine Sylvester, Feminist International Relations: An Unfinished Journey, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2001, p. 32; Judith Stiehm, ‘Book Review: Cynthia Enloe,
Maneuvers’, Millennium: Journal of International Studies, 2000, vol. 29, 489–92.
7 Cynthia Enloe and Marysia Zalewski, ‘Feminist Theorizing from Bananas to Maneuvers’
International Feminist Journal of Politics, 2001, vol. 1, 138–47, at p. 139.
8 Enloe and Zalewski, ‘Feminist Theorizing from Bananas to Maneuvers’, p. 139.
9 Other selected works include Enloe, Nimo’s War, Emma’s War: Making Feminist Sense of the
Iraq War, Berkley, CA: University of California Press, 2010; Enloe, Globalization and Mili-
tarism: Feminists Make the Link, Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, 2007; Enloe, The
Curious Feminist: Searching for Women in The New Age of Empire, Berkeley, CA and
London: University of California Press, 2004.
10 Kimberley Hutchings, ‘1988 and 1998: Contrast and Continuity in Feminist International
Relations’, Millennium: Journal of International Studies, 2008, vol. 37, 97–106.
11 Kimberley Hutchings, ‘The Personal is International: Feminist Epistemology and the Case of
International Relations’, in Kathleen Lennon & Margaret Whitford (eds), Knowing the Dif-
ference: Feminist Perspectives in Epistemology, London: Routledge, 1994, p. 155.
12 Key contributions to feminist standpoint theory include Sandra Harding, Whose Science/
Whose Knowledge?, Milton Keynes: Open University Press, 1991; Sandra Harding,
‘Rethinking Standpoint Epistemology: What is Strong Objectivity?’, in Linda Alcoff and
206 Alexandra Hyde and Marsha Henry
Elizabeth Potter (eds), Feminist Epistemologies, New York and London: Routledge, 1993;
Sandra Harding (ed.), The Feminist Standpoint Theory Reader, New York and London:
Routledge, 2004; Donna Haraway, ‘Situated Knowledges’, in Harding, Feminist Standpoint
Theory Reader, pp. 81–102; Nancy Hartsock, ‘The Feminist Standpoint: Developing the
Ground for a Specifically Feminist Historical Materialism’, in Harding, Feminist Standpoint
Theory Reader, pp. 35–54; Patricia Hill Collins, Black Feminist Thought: Knowledge, Con-
sciousness and the Politics of Empowerment, New York and London: Routledge, 1990; Patri-
cia Hill Collins, ‘Learning from the Outsider Within: The Sociological Significance of Black
Feminist Thought’, in Harding, Feminist Standpoint Theory Reader, pp. 103–26; Dorothy
Smith, ‘Women’s Perspective as a Radical Critique of Sociology’, in Harding, Feminist
Standpoint Theory Reader, pp. 21–34.
13 V. Spike Peterson, ‘How (the Meaning of) Gender Matters in Political Economy’, New Poli-
tical Economy, 2005, vol. 10, 499–521; Penny Griffin, ‘Refashioning IPE: What and How
Gender Analysis Teaches International (Global) Political Economy’, in Review of Interna-
tional Political Economy, 2007, vol. 14, 719–36.
14 Wendy Chapkis and Cynthia Enloe, Of Common Cloth: Women in the Global Textile
Industry, Washington, DC: Transnational Institute, 1983.
15 Ruth Pearson, ‘Nimble Fingers Revisited: Reflections on Women and Third World Indus-
trialisation in the Late Twentieth Century’, in Cecile Jackson and Ruth Pearson (eds), Fem-
inist Visions of Development, Gender Analysis and Policy, Oxford and New York: Routledge,
1998, pp. 171–88, at p. 171.
16 For a comprehensive discussion of these and other epistemological approaches within IPE see
Peterson, ‘How (the Meaning of) Gender Matters’, p. 502.
17 Rhacel Parrenas, Servants of Globalization: Women, Migration, and Domestic Work, Stan-
ford, CA: Stanford University Press, 2001.
18 Sylvester, Feminist International Relations, p. 8.
19 Enloe and Zalewski, ‘Feminist Theorizing’, p. 138.
20 J. Ann Tickner, Gender in International Relations: Feminist Perspectives on Achieving Global
Security, New York: Columbia University Press, 1992, p. ix.
21 Enloe and Zalewski, ‘Feminist Theorizing’, p. 141.
22 Enloe and Zalewski, ‘Feminist Theorizing’, p. 6.
23 Jean Bethke Elshtain, Women and War, Brighton: Harvester Press, 1987.
24 Sylvester, Feminist International Relations, p. 18.
25 See, for example, Carol Cohn, ‘Sex and Death in the Rational World of Defense Intellec-
tuals’, Signs, 1987, vol. 12, 687–718; Sarah Ruddick, Maternal Thinking: Towards A Politics
of Peace, Boston: Beacon Press, 1989; Jan Jindy Pettman, Worlding Women: A Feminist
International Politics, Sydney: Allen & Unwin, 1996.
26 Selected examples include Robert O. Keohane, ‘International Relations Theory: Contribu-
tions of a Feminist Standpoint’, in Rebecca Grant and Kathleen Newland (eds), Gender
and International Relations, Milton Keynes: Open University Press, 1991, pp. 41–51; J.
Ann Tickner, ‘You Just Don’t Understand: Troubled Engagements between Feminists and
IR Theorists’, International Studies Quarterly, 1997, vol. 41, 611–32; and Gillian Youngs,
‘Feminist International Relations: A Contradiction in Terms? Or: Why Women and
Gender Are Essential to Understanding the World “We” Live In’, International Affairs,
2004, vol. 80, 75–87.
27 Youngs, ‘Feminist International Relations’, p. 76.
28 Hutchings, ‘1988 and 1998’, p. 97.
29 Marysia Zalewski, ‘Do We Understand Each Other Yet? Troubling Feminist Encounters
With(in) International Relations’, The British Journal of Politics and International Relations,
2007, vol. 9, 302–12.
30 Zalewski, ‘Do We Understand Each Other Yet?’, p. 305.
31 Zalewski, ‘Do We Understand Each Other Yet?’, p. 305.
32 Adam Jones, ‘Does “Gender” Make the World Go Round? Feminist Critiques of Interna-
tional Relations’, Review of International Studies, 1996, vol. 22, 405–29.
33 Jones, ‘Does “Gender” Make the World Go Round?’, p. 412.
34 Jones, ‘Does “Gender” Make the World Go Round?’, p. 421.
35 R. W. Connell, Masculinities, Cambridge: Polity Press, 1995.
Cynthia Enloe: Bananas, Beaches and Bases 207
36 Paul Higate (ed.), Military Masculinities: Identity and the State, Westport, CT: Praeger, 2003.
37 Jones, ‘Does “Gender” Make the World Go Round?’, p. 424.
38 Jones, ‘Does “Gender” Make the World Go Round?’, p. 424.
39 Tickner, Gender in International Relations, p. 129.
40 Jones, ‘Does “Gender” Make the World Go Round?’, p. 414.
21 The limits of international relations: R. B. J.
Walker’s Inside/outside: International
Relations as Political Theory
Tom Lundborg and Nick Vaughan-Williams1
Theories of international relations, I will argue, are interesting less for the sub-
stantive explanations they offer about political conditions in the modern world
than as expressions of the limits of the contemporary political imagination when
confronted with persistent claims about and evidence of fundamental historical and
structural transformation (p. 5).
Despite seemingly endless evidence that major historical and structural transformations
are under way, it is still in relation to the distinction between inside and outside that
claims regarding the political significance of such transformations gain legitimacy.
They become ‘legitimate’ in the sense of not being automatically ruled out as naïve,
utopian or unable to accept some of the so-called eternal wisdoms that realist IR is
said to offer. In this sense it also becomes extremely difficult to offer any alternative
solutions to the puzzle of universalism and particularism – solutions based for example
on ideas about a ‘world politics’, a ‘universalist ethics’ or a ‘common humanity’. If
such ideas are to be taken seriously they must first recognize the inside/outside dis-
tinction as a ‘natural’ starting point upon which their ideas are formulated. Hence, they
must also come to terms with the limits of their own possibility to move beyond the
spatial order of sovereign states.
The history of political thought turns into an ahistorical repetition in which the
struggles of these thinkers to make sense of the historical transformations in which
they were caught are erased in favour of assertions about how they all articulate
essential truths about the same unchanging and usually tragic reality: the eternal
game of relations between states (p. 92).
Conclusion
In many ways the subtitle International Relations as Political Theory holds the key to
understanding the main thesis of Inside/outside. ‘International Relations’, Walker
216 Tom Lundborg and Nick Vaughan-Williams
argues, cannot be understood as a separate discipline, which is somehow divorced from
‘Political Theory’. Rather, IR is inextricably linked to Political Theory, in ways that
make them inseparable from the same political imaginary of modernity. Following this
imaginary there can be no ‘International Relations’ without ‘Political Theory’ and vice
versa; each ‘discipline’ relies upon something that lies outside its own disciplinary
boundaries, something that supposedly ‘belongs’ to the ‘other’ discipline.
On the one hand, as a discipline that is supposed to be concerned with what happens
outside the sovereign state, IR relies upon a set of assumptions regarding the purpose
and meaning of political community inside the state. Modern theories of IR are expres-
sions of an idealized understanding of the sovereign state, in which ethics and ideas about
the universally good can be aspired towards only within the borders of the state. On the
other hand, as a discipline that is supposed to be concerned with questions about what
goes on inside the limits of political community, Political Theory must nevertheless rely
on a set of assumptions regarding what lies outside the state: a world of IR character-
ized by the lack of political community and authority. Ideas about a legitimate political
order and good government within states are, thus, defined against the dangers, vio-
lence and lack of order beyond states. In this respect, an alternative subtitle to Inside/
outside would be Political Theory as International Relations.
While demonstrating how inside and outside, Political Theory and International
Relations, the domestic and the international are interdependent and co-constitutive,
Inside/outside is nevertheless limited to a critical engagement with the relationship
between the inside and the outside of the state. In subsequent publications, however,
Walker has developed his critique further, taking into account several co-existing layers
of borders, boundaries and limits. With the publication of After the Globe, Before the
World (2010), Walker has shown how, in order to engage critically with the limits of
the modern political imagination, it is necessary to expand the analysis beyond a
narrow focus on the modern logic of inside/outside of the sovereign state.15 Taking into
account not only the constitutive outside of the sovereign state but the double con-
stitutive outside of the state and international system of states, Walker demonstrates the
difficulty of rethinking modern assumptions about the place and meaning of political
life in the so co-called late modern era. In doing so, Walker takes his accomplishments
in Inside/outside to a new level and sets the bar even higher for students and scholars of
IR who are trying to come to terms with the profound challenges of thinking about
politics in the contemporary world.
Notes
1 We would like to thank Rob Walker for his comments on an earlier draft and support of our
work more generally.
2 R. B. J. Walker, Inside/outside: International Relations as Political Theory, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1993. Page numbers placed in parentheses in the text refer to this edition.
3 Email correspondence between the authors and R. B. J. Walker, August 2011.
4 For a discussion of the politics of historicity in IR, influenced by Walker’s approach among
others’, see Nick Vaughan-Williams, ‘International Relations and the “Problem of History”’,
Millennium: Journal of International Studies, 2005, vol. 34, 115–36.
5 For a further engagement with this difficulty, see Tom Lundborg, Politics of the Event: Time,
Movement, Becoming, London: Routledge, 2012.
6 For a fuller discussion of the concept of the border in Walker’s work see Nick Vaughan-Williams,
Border Politics: The Limits of Sovereign Power, Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press,
2009.
R. B. J. Walker: Inside/outside: International Relations as Political Theory 217
7 See Yosef Lapid, ‘The Third Debate: On the Prospects of International Theory in a Post-
Positivist Era’, International Studies Quarterly, 1989, vol. 33, 235–54.
8 Two important exceptions to the lack of more substantial engagements with the core argu-
ments of Inside/outside are Lene Hansen, ‘R. B. J. Walker and International Relations:
Deconstructing a Discipline’, in Iver B. Neumann and Ole Wæver (eds), The Future of
International Relations: Masters in the Making, London: Routledge, 1997, pp. 316–36, and
Colin Hoadley, ‘Machiavelli, A Man of “His” Time: R. B. J. Walker and The Prince’, Mil-
lennium: Journal of International Studies, 2003, vol. 30, 1–18.
9 James Brassett, ‘After Walker’, Contemporary Political Theory, 2010, vol. 10, 291–93.
10 Fred Halliday, ‘Book Review: R. B. J. Walker, “Inside/outside: International Relations as
Political Theory”’, Millennium: Journal of International Studies, 1993, vol. 22, 362–65 and R.
E. Jones, ‘The Responsibility to Educate’, Review of International Studies, 1994, vol. 20, 299–311.
11 Jens Bartelson, The Critique of the State, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001, p. 167.
12 We have elaborated on this theme in our own respective work. See Vaughan-Williams, Border
Politics and Tom Lundborg, ‘What Lies Beyond Lies Within: Global Information Flows and
the Politics of the State/Inter-State System’, Alternatives, 2011, vol. 36, 103–17.
13 Justin Rosenberg, The Follies of Globalisation Theory, London: Verso, 2000.
14 R. B. J. Walker, After the Globe, Before the World, London: Routledge, 2010.
22 The state has a mind: Alexander Wendt’s
Social Theory of International Politics
Alan Chong
The constitution of agents and structures are not two independently given sets of
phenomena, a dualism, but represent a duality. According to the notion of the
duality of structure, the structural properties of social systems are both medium
and outcome of the practices they recursively organise … Structure is not to be
equated with constraint but is always both constraining and enabling … Structure
has no existence independent of the knowledge that agents have about what they
do in their day-to-day activity.14
Wendt attempts to reproduce this logic in his elaboration of why structure and
agency come together to explain why and how ‘culture’, broadly interpreted as values,
ideas and intentions, matter in international politics. Culture as a form of structure can
bring about a meeting of minds and bodies on the basis that each self-regarding agent has
acted simply on the basis of predicting the other’s moves based on common knowledge
derived from prior socialization in the pre-encounter period. Culture can also be con-
stitutive in the sense that mental states are derived from pre-existing ‘brain states’ that
paint a picture which directs the agent to believe, or imagine, a reality that accom-
modates a role destined for the agent (p. 173). If the individual human agent can be
likened to the corporate agency of an entire nation state, then one can imagine how the
222 Alan Chong
US hegemon may sometimes perceive itself to be acting benignly to thwart ‘rogue state
actions’ threatening itself and the general peace, while the rest of the international
community condemns the USA for reckless unilateral behaviour on the basis of alter-
native shared identities. Compare, for instance, the Group of 20’s communiqués relat-
ing to world order with the stance taken by Washington. If one considers the possibility
that common knowledge might be widely disseminated, and hence shared, by both the
USA and the international community prior to policing ‘rogue states’ such as Iran and
North Korea, the USA’s behaviour might not incur any opprobrium at all among the
international community (pp. 176–77).
The mind of the state: the politics of reality, social memory and area studies in IR
How then might one assess such an enormously complex book? In a very ironic way,
some of the salient criticisms of Wendt’s work pay Social Theory its highest compli-
ments. The book is an enduring contribution to IR because it lends itself to debating
the seemingly intangible assumptions that underpin the construction of reality. Maja
Zehfuss’s interpretation of constructivism opens up the ‘politics of reality’ that con-
structivists of three different stripes, Wendt, Kratochwil and Onuf, introduce but
stumble over in their explanatory angles: ‘although constructivism is about construction,
it takes reality as in many ways given. In other words, constructivism purports to
explain construction whilst still taking account of “reality”’.24 Utilizing an extended case
study of the intense framing debates over German military commitments to humani-
tarian missions in Bosnia-Herzegovina and Somalia in the early 1990s, Zehfuss takes
aim at Wendt’s silence on the realities of how policy actors frame ‘the necessary mul-
tiplicity of origins referred to in telling identity’.25 The Federal Republic of Germany
was partly construable by some political quarters as the morally purified successor to
the Nazi regime that initiated World War Two, and there was also space for rival
politicians to assert that the Federal Republic was a NATO member with significant
overseas responsibilities in burden sharing. Moreover, post-1945 ‘war guilt’ could also be
debated by parliamentarians across the political spectrum through the frame of its con-
sistency, or lack thereof, with the Federal Republic’s Grundgesetz (Basic Law). It is
therefore uncertain which parts of structure, or agency, should a ‘Wendtian’ analysis
have chosen to explain a constructed German military action abroad.
Taking Wendtian constructivism to a more sophisticated level is perhaps the work of
Karin Fierke. In her book Diplomatic Interventions: Conflict and Change in a Globalizing
World, Fierke argues that constructivists can perform an invaluable service by drawing
attention to the fact that every cross-border physical intervention is constituted by a
range of prior interventions. To Fierke, ‘intervention is a more general term that refers
to that which through its presence modifies an existing state of affairs’.26 These are
‘diplomatic interventions’ to the extent that ‘they may involve some form of commu-
nication to avoid or limit recourse to force, as well as to realize it’.27 Interventions are
morally, psychologically and economically costly affairs – take, for example, those in
226 Alan Chong
Bosnia, Afghanistan, Iraq, Libya and Syria – simply because statesmen, soldiers and
non-governmental activists have had to make their case for participation, as well as to
endure the censure of policies that have gone awry midway through the physical inter-
ventions. Likewise, the nuclear security scholarship of Nina Tannenwald and Carol
Atkinson has treated nuclear weapon ‘non-use’ in the similar vein of an ideational
intervention that by itself acts as a potent instrument of latent power for manipulating
agendas in world politics.28 Witness, for instance, North Korean and Iranian behaviour
from 2002 to 2012. An even more recent attempt at synthesizing realism, neoliberalism
and constructivism under the grand label of ‘cosmopolitan power’ has also adapted a
very basic understanding of constructivist ‘intervention’ to substantiate the argument
that soft power is a major augmentation of pre-existing ‘hard’ achievements by nation
states in economics, popular culture, political prestige and military power.29
In her other works Fierke introduces the constructivist concept of social memory and
trauma as a conditioner of international politics. This extends Wendtian arguments
about treating nation states as the primary and personified actors in world politics.
Nation states systematically collect traces of memory through their hierarchies of
functionaries as a guide towards future policy behaviour, and equally with a view
towards avoiding the perceived mistakes of the past. In Karin Fierke’s elaboration:
social memory as a picture of past trauma, may, at one and the same time, take a
narrative form and provide a script for re-enacting a cultural package inherited
from the past. Both help to bind together the identity of the group. What is
reproduced is less an identical set of practices than a relationship between victim
and perpetrator, which in ‘acting out’ is reversed.30
In this way, Wendtian obsessions with language and agency, pondering the dialectics
between material and ideational motivations, and constructivism’s application through
the storytelling technique, can all be brought to bear in a very elementary manner in
accounting for the diplomatic burden of the Holocaust in Germany’s foreign relations,
the Vietnam Syndrome in US foreign policy, or the shadow of the Nanjing Massacre in
Sino-Japanese relations.
Area studies also stand to benefit from constructivist approaches. Consider Asia for
instance. First, this is a region that has practised the form and function of the modern
nation state for less than a century. In fact, the nation state was an idea grafted artifi-
cially onto Asian polities in the pursuit of decolonization. A great number of political
ideas in Asia exist therefore on an experimental stage, implemented piecemeal,
amounting to curious outcomes such as the Association of Southeast Asian Nations
(ASEAN), which observes Westphalian principles with informal ‘face saving’ procedures
for avoiding open confrontation between member states. Asians seem to be proficient in
synthesizing mainstream diplomatic norms, such as those practised at the UN, and
local preferences, to match complex local reality. This is captured in the scholarship of
Amitav Acharya who claims that Asian regionalism has contributed the constructivist-
derived lexicon of ‘constitutive localization’ of norms governing pacific state behaviour.
In Acharya’s words, constitutive localization ‘may start with the reinterpretation and
re-representation of the external norm, but may also extend into more complex pro-
cesses of reconstitution to make an external norm congruent with an existing local
normative order’.31 Second, Asia, like so many political regions of the world, is still in
pursuit of equilibrium between Western-originated ideas of modern development and
Alexander Wendt: Social Theory of International Politics 227
the rediscovery of pre-modern indigenous ideals. Constructivism is normatively liberating
as a method of analysing the emerging Asian cultures of international relations insofar
as, unlike its rivals, it does not carry preconceived ideological baggage such as realism,
liberalism, Marxism and neo-Marxism. Asian nation states are still struggling to sta-
bilize domestic governance, and in the process will generate changes in their national
outlooks on foreign relations. In this context, the Wendtian framework of ‘ideas most
of the way down’ can illuminate Asian perspectives in their treatment of materialistic
considerations in either forging peace or waging war.32 Acharya and many others
believe that Asian ideas that have become operational on the international stage are not
likely to constitute a clash on the scale predicted by Samuel Huntington’s famous
thesis.33 There could instead be a constitutive dialogue of civilizations underway in the
present century where norms are shared through local filters. Constructivism is therefore
potentially less of a formal ‘IR theory’ as Wendt confesses (p. 7), and closer to a value-
free method of comprehending the non-Western world. One can be reasonably certain
that African and Latin American scholars will also agree that this is probably the
greatest contribution of Social Theory, apart from co-constituting agency and structure.
Designating a book that was only published ten years ago a classic of the field is always
going to be contentious. This is especially the case when the book has generated an array
of reactions ranging from outlandish praise to outright condemnation. Nevertheless, in
this chapter I am going to argue that John J. Mearsheimer’s The Tragedy of Great
Power Politics (TGPP) will, in time, become a classic work of International Relations
(IR).1 In the process of reviewing the main arguments of Mearsheimer’s book, I will
provide three principal reasons that justify designating TGPP a classic in the making.
First, the book makes an important contribution to the realist tradition, which con-
tinues to be the most influential tradition of IR. Second, the theory that Mearsheimer
develops – offensive realism – has not only become an important new branch of realist
theory, but it has precipitated a number of debates within realism, including a key
debate with Kenneth Waltz’s version of structural realism. Offensive realism is deliber-
ately meant to provide a different account of international politics than that provided
by Waltz, and those designated as defensive realists. Most fundamentally, offensive
realism argues that great powers are continuously seeking opportunities to increase
their power relative to other states. Third, the arguments that Mearsheimer develops in
his book have influenced some of the important post-Cold War US foreign policy
debates. To his credit, Mearsheimer has not shied away from the public arena, and he
has used his theory to make a number of controversial predictions and policy recom-
mendations.2 When all three of these reasons are considered together, there is ample
justification for my claim that TGPP will be recognized as a classic text of IR.
Notes
1 John J. Mearsheimer, The Tragedy of Great Power Politics, New York: W. W. Norton, 2001.
Page numbers placed in parentheses in the text refer to this edition.
2 For an interesting interview, see ‘Conversations in International Relations – Interviews with
John J. Mearsheimer (Part I)’, International Relations, 2006, vol. 20, 105–24 and ‘Conversa-
tions in International Relations – Interviews with John J. Mearsheimer (Part II)’, Interna-
tional Relations, 2006, vol. 20, 231–43. For an interesting recent reappraisal, see Robert D.
238 Brian C. Schmidt
Kaplan, ‘Why John J. Mearsheimer Is Right (About Some Things)’, The Atlantic, January/
February 2012.
3 See e.g. Robert O. Keohane, ‘Theory of World Politics: Structural Realism and Beyond’, in
Ada W. Finifter (ed.), Political Science: The State of the Discipline, Washington, DC: Amer-
ican Political Science Association, 1983, pp. 503–40; Stefano Guzzini, Realism in Interna-
tional Relations and International Political Economy: The Continuing Story of a Death
Foretold, London: Routledge, 1998; and Stephen M. Walt, ‘The Enduring Relevance of the
Realist Tradition’, in Ira Katznelson and Helen V. Milner (eds), Political Science: The State
of the Discipline, New York: W. W. Norton, 2002, pp. 199–230.
4 On the difference between a historical and an analytical tradition, see Brian C. Schmidt, The
Political Discourse of Anarchy: A Disciplinary History of International Relations, Albany, NY:
SUNY Press, 1998.
5 See Nicolas Guilhot (ed.), The Invention of International Relations Theory: Realism, the
Rockefeller Foundation, and the 1954 Conference on Theory, New York: Columbia University
Press, 2011 and his chapter on this book in this volume.
6 See Anders Wivel’s chapter on this book in this volume.
7 The six questions are: (i) why do great powers want power?; (ii) how much power do states
want?; (iii) what is power?; (iv) what strategies do states pursue to gain power?; (v) what are
the causes of war?; and (vi) when do threatened great powers balance against a dangerous
adversary and why do they attempt to pass the buck to another threatened state?
8 See Brian C. Schmidt, ‘Competing Realist Conceptions of Power’, Millennium: Journal of
International Studies, 2005, vol. 33, 523–49.
9 On the ‘evil school’, see Arnold Wolfers, Discord and Collaboration: Essays on International
Politics, Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1962.
10 There are a number of scholars who concur with this assessment. See e.g. Walt, ‘The Endur-
ing Relevance of the Realist Tradition’; Jeffrey W. Taliaferro, ‘Security Seeking Under Anar-
chy: Defensive Realism Revisited’, International Security, 2000/2001, vol. 25, 128–61; and
Robert Jervis, ‘Realism and the Study of World Politics’, International Organization, 1998,
vol. 52, 971–91.
11 For more on the offensive realism-defensive realism debate, see Charles Glaser, Rational
Theory of International Politics: The Logic of Competition and Cooperation, Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press, 2010.
12 Kenneth N. Waltz, ‘The Origins of War in Neorealist Theory’, in Robert I. Rotberg and
Theodore K. Rabb (eds), The Origin and Prevention of Major Wars, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1989, pp. 39–52, at p. 40.
13 See Jeffrey D. Berejikian, ‘The Rationality of Sanctions Reconsidered: Offensive or Defensive
Realism?’, paper presented at the annual meeting of the Southern Political Science Associa-
tion, New Orleans, January 6–9, 2004; Taliaferro, ‘Security Seeking under Anarchy’; Brian C.
Schmidt, ‘Realism as Tragedy’, Review of International Studies, 2004, vol. 30, 427–41; and
Peter Toft, ‘John J. Mearsheimer: An Offensive Realist between Geopolitics and Power’,
Journal of International Relations and Development, 2005, vol. 8, 381–408.
14 See also Glaser, Rational Theory of International Politics.
15 On the offence-defence balance, see Robert Jervis, ‘Cooperation under the Security Dilemma’,
World Politics, 1978, vol. 30, 167–214; and Sean M. Lynn-Jones, ‘Offense-Defense Theory
and its Critics’, Security Studies, 1995, vol. 4, 660–91.
16 Joseph M. Grieco, ‘Realist International Theory and the Study of World Politics’, in Michael
W. Doyle and G. John Ikenberry (eds), New Thinking in International Relations Theory,
Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1997, pp. 163–201, at p. 167.
17 See John J. Mearsheimer, ‘Reckless States and Realism’, International Relations, 2009, vol. 23,
241–56.
18 See e.g. Barry R. Posen, ‘The Best Defense’, The National Interest, 2002, vol. 67, 119–26;
Peter Gowan, ‘A Calculus of Power’, New Left Review, vol. 16, 47–67; Shiping Tang, ‘Social
Evolution of International Politics’, European Journal of International Relations, 2010, vol. 16,
31–55; and Toft, ‘John J. Mearsheimer: An Offensive Realist between Geopolitics and Power’.
19 See Stephen G. Brooks and William C. Wohlforth, World Out of Balance: International
Relations and the Challenge of American Primacy, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press,
2008.
John J. Mearsheimer: The Tragedy of Great Power Politics 239
20 Christopher Layne, ‘The “Poster Child for Offensive Realism”: America as a Global Hege-
mon’, Security Studies, 2002/2003, vol. 12, 120–64.
21 See Barry R. Posen, ‘Command of the Commons: The Military Foundation of U.S. Hege-
mony’, International Security, 2003, vol. 28, 5–46.
22 Mearsheimer now concedes that from Clinton on the US has pursued global dominance. See
‘Imperial By Design’, The National Interest, 2010, vol. 111, 16–34.
23 See e.g. the following articles by John J. Mearsheimer: ‘The Only Exit from Bosnia’, New
York Times, 7 October 1997; ‘The Gathering Storm: China’s Challenge to US Power in Asia’,
The Chinese Journal of International Politics, 2010, vol. 3, 381–96; ‘Guns Won’t Win the
Afghan War’, New York Times, 4 November 2001; and, with Stephen M. Walt, ‘An Unne-
cessary War’, Foreign Policy, 2003, vol. 134, 50–59; and ‘Keeping Saddam in a Box’, New
York Times, 2 February 2003.
24 See Ido Oren, ‘The Unrealism of Contemporary Realism: The Tension between Realist
Theory and Realists’ Practice’, Perspectives on Politics, 2009, vol. 7, 283–301.
25 On the role of domestic lobbies, see John J. Mearsheimer and Stephen M. Walt, The Israel
Lobby and U.S. Foreign Policy, New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux, 2007. Also see John J.
Mearsheimer, Why Leaders Lie, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011.
26 Gowan, ‘A Calculus of Power’.
24 Interrogating the subject: Errol Morris’s
The Fog of War
Casper Sylvest1
While the relationship between politics and film-making or photography has long been
of interest to the human sciences, there has been a tendency to ignore or downplay the
role of documentaries in such analyses, perhaps because the once-dusty genre has either
been seen to unproblematically reflect reality or to embody fiction in sheep’s clothing.
Both positions are unsatisfactory. Bowling for Columbine (2002), Supersize Me (2004),
An Inconvenient Truth (2006) and numerous other films, including recent releases like
The Cove (2009) or Restrepo (2010), have accorded documentaries a new prominence.
In conjunction with technological developments and a wider proliferation of film-
making equipment, more films portraying, or pretending to portray, reality are avail-
able. Since the 1990s film studies has increasingly delved into the history and nature of
‘docs’.11 Political studies have so far not followed suit despite the recent explosion in
politically relevant documentaries. While recent decades have witnessed the emergence
of a literature on film and IR which reflects a broader interest in various forms of visual
representation, the nexus between politics, culture and documentary film-making
remains curiously understudied.12
Defining documentary is no easy feat. A watertight definition is ‘effectively impos-
sible’, one scholar maintains.13 Even negative criteria that appear as obvious minimum
requirements – like not using a script or not using actors – are challenged by films that are
242 Casper Sylvest
commonly accepted to be part of the genre. Indeed, documentary film has been likened
to a ‘pluripotent stem cell’ that produces a variety of sub-genres (from rockumentaries
to cinema vérité).14 While these films are supposed to deal with ‘real people’ or ‘real
phenomena’, accuracy is an unproductive yardstick.15 Relying on common sense (‘we
know a documentary when we see one!’) is a seductively appealing but intellectually
unsatisfactory option. Conversely, we could acknowledge that there is a difference
between fiction feature films and documentaries – not least with respect to the ways in
which the latter lay claim to (parts of the) truth or reality – yet otherwise concentrate
on the most obvious similarity between them: they are both edited!
From this perspective, since documentaries deal with themes, figures or phenomena
that are, directly or indirectly, of public interest they are inherently political. Non-fiction
(as well as fiction) films can serve a host of purposes, but they are perhaps best seen as
narrative structures that (like other narratives making use of other mediums) claim,
show, argue, posit, assume and criticize.16 Together with other forms of communication
they share a challenge of ensuring that an intended meaning, even if it is equivocal, is
received and accepted by the audience. Clearly, the editing process is paramount in
this context. It is an intensely political practice, which virtually all directors recognize
as such. This is no less true of Morris, who fittingly considers documentaries to offer
‘almost unlimited possibilities of self-expression’. The narrative structures and force of
Morris’s films emerge through a ‘process of discovery’ in the editing room, during
which a massive condensation and elimination of material takes place.17
Apart from FOW, his best-known production, Morris’s output includes the portraits
of the USA Gates of Heaven (1978) and Vernon, Florida (1981), the ‘detective-documentary’
The Thin Blue Line (1988) that solved the murder of a Dallas policeman and led to the
overturning of the conviction of an innocent man (who later sued Morris for the
rights to his life story), the portrait of Stephen Hawking in A Brief History of Time
(1991), and Mr Death (1999), a harrowing portrait of the 40-cups-of-coffee and 120-
cigarettes-per-day engineer Fred Leuchter, whose libertarianism and professional
career as a designer of execution equipment for US penitentiaries led Leuchter to
conduct an amateurish ‘investigation’ of Auschwitz that was later exploited by Holo-
caust deniers. His latest films include Tabloid (2010) and Standard Operating Procedure
(2008). The latter revolves around the Abu Ghraib prison scandal in Iraq and is
simultaneously an investigation into the nature of photography and an attempt to
question the superficial public condemnation of Lynndie England and other mem-
bers of the 372nd Military Police Company. Morris looks beyond and behind the
photographs and (indirectly) questions the political and military establishment and
their role in creating a culture in which torture and degradation was anything but
untoward.18
In most of Morris’s work, simple existential or epistemological questions are pursued in
a manner that evokes philosophical debate more than ideological crusade. This is
unsurprising given Morris’s academic background. He studied history at the University of
Wisconsin, before unsuccessfully pursuing graduate studies in the history and philoso-
phy of science at the Universities of Princeton and Berkeley. As well as struggling with writer’s
block and other difficulties, Morris also fell out with his supervisor, Thomas Kuhn,
who ‘physically assaulted me and shortly after that threw me out of Princeton’.19
Truth, self-deception, the achievement of justice, guilt, evil (or the capacity to do evil),
the metaphysics of killing and overcoming or dealing with human suffering are recurring
themes in films by Morris. Clearly, a miscarriage of justice, the naivety and hubris of a
Errol Morris: The Fog of War 243
little-known engineer and the political career of McNamara are only superficially
related; yet, they all expose the marvels and mysteries of human self-creation.
I’ve always been fascinated by how people see themselves as virtually anything. It’s
like our capacity for credulity, our capability of believ[ing] utter nonsense, to ima-
gine things that are utterly ridiculous and clearly untrue. Our abilities are unfet-
tered in that direction.20
The eccentric, delusional and often controversial subjects of Morris’s films are used,
then, to illuminate something important and familiar about the human condition.
However, their lives or deeds and their own understanding of these are always central
concerns. ‘My films don’t document news stories or external events, they’re more
excursions into people’s personal dreamscapes.’21 Through a mixture of wit, authenti-
city and an engagement with deeply ethical and metaphysical questions, Morris man-
ages to humanize and expose his subjects (or victims as some critics would have it).
Morris achieves these qualities in his film-making through a cynical interview style and
cinematic techniques that have become trademarks of his first-person film-making. His
notorious interview machine, the ‘Interrotron’, etymologically derived from ‘interview’
and ‘terror’, works by projecting Morris’s image onto a two-way mirror placed
directly in front of a camera through which the interview is recorded. The device
allows Morris to conduct interviews that create directness, eye contact, authenticity and
create a distance between Morris and the interviewee, which in turn makes the inter-
viewee talk.22 Yet, talk is intensely interesting since, ‘the thing that makes civilization
possible’, according to Morris, ‘is that people lie to one another routinely’.23 And to
themselves one might add.
In the technologically mediated intimacy created by the ‘Interrotron’ focus is (after a
while) shifted away from the interview process which in turn facilitates an exploitation
of uncomfortable silences. Enter Morris’s three-minute rule: ‘My rule of thumb is to
leave people alone, let them talk, and in two or three minutes they’ll show you how
crazy they really are.’24 Experience has taught Morris that combining silence with the
appearance of an attentive listener is a successful strategy. This well-staged ‘let-’em-
talk-until-they-spill-the-beans’ procedure reveals that for Morris, ironically, a good
interview is almost a monologue.
Morris’s films often have a deft comic quality to them despite dealing with themes such
as evil, death and wrongdoing. Although the interview is mediated and constructed,
Morris’s editing adds a further layer. The documentary, a term with which Morris is
distinctly uncomfortable due to its cinéma verité connotations, is clearly not pure film-
making.25 Often using modernist music, re-enactments (a term Morris is not keen on)
and an aggressive editing style, the subjects at the centre of Morris’s films appear to
speak for themselves – but clearly not under circumstances of their own choosing.
FOW is an intense movie. Apart from Morris’s voice which can be heard shouting
between eight and ten times during the film, the only contemporary figure that the
244 Casper Sylvest
viewer meets is McNamara. The film is based on more than 20 hours of filmed inter-
views begun in May 2001. Mixed with historical audio and audiovisual clips, McNamara
is the central narrating voice on a journey that has three key diachronic reference
points: the allied strategic bombing of Japanese cities during the Second World War,
the legendary 13 days of October 1962 during which the Cuban Missile Crisis unfolded
and US troop and conflict escalation during the Vietnam War. These are not only some
of the most excruciating events of the World War II and the Cold War; they are also
milestones in the personal life of McNamara: he shaped and was shaped by US strat-
egy and policy. The film does not directly deal with McNamara’s public life after he
left government in the late 1960s. During this latter part of McNamara’s life he was
President of the World Bank (1968–81) and later an outspoken critic of US nuclear
policy, one among many former US government officials that are collectively known as
‘the eliminators’.27 Yet, many other dimensions of McNamara’s life – from childhood,
university education (Berkeley) and professional life (from Harvard Business School to
Ford Motor Company) – are woven into a selective political and cultural history of the
USA during the middle quarters of the twentieth century.28
The film begins with a poised, professional and slick-looking McNamara who is
about to begin a Pentagon press briefing during the Vietnam War. Utterly at ease
in the situation, McNamara pronounces the first words of the film: ‘Is this chart a
reasonable height for you?’ This is perhaps the dominant image of McNamara: the
brightest of the bright, the whizz-kid par excellence. One hour and forty-five minutes later,
the film closes with a determined McNamara refusing to engage in further discussion
about Vietnam (‘I would rather be damned if I don’t’), set to footage of this aged,
bleak-looking man driving his Ford around Washington, DC. In between this front and
back cover of the movie, Morris takes us through the Cuban Missile Crisis, the First
World War, the Depression, the World War II, the Tonkin Gulf Affair and the heated
debates about Vietnam inside and outside the White House.
What makes the narrative riveting and intense are not only Morris’s skills as a
director, but also the fact that McNamara since retirement has tried to come to grips
with his involvement in and decisions during some of these controversial events.29
Visually this self-reflexive exercise conducted in McNamara’s gripping voice is accom-
panied by historical documents, footage, re-enactments and texted audio clips against a
background of the legendary rolling tape recorder. Unsurprisingly, a great deal of the
debate surrounding FOW has been about Cuba and Vietnam, the symbolic pointers of
Cold War history and politics. Morris has received the harshest criticism in relation to
McNamara’s role in and recollection of the Cuban Missile Crisis and his responsibility
for and his (failed) attempt to avert the Vietnam tragedy.30 The gist of this critique is
that Morris is too soft on McNamara, that Morris fails to bring out what Hendrickson
has called the ‘deep and rigid and almost schizoid but in any case deceitful code of
opposites’ in McNamara’s character.31
At first sight, Morris might look guilty as charged. ‘I’m never in an adversarial
position with the people that I film’, he has argued.32 This is also true of McNamara:
the pair promoted the film together, a desolate McNamara dominates the commercial
packaging of the film, and Morris has relayed how he grew to like McNamara and his
(in Morris’s opinion) sincere attempt to come to grips with his political deeds and
misdeeds. Clearly, Morris’s treatment of the most controversial aspects of the Cuban
Missile Crisis and Vietnam – was the second letter from Khrushchev ‘dictated by a
bunch of hard-liners’ as McNamara argued, was McNamara trying to help Kennedy to
Errol Morris: The Fog of War 245
‘keep us out of the war’ and was McNamara responsible for the escalation of the Vietnam
War or did he try to prevent it? – glosses over significant historical complexities and
controversies. The debates among historians about these issues, essentially political
debates about the legacies of statesmen and policies, are endlessly interesting. Film
is, however, an unpromising media in which to conduct such discussions, even if it can
be persuasively argued that Morris succeeds in unsettling ingrained prejudices. Yet,
what redeems the film is the effect that Morris seeks and achieves with his audience:
critical reflection.
FOW is a powerful reminder that in international politics what you believe governs what
you do and that action, while often irreversible, provides stimulus for reflection and,
possibly, learning. Yet, a case can be made for seeing the film as an allegory on inter-
national politics more broadly. Morris has described the film as ‘part history, part self-
analysis, part mystery, part self-justification’,34 but even this is unnecessarily restrictive.
Indeed, the composition of FOW and Morris’s editing and film-making style turns the
film into an unresolved, tension-ridden and challenging essay on fundamental issues in
international relations, including communication, learning, weapons and war. At this
point, it is worth returning to the aforementioned 11 lessons, which both serve as the
subtitle and main organising device of the film (these lessons are recapitulated in Box
24.1). It is in the matrix – or maze, rather – constructed by these ‘lessons’ and through
his subject McNamara that Morris’s near-nihilism and ceaseless, poignant questioning
of central themes in the conduct and study of international politics emerge: ‘I often
think that if my movies are any good it’s because they are full of unresolved questions
you can keep thinking about.’35 Using this yardstick, I argue, FOW is indeed a
successful movie.
While the lessons are extrapolated from McNamara’s life and recollections, they can, by
the same token, be read as an ironic and deeply pessimistic philosophy of international
246 Casper Sylvest
politics: ‘I don’t think that the lessons in any way summarize the film. They have, if
anything, an ironic absurdist quality that leads you from one step to the other.’36 Part
of this thought-provoking quality has to do with the alluring nature of the lessons and
their obviously strained interrelations. While every lesson is, on its own, trivially rea-
sonable, as a collective the lessons groan loudly against each other. For example, while
the second lesson teaches that ‘rationality will not save us’, the fourth lesson (presented
to the audience a mere ten minutes later) pays homage to undiluted means-end
rationality by urging us to ‘maximize efficiency’. As Morris puts it, ‘McNamara is a
control freak, yet he explains to us that the world is, essentially, out of control’.37
Similarly, the sixth lesson teaches us to ‘get the data’, while the seventh lesson invali-
dates our sensory experiences by proclaiming that ‘belief and seeing are both often
wrong’. Indeed, it has persuasively been argued that:
[T]he lesson of the lessons is that they are without lesson: they do not summarize a
formalizable knowledge that can be transmitted … [T]he lesson of McNamara’s
lessons is that he has intuited something about the nature of knowing, especially in
times of crisis when unprecedented events unfold in unprecedented ways such that
one must reckon with what exceeds present categories of comprehension, decision,
action, and anticipatable consequence, putting one in the position of having to
invent on the spot new means of responding to the danger at hand.38
This is a precise description of the incongruity that Morris lays bare and the chal-
lenges he presents for IR scholars. It is a position that has some affinities with classical
realism and its understanding of politics as tragedy,39 yet it is also, ultimately, more
misanthropic in its resignation to the tragicomic nemesis of human folly. Indeed, while
the film could be taken merely as a sign of the confusion which McNamara’s soul-
searching has landed him in, there is more at play. This is most obvious towards the
end of the film when any illusions about intellectual and moral progress in politics
made through the first 10 lessons are punctured in a moment of supreme irony: the
final, eleventh lesson bluntly states that ‘you can’t change human nature’.
The intention, I submit, is to stimulate reflection, and in FOW, Morris deploys
cinematic technique to achieve this objective. Despite the fact that Morris only inter-
views one person and that success is defined as the breakdown of dialogue, the film is a
double interrogation. On the one hand, McNamara’s near-monologues are clearly pro-
voked by Morris’s pointed questions and the intimidating interview context. On the
other hand, FOW is a bombardment of the senses in which a juggernaut of music and
editing virtually assault, enhance or question anything McNamara has to say during
the film. Set to Philip Glass’ vexing scores, aggressive editing techniques – historical
footage, close-up photos of print media and the interviewee, the de-centring of
McNamara in the frame, and re-enactments – accompany McNamara’s spoken word
while simultaneously structuring and pacing the narrative.
While these techniques can be read as legitimating what McNamara portrays as
necessary evils,40 this is unduly confined. Sometimes the editing supports or illustrates a
point or a logic described, at other times it adds to the characterization of McNamara.
At yet other junctures in the film, it works to expose McNamara and his worrying
concept of empathy. In these passages, the music and editing do seem to be a strategy
of suspicion that is used to visualize or question statements or assumptions made by
McNamara that appear to be uncontroversial or trivial but which turn out to harbour
Errol Morris: The Fog of War 247
deep moral, political and philosophical dilemmas. Perhaps the best example of this is
the recurrence of objects dropping towards the ground: skulls, bombs, napalm, Agent
Orange, dominos or a graphic manipulation of numbers from one of McNamara’s
World War II reports about bombing efficiency. The free fall transmits both a measure
of serenity and eeriness but without putting across one equivocal point. Other iconic
images of war – the bomber, the mounting of weapons on aircrafts, the strategy meet-
ings of generals, and panorama images of large-scale destruction – while apparently
creating distance between political decisions and actual suffering and violence are
nevertheless paced and cut into the film in ways that produce dissonance, evoke doubt
and facilitate reflection. One example of this is the way in which target destruction
rates of Japanese cities during the World War II are illustrated (using accelerating cuts)
by reference to US cities of equivalent size.
Why, one might well ask. Why does Morris seek to place his audience in this tangle
of politics, hypocrisy, normative principles, apparently good intentions and mostly
shocking consequences (in the McNamarian sense in which ‘results are what we expect
and consequences are what we get’)? Well, ‘[l]anguage is the ultimate tool of conceal-
ment’, Morris argues.41 The same could be said of film, but in Morris’s hands the
documentary is above all critical by virtue of exposing the philosophical, political, and
moral dilemmas and paradoxes that we too often keep under wraps in trying to make
sense of international politics. This is why FOW is a classic of IR.
Notes
1 I thank Duncan Bell, Signe Blaabjerg Christoffersen, James Der Derian, Suzette Frovin, Rens
van Munster, Nils Arne Sørensen and my students for stimulating discussions about Morris’
film-making.
2 The Fog of War, directed by Errol Morris, 106 min., Sony Pictures Classics, 2003.
3 Fred Kaplan, ‘The Evasions of Robert McNamara: What’s True and What’s a Lie in The Fog
of War?’, Slate Magazine, 19 December 2003. Available at: www.slate.com/id/2092916/
(accessed 19 January 2012). The film was also accompanied by the publication of a book:
James G. Blight and Janet M. Lang, The Fog of War: Lessons from the Life of Robert S.
McNamara, New York: Rowman & Littlefield, 2005.
4 Seth Fein, Review of The Fog of War, American Historical Review, 2004, vol. 109, 1260.
5 Choices Program and the Critical Oral History Project at the Watson Institute for Interna-
tional Studies, Brown University, Official Teacher’s Guide for the Fog of War (2004). Avail-
able at: www.choices.edu/resources/supplemental_fogofwar.php (accessed 19 January 2012).
6 Michael J. Shapiro, ‘The Fog of War’, Security Dialogue, 2005, vol. 36, 233–46; Lloyd S.
Etheredge (ed.), ‘Symposium: McNamara’s Lessons and The Fog of War’, prepared for Per-
spectives on Politics. Available at: www.policyscience.net/mcnamara.pdf (accessed 19 January
2012). See also Richard New Lebow, ‘Robert S. McNamara: Max Weber’s Nightmare’,
International Relations, 2006, vol. 20, 211–24. In film studies, Morris’ work is more widely
appreciated. For recent, well-referenced studies, see Zoë Drucik, ‘Documenting False History:
Errol Morris and Mr. Death’, Studies in Documentary Film, 2007, vol. 1, 207–19; William
Rothman (ed.), Three Documentary Filmmakers: Errol Morris, Ross McElwee, Jean Rouch,
New York: SUNY Press, 2009; Lucia Ricciardelli, ‘Documentary Filmmaking in the Post-
modern Age: Errol Morris & The Fog of Truth’, Studies in Documentary Film, 2010, vol. 4,
35–50.
7 Errol Morris, ‘The Anti-Postmodern Postmodernist’, in Livia Bloom (ed.), Errol Morris
Interviews, Jackson, MI: University Press of Mississippi, 2010, pp. 118–30, at p. 128. For the
reflective mood, see e.g. John J. Mearsheimer, ‘Hans Morgenthau and the Iraq War: Realism
versus Neo-conservatism’, Open Democracy, 18 May 2005. Available at: www.opendemocrac
y.net/democracy-americanpower/morgenthau_2522.jsp (accessed 19 January 2012).
248 Casper Sylvest
8 The phrase is from Paul Hendrickson, The Living and the Dead: Robert McNamara and Five
Lives of a Lost War, London: Papermac, 1997, p. 356.
9 Chris Brown with Kirstin Ainley, Understanding International Relations, 4th edn, Basing-
stoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2009, p. 14.
10 Roy Grundmann and Cynthia Rockwell, ‘Truth is Not Subjective’, reprinted in Bloom (ed.),
Errol Morris Interviews, pp. 86–101, at p. 86.
11 See particularly Patricia Aufderheide, Documentary Film: A Very Short Introduction, Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 2007; Michael Chanan, The Politics of Documentary, London:
British Film Institute, 2007; Jonathan Kahana, The Politics of American Documentary, New
York: Columbia University Press, 2008.
12 Rens van Munster and Casper Sylvest, ‘Documenting and International Relations: Doc-
umentary Film and the Creative Arrangment of Perceptibility’, unpublished manuscript,
March 2013. On film and IR see e.g. Cynthia Weber, International Relations Theory: A Cri-
tical Introduction, 3rd edn, London: Routledge, 2009; Michael J. Shapiro, Cinematic Geo-
politics, London: Routledge, 2009. Conspicuously, prominent scholars in the field, like
Cynthia Weber, Michael T. Klare and James Der Derian, have recently turned to (documentary)
film-making.
13 Chanan, The Politics of Documentary, p. 5.
14 Marsha McCreadie, Documentary Superstars: How Today’s Filmmakers Are Reinventing the
Form, New York: Allworth Press, 2008, p. ix.
15 See e.g. Felicity Mellor, ‘The Politics of Accuracy in Judging Global Warming Films’,
Environmental Communication, 2009, vol. 3, 134–50.
16 For a discussion of these characteristics of the genre attuned to the agenda of IR as well as a
typology of subgenres, see Sylvest and van Munster, ‘Documenting International Relations’.
17 This was also the case for FOW. See Paul Cronin, ‘It Could All Be Wrong: An Unfinished
Interview with Errol Morris’, in Bloom (ed.), Errol Morris Interviews, pp. 144–209, at pp.
176, 187, 194.
18 The film was also accompanied by a book: Philip Gourevitch and Errol Morris, Standard
Operating Procedure: A War Story, London: Picador, 2008.
19 Morris in Cronin, ‘It Could All Be Wrong’, p. 194.
20 Morris in Alice Arshalooys Kelikian, ‘Film and Friendship: Werner and Errol’, in Bloom
(ed.), Errol Morris Interviews, pp. 210–29, at p. 216.
21 Cronin, ‘It Could All Be Wrong’, p. 184.
22 The Interrotron has since been superseded by the more technologically advanced Megatron.
Morris has directed many commercials using the Interrotron, a phenomenon that has since
exploded. Morris’ production also includes commercials for the 2008 Obama campaign
(‘People in the Middle for Obama’. Available at: www.youtube.com/user/middleforobama/
featured (accessed 19 January 2012)).
23 Morris quoted in Alan Chang, ‘Planet of the Apes’, reprinted in Bloom (ed.), Errol Morris
Interviews, pp. 55–61, at p. 55.
24 Bloom (ed.), Errol Morris Interviews, back cover.
25 Morris pursues some of these concerns about the relationship between photography and truth
on his New York Times blog. Available at: http://opinionator.blogs.nytimes.com/category/
errol-morris/ (accessed 19 January 2012).
26 President Lyndon B. Johnson, 25 February, 1964 (in telephone conversation with McNamara),
in The Fog of War. All references to the film are taken from the transcript available on
Morris’ website. Available at: www.errolmorris.com/film/fow_transcript.html (accessed 19
January 2012).
27 The eliminators (not to be confused with the professional wrestling tag team of the same
name) are made up of former national security cabinet officials who seek to eliminate nuclear
weapons. McNamara has characterized US nuclear policy as ‘immoral, illegal, militarily
unnecessary, and dreadfully dangerous’. (Robert S. McNamara, ‘Apocalypse Soon’, Foreign
Policy, 2005, 148, p. 28.) See also Joseph Cirincione and Alexandra Bell, ‘The Eliminators’,
Center for American Progress, 17 January 2008. Available at: www.americanprogress.org/
issues/2008/01/the_eliminators.html (accessed 19 January 2012).
28 For a fuller sketch see Tim Weiner, ‘Robert S. McNamara, Architect of a Futile War, Dies at
93’, New York Times, 7 July 2009; and Hendrickson’s excellent The Living and the Dead.
Errol Morris: The Fog of War 249
29 Robert S. McNamara, Blundering into Disaster: Surviving the First Century of the Nuclear
Age, New York: Pantheon, 1986; Robert S. McNamara, In Retrospect: The Tragedy and
Lessons of Vietnam, New York: Random House, 1995; Robert S. McNamara and James G.
Blight, Wilson’s Ghost: Reducing the Risk of Conflict, Killing and Catastrophe in the 21st
Century, New York: Public Affairs, 2001.
30 See particularly Kaplan, ‘The Evasions of Robert McNamara’. More heated versions of the
same argument include Eric Alterman, ‘The Century of the “Son of a Bitch”’, The Nation, 26
November 2003 and the ensuing debate with Morris (7 January 2004); Alexander Cockburn,
‘The Fog of Cop-Out’, The Nation, 9 February 2004 (A longer version is available at: www.
counterpunch.org/cockburn03012004.html (accessed 19 January 2012)).
31 Hendrickson, The Living and the Dead, p. 23.
32 McCreadie, Documentary Superstars, p. 92.
33 Errol Morris, ‘Musings on the Universe’, in Bloom (ed.), Errol Morris Interviews, pp. 251–56,
at p. 251.
34 Morris quoted in Kenneth Turan, ‘Movie Review: The Fog of War’, Los Angeles Times, 19
December 2003. Available at: www.errolmorris.com/content/review/fog_turan.html (accessed
19 January 2012).
35 Morris in Cronin, ‘It Could All Be Wrong’, p. 204.
36 Livia Bloom, ‘Clearing the Fog’, in Bloom (ed.), Errol Morris Interviews, pp. 131–35, at p. 132.
37 Morris in Cronin, ‘It Could All Be Wrong’, p. 193. See also p. 206. It is worth noting that in
the supplementary material on the FOW DVD, McNamara is given opportunity to introduce
ten more complicated and consistent lessons that he himself prepared.
38 Timothy Donovan, A. Samuel Kimball and Jilian Smith, ‘Fog of War: What Yet Remains’,
Postmodern Culture, 2005, vol. 16 (no pagination).
39 Cf. the chapters on Carr, Morgenthau and Herz in this volume. See also the discussion in
Carl Platinga, ‘The Philosophy of Errol Morris’, in Rothman, Three Documentary Film-
makers, pp. 43–62.
40 See Shapiro’s contribution to Etheredge (ed.), ‘Symposium’ and Shapiro, ‘The Fog of War’,
esp. pp. 241–45.
41 Morris in Cronin, ‘It Could All Be Wrong’, p. 200.
25 Restraint in the global polity, the remix:
Daniel Deudney’s Bounding Power
Brent J. Steele1
With all that has been written on international relations in the history of the field that
bears its name, one would think that there is nothing else left to be said, theoretically
anyway, that represents anything more than the clichéd ‘putting old wine into new
bottles’. Yet, to briefly extend that metaphor, sometimes scholars come along who say
something creative by blending the wine in unique ways. They do so to such effect that
we really couldn’t care less how old, popular, or worn-out each ‘component’ wine is
that went into the blend – because the outcome, its product and what it does for us is so
crisp, sharp and useful, that we know we have consumed something so new that it
surely will alter the field. Such achievements make it possible to see the world and the
arrangements through which humans have confronted violence differently as both more
dangerous and fragile, as well as more hopeful, stable and secure, than we previously
considered.
Despite its charged shortcomings, Daniel Deudney’s Bounding Power is such a book,
and it is the way in which Bounding Power gets us to that point that makes it a ‘classic-
in-the-making’ of International Relations (IR). Although it goes against the grain of
much conventional analysis, Deudney’s use of exegesis and reconstruction is a method
actually deployed quite frequently, and especially by those in the emerging fields of
international political theory.2 It is simply one of the most exceptional examples of the
best that this method can provide us. A combination of various philosophical and
theoretical perspectives, exegesis and reconstruction is itself a skill that has for far too
long been ignored as such. I liken this method’s underrated status to the debates in the
1990s about ‘sampling’ in the US hip-hop scene. When it appeared with greater fre-
quency in the early years of that decade, sampling was seen as a simple regurgitation
of past music onto existing tracks. What critics failed to recognize was that hip-hop
artists during that time had to figure out not only which parts of which songs belonged
on a music track, but also how those parts worked together to create a particular product,
a particular sound or beat, and a particular ‘collage’.3 Furthermore, not just anyone
could ‘sample’ – one needed the skills to not only represent each individual ‘track’ or
‘artist’, but to know how they could fit together into a coherent flow. Yes, some of
the thinkers (samples) Deudney engages with have been engaged with before – but
not in this way, not in this combination, and certainly not in a time period where the
world, and the USA itself, was trying to come to grips with the changing material and
geopolitical contexts which bedevilled the 1990s and 2000s. What comes through in
Deudney’s exegesis and reconstruction is a product with insights that urgently focus our
attention on the stakes of potential violence that republican security theory takes so
seriously.
Daniel Deudney: Bounding Power 251
This chapter engages Deudney’s text, summarizes the core arguments and proposi-
tions of Bounding Power, acknowledges its shortcomings, and assesses its status as a
‘classic’ text of IR. While it is difficult to maintain that Bounding Power is a classic text
in the way that books treated in the previous chapters are, and while other practical
aspects of the work should be commended, it is the methodological contribution of
Deudney’s work that especially deserves our attention – for it is this achievement that
may prove to be Bounding Power’s lasting success.
The book advances this argument through three parts, beginning with Part One,
which advances the main argument and views its ‘relatives and descendants’. A second
part, ‘From the Polis to Federal Union’, cross-examines republican security theory as
explicated from various thinkers beginning in antiquity (Greek and Roman), extending
through works on European republicanism, and ending in the founding of the USA.
Part Three, ‘Toward the Global Village’, begins by examining the various insights on
world government provided by Kant and Publius, Scottish Enlightenment thinkers, and
early twentieth-century writers like H. G. Wells and John Dewey. The book concludes
with two chapters examining world government in both a nuclear age and a ‘global
village’ context.
Thus, Deudney brings us back to the interplay between materials and ideas, between the
physique of political violence and the minds which shape its use, purpose and context.
In addition to these necessary and creative combinations of seemingly opposing
binaries, Deudney once again demonstrates what we have come to expect as his sig-
nature conceptual contribution to IR theory – the role of technology on security (and
vice versa), a contribution that goes back to at least his seminal works from the 1990s.9
Deudney casts technology as a material context just like geography – and, like different
geographic formations, a development that is not socially constructed but ‘discovered’.
The role of technology in security arrangements comes through most vividly in Chap-
ter 7, in the book’s exegesis of H. G. Wells and John Dewey. It was not the former’s
predictions that prove useful for Deudney, but rather the emphasis by Wells on the
transformations – good and bad – that technology was bringing (or would bring) about
in global politics. Of Dewey, Deudney explicates the role in which technology (specifi-
cally the industrial revolution) was altering (in Dewey’s time) notions of community
and extending an ‘industrial public’, an alteration which governments and policy-
makers had yet to catch up to. However, even today, technology itself has not only
pushed the boundaries of material frontiers, it has transformed our understanding of a
frontier, where science and technology are that frontier, whereby ‘the interaction
between nature and politics is still open and subject to major change’ (p. 243).
These contributions have been noted by others,10 but the contribution identified in
the Introduction to this chapter – as a stellar methodological example of exegesis and
reconstruction, is the one I would suggest makes Bounding Power such a provocative
but also meaningful work of IR. As Deudney states from the beginning, republican
security theory is ‘formulated in ways alien to contemporary academic social science’,
containing ‘normative, scientific and design claims’ (p. 21). Far from being a unique
approach to politics, this is one which is based in, indeed depends upon, the ‘traditions’
of international theory, those which Deudney assertively characterizes as having per-
sistence and value which ‘constitute almost all of the quite limited set of major insights
about security politics produced by Western political science’ (p. 265). Yet Deudney
develops the exegesis and reconstruction of texts as more than just a practice (one
254 Brent J. Steele
which he demonstrates splendidly throughout the book), via the ‘metaphors of con-
stellations and maps’ in his conclusion (p. 265). The scholar uses this method to
‘assemble’ texts – as Deudney does in this book – into ‘simple pictoral constellation(s)’.
In response to an ‘anything goes’ critique, Deudney informs us that different genera-
tions will pull together different points across these texts into ‘different constellations’.11
The constellation provided by Bounding Power is one which speaks to the present, with
an eye on the future, by combining insights from texts and authors seemingly over-
looked by contemporary international theorists. Deudney’s is, thus, a unique recombi-
nation (or ‘blend’ to connect to my Introduction) of these thinkers, compared to
previous revisitations of the ‘classical’ resources of each tradition. Michael Doyle,
for instance, in his Ways of War and Peace, focused on ‘typical’ philosophical pro-
genitors of realism – such as Machiavelli and Hobbes; and liberalism – such as Kant
(especially), and Locke. Deudney’s construction of these traditions via the ancients, as
well as modern theorists such as Montesquieu, not only draws out a forceful and
novel set of assertions regarding republican security theory – it renders the tradi-
tions of realism and liberalism richer and more complex. And, further, it radically
alters our understanding of different security environments: what produces them,
what they help to produce, and how robust – or fragile – they have been through time. As
an example, Deudney points to the almost radically contingent – rather than inevi-
table – nature of ‘republics’. In his Conclusion, and after having consulted a more
diverse array of thinkers than liberal internationalists have consulted in their works,
Deudney precisely captures the concluding function of this philosophical ‘constellation’:
Republican union, not only as a form of government but as a practical security fra-
mework, prevented the USA from suffering the same hierarchically implosive fate as
other republics (such as the Roman), and, further, allowed ‘republics to attain the size
and thus security previously only available to despotic empires’ while keeping intact
notions of ‘liberty’ and popular sovereignty. The key was that a too-small republic
risked its own survival (a result of anarchy); a too-large republic risked despotic rule
(radical hierarchy). Instead, republics like the USA were both still around, and powerful
enough, to ‘protect smaller liberal democracies’ during the conflicts of the twentieth
century. As a result, ‘security through federal union, not peace among democracies, has
been the most important security fact for free polities over the last two centuries’ (p. 270,
emphasis added).
I might also expand on the insight, personally and intellectually, which I found to be
the most provocative and useful contribution of Bounding Power – namely, its critique
of the Kantian origins of liberal international theory and its pragmatic and useful
provision of restraint. Several scholars of my generation have reacted to some of the
more strident applications of ‘Wilsonian’ internationalist policies of the past decade by
seeking refuge largely within what Deudney would call the post-WWII generation of
classical realist writings, marshalling insights from those works to formulate particular
Daniel Deudney: Bounding Power 255
critiques of the liberal-idealist policies of especially the USA and the UK. Inspired by
reinterpretations of the works of Niebuhr, Morgenthau and Herz in particular,12 I once
entitled this movement ‘reflexive realism,’ which I defined as ‘the attempt to restore
classical realist principles … to provide a practical-ethical view of international poli-
tics’,13 and in another co-authored study characterized it as consisting of ‘a broad and
pluralistic cadre of efforts to (re)convene discussions about realism’s philosophical and
humanistic roots and the practical issues that engrossed the progenitors of the field’.14
The point in identifying this trend was not that it was the first occasion (nor the last)
when scholars engaged and utilized insights from classical realists. Rather, the point
was that there was something about the application of classical realist insights in the
2000s that seemed particularly pointed, focused, and even urgent. For myself, it was the
realist focus on restraint as a form of prudence, whereby ‘being prudent means to
restrain from the use of force even on occasions when such force could easily be
employed’, which seemed a potentially useful (although, admittedly also elusive) tonic
to the hyperreactive tendencies of a US polity seeking to grapple with the anxious
‘global war on terror’ environment following the 9/11 attacks.15 The proposal here was
on how the self of a polity could promote a practical principle of restraint, a principle
made possible, however, through self-discipline. Cian O’Driscoll, commenting on simi-
lar assumptions pervading international society and jus ad bellum in the early twentieth
century describes this as empowering ‘states to gauge for themselves the rights and
wrongs of any particular use of force that pertained to their interests. This was an
approach … that stressed the “self” in self-limitation, self-judgment, and self-help’.16
Yet, O’Driscoll exposes in one line the drawback to any proposal – or ethos – which
emphasizes self-restraint, it has been at times ‘exposed as a catastrophe waiting to
happen’, during episodes such as World War I, or in the face of any modern crisis or
adversity (such as transnational terrorism, for instance).17
It is here that Deudney’s proposal for ‘restraint’ republicanism, the ‘bounding’ of
power itself, is so useful. Deudney focuses our attention on the many ways in which
negarchy might develop and expand its political-structural restraint, a restraint that is
both material and political-strategic. Deudney’s republicanism, thus, puts forth not just
principles to be executed through republican practices, but material facts and contexts
such as ‘nature as it presents itself for human activity’ which serves as both enabling and
restraining factors of violence: ‘Global technological interdependence has altered the scope
of interaction and hence number of humans and human groups among whom restraint
of violence is necessary for security’ (p. 274, emphasis added). It should be noted that
some of the most persuasive ‘reflexive realist’ works, especially towards the end of the
2000s were those which also drew out the republican themes of classical realism, and
the restraint made possible by changes in material-technological contexts.18
Shortcomings
With a book so complex, rich, analytically rigorous but stylistically argued, it is hard to
detect too many shortcomings, especially this soon after Bounding Power’s publication.
Time will tell how influential the proposals of the book will be, for both the study and
practice of global politics. That said, others have identified some would-be problems in
the text, ones which after the past decade of US foreign policy would seem to require
urgent attention. William Scheuerman has a particularly vivid critique of Deudney’s
text – for all its merits, it may actually reproduce, in an ‘America-first’ fashion, a
256 Brent J. Steele
‘nationalistic’ version of world government.19 Scheuerman points out that Deudney’s
reading of the Philadelphian system is ‘tendentious,’ serving to cherry-pick the favour-
able attributes at the expense of the rather unfavourable, and even dark, history of the
period. In one borderline incendiary charge, Scheuerman notes:
The built-in restraint of this system rested on a form of ‘states rights’, and an individual
lauded by Deudney for intellectually defending negarchical structures – John C. Calhoun – is
rightfully noted by Scheuerman as one of ‘the intellectually most impressive southern
defender[s] of states’ rights (and slavery)’.21
This particular criticism of Scheuerman’s is correct, of course, but it also feels a bit
strained. Deudney’s proposal for negarchy is an attempt to take particular aspects of past
republican security arrangements and suggest their use in restraining violent practices
in contemporary global politics. If one were to think that such arrangements in a con-
temporary context would throw out the baby with the bathwater – that slavery would
immediately return with a global version of the Philadelphian system – then this criticism
would seem more persuasive. We might further note that the same system and indivi-
duals that Deudney lauds were also commended in the same way by some of the same
realists that Scheuerman defends, like Morgenthau for example.22 Finally, Scheuerman’s
criticism would also be persuasive if we failed to notice what Deudney himself discloses
in his Preface, namely that ‘as an American writing about a significantly American
topic, I am animated by American anxieties (shared by many non-Americans) about
America’, and Deudney notes that these include the way in which the US Republican
party ‘expends its formidable energies in an at-times hysterical … war against domestic
public welfare government, but largely ignores (or even embraces) the far more omi-
nous (at least from the founders’ standpoint) national security state that necessity and
opportunity led the Americans to construct over the last half-century’ (p. xiii).
However, Deudney does not, admittedly, confront this ‘anxiety’ as directly as he
might have throughout the text, and thus what Scheuerman’s overall critique does open
up are two of what I would call missed opportunities found in Bounding Power. These
missed opportunities represent how the argument could have been extended to confront
concerns like Scheuerman’s. What Scheuerman is calling for is a more interrogative
engagement, it seems, of the US polity’s past. Thus, the book’s propositions regarding
the republican security practices – especially their role in restraining both radical
extremes of anarchy and hierarchy – could have contributed a more chastened view of
US history to ongoing debates over neoconservatism, a perspective celebrating the
founding of the USA and its history as a republic.23 On a few occasions, Deudney does
make passing reference to neoconservatism as a strand of Wilsonianism – and points
out, briefly, Wilsonians’ inadequate grasping of the ‘republican security logic behind
the American Liberal internationalist project and the central role violence inter-
dependence plays in it’ (p. 186).
One of the core insights of republican security theory is that the answer to anarchy is
not hierarchy, but negarchy, a more stable form of ordering because of its built-in
Daniel Deudney: Bounding Power 257
mechanisms of mutual restraint. This is one missed opportunity of Bounding Power, as
this argument is in some ways 180 degrees at odds with neoconservatism’s view of the
USA’s leadership role in a world that hijacks US ambitions and confronts the gravest
threats in ‘slow motion’.24 Indeed, when reading Bounding Power, one thinks of Michael
Williams’ closing remark in his seminal 2005 article on neoconservatism and IR theory,
that ‘IR possesses resources within its theoretical traditions that provide a basis for a
direct and critical engagement with neoconservatism at its very foundations’.25
Republican security theory, especially as it is rendered by Deudney, surely provides us a
lot of fuel for just such a rigorously critical and intellectual engagement of neoconser-
vatism. However, Deudney does not directly confront neoconservatism, and it leaves
him open to the types of charges levelled by Scheuerman. While one cannot engage
everything that is ‘out there’ in the field of international theory, engaging neoconser-
vatism more directly would have demonstrated what I find to be a significant distinc-
tion between Deudney’s proposal and one which fails, according to Scheuerman, to
‘rais[e] the necessary critical questions about the deeply ambivalent and by no means
consistently beneficial role of the United States in foreign affairs in the last century’.26
A similar lack of engagement with the English School represents another missed
opportunity for extending Bounding Power’s arguments into other ‘International
Theory’ perspectives. As with neoconservatism, Deudney does have a few direct and
indirect assessments of English School theory (p. 159). Yet, considering Hedley Bull’s
proffering of an ‘anarchical society’, and that, furthermore, his assertion that the great
powers were the ‘custodians’ of this international society and its rules,27 there appears
to be some overlap with Deudney’s views of negarchy. For instance, it would have been
interesting to consider how negarchy might be considered not only as a ‘negation’ of
both anarchy and hierarchy but as an ordering arrangement set along the so-called
international system-international society-world society ‘triad’ of the English School.28
The debates in the English School over how societies form – the so-called Gemeinschaft
versus Gesellschaft formation of international societies – and how they disintegrate can
also be linked with Deudney’s recognition of the fragility of global arrangements of
mutual restraint. While the English School discusses how societies form, it might be
aided by Deudney’s thesis that changes in technology (such as the Industrial Revolu-
tion leading up to World War I) represent forms of violent interdependence that
threaten to unravel those arrangements within a short period of time.
Alas, the engagement with either neoconservatism or the English School does not
occur here, and so is left to others to take Deudney’s argument and critically assess
these two perspectives. In this way, both of the shortcomings represent heuristic
opportunities for current and future IR theorists.
If global nuclear material controls are weak, states will be compelled to increas-
ingly penetrate civil society with controls. If global nuclear material containment is
strong, then Liberal states will be able to stay Liberal … to an unprecedented
extent, the preservation of domestic liberty comes to hinge upon the success in
abridging international anarchy (p. 262).
In this passage, and throughout this impressive work, Deudney captures one of the
final messages of Bounding Power – the value of republican security theory’s promotion of
restraint – not only in suppressing the ‘evil urges’ of others, but by constraining our
own tendencies to overreact to the phantasms of those possible urges with ones of
our own.
Daniel Deudney: Bounding Power 259
In the years and decades that follow its recent appearance on the scene of IR theory,
scholars may debate Deudney’s work with regard to a variety of the book’s features –
especially how he arrives at some of these conclusions via his particular readings on,
and combinations of, theorists. While it is a safe bet that its resurrection of republican
security theory will not only be regarded as an important historical and theoretical
feat, it may also be considered a proposal that only suggests and intimates how con-
temporary and future generations might make the world more secure in the future. Yet,
what I have suggested in this chapter is that the contribution of a text to IR rests not
only (or solely) in its practical application to contemporary problems, but also in the
exemplary demonstration of a method – in this case reconstruction and exegesis –
which has for too long gone unappreciated and unvalued in IR. Thus, the immediate
value of Daniel Deudney’s Bounding Power lies in its testimony to the ability of a
scholar who can take theory and thought, whether centuries-old or contemporary in
their inception, and remix, reformulate and craft them so that they refocus our atten-
tion on global politics – its past and its present – in novel ways.
Notes
1 Daniel H. Deudney, Bounding Power: Republican Security Theory from the Polis to the
Global Village, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2007. Page numbers placed in
parentheses in the text refer to this edition.
2 On how the engagement of texts can take on meanings outside of what was intended by the
original author, see Richard Ned Lebow, The Tragic Vision of Politics, Cambridge: Cam-
bridge University Press, 2003, Chapter 2.
3 The term ‘collage’ is Murray Forman and Mark Anthony Neal’s, That’s the Joint! The Hip-
Hop Studies Reader, London: Routledge, 2004, p. 75.
4 Deudney only engages it on occasion, but Onuf ’s classic work on the topic is perhaps the
best-known of these treatments: Nicholas Onuf, The Republican Legacy in International
Thought, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998.
5 Available at: http://scholar.google.com/scholar?q=bounding+power+deudney&hl=en&btnG=Sear
ch&as_sdt=1%2C5&as_sdtp=on (accessed 17 April 2012). Alexander Wendt, Social Theory of
International Politics, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999, by comparison (and
published eight years earlier), has over 3,300 citation ‘hits’ on the same search engine.
6 Casper Sylvest, Political Studies Review, 2007, vol. 5, 440; Bryan Mabee, Millennium, 2008,
vol. 36, 651–53; Chris Brown, Political Theory, 2008, vol. 36, 647–50.
7 The other two were Joshua S. Goldstein, War and Gender: How Gender Shapes the War
System and Vice-Versa, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001, and Bruce Russett
and John Oneal, Triangulating Peace, New York: W. W. Norton & Company, 2000.
8 The binary is presented in detail in Wendt’s Social Theory, especially Figure 1 (p. 29), which
is a take on Hollis and Smith’s Explanation and Understanding in International Relations,
Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1991.
9 See especially his ‘Geopolitics and Change’, in Michael Doyle and John G. Ikenberry (eds),
New Thinking in International Relations Theory, Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1997, pp. 91–127.
10 See especially Bryan Mabee’s review noted above.
11 Kratochwil, in a seminal article which discusses the way in which we defend ourselves against
the ‘anything goes’ charge, posits that ‘[i]nstead, warrants are provided or defeated by the
inter-subjective defensibility of the assertions made in our arguments’, Friedrich Kratochwil,
‘History, Action and Identity: Revisiting the “Second” Great Debate and Assessing its
Importance for Social Theory’, European Journal of International Relations, 2006, vol. 12,
5–29, at p. 7.
12 Some examples include Michael C. Williams, The Realist Tradition and the Limits of Inter-
national Relations, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004; Michael C. Williams (ed.),
Realism Reconsidered, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007; Anthony F. Lang, Agency and
Ethics, Albany, NY: SUNY Press, 2002; Lebow, The Tragic Vision; Vibeke Schou Tjalve,
260 Brent J. Steele
Realist Strategies of Republican Peace: Neibuhr, Morgenthau and the Politics of Patriotic
Dissent, New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2008; Casper Sylvest, ‘Realism and International
Law: The challenge of John Herz’, International Theory, 2010, vol. 2, 410–45.
13 Brent J. Steele, ‘“Eavesdropping on honored ghosts”: From Classical to Reflexive Realism’,
Journal of International Relations and Development, 2007, vol. 10, 272–300, at p. 273.
14 Andrew R. Hom and Brent J. Steele, ‘Open Horizons: The Temporal Visions of Reflexive
Realism’, International Studies Review, 2010, vol. 12, 271–300, at p. 271.
15 Steele, ‘Eavesdropping on honored ghosts’, p. 278.
16 Cian O’Driscoll, ‘Just War in the Twentieth Century’, in E.A Heinze and B.J. Steele (eds),
Ethics, Authority, and War: Non-State Actors and the Just War Tradition, New York: Palgrave
Macmillan, 2009, emphasis added.
17 O’Driscoll, ‘Just War in the Twentieth Century’, 26.
18 In this vein, Tjalve and Sylvest’s works, noted above, deserve special mention.
19 William E. Scheuerman, ‘Deudney’s Neorepublicanism: One-world or America first?; Inter-
national Politics, 2010, vol. 47, 523–34.
20 Scheuerman, ‘Deudney’s Neorepublicanism’, p. 531.
21 Scheuerman, ‘Deudney’s Neorepublicanism’, p. 531.
22 See the opening paragraph to H.J. Morgenthau, ‘The Mainsprings of American Foreign
Policy’, American Political Science Review, 1950, vol. 44, 833–54, specifically that the ‘poli-
tical wisdom’ of the commonwealth of the USA was found in the ‘first generation of Americans’,
many of whom, if we were taking Scheuerman’s argument whole cloth, were slave-owners
themselves.
23 This topic is finally getting a rigorous treatment by IR theorists: Michael C. Williams, ‘What
Is the National Interest? The Neoconservative Challenge in IR Theory’, European Journal of
International Relations, 2005, vol. 11, 307–37; and Brian C. Schmidt and Michael C. Williams,
‘The Bush Doctrine and the Iraq War: Neoconservatives versus realists’, Security Studies, 2008,
vol. 17, 191–220.
24 These are John Bolton’s words describing the problems with the ‘multilateral diplomatic
course’ that the USA tried to utilize in confronting the ‘seriousness’ of the Iranian nuclear
‘threat’. John Bolton, Surrender Is Not an Option, New York: Simon & Schuster, 2007, p. 314.
25 Williams, ‘What Is the National Interest?’ p. 327
26 Scheuerman, ‘Deudney’s Neorepublicanism’, p. 532.
27 Hedley Bull, The Anarchical Society, New York: Columbia University Press, 1977, p. 17.
28 See Tim Dunne, ‘The English School’, in Tim Dunne, Milja Kurki, and Steve Smith (eds),
International Relations Theories: Discipline and Diversity, 2nd edn, Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 2010, pp. 148–49.
29 This is a play on the title of the first chapter of Bruce Russett, Grasping the Democratic Peace,
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1993.
30 Two unrelated examples can be seen in Thomas Friedman’s The World Is Flat, New York:
Farrar, Straus, and Giroux, 2005, and Richard N. Haas, ‘The Age of Nonpolarity: What Will
Follow U.S. Dominance?’ Foreign Affairs, 2008, vol. 87, 44–56.
31 Deudney distinguishes this modified approach to ‘classical one worldism’ near the end of
Bounding Power. Whereas classical one worldism ‘assumed that nuclear weapons had shifted
the scale of state formation processes’ the ‘modified diagnosis is that nuclear weapons, com-
bined with the general increase and diffusion of violence capability [to non-state actors, for
instance], have greatly reduced the problem of interstate aggression, while creating a new
threat of general annihilation’ (p. 258).
26 Conclusion
Henrik Bliddal, Casper Sylvest
and Peter Wilson1
In closing, it is fitting to begin where the last classic presented in this volume left off. In
the conclusion to Bounding Power, Deudney writes:
Traditions are composed of distant luminaries, great intellectual figures of the past
whose works are perennially burning lights that can be observed but never chan-
ged. Acts of reading and interpreting assemble illuminating texts into various
constellations by ‘connecting the dots’ into a simple pictoral constellation.2
Surely Deudney wrote these words in a different context, but if we think of Interna-
tional Relations (IR) as a tradition, albeit today a highly diverse one, this volume has
also sought to ‘connect the dots’. As we see it, the works appraised here represent some
of the brightest stars in the firmament of IR. Not everyone will agree with our parti-
cular mapping of it, and some scholars, including the authors of some of the classics
covered, might reject the very notion of an IR firmament. We see our job, however, not
in terms of the presentation of a definitive case but to further the debate about which
works should be considered IR classics, and what this particular status means – for the
work, the author and the discipline.
Mappings of the discipline are unavoidable. Some might find this regrettable, but we
believe that this practice, if carefully undertaken, is essential to the health of the field.3
As Deudney continues, ‘[w]e draw these pictures to make our world more intelligible
and, like mariners at sea or shepherds in the wilderness, to help tell us where we are
and how we might travel safely to where we want to be’.4 Nevertheless, we need to be
careful not to fix our constellations too firmly and to be prepared periodically to
redraw our charts. After all, stars fade away or implode, and shooting stars burn out.
We may have also misjudged the brightness of some and failed to spot others. In short,
we intend this book to be the beginning of a new engagement with classics of the dis-
cipline, not the end. In this spirit we offer two sets of concluding observations. First, we
reflect upon the characteristics of the classics we have uncovered in this book. What
makes these works stand out in importance? No single pattern or ‘recipe’ can be
detected, but there are some important commonalities. This leads to our second pur-
pose: a brief discussion of the future of the classic work in IR and the social and
intellectual factors likely to influence its fate.
262 Henrik Bliddal, Casper Sylvest and Peter Wilson
Some observations about classics of IR
If the essentialist understanding of what makes a classic in literature (see Introduction)
held sway well into the twentieth century, an essentialist understanding of what makes
a classic of IR prevailed even longer. This may come as a surprise to those new to the
field given the increasingly wide acknowledgement in social studies of the absence of a
transhistorical and/or transcultural basis for making truth claims. However, works such
as The Twenty Years’ Crisis, Politics Among Nations and Man, the State and War were
held by many to be classics well into the 1980s because they captured timeless truths
about international life, lifting the veil of moralism, progressivism and liberal wishful
thinking that shrouded the harsh realities of an anarchical international system.5
Today, it is likely that all but a few would accept the sociological conception of the
classic; in other words, a classic is a work widely considered to be a classic within any
given social setting or community. An IR classic, certainly, is a work deemed to be
seminal or exemplary in some way. It is a work that has exerted influence and in
many cases continues to do so. It may be a work widely considered to be pivotal in
some given movement of thought. Often, most simply and powerfully, it is a work
deemed to be an intellectual landmark. All these notions are wrapped up in our
understanding of a classic.
In his chapter about Waltz’s Theory of International Politics, Wivel offers five
tongue-in-cheek rules on how to write a classic. Of course, it is not that easy. No
simple or even complex formula exists. Indeed, one could begin by pointing out the
conditions that do not appear necessary. One does not need to be a gifted or ima-
ginative writer pouring forth elegant prose and/or fine turns of phrase on every
page – though clearly this quality has been no hindrance to the longevity of Woolf ’s
Three Guineas, Carr’s The Twenty Years’ Crisis or Beitz’s Political Theory and Inter-
national Relations. One does not need to be widely read, either generally or in acade-
mia – just being thought of as a classic within a certain cultural or intellectual milieu
might suffice, as is the case with Mitrany’s Working Peace System or Aron’s Peace
and War. One does not have to be useful to policy-makers, although a work such
as Jervis’s Perception and Misperception certainly is useful. One does not need to
share the humility of an Aron, Bull or Jervis, even though it would surely be bene-
ficial to most people if they walked away from a book with ‘a slightly deflated (or at
least, a less inflated) ego’, an effect Shiping Tang in his chapter attributes to Perception
and Misperception. One does not need to produce a text that is popular in the class-
room, though Bull’s Anarchical Society and especially Morgenthau’s Politics Among
Nations became best-selling student texts almost immediately on publication, nor
does one need to devise a great teaching aid, though Kubrick’s Dr. Strangelove and
Morris’s Fog of War are often used in this way. One does not need to be as intel-
lectually bold or adventurous as Waltz with Theory of International Politics or
Walker with Inside/outside; circumspection can be an advantage too, as Aron’s Peace
and War and Keohane and Nye’s Power and Interdependence illustrate. Some of these
characteristics may be important, but none of them are necessary and certainly not
sufficient for creating a classic of the field. So beyond the near-truism that an IR
classic is a work deemed by the IR community to be in some way seminal, exemp-
lary or pivotal, is it possible to identify any commonalities among the works discussed
in this volume that make them stand out?
Conclusion 263
The centrality of the questions
One common denominator of the classics presented in this book is that they ask fun-
damental questions about international politics. In the Introduction, we identified a set of
concerns and phenomena – war, peace, power, the state, international law, order, jus-
tice, diplomacy, anarchy and sovereignty – around which such questions have traditionally
revolved. Of course, the specific nature of this questioning depends on the learning and
intellectual imagination of the various authors, which has led to questions that we did
not know we ought to ask before someone asked them. For example, in their chapter
Hyde and Henry make a powerful case that Enloe’s Bananas, Beaches and Bases has
done exactly that. The same might be said of that other work of gender and the inter-
national featured in this volume, Woolf ’s Three Guineas, as argued in Wilson’s chapter.
It is remarkable that the quality, and perhaps the staying power, of a classic work of
IR is often determined not by the particular answers given but by the questions and the
way they are asked, structured or presented. In Frost’s chapter on Peace and War for
example, Henry Kissinger is quoted to the effect that ‘Mr. Aron does better than give
us answers – he teaches us which questions are significant’. Answers to specific ques-
tions will change over time, as circumstances change and new factors emerge. Some key
works of IR, however, have raised questions that have barely changed for decades. One
example concerns the effect of formal and informal networks of interdependence on
patterns of inter-state cooperation and conflict, as asked by Keohane and Nye.
Another example is the way in which Waltz, in Man, the State, and War, organized and
explored three levels at which the causes of war had been located in the history of
political thought – at the level of the individual, the states or the system. Schmidt
contends in his chapter that ‘it is incredibly difficult to imagine how IR would have
evolved if he had not written this book’. In short, the centrality of the questions to our
quest to understand the human condition matter. This is also why some classics did not
make their mark upon release and why some may have been forgotten but later redis-
covered. Their questions and particular answers may not have seemed relevant to many
at the time but they matter at the time of their rediscovery. Works such as The European
Anarchy and Three Guineas fall into this camp; not, it should be added, because their
answers command universal assent, far from it, but because the questions they asked
and the way they framed them was ahead of their time.
Notes
1 We would like to thank Manuel Almeida, Peter Marcus Kristensen and Brian Schmidt for
their comments on an earlier draft of this chapter.
Conclusion 269
2 Daniel H. Deudney, Bounding Power: Republican Security Theory from the Polis to the
Global Village, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2007, p. 265.
3 For a valuable recent exchange on the virtues of mapping the field in terms of ‘isms’ see
David A. Lake, ‘Why “isms” Are Evil: Theory, Epistemology, and Academic Sects as Impe-
diments to Understanding and Progress’, International Studies Quarterly, 2011, vol. 55, 465–80;
and replies by Rudra Sil and Peter Katzenstein, and Henry Nau, in the same issue.
4 Deudney, Bounding Power, p. 266.
5 The irony here of course is that the first two of these works contain forceful expositions of the
situatedness of historical and political knowledge, as Peter Wilson and Nicolas Guilhot
demonstrate in their chapters, which cast doubt on the possibility of ‘timeless’ historical or
political truths.
6 See Peter Wilson, ‘Where Are We Now in the Debate about the First Great Debate?’, in
Brian Schmidt, International Relations and the First Great Debate, London: Routledge, 2012,
pp. 133–51; and many of the chapters in Nicolas Guilhot (ed.), The Invention of International
Relations Theory, New York: Columbia University Press, 2011.
7 Ole Wæver is the source of this observation (personal correspondence with Henrik Bliddal,
August 2012).
8 See e.g. Robert Adcock, Mark Bevir and Shannon C. Stimson, ‘A History of Political Sci-
ence: How? What? Why?’, in R. Adcock, M. Bevir and C. Stimson (eds), Modern Political
Science: Anglo-American Exchanges since 1880, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press,
2007, pp. 1–17.
9 See Ole Wæver, ‘Still a Discipline After All These Debates?’, in T. Dunne, M. Kurki and S.
Smith (eds), International Relations Theories: Discipline and Diversity, Oxford: Oxford Uni-
versity Press, pp. 297–318.
10 This is exemplified by the use of classics by countries new to IR to prime themselves on the
nature and state of the game. For the use of IR classics for this purpose in China since 1979
see Qin Yaqing, ‘Why Is there no Chinese International Relations Theory?’, International
Relations of the Asia-Pacific, 2007, vol. 7, 313–40.
11 Wæver, ‘Still a Discipline’, pp. 311, 314. The notion of ‘The End of International Relations
Theory’ was a noticeable theme at the 2012 ISA Annual Convention (San Diego, 1–4 April)
and the 2012 Joint BISA-ISA International Conference (Edinburgh, 20–22 June), where the
editors of one the discipline’s flagship journals – The European Journal of International
Relations (EJIR) – ran several panels on this theme (see e.g. www.uk.sagepub.com/ejt2012.sp
(accessed 17 December 2012)). The papers of the panelists, all prominent figures in the dis-
cipline, are likely to be published in EJIR during 2013. Cf. also Chris Brown, ‘IR Theory in
Britain: The New Black?’ Review of International Studies, 2006, vol. 32, 677–87.
12 See Arlene B. Ticker and Ole Wæver (eds), International Relations Scholarship Around the
World, London: Routledge, 2009, particularly the Introduction and Conclusion. See also
Stanley Hoffmann, ‘An American Social Science: International Relations’, Daedalus, 1977,
vol. 106, 41–60; Yaqing, ‘Why Is there no Chinese International Relations Theory?’ 315–26.
13 Ole Wæver, ‘The Sociology of a not so International Discipline’, International Organization,
1998, vol. 52, 687–727; Marijke Breuning, Joseph Bredehoft and Eugene Walton, ‘Promise
and Performance: An Evaluation of Journals in International Relations’, International Studies
Perspectives, 2005, vol. 6, 447–61; Tickner and Wæver, ‘Introduction: Geocultural Epis-
temologies’, in Tickner and Wæver, International Relations Scholarship around the World,
London: Routledge, 2009, pp. 1–31.
14 See Simon Head, ‘The Grim Threat to British Universities’, The New York Review of Books,
13 January 2011.
15 Research Information Network, Communicating Knowledge: How and Why UK Researchers
Publish and Disseminate their Findings, London: RIN, 2009, p. 5; see also Laura Brown,
Rebecca Griffiths and Matthew Rascoff, University Publishing in a Digital Age, Ithaka, 2009.
Available at: www.ithaka.org/ithaka-s-r/strategyold/Ithaka%20University%20Publishing%
20Report.pdf. Again, this is not a universal pattern. See Tickner and Wæver, ‘Conclusion:
Worlding where the World once Was’, in Tickner and Wæver, International Relations Scho-
larship around the World, London: Routledge, 2009, pp. 328–41.
16 Few submissions make it through to publication in these journals today without substantial
revisions, and a standard format is developing: introduction to subject; review of literature;
270 Henrik Bliddal, Casper Sylvest and Peter Wilson
identification of problem; method for solving problem; solution; suggestions for further
research; extensive notes and/or references. Increasingly, daring, unconventional or adventur-
ous works do not make it into print as they fall short of high standards of proof required by
most referees.
17 In the case of Carr, the gestation period began with Versailles (see Peter Wilson, ‘Carr and his
Early Critics: Responses to The Twenty Years’ Crisis, 1939–46’, in Michael Cox (ed.), E. H.
Carr: A Critical Reappraisal, London: Palgrave Macmillan, 2000, p. 185). In the case of Bull
it began with his work on The Control of the Arms Race (London: Weidenfeld & Nicolson,
1961) and his involvement (also from 1961) in the British Committee on the Theory of
International Politics (see Tim Dunne, Inventing International Society: A History of the Eng-
lish School, London, Macmillan, 1998, pp. 89–115).
18 See Wæver, ‘Sociology of a Not so International Discipline’. Moreover, flagship journals of
the discipline also tend to reflect epistemological and geographical divides in the discipline.
See Richard Jordan, Daniel Maliniak, Amy Oakes, Susan Peterson, Michael J. Tierney, One
Discipline or Many? TRIP Survey of International Relations Faculty in Ten Countries, Wil-
liamsburg, VA: College of William and Mary, 2009; Barry Buzan and Ole Wæver, ‘After the
Return to Theory: The Past, Present, and Future of Security Studies’, in Alan Collins (ed.),
Contemporary Security Studies, 2nd edn, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010, pp. 463–83.
19 See e.g. Stephen van Evera, ‘Director’s Statement: Trends in Political Science and the Future
of Security Studies’, MIT Security Studies Program: Annual Report 2009–2010 (2010).
20 See e.g. the remarks on Aron in Bryan-Paul Frost’s chapter in this volume, and John H. Herz,
‘The Relevancies and Irrelevancies of International Relations’, Polity, 1971, vol. 4, 25–47.
21 Wæver, ‘Still a Discipline’, p. 297.
Index