The Problem of Defining Religion PDF
The Problem of Defining Religion PDF
J. Kuruvachira
Introduction
Defining religion is seen as a major problem in contemporary religious studies. In fact, today, a
commonly accepted definition of religion hardly exits among scholars. Any attempt to define religion
would imply retaining some aspects and omitting others. The difficulty in defining has only increased
in the wake of our knowledge that there is almost an infinite variety of religions, each proposing
worldviews that considerably differ from one another, and at times even conflict with each other.
Religious scholars have put forward a wide variety of definitions. It might be stated that religion is such
a complex and diverse cultural phenomenon that reducing it to any single definition would either fail to
capture what it really is, or merely misrepresent it. Some do not define religion, arguing that the
definitions one begins with often influences the course of research in decisive ways. Others put forward
definitions but fall short of universal acceptance. Yet religion is a major factor in human life and it is
likely to remain so for the foreseeable future. Hence, one needs to know what religion is and what its
essential elements are. This means that attention to the problem of defining religion is a fundamental
prerequisite to the study of religion. In this article I will briefly examine the concept of ‘religion’,
problem of defining religion, major types of definitions with a critique of the functional definition of
religion and definition of religion by essential elements, and conclude by arguing that a complementary
approach to the definition of religion might be more suited to a complex subject like ‘religion’ than a
compartmentalised approach.
1 Cfr. U. Berner, “Religione”, Nuovo Dizionario delle Religioni, Hans Waldenfels (ed.), Milan, Edizione Pauline, 1993,
756-757; Paolo Grassi, “Religione”, in Enciclopedia Filosofica, Vol.10, Milano, Bompiani, Fondazione Centro Studi
filosofici di Gallarate, 2006, 9578-9579.
2 Cfr. Charles B. Jones, Introduction to the Study of Religion, Parts I & II. Virginia, The Teaching Company, 2007, 5.
3 Cfr. Jonathan Z. Smith, “Religion, Religions, Religious”, in Mark C. Taylor (ed.), Critical Terms for Religious Studies,
Chicago, The University of Chicago Press, 1998, 270-271.
1
came to indicate a category of which other religions were equal members.4 Today many scholars are
inclined to use the term ‘tradition’ for what we commonly understand by ‘religion’. Thus they speak of
Christian tradition, Buddhist tradition, Islamic tradition, Judaic tradition, etc.
The word ‘religion’ can have different shades of meaning across diverse cultural contexts. Hence the
use of cross-cultural concepts can become advantageous because of their remarkable power to make the
nuances clearer, richer and more accurate in languages other than European. For example, some
alternative concepts for religion in non-European cultures are: dharma (teaching, law), darsana
(worldview), marga (way) in Sanskrit, and chiao (teaching) and Tao (way) in Chinese.5
Some scholars consider religion as a species of the genus ‘worldviews’ which includes also secular
ideologies (like Atheism, Communism, Existentialism, Humanism, Marxism, Maoism, etc). According
to them, those systems which are conventionally and traditionally called religions are only one species
of the worldviews, and the rest could be called non-religious worldviews.6
It has been argued by some that there is no such thing as ‘religion’ per se, only culture, and the
various cultural manifestations, and that some aspects of culture have been arbitrarily singled out and
grouped together, and given the label ‘religion’. According to them ‘religion’ exists merely in the
minds of scholars studying culture, and has no independent existence of its own.7
There are scholars who argue that the term ‘religion’ should be used in the plural because all
religions are particular and there exists no religion in the abstract. Ninian Smart says: “Perhaps there is
no such thing as religion in general – all that we meet are particular religions.”8 However, there are
others who admit a plurality of religions but also see certain common elements among them which
make it possible to use the term ‘religion’ in the singular. For instance, the Jesuit scholar Giovanni
Magnani holds that there is some common and universal phenomenon which unites the different
religions, and therefore the term can be used in the singular.9 Friedrich Schleiermacher adds that
religion is infinite in nature and in the different manifestations of religion one should discover the
universal element, namely, ‘religion’. He says: “in the religions, you are to discover religion”.10 Then
there are others who maintains that ‘religion’ is a univocal term11 and can be predicated to any
experience of the transcendent or something analogous to it in any culture.
These conflicting views about ‘religion’ only reveals that it is a very complex concept and there are
no easy answers as to what does and does not qualify as ‘religion’. There are people who think that
religion is all very simple and obvious, but they merely betray a superficial and simplistic familiarity
with the concept and fail to capture its multifaceted aspects and the difficulty in articulating what it
really is. This has even led some scholars to drop the word ‘religion’ altogether. Wilfred Cantwell
12 Cfr. Wilfred Cantwell Smith, Patterns of Faith Around the World, Oxford, Oneworld, 1998, 8-12.
13 Cfr. Frederic Ferré., “The Definition of Religion”, Journal of the American Academy of Religion 38 (1970), 3-6.
14 Cfr. Ninian Smart, “What is religion?”, 13.
15 Cfr. Zygmut Bauman, “Postmodern Religion?”, in Paul Heelas (ed.), Religion, Modernity an Postmodernity, Oxford,
Blackwell, 1998, 55.
16 Cfr. Heinrich von Stietencron, “Der Begriff der Religion in der Religionswissenschaft”, in Walter Kerber (ed.), Der
Begriff der Religion, München, Kindt 1993, 117.
17 Cfr. James H. Leuba, A Psychological Study of Religion, New York, Macmillan, 1912, 339-361.
18. Cfr. Jonathan Z. Smith, “Religion, Religions, Religious”, 281.
3
philosophy, theology, history of religions, sociology, anthropology, psychology, jurisprudence, etc.
Hence defining religion is possible.
28 Cfr.Emile Durkheim, The Elementary Forms of the Religious Life, tr. Joseph Ward Swain, New York, The Macmillan
Company, 1915, 10.
29 Cfr. Anthony C. Thiselton, A Concise Encyclopaedia o the Philosophy of Religion, Oxford, Oneworld, 2006, 262.
30 Sigmund Freud, The Future of an Illusion, James Strachey (trs. and ed.), New York, W.W. Norton and Company,
1961, 55.
31 http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/The_God_Delusion. Accessed on 11 March 2011. Richard Dawkins (b.1941-) is a British
ethnologist and evolutionary biologist who openly states that he loathes religion. His recent book The God Delusion (2006)
is not only a defense of atheism, but also goes on the offensive against religion. He sees religion as subverting science,
fostering fanaticism, encouraging bigotry against homosexuals, and influencing society in other negative ways. Ibid.
5
2.3 The classical dilemma in defining religion
If we maintain that we need to define religion we are faced with a classical dilemma: should the
definition precede the analysis of the data about religion, or should it follow the analysis? Some
scholars assert that unless we start out with a definition of religion and specify what we are looking for,
there is no way to separate religion from non-religion. Therefore, we must have some preliminary
concept of ‘religion’ at the start, or we might end up studying something other than religion, like
culture, or theology, or psychology or sociology or anthropology or something else. Others retort that if
one defines the subject beforehand, he or she might distort the data owing to preconceptions, or at very
least he or she might miss some data which are really relevant, but which have been mistakenly
excluded from the outset. Hence they maintain that after having studied the data about religion one can
define what is religion. Max Weber was one who argued that if we attempt to define religion at all, it
must be done at the conclusion of the study.32 The Italian philosopher of religion Adriano Alessi holds
a similar view.33
But we propose a way out of this dilemma. We can divide the definitions of religion into two
categories, each serving a special function and only a function. We could call them ‘preliminary
definitions’ and ‘final definitions’.34 We could start with a number of elementary preliminary
definitions for determining the subject matter of the study, and conclude with some ‘final definitions’,
either by refining some of the existing definitions or by creating new ones altogether. The preliminary
definitions should be several. It is best done by referring to the definitions of some of the well known
scholars of religion over a wide timeframe, from different disciplines, and from cross cultural contexts,
and then briefly criticism them from one’s own experience and knowledge of religions, in order to
discover what are the elements that are positive and negative in them. At this stage it is also important
that different categories of definitions are provided, such as, essential-intuitive, lexical, functional,
substantive, etc. At the final stage too it is good to furnish more than one ‘final definition’ of religion so
that one is made aware that no definition is absolute and that each definition is open to further
refinement. The plurality of definitions at the final stage will also allow one to choose from several
options according to one’s preference or discard them altogether for a new definition of one’s own
formulation, because as Peter Berger says, “definitions are matters of taste and thus fall under the
maxim de gustibus”.35
37 He defines religion as: " a system of symbols which acts to establish powerful, pervasive, and long-lasting moods and
motivations in men by formulating conceptions of a general order of existence and clothing these conceptions with such an
aura of factuality that the moods and motivations seem uniquely realistic." Clifford Geertz, “Religion as a Cultural system”,
in Michael Banton (ed.), Anthropological Approaches to the Study of Religion, London, Tavistock Publications, 1996, 4.
38 Cfr. http://kirkland.myweb.uga.edu/rk/pdf/guides/RELDEFINE.pdf. Accessed on 13 March 2011.
7
have definitions of religion which implied a reductionist philosophy of religion, and he called this
method ‘assassination through definition’.39
Another criticism against the functional definition is that anything which performs the prescribed
function thereby becomes ‘religion’. Such a definition does not permit any clear boundary separating
religion from non-religion. A typical case of this is Paul Tillich’s definition of religion as ‘Ultimate
concern’. Anything can be an ultimate concern for a person or society. It does not mean that every
‘ultimate concern’ is religion. Therefore, no purely functional definition of religion can be considered
as a satisfactory definition of religion.
39 Cfr. Peter Berger L., "Some Second Thoughts on Substantive versus Functional Definitions of Religion," Journal for
the Scientific Study of Religion, Vol. 13 (1974), 126.
40 Cfr. Daniel L. Pals, Eight Theories of Religion, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2 nd edition, 2006, 13.
41 Cfr. Peter L. Berger, "Some Second Thoughts on Substantive versus Functional Definitions of
Religion", 127-128.
42 Cfr. Karel Dobbelaere, Jan Lauwers, “Defining Religion – A Sociological Critique”, Social Compass, Vol.20 (1973-
1974), 549.
43 Ninian Smart “What is Religion?”, 13-14.
44 Cfr.Mark Owen Webb, “An Eliminativist Theory of Religion”, Sophia, Vol. 48 (2009), 36.
8
yet if we apply analogy as part of the methodology of the study of religion, it may not be difficult to
discover certain common elements in them.
Another problem with the scholars who object to definition by essential elements is that their study
of religion remains at the level of the phenomena, and they fail to make a philosophical reflection on
the phenomenological data. This is once again a methodological deficiency. Unless the
phenomenological data is subject to philosophical reflection through rigorous use of comparison,
analysis, deduction, induction and intellectual intuition, one cannot discover any common element in
religions. For instance, religions may refer to a transcendent reality using different names, such as
Brahman, Trinity, Nirvana, Emptiness, state of isolation, etc. When we analyse these concepts from a
philosophical perspective it is not difficult to conclude that they all refer to a transcendent reality,
understood analogically.
Those who study religion must admit that not all the essential elements of religions are empirically
verifiable, though some of them can be, such as rituals, myths, narratives, institutions, religious
authority, religious community, ethical code, ability of religion to help people cope with life, etc. But at
the same time religious symbols and ritual acts have an intentionality that point to certain transcendent
realties, and which are beyond the grasp of those who employ the empirical method.
Certain essential elements of religion can be reached only through a philosophical reflection on the
religious data. Such an approach is justified because the study of religion belong to humanities and not
to science proper where the method employed is empirical. Strictly speaking the study of religion does
not fall within the field of science. Science has nothing to say about assertions that are beyond the
empirical. No one can prove scientifically that the supernatural beings or transcendental states about
which religious people speak do not in fact exist. As non-empirical entities, their existence can be
neither proven nor disproven by the method of science. Since religion, by any reasonable definition,
contains non-empirical elements, it is clearly an unfit object for application of the scientific method.45
Hence there is no a priori reason to deny the validity of definition of religion by essential elements.
Conclusion
We conclude by affirming that defining religion is possible and necessary for the study of the
religious data. Definitions of religion can serve to stimulate the understanding of the nature of religion.
Religion is a complex phenomenon, and as such no single definition can capture all its aspects. Hence
there is no point in advancing a single definition of religion hoping that it would meet with universal
acceptance or be rated as the best by scholars. But this need not deter us from attempting definitions of
religion. But in defining religion one should keep aloof from ideological standpoints, and personal like
and dislikes. One should also make a clear distinction between a definition of religion and an
explanation of religion. Since religions are dynamic in nature and constantly evolving, the definitions
of religion must also become an on-going process. One should constantly re-think the fundamental
elements of one’s definition and refine them in accordance with the changed views in different
disciplines. As Peter Berger says, definitions are always ad hoc constructions and have a definitive
cognitive purpose.46 Finally we maintain that a complementary approach to defining religion is better
than a functional definition or definition by essential elements taken independently. Such an approach
would imply that the study of religion should be interdisciplinary.
46Cfr. Peter Berger L. "Some Second Thoughts on Substantive versus Functional Definitions of
Religion", 127.
10