The "Ayodhya" Case: Hindu Majoritarianism and The Right To Religious Liberty
The "Ayodhya" Case: Hindu Majoritarianism and The Right To Religious Liberty
The "Ayodhya" Case: Hindu Majoritarianism and The Right To Religious Liberty
net/publication/276353122
The "Ayodhya" Case: Hindu Majoritarianism and the Right to Religious Liberty
CITATIONS
READS
0
14,968
1 author:
Ratna Kapur
Queen Mary, University of London
51 PUBLICATIONS 652 CITATIONS
Some of the authors of this publication are also working on these related projects:
All content following this page was uploaded by Ratna Kapur on 16 May 2015.
Recommended Citation
Ratna Kapur, The “Ayodhya” Case: Hindu Majoritarianism and the Right to Religious Liberty, 29 Md. J. Int'l L.
305 (2014). Available at: http://digitalcommons.law.umaryland.edu/mjil/vol29/iss1/14
ftis Special Issue: Articles is brought to you for free and open access by the Academic Journals at DigitalCommons@UM Carey Law. It has
been accepted for inclusion in Maryland Journal of International Law by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@UM Carey Law.
For more information, please contact smccarty@law.umaryland.edu.
ARTICLE
INTRODUCTION
“Here is a small piece of land (1500 square yards) where angels fear
to tread . . . It is full of innumerable landmines.”
-Justice Sibghat Ullah Khan1
The long-standing contest over a 1500 square yard plot of land,
situated in the city of Ayodhya, located in the district of Faizabad in
the state of Uttar Pradesh in north India, has become a site where
religious groups, pilgrims, lawyers, and even gods are battling to
establish their claims of rightful ownership. The issue has been
simmering in independent India since its birth in 1947 and arose well
before that time. The courts have been called upon time and again to
adjudicate on this fraught issue, where their decisions are not only
defining the parameters of the right to freedom of religion, but are
implicated in the very construction of faith and belief.
† Professor of Law, Jindal Global Law School. This article draws on a shorter
earlier version published in South Atlantic Quarterly. See Ratna Kapur, A Leap of
Faith: The Construction of Hindu Majoritarianism Through Secular Law, 113 S.
ATLANTIC Q. 109 (2014). Earlier versions of this article were presented at the
Politics of Religious Freedom Workshop, supported by Henry R. Luce Foundation,
in December 2011 in Chiang Mai, Thailand; Jindal Global Law School; the NYU
Gallatin School; and Yale Law School. My thanks to all those who provided
feedback and comments on these occasions. I am grateful for the advice, comments,
and criticisms of Peter Danchin, Elizabeth Shakman Hurd, Saba Mahmood, Vasuki
Nesiah, Rajeswari Sunder Rajan, and Winnifred Sullivan. Thanks to Adil Khan for
his invaluable research assistance. Thanks also to Mohsin Alam Bhatt, Aparna
Chandra, Latika Vashist, and Apurva Tripathi for their very able research support.
1. Visharad v. Ahmad, O.O.S., No. 1 of 1989, All. H.C., 4 (2010) (Khan, J.)
[hereinafter Ayodhya]. The Ayodhya Judgment is a consolidation of opinions from
1986 and 1989, and these consolidated opinions may sometimes be referred to as
the “Decision of Honorable Special Full Bench Hearing Ayodhya Matters.”
305
306 MARYLAND JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW [VOL. 29:305
requires a “next friend” to represent the idol in any legal or other proceeding . See,
e.g., Vidya Varuthi Thirthia Swamigal v. Baluswami Ayyar, A.I.R 1922 P.C. 123
(India) (holding that a Hindu deity is a juristic person); Sri Radhakhanta Deb v.
Comm’r of Hindu Religious Endowments, A.I.R. 1981 S.C. 798 (India) (where the
Supreme Court recognized a Hindu deity as a juristic person); Shiromani Gurdwara
Parbandhak Comm. Amritsar v. Som Nath Dass, A.I.R. 2000 S.C. 1421 (India)
(finding the mosque and Sikh scriptures to be juristic persons); Sri Adi
Visheshwara of Kashi Vishwanath Temple v. State of Uttar Pradesh, (1997) 4
S.C.C. 606 (India) (where the court recognized the right of a deity to move the
court in a case involving a challenge to the Kashi Temple Act of 1983).
despite the fact that the case was primarily a dispute about title to
property and not a constitutional matter. I offer a detailed account of
the arguments presented by the respective parties in an effort to
unravel the ways in which the right to freedom of religion as
manifested in the Ayodhya case has long lasting implications on the
meaning of secularism in India as well as on the ways in which
religion itself is shaped and constructed through the discourse of
secularism and the right to freedom of religion.
The struggle over the meaning of the right to freedom of religion
has also involved a struggle over the contours and content of religion.
Quite specifically, it has involved a contest over the meaning of
Hinduism and a battle over what constitutes its core or essential
elements. A number of scholars have located the definition of
Hinduism within the colonial context, arguing that Hinduism is a
colonial construction adopted by the Europeans as a name for the
religions of India towards the end of the eighteenth century. 4 The
constructionists have argued that the attributes of Hinduism were
based on Christian understandings of what constituted religion, and
focused on those properties that were regarded as usually associated
with a religion, that is sacred texts, doctrines and priests. While these
features could be attributed to a Brahmanical tradition, they came to
be imagined as the beliefs and practices of the people of the
subcontinent and formed one pan-Indian religion.
Similarly, in the context of the late-nineteenth and early-
twentieth-century anti-colonial struggles, Hindu nationalists sought to
retrieve an authentic past based on Hindu traditions and practices as
the basis for constructing the identity of the newly emerging Indian
4. See, e.g., Richard King, Orientalism and the Modern Myth of ‘Hinduism,’
46 NUMEN 146, 146 (1999) (arguing that the construction of the concept of
“Hinduism” as a single religion was based on Christian presuppositions); See also
Gauri Viswanathan, Colonialism and the Construction of Hinduism, in THE
BLACKWELL COMPANION TO HINDUISM 1, 23-44 (Gavin Flood ed., 2003)
(cautioning against explaining the idea of Hinduism as a hegemonic religion
exclusively as an outcome of colonial intervention in tradition); David Ludden,
Ayodhya: A Window on the World, in CONTESTING THE NATION: RELIGION,
COMMUNITY, AND THE POLITICS OF DEMOCRACY IN INDIA, 1, 6–8 (David Ludden
ed.,1996) (“Under British rule, ‘Hindu’ became a category for people in India who
were not Muslims, Christians, Sikhs, Jains, Parsis, Buddhists, or others.”). See
generally RICHARD KING, ORIENTALISM AND RELIGION: POSTCOLONIAL
THEORY, INDIA AND “THE MYSTIC EAST” (1999); RETHINKING RELIGION IN
INDIA: THE COLONIAL CONSTRUCTION OF HINDUISM (Esther Bloch et al. eds.,
2011).
nation-state.5 This move was in part an effort to counter the colonial
representation of India as a barbaric and civilizationally backward
society because of its beliefs, practices, and traditions, a move that
simultaneously served as a justification for the continuance of
colonial rule. While there was a Brahmanical collaboration with the
Hindu nationalist movement at the time of independence that led to
the sanskritization, textualization, and unification of so-called Hindu
traditions, what is significant is that this construction was thoroughly
modern in its genesis.6 These contests over the core or essential
ingredients of religion continue to play out doctrinally in law in the
contemporary period through the “essential practices” test.7
This paper is divided into three sections. In the first part, I set out
the constitutional jurisprudence on Indian secularism, briefly
summarizing three significant decisions of the Indian Supreme Court:
the Bommai decision,8 a cluster of decisions collectively described as
political wing of the Hindu Right, following the destruction of the Babri mosque at
Ayodhya in December 1992 and the ensuing communal riots). In Bommai, the
Constitutional Bench of the Supreme Court upheld the validity of the declaration,
and in so doing passed considerable comment on the meaning of secularism in
Indian constitutional life. Id.
9. The Hindutva cases involved a series of challenges to the election of Shiv
Sena (foot soldiers of Shiva) and BJP candidates in the December 1987 State
elections in Maharashtra on the grounds that the candidates had committed corrupt
practices in violation of section 123 of the Representation of the People Act, 1951.
Section 123(3) of the Act prohibits candidates from any appeal to his or her
religion, race, caste, community, or language to further his or her prospect for
election or for prejudicially affecting the election of any other candidate. The
collection of thirteen cases that came before the Supreme Court of India include
Manohar Joshi v. Nitin Bhaurao Pati, (1996) 1 S.C.C. 169 (India); Ramesh
Yashwant Prabhoo v. Prabhakar Kasinath Kunte, A.I.R. 1996 1 S.C. 1113 (India);
Bal Thackeray v. Prabhakar Kasinath Kunte, (1996) 1 S.C.C. 130 (India);
Ramchandra G. Kapse v. Haribansh Ramakbal Singh, (1996) 1 S.C.C. 206 (India);
Pramod Mahajan v. Haribansh Ramakbal Singh, (1996) 1 S.C.C. 206 (India);
Sadhvi Ritambhara v. Haribansh Ramakbal Singh, (1996) 1 S.C.C. 206 (India);
Ramakant Mayekar v. Smt. Celine D’Silva, (1996) 1 S.C.C. 399 (India); Chhagan
Bhujbal v. Smt. Celine D’Silva, 1 S.C.C. 399 (India); Pramod Mahajan v. Smt.
Celine D’Silva, 1 S.C.C. 399 (India); Balasaheb Thackeray v. Smt. Celine D’Silva,
1 S.C.C. 399 (India); Moreshwar Save v. Dwarkadas Yashwantrao Pathrikar, (1996)
1 S.C.C. 394 (India); Chandrakanta Goyal v. Sohan Singh Jodh Singh Kohli,
(1996) 1 S.C.C. 378 (India); Shri Suryakant Venkatrao Mahadik v. Smt. Saroj
Sandesh Naik, (1996) 1 S.C.C. 384 (India).
10. A.I.R. 1995 S.C. 605 (India).
11. Gopal Singh Visharad v. Zahoor Ahmad, O.O.S., No. 1 of 1989, All. H.C.
(India); Nirmohi Akhara v. Baboo Priya Datt Ram, O.O.S., No. 3 of 1989, All.
H.C. (India); Sunni Central Board of Waqfs, U.P v. Gopal Singh Visharad, O.O.S.,
No. 4 of 1989, All. H.C. (India); Bhagwan Sri Ram Virajman v. Rajendra Singh,
O.O.S., No. 5 of 1989, All. H.C. (India). The judgment was delivered in the High
Court of Judicature at Allahabad (Lucknow Bench), on September 30, 2010.
12. Appeals against the High Court decision were filed by all sides of the case,
including Hindu and Muslim organizations, and the Court directed the parties to
decision remains relevant in terms of its ability to influence the
understanding and meaning of secularism in both judicial and popular
discourse.
I. THE JUDICIAL (RE)SHAPING OF INDIAN SECULARISM
Increasingly, the struggle over the meaning of secularism and the
place of religion has been fought out in the legal arena. This section
focuses on three significant Supreme Court decisions that highlight
this contest, including Bommai, the Hindutva cases, and Ismail
Faruqui v. Union of India. The increasing influence of the Hindu
Right, which has become a central player in defining the scope and
parameters of the various components of secularism in law in India,
has exposed how the discourse can be used to advance a majoritarian
political agenda. The Hindu Right consists of three primary actors,
including the Bharatiya Janata Party (BJP) (Indian Peoples Party),
which is responsible for formulating and pursuing the political
agenda of the movement; the Rashtriya Swayamsevak Sangh (RSS)
(National Volunteer Organization), which was established in 1925 to
build a strong Hindu community to counter British rule as well as
Muslim separatism and responsible for developing and expounding
the ideological doctrine of the Hindu Right; and the Vishwa Hindu
Parishad (VHP) (World Hindu Council), founded in 1964 to
popularize the Hindu Right’s religious doctrine and consolidate its
support at a grassroots level. 13 The VHP also includes a militant
youth wing, the Bajrang Dal (Hanuman gang) established in 1984.14
There are several other peripheral players associated with the Hindu
right parties, including the militant and virulently anti-Muslim Shiv
Sena (Foot soldiers of Shiva).15 The movement collectively promotes
the ideology of Hindutva—which posits Hinduism not simply as a
religion but as a nation and a race that is indigenous to India.16 This
maintain the status quo at the site, although it added that the Hindu prayers
currently being conducted at the makeshift temple on the dispute cite could continue
without interference. The stay was granted on the grounds that the High Court, in
partitioning the land, had granted a relief that no party had requested. The decision
is to be listed before a larger bench of the Supreme Court for arguments.
13. Ratna Kapur, Normalizing Violence: Transitional Justice and the Gujarat
Riots, 15 COLUM. J. GENDER & L. 885, 890–91 (2006).
14. Id.
15. Id.
16. See generally JYOTIRMAYA SHARMA, HINDUTVA: EXPLORING THE IDEA OF
HINDU NATIONALISM (2003). See also CHRISTOPHE JAFFRELOT, THE HINDU
NATIONALIST MOVEMENT IN INDIA 27 (1998) (discussing V.D. Savarkar’s
definition of Hindutva as “an ethnic community possessing a territory and sharing
the same racial and cultural characteristics”).
312 MARYLAND JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW [VOL. 29:305
17. Supra note 5. V. D. Savarkar was the ideological leader of the Hindu
nationalists during the struggle for freedom from colonial rule. He later became
leader of the Hindu Mahasabha, a Hindu communalist party that was intensely
involved in the Independence struggle. His writings on Hindutva continue to
represent the ideological foundations of the contemporary Hindu Right. See
SAVARKAR, supra note 5, at 3–4, 92. Savarkar asserted that for Hindus the
fatherland (pitribhumi) and religious land (punyabhumi) are the same. Muslims on
the other hand have their religious fealties elsewhere, (i.e. Mecca) and hence are
not part of the same civilizational fabric. M.S. Golwalkar was an active member of
the RSS, the ideological wing of the Hindu Right. He became the second Supreme
Chief (Sarsangchalak) of the RSS from 1940-1973 and a major exponent of the
ideological doctrine to establish India as a Hindu State (Rashtra). See generally
GOLWALKAR, supra note 5; M.S. GOLWALKAR , BUNCH OF T HOUGHTS 130
(1966) (where he called upon the religious minorities to give up their “foreign
mental complexion and merge in the common stream of our national life.”).
18. See generally TAPAN BASU ET AL., KHAKI SHORTS AND S AFFRON
FLAGS (1993) (discussing the history and political thought of the Hindu Right).
19. The Resolution on Fundamental Rights and Economic and Social Change
was adopted in 1931 in Karachi, which provided: “The state shall observe
neutrality in regard to all religions.” See also Asghar Ali Engineer, Secularism in
India—Theory and Practice, in SECULARISM AND L IBERATION : PERSPECTIVES
AND STRATEGIES FOR INDIA TODAY 38, 44–45 (Rudolf C. Heredia & Edward
Mathias eds., 1995) (“The Indian state, hence could not remain indifferent to
religion, and in the Indian situation secularism would mean equal protection to all
religions so far as the state was concerned.”).
minorities or state support to state recognized religions. This liberal
democratic understanding of secularism does however prohibit state
involvement in the sphere of religion. This model is based on the
assumption that these protections emanate from a neutral state—it
does not acknowledge the presence of majoritarianism as structuring
secularism and thus the position of the state.20
In contrast, since independence, almost all debates on the subject
of secularism have been based on the idea of equal treatment of all
religions (sarva dharma sambhava) within both the public and
private spheres.21 Like the liberal democratic vision of secularism,
22. Brenda Cossman & Ratna Kapur, Secularism’s Last Sigh?: The Hindu
Right, the Courts, and India’s Struggle for Democracy, 38 HARV. INT’L L. J. 113,
141 (1997).
23. See id. at 141–42 (discussing how India has adopted its own distinct
version of secularism which does not separate state and religion but rather respects
all religions).
24. Id. at 142. See generally DONALD EUGENE SMITH, INDIA AS A SECULAR
STATE (1963) (discussing the contested approaches to secularism in India).
25. Article 14 provides: “The State shall not deny to any person equality before
the law or the equal protection of the laws within the territory of India.” I NDIA
CONST., art. 14. Article 15 provides:
(1) The State shall not discriminate against any citizen on grounds only of
religion, race, caste, sex, place of birth or any of them; (2) No citizen
shall, on grounds only of religion, race, caste, sex, place of birth or any of
them, be subject to any disability, liability, restriction or condition with
regard to—(a) access to shops, public restaurants, hotels and palaces of
public entertainment; or (b) the use of wells, tanks, bathing ghats, roads
and places of public resort maintained wholly or partly out of State funds
or dedicated to the use of the general public; (3) Nothing in this article
shall prevent the State from making any special provision for women and
children; (4) Nothing in this article or in clause (2) of Article 29 shall
prevent the State from making any special provision for the advancement
of any socially and educationally backward classes of citizens or for the
Scheduled Castes and the Scheduled Tribes.
Id. art. 15.
26. Id. arts. 25–26. These constitutional guarantees contemplate both
individual and collective rights to freedom of religion that extend well beyond the
limited right to worship. Article 25 enshrines the right to individual freedom of
religion, but also permits the state to regulate the “economic, financial, political or
other secular activity which may be associated with religions practice” and to
specifically intervene in Hindu religious institutions. Id. art. 25. The right under
prohibiting religious instruction in state schools, or taxation in
support of any particular religion; 27 and Article 51A, prohibiting the
establishment of a state religion.28 The right to equality and the right
to freedom of religion are, within this vision, seen as fundamentally
interconnected—that is, all citizens must have the equal right to
freedom of religion and the State must not discriminate on the basis
of religion. Following from the dominant understanding of
secularism as equal treatment of all religions, the constitutional
discourse does not insist on a wall of separation between religion and
politics.29 Rather, discussions tend to emphasize the principle of
toleration—that is, the equal toleration of all religions, and Articles
30 and 51A are generally highlighted. 30 The constitutional guarantees
on equality and freedom of religion that are seen to frame this
Article 26(a) is a group right and available to every religious denomination. Article
26(b) guarantees every religious denomination the right “to manage its own affairs
in matters of religion.” Id. art. 26(b). “The expression ‘matters of religion’ includes
‘religious practices, rites and ceremonies essential for the practicing of religion.’”
Articles 25 and 26 accord primacy to public interest over religious claims and
hence provide a wide margin of appreciation for the State to sponsor reforms.
27. Article 30 provides:
(1) All minorities, whether based on religion or language, shall have the
right to establish and administer educational institutions of their choice.
(1A) In making any law providing for the compulsory acquisition of any
property of an educational institution established and administered by a
minority, referred to in clause (1), the State shall ensure that the amount
fixed by or determined under such law for the acquisition of such property
is such as would not restrict or abrogate the right guaranteed under that
clause.
31. SMITH , supra note 24, at 133. Smith has argued that the third principle of
liberal democratic secularism regarding the “[s]eparation of religion and state
includes two distinct principles: (1) the non-interference of the state and religious
organizations in each other’s affairs; (2) the absence of a legal connection between
the state and a particular religion. The Indian Constitution . . . does not subscribe to
the first principle; it does, however, uphold the second.” Id. at 132.
under the Constitution. Some of these provisions include the rights of
religious minorities to establish and administer their own educational
institutions,32 to personal status laws, as well as the special
autonomous status for the Muslim dominated state of Kashmir.33
B. The Role of the Hindu Right
The Hindu Right has increasingly been trying to cast itself as the
true inheritors of India’s secular tradition. Secularism in its vision
requires that all religious communities be treated the same. Any laws
that are designed to protect the rights of religious minorities are
attacked as “special treatment” and as a violation of the constitutional
mandate of equal treatment.34 The vision of secularism within the
discourse of the Hindu Right comes to equate secularism with a
Hindu state.35 This vision requires that religious minorities must be
treated the same as the Hindu majority (i.e., where those religious
minorities are effectively assimilated into the Hindu majority), and
that any protection of the rights of religious minorities amounts to
“appeasement,” and a violation of the “true spirit” of secularism. By
emphasizing the model of formal equality—that is, the formal equal
treatment of all religions—the Hindu Right’s vision of secularism
operates as an unmodified majoritarianism whereby the majority
Hindu community becomes the norm against which all others are to
be judged and treated.36 The result is that the project of secularism
becomes a project about assimilating religious minorities rather than
about the protection of the rights of religious minorities. Secularism
ends up as a powerful tool in the Hindu Right’s quest for discursive
political power.37 Armed with the ideology of Hindutva, the Hindu
Sunder Rajan, eds., 2007); SHABNUM TEJANI, INDIAN SECULARISM: A SOCIAL AND
INTELLECTUAL HISTORY 1890-1950 10–11 (2008).
38. See THE BABRI MASJID QUESTION , 1528–2003: A MATTER OF
NATIONAL HONOUR 1–6 (A.G. Noorani ed., 2003) (describing the 1992
destruction of the Babri Masjid mosque); Nandini Rao & C. Rammanohar Reddy,
Ayodhya, the Print Media and Communalism, in DESTRUCTION AND
CONSERVATION OF CULTURAL PROPERTY 139, 147 (Robert Layton et al. eds.,
2001) (same).
39. Id.
40. See THE BABRI MASJID QUESTION, supra note 38, at 4 (stating that the
state was brought under presidential rule).
41. INDIA CONST., art. 356. Under presidential rule, the central government
rules the state through the governor of the state, the official representative of the
president at the state level.
Supreme Court in 1994 upheld the declaration of presidential rule in
all four states.42
In the Bommai decision the full constitutional bench of the
Supreme Court declared the integral importance of the place of
secularism in the Constitution.43 In the course of lauding the
importance of secularism based on religious tolerance and equal
treatment of all religious groups, the Supreme Court also strongly
condemned the political forces committed to undermining a more
pluralistic instantiation of this constitutional ideal. 44 The Court
remarked on the distinctness of the concept of secularism in India—
that is, the equal treatment of all religions and tolerance. 45 For
example, Justice Sawant echoed the common view that in India
secularism does not involve a complete separation of religion and the
state, but rather the notion of treating all religions equally:
[T]he ideal of a secular State in the sense of a State
which treats all religions alike and displays
benevolence towards them is in a way more suited to
the Indian environment and climate than that of a truly
secular State by which [is] meant a state which creates
complete separation between religion and the State.46
71. In a subsequent case, the Supreme Court issued an order directing that no
religious activity of any kind by anyone either symbolic or actual be allowed to
take place on the 67 acres of land adjacent to the disputed site. It further clarified
that even though no title rights were in dispute in the adjacent land, and that the
order amounted to denying real property holders from worshipping on their own
land, the restriction was necessary to ensure that (approvingly quoting from the
Ismail Faruqui judgment) “the final outcome of the adjudication should not be
rendered meaningless by the existence of properties belonging to Hindus in the
vicinity of the disputed structure in case the Muslims are found entitled to the
disputed site.” Mohd. Aslam, alias Bhure v. Union of India, A.I.R. 2003 S.C. 3413.
72. A.I.R. 1996 S.C. 1113 (India).
73. The Representation of the People Act, No. 43 of 1951, I NDIA CODE (1951),
§ 123(3).
74. See INDIA CONST. art. 370; The Muslim Women (Protection of Rights on
Divorce Act), No. 25 of 1986, INDIA CODE (1986).
were both intolerant and discriminatory. 75 The difference in treatment
of religious minorities was stated to be in violation of the
Constitutional mandate of equal treatment of all religions, based on
sameness in treatment, which was a central component of Indian
secularism.76 The Court held that several candidates were guilty of
appealing to religion to gain votes. At the same time, it also held that
Hindutva—the ideological linchpin of the Hindu Right—simply
represented “a way of life of people of the subcontinent” rather than
an attitude hostile to persons practicing other religions or an appeal to
religion.77 The Court held that, in fact, the speeches at issue appealed
to the principle of secularism and to violations of the right to
equality.78 According to the Court, election speeches that referred to
religion during the course of the election campaigns with a secular
stance that alleged discrimination against any religion and promising
to remove that imbalance was consistent with secularism and outside
the purview of section 123(3).79 As the speeches did not include an
appeal to vote for or against a candidate on the basis of his religion it
was not caught within the terms of the section. 80 In other words, in
criticizing the “pseudo-secularism” of their political opponents by
pointing out the discrimination against Hindus that this version of
secularism encouraged meant that the speech was of a secular
nature.81 By validating the secular nature of the Hindu Right’s version
of secularism, the Court allowed the Hindu Right’s version of
secularism to officially enter into legal discourse.
In arriving at its’ conclusions about Hindutva, the Court quoted
extensively from two earlier decisions by the Constitutional Bench of
the Supreme Court. The decision in Shastri Yagnapurushadji v.
Muldas Bhudardas Vaishya82 included a lengthy discussion about the
identities of Hindus and provided extensive commentary involving
the definition of Hinduism to demonstrate that the Hindu religion
“does not appear to satisfy the narrow traditional features of
any
religion or creed” and therefore it could be broadly described as a
way of life.83 Similarly, in the Comm’r. of Wealth Tax, Madras v.
view, the Bommai case did not relate to the interpretation of the
provisions of the Representation of the People Act 1951, and
therefore there was nothing in the Bommai decision that was of
assistance for constructing the meaning and scope of these
provisions.93 At the same time, the Court sought to clarify its decision
in the Hindutva cases, stating that it was simply based on earlier
decisions of the Supreme Court that it was bound to follow and that
in no way had it condoned the appeal to religion to gain votes in an
election.94 The Court did not take up the opportunity to address a
central contradiction in the Hindutva cases: the interpretation on the
meaning of Hindutva and the secular nature of the speeches of the
Hindu Right. The Courts conclusion in the Hindutva cases thus
effectively vindicated the profoundly anti-secular vision of
secularism that the Hindu Right has long been trying to promote and
unwittingly left the door ajar for the Hindu Right to continue their
discursive strategy in pursuing secularism for their distinctively anti-
secular ideological agenda.
The Hindu Right hailed the decision in the Hindutva cases as a
victory and continue to deploy the decision in its political advocacy
not only as an endorsement of the “true meaning and content of
Hindutva as being consistent with the true meaning and definition of
secularism” but also to vindicate and validate its movement to begin
the construction of the temple at Ayodhya.95 Their campaign to
construct a Hindu temple where the Babri mosque once stood, by
alleging that the mosque was built on the site of the birth of the
Hindu god Ram, has generated broad-based support for the Hindu
Right. Throughout the campaign some of their supporters have
followed the marches to Ayodhya while other others have sent money
and bricks to Ayodhya to help construct the new temple. 96 The
campaign, which eventually culminated in the destruction of the
Babri Masjid on December 6, 1992, was cast by the Hindu Right as a
97. See Shri L.K. Advani, Statements on the Babri Masjid Demolition, BJP
TODAY, Jan. 15, 1993, reprinted in THE BABRI MASJID QUESTION, supra note
38, at 44–45 (defending those who pulled down the mosque as “exasperated by the
tardiness of the judicial process, and the obtuseness and myopia of the executive”).
98. Visharad v. Ahmad, O.O.S., No. 1 of 1989, All. H.C., 232 (2010) (Khan,
J.).
99. Id. at 72–73, 77–78.
100. As a number of historians have argued, the claim that Ram is the central
Hindu deity runs counter to the polytheist character of Hinduism, transforming its
pluralist character that accords well with a modernist and monotheist construction
of religion. See Romila Thapar, Syndicated Moksha?, 313 SEMINAR 14, 15 (1985).
See also Romila Thapar & Bipan Chandra, The Political Abuse of History, in
BABRI MASJID/RAMA JANAMABHUMI DISPUTE 235 (Asghar Ali Engineer, ed.,
1987); Chetan Bhatt, Primordial Being: Enlightenment and the Indian Subject of
Postcolonial Theory, in PHILOSOPHIES OF RACE AND ETHNICITY 40, 60–61 (Peter
Osborne & Stella Sandford eds., 2002).
332 MARYLAND JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW [VOL. 29:305
101. Sunni Central Waqf Board v. Gopal Singh Visharad, O.O.S. No. 4 of
1989, All. H.C., Mar. 5, 2003, reprinted in THE BABRI MASJID QUESTION , supra
note 38, at 135–139.
102. Ayodhya, (2010) All. H.C at 59 (Agarwal, J., Vol. 1). The Nirmohi
Akhara was to become one of the main claimants in the Ayodhya legal dispute.
They represent one of seven cloisters or akharas in Ayodhya, who worship Vishnu,
and Ram as Vishnu’s avatar or incarnation. Hence the site is of particular relevance
to Vaishnavite Hindus. See Hans Bakker, Ayodhya: A Hindu Jerusalem: An
Investigation of “Holy War” as a Religious Idea in the Light of Communal Unrest
in India, 38 NUMEN 80, 89–90 (1991) (stating that they view Ayodhya as sacred
because Vishnu was born there and that Ram is Vishnu’s incarnation).
103. Ayodhya, (2010) All. H.C at 20–23 (Sharma, J., Vol. 4).
104. Id. at 29–30 (Agarwal, J., Vol. 1).
105. Id.
The historical claims provide the backdrop to the legal contest
that has been in existence since the latter part of the nineteenth
century.106 In 1857, a series of skirmishes took place when Hindu
ascetics occupied the alleged birthplace of Ram and the Muslims in
the area retaliated.107 A compromise was reached whereby a partition
was constructed on the disputed land in two equal parts. 108 The inner
portion or inner courtyard was allotted to the Muslims and the outer
portion or outer courtyard was allotted to the Hindus.109 In 1885,
Raghubar Das, the Hindu Mahant (head priest), sought permission
from the district court to build a temple over the Ram Chabutra in the
outer portion, that is, the land adjoining the Babri mosque. 110 The suit
was filed when some Hindu ascetics attempted to extend the
boundary of the outer courtyard that would have also incorporated a
Muslim cemetery that existed on the site.111 This case marks the first
moment when the dispute was initiated into the legal arena. The
Mutwalli (manager) of the Babri Mosque contested the suit claiming
that the entire land belonged to the mosque.112 He argued that merely
because Hindus had been allowed to pray in the mosque from time to
time they could not acquire title over the property. A map submitted
to the court indicating the demarcation of the land into two equal
parts was not however disputed.113 While the possession of the land
by the Hindus was accepted, the suit was denied on public policy
grounds that the construction of a temple would lead to the
performance of noisy rituals including the blowing of conch shells,
and since Muslims were praying nearby, their service would be
disrupted. The court held that the construction would aggravate the
already pervasive ill will and tension between the two
communities.114
106. See Parmanand Singh, The Legal History of the Ayodhya Litigation, in
RAM JANMABHOOMI BABRI MASJID: H ISTORICAL DOCUMENTS, LEGAL
OPINIONS AND JUDGMENTS 29 (Vinay Chandra Mishra ed., 1991) (noting that a
lawsuit was bought in 1885 regarding an attempt to construct a Ram Temple on the
site of the Babri-Masjid).
107. Ayodhya, (2010) All. H.C. at 6 (Khan, J.). See THE BABRI MASJID
QUESTION, supra note 38, at (173–175).
108. Ayodhya, (2010) All. H.C. at 6–7.
109. Id. at 7.
110. Id. at 9–12.
111. Id.
112. Id. at 16; THE BABRI MASJID Q UESTION, supra note 38, at 178–
181. 113. Ayodhya, (2010) All. H.C. at 13–15, 17.
114. See A.G. Noorani, Legal Aspects to the Issue in ANATOMY OF A
CONFRONTATION : THE RISE OF COMMUNAL POLITICS IN INDIA 65 (Sarvepalli
Gopal ed., 1991) (discussing the judge’s reason for declining to decree the suit).
A similar logic was adopted in subsequent court appeals. In the
first appeal, Judge F.E.A. Chamier visited the disputed spot and
admitted, “[i]t is most unfortunate that a Masjid should have been
built on the land especially held sacred by the Hindus. But as that
occurred 356 years ago, it is too late now to remedy the grievance.
All that can be done is to maintain the parties in status quo.” 115 A
further appeal was also dismissed, with the Judge stating:
This spot is situated within the precinct of the ground
surrounding a mosque erected some 350 years ago
owing to the bigotry and tyranny of the emperor who
purposely chose this holy spot, according to Hindu
legend, as the site of his mosque. The Hindus seem to
have got very limited rights of access to certain spots
within the precinct adjoining the mosque and they
have for a series of years been persistently trying to
increase those rights and to erect buildings on two
spots in the enclosure namely: (1) Sita- ki-Rasoi
(kitchen of Sita) and (2) Ram- Chander-ki-
Janmabhoomi (birthplace of Lord Ram). The
executive authorities have persistently refused these
encroachments and absolutely forbid any alteration of
the status quo.116
He further added that there was nothing on record to show that
the plaintiff Raghubar Das was a proprietor of the land. 117 The
proceedings represented the first time when the disputed land was
formally divided into a Hindu and a Muslim portion and also marks
the emergence of the legal contest over the content of religious
liberty. The modes of worship of the Hindus and Muslims would
become a focus of judicial attention in the subsequent legal narrative
of the case, with a persistent question remaining as to how these
modes of worship and claims to property could be evaluated. The
visit to the disputed site by the judges, as well as the recording of
identifying marks and inscriptions on the monument, the routines of
prayer and their timings, and the drawing up of procedures for
regulating entry into the disputed site, were all used to construct the
terms of the dispute and the content of the right to freedom of
religion.
115. Id.
116. Id. at 66.
117. Id.
In 1934, there were further riots between Hindus and Muslims at
the disputed site, which caused severe damage to the mosque.118 The
damage occurred when some sadhus (holy men) led by the Nirmohi
Akhara forcefully occupied the mosque. Some of the Hindu parties
claimed that the structure ceased to exist as a place of worship for
Muslims from that time and as Hindus continued to hold their prayers
at the disputed spot they could claim possession of the entire
property.119 Muslim parties, in particular the Sunni Central Waqf
Board, claimed that Muslims had continued to offer namaz (prayers)
in the inner courtyard and remained in possession of the property. 120
In addition, in 1936, the board claimed that the mosque was waqf
property and that the Sunni Board was its sole legatee.121
In 1947, the City Magistrate of Faizabad ordered that the Ram
Chabutra could not be converted into a permanent structure. Muslims
were at the same time prohibited from re-building the damaged
section of the mosque.122 The order further embedded the dispute
within the legal process. In 1949, there were a series of further
disturbances that culminated in some Hindu worshippers placing the
idols from the outer area into the inner courtyard under the central
dome of the mosque during the night of December 22, claiming the
spot to be the exact birthplace of Ram.123 The court immediately
issued a notice to attach the disputed property and handed temporary
possession to a government appointed receiver.124
A few days after the installation of the idols, K.K.K. Nayar, the
District Magistrate of Faizabad in correspondence with the Chief
Secretary of Uttar Pradesh, requested that the Hindus be given
permission to erect a “decent and vishal (large) temple,” stating that
magistrate to order that the devotees could only practice worship from behind the
railing that had been installed.
132. Id. at 44.
133. Id. See Nirmohi Akhara v. Baboo Priya Datt Ram, O.O.S., No. 3 of 1989,
All. H.C. (India).
134. While the Archeological of India (ASI) came to the ambiguous
conclusion that its excavations revealed the existence of remnants of a temple-like
structure in the place where the mosque was constructed, these findings remained
disputed throughout the course of the proceedings by the Sunni Central Wakf
Board as well as various academics. See Supriya Varma & Jaya Menon, Was There
a Temple under the Babri Masjid? Reading the Archaeological “Evidence,” ECO.
& POL. WKLY., Nov. 11, 2010, at 61, 61–71 (2010).
135. Ayodhya, (2010) All. H.C. at 32 (Agarwal, J., Vol. 1).
136. Id. at 47–49 (Khan, J.).
137. Id. at 50–51, 58–59 (citing Sunni Central Board of Waqfs, U.P v. Gopal
Singh Visharad, O.O.S., No. 4 of 1989, All. H.C. (India)).
138. Ayodhya, (2010) All. H.C. at 1 (Sharma, J., No. 2, Vol. 1).
139. Id. at 55–56 (Khan, J.).
140. Id. at 78–79.
their own name and of suing and being sued.141 They acquired a legal
personality with the attributes of real individuals, backed by
administrative doctrines.142 The petitioner filed the suit as “a friend”
of the idol, seeking title and possession of the disputed property
solely in favour of Ram. The petitioner was a member of the VHP,
established in the mid-1960s to popularize the message of the Hindu
Right.143 The relevance of this suit lay partly in the fact that the VHP
did not trust the Nirmohi Akhara, whose interest seemed to be in
asserting a religious claim and not with the broader political agenda
of the VHP. This suit was filed at a time when the political climate in
India had changed considerably as a mass based agitation had been
launched for the construction of the temple spearheaded by the BJP
and led by its former head L.K. Advani.144
141. Id. at 69–70. A deity has the identity of a juridical entity, who can be both
sued and also sue. The deity can be represented by a qualified person, who is
known as the Shebait/Dharmakarta, and whose responsibility it is to protect the
idol’s property. The origin of the notion that idols are juristic persons in law seems
to be based in Roman law, where a similar concept operated with respect to
churches. See FREDERICK POLLOCK & FREDERIC WILLIAM MAITLAND, THE
HISTORY OF ENGLISH LAW BEFORE THE TIME OF EDWARD I 481 (1895) (“Perhaps
the oldest of all juristic persons is the god, hero or the saint.”). However, over the
years, the notion of a juristic person for the idol has been developed by Indian
courts as one based on the religious customs of the Hindus themselves. See, e.g.,
Pramatha Nath Mullick v. Pradyumna Kumar Mullick, (1925) 52 I.A. 245 (India)
(stating that a Hindu idol has the power to sue and be sued); Kalanka Devi
Sansthan v. Maharashtra Revenue Tribal, Nagpuri, A.I.R. 1970 S.C. 439, 441
(India) (“[W]hen property is given absolutely for the worship of an idol it vests in
the idol itself as a juristic person.”).
142. Hindu religious idols and images are considered animate and capable of
making economic, political, and legal claims. See J. D UNCAN M. DERRETT ,
RELIGION , LAW AND THE STATE IN INDIA 484–85 (1968) (discussing the legal
personality of Hindu idols).
143. See generally MANJARI KATJU, VISHVA HINDU P ARISHAD AND INDIAN
POLITICS (2003) (providing a detailed discussion on the role of the VHP in Indian
politics).
144. L.K. Advani was the leader of the opposition BJP in September 1990. He
launched a rath yatra (journey of the charioteer) across a number of states in India
to garner support for the construction of the Ram temple in Ayodhya. See Pinarayi:
Sudheeran’s Remarks a Challenge to Secularism, H INDU (March 19, 2014),
http://www.thehindu.com/todays-paper/tp-national/tp-kerala/pinarayi-sudheerans-
remarks-a-challenge-to-secularism/article5803249.ece (stating that Advani, along
with former Prime Minister A.B. Vajpayee that created “communal agitation all
over the country for constructing a Ram temple in Ayodhya”).
From the mid-1980s, the Hindu parties stepped up their rhetoric
and sought court sanction over the performance of specific rituals at
the site. These interventions coincided with the rise of the Hindu
Right as a powerful political force in contemporary Indian politics.
Some of these interventions included a suit seeking the removal of
the locks that had been placed on the fenced off portion.145 In 1986,
the local district Judge directed that the locks of the mosque be
opened, without hearing the application for impleadment made by
interested Muslim parties as well as the Waqf board. The Judge urged
the Muslims to recognize the fact that the idols and site were juristic
entities and had a legal personality, and that they should permit
Hindu worshippers to access the site. He stated that the Muslims
would not be affected in any manner if the locks of the gates were to
be opened and pilgrims and devotees allowed inside the premise to
worship. The court added:
It is undisputed that the premises are presently in the
court’s possession and that for the last 35 years Hindus
have had an unrestricted right of worship as a result of
the court’s order of 1950 and 1951. If the Hindus are
offering prayers and worshipping the idols, though in
a restricted way for the last 35 years, then the heavens
are not going to fall if the locks of the gates are
removed.146
In the process of delivering its order, the court initiated a process
of universalizing the practice of worshipping at the site as an
essential practice and an experience and belief of all Hindus. The
locks were broken open within half an hour of the pronouncement of
the order.147
Thereafter, in 1989, the VHP, one of the parties to the Ayodhya
dispute, conducted an event consecrating the bricks to be used for the
construction of the temple and invited villagers and communities
around the country to make bricks for the temple that would be
transported to the site.148 The Allahabad High Court refused a request
for an injunction against the consecration and transportation of the
bricks, while it also directed that the status quo over the disputed site
145. Umesh Chandra Mishra Pandey v. State of Uttar Pradesh, 1991 L.L.R.
638 (India) reprinted in THE BABRI MASJID Q UESTION , supra note 38, at 267–69.
146. NOORANI , supra note 114, at 79.
147. Ayodhya, (2010) All. H.C. at 88 (Khan, J.). Mohammad Hashim filed a
write petition in the Allahabad High Court challenging the order. See THE BABRI
MASJID Q UESTION, supra note 38, at 270.
148. DIANE P. MINES, FIERCE GODS 203 (2005).
340 MARYLAND JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW [VOL. 29:305
149. See Sunni Central Board of Waqfs, U.P v. Gopal Singh Visharad, O.O.S.,
No. 4 of 1989, All. H.C. (India).
150. THE BABRI MASJID Q UESTION , supra note 38, at 331–33; Krishna
Pokharel & Paul Beckett, Ayodhya, the Battle for India’s Soul: Chapter Four,
WALL ST. J. (Dec. 6, 2012),
http://blogs.wsj.com/indiarealtime/2012/12/06/ayodhya-the-battle-for-indias-soul-
chapter-four/; Mark Tully, Ayodhya Showed that Mixing Religion and Politics is
Playing with Fire, INDIA TODAY (Dec. 17, 2012),
http://indiatoday.intoday.in/story/mark-tully-ayodhya-babri-masjiddemolition/1/23
6638.html.
151. Uttar Pradesh State Gov’t Notification No. 3814/XLI-33-86, dated Oct. 7,
1991, reprinted in THE BABRI MASJID QUESTION, supra note 38, at 334–36.
152. Mohd. Hashim v. State of Uttar Pradesh, Order on Writ Petition 3540
(M/B) of 1991, reprinted in THE BABRI MASJID QUESTION, supra note 38, at 337.
153. Id. (the notification said the purpose of the acquisition was for developing
tourism and providing amenities to pilgrims).
154. In a separate writ filed by the Sakshi Gopal Temple ensuring that the
acquisition would not affect the religious character of the site, the court held that the
acquisition would be subject to the caveat that the deity in the temple would be
preserved and that no permanent structure would be constructed at the site. Shakshi
Gopal v. State of Uttar Pradesh, Writ Petition No. 3579 (HB) of 1991, reprinted in
THE BABRI MASJID QUESTION, supra note 38, at 344.
Right organized a religious prayer ceremony that was to mark the
symbolic construction of the temple. 155 The destruction of the mosque
was partly facilitated by the history of the legal dispute that preceded
it, where the courts invariably decided in favour of the Hindu parties,
together with the ideological zeal of the Hindu Right, which
remained determined to establish the site as integral to the Hindu
faith and identity.
As discussed earlier, the government subsequently issued an
ordinance to acquire the disputed site and adjacent lands following
the destruction of the mosque, and a constitutional challenge to the
act was dismissed. The Court however invalidated section 4(3),
which provided for the abatement of all pending suits and legal
proceedings pertaining to the disputed structure.156 In light of this
decision, in 1995, a three-judge bench of the Allahabad High Court
re-commenced proceedings to hear the arguments in the dispute and
delivered its decision on September 30, 2010.
B. The Judicial Holdings
On September 30, 2010, the decision in the Ayodhya land-
holding case was delivered by a three-member bench of the
Allahabad High Court, located in India’s western state of Uttar
Pradesh, amidst tight security.157 The three judges included: Justice
Khan, a Muslim; Justice Agarwal, who delivered the majority
opinion; and Justice Sharma, who was the dissenting judge in the
case. The decision ran into a staggering 8,189 pages, the longest
being 5,238 pages and delivered by Justice Agarwal. While there was
no outbreak of public violence after the decision was pronounced,
appeals were filed by all sides in the Supreme Court, reflecting
considerable dissatisfaction over the ruling.
On the specific issue of the right to freedom of religion, the
“Muslim” parties did not advance any arguments based on the
freedom of religion clauses. And Justice Khan was the only one of
the three judges who did not address the arguments made in
relation to
155. Id. at 254. Dilip Awasthi, Babri Masjid Demolition - 1992: A Look at the
Countdown to Disaster, INDIA TODAY (Dec. 5, 2011),
http://indiatoday.intoday.in/st ory/babri-masjid-demolition-1992-ayodhya-
shame/1/162900.html.
156. Ismail Faruqui v. Union of India, (1994) 6 S.C.C. 360, 383 (India).
157. Several companies of the Central Security Paramilitary forces as well as
the police were deployed across the state and through different parts of the country,
and special security was provided to the three judges who rendered the decision in
the title disputes. Tight Security Across the Country amid Appeals for Peace,
HINDU (Sept. 30, 2010), http://www.thehindu.com/news/national/tight-security-
across-the-country-amid-appeals-for-peace/article804415.ece.
342 MARYLAND JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW [VOL. 29:305
Articles 25 and 26, but focused exclusively on the issue of title. 158
Justice Khan held that neither party was able to demonstrate
exclusive title to the disputed property.159 The available evidence
indicated that by the middle of the eighteenth century there existed a
mosque at the site and that by the middle of the nineteenth century
Hindus were claiming that this site was the birthplace of Ram. 160
Since 1855, both parties appeared to be in joint possession of the
site.161 Justice Khan decided to divide the disputed property into three
equal parts: one part was awarded to the Muslim parties; one part was
given to the Hindu Idols, with the caveat that their part should
include the land under the central dome; and one part was handed
over to the Nirmohi Akhara with the caveat that their part should
include the outer courtyard.162 Justice Khan based his decision on the
issue of title and possession, rather than on considerations of the right
to freedom of religion, although he recognised the significance of the
site for Hindus.163
Justice Khan’s decision to divide the property into three parts is
curious and there is no real explanation for altering the situation from
1949 when the property was divided into two nearly equal parts
between the Hindu and Muslim communities. In permitting the area
under the central dome to be given over to the idols, the judge’s
decision is contrary to the acknowledged fact that the idols had been
placed there illegally and only in 1949. Justice Khan’s decision
placed the onus on the Muslim community to make all the necessary
adjustments in relation to the dispute.164
Justice Agarwal accepted that there was a non-Islamic, ancient
structure that stood where the mosque once stood.165 While the earlier
158. Ayodhya, (2010) All. H.C. at 250–55 (Khan, J.) (addressing the issue of
title); id. at 4997–98, 5043–44 (Agarwal, J.) (discussing protections under Articles
25 and 26); id. at 166 (Sharma, J.) (noting the differences in protection provided by
Articles 25 and 26).
159. Id. at 255, 283 (Khan, J.).
160. Id. at 206, 281, 283.
161. Id. at 250, 260.
162. Id. at 275–76, 284–85.
163. Id. at 243–44, 250–56.
164. See id. at 279–80 (“Indian Muslims … are therefore in the best position to
tell the world the correct position. Let them start with their role in the resolution of
the conflict at hand.”).
165. Id. at 4414–15 (Agarwal, J., Vol. 18); see also ALIGARH HISTORIANS
SOCIETY, HISTORY AND THE JUDGEMENT OF THE ALLAHABAD HIGH COURT,
(LUCKNOW BENCH) IN THE RAMJANMABHUMI–BABRI MASJID CASE iii–iv (2010)
structure appeared to be a Hindu religious place, the ruins could also
be evidence of other non-Islamic traditions or practices.166 He also
accepted that there was evidence of persistent practice as well as a
strong belief on the part of Hindus that the disputed spot, particularly
the spot under the central dome, was the birthplace of Ram. 167 This
faith was borne out by ancient literature that Justice Agarwal stated
168
should be “accepted on its face without any ‘tinkering.’” He thus
implied that such persistent practice and faith was enough to deify the
place and give it a juridical personality.
Justice Agarwal addressed the issue of whether a deity has a
right to file a suit, a right that was contingent on whether the idol had
been properly consecrated and hence acquired a juristic personality.
The Judge observed that a determination whether the idol had been
properly consecrated could only be made according to the doctrine
and belief of the respective religious denomination.169 In considering
this issue, Justice Agarwal involved himself in the construction of
Hindu tradition and belief. The Hindu parties contended that the
entire site would be regarded as a temple and have a juristic
personality.170 During the course of the proceedings, Justice Agarwal
asked the Hindu parities whether the worship of rivers and hills by
Hindus, would render all such places juristic persons? 171 In response,
the defendants stated:
[I]t is the belief of the Hindu people that the fort of
King Dashrath situated at Ayodhya included the part
of the building wherein Lord Rama was born
according to Hindu belief and the disputed area
covered that house. It is believed that it is this place
which is so pious and sacred for Hindu people being
the birthplace of Lord Rama and, therefore, in this
particular case, it is not necessary to go into larger
question since it is not the claim of the Hindu parties
that the entire city of Ayodhya or the entire locality is
birthplace of Lord Rama. He was born at Ayodhya is a
well-known fact. In Ayodhya, it is the disputed place
(discussing Judge Agarwal’s judgment and how his reasoning and understandings
of the dispute are historically flawed).
166. Ayodhya, (2010) All. H.C. at 4414–15.
167. Id. at 4436.
168. Id. at 3502.
169. Id. at 2173.
170. Id. at 1807, 1831, 1975 (Agarwal, J., Vol. 8).
171. Id. at 1974–75.
where the Lord of Lords was manifested in the form of
natural person and, therefore, it is believed to be the
birthplace of Lord Rama by Hindus for time
immemorial and they visit it to worship and Darshan.
This satisfy [sic] the requirement of a ‘deity.’ He
submits that ‘deity’ in the name of birthplace of Lord
Rama is a legal person considering the concept of
legal personality of Hindu deity…172
The Judge accepted this argument (while construing the spiritual
nature of Hinduism) and held that “[i]f the public goes for worship
considering that there is a divine presence and offer worship thereat
believing that they are likely to be the recipient of the bounty of God
then it satisfies the test of a temple. Installation of an idol or the mode
of worship are not the relevant and conclusive test.” 173 Justice
Agarwal also held that the deity was a perpetual minor and therefore
no claim of adverse possession could be made against the deity.174 For
the same reason the suit on behalf of the Lord Ram filed in 1989 was
not time-barred and a next of friend was entitled to represent the
deity.
Various Indian courts have recognised a temple deity as a legal
entity and that even a devotee or a regular worshipper can move the
court on behalf of the presiding deity. 175 Justice Agarwal’s holding
could have serious implications with regards to claims being made all
over India in relation to Islamic structures and historical monuments.
He also cited the right to freedom of religion and the view that the
right to worship at the birthplace of Ram constituted a core ingredient
204. Both judges relied on the Supreme Court’s decision in Ismail Faruqui v.
Union of India, (1994) 6 S.C.C. 360, 417 (“While offer of prayer or worship is a
religious practice, its offering at every location where such prayers can be offered
would not be an essential or integral part of such religious practice unless the place
has a particular significance for that religion so as to form an essential or integral
part thereof.”). Ayodhya, (2010) All. H.C. 161, 164 (Sharma, J.); id. at 2551–52
(Agarwal, J.).
205. See Kumkum Roy, Issues of Faith, ECON. & POL. WKLY., DEC. 11,
2010, at 53 (2010) (who argues that the court ignored the polytheisim in Hindu
religion and de-recognized the diversity of faith. She posits a critical question as to
whether the recognition of a personal god is intrinsic to secularism); see also
Nivedita Menon, The Ayodhya Judgement: What Next?, ECO. & POL. WKLY., July
30, 2011 at 81, 86–87 (2011). At the same time, some progressive scholars have
also argued that the case opens the possibility of recognizing the importance of
faith in individual human life. See Lata Mani, Where Angels Fear to Tread: The
Ayodhya Verdict, ECO. & POL. WKLY., Oct. 16, 2010, at 10, 11 (2010); Ashish
Nandy, The Judges Have Been Injudicious Enough to Create a Space for
Compassion and Human Sentiments, TEHELKA, Nov. 6, 2010, at 16.
206. Some scholars have unpacked the majoritarianism implicit in the
American model of secularism, which is ostensibly based on state neutrality.
352 MARYLAND JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW [VOL. 29:305
218. See SEN , supra note 7, at 28 (stating that he “whittle[d] the protection
of essential practices to those that the court would deem suitable”).
219. (1962) 1 S.C.R. 383 (India).
220. Id. at 412.
221. Judge Gajendragadkar further reinforced this process of “rationalizing”
religion in Tilkayat Shri Govindlalji Maharaj v. The State of Rajasthan and Others,
(1964) 1 S.C.R. 561, 622–23 (India). See also Mohammad Hanif Quraishi v. State
of Bihar, A.I.R. 1958 S.C. 731 (where the Court dismissed a claim by Muslims
who argued that a law prohibiting cow slaughter violated their right to freedom of
religion as Muslims were compelled by their religion to sacrifice cow at Bakr-Id, a
religious festival, was not an essential practice for Muslims). A later Supreme
Court decision followed this move. D.A.V. College, Bhatinda v. State of Punjab,
A.I.R. 1971 S.C. 1731 (rejecting the argument that the Arya Samaj is a separate
religion, a status that they sought in order to claim the autonomy that is granted to
religious minorities in respect of establishing and administering their own
educational institutions).
222. See SEN, supra note 7, at 49–50. This turn becomes evident in a case by a
woman who claimed to have the right to have worship conducted in perpetuity at
the Samadhi (a place where realization and state of consciousness free from the
creation is attained) of her late husband. While the case did not involve an
interpretation of the freedom of religion clauses, the Court took on the role of
determining whether or not such a practice was an essential practice of the Hindu
faith. It held that only practices that had a basis in the shastras or sacred texts would
be allowed. The recognition of a ground for the perpetual dedication of the
claimant’s husband for the purpose of acquiring religious merit was not such a
turn was similar to the move by colonial judges to ascertain the
validity of religious practices.223
This feature of modern states and laws making scripture the
linchpin for their definition of what is or is not a religion is a
longstanding characteristic of liberal secularism. Hinduism does not
have a central scripture, and hence this modern construction of
Hinduism as text based is dramatic in the shift that it stages. The
tension is explicitly demonstrated in the Satsangi case involving the
regulation of entry into a temple. The petitioners challenged
legislation that was enacted in Bombay in 1947 which was directed at
ensuring that Hindu temples were opened to individuals of all
castes.224 They claimed that as they were not Hindus the act did not
apply to them. The Court held that the Satsangis were in fact
Hindus.225 In coming to this determination, the bench was compelled
to consider who was a Hindu. It declared that the teachings of the
Satsangis were identical to Hinduism and also that its leader was
simply one of many reformers of Hinduism. 226 The petitioners tried
to distinguish themselves by stating that they initiated women and
also permitted Muslims and Parsis to become full members of the
sect without forcing them to forsake their own religion. They also
argued that the founder of the sect was worshipped as a god in the
temple. The decision written by Justice Gajendragadkar held that all
of these arguments were consistent with Hinduism and its basic claim
practice. Saraswathi Ammal v. Rajagopal Ammal, (1954) S.C.R. 277, 288 (India);
see also Sri Venkataramana Devaru v. State of Mysore, (1958) S.C.R. 895 (India)
(validating a state law allowing Harijans (untouchables) unrestricted access to enter
a temple that was founded by upper cast Brahmins, despite the right to determine
who can enter temples, conduct the worship and how to conduct the worship being
matters of religion, because Article 25 (2)(b), which deals with the State’s right to
open public temples to all Hindus, took precedence over Article 26).
223. For a discussion of the academic debates on this issue, see generally
Bloch, supra note 4.
224. See Shastri Yagnapurushdasji v. Muldas Bhudardas Vaishya, (1966) 3
S.C.R. 242, 264 (India). In India, a category of people described as untouchables
(Harijans or dalits) who were considered to be unclean, and excluded from access
to common public spaces including temples. These castes were relegated to low-
status jobs and experienced restricted social mobility on the grounds that they were
regarded as untouchable. British colonial rule strengthened this caste based politics
as a measure by which to consolidate their political power over the native subject.
In post-independent India, the practice of untouchability was banned under Article
17 of the Constitution and the community has mobilized and become a significant
political force in mainstream politics, though they still suffer the effects historic
and systemic disadvantage.
225. Id. at 271.
226. Id. at 271–74.
to being tolerant and accommodating. The Judge referred to the Gita
as a central Hindu text to substantiate the idea that the worship of
other deities was not proscribed by Hinduism and in the process also
cast Hinduism as accommodating and progressive.227 On the basis of
this reasoning any discrimination or socially regressive practice could
be cast as a misunderstanding of the “true” faith and teachings.228
Relying on a text-based approach, the courts have continued to
set out the distinction between the true religious experience as
opposed to rituals and symbols.229 In the case of Hindus, this
approach is directly connected to the way in which Hinduism was
articulated by reformists in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries
through an anti-colonial nationalist lens.230 Hinduism does not have a
single foundational scripture, yet as many historians of modern
religion have noted Hinduism during the colonial period came to
acquire a form modeled on the Abrahamic religions, Christianity in
particular. Lata Mani has argued that statist projects directed at
regulating religion since the colonial period have tended to
essentialize religious claims. In her work on the regulation of sati, the
practice whereby a widow would immolate herself on her husband’s
funeral pyre, under colonial rule, she shows how the British, as much
as the Indian nationalist (primarily Bengali) elite, reified “scripture”
as the primal source of religion thereby homogenizing and
essentializing the polivocality of the tradition. 231 As a result sati came
to be equated with Indian culture and ideal Indian womanhood that
was disconnected from the reality of its actual practice. Similarly,
Mrinalini Sinha’s work illustrates how the contest over the scriptural
basis of a tradition was central to the legal reform of women’s
227. The Court was unable to resolve the tension raised in Sri Venkataramana
Devaru, which involved a similar issue, where in upholding the constitutional
validity of the Act, the Court acknowledged that the Act may be violating the right
to religious freedom. (1958) S.C.R. 895, 920–21 (India).
228. Id. See also Seshammal v. State of Tamil Nadu, (1972) 3 S.C.R. 815,
833–34 (India) (referring to scriptural authority to justify upholding a state act
abolishing hereditary appointments of temple priests, according to which the mode
of appointment of a priest was a secular and not a religious function and thereby
could be regulated).
229. See Shri A.S. Narayana Deekshitulu v. State of Andhra Pradesh and
Others, (1996) A.I.R. 1765 (India) (identifying the rituals involved in an
appointment process as not being an essential part of religion or religious practice).
230. See, e.g., King, supra note 4, at 177–79.
231. See LATA MANI, CONTENTIOUS TRADITIONS: THE DEBATE ON SATI IN
COLONIAL INDIA 25–26 (1998).
rights.232 The nineteenth century colonial encounter came to inform
the ways in which the Hindu religion has come to be understood and
taken up in the postcolonial present in law.
In the contemporary moment, core religious practices have come
to be identified in Supreme Court decisions as based on foundational
documents and the construction of a common Hindu belief and
culture. While the earlier cases tended to offer a wider understanding
of religion as including rituals and superstitious practices, the
Supreme Court gradually whittled down the scope of what constitutes
religion by introducing a requirement that the practice must have a
scriptural or textual basis.233 In the process a juridically constructed
“rational Hinduism” has come to define the parameters of legitimate
faith.234 In articulating a common Hindu culture and belief, the Court
has cast Hinduism in the same framework as Semitic traditions—that
is, as a monolithic religion based on foundational documents. 235 It is
also a position that ends up converging with the position of the Hindu
nationalists.236 The doctrine of essential practices is reflective of a
“secular rationality” that has emerged with the modern state and in
the process it has rearticulated religion and its content. In other
words, rather than being opposing ideologies or understood as
unalterable essential concepts, secularism and religion have both
been mutually constitutive.237
253. Peter Danchin, Islam in the Secular Nomos of the European Court of
Human Rights, 32 MICH. J. INT’L LAW 663, 747 (2011).
254. BHARATIYA J ANATA PARTY , C ONSTITUTION AND RULES ART. II, (Sept.
2012), http://www.bjp.org/images/pdf_2012_h/constitution_eng_jan_10_2013.pdf.
255. Cossman & Kapur, supra note 22, at 149.
256. Id. See, e.g., BJP ELECTION MANIFESTO 1998, supra note 95, at 36
(“Amend Article 30 of the Constitution suitably to remove any scope of
discrimination against any religious community in matters of education.”).
362 MARYLAND JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW [VOL. 29:305