Philosophy in Germany Critchley Honneth

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 13

Philosophy in Germany

Simon Critchley and Axel Honneth

SC: Simply as a way of initially organizing our discussion, we both agreed to read a short
article by Dieter Henrich that appeared in Merkur in his philosophy column, ʻEine Generation
im Abgangʼ (ʻA Passing Generationʼ).1 Henrich rightly claims that a change of generations
is coming to an end in German philosophy, which is most clearly marked by the retirement
of Jürgen Habermas in 1994 and the death of Hans Blumenberg in 1996. But we might also
speak of a wider generational change that would include Karl-Otto Apel, Ernst Tugendhat,
Michael Theunissen and Niklas Luhmann, as well as figures like Otto Poeggeler and Robert
Spaemann. Almost all of this generation are now retired, and it is at the moment unclear who
and what will take their place.
As Henrich explains, the oldest and the youngest of this generation are only separated by
about fifteen years, and most of then came out of three philosophical schools – Bonn, Münster
and Heidelberg. Gadamerʼs name, and his brand of urbane Heideggerianism, should also be
mentioned in this postwar conjuncture, although he precedes the generation we are talking
about. Before moving on to the question of how the contemporary philosophical scene looks
in Germany, we might perhaps begin with Henrichʼs description of what the ʻpassing genera-
tionʼ had in common. First and foremost, despite their obvious philosophical and ideological
differences, what they shared was a common context: the overwhelming presence of the trauma
and catastrophe of National Socialism. Thinking of Habermas, if one reads a fascinating
early piece from 1961 on ʻDer deutsche Idealismus der jüdischen Philosophenʼ (ʻThe German
Idealism of Jewish Philosophersʼ), it reveals the postwar philosophical ambition to reconcile
Jews and Germans.2 But Henrich puts the issue in the following terms:

With these considerations in mind one has really understood what the first task of young
philosophers in postwar Germany had to be: essentially they worked in order to maintain
or restore the worldwide credibility of thinking in the German language. Alongside music,
philosophy was for a long time the most significant cultural export good of Germany. Since
Kant, German philosophy has distinguished itself through a basic style of investigation that
always ended in a synthesis in answer to questions of principle, limit and life. 3

To this demand for synthesis, we might also add the requirement of universalism and the
method of rational argumentation. So it would seem that it is through a rationally achieved
synthesis with a universalist scope that German philosophy responds to the catastrophe of
National Socialism; and this is combined with an overwhelming fear of relativism and irra-
tionalism, which always seems to go together with the fear of reducing the wissenschaftlich
(ʻscientificʼ) character of philosophy, or the reduction of philosophy to what Henrich calls
ʻLiterarisierungʼ (ʻmaking literaryʼ). In your view, is this a fair characterization of German
philosophy in the postwar period?

AH: Yes, I think it is to a certain degree, but maybe it is not broad or differentiated enough.
As is indicated by the Habermas article you mentioned, there was not only the search for the
restoration of a certain kind of credibility; there was also from the beginning among some
of that postwar generation the ambition to address and clarify the moral disaster of National
Socialism. There was therefore not only the attempt to regain the great German tradition
in the sense of the Kantian heritage but also to regain or overcome the separation from the
Jewish tradition, which was highly specific and extremely important for the whole of German

Radical Philosophy 89 (May/June 1998) 27


philosophy at the beginning of the century. This was not only an enterprise of Habermas, but
others too, who attempted to reconstruct the specifically Jewish element in German philosophy.
If you take the example of someone like Michael Theunissen, he spent a lot of energy in his
first major work – the book on the Other – reconstructing the work of Martin Buber, and that
was intentional.4 It was meant to overcome the separation between the Jewish tradition and
the German situation after the Second World War. This is something totally excluded from
the picture given by Henrich.
The other thing that he underestimates is, let us say, the moral dimension of the early
period of German philosophy after the Second World War, after the disaster or catastrophe.
This is something best described by Karl-Otto Apel in a famous article which I strongly
recommend.5 There Apel describes his own enterprise – namely, the search for a universal
ground for moral principles of respect and autonomy – as a response to, and a clarification
of, the moral dimension of the disaster. So there was also the moral dimension in that whole
postwar period, and this is also not clearly enough indicated by Henrich. That is very closely
connected with people in Bonn. I mean, if you take the three universities mentioned by Henrich,
then one should be careful to differentiate between these places. For example, it is interesting
that in Münster from very early on – the middle of the 1950s I think – there were several
people trying to come into contact with Carl Schmitt. It is hard to explain why suddenly, in
a group of younger people, there was this interest in the work of Schmitt when they were all
aware that he had been deeply involved in the fascist juridical administration. These people
were no longer connected to the fascist world; they were trying to be liberals, democratic
liberals. I think one can explain this interest in Schmitt because he was the only one who
participated in fascism who never publicly regretted having done so. This made Schmitt quite
singular because all the others – Gehlen and even Heidegger – were either silenced by their
involvement, or very quickly became converts to the new regime. So, to complicate Henrichʼs
picture, this interest in Schmitt at Münster, which came out of the circle of Joachim Ritter,
led to a very fruitful, although not unproblematic, relation to the prewar past. All I want to
say is that Henrichʼs picture is not differentiated enough. I think it is rather simplistic to say
that the main ambition of postwar German philosophy was to regain credibility; there were
so many other motives, moral motives. There was also the motive of finding oneʼs place in a
culture increasingly influenced by the United States. One should not forget the continuation
of the Heideggerian tradition to an incredible degree in the postwar period. In Bonn, where
Habermas and Apel were students, the influence of Heidegger was striking. Habermas and
Apel started as what we might call left Heideggerians. If one adds these additional elements
to Henrichʼs picture, then I think it is basically correct.

SC: OK. But what about the desire for synthesis that Henrich talks about. Does this define
the postwar period of German philosophy?

AH: Yes. I think what was still very important, and almost seen as self-evident in that period,
is that any philosophical enterprise requires synthetic power. I wouldnʼt reduce that requirement
uniquely to Kantʼs philosophy, as it is a very traditional idea of German philosophy that you
have to construct your own system. You have to find your own theory, your own philosophical
position. This was a requirement not explicitly formulated but deeply internalized. So it was
true that almost all the main figures in the generation we are speaking of had the strong
belief that they had to formulate their own systematic philosophical position during the next
ten or twenty years. This was indeed as it has been in the prewar period, where you had
Husserl or Nikolai Hartmann or Heidegger; where you not only had philosophical teachers
and professional philosophers, but strong philosophical positions connected to specific persons.
Each one stood for a whole programme, and you could describe the philosophical landscape
with reference to persons who represented clearly demarcated positions, discrete forms of
synthesis. It was clearly understood that in order to find your own synthetic position, your

28 Radical Philosophy 89 (May/June 1998)


own new and original position, you had to rework the philosophical tradition. Originality was
the requirement both before and after the war.

The present generation


SC: Let us now turn to the present situation. At the end of Henrichʼs article, he makes the
following observation. First: that the generation that is now coming to an end achieved a
remarkable international notoriety, and worldwide recognition. This is most obviously the
case with Habermas, but also with Henrich himself and Apel and others. But what of the
present generation?
Henrich is extremely critical of the generation that followed his own – your generation
– and indeed alludes to a kind of analytic–continental split in German philosophy, between
what he sees, rightly or wrongly, as a kind of Derridean playfulness and endless paraphrase
on the one side, and an early Putnamian analytic narrowness on the other – what Henrich
sees as a bad professionalism. Henrich goes so far as to say that the ʼ68 generation brought
up under Adenauer are ʻturnshoesʼ, and is rather pessimistic as to whether philosophy can
avoid the double threat of Literarisierung on the one hand and narrow professionalism on
the other. He writes:

If one takes note of the connections I have tried to develop, then it is self-evidently neces-
sary to ask the question as to whether the generation of German philosophers who are now
taking up their places will be able to bring about a beginning with long-term effect, or
whether they can simply be understood as a distant reverberation of the Weimar Republic
in the radically changed conditions of the postwar period. An effective break in motiva-
tional history [Motivationsgeschichte] would then first enter onto the scene with those who
were born after the war, in Adenauerʼs Federal Republic. It might be able to explain why
the surprising success of postwar German philosophy in the wider world finds no continua-
tion for the time being.

Is Henrich right? Is your generation so bad? Is this description at all justified?

AH: That is also a very complicated question. To start with the last sentence, the fact that the
younger generation of philosophers – the middle generation letʼs say – born in the 1940s and
early 1950s has not gained such an international reputation or recognition is also due to the
fact that it was only after the 1970s that the Anglo-Saxon colonization of the philosophical
world began. This situation was something that the earlier generation was not really confronted
with. In that time, I would say, there was a kind of multicultural situation in philosophy, albeit
a multiculturalism restricted to the Western world. What I mean is that there were strong
influences from France on the philosophical agenda in the 1950s and 1960s. Sartre had an
incredible influence; French existentialism was one of the main positions at that time. And
Merleau-Ponty was famous and widely read. Thus, it was not a situation in which there was
a clear hegemony of one tradition: Anglo-Saxon philosophy. So it was maybe a little easier
at that time, and the chances of gaining international respect were higher, as well as having
cross-national contacts, influences, etc. So that is the first remark I would like to make: that
today, under these new conditions where it is obviously the fact (and I donʼt want to judge
this fact) that the analytic tradition is hegemonic, it is much more complicated for people
from other countries easily to gain that kind of international respect.
The other remark would be directly concerned with Henrichʼs description. I think to a
certain degree he is right, but maybe it is more complicated to explain why that is the case.
I think it is right to say that there is a new tendency to a kind of bad professionalism in
German philosophy. If you look at what normally happens in the big meetings of the German
Philosophical Association, it is extremely boring, and to a certain degree that is because
of professionalism. I donʼt even see that there are many tendencies towards what he calls
Derridean playfulness. I donʼt really see that in philosophy. Maybe it has a bigger role in
other disciplines or in other areas, but not in philosophy. But what Henrich is underestimat-
ing, I think, and characteristically underestimating, is that in the 1960s when this generation

Radical Philosophy 89 (May/June 1998) 29


received their main influences in philosophy as students there was a new motivation emerging,
of which he is not really aware. It is perhaps not surprising that he is not aware of it because,
as far as I know, Henrich reacted negatively to what took place in the ʼ68 student movement
– namely, that new questions came up which together formed a horizon of motives for younger
philosophers. Clearly, the main motive was for the first time a really sharp awareness of the
fact that oneʼs own parents – fathers, sometimes mothers – had collaborated in fascism. This
was the experience of that generation, I think, and you can still see it in some of the small
philosophical enterprises where it functions as a kind of background motivation. I must say
that the other strong motive is something beyond Henrichʼs horizon – the whole question of
what Habermas is now calling, in the title of his latest book, Die Einbeziehung des Anderen
(The Inclusion of the Other).6 This is the fact that others are not only playing the role of
citizens, but are there in very different roles; that the other has many faces; that it is more of
a task to acknowledge or recognize these other spheres of the other. The whole problem of
the other is something that was new for that generation. Maybe the title of Theunissenʼs book
already indicated that task, but it became a very strong force behind a lot of the writings of
the 1960sʼ generation, as a background cultural motivation.
The other background motivation I would mention is the problem of freedom, which is
obviously the main issue of the ʼ68 movement. We might speak here of the ambivalences of
liberalization. What I mean is the fact that freedom is something more radical than seen in
earlier times; that freedom is also about cultural roles, sexual roles, gender roles, which is
something that this generation created and explored. And I think this also goes some way to
explaining why, at the beginning of the 1970s and 1980s, there were still some philosophical
figures of my generation who tried to create original work of a synthetic character, who were
either ignored by the system, or who became more or less integrated into it, but continued along
the same route. To mention one name: Andreas Wildt, who never got a university position,
who came originally from Dieter Henrich, and then was an assistant of Michael Theunissen.
He wrote a very interesting book on Hegel and Fichte in this synthetic tradition, which is an
extremely powerful reinterpretation of the practical philosophy of Hegel and Fichte with the
aim of creating a kind of moral philosophy aware of the non-legal relation to others.7 This is
only an example. It is meant to indicate that Henrich is right in his description of the present
generation, but that he is ignoring some stronger energies in that generation which either had
the chance to survive the last fifteen years – fifteen years of high professionalization and a
boring development in German philosophy – or were repressed by the philosophical system
and the philosophical establishment. He is simply overlooking the fact that the philosophical
establishment ignored some of the creativity of the ʼ68 movement.

SC: Is there a philosophical establishment in Germany? If so, how would you characterize
it?

AH: Yes, there definitely is and it is typical that people like Habermas, Apel, Theunissen
and Tugendhat never belonged to that establishment. There is an establishment, the members
of which are not even very well known in the outside world, who are mainly professionals
doing their ordinary jobs, writing more or less interesting or boring books, but who had
something like the power of academic philosophy in their grasp. And they are to a certain
degree responsible for the fact that more creative persons never had a chance. Take Peter
Sloterdijk, who at the outset was quite an interesting philosopher, who very early on wrote
an extremely interesting article on Foucault, and then published his book on the Critique of
Cynical Reason.8 Maybe if he had had a chance in the philosophical system, he wouldnʼt have
gone in the direction he is now going – namely, a kind of wild journalism.

SC: You have already begun to answer my next question, which concerns the Motivations-
geschichte of contemporary German philosophy. If the motivation of the postwar generation
was found in a response to the moral disaster of National Socialism, then the question that
Henrich raises concerns the motivation for your own generation. You have answered this

30 Radical Philosophy 89 (May/June 1998)


question in terms of the problem of freedom, the questioning of established orders, and,
tangentially perhaps, the whole issue of power. Let us push the logic of Henrichʼs position
a little further. What Henrich seems prepared to admit – which is an extremely interesting
and un-English thought – is that there has to be some sort of almost traumatic motivation to
philosophizing; that philosophy comes out of, and tries to make good on, a traumatic situa-
tion. If one were looking for a recent historical event in Germany that might provide such a
motivation to philosophizing, then one would obviously think of ʼ89: the Wende. Now maybe
it is just too soon to tell what is going to happen, if anything, and whether the changes in
Germany will have intellectual consequences. Of course, one persuasive diagnosis of what
happened in the philosophical profession after ʼ89 is a complete philosophical takeover of the
East by the West, which is obviously to do with the peculiar character that philosophy had
in the ideological superstructure of the former DDR – that is, its strongly Marxist-Leninist
orientation. Do you think that what took place was simply a takeover? And do you think
anything will come out of the reunification of Germany as a historical event in terms of a
possible motivation for philosophy?

AH: Yes, without hesitation I would even use the word colonization to describe what took
place in the former DDR. I think it was a takeover. It has to do with the fact that there is
a philosophical establishment in the West which was not sensitive enough in the period of
reunification towards creative potentialities in the DDR. I mean that there were people who
were intellectuals, creative, quite original, but not established. They were forced to write in
another kind of language, not that of Western professionalism. I think it would have been
better not simply to introduce our professional standards into that new situation, but to open
the standards to other forms of talent and other potentialities; or at least try to integrate
those people into the new university and economic system. But that was never really tried.
In that sense it was a colonization process on both the administrative and intellectual level.
Philosophy in the DDR was simply assimilated. I canʼt really say whether the experience of
ʼ89 is a kind of motivational force which could lead to a new kind of philosophical original-
ity. At the present time, I donʼt see anything like that happening. Maybe there are some new
Jörg Immendorff, Café Deutschland 1, 1978

Radical Philosophy 89 (May/June 1998) 31


discussions, once again, about how to respect the other, if you understand the former DDR
as the other of our own society. And there are some quite interesting debates which try to
apply the multiculturalism controversy to exactly that situation. But I donʼt see that it is really
a kind of new horizon which has been opened up by that experience. It has to do with the
fact that nobody experienced reunification as a kind of traumatization. It wasnʼt a traumatic
experience. Maybe it will become a traumatic experience for those from the East who had no
chance to survive as philosophers or as intellectuals after reunification.
And let me say something else about this whole idea of Motivationsgeschichte: I think it
is very interesting to use that kind of concept. I think it is quite different from the self-under-
standing of philosophy in the analytical world and runs against all forms of professionalism.
Henrich seems to be convinced that there must be extra motivation behind serious philosophy.
I think thatʼs true. At least it is true for the German tradition, where traumatic, or letʼs just
say deep, experiences provide the motivation for the creative synthesis of which he speaks.
The clearest case is German Idealism and Romanticism. It is clear that the experience of the
French Revolution in Germany was the kind of experience that Henrich has in mind. And
the same is true for the First World War, which was a traumatic experience for philosophers
like Heidegger. So the question again is whether the fact that there was not something like a
deep negative experience in the background and education of my own generation leads to a
kind of philosophical emptiness. Although, as I have already said, I think that my generation
had its own background motivations which were not negligible.

SC: Of course, the curious thing about trauma is that traumatic neurosis often has a delayed
effect, it is always nachträglich. If you look at the last fifty years of German history, there
was the trauma of the postwar generation, the generation born before the war, that studied
in the postwar years and then, in Henrichʼs words, tried to restore the credibility of German
philosophy. But what is interesting about postwar German history is that the trauma took
a generation to begin to be worked through, so that it is the ʼ68 generation that in a sense
feels the trauma and is visited by the sins of the fathers, where the Holocaust only becomes
a significant national issue from the 1960s and a dominating issue in the 1970s. So, in a
sense, whether the Wende will become traumatic for the following generation is still an open
question. But let us go on to our second topic.

German philosophy, Anglo-American hegemony and


Franco-German (mis)understanding
SC: For me, it has been an odd but interesting experience being in Frankfurt over the past
year. Although I have felt increasingly compelled in recent years by the first generation of
the Frankfurt School, a lot of my work, as you know, has been concerned with contemporary
French philosophy – in particular, the work of Derrida and Levinas, but more generally with
post-Heideggerian phenomenology. This brings me to the question or the relation of phil-
osophy in Germany to other traditions – in particular, the strongly contrasting relation to the
Anglo-American and French contexts, where the complete acceptance of the former seems
to be predicated upon steadfast refusal of the latter.
I think it would be genuinely surprising to many people concerned with philosophy in the
English-speaking world how utterly much contemporary German philosophy is dominated
by the Anglo-American agenda. In metaphysics, epistemology and philosophy of mind and
language, it is difficult to see any substantial difference between what passes for philosophy
in Germany and what a student might expect to find in a mainstream syllabus in Britain.
The currency of philosophical exchange is the names of Davidson, Quine, Putnam, Bernard
Williams, etc., and there is a considerable interest in post-analytic philosophers like Taylor
and Rorty. And many of the younger German students I have met have little knowledge of
the German tradition, with the exception of Kant and elements of German idealism. During
my time at Frankfurt, no courses were offered on phenomenology, whether Husserlian or
Heideggerian; not to mention the absence of Dilthey, the hermeneutic tradition, and obviously
the complete absence of French philosophy, with the complex exception of Foucault. For me,

32 Radical Philosophy 89 (May/June 1998)


this was both surprising and slightly saddening. Thus, for the visitor from the English-speaking
world, philosophy in Germany is characterized by a certain shock of the familiar. On the other
hand, two things are on offer in Germany that a student could not expect to find in Britain:
the philological tradition of textual study; and also, more importantly, the tradition of social
philosophy, which is more or less absent in the UK. We might like to discuss this later.
However, this is not my point, for what is interesting is that there is a complete openness
to everything that comes out of the English-speaking world, and to what Henrich calls an
Englischen gewonnene Argumentationskultur (a culture of argumentation won from the
English); whilst there is a complete blindness and antagonism to the French philosophical
scene. Again, Henrich is revealing in this regard, for he makes the contrast between the need
for ʻsolid argumentationʼ and ʻevidenceʼ, and the French tendency, which he characterizes in
terms of the identification of philosophy with literature and the domination of the masters
of suspicion – Marx, Nietzsche and Freud.9 Of course, one can find many similar statements
in Habermas, even in his most recent texts.10 Such statements are symptomatic, I believe. Do
you think that the openness to Anglo-American philosophy has been achieved at the expense
of a relative blindness to the French tradition? And how do you see this geo-philosophical
picture? What does the French tradition represent for the postwar generation of German
philosophers? To my mind, it seems to play the role of a memory of a German tradition no
longer acceptable in Germany, a tradition allegedly compromised by fascism. In this sense,
French philosophy is a sort of ʻreturn of the repressedʼ for German philosophy. How do you
see this complex set of issues?

AH: Let me start with the last point. I do not think it is totally fair to describe the role of
post-structuralism or deconstructivism as being only a kind of repressed memory of the
German tradition. That is simply not true, because it underestimates the strong impact that
Heidegger still has on German philosophy. I think that what you say may be true for Frankfurt,
and especially true for Habermas. But it is not a fair picture of the philosophical situation in
Germany. You shouldnʼt forget that not only in Freiburg but in many places – Heidelberg and
Tübingen, maybe in Munich or Berlin – the role of Heidegger is still quite dominant and is
even growing today. One philosophical consequence of the situation after ʼ89 was a kind of
broad rehabilitation of Heidegger. So in many ways matters are the reverse of the way you
claim. The fact that Habermas is still criticizing a certain Heideggerianism is a result of the
growing influence of Heidegger in Germany. The whole vast enterprise of the publication of
Heideggerʼs Gesamtausgabe is an indication, an objective indication, of that fact.
I think the more significant fact today is the ever-growing influence of Anglo-Saxon phil-
osophy in Germany. To explain that, I think it is necessary to remember that when we started
studying philosophy (and now I am talking about members of my own generation), the German
university was in most places, with very few exceptions – Frankfurt being one, Heidelberg and
Berlin others – utterly dominated by the philological tradition. My own experience, when I
started studying philosophy in Bonn, was that this was an extremely boring kind of philosophy:
thousands of lines interpreting Kant again, or Hegel, or maybe Aristotle, or the whole grand
tradition in a kind of endless repetition. This is a style of philosophy which is still quite present
today and sometimes not really seen from outside because it is so boring. Factually speaking,
I am sure that we have more literature on Hegel than any other philosophical culture in the
world. But our literature on Hegel is, I would say, simply more boring than that produced in
the United States today. We have a strong tradition of philological expertise and excellence,
a style which finds its highest expression in Gadamer, because he is brilliant at producing
philosophical arguments by reinterpreting classical texts. But normally what is going on is
a kind of philological exegesis which leads, I would say, to no significant systematic results.
So that is the background you have to be aware of in order to understand why a lot of
members of my own generation, and especially parts of the younger generation, are very
attracted by the Anglo-Saxon style of argumentation. It at least produces a kind of philosophical
atmosphere in which arguments count; in which you have to produce arguments; and in which

Radical Philosophy 89 (May/June 1998) 33


you can have fruitful discussions about where arguments lead. In a philological culture, there
are no debates like that at all.

SC: So, you are saying that analytic philosophy in a German context has had an emancipa-
tory effect.

AH: Yes, exactly. It emancipated us from extremely boring teachers, and is still emancipating
us from them. Even if you look at our own department in Frankfurt, you can see how fruitful
it can be to learn a little bit of the Anglo-Saxon tradition in order to get rid of these boring
people who are repeating one sentence after the other without making any point. The conse-
quence of this, and I think that you are right, is a certain and still growing underestimation of
the French tradition, which I would not reduce (as Henrich does) to a kind of playfulness or
reduction of philosophy to literature. This is simply an unfair description of what has happened
in French philosophy in the last fifty years. It is an underestimation of the phenomenological
tradition, which is still extremely lively, powerful and fruitful in France. I think it is true that
this type of French philosophy is getting lost today in Germany.
The fact that there has been no fruitful dialogue with French philosophy during the last
twenty years is more difficult to explain. I think to a certain degree it is a result of a very
unfruitful period in German philosophy during the last ten or fifteen years, where Habermas
produced a picture of French philosophy as being nothing other than a kind of playful literature.
This seems to have had the consequence that in the end nobody really took it seriously, and
Henrich is simply repeating what Habermas is saying. I simply think Henrich is no longer
aware of what is going on in France. So I reckon that Habermasʼs intervention has had a very
damaging effect and placed the Franco-German relation under the heading: irrationality versus
rationality. I think this is a fruitless dualism. It means that we are now in a situation in which
this kind of dialogue has been interrupted. Of course, there are exceptions; and it is interesting
to see that in some analytical areas of German philosophy an interest in Sartre is growing
again – for example, in the work of Peter Bieri. That is, Sartre is being understood and taken
seriously as a philosopher of subjectivity. With respect to Henrich, this is interesting because
it is his disciples, like Manfred Frank, who are taking Sartre seriously.

SC: Sartre is also an exception in Britain, where he is the so-called continental philosopher
who has most often been taught on philosophy syllabuses, and whose concerns seem to have
been closest to analytic philosophy. This has often struck me as a curious state of affairs
which is premissed on simply not reading Sartreʼs later work.
But I would like to pick up again on the question of social philosophy in a slightly rounda-
bout way. Listening to what you said about the emancipatory function of analytic philosophy
in Germany, I think we find ourselves in an oddly paradoxical cultural situation. For your
generation of philosophers educated in Germany, the fact that the reading of analytic phil-
osophy had an emancipatory effect contrasts strongly with the experience of that generation of
British philosophers (like me) who rather awkwardly call themselves ʻcontinentalʼ or ʻmodern
Europeanʼ, or whatever. In Britain, for good or ill, theories were imported from France and
Germany in order to confront the perceived cultural irrelevance and apolitical neutrality or
conservatism of the analytic tradition. So we find in Britain and Germany precisely opposing
philosophical resources being employed for the same emancipatory goal, which is an odd situ-
ation. Perhaps the philosophical grass is always greener on the other side of the cultural fence.
But what I would like to emphasize here, which is not properly understood in Germany, is that
the interest in continental philosophy often goes together, with certain striking exceptions, with
a broadly leftist concern for the social, cultural and political function of the philosopher. This is
supported by the British cultural fantasy of the continental intellectual as that person who can
address their culture, who speaks out of a public culture, and who speaks to a public culture,
who is socially and politically engaged, etc. And this fantasy opposes another – namely, the
image of English philosophy as being insulated from cultural and political concerns, hidden

34 Radical Philosophy 89 (May/June 1998)


away in the secluded beauty of Oxbridge colleges. I should emphasize that all of what I say
in this connection is articulated at the level of cultural fantasy.

AH: Let me say something about social philosophy, because it is an intellectual field that
allows philosophers to play the role you just referred to. I think this is one really specific
element of the German tradition which to a great extent has to do with the Jewish influence
on the German tradition. I would say it is a kind of Jewish-German heritage and it starts,
I think, with German Idealism, especially in Hegel, but also in Fichte, if you think of how
some of the latterʼs writings are concerned with a diagnosis of his times. This tradition stems
from a Protestant movement, but then goes over to a secularized Jewish culture in Marx and
from that time has been part of the philosophical heritage in Germany. If you take people like
Georg Simmel or Martin Buber, or the early sociologists in Germany; if you take Benjamin
and Adorno; then this is something that I would describe in a very broad sense as social
philosophy. And there are even other influences which come together in this connection:
some of Max Schelerʼs writings offer a diagnosis of the time we are living in. So this is a
heritage which was quite powerful and which to a certain degree could survive, and is still an
important element of German philosophy in those places that are not dominated by a kind of
empty professionalism. In this connection, I would mention also Theunissen, who at a certain
period was doing nothing that one would call social philosophy; obviously Habermas; but also
a Catholic philosopher like Robert Spaemann, who I think is doing a kind of social philosophy,
in so far as he is offering a kind of critical understanding of certain social pathologies in
our present society. Although he would describe himself as a philosopher of language and
morality, Ernst Tugendhat could be understood as a social philosopher in this sense. So this is
a very important element of German philosophy and I would think it is one of the main tasks
of the younger generations to keep this tradition alive. If Henrich is right, if the situation of
my generation is really torn between empty professionalism and a kind of empty playfulness,
then the tradition of social philosophy would die out, and that would be dreadful.

What is critical in contemporary Critical Theory?

SC: That brings us neatly to our third and final topic. For if there is a tradition where social
philosophy is maintained, it is the intellectual tradition and school associated with the city
in which we are having this conversation, namely Frankfurt. One has become accustomed to
speak of three generations of Critical Theory: that of Adorno, Horkheimer and Marcuse as the
first, and that of Habermas and Apel as the second. One also speaks, much more nebulously,
of a third generation, the most prominent member of which would be yourself.
But there is an interesting philosophical question for me in how the Habermasian impulse of
Critical Theory is to be continued, or not continued, supplemented or whatever. To my mind,
there are two possible routes being taken both here in Frankfurt and elsewhere. One of these
would see Critical Theory become part of mainstream political philosophy, what I would call
a sort of ʻleft Rawlsianismʼ – a tendency that would seem to be exacerbated by Habermasʼs
recent work on legal theory. The other route is to adopt the Habermasian discourse ethics
framework as offering a powerful theory of justice, but to claim, as you do, that it overlooks
the whole Hegelian dimension of the dialectical struggle for recognition, and in particular
what you call the first level of recognition – namely, the question of the private sphere, of
the development of the subject, questions of love, the family, or whatever. Before we go any
further, despite the interpretative violence of what I have said, does this sound like a fair
representation, in terms of these two routes?

AH: Yes, I think it is a fair description. But I would see more than you in the implications
of these two routes. The first route, which you describe more or less as ʻleft Rawlsianismʼ, to
my mind does entail a definitive end to the tradition of Critical Theory. It no longer really
represents the broader aims of that philosophical culture or school, because it would mean

Radical Philosophy 89 (May/June 1998) 35


that Critical Theory is introduced into mainstream political theory or political philosophy and
would then give up its own identity. Maybe this is not a mistaken development. I do not want
to say it is wrong. I only want to say that this route would lead to the end of the tradition of
Critical Theory. But maybe that is a fruitful result; maybe that tradition is over. Maybe it is
simply an artificial aim to try to continue the tradition of Critical Theory, to continue it in a
world that has not only radically changed both socially and politically, but which has also been
transformed philosophically. Maybe it was even Habermasʼs indirect and unstated intention
to indicate in his later writings that this tradition canʼt be artificially kept alive any longer.
We should therefore combine the best elements of this tradition with mainstream political
philosophy and defend some stronger theory on this new terrain – what you would call ʻleft
Rawlsianismʼ. So this is one possible development. My only point is that it would no longer
make any sense to speak of this development in terms of Critical Theory.
The other route, which I would see myself as espousing, is to maintain and keep open
some of the broader ambitions of Critical Theory. I would call that a philosophically informed
social theory, which means that we are interested not only in describing or criticizing certain
important injustices of our society, but also in certain pathologies of our society. And I would
say that the main ambitions of the first generation of Critical Theory can be understood in that
way, even the extreme interest in art which is common to Adorno, Benjamin, Marcuse and
even Horkheimer. I take it that the link between art and social pathology is that the former
can be seen as a kind of representational medium of the latter, or is a medium that is to some
extent free of these pathologies. Art is a placeholder for social pathologies.
So I would say the only chance we have to keep the tradition of Critical Theory alive is
to continue that kind of enterprise – namely, the social-philosophical enterprise of a kind of
diagnosis of our present culture, the pathologies of that culture, of a certain capitalist culture.
And that means a great deal; I mean it requires a lot of philosophical work. So I think your
description is right, and yet the consequences of these two directions are more radical than you
allow. The first route entails a dying out of the Critical Theory tradition; the second involves
the ambition to keep it alive. I donʼt want to suggest that it is easy to keep that tradition alive,
but I think itʼs the only chance we have if we want to do it.

SC: You have already begun to answer a related question that I wanted to pose, but let me
specify this a little further. It has become something of a truism to say, as I have heard you
say yourself, that Critical Theory moves between the poles of Kant and Hegel, recalling the
famous Kant oder Hegel debates of the 1980s. Now, in terms of the two routes I delineated,
one way of looking at what I call ʻleft Rawlsianismʼ is in terms of an increasingly Kantian
development in Critical Theory, whereas the other route could easily be seen to represent a
much more Hegelian tendency. So Critical Theory moves between the poles of Kant and Hegel.
But the question that I want to come back to, which was suggested by Elliot Jurist, is the issue
of what is critical in Critical Theory. If it moves between the poles of Kant and Hegel, then
what role do the three great ʻmasters of suspicionʼ continue to play in the project of Critical
Theory? Marx, Freud and Nietzsche: each of these thinkers, in distinct and nuanced ways, plays
an organizing function in the first generation of Critical Theory, most obviously in Adorno.
What role do the critiques of capital, of bourgeois morality and primacy of consciousness,
continue to play in the project of Critical Theory?

AH: That, I think, has to do with how one describes these two possible routes that Critical
Theory can take today. If it takes the Kantian route, then I think you would be right that the
masters of suspicion would no longer play an important role, perhaps with the exception of
Marx. Even the Habermas of contemporary legal theory is still very aware not so much of
Marx as of a Marxist tradition of critical economy. If there is ever to be something like a ʻleft
Rawlsianismʼ, then it would have to be highly influenced by the insights of a Marxist critical
economy. If I speak of the Hegelian route, my understanding of this tradition (which is not to
say it is there in Hegel himself) would include those components you mentioned – namely, the

36 Radical Philosophy 89 (May/June 1998)


critical insights of the Nietzschean and the Freudian traditions. According to my own under-
standing of these matters, if you take a Hegelian route then you have a much more complex
understanding of the subject – that is, a richer account of the motivating drives in a society.
To adopt the picture of social pathologies means to include psychoanalytic components, and
maybe even components of Nietzscheʼs moral psychology. I am acutely aware of that. For
example, if you speak of recognition you canʼt be so naive as not to see the negative side of
it, which Nietzsche was aware of when he spoke of resentment. I think you have to broaden
out the moral psychology of Critical Theory, and you can do that only by incorporating
Freudian and Nietzschean elements. Taking the Hegelian route seriously would sooner or
later mean including the task of incorporating insights of that critical tradition. So I would
say that it is only the consequence of the present situation that these elements are not really
strongly enough represented.
But in describing the picture in the way you do, I think you underestimate the fact that
Critical Theory is not only represented by Habermas and his disciples. Even here in Frankfurt
there are other groups, other philosophers, who try to keep that critical tradition alive in a
more powerful way. If you think of somebody like Gunzelin Schmid Noerr, who is responsible
for the collected edition of Horkheimerʼs work, then I think he is now doing serious and
interesting work on Nietzscheʼs moral psychology and keeping that tradition alive within
Critical Theory.11 So my hope would be that in taking a Hegelian route, which for me does
not mean reducing Critical Theory to the enterprise of political philosophy defined by liberal
principles of justice, Critical Theory would include elements of tradition you mentioned and
keep alive the memory of Freud and Nietzsche.

SC: But do you think the language of pathology is sufficient to capture what you are after?
I suppose I have a rather naive problem with the language of social pathologies in so far as
pathology would seem to imply a dysfunctional behaviour. What I mean is that the language of
pathologies always seems to presuppose some normative conception of how these pathologies
might be overcome, or normalized – that is, that we could correct the social dysfunctioning
and return to a fully integrated Lebenswelt.

AH: I guess I think you canʼt do it without the language of pathologies. And even in Adorno
and Horkheimer, and especially Marcuse, although they would never talk of normal life or
normal society, the Critical Theory of society presupposes some vision of a society that
would exclude the sorts of damage they describe. So this kind of normative underpinning of
an enterprise like the critique of social pathologies is always there. I am fully aware of the
difficulties of the notion of pathologies, especially its roots in the quite complicated history
of which Foucault was most acutely aware: the deeply ambivalent history of normalization.
In this sense, pathology was mainly a conceptual means for creating or excluding subjects.
On the other hand, I simply donʼt have a better word for describing what Nietzsche was doing
when he described nihilism not only as a fruitful starting point for oneʼs own enterprise, but
also as the disastrous situation of European culture. Or what Freud was doing in his more
sociological writings in describing the situation of this present culture. I think one way to
approach this would be to describe such analyses as a diagnosis of social pathologies. Maybe
there are better words, but I would say that the task remains the same even if you find a
better word to describe it.

SC: Let us go to the last set of questions. If we (according to you) maintain the Hegelian
impulse in Critical Theory – that is (according to me), maintain the critical impulse in Critical
Theory – then the question this raises has to do with the nature of the philosophical task. I
would, first, want to assume against Rorty that there is a task for philosophy, and that this
task cannot be reduced to the business of literary criticism and journalism (not that these
are such bad things). What I mean is that critical impulse of Critical Theory – and not just
Critical Theory, but also in my view phenomenology and deconstruction – was always linked,
and rightly to my mind, to the emancipatory function of philosophy. Critique and utopia were

Radical Philosophy 89 (May/June 1998) 37


two ends of the same piece of string, in the sense that the critical impulse is maintained in
relationship to a utopian, transformative, emancipatory hope for thinking and for the world.
Now the first issue would be whether you agree with that, whether there is a philosophical
task and how the philosophical task of critique is linked to the question of emancipation and
the utopian element in Critical Theory. And the second question, if one accepts that, is how
the question of emancipation changes the philosophical task. What I mean by this is that
it seems to me that one of the things that the Frankfurt tradition inherits from Marx is a
certain conception of the poverty of philosophy. That is, if philosophy is going to be in the
business of reflecting upon what prevents and enables human emancipation, then it has to be
linked – essentially – to non-philosophy, whether we conceive that as sociology, aesthetics,
psychoanalysis or whatever. How do you see this set of issues?

AH: That is a most complicated question.

SC: Thatʼs for sure, which is why I asked it. Let me restate it more directly and slightly
nostalgically: how do you understand the relation between philosophy and praxis?

AH: I would like to answer in two steps. As a first step, I would simply like to say that even
the more conventional tasks of philosophy – for example, conceptual clarification of structures
of our practical behaviour – are kinds of emancipation. I think it would simply be nonsense
to say that philosophy in this sense is not internally linked to a kind of human emancipation,
if you understand emancipation as a process in which we gain autonomy by clarifying our
own as yet unknown dependencies and the elements of our situation. In that respect, this is a
kind of Habermasian answer: namely, that all philosophy represents a kind of emancipatory
interest of the human species.
But I think you have in mind a more restricted notion of emancipation, namely social
emancipation, and in that respect I also strongly believe, against Rorty, that there is a task
for philosophy today because there is no other place, and there is no other theoretical or
intellectual medium which allows us, with a certain intention of universality, to reflect on
systematic deficiencies of our own culture, our own society. I think it is wrong to say, as Rorty
does, that this is only a task for literature. It is clear that you can understand literature in such
a way, as a kind of medium for violations, deficiencies and ruptures of our life.

SC: For example, if we think of Rortyʼs rather good discussion of George Orwell.12

AH: Right. You could even say all literature is of that kind. It reflects or imagines or demon-
strates, by means of aesthetic mediation, those deficiencies, ruptures or traumas of everyday
life. But by definition that kind of literature is extremely subjective, and is meant to be so. It
is only fruitful as long as it represents an extremely radicalized subjective perspective on those
deficiencies. The question is: are there places, are there mediums, are there intellectual spaces,
in which we together as members of a society have the chance to find justifiable articulations
of those deficiencies? And I must say that the social sciences, which maybe in the beginning
played more or less that role, can no longer do so because of an excessive professionalization.
So I think this task goes over to philosophy. I think there has been a kind of change in the
intellectual division of labour in the last hundred years. If you look at the situation in which
sociology started, if you look to the first generation of famous sociologists – Max Weber, Émile
Durkheim, Georg Simmel – I would say that they started as social philosophers. There was
no really clear differentiation between philosophy and sociology in their work. They started
as theorists interested in a diagnosis of certain deficiencies, pathologies or crises of our own
culture. The professionalization of sociology has led it into other directions – piecemeal work
of a certain kind, very fruitful sometimes, less fruitful sometimes. But it no longer represents
the kind of conceptual space in which you can articulate those common and intersubjectively
articulated crises or deficiencies. So I think this role reverts to philosophy, which is where it
started from originally.

38 Radical Philosophy 89 (May/June 1998)


Itʼs an interesting historical process which you can observe from, letʼs say, Rousseau
until today. Rousseau was a kind of sociologist – his critique of culture is the first moment
of sociology – but he understood himself as a philosopher. Then you have a long period of
philosophy doing exactly that job. I mean that Hegel did that job, but not only Hegel; a lot
of his generation played that role, and we have John Stuart Mill in your own tradition. Then
that role goes over to sociology and was kept alive there for fifty years or so. But since the
Second World War, the professionalization of sociology has been so radical that now I think
it is a very necessary task of philosophy to resume that role. As I said, the role is one of
opening up a conceptual space in which we together can debate certain deficiencies of our
own life-world and culture with at least the hope for universality.

SC: And where would that lead? Wozu, as they say over here?

AH: To the opposite of what Rorty wants. That this task canʼt go over to literature. That there
is a necessary task for philosophy.

SC: So in that sense, if Rorty argues for the subordination of philosophy to democracy, then
you, like me, would want to make the opposite case.

AH: I would argue for a fruitful dialogue between a philosophy of the kind I have discussed
and a democratic culture, a democratic public. It would mean to say that we are the specialists
for the deficiencies of society – that we are, in a sense, the doctors of society. If we want to
be in dialogue with the public, then we cannot only be specialists. I think the whole idea of
subordination is wrong, whether it is a subordination of one type or the other.

SC: So philosophy is an essential moment of democratic reflection.

AH: Exactly. Itʼs a wonderful last word.

Conversation recorded in Frankfurt am Main, 7 January 1998

Notes
Simon Critchley would like to thank Noreen Harburt for her help in transcribing this exchange.
1. Dieter Henrich, Merkur, vol. 49, 1995, pp. 1055–63.
2. Habermas, Philosophisch-politische Profile, Suhrkamp Verlag, Frankfurt am Main, 1981, pp. 39–
64.
3. Henrich, p. 1060.
4. Michael Theunissen, The Other, trans. C. Macann, MIT Press, Cambridge MA, 1984.
5. See Karl-Otto Apel, ʻZurueck zur Normalitaet? Oder Koennten wir aus der nationalen Katastrophe
etwas Besonderes gelernt habenʼ, in Diskurs und Verantwortung, Suhrkamp Verlag, Frankfurt am
Main, 1988, pp. 370–474.
6. Suhrkamp, Frankfurt am Main, 1997.
7. Andreas Wildt, Autonomie und Anerkennung: Hegels Moralitaetskritik im Lichte seiner Fichte-
Rezeption, Klett-Cotta, Stuttgart, 1982.
8. Critique of Cynical Reason, trans. M. Eldred, Minnesota University Press, Minneapolis, 1987.
Sloterdijkʼs early essay on Foucault is ʻMichel Foucaults strukturale Theorie der Geschichteʼ, Phi-
losophisches Jahrbuch, vol. 79, 1972, pp. 161 ff.
9. Henrich, p. 1059.
10. See Habermasʼs almost self-parodic characterization of Heidegger and postmodernism as part of a
critique of the reflexive modernization hypothesis in Beck and Giddens in his 1997 lecture, ʻJenseits
des Nationalstaats? Bemerkungen zu Folgeproblem der wirtschaflichen Globalisierungʼ (unpublished
typescript).
11. In this regard, see Schmid Noerrʼs article on Horkheimer in A Companion to Continental Phil-
osophy, edited by S. Critchley and W. Schroeder, Blackwell, Oxford and Cambridge MA, 1998, pp.
362–9.
12. Contingency, Irony, Solidarity, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1989, pp. 169–88.

Radical Philosophy 89 (May/June 1998) 39

You might also like

pFad - Phonifier reborn

Pfad - The Proxy pFad of © 2024 Garber Painting. All rights reserved.

Note: This service is not intended for secure transactions such as banking, social media, email, or purchasing. Use at your own risk. We assume no liability whatsoever for broken pages.


Alternative Proxies:

Alternative Proxy

pFad Proxy

pFad v3 Proxy

pFad v4 Proxy