GST311 Text Book PDF
GST311 Text Book PDF
GST311 Text Book PDF
©
ACKNOWLEDGMENT
□irnen^b zi y^bsiv/cMpl .aiaw Ji
i';i; I must register my gratitude to my numerous
colleagues, friends, “brethren”, and students (past and
present) whose constructive criticisms, comments,
observations and moral support have made this edition
possible. Of note are Dr. G. O. Ozumba, Dr. Princewill
Alozie, Dr. (Mrs.) Grace Umoren, Dr. Andrew Efemini, and
particularly Dr. Oghenekaro Ogbinaka. The contribution of
the philosophical guru, Professor J. I. Omoregbe, to my
academic progress has not gone unnoticed. His counsel and
encouragement have been invaluable.
I commend my wife and children for their love and
understanding during those lonely hours I was try ing to put
my ideas together.
The authors whose books were consulted are too
numerous to mention here.
I remain grateful to my publishers AAU VITALIS
BOOKS CO. for a job well done.
Finally, 1 give God the glory for who He is and what
He is to me.
I
. 1O22W
TABLE OF CONTENTS
:K lyicpifl J
:P Tjiquri.)
Foreword to Second Edition,
Preface to F irst Edition.......
Preface to Second Edition...
Preface to Third Edition.................................................. ......... viii
Preface to Fourth Edition...;.................................... ix
Acknowledgement........................... ................
V PARTONE:
PHILOSOPHY, SCIENCE AND PHILOSOPHY
OF SCIENCE
nsaitrnqoO arlT
Chapter 1:
Philosophy and its Rivals,.......................................1
Chapter 2:
What is Science..........................................................................20
Chapter 3:
What is Philosophy of Science,,.,, .........................................26
Chapter 4:
On the Relationship between philosophy and Science..........31
J ■ 'i-
33143132 14L22M PART TWO ) HH3 W
HISTORY OF SCIENCE
, „ . aP er‘’ .o
Ancient and Medieval Science..,,...,................................ —48
o v „ .CVP'?r,6: , O
Science in the Renaissance Interlude and Modern Science
(15“-17“ Century AD).... ......... .................. . ..................... 72
Chapter 7:
Science
/. :
in the 18 ,h , 19 lh and 20lhCenturies1 '............
i • I . *’ .
..r. .............. 77
1 1 I I I I I I»I 1 J t i t « /
Chapter 8:
History of Medicine........................ 87
Chapter 9:
History of Mathematics.......................................... 92
Chapter 10:
A Summary of the History of Western Science.................... 106
i PARTTHREEu ... •
PHILOSOPHY AND THE RISE OF MODERN SCIENCE
. Chapter 11:
Aristotelian Science.......... ....................................................... 116
Chapter 12:
The Copernican
Revolution............................... 121
Chapter 13:
The Scientific Method of Galileo, Descartes and Newton........ 128
Chapter 14:
Einstein's Theory of Relativity........................................ 136
Chapter 15:
Quantum Mechanics.......................................................... ....146
PART FOUR
SOME PHILOSOPHICAL ’ISMS’ IN SCIENCE
Chapter 16:
Rationalism and Empiricism in Science................................ 154
Chapter 17:
Realism in Science..................................... 164
’ Chapter 18:
Idealism ih Science................................... 179
Chapter 19:
Materialism in Science........................................................... 187
Chapter 20:
Pragmatism in Science............................................................ 194
Chapter 21:
Determinism in Science.......................................................... 204
PART FIVE
SOME PHILOSOPHIES/METHODS OF SCIENCE
Chapter 22:
Positive Methodology of Science........................................... 210
Chapter 23:
Inductivism and the Problem of Induction............................ 218
Chapter 24:
Critical Rationalist Methodology of Science (Karl Popper
and Imre Lakatos)..................................................................... 243
Chapter 25:
Historical and Revolutionary Science of Thomas Kuhn ....257
Chapter 26:
Marxist /Leninist Dialectical Methodology of Science............ 261
Chapter 27:
Feyerabend's Anarchic Conception of Science..................... 275
PART SIX
SOME ISSUES AND NOTIONS IN SCIENCE AND
TECHNOLOGY
Chapter 28:
Man: His Origin, Nature and Destiny, and Cosmic
Environment............... «....................................... .288
Chapter 29
The Notion of Scientific Explanation 307
Chapter 30
The Notion of Scientific Truth.......... .323
Chapter 31
The Notion of Scientific Progress.... 333
Chapter 32:
Technology in Nigeria: Transfer and Appropriateness... ..........343
PART SEVEN
ENERGY RESOURCES AND ENVIRONMENT
ui ■' «-i I Z1A 8
HHO
Chapter 33:
Energy Resources........... «....,,........................................ 358
Chapter 34:
Environmental Pollution ..................................... 366
■l **
!*• ■
PART EIGHT
igqqc NUTRITION, DISEASE AND HEALTH
EK.......... ...................... ■
Chapter 35:
Nutrition.. •••••••
rl GJ J J ■........... ■• *.......... 37 6
Chapter 36:
Newer and Common Diseases..p.j,...... ............ 395
Chapter 37:
Preventive Health Practices........................... 413
<____________________________________________________ -
t
CHAPTER ONE
PHILOSOPHY AND ITS RIVALS
In this chapter, I will first discuss briefly the question
-what is philosophy? Next, I will examine the connection
between philosophy and each of its rivals. In the concluding
part, I will assert and defend the view that commonsense is
the bedrock of knowledge, whether mythic, religious,
philosophic or scientific. I shall also try to debunk the
alleged superiority of science to other disciplines.
What is Philosophy?
It is difficult, if not impossible, to define philosophy
in a given way. To attempt to define philosophy is like
attempting to catch one’s shadow. Because of the
complexity of the phenomenon of philosophy, we can only
give ‘a definition of philosophy’ and not ‘the definition of
philosophy’. No wonder some sarcastic persons have
preferred to define it as everything and/or nothing. This is
not to say that serious efforts have not been made to define
the term. But the fact is that they are only efforts or
attempts. For this reason, instead of trying to define
philosophy in a given way, it is better to look at the different
conceptions of the term. Even at that, there are as many
conceptions as there are different schools of philosophy.
Let us, however, examine some of the many conceptions of
philosophy
a) Etymological Conception:
The oldest'and of course the broadest concept of
philosophy is derived from the etymological analysis of the
1
term which means love of wisdom or the^ursuitofetemal
truths. This conception of philosophy is credited to the
Greek Mystic, Philosopher and Mathematician Pythagoras.
Wisdom in the context of this conception of philosophy
covers all areas (both theoretical and practical) where
intelligence can be exercised or displayed. Philosophy, in
this sense, is seen as a universal science, which proposes to
provide a true and reasonable explanation of the whole of
reality through its ultimate principles. This was the
meaning given to philosophy during the ancient, medieval
and modern period of Western philosophy. For instance,
during ancient period of Greek philosophy, Aristotle held
that philosophy and science meant the same tiling.
In more recent times, most philosophers are no
longer concerned with the formulation of complete systems
of thought about the whole reality. Rather, they are
interested in clarifying and analyzing the concepts, theories
and presuppositions of other disciplines. Consequently,
philosophy is now seen as a second-order discipline
concerned primarily with helping other disciplines to
resolve their conceptual and linguistic problems.
kX”
b] The Positivist Conception:
The positivists ably represented by BertrandRussell
andmembers of the Vienna Circle, conceive of philosophy
as a collective term for any knowledge claim that is yet to be
^empirically verified or confirmed. This conception has
, been criticized for its antf metaphysical stance.
.1
c] The Existentialist Conception:
According to the existentialist philosophers, the
concern of philosophy transcends normal human reason or
mere intellectual activity alone, the human will and the
fantasy also come into play.
2
d] The Linguistic Conception:
This is also called the analytic conception of
philosophy. Here analysis of the language of philosophy
and other disciplines is seen as the main business of
philosophy.
3
i] The Scientific Conception:
Philosophy is concerned with the nature of arid
claims about scientific knowledge and the analysis of
scientific concepts to make their usage clear.
It nlust be mentioned that the various conceptions
outlined above are associated with the different objects of
philosophy and hence the different branches of philosophy.
We have also seen that philosophy goes after general as
opposed to specific questions. “Where the individual
disciplines stop their inquiry, philosophy questions further.
For instance, where the other disciplines formulate laws,
philosophy asks, what are laws? Where they claim
knowledge, philosophy asks, what is knowledge”
(Bochenski21).
4
view of the world is the view that there is an external,
physical world^that pauses the perception we do have, and
that our perceptions of the external world more or less
resemble the qualities that are really present in the object.
For the commonsense person * . therefore, appearance is
reality; there is no other reality behind or other than what is
presented to us'by our senses. An object that appears to be
yellow is really yellow; the one that is perceived to be hot or
cold is really hot or cold. In short, the physical world exists
independent of the perceivers. If all perceivers were
eliminated, there would still be a physical world, though, of
course, there would be no sentient beings to perceive it.
This view is also called naive realism. G. E. Moore (1873 -
1925) is an advocate of the commonsense view of l* e
world. He stated his celebrated position in his influential
essay “A Defence of Coninionsense" (1925). To quote
Walsh who quoted Moore’s words from this essay:
There exists a living human body, which is my
body. The body was born at a certain time in
the past, and has existed continuously ever
since, though not without undergoing
changes,.. .ever since it was born, it has either
been in contact with or not far from the surface
of the earth; and at every moment since it was
bom, there have also existed many other
things, having shape and size in three
dimensions ...from which it has been at
various instances...Among the things
which...have formed part of its
environment...there have ...been large
numbers of other living bodies... which have
lived upon the earth.. .each has been the body
of a different human being, who has during the
5
life time of that body, had many different
experiences (just as 1 had mine) (114).
G. E. Moore regards each of these propositions as a
truism. These statements as could be seen are all concrete
statements, that is, statements about particular bodies or
objects. What in essence Moore was trying to assert in a
general sense is that material objects are real and that beside
myself there are other sentient beings in the universe.
According to Walsh, “Moore wants to point out the
impossibility of simultaneously subscribing to a
philosophical thesis of idealism, that nothing exj^ts except
spirit, and persisting in the asseverations of everyday life.
Given that we are sometimes correct in the latter (and on
this point Moore says that none of us is in any real doubt),
the falsity of the former immediately follows” (Walsh 114).
Moore does not, however, think that • commonsense is
infallible. He seems to have treated universal or very
general acceptance as the identifying mark of a
commonsense belief and he mentions that things that
everybody once believed have turned out to be false. He is
also prepared to allow that there might be many false
propositions included within the vague boundaries of the
commonsense view of the world (Edwards 158).
Now, how is philosophy connected with
commonsense? Some people have argued that philosophy
is synonymous with commonsense. Their argument is that
every philosophy contains some cultural imprints or as
Bertrand Russell put it, philosophers are the outcome of
their milieu (7). I wish to argue, on the contrary, that the
whole activities and beliefs of men of different cultures do
not constitute philosophy simpliciter. It is common
knowledge that inherent in every culture are elements of
ignorance, emotion, superstition, prejudices and
assumption. But these do not really constitute philosophy.
6
It is “the attempt to ascertain the truth of these cultural
elements, which is not in any way designed to comfort the
ignorant or assuage the fears of superstition, and which is
not to be judged by emotional criteria that should be called
philosophy” (Jones 202).
I concede that philosophy might begin with and
analyze cultural beliefs. But I wish to argue that it extends
beyond them. It is too naive to hold that these cultural
beliefs are what make up philosophy. Cultural survivals and
manifestations conceived of as philosophy is
commonsensical and are thus considered by philosophers
as raw data. Philosophy in the academic or professional
sense goes beyond commonsense, though as .mentioned
above, it (sometimes) uses commonsense beliefs as raw
materials and as starting point of its procedures. /
Philosophy, in the end, is a critique of commonsense.
Commonsense postulates the existence of the external
world as a given (without critical reflection). But
philosophy critically reflects on what is given to determine
whether the knowledge claim about it is authentic or not.
For instance, the philosopher might criticize the
commonsense view that objects are really what they are as
presented to us by our senses. He can do this by alluding to
the fact that we sometimes perceive things the way they are
not (such as in illusory perceptions) and sometimes we
perceive things that are not (such as in hallucinations). He
may further ask, if our senses deceive „us sometimes, why
not always? He may continue this argument until he settles
down with the conclusion that the commonsense view leads
to solipsism - the view that my subjective experiences and I
are the only objects that exist.
Let me mention that the commonsense view is a
philosophical position in the debates regarding the
ontological status of the external world. Because of the
7
unreflective nature of the position, attempts have been
made to refute it. Philosophical doctrines like
representationism (or critical realism), idealism and
phenomenalism (or sense - datum theory) are reactions
against the commonsense or naive realist position.
Closely connected with commonsense is intuition. It
must be admitted that the term ‘intuition’ is verbally
indefinable (Hospers 136). At any rate, it can be described
as a kind of experience or conviction that comes to one
suddenly like a lightening flash and instantly one is
convinced that what comes to one in the flash is true. To
know something by intuition is to know it a prior. If an
intuitious experience grows over a period of weeks or
months we will no longer call it intuition. However, like
commonsense, philosophy brings the acceptability of
intuition to question when it is made to underwrite a claim
to knowledge. Intuitious knowledge is sometimes
subsumed under commonsense because both claims to
. knowledge are held without critical reflection.
Consequently, some of the problems that face the
commonsense realist also face the intuitionist. For one
thing, intuitive knowledge is subjective knowledge. It is
common knowledge that different people’s intuitions
conflict and there is no direct way of ascertaining which of
the conflicting intuitions is right. Like is with the
commonsense position, the ultimate problem facing the
intuitionist is-solipsism.
9
things, and the nature and destiny of man. I think
O’Connor was drawing a demarcating line between mythic
thought and philosophic thought when he said:
In the myths the great mystery is explained by
analogy with, and using the terminology of
biological processes, and the actors are
anthropomorphic monsters. In Milesian
cosmology these biological processes are
Jaced
^-re
* by manufacturing processes
/'(“separating off’ and “felting”) arid the gods
are replaced by a material. It is not “more
C ’ rational” to prefer manufacturing processes to
gods, unless you have good evidence in your
favour. But though they were not scientists,
they (the milesians) show a commonsense and
unmystical attitude, which is a part of the
scientific temper (3).
Apart from the above distinction, another distinction
between mythic thought and philosophic thought is that
whereas there is a blurring of classes in the former, the latter
begins with classification of things in the world. All this is
not to say that there is no continuity between mythic
thought and philosophic thought. There is not only
continuity, but a connection. Indeed, it is on record that the
mythic thoughts of Homer and Hesiod greatly influenced
th^presocratic philosophers in their speculations about the
world. Needless to say that in African metaphysics,
ontology is intimately bound up with myths. We proceed to
examine the connection between philosophy and religion.
10
Philosophy and Religion
Etymologically, there was a marriage between
philosophy and religion. Many great philosophers of
antiquity were greatly influenced by their religious beliefs.
For instance, the Pythagorean mathematical conception of
the universe was in no small way influenced by the Orphic
religious teachings on the problems of purification and
immortality of the soul. According to Stumpf, “Pythagoras
became interested in mathematics for what appear to be
religious reasons. His originality could be said to consist in
his conviction that the study of mathematics is the best
purifier of the soul” (9-10).
Apart from the Pythagoreans, the philosophical
speculations of Socrates, Plato and Plotinus were greatly
influenced by their religious convictions. It may also
interest us to know that in their attempt to explain the
confluence between philosophy and religion the medieval
thinkers (the ‘Fathers’ of the Church.) extolled religion
above philosophy. Their dictum was ‘I believe in order to
understand’, which meant for them that belief in God
preceded understanding' df phenomena. What this boils
down to is that faith precedes reason.
The influence of religion on philosophy seems not to
have been substantial during the modem period. The
analytic philosophers of the contemporary philosophy
would not entertain anything speculative. They treated
religious or metaphysical assertions as meaningless
because of their inability to stand the test of meaningfulness
or verifiability. In their attempt to destroy religion and
metaphysics, the analysts destroyed philosophy as well.
Wittgenstein’s claim in the Tractatus that “whereof one
- , ’ ’• *
- ' ’ll
cannot speak, thereof one must be silent” was no doubt a
destructive blow to traditional speculative philosophy.
Russell’s definition of philosophy as the no man’s land that
stands in between science and theology is a way of saying
that philosophy is neither factual (science) nor dogmatic
(theology). But this does not mean that today philosophy
has nothing to do with religion. In the various “philosophies
of’ which come under the subject of philosophy, we have
philosophy of religion, which is currently concerned with
tackling conceptual puzzles and difficulties that arise out of
religious beliefs and practices. For instance, to say that
Jesus Christ was God made flesh to redeem mankind from
sin is to trigger off a religious issue, which poses a
theoretical, conceptual puzzle. The philosopher might want
to know how God, generally thought of as a spiritual,
immaterial being could become flesh and bones. How does
this work for him after about 2000 years? Now, to solve this
puzzle, it is the philosopher again who comes to the rescue
" -in the form of a theologian. He might stiy that Jesus and God
are one and the same. Just as the same substance can have
different properties without itself changing in any essential
way, so the spiritual nature of God can take on material form
without undergoing substantial change. God the Father and
. Jesus are different manifestations of the same underlying
substance (Blocker & Hannaford 162). One of the greatest
proponents of this position is Baruch Spinoza (1632 -
1677).
12
of fact, there was no sharp distinction between pl^losophy
and science. For instance, ancient Greek thinkers, were both
philosophers and scientists, though their science is often
described as crude or primitive. Until recently, the various
sciences (especially physics) came under the name
“Natural philosophy”. In time, the various sciences broke
away from philosophy and became independent
disciplines. This is why today we have the various sciences
such as physics, Chemistry, biology, astronomy, and even
the social sciences, which of late became independent
sciences.
It is often said that various sciences broke away from
philosophy because they have been able to solve certain
problems which philosophy could not solve, and that when
problems are solved by sciences, there is no further need for
the philosopher. But I wish to maintain that this -js not
completely true. Even after science has solved certain
problems there remains the need to understand, interpret
and evaluate the body of facts accumulated by science.
Facts do not evaluate themselves, neither do they clearly
reveal to us what should or should not be done. It is the
philosopher who seeks to assimilate and understand these
facts and also seeks to put them into a larger and more
general context, which includes humanity’s quest for a
rational and fulfilling destiny (Stumpf 2). Today,
philosophy of science takes care of this function. Apart
from its role of clarifying and analyzing scientific concepts
and theories with the aim of making their scientific usage
clear, philosophy of science functions as a second order
discipline that attempts to answer the following questions;
What characteristics distinguish scientific inquiry from
13
other types of investigation? What procedures should
scientists follow in investigating nature? What conditions
must be fulfilled for a scientific explanation to be correct?
What is the cognitive status of scientific laws and
principles?
What 1 have tried to show above is that contrary to
the generally held view that there is no connection
whatsoever between philosophy and science, there is
indeed a deep connection between the two disciplines. In
fact, the activities of the philosopher and the scientist do
interpenetrate. For instance, it is the scientist who judges
one theory to be superior to another, but it is the philosopher
who evaluates the criteria of acceptability implied in the
judgment of the scientist. The observation of the close tie
between science and philosophy must have prompted John
Losee to say that:
The scientist who is ignorant of precedents in
the evaluation of theories is not likely to do an
adequate job of evaluation himself. And the
philosopher of science who is ignorant of
scientific practice is not likely to make
perceptive pronouncements on scientific
method (2).
14
bedrock of all fields of knowledge. Commonsense provides
the raw materials for all other areas of study mentioned in
this chapter. Myth, religion, philosophy and science all
draw upon commonsense in their quest for knowledge. The
alleged superiority of philosophy to commonsense does not
really hold. It can be rightly argued that philosophy does not
only begin with commonsense, it also ends with it. If
philosophers are continually testing and questioning
commonsense without ever having a consensus opinion on
the answers to the questions raised, does it not mean that
philosophy never really advance beyond the level of
commonsense? Are philosophical positions not merely the
subjective and biased claims of individual philosophers- a
situation leading to solipsism? Let it be stated categorically
that aside from disputes and disagreements among
individual philosophers, no single philosopher ever agrees
with himself. The individual philosopher keeps changing
his views with time. Even the alleged superiority of science
over myth, commonsense and philosophy, and in short all
other disciplines does not hold. I make bold to say that
science is founded on and nurtured by commonsense. Take
for instance the historical development of the theory of
atomism. This theory is by all accounts founded on
commonsense and myth. It has thrived on commonsense
speculation and bold guessing. In its original form as
propounded by Leucippus and Democritus, the term ‘atom’
meant ‘not cut’. It means ‘not cut’ because it was believed
that atoms were indivisible. The atoms were regarded as the
ultimate units of the world or the simplest particles of
matter. It was also believed that sense impressions and
appearances were produced by atoms, and that the changes
15
observable in the world were caused by real changes in the
positions and arrangements of atoms. Life itself was
thought to depend on the retention (through the process of
respiration) within the body of sufficient number of soul
atoms. One peculiar characteristic of the Democritian
atoms is that they had size, shape and position, but no
weight. And because they had no weight, they moved
randomly irj-tlW void like dust particles. But following the
death of Democritus, the theory of atomism declined and
was overshadowed by the views of the Socratics. The
theory was however revived in the 4th century B. C. by
Epicurus who added weight to size, shape and position as
the basic attributes of atoms. After the death of Epicurus
nothing was heard about atomism until two centuries later
when Lucritus (the Roman poet) revived it. From this point
atomism disappeared not to resurface until 17th century
when Galileo revived it. In the 20th century, Einstein gave a
new conception of atom in his quantum theory, denying the
indestructibility of atoms. In short, atom is no longer
regarded as solid and indivisible but divisible into
electrons, protons, neutrons and so on. Another good
example is the overthrow of the geocentric view of the
world by the heliocentric view of the world. Ptolemy had
proposed the geocentric theory, which placed the earth at
the centre of the universe. The whole world was made to
take this view as a scientific truth. But later a man by name
Nicolaus Copernicus proposed the heliocentric theory,
which explained the solar system much more convincingly
than the Ptolemaic conception. Even over the years the
heliocentric theory of Copernicus has been seriously
modified.
I
16
. These two examples suffice to show that scientific
truths and theories keep changing with time as
commonsense knowledge changes. This shows that the
generally held belief that the sciences are bodies of
established facts is mistaken. There is nothing either
permanent or unalterable in science, and science does nor
necessarily grow by adding new certainties. As Karl
Popper put it in his The Logic ofScientific Discovery:
The empirical basis of objective science has
nothing thus absolute about it. Science does
not rest on solid bedrock. The bold structure of
its theories rises, as it were, above a swamp;
but not down to any natural or “given” base,
and if we stop driving the piles deeper, it is not
because we have reached firm ground. We
simply stop when we are satisfied that the piles
are firm enough to carry the structure, at least
for the time being (111)
Popper calls science conjecture and refutation or
trial and error. Science, for him, is constantly engaged in
falsifying theories to death and formulating new ones.
Imagination and guesswork, he would argue, play
prominent-roles in science. All this boils down to the point
that science is not far from commonsense. Science is as
illusory and unreliable as commonsense. What on earth
made Paul Feyerabend to equate science with magic? Of
course, it is partly because of the problems discussed
above.
I do not share the view that physics falsifies
commonsense or naive realism. People who hold this view
make a distinction between ‘things as they appear to us’ and
17
‘things as they are in themselves’. While the naive realist is
concerned with things as they appear to us, the physicist is
concerned with things as they are in themselves. For
example, while the naive realist would assert that colour is
really in the table, the physicist would argue that colour is
not really in the table but is caused by the presence of light
and the emitting of electromagnetic radiation from the sun.
Now the whole idea of things as they are in
themselves or that there is a reality behind appearance is
indeed a metaphysical inquiry. Does this not mean that
physics is plagued with metaphysics while commonsense
is free from it? This problem led philosophers like Ramsey
to call commonsense or naive realism ‘the primary system’
and physical theory (physics) as ‘the secondary system’.
According to Michael Dummett,
The “primary system” embodies “the sum
total of... purely factual propositions; the
function of the secondary system is ‘purely
explanatory’, and the entities to which it refers,
in so far as they cannot be identified with those
figuring in the primary system, are simply
conceptual tools serving to arrange the
primary facts. This then is simply a version of
instrumentalism. The actual facts, the hard
facts; those that we really believe to obtain, are
those of the primary system; the statements of
scientific theory represent fictions, in which
we do not really believe (as Ramsey confessed
that he did not really believe in astronomy), but
which we devise as a vivid means of
encapsulating patterns and regularities
detectable amongst the primary facts (1).
This is not to say that the commonsense view
presents a single, unchanging theory, unadulterated by the
smatterings of philosophical and scientific knowledge.
Indeed, the idea of a commonsense view of the world
uninfluenced or unaffected by either philosophic or
scientific knowledge is a myth. In actual fact, all are
profoundly affected, in their view of the world and of
ordinary things in it, by the smatterings of scientific
knowledge that they possess” (Dummett 18). But what 1 am
insisting on is that commonsense is tl^ebasis or foundation
of all knowledge. It provides the raw materials upon which
the various disciplines draw in their attempt to establish
knowledge claims.
19
CHAPTER TWO
WHAT IS SCIENCE?
Different Conceptions of Science
in studying the philosophy of science, it seems
reasonable and logical to begin with a definition of science.
But this is not an easy task. There is no one standard
definition of the term. Consequently, instead of looking for
a standard definition of science, it is advisable to look at
different conceptions of science. Let us discuss some of
them.
Literally, and according to various dictionary
definitions, the term ‘science’ means knowledge arranged
in an organized or orderly manner, especially knowledge
derived from experience, observation and experimentation.
For this reason, it is often claimed that scientific knowledge
is proven knowledge. Science is based on what we can see,
touch, taste, hear and smell. Personal opinions, prejudices
or preferences, superstitions and speculative imaginings
have no place in science. From this conception, it is clear
that science is a discipline. It has shown that science is
systematic and comprehensive. It has characteristic
methods, addresses specific types of questions, advances
specific types of answers and carries with it a fund of results
(often changing) as well as characteristic set of
propositions (also sometimes changing) (Ratzsch 14).
It must, however, be mentioned that not all
disciplines are sciences. For instance, engineering is a
discipline, yet not a science in the strict sense of the word.
While engineering is an applied discipline, the sciences are
basically theoretical disciplines dealing essentially with
theoretical processes and principles. Whereas the former
20
deals with the practicalities of ‘how to’, the latter are more
concerned with understanding. This, of course, is not to say
that its being theoretical distinguishes natural science from
other disciplines. Philosophy itself is theoretical in this
broad sense. But while philosophy is basically concerned
with abstract or immaterial phenomena and concerns, the
objects of science are material things and events. Yet the
material or natural is not the only concern of the sciences.
For instance, theology is also concerned with the natural
world, though in terms of God’s specific activity. However,
rather than seeking supernatural explanations of events in
the world, the science .seek to provide naturalistic or
mechanistic explanations of the events in their specTTTc~
domains.
Science has been broadly classified into two, namely,
-"Tealscience and formal science. While the former goes after
sensory realdies^or^empirical data^ the latter goes after
abstract structures or entities.TVfiile the former achieves its
fesultsllirou^?expenence?observation and testing of facts,
the latter achieves its result through logical reasoning.
Included within the purview of real science are the natural
sciences, the social sciences and the cultural sciences;
whereas formal science includes mathematics, structural
science and formal logic.
Three concepts, according to the first conception of
science still under consideration, namely, the empirical, the
objective and the rational are centraLto real science. In other
words, real science must possess empirical base, objectivity
and rationality. First, a genuine science must be in tune with
relevant facts or empirical data by senses or by empirical
processes. Secondly, the empirical base of science cannot
be an arbitrary one. This is where science differs from
'pseudo-science. While the empirical data of pseudo
science are often preferentially selected, real science
21
exhibits some degree of objectivity in handling those data.
Thirdly, real science requires that there be some rational
connection between empirical data and explanatory theory?
How is the achievement of these criteria or norms ensured?
The answer is not far - fetched. The empirical base of
science is preserved mainly through testing; mathematics
constitutes one of the reliable ways of preserving
rationality within science; the communal or public nature
of science is one way in which objectivity is fostered in
science. From this conception of science, the following
working definition of science emerges: “..■Science is a
theoretical explanatory discipline which" objectively
addresses naturaTphenomena witfnn the general constraint^
That (1) its theories must be rationally connectable to~~
generally specifiable empirical phenomena and that (2) it
normally does not leave the natural realm for the concepts
employed in its explanations” (Ratzsch 15).
A second view of science has it that science is a study
of the mastery of man’s material environment. This implies
*
the application of scientific knowledge, principles, laws
and theories in solving man’s environmental problems. The
limitation of this definition stems from the fact that it tends
to identify science with the tangible result of its
applications. This conception of science obviously
confuses science with technology. Again, since it limits
science to the physical (the study of matter), it excludes the
non-physical from the realm of science. Such a conception
is grossly inadequate. Science is sometimes concerned with
the non-physical.
A third conception of science identifies science with
scientific methods. This conception recognizes
experimentation as the only authentic procedure of
observing the consequences of events and circumstance
over which man is incapable of' controlling or
22
manipulating. A conception such as this makes no room for j
sciences like geology and astronomy (which are generally ;
considered as exact sciences). Apart from that, it tends to
undermine the strong theoretical and logical flavour
needed to hold together the results of observations and
experiments and give them force and which provides the
basis for the explanation of similar future observations.
Most philosophers conceive of .science as a
systematic process of searching for the truth about nature
.through logical inference from empirical observations and
.testing. This involves drawing a generalization from the
instances, which have been observed to occur several
times. In a general sense, observations are made using the
sense organs to collect impressions. Pre-requisite
conditions for observations include ability to imagine,
curiosity to investigate and motivation to search for
explanation (Okoroji 35). These enable the scientist to
piece together his observations in an orderly manner. As it
is practically impossible to make all observations
concerning a phenomenon, the scientist obviously and
actually jumps to conclusion without waiting for further
confirming instances. Past and repeated observations
generate a confidence on the future reoccurrence of the
phenomenon. A general statement is thus formulated
concerning the phenomenon and this is taken as a
hypothesis. This hypothesis is a tentative law considering
23
theory as scientific bearing upon reality and generally
. applicable within its domain of operation. As will be shown
in the chapter dealing with Inductivism and the Problem of-
Induction, this conception of science is replete with
insurmountable difficulties, chief among which is the
problem of‘inductive leap’, the leap from the known to the
unknown, from finite data of experience to an infinite
datum.
In conclusion, an integrative or synoptic definition of
science can be gleaned from the four conceptions discussed-
above. According to this eclectic definition, science is a-
process of searching for the truth about nature, and the
product that results from such a process. As a process
science involves scientific methodology; as a product,
science involves scientific knowledge - facts, concepts,
. laws, theories, generalizations, and other forms oi
knowledge which guide practices and find applications as
technology, and as stored and written in textbooks and
taught to learners as science. It will be necessary to round
off this section with a few words on scientific methodology.
Scientific Methodology
The enterprise of science has been progressive. Ever
since it be^an to evolve into' its modem form especially
from the 16" century onward, most discoveries have tended
to follow a pattern or procedure that can roughly be called
‘scientific methodology’. This procedure involves various
elements such as observational procedures, patterns of
arguments, methods of representation and calculations, and
the evaluation of the grounds of their validity from the
points of view of^ormal logic, practical methodology and
metaphysics. The general procedure generally held to be
successful involves five major steps namely;
24 I
i
(a) Problem Formulation: Here efforts are made to ask
pertinent questions concerning the occurrence of a certain
phenomenon. For instance, how does a bat (generally
believed not to see in daytime) fly in the daytime without
having an accident?
25
CHAPTER THREE
26
though all our knowledge, consists of a series of
impressions derived from the senses, yet we obviously
possess a kind of knowledge, which does not arise from
experience even though it begins with experience. Thus,
for Kant, there are_two sources of knowledge, namely,
sensibility and understanding. Consequently, Kant
distinguished between phenomenal reality and noumenal.
reality. While the former refers to the world as we
experience it, the latter refers to intelligible, nonsensual
reality, or the thing-in-itself.
' ” WtuTFphenomenal reality is the object of scientific
investigation, noumenal reality is associated with
philosophy. Thus with Kant, there was a formal separation
between science and philosophy. But interestingly, Kant
maintained that, rather than being diametrically opposed to
one another, both realms (phenomena and noumenal)
complement one another. While the phenomenal realm
supplies us with knowledge of reality external to us, the
noumenal realm helps us to organize the raw materials
presented to us by our senses. This shows that while the
former increases our knowledge, the latter reminds us of
the limits of our knowledge. Consequently, the latter
(which is philosophy in general, and philosophy of science
in particular) helps us to tackle the problems that arise from
the former (sciencef Let us now examine the different
conceptions of philosophy of science.
(a) Philosophy of science consists in the formulation of
world-views that are consistent with findings in science or
based on scientific laws and theories. Although this
conception looks good, yet when the sledge-hammer of
criticism is applied against it, it will be found not to serve as
27
a working definition in this work. The formulation of
world-views cannot be the function of philosophy of
science because it is inconsistent with the principal
functions of philosophy, which are reflection and analysis.
Again, to say that philosophy of science consists in the
formulation of world-views based on important scientific
theories or laws tends to project the philosopher of science
as one who has nothing to do except and until scientific
theories or laws are formulated. The interest of the
philosopher of science goes beyond pointing out the
implication of theories.
(b) Philosophy of science is concerned with uncovering the
presuppositions and predispositions of the scientist. This
conception is borne out of the fact that philosophy is a
presuppositionless and predispositionless discipline. The
philosopher of science does not presuppose or predispose
any knowledge claim, but, instead, he strives to unveil the
presuppositions and predispositions of other disciplines.
Science, for instance, presupposes that there are
regularities or uniformities in nature, which can be
discovered by the investigator. Scientists are predisposed to
accept deterministic laws or explanations rather than
teleological explanations. The task of the philosopher of
science is the uncovering of presuppositions or
predispositions such as these. But it must be argued that this
is an accurate picture of what.a sociologist does. Thus, this
conception"Tbnds to assimilate philosophy of science to
’ sociology. But philosophy of science does not proceed like
sociology and their methodologies are quite different from
one another.
28
(c) Philosophy of science is the clarification and analysis of
scientific theories and concepts with the aim of making
their scientific usage clear. Now, there are problems
associated with this conception of philosophy of science.
First, the position tends to portray the scientist as someone
who has no regard for meaning as he does for facts. And so.
he needs the philosopher of science to explain the meaning
of the concepts he uses to him. Another possibility is that
the scientist understands the concepts he uses but that he
does not consider it important to begin to waste time
analyzing a concept whose meaning is assumed to be
generally known. But it is a well-known fact that scientists
do inquire into the relations of a particular concept to other
concepts and to operations of measurement [Losee 35]
Our conclusion here must be that although analysis
of scientific concepts is part of the business of philosophy
of science, not all conceptual analysis carried out in science
qualifies as philosophy of science.
[d] Philosophy of science plays a second order role to
science by answering questions bordering on the meaning
of scientific concepts such as law, theory and explanation,
the nature of, and claims about, scientific knowledge, the
logic and procedures of scientific explanation, and the
cognitive status of scientific laws and principles.
It can be seen that although the fourth conception
incorporates some elements of the second and third
conceptions, it is, nevertheless, the best of the four
conceptions. The reason is that in it the traditional
distinction between ‘is’ and ‘ought’, that is, between doing
science arid thinking about science is brought into focus.
Following this, science is to be seen as a discipline whose
subject-matter is the explanation of facts, while philosophy
29
of science is to be seen as a second-order discipline whose
subject matter is the analysis of not only the concepts and
theories of science but also the procedures and logic of
scientific explanation.
Regarding the nature and manner of scientific
inquiry, at least two positions, namely, empiricism and
realism, have emerged. While the empiricist standpoint has
it that scientific inquiry is carried out inductively through
observation and experimentation, the realist school holds
that since we cannot know everything through observation
and experimentation, the inductive method of scientific
inquiry is to be treated as inadequate. In trying to acquire
knowledge, the knower [the scientist] brings in his
organizing capacity, and this varies from scientist to
scientist by reason of circumstances of age, training and
prejudices [Losee 35],
30
CHAPTER 4
ON THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN
PHILOSOPHY AND SCIENCE
Introduction
In this chapter, we will first clarify further the meaning of
philosophy and science before delving into the similarity and
difference between them.
What is Philosophy?
It is difficult, if not impossible, to give a precise
definition of philosophy. In fact, the issue of the definition of
philosophy is as controversial as controversy itself.
Consequently, there are basic differences of opinion regarding
what constitutes the subject matter of philosophy. However, the
broadest, and of course, the oldest conception of philosophy is
its etymological conception. Etymologically, the term
'philosophy' derives from the ancient Greek noun 'philosophia'
which literally translates to 'love of wisdom'. Wisdom here does
not connote mere knowledge, for it is possible to have
knowledge and yet be unwise. But wisdom simply refers to the
ability to put knowledge to good or practical use. True, a wise
man is one who knows what he has to do and actually plans and
manages to do it properly. This is true wisdom which philosophy
aims to impart. This deepest knowledge can only be acquired by
the unaided powers of reason, not by the senses, authority or
revelation.
Apart from the etymological conception, each school of
philosophy has its own view of what philosophy is and how it is
to be practiced. For the platonic tradition, the goal of philosophy
is the attainment of wisdom through a vision of the absolute
ideas: beauty, truth, piety,justice and so on. Human knowledge,
31
for Plato, is only a stepping stone for the apprehension of these
absolute realities in and for themselves. On his part, Aristotle
questions the ontological bifurcation of philosophy into
practical and theoretical, claiming that the function of the
philosopher is the investigation of all fields through
observations and speculations which constitute knowledge in
these fields. For him, philosophy is a fundamental science, in
which man, using his powers of thought, attempts to discern the
nature of being, substance, unity, plurality, causality, change,
and other such theoretical notions which are basic to the other
sciences. In this investigation, the extent of his knowledge is
limited only by the powers of his own rational faculty
(Bronstein, et al 3). In arguing against the notion of philosophy
as a theoretical enterprise which can be engaged in and
understood without reference to daily practical living, the
pragmatists, ably represented by William James and John
Dewey, are of the view that philosophy is a practical venture,
whose main goal is the transformation of existing realities. This
view is somewhat akin to the Marxian view that, for a
philosophy to be significant, it must ensue in action directed
towards specific goals. Thus, for Marx, philosophy is an
instrument for attaining social and political goals. For Thomas
Aquinas, there is no formal separation between philosophy and
theology. He maintains that the proper way to philosophize is to
blend the study of philosophy with obedience to the Christian
k faith. The advantage of this, he probably reasoned, is to protect
philosophical research against the risk of error while still giving
room for freedom of investigation. Finally, analytic
philosophers are of the view that the main business of
philosophy is the analysis of language or the clarification of
meaning. Analytic philosophy takes the process of analysis to be
the central philosophical method and progress. It holds that the
surface form of a language may conceal hidden logical structure,
32
and may mislead us as to that structure. This could be revealed
by a process that would itself solve philosophical problems or
show them to be the offspring of the delusive surface forms of
ordinary language. The analysts believe that philosophical
analysis will provide a scientific, objective approach to
traditional problems. Just as a mathematician is able to define a
complex notion, reveals its identity in terms of a sequence of
31njp|pr operations, the philosopher-analyst will be able to
identify the nature of a complex concepts in terms of simple
constituent ideas and operations. Confidence in the method of *
analysis was booted by the early success of Frege and Russell in
reducing mathematics to logic, and by the insights gained from
the theory of definite descriptions. However, the programme of
philosophical analysis attained its peak with the early work of
the logical positivists, notably Carnap (Blackburn, 14-15).
Looking at the historical development of philosophy and
its division into various branches, it will be clearly seen that
early Greek philosophers seemed to have taken to themselves a
rather formidable task. Using contemporary categories, for
instance, Aristotle's works alone contain treatises on nature,
science, logic, political theory, moral philosophy (ethics),
epistemology and aesthetics. Over the centuries, however, the
philosophical enterprise has gone through much refinement
giving rise to various first-order disciplines such as physics,
chemistry, biology, mathematics, psychology, political science,
physiology, law, history and so forth. Philosophy now plays the
role of a second-order discipline whose chief concern is the
examination of the inquiries undertaken by these first-order
disciplines. As a result, we have established bodies of
knowledge in philosophy of science, philosophy of
mathematics, philosophy of the social sciences, philosophy of
law, philosophy of history and so on. Thus, contrary to the fear of
some people that the series of breakaways from philosophy
33
might narrow down its field of attention, the fact is that the field
of philosophy is ever widening in horizon. Moreover, its
traditional branches: metaphysics, epistemology, ethics, logic,
social and political philosophy, and aesthetics are as vibrant and
flourishing as they were in the early days of philosophy. That
does not however mean that contemporary philosophy is exactly
the same as ancient Greek philosophy. The fact is that there are
points of similarity and points of departure between them.
To conclude this section, it must be mentioned that virtually all
activities and professions raise philosophical issues. The
practice of law and medicine, science, psychology, theology,
electoral process, sports and even taxation all trigger off
philosophical questions. Woodhouse as cited in Velasquez (13)-
has put forward the following examples:
fnnd ) nFniRr^ /Iclrtnn srii
1. A neurologist while establishing correlations between
certain brain functions and the feeling of pain, begins to
wonder whether the 'mind' is distinct from the brain.
35
philosophical questions are continuously raised in everyday life
and conversations. It will not, therefore, be an overstatement to
conclude that philosophy is 'jack of all trades, master of all', the
'queen of all disciplines', the 'beautiful bride of all subjects', the
'synoptic visioner of all disciplines', the 'ultimate science', the
'gadfly of all subjects', the 'mother subject', the 'summit and
synthesis of all knowledge'. •
What is Science?
Science can be provisionally defined as “the process or group of
inter-related processes through which we have acquired our
modern, and ever changing knowledge of the natural world
which encompasses inanimate nature, life, human nature and
human society”(Richterl). Although this definition appears
narrow, it is however clear enough to indicate the approximate
boundaries of the subject matter of science and reasonably at
home with popular usage. Knowledge gotten through this
process may be regarded as 'scientific', with the understanding
that what is accepted as 'scientific' at one time may be termed
anachronistic at a later time. Those who creatively participate in
science are called 'scientists' while all 'scientists', as long as they
relate among themselves about their respective scientific
activities may be recognized as members of the scientific
community. A scientific community consists of members of a
scientific specialty who share the same goals, basic
assumptions, beliefs and norms. Although this conception of
science cautiously avoids commitments on some important
issues connected with the concept of science, it is obviously
broad enough to accommodate within its framework, a variety
of alternative conceptions of science. However, the conception
involves a strong sociological dimension in that it commits us to
a conception of science based on western standards, even though
science as we know, has existed to some extent in times and
cultures other than the western culture.
36
... x '■ ' • <\
t
Thus, conceived, science does have historical roots in
several ancient cultures, especially the Greek culture. However,
it first emerged in its modem form in Western Europe in the 17"'
century. As Richter observed, the transition from pre-modern to
modern science involved several inter-related aspects. For him,
science came to be associated with a distinctive view of nature as
operating according to general laws which remain largely
hidden under ordinary observational circumstances but which
can be uncovered through systematically controlled observation
and experiments. Science became reasonably, clearly
differentiated from such related subjects as philosophy, religion,
magic and technology. In other words, the role of the scientist
became differentiated from other roles, as scientists came to
communicate with each other systematically in ways which *
make the beginning of what is now called the 'scientific
community'. After many centuries of irregular growth, science
came to attain a self-reinforcing capacity which has become
noticeable in the massive, sustained growth of science from the
17th -century to the present time (2).
Modern science is thus distinctively European in origin.
From its birthplace in Western Europe, it has gradually spread to
non-western lands. The dual status of modern science as western
in its cultural background and its universal relevance has made it
a powerful catalyst in the transformation of the western culture
to a position of global dominance. The complex and changing
patterns of modern science are today evident in its
differentiation into the 'sciences' or 'branches of science'. Today,
we have the various physical, biological and social disciplines
which come under the rubrics of science. Some disciplines such
as physics and astronomy which are as old as science itself, have
produced fantastic results, and served as paradigms for the less
developed sciences. At the extreme are disciplines such as
37
I
sociology, which though they are comparatively young, have
nevertheless recorded some modest achievements and have
tended to imitate other sciences rather than serve as models to
others. Such disciplines are marginal as exemplification of
science, even though not intrinsically less scientific or less
important than those which provide richer sources of materials
for illustrating the scientific process (Richter,4).
The aims of the empirical (physical) sciences are
description, explanation and prediction. While description is
basic and indispensable to science, explanation and prediction
are somewhat related activities which arise as the most desirable
fruits of scientific labours whenever inquiries transcend the
mere fact-gathering stage.
The aims of the empirical scientists are essentially the
same I the whole field. They all seek descriptions, explanations
and predictions which as much as possible are adequate and
accurate in the given context of research. There are certain
standards or criteria by which the quest for scientific knowledge
is regulated. It must be mentioned that these are ideals to be
approximated, but which may never’be fully attained. The most
important of these criteria are as stated below:
*38
cultural bias. The objectivity of science is therefore based
on the fact that pure or naked facts form the basis of
scientific discoveries and theories. The criterion of inter-
subjective testability thus delimits the scientific from the
non-scientific activities of man.
39
degree than the problem in hand requires (you
need no razor to cut butter) (68)
42
explanation, is a synthetic view of its object. Since philosophy is
a discipline which subjects all things to critical examination to
give their raison d'etre, to that extent that it can be called a
science. Whereas the pure sciences are directed to groups of
objects more or less restricted, philosophy is interested in the
totality of reality. Philosophy is, thus, a general science, whose
formal object is common to all things and drawn by abstraction
from the very' depth of reality. It is the science of all things
through their simplest and most general reasons, or through their
most far-reaching causes (Uzoma, 23-24). The points of
similarity between philosophy and science can be summarized
as follows:
1. Philosophy and science are similar in their basic aim,
which is to understand the world and use this for man's
benefits. The difference between the two is just a matter
of degree. Philosophizing is a higher level of abstraction
than that of other branches of study. Mathematics ranks
higher than the empirical sciences on the level of mental
abstraction, while metaphysics ranks above both
mathematics and the physical sciences.
2. Both disciplines try to understand the world through
reflective thinking. In their approach to truth, they abhor
dogmatism, partiality and narrow mindedness. They are
interested in organized and systematized knowledge.
3. Both disciplines complement one another in that where
one stops, the other begins. When the particular sciences
have given partial explanation of reality, philosophy
takes over from there by organizing and systematizing
the piecemeal knowledge in a more complete and
integrated view of the world. In other words, science
provides the raw material (factual information) upon
43
which philosophy is built. That is why the philosophy of
any age is a reflection of the science of that age. Science,
on its part, check-balances philosophy by helping it to get
rid of unscientific ideas. Indeed, the outstanding
contributions of science in contemporary times have
gone a long way in resolving philosophical puzzles
which were hitherto unresolved. We conclude with
Uzoma that “philosophy and science complement,
support and clarify each other on the condition that both
hold strongly to things and respect each other” (28).
45
methods have made immense contributions to the development
and growth of science (32).
46
PART TWO
HISTORY OF SCIENCE
CH APTER 5
49
movement toward what we should call the temperament of
science” (4).
Man, it has always been claimed, has been a
scientist since his appearance on this planet. This idea is
supported by the fact that man’s attempt at building,
construction, agriculture and health - care through the use
of herbs has scientific bearings. However, the conscious
study and attempted analytical application of science
started in ancient Greece some 3000 years ago. As E. M.
Rogers put it,
if science is more than an accumulation of
tacts; if it is not simply positive knowledge;
but systematized positive knowledge; if it is
not simply unguided analysis and haphazard
empiricism but synthesis; if it is not simply a
passive recording, but constructive activity;
then undoubtedly (ancient Greece) was its
cradle [23].
It is exactly the view of some people that ancient
Greece is the cradle of science that we have set out to
examine in this chapter. To achieve the goal, surviving
fragments of the postulations of some early Greek
philosophers will be subjected to analysis, using materials,
methods and facts of modern scientific theories.^ the end,
it would have been re-established and re-asserted that
ancient Greece’s contributions are a sine qua non to modem
scientific development?-
The age of mythology was the age that preceded the
age of actual philosophical cum scientific speculations. In
fact, the genius of the Greeks-started from their mythology
about gods.- During the age of mythology [which lasted
between the 8th and 5"' centuries B.C.], all happenings in the
natural world were attributed to the behaviour of gods. The
Homeric gods were believed to inhabit Mount Olympus
50
•/
from where they came to intervene in human affairs when
occasions demanded it. These gods were however said to
be subject to the same fate as their human counterparts, jbkf
complete account will be given of the age of mythology
without making mention of the names of Homel and
Hesiod whose poems represented the spirit of the age. Sir
Dampier said of the Greek religion “it...was to interpret
nature and its processes in terms which could be
understood to make man feel at home in the world”[ 12],
But the consequence of attributing all occurrences
[whether good or bad] to the gods was that, instead of
looking into the scientific causes and explanations of such
occurrences, supernatural causes and explanations were
invoked and hence hindering real advance in human
knowledge. Hesiod summarized the spirit of the age when
he said, “There is no way to escape the will of Zeus”. This
submission to the will of the gods was the order of the day
and the consequence of this was recognized by scholars
such as Jones who said: “The myths not only failed to
inform; they actually inhibited scientific advance. As long
as the causes of events were attributed to the will of the
gods, a science of meteorology, for instance,, was
impossible”[9].
The above was the case in Greece until the 5"’ century
B.C. when the doors of philosophico-scientific
speculations were thrown open by Thales who lived in~
Miletus, a port city in Ionia on the coast of Asia Minor.. At
the time of Thales, Greece was divided into four main parts,
namely, Ionian Greeks, Dorian Greeks, Aeoloan Greeks
and Achen Greeks. The Ionian Greeks are the main focus of
this chapter. Lewes described the lonians “as... the first and
only people who disengaged speculation from theological
guidance... and it was he [Thales] who made the first
attempt to establish a physical beginning without the
51
)
52
in general will be discussed together, in treating the
Atomist schoob_W£L&halJ-tFeat Democritusas representing
the school.
54' ■
the break-up of water molecules into hydrogen and oxygen
(7). As the percentage of oxygen in the atmosphere
increased, organisms started to emerge from the seasrWhen
this oxygen was acted upon by the ultraviolet rays from the
sun it turned into Ozone gas, which in turn shielded off the
harmful ultraviolet rays.
The question we may ask at this juncture is, what is
the origin of water itself, considering the fact that
chemically, water is made up of two molecules of hydrogen
and one molecule of oxygen, and considering that it has
been stated that water was initially lacking in the
atmosphere? Here, we might guess that oxygen gas. might
have been given up in volcanic eruptions and this oxygen
cannot be denied being there in the sense that volcanic
eruption is a kind of combustion and combustion cannot
take place without oxygen. Carbon dioxide is,- as we are
told, the largest by-product of combustion. In the light of
the fact that hydrogen gas was present in the atmosphere, it
can be postulated that oxygen which came as a chemical
appendage of carbon dioxide under the very high pressure
of volcanic eruptions eventually combined with hydrogen
in the atmosphere in an exothermic reaction to form water
after the cooling of the environment [34]. Another way of
explaining this in simpler terms is that water vapour, which
is another way of describing water in the gaseous form,
must have been given up in volcanic eruptions. And it is a
well-known scientific fact that water vapour is not formed
unless water is heated up to a temperature of about 100"C
and above.
If the evolutionary theory above is debunked, then it
will mean the origin of water in the biosphere will be
attributed to no other source than God. And, of course, this
will form another standard argument in favour of the
limitations of modern science. If we agree that water is the
55
ultimate source of all things as the evolutionary theory
suggests, then the second perspective of Thales’
postulation [i.e. that water is the essence of all things] is
affirmed. That is to say that all things invariably have water
as their essence.
In conclusion, therefore, we can see that Thales view
that water is the source and essence of all things is not
absurd in any form, despite the absence of scientific steps in
his postulation. His was a product of the epoch in which he
lived and philosophized. In this sense, we take Thales as a
scientist who contributed in his own small way to the
development of science.
56
Apart from the above-mentioned scientific strides by
the Pythagoreans, the most important aspect of their work is
to be found in their theory that number is at the base of all
things. In this theory, the world is taken as infinite and
things as units, which in turn form the numbers. Although
this theory has elements of mysticism surrounding it, this
mysticism does not in any way hamper the scientific
implications of their idea. According to Dampier, in
practical mathematics t^e discovery that number is the
basis of all things made arithmetic possible; in philosophy it
led to the belief thafliumber lies at the base of the real world
[16].
• How did this help arithmetic as stated in the
quotation above? The answer is simply that in arithmetic as
well as in mathematics, relations are employed. Two things
can only relate successfully when there is an intrinsic
quality common to them. Thus, X -2 conveys no relation of
idea just as ‘goats minus cats’ conveys no relation of idea.
It is only When we ascribe a numerical value, say 5, to X that
meaning will be conveyed. When we give the numerical
value 5 to X we can conveniently subtract 2 from 5 to arrive
at the number 3.
Science in its various probes and researche&has been
of considerable help in throwing more light on the
philosophical position that numbers lie at the base of the
real world. A few examples from the science of physics will
not be out of place. Let’s finft take the example of speed. In
the description of speed, the science of physics has been
able to lend support to the Pythagorean theory that numbers
lie at the base of the real world.
Speed is defined as distance traveled divided by time
taken. Speed could be measured in units of kilometers per
hour or minute, feet per second and centimeters per second
as the case may be [Whitely 23]. For example, if a car
57
covers a distance of 60km in 30 minutes, the speed of the car
can be calculated as follows:
Speed = Distance travelled i.e. 60 = 2km/min.
Time taken 30
By reformulating the formula above we can get the
distance covered given the speed and time taken. For
example, if a car is moving at a speed of 2kms in a minute,
we can calculate the distance covered in 40 minutes as
follows:
Speed x Time =2x40= 80kms.
As in the case of speed, all phenomena of the real
world such as sound, light, energy, temperature, heat,
attractions, repulsions and so on, are quantifiable and can
also be given units of expressions in numbers. This is why it
is possible for science to make use of measuring
instruments like the rule, thermometer, hydrometer, and so
on. Numbers, again, can be seen as lying at the base of the
phenomenon of time. Time is no doubt an important aspect
of human consciousness. Man really depends on time for all
his successes and failures in life. Indeed, his attempts and
achievements are all products of time. However, time is
very relative because every phenomenon in the real world
has its own time clock. In view of this, if not for the use of
numbers to mark or identify time, man’s social endeavours
and other pursuits could have been a meaningless venture
(Aluko43).
Furthermore, number is very useful in the natural
- sciences for the purpose of predictions. In the field of
sociology, population growth is measured in numerical
terms. The rate of desert encroachment and the rise in the
volume of ocean waters are all presented in numerical
values. Number is therefore indispensable to life. There are
58
no suitable words to aptly describe the contributions of the
Pythagoreans than the words of Sir Dampier who said:
In our own day, Aston with his integral atomic
weights, Mosley with his atomic numbers,
Planck with his quantum theory, and Einstein
with his claim that physical fact such as
gravitation are exhibitions of local space-time
properties, are reviving ideas that, in older
crude forms, appear in Pythagorean
(
philosophy
* 18).
60
atoms] remain. To explain this in the light of modern
science, the term ‘energy’ in physics is defined as that
which gives the ability to work, to make impact or to resist
impact. It has two forms, namely, potential energy and
kinetic energy. While the former is energy stored for work,
the latter is energy used for work. Again, while the former
is possessed by a body by virtue of its position and
mechanical condition, the latter is energy due to motion.
Although these two forms of energy make series of
transformations in a body, they are never lost. For
example, when water boils, the vapours produced are never
lost. Realizing the non-annihilation of atoms, scientists
experimented and came up with the law of conservation of
energy which states that during transformation of energy
from one form to another, the total amount of energy is
unchanged [Whitely 68]. This is also a basic law in the
physics of thermodynamics.
According to Democritus, atoms have many sizes
and shapes but identical substance. The implication of this
postulate is that differences in the properties of things can
be accounted for as differences in size, shape, position and
movement of the ultimate particles [atoms]. The assertion
is logical and in fact chemistry has proved that atoms differ
in sizes and shapes through Neil Bohr’s discovery that
electron shells surround atoms and these electron shells are
determined by the atomic numbers of the element in
question [Holderness & Lambert 73-74],
Furthermore, Democritus postulated that atoms
move in all directions through the void [infinite space]
striking against each other and producing lateral -
movements and vortices which bring similar atoms
together to form elements, which in turn start the formation
of innumerable worlds. These innumerable worlds grow,
decay and ultimately perish. Regarding this. Sir Dampier
61
said: “Here we see a faint forecast of the nebula hypothesis,
and of the Darwinian theory of natural selection” (24). The
truth of the nebula hypothesis has been somewhat proved
and many instances of solar materials like stars and galaxies
coming together have been observed. Many of the
‘innumerable worlds’ are known to have a short life span
and many of them crash to the earth as meteorites when they
decay.
As we can see from the above, the philosophy of
atomism no doubt went beyond the bounds of its
predecessors. To be precise, it succeeded where its
predecessors~faffed: if combined logic with evidence to
dri ve Tome its point... As Bernal observed, Greekatomism
was the lineal and acknowledged ancestor of all modem
atomic theories in that Gassendi, the first of the modem
atomists, drew his ideas straight from Democritus and
Epicurus and Newton, a fervent atomist, inspired John
Dalton [184], It is nothing short of this fact and recognition
that modem science accorded the efforts of the Greek
atomists that made Sir Dampier to refer to the destructive
criticisms of Greek atomism by Plato and Aristotle as a
great misfortune.
Aside from philosophers discussed above, there are
other philosophers of early Greece whose scientific
achievements deserve mentioning. Anaximander—
^explained the cosmic origin of things in terms of the
unoriginated and indestructible primary substance called
~tTe ‘Apeiron’ or ‘indeterminate boundless’. For him, the
eternal motion of this substance brought the various
specific elements in the world into existence through the
process of‘separating off’. .Contrary toffhales’- View that
the earth was flat as a disk and floated on —water.
Anaximander theorized that the earth was cylindrical in
shape. Anaximenes [585-528 BXT] designated air as the
62
primary substance of all things. He is credited with the leal
of being the first to’hit upon the highiyrespectable concepts
~oP rarefaction’ and^condensation
* as the specific forms of
motion, which lead to describable changes in air.
Heraclitus said that the material substance of the world is
fire?^ Empedocles^is credited with many scientific
hypotheses. For example, he was the first to pose the
problem of natural selection as the basis of biological
evolution and took a great interest in the study of the
structure of the human body. Particularly, he formulated a
consistent theory of the eye and the mechanism of visual
sensation. He maintained that the moon was formed as a
result of air condensation. His surmise that light spreads al
a certain speed is considered today as that of a no mean
thinker.
Plato is regarded as the earliestphilosopher who was
a propagandist for mathematics. His approach, to the
subject was basically theoretical. Aristotle who was a
student of PLato often comes after his master with a
difference? Whereas Plato’s approach to science was,
theoretical, the approach of Aristotle w as both theoretical
and practical.- All branches of science as we have them
today found expressions in the works of Aristotle. Among
his works on natural science are: Physics, Parts of Animals
and Meteorologica. It is said that through accurate
observations and disciplined theorizing, Aristotle created a
biological science and taxonomy much like those in use
today. In the field of physics, Aristotle theorized that a body
could only remain in motion if there is an abiding contact
between it and a mover operating continuously. His theory -
of causation or causality identified four major types of
causes, namely, the "formal cause”- what a thing is (e.g. a
chair);jmaterial cause- that out of which a thing is made (in
the case of a chair, wood); efficient cause- by which or
63
\Vhom a thing is made [in the case of the chair, a carpenter.],
final cause, that is, the end for which a thing is made [in the
case of achair, for sitting]._
64
electrons in the atom (226k.Neil.BQhr in 1913 postulated a
theory of electron positioning in which he suggested the
existence of certain circular orbits or shells at definite
distances from the nucleus of the atom in which the electron
may rotate. These electron shellFare numbered 1.2.3,etc.
outwards from the nucleus. Perhaps a diagrammatic
example will be of help. < \
X= Electrons
65
Taking a cue from above, one readily sees that Bohr’s
theory was a fruitful imagination, which ultimately yielded
positive results, considering the role of Atomic Chemistry
in the field of Nuclear Engineering. It should be remarked
here that ‘fruitful imagination’ which was once the
exclusive reserve of philosophers, is the confluence of the
ancient and modern scientific thoughts. If, therefore,
‘fruitful imagination’ is taken to be the foundation for all
successful scientific enterprise, then we can assert that
philosophy is the cornerstone of modern scientific
development. In my opinion, fruitful imagination is what
philosophy bequeathed to science and which science in turn
uses to its best advantage.
With such a submission, it is argued that ancient
Greece is not only th$ cradle of modern science, it is the
source of the material! used in constructing the incubator in
which modern science was hatched in the 17th century A.D.
But there is a school x>f thought that ascribes this.feat to
ancient Egypt.
The ancient Greeks thought that their solutions to the
problems they sought to solve were logical and correct. But
it is a well-known fact that a vital task of contemporary
science has been to unravel the flaws in the solutions they
proffered. Indeed, without Greek science, some or most of
these problems would not have been solved at all.
z Finally, it is unfair to condemn the pre-Socratic
philosophers as idle speculators. We align with
-intellectuals like Jones who said that:
If we combine Pythagorean emphasis on
mathematics and measurement with the
Atomists’ view that reality consists in entities
varying only in shape, size and velocity, we
have the conception from which modem
physical theory began its great career [38]
66
Science in Africa
Although the African world is a heterogeneous
society, there exist certain common cultural and traditional
elements that identify Africa as an entity. These common
elements can be found in the beliefs and practices of the
people. Belief in one supreme deity and divinities, good
and evil spirits, and ancestors .is commonly held by
Africans. Craft and sculpture are some of the practices
commonly held by African peoples. Ancient Egypt had
these common elements that constitute the bedrock of
African science more than any other African culture.
Consequently, ancient Egypt is often used as a paradigm in
talking about African source of science.
Ancient Egypt is often regarded as the^cradle^of
civilization^ It is held that as far back as 1000 years before
the emergence of ancient Greek science, scientific
elements were to be found in one of the older civilizations
in Africa, Egypt in particular. Because there is no direct
historical record confirming this fact, Egyptian science has
been denied the debt modem science owed to it. Farrington
Benjamin writes:
The bridge connecting the Egyptians’ Science
and the beginning of Greek Science has been
practically broken down through the loss of the
historical tradition...it is undeniable that the
historian of science could not fail to
acknowledge the debt of modern science to the
Greeks. But ignorance reigned to that of
Egypt. On the other hand, the Greeks
acknowledged a heavy debt for the elements of
their mathematical knowledge to the
civilization of the Nile in Egypt (1).
Ancient Egyptian science, unlike ancient Greek
67
Science, was more of technique than theory. This means
that the Egyptians were more versed in practical
[tcchno]ogy]Ahan in theoretical science. This does not,
however, mean that theEgyptians cannot be linked with the
source of the present science. It is common knowledge that
science and technology interpenetrate one another. In fact,
the connection between the two is very close and important.
The importance lies in the fact that both practical and
theoretical sciences seem to have been antecedented and
presupposed by technology. Based on this fact, the
techniques of ancient Egypt should be regarded as
constituting genuine knowledge. Apart from that,
techniques are fertile .|>eds or foundations upon which
science is raised. WitWieir techniques, ancient Egyptians
achieved a Jot in the fi^ds of agriculture, architecture and
medicine. As part ofpieir contribution to science, they
invented a practical system of geometry to fix property
.'lines, developed a c^fendar, studied the stars, invented
astronomy, named the constellations, discovered an
alphabet, introduced the art of writing, and learned some
physiology and surgery while embalming their dead
With these facts, it will be unfair to deny Eq [in
particular] and Africa [in general] a place in the history of
science.
70
physical labour associated with men of classical antiquity;
food was produced above sustenance level. The wealth
accruing from the surpluses was invested in some notable
projects such as the building of great "cathedrals, the
crusades, and the founding of higher institutions of learning
between 11th and 13 th centuries.
In the area of the crafts, a lot of innovations were also
recorded/"O f note are the spinning wheel used in the textile
trade, waterpower that was applied to sawmills and for
draining mines. Perhaps the most important application of
waferpower was to the bellows of iron furnaces, giving a
blast, which elevated the smelting temperature and melted
the iron, so that it could be cast. Cast iron appeared first
during the thirteenth century in Europe, though blast
furnaces did not become common until the fifteenth
century (World Book Encyclopedia 107). .Other technical
innovations included printing (which made the printing of
the Bible in large numbers possible during Protestant
Reformation), gunpowder-making, canon-casting and later
the making of firearms, which improved military power.
71
CHAPTER 6
72
modes of freedom and expression, causing at some points
some discontinuity with the past while changing the
emphasis in areas in which continuity with the past was
preserved” (Mason 224). Renaissanne__thinkers_ pursued
questions principally about the physical world. Indeed,
“one of the significant aspects of the Renaissance was the
gradual emergence during this period of the methods of
modem science (Mason225).
The Renaissance produced scientists who achieved
the feat of devising a new method for discovering
knowledge. Unlike the medieval thinkers who took the
traditionaLtgxts as their final authority, the early modern
scientists shifted emphasis to observation and the
formation of hypotheses. Men now began to look for the
principles and laws governing heavenly bodies rather than
attempting to confirm biblical statements. Various
instruments were devised to test the exactness of then-
observations. With the use of instruments and through the
use of imaginative hypotheses, fresh knowledge began to
- unfold. Galileo discovered the moons around Jupiter, and
Leeuwenhoek (1633-1723) discovered spermatozoa,
protozoa, and bacteria. Whereas Copernicus (1463 - 1543)
formedli new hypothesis of the rotation of the earth around
the sun. Harvey (1578 -1657) discovered the circulation of
the blood. Gilbert (1540 - 1603) wrote a major work on the
magnet, and Boyle (1627 - 1691) the father of chemistry,
formulated hisLfarnoiis law concerning the relation of
temperature, volume and pressure of gases. Added to these
inventions and discoveries was the decisive advance made
in mathematics especially by _ Sir Isaac Newton and
Leibniz, wlio independently invented-differential and , ...
.integral ~calculus7 The method of observation and-
mathematical calculation now became the hallmarks of
modern science” (226).
73
two
The new science had two important consequences on
philosophy. Firstly, the hypothesis that the processes of
nature can be explained and described in observable and
mathematical terms triggered off the philosophical
assumption that everything including the heavens, the
minutest particles and even human thought were subject to
the laws of motion or mechanical laws. Secondly, the
medieval assumption that the earth was the centre of the
universe and that man was the crown of creation was
shattered. Thus, the geocentric assumption, which found
great prominence in Ptolemaic astronomy, gave way to the
more refined heliocentric conception, which was initiated
by Nicolaus Copernicus. The new hypothesis of
Copernicus placed the sun at the center of the universe. The
earth attended by the moon now became one of the planets
that revolved around the sun. Scholars like Tycho Brahe
(1546 -1601), Johannes Kepler (1571 -1603), Galileo and
Isaac Newton supported this new theory (but with slight
modifications). With the emergence of the new science,
not much reference was made to the supernatural in
explaining the phenomena of nature. Rather, “the whole
drift of the new scientific method was toward a new
conception of man, of nature, and of the whole mechanism
of humarl knowledge ...and it was this new attitude of
science that had the most immediate effect upon ... Francis
Bacon and Thomas Hobbes” (Mason 231).
Bacon devised a new Method for assembling and
explaining facts. He believed^'that this method would
uncover the secrets of nature. He considered the mind as
having been distorted by passions and errors of traditional
learning, which he called idols, and distempers of learning,
respectively. These obscuring elements,'according to him,
prevent the mind from reflecting truth accurately.
Consequently, he advocated that to discover scientific
74
I
knowledge the mind must be cleansed of the obscuring
elements. This led him to advocate the method of induction
by simple enumeration. This is the method of deriving laws
from the observation of particulars (facts) and their series
and order (Mason 232). It appears that Bacon could not
offer tangible solutions to the limitations of this method.
The first limitation is that his assumption that a hypothesis •
simply suggests itself after enough facts have been
assembled is not in conformity with the modern scientist’s
conception of a hypothesis as a guide in the selection of
facts that are relevant to the experiment. The second
limitation of his method is that it undermines the
importance of mathematics for science. Thomas Hobbes
of England, Bacon’s friend and Countryman, overcame
these limitations.
JHobbes’ greatest achievement in science is the
addition of mathematical and deductive reasoning to
scientific philosophy. Hobbes fell in love with geometry
when he came across Euclid’s book titled Elements. He
later joined a small pool of thinkers of his day who believed
that geometry was the key to the study of nature. He sought
to recast the whole gamut of knowledge in line with this
single approach. To do this, Hobbes assumed that it
mattered little what the object of study was, that the method
of observation and deductive reasoning from axioms,
formed from observation, would yield exact knowledge.
He, therefore, set out an ambitious project, which was to
recast the study of physical nature, the nature of man, and
the nature of human society, using the same method
throughout (Mason 234).
Rene Descartes followed the tradition of Bacon and ,
Hobbes to urge that general principles must be the basis for
deduction. His great interest in mathematics led him to the
belief that mathematical reasoning provided the best
75
method for discovering true knowledge. He hoped to
generalize the use of the mathematical method for use in
understanding the operations of nature. For him, scientific
theories must be trimmed down to those susceptible of
mathematical development. It is his view that experiments
served to illustrate ideas from intuitively given principles;
they did not determine those principles (Onuobia 15). Both
Newton and Galileo were to agree with Descartes that
mathematical deductions should be based upon general
principles. Their point of difference lies in the fact that
while Descartes urged that the general principles in
question are intuitively given, both Newton and Galileo
urged that the principles are experimentally given.
CHAPTER 7
SCIENCE IN THE 18TH,
19TH AND 20TH CENTURIES v
77
Science in the 19th Century.
The 19th century witnessed great achievements in
Europe in the field of physics, chemistry, geology and
biology. jLjs often regarded as the golden age of modern
science. Many important advances were made, more so in
the formulating and discovering of the fundamentals of
Physical Science.
James P. Joule discovered that heat is a form of
energyT’The famous Law of Conservation of Energy is
credited to him. This law states that energy can only
undergo a change in form, but can neither be created nor
destroyed. In 1931, Michael Faraday discovered that a
.moving magnet is capable of inducing an electric current.
H. C. Maxwell described Faraday's work on electricity and
magnetism mathematically. He also showedlliaT light and
other energy waves are fundamentally the same. ~
Dmitri Mendeleev of Russia simplified and
systematized the description of chemical reactions. This is
shown in the periodic table of elements published by him in
1869. In this table, elements are grouped according to their
atomic weights and chemical properties, thus clarifying the
relations between the various elements. Other chemists of
the period explained the nature of organic compounds, and
devised new ways of explaining chemical reactions in
mathematical terms •
Charles Lyell, a British geologist, put forth a proof to
show that the development of the earth surface has been a
very slow and gradual process through millions of years.
Other geologists theorized that the earth reached its present
shape through violent changes known as cataclysms.
Charles R. Darwin, in 1858, put forward _an
evolutionary theory of the origin of plants and animals. He
theorized that plants and animals evolved through ages
through an orderly, gradual process of evolution. His
78
explanation of how this process might take place led him to
the idea of natural selection through competition and the
survival of the fittest. Gregor Mendel, an Austrian Monk,
laid the foundation of the science of genetics when he
discovered the basic laws of heredity in 1800’s. Louis
Pasteur founded modern microbiology with his studies of
fermentation and disease. In Leipzig, Germany, Wilhelm
Wundt founded the first laboratory of experimental
psychology in 1879 (World Book 171-172).
70
plate tectonics, volcanic eruptions, earthquakes, polar
wandering, and so on.
In healthcare delivery, the combined forces of such
world organizations as World Health Organization (WHO),
United Nations Children Education Fund (UNICEF),
Public Opinion and Governments have resulted in
biological researches which have led to break-through
against such killer diseases as tuberculosis, malaria, polio,
whooping cough, and so on. Though no real cure has been
found for the killer disease Acquired Immune Deficiency
Syndrome (AIDS), research war against the AIDS virus is
still raging fiercely. The discovery and development of
natural antibiotics (Penicillin) by Fleming (1881-1955) and
synthetic antibiotics by Ehrlich (1854-1915) has not only
made medical treatment effective, but has also contributed
to a better understanding of the processes underlying life. I
will not fail to mention the names of Marie Curie (1867-
1934), a notable female scientist, whose discovery of
radiotherapy has helped in the treatment of cancer, and
Christian Barnard who pioneered heart transplantation.
There have also been great advances in electronics,
communications and computers. In short, this age is now
known as the computer age.
In the field of aviation, following the initial flight
success of the Wright brothers, the initial entertaining role
of plane flight has risen to the exclusive role of military
fighting and civil transportation. The discovery in this
century of modern rocket system has contributed to both
space exploration and space research. The United States
of America and the former Soviet Union successfully
launched lunar and planetary probes and even the Sputniks.
Major Yuri Gagari of Russia became the first to
successfully orbit the earth in 1961 (Alozie 96-118). Today,
man can travel to and from the moon and there are artificial
satellites orbiting the earth.
80
CHAPTER 8
HISTORY OF MEDICINE
Lack of documentary records has been the bane in
the study of the history of medicine. Record
documentation dates back only to about 4000 B.C. when
human civilization reached a reasonable level. Today,
however, the history of medicine is a distinct and important
discipline in the field of medicine.
TheLaim of history ofmedfoingJ^J^-O^fold._Eirst,
since knowledge is a never-ending process, docunientation
of historical records in medicine will ensure continuity.. Jt
is said that today’s knowledge is a product of pre-existing
knowledge. Second, historical documentation will foster
research. By referring to past methods present day medical
practitioners have a lot to gain. A study of the difficulties
encountered in the past will undoubtedly spur up present
practitioners in identifying difficulties of the present and so
develop a critical sense, which is a prerequisite for medical
thinking. We shall now examine briefly the history of
modem medicine.
The history of medicine, as it were, is co-ever with
man. When man developed ailments, he was constrained
to seek empirical remedies for them. The history of
medicine has developed from primitive practices through
conjecturing and hypothesizing of the medieval period to
present day scientific reasoning.
Ancient Greece
It is said that the Greeks laid the foundations of
organized medical practice. “The priest-doctors of Eastern
civilization carried out numerous experiments whose
results reached Greece. These provided the basis for the
Greek schools of medicine which together gave rise to the
so-called Hippocratic medicine” (Korubo -Owiye 106)
82
Roman Period
It iS said that medical science was obliviated by the
fall of Greek political power and the rise of Roman Empire.
The Romans were so pre-occupied with warfare that they
had no time for medicine. The practice of medicine was
unbelievably left to educated slaves. It was not until the
reign of Julius Caesar that foreign doctors were granted
Roman citizenship. During the succeeding centuries Greek
physicians namely, Dioscoridees, Celsius and Galen
helped a great deal in coordinating and strengthening
medical knowledge in various fields.
16th-18thCentury.
The practice of Anatomy was revived at the
beginning of this period. Some of the important strides in
the field of medical science during this period included:
1. Leonardo de Vinci (1452- 1570) studied Anatomy by
the practice of dissection. In 1500, he likened
animal nutrition to the burning of a candle and
asserted that animals could not survive without
combustion.
2. The Italian physician Girolamo Fracastoro (1484-
1553) put forward a theory that diseases were seed -
like entities. As an avowed atomist, he suggested
that certain diseases were contagious because there
were atoms or seeds of disease, which reproduced
themselves and were transferred from one person to
another through contact or the air. In this way he
envisaged in a general but vague way the later germ
theory of disease.
3. Paracelsus (1493- 1541), a Swiss physician, tried to
bring into being a new science of medical-chemistry,
84
or Iatrochemistry as it was called, by unifying
medicine with alchemy. He defined alchemy as a
science concerned with the transformation of the
raw materials of nature into the finished products
useful to humanity. He hypothesized that the human
body was essentially a chemical system composed
of the three principles of the alchemists, namely,
mercury, sulphur and salt. For him, illness could
arise when there is a lack of balance between the
principles. He postulated the doctrine that diseases
were highly specific in their action and hence each
disease needed a specific chemical cure. He was
totally opposed to the old cure-all remedies
containing numerous constituents, and proposed the
administration of single substances as medicaments.
Such a re-orientation stimulated the study of
particular diseases and helped in differentiating
between useful and harmful medicaments.
4. John Baptist van Helmont( 1580- 1644), a noble man
of Brussels, wrote a work titled On the Development
ofMedicine, which was published posthumously in
1648. He held that parts of a composite entity, such
as the organs of the human body had a life and being
of their own deriving from the vital force, which
controls that part. For him, disease was a foreign
guest, which entered the body, settled in a particular
organ and monopolized its vital processes. Thus, a
disease was to be treated by its specific remedy- a
simple inorganic or plant substance, not the old
complex cure-all medicaments. For him, ancient
physicians had confused diseases with their
symptoms, and in their attempt to effect a cure had
tried to remove the symptoms instead of the
occasional cause.
85
5 In 1595, Galileo invented the first instrument for
measuring temperature. In 1610, he effected a
transition from telescope to microscope by adapting
the optical instrument he used to study the skies to
observe small, close objects.
6 Marcello Malphighi (1628 - 1694) was a Professor
of Medicine in various Italian universities and then
physician to Pope Innocent XII. He attempted to
find a method of classifying all living creatures into a
vertical scale. His interest in Harvey’s theory of the
circulation of the blood and the attendant problem of
the role of respiration led him in 1660 to use the
microscope to see the capillaries which connected up
the veins with the arteries in the lungs of a frog.
Thereafter he went on to examine the respiratory
systems of other organisms. At the end of the
investigation, he placed plants at the bottom of the
scale because they were found to be filled with air
tubules, next were the insects because they had
numerous air passages; then fishes because they had
smaller, though complex, gill system; finally man
and the higher animals, which he placed at the top of
the scale because they had only a pair of lungs which
were small compared to the size of their other
organs.
7 In 1628, William Harvey gave the final definitive
description of the circulation of the blood. Before
him, the Spaniard Michele Servitus and the Italian
Andrea Gesalpino had made useful contributions to
it.
8 In 1665, Robert Hooke (1635-1703) discovered that
living tissue was made up of basic .microscopic units
called cells. He, together with Boyle, Richard
Lower, and John Mayow, tried to show that the
86
change from dark red venous blood to bright red
, arterial blood in the lungs was a result of the uptake
of part of the air and that the air so absorbed played a
function in the body akin to that of chemical
combustion. The work of Boyle, Hooke, and Lower
was summarized and expanded by Mayow in his
Five Medico- Physical Treatises, published in 1674.
9 Antony Van Leeuwenhoek (1674- 1683) was a
Dutchman who perfected the microscope. With the
aid of the microscope, he was able to see the actual
circulation of the blood through the capillaries in the
tail of a tadpole and in the foot of a frog. With this
discovery the mechanics of the circulation of the
blood was finally settled and scientists were now
able to investigate what function the circulation of
the blood served. The industrial revolution in the
18th Century led to great scientific and medical
discoveries:
10 Earlier in this century, Giovanni Battista Morgagni
made great contribution to medicine. He is credited
with laying the foundation of pathology.
11. William Hunter (1752-1783) suggested that the seat
of disease was not at the organ level, but tissue level.
12. Reamure and Spallanzani hypothesized that
digestion was a chemical process. Spallanzani laid
the foundation of experimental physiology.
13. 1750 - 1875. The connection between dietary
deficiency and particular diseased states was
discovered. Consequently, the British Navy
introduced lemon juice into the rations of its officers
and men to control scurvy.
14. In 1762, Plenciz confirmed the already known idea
that infectious diseases were caused by living
agents.
87
15. Edward Jenner discovered smallpox vaccine in
1798. He showed that the much milder disease,
cowpox, provided human immunity against
smallpox, a discovery based on the observation that
dairymaids rarely caught small- pox. Consequently,
in the 1880’s, the practice of. inoculation was
generalized, finding a rational basis in the germ
theory of disease.
16. Pacin, an Italian, discovered the first microbe
associated with human disease - the cholera
organism called vibro comma.
17. Ini 863, Louis Pasteur (1822 - 1895) showed that a
micro-organism caused the fermentation (souring)
of wine, and he demonstrated that warming the wine
to 55°C could kill the microorganism. In the
following year he was asked by the French Ministry
of Agriculture to investigate the disease of
silkworms. Within a few months he succeeded in
isolating the micro-organisms responsible for two
kinds of diseases caused by silkworms, and showed
how the disease -free eggs, worms, and moths could
be recognized and isolated for use in breeding. A
decade later he investigated cattle anthrax and
chicken cholera, and finally in the 1880’s he studied
some of the diseases, which affected human beings.
He confirmed the scientific validity of the already
known preventive immunization. In 1885 he
successfully treated one Joseph Minter of rabies.
18. In 1876, Robert Koch (1843- 1910) discovered that
the micro-organisms responsible for cattle anthrax
could be grown outside the animal body in a culture
medium made up of meat broth jelly. By these
means, he was able to discover and isolate the
bacteria responsible for tuberculosis (TB) in 1882,
88
and to isolate the cholera micro-organism in the
•following year.
19. In 1849, Berthhold demonstrated that testis
produced a blood-borne substance, which
conditioned sexual characteristics.
20. In 1861, Gregor Mendel (1822 - 1884) published his
principle of inheritance.
21. In 1864, Lord Joseph Lister (1827 - 1912)
introduced the practice of antiseptics in surgery.
22. From 1880-1890, Alexander Fleming and others
elucidated the essential facts of cell division and
emphasized the importance of equality of
chromosome distribution to daughter cells.
23. In 1859, Charles Darwin (1809 - 1882) brought out
his great work On The Origin of the Species by
Means of Natural Selection. Here he summed up
his position in the words that evolution “has been
effected chiefly through the natural selection of
numerous, successive, slight variations, aided in an
important manner by the inherited effects of the use
and disuse of parts, and in an unimportant manner,
that is, in relation to adaptive structures, whether
past or present, by the direct action of external
conditions, and by variations which seem to us in our
ignorance to arise spontaneously” (cited in Mason
419).
In 1871, Darwin published The Descent ofMan.
20th Century
The 20th century witnessed two World Wars, the
aftermath of which was great scientific and
medical discoveries:
24. In 1901, Wilhelm Roentgen received the Nobel Prize
for the discovery of X-rays. About the same time
89
Mme Curie (1867 - 1934) and Pierre discovered a
radioactive element - Radium. These two great
discoveries revolutionized medical diagnosis and
treatment.
25. In 1908, Paul Ehrlich, a German, and Noguchi, a
Japanese, developed the first chemotherapeutic
agent, thus laying the foundation of modern
chemotherapy.
26. In 1921, Banting and Best discovered the insulin.
This was a great boost to the field of Endocrinology.
27. In 1929, an important breakthrough was recorded in
the treatment of infectious disease when Alexander
Fleming discovered Penicilin.
28. From 1926 - 1935, Vitamins were isolated and
chemically characterized. An important landmark
was recorded in the field of psychiatry when
Sigmund Freud proposed his theory of
psychoanalysis. The first effective vaccine against
polio was discovered. Albert Sabin is credited with
the discovery of the polio vaccine still in use today.
90
In Nigeria the practice of traditional medicine has a
very long history. Even today traditional medicine still
plays a significant part in the health care of a significant
proportion of both rural and urban population.
In the area of orthodox medicine, Korubo - Owiye
has identified as possible sources the Eastern Arabic
influence (which came across the Sahara to Western Sudan
and then to Northern Nigeria), Western influence (which
came through the trading missions of various Western
powers to the Niger Delta region and later through the
Portuguese), Slave trade (with slave ships normally
bringing-along, medical doctors), early explorers (with
some of the expeditions being led by doctors), and the
missionaries ( some of who established hospitals in the
costal area) (113-114).
In a more recent sense, the origin of public health
services in Nigeria can be traced to the British Army
Medical Services. After the Second World War medical
services were extended to civil servants. Further efforts’by
government and religious bodies led to the extension of
medical services to the local population.
The first known Nigerian doctors were trained in
mid 19" century first at Fourah Bay Institute in Sierra
Leone, and then in United Kingdom to qualify for practice.
On return to Nigeria, they first served in Army hospitals
before going into private practice. These included Dr. J. A.
B. Horton (1858)s Dr. Obadiah Johnson (1886), Dr. John
Randle (1888), Dr. S. A. Legh - Sodipe (1892), and Dr.
Oguntola Sapara (1895) (Korubo -Owiye 114).
91
CHAPTER 9
HISTORY OF MATHEMATICS
What is Mathematics?
Mathematics can be roughly defined as the
deductive study of numbers, geometry and various abstract
constructs. Its main branches include foundations, algebra,
. analysis, geometry, and applied mathematics. Foundations
is concerned with the formulation and analysis of the
language, axioms and logical methods, which form the
basis of mathematics. Set theory, which was developed by
George Cantor, now constitutes the universal language of
mathematics. Algebra studies the solutions of one or
several algebraic equations, involving polynomial
functions of one or several variables. Arithmetic and
number theory are areas of algebra, which deal with special
properties of the integers. Geometry deals with the spatial
aspect of mathematics, that is, the properties of and
relationships between points, lines, planes, figures, solids
and surfaces. Topology is concerned with the structures of
geometric objects in a very general way. Applied
mathematics deals with a wide range of issues with
significant current use in the empirical sciences. It includes
mathematical statistics, mathematical physics, computer
science and probability theory.
History of Mathematics
Mathematics is a growing discipline, which has
varied with time. Although mathematics as we know it
today is an axiomatic - deductive discipline, it did not start
92
that way. It is said that mathematics starts with counting.
This does not mean that early counting was mathematics.
What it does mean is that it is only when some record of the
counting was kept that mathematics actually started.
Early Civilizations
The earliest records show that mathematics arose in
response to the practical needs of agriculture, business,
surveying, navigation, and industry in the 5*, 4*, 3- and 2
millennia B.C. in Egypt, Babylonia, and possibly in India
and China. In Egypt, for example, the annual flooding of
the Nile valley forced the ancient Egyptians to devise
formulas that would help in re-establishing land
boundaries. Also, the need to have mathematical formulas
for construction, calendar and commerce provided the
impetus for mathematical developments. Egyptian and
Babylonian mathematics was empirically based, and hence
devoid of logical demonstration.
Greece
Although the debt of Greek mathematics to Egyptian
and Babylonian mathematics is difficult to appraise, it is
nevertheless clear that the Greeks succeeded in
transforming the subject into something very different from
the set of empirical rules worked out by the Egyptians and
Babylonians.
Between 3rd and 2nd Century B.C., the classical
Greek philosophers Thales. Pythagoras. Plato, Aristotle,
Euclid, Archimedes, and Zeno of Elea profoundly altered
the nature of mathematics. They introduced such abstract
notions as ‘infinity’ and ‘irrational numbers’, and a
deductive system of proof.
93
The ancient knowledge of geometry was passed on
to the Greeks who insisted that geometric statements
should be established by deductive reasoning as opposed to
trial and error. Thales, the originator of this was quite
familiar with the computations handed down from- the
Egyptians and Babylonians. His attempt to determine
which of the computations were correct led him to the
development of logical geometry. This orderly
development of theorems by proof was a novel invention.
The Pythagoreans continued this new mathematics
begun by Thales over the next two centuries. The
Pythagoreans, a school led by Pythagoras in the 6th century
B.C., were struck by the fact that phenomena that appear
different can exhibit identical mathematical properties.
They concluded that these properties could be expressed in
number or in numeral relationships. For them, the study of
music and mathematics can bring about the elevation of the
soul and union with God. Nonetheless, they were able to
develop a large body of mathematics, using the deductive
method.
Zeno of Elea made an important contribution to
mathematics. His paradoxes led to the atomic theory of
Democritus, •'he realization that the rational numbers are
no sufficient to measure all lengths was brought about by a
more precise formulation of concepts. Studies in the
geometric formulation of numbers led to a form of
integration.
The Platonists, led by Plato, expanded and
propagated the Pythagorean doctrine of the mathematical
design of nature in the 4th century B.C. Plato postulated
that there is an ideal world, a world of forms, that is
94
designed mathematically, and that the world of sense is an
imperfect representation of the ideal world. Though the
Aristotelians differed from the Platonists regarding the
relation of mathematics to the physical world, they still
propagated the doctrine of the mathematic design of nature.
At the end of the classical Greek period, the doctrine
of the mathematical design of nature had been fully
established and the quest for mathematical laws or truths
instituted. Of course, searching for mathematical truths
meant the abandonment of the Egyptian and Babylonian
emphasis on empirical and often approximate results.
What informed this development is that if mathematics is
truly a body of truths, then mathematical reasoning must be
tailored towards securing truths about physical
phenomena. The first principle was that mathematics
should be concerned with abstractions, that is, abstract
concepts (such as point, line, and whole number), in terms
of which other concepts such as triangle, square and circle
could then be defined. To reason with mathematical
concepts, the Greeks decided to start with axioms, that is,
self-evident truths, from which conclusions could be
arrived at through deductive reasoning.
How successful the search for mathematical truths
was is evidenced in the mathematical work of such men as
Euclid (about 300 B.C), Appollonius and Archimedes in
the 3rd Century B.C., and Ptolemy in the 2nd Century A.D.
These men belonged to the second great period of Greek
history called the Hellenistic or Alexandrian period (300
B.C-600A.D.).
Euclid’s work is a logical organization of a vast
account of the separate discoveries of many classical
95
Greeks. His major work Elements stipulates the laws of
space and of figures in space. This work consists of a large
body of known mathematics, including his own
discoveries, which he organized into the first formal system
of mathematics. This formal structure was shown by the
fact that the Elements began with an explicit statement of
assumptions known as axioms or postulates, as well as
definitions. The accompanying statements were then
shown to follow logically from these axioms and
definitions. The entire structure of Books I - IV, VII, and
IX of the treatise dealt primarily with what we now call
Euclidean geometry.
Euclidean geometry as conceived by its originator
was an idealization of physical geometry. The entities of
mathematical system are concepts abstracted from physical
experience but differing from physical .entities the same
way an idea differs from the object itself. However, there is
a correlation between the two. For example, the angle sum
oi a mathematical triangle was said to be 180°, and if one
measured the angles of physical triangles the angle sum
seemed to be 180°. The same held for a multitude of other
relations. Based on this agreement between theory and
practice, many writers have suggested that Euclid’s axioms
should be regarded as self-evident truths. Centuries later,
the great German philosopher Immanuel Kant surprisingly
declared that the human mind is essentially Euclidean and
can only conceive of space in Euclidean terms.
Euclid- based his geometry on five fundamental
postulates or assumptions, namely,
96
Postulate I: For every point P and for every point Q not
equal to P there exists a unique line that passes through P
and Q.
98
Middle East by Romans, and the final conquest of Egypt by
the upsurging Muslims in 640 AD, Greek civilization nose -
dived. Consequently, there was a decline in learning in the
West. The Indians, the Arabs and the Chinese continued
the development of mathematics. The Indians invented the
numeral system, which is still in use today in the civilized
world. Although the work in these countries did not match
the progress made by the Greeks, it did preserve Greek
mathematics to some extent. Moreover, after the conquest
of Egypt, most Greek scholars migrated to Constantinople
(now Istanbul), which had become the capital of the Eastern
Roman Empire at that time. This increased the body of
knowledge that eventually reached Europe about 800 years
later.
The Hindus and Arabs used whole numbers and
fractions, but they also used irrational numbers without
hesitation. They introduced new and correct rules for
addition, subtraction, multiplication, and division of
irrational numbers.
The Renaissance
The most important concern in late medieval Europe
was the acquisition and study of Greek works. This was
made possible through the Arabic translations of those
Greek works proper which had been kept in safety in
Eastern Roman Empire. When the Turks conquered this
empire in 1453, many Greek scholars migrated westward,
bringing their books along. It was through these works that
the intellectual leaders who championed the revitalization
of Europe learned the doctrine of the mathematical design
of nature.
99
16th Century
The beginning of 16* century witnessed great strides
in mathematics in Europe. Pacioli, Cardan, Tartaglia and
Ferrari provided the algebraic solution of cubic and quartic
equations. Copernicus and Galileo revolutionized the
applications of mathematics to the study of the universe.
Added to the body of mathematical knowledge was
mathematical induction, the binomial theorem and
approximate results of finding new roots of low and high
degree equations - though proofs were not provided for
these results. The major contributors were Francois Vieta,
Thomas Harriot, Albert Girard, Pierre de Ferment, Rene
Descartes, and Isaac Newton.
17th Century
In the 17th century Napier, Briggs and others
developed decimal fractions and logarithms, and the study
of projectile geometry and probability was started. Napier,
Briggs, Blaise Pascal, Fermat, Galileo and Kepler made
useful contributions. Fermat and Pascal began the
mathematical study of probability. Under the influence of
earlier mathematicians, especially his former teacher
Barrow, Newton developed the calculus as a tool to extend
the frontiers of the study of nature. In short, the greatest
discoveries of the century were the invention of analytical
geometry by Descartes and of the calculus by Newton and,
independently, Leibniz. Leibniz’s influence on the various
members of the Bernoulli family was to ensure the growth
of the calculus in power, and variety of applications.
Newton’s theories of gravitation and light usher us into the
18th Century.
100
18th Century
* The history of mathematics in the 18th century is
characterized by development of the calculus and its
application to physical problems, both terrestrial and
celestial, with the Bernoulli family, Leonhard Euler, Joseph
Lagrange, and Pierre de Laplace playing leading roles.
Euler invented two new branches, namely, calculus of
variations and differential geometry. He effectively
expanded the new number theory begun by Fermat.
Toward the end of the ‘18th century Lagrange began a
rigorous theory of functions and of mechanics. A branch of
mathematical physics was launched in the 18th century
known as fluid dynamics. This is concerned with the study
of the flow of fluids and motion of bodies in fluids. Daniel
Bernoulli suggested that the theory might be used in
describing the flow of blood in human veins and arteries,
while Euler derived the equations for the motion of
compressible fluids.
19th Century
The most prominent figure in this century is Carl
Gauss, who made fundamental contributions to algebra,
arithmetic, geometry, number theory and analysis.
Another great addition to mathematical knowledge was the
invention of non-Euclidean geometry independently by
Nikolas Lobachevsky. Bolyai, and in another form, G.F.B.
Riemann, whose work was foundational to the
development of the general theory of relativity. Sir
William Rowan Hamilton, M. S. Lie, George Cantor, Julius
Dedekind, and Karl Weierstrass made great contributions
to number theory and abstract algebra. Weierstrass and
101
Augustine Cauchy introduced new rigours to the study of
calculus and of analysis. Cayley carried forward algebraic
geometry. Hamilton and Grassmann complemented his
work on matrices and linear algebra. At the end of the 19th
century Cantor invented set theory almost single-handedly.
He had discovered a contradiction while trying to assign a
cardinal number to the set of all sets and an ordinal to set of
all ordinal numbers. Cardinal number refers to the number
of elements in a set. For example, the cardinal number on
one hand is 5. Ordinal numbers refer to ordered rank. For
example, we can assign ordinal number 1 to the thumb, and
ordinal number 5 to the little finger. This innovation by
Cantor opened the eyes of mathematicians to the fact that
they had been using similar concepts not only in the newer
creations but also in the purportedly well-established older
mathematics. These contradictions were called paradoxes
(now antinomies) because it was thought that paradoxes
could be resolved. The English philosopher Bertrand
Russell formulated a more popular version of the nature of
paradoxes.
20th Century
There were two main trends in the twentieth century.
The first was towards increasing generalization and
abstraction, exemplified by investigations into the
foundations of mathematics by David Hibert, Bertrand
Russell and Alfred North Whitehead, and Kurt Godel. The
second is towards concrete applications to such areas as
social sciences, linguistics, and computer science, made
possible by the work of John Von Newmann, Nonbert
Wiener, and others.
102
A major problem that plagued mathematicians in the
20th century is called the problem of completeness. Simply
put, completeness means that the axioms of any branch of
study are adequate to establish the correctness or falsity of
any meaningful assertion involving the concepts of that
' branch.
In the first decade of the century mathematical giants
split into different camps in their efforts to find solutions to
the problems plaguing mathematics. Four major schools of
thought emerged to tackle these problems. They include:
1. The logistic school, which was spearheaded
byRussell and his friend Whitehead.
This school founded mathematics on logic.
2. The intuitionist school, which was initiated by
the Dutchman 1. E. J. Brouwer. This school
reliedsolely on concepts and theorems
acceptable to human minds.
3. The formalist school, initiated by David
Hibert. This school built mathematics on
logical and mathematical axioms and
proposed a mathematical programme to
prove the consistency of mathematics.
4. The set theoretic school was founded by Ernst
Zermelo and modified by Abraham A.
Fraenkel. This school built mathematics on
axioms of sets so carefully chosen
that presumably the deduction of
contradictions is impossible.
The main bone of contention among members of
these four schools centred on the question of what
foundation was necessary to establish consistency. Other
103
minor issues centred on whether one should use the axiom
of choice or the continuum hypothesis, and the status of
what are called existence proofs.
As if to worsen the situation created by the
contentions and differing positions of the various schools of
mathematics, Kurt Godel of the University of Vienna
published a paper in 1931 which dealt a devastating blow to
mathematics. On the issue of consistency, Godel argued
that even the consistency of a mathematical system that
only embraces the arithmetic of whole numbers could not
be established by the logical principles adopted by the
various foundational schools. Godel’s ‘incompleteness’^
result states that, if any formal theory T adequate to
embrace the theory of whole numbers is consistent, then T
is incomplete. Thus, for Godel, the price of consistency is
incompleteness. Godel’s result also exposed the
inadequacy of all known axiomatic systems. Since
consistency cannot be proved, it means that
mathematicians are talking nonsense because a
contradiction can be found at any time. When this happens
and the contradiction cannot be resolved, then all
mathematics becomes pointless. Of course, one of two
contradictory propositions must be false. Does that not
mean that mathematicians have been labouring under a.
threat of doom?
Further attempts to resolve the problem of finding
proper foundation for mathematics have compounded
rather than solved the problem. Godel’s later work (1940)
and Paul Cohen’s work (1963), indicated that the axiom of
choice and the continuum hypothesis are independent of
other axioms of set theory. It follows that if one builds*
104
mathematics on set theory, there are several positions one
can take. Does that not mean that there are several
mathematics? As Morris Kline has rightly observed.
The developments on the foundations of
mathematics since 1900 are bewildering and
the present state of mathematics anomalous
and deplorable. The light of truth no longer
illuminates the road to follow. In the place of
the unique universally admired, and
universally accepted body of mathematics
whose proofs, though sometimes requiring
emendation, were regarded as the acme of
sound reasoning, we now have differing and
even conflicting approaches to mathematics.
What practical course can mathematicians
pursue? Beauty and intellectual challenge may
justify many creations; but to decide among
the many differing views about which
mathematics is sound for applications, only the
test of applicability is available. Ironically,
such a test means reverting to the empirical
nature of Egyptian and Babylonian
mathematics (502).
Thus, we are back to the starting point of mathematics!
105
CHAP ! I R Id
A SUMMARY Ol HIE HISTORY OF
WESTERN SCIENCE
In this chapter. I present a summary of the trends and
developments in the history of Western Science. The
scientific postulations and achievements of distinguished
scientists of different periods are specifically highlighted.
The aim of this chapter is, therefore, mnemonic.
- ,
Wilhelm
1895 v- ii •
Roentgen discovered
R. ,IW." /p.x
X-rays.
3
1957 Russia launched the first artificial satellite. Arthur
Kornberg grew DNA, the basic chemical of the gene
in a test tube.
114
----------------- —_ ,
PART THREE:
ARISTOTELIAN SCIENCE
Biographical Sketch
Aristotle [384-322 B.C.], was bom in the small town
of Stagira on the northeast coast of Thrace. His father was
the personal physician to the Macedonian King. His great
interest in science, especially biology was nurtured in his
early childhood. At seventeen years, he enrolled at Plato’s
Academy in Athens, where he stayed as a pupil and
member in the next twenty years. While there, he was
greatly influenced by Plato’s thought and personality. At
the Academy, he wrote many dialogues in a platonic style.
He eventually left the Academy to found his own
institution, the Lyceum, in order to formulate his own
philosophical ideas. At the Lyceum, he and his pupils
studied philosophy, mathematics, and the empirical
sciences, especially biology. He wrote books on a variety
of subjects including logic, Metaphysics, physics, ethics,
biology, politics, psychology, rhetoric and aesthetics. He is
reputed to be the first to develop logic as a science or as an
academic discipline. He became the teacher of Alexander
the Great in 343/342 B.C. As a teacher to a future leader,
his interests included politics. When Alexander ascended
the throne, his work as a tutor came to an end. He then left
for Athens in 335/334 B.C. where he embarked upon the
most productive period of his life. When Alexander died in
, 323 B.C., the subsequent wave of anti-Macedonian feeling
that arose forced him to flee Athens [because of his close
connections with Macedonia], lest, according to him, the
116
Athenians should sin twice against philosophy, the killing
of Socrates being the first. He left the lyceum and went to
Chaicis where he reportedly died in 322 B.C. of a long
standing digestive ailment.
Aristotelian Science
The early work of Aristotle, which focused on the
nature of the heavens, was speculative in method, while his
later works, which focused on biology, were based more
closely on observation.
In the field of astronomy, Aristotle held that the
spheres, which bore the heavenly bodies round their
courses were indeed physical bodies as opposed to
geometrical constructions, as supposed by Eudoxus. Each
sphere passed on its motions to the one immediately below
it so that the outermost sphere carrying the fixed stars, by
rotating daily on its axis, caused the diurnal rotation of all
the spheres and the heavenly bodies attached to them with
it. In order that the motions peculiar to one heavenly body
should not be passed on to the body immediately below it,
Aristotle introduced a number of what he called ‘unrolling
spheres’ between each set of spheres carrying a planet. The
similarities among the spheres included that they had the
same axes of rotation, they had the same speeds; they were
of the same number as the spheres which moved the planet
above them. The difference among them, however, is that
they moved in an opposite direction so that they were able
to neutralize all the motions peculiar to that planet, only the
diurnal rotation being passed on. For him. there were about
twenty-two ‘unrolling spheres’ that were geometrically
redundant [Mason 41],
Aristotle believed that the outermost sphere of the
fixed stars was moved by what he called the ‘Unmover
117
Mover’, which, according to him, is stationed at the,
periphery of the universe from where it controlled the entire
universe. He probably thought that each of the other
spheres had a lesser ‘Prime Mover’, which was responsible
for its motion. He likened the relation between a sphere
and its mover to that of a body to a soul. For him, the
movers of a planet worked contrary to the Prime Mover and
this made them to have their own west/east motions
contrary to the diurnal rotation. The planet Saturn, which is
the outermost planet, had the longest period of rotation
because of the difficulty it had in trying to overcome the
‘Primum Mobile’. The moon had the shortest period of
rotation because it was the innermost body. This informed
Aristotle’s arrangement of the heavenly bodies in order -
outwards from the earth in accordance with their periods of
revolution-Moon, Sun, Venus, Mercury, Mars, Jupiter and
Saturn.
In the field of physics, one of the main concerns of
Aristotle was the question of how things came to be in the
physical world. He began with the notion of Prime Matter,
by which he supposedly meant the substratum of things that
was capable of becoming other things or assuming new
forms. For him, the processes of nature involved the
continuous transformation of matter from one form to
another. He believed that nature made things from what he
called ‘simple bodies’, namely, air, water, fire and earth.
All things were reducible to these basic elements. When
these elements combined with one another, they gave rise
to new substances. The genesis of these new forms was a
product of nature itself, since inherent in these bodies was a
principle of motion and rest. For this reason, “fire tends to
rise to become air. water to fall and become earth, the solid
to become liquid, and the wet to become dry. In any case, to
118
say that things change is to say that these basic simple
bodies are constantly being transformed into things through
their internal principle of motion and by the motion of
things” [Stumpf 100-101],
Denying the existence of empty space, which the
atomists believed to exist, Aristotle argued that it was
inconceivable that a vacuum could exist, as space must be
filled with matter to transmit physical effects by direct
contacts in this way. For instance, when a stone is thrown it
is maintained in motion by the air which streams behind it to
prevent the formation of vacuum. Following this, the
atomists must be wrong to have supposed that the world
consists of atoms in the void, for space is a continuum of
matter.
Aristotle is said to have a richer view of causality
than Plato. He indicated four main types of causes namely:
1. Material cause: This refers to the primary matter out of
which objects are made.
2. Formal causes: These refer to the designs, forms and
patterns, which are impressed upon the primary matter.
3. Efficient causes: These refer to the agents who provide
the mechanisms whereby such designs are realized.
4. Final Causes: These are the purposes for which objects
are designed.
For Aristotle, what confers life upon certain kinds of
bodies is the soul.. The soul accounts for the transition
from inorganic to organic forms. All bodies are a
combination of the primary elements, but while some have
life, others do not. He uses ‘life’ here as a correlate of decay
to mean nutrition and growth. Matter as such is not a
principle of life because material substance can only be
potentially alive, but form is actuality. A body that is
potentially alive derives its life from what is actually alive,
namely, form. The soul, then, is the form of an organized
119
body. However, soul and body are not two separate entities
but are rather matter [body] and form [soul] of a single
unity. From this, it follows that the soul cannot be separated
from the body. Without the body, the soul cannot exist in
the same way that there cannot be vision without an eye.
By way of conclusion, it should be mentioned that
Aristotle marks a turning point in the history of Greek
Science, for he was the first to embark upon extensive
empirical inquiries.
120
CHAPTER 12
121
The Copernican System
One of the early achievements of modem science
was in the science of observational astronomy. The
common cosmological view of men in ancient times was a
geocentric one. It was believed that the inhabited earth was
at rest at the centre of the universe, with other planets
(including the sun) revolving round it. This belief was
derived from familiar facts of common experience, ideas
from the Bible, and early Greek philosophy and science,
especially those of Aristotle and Ptolemy.
In his work The Garden ofEpicurus,, Anatole
France captures the mind-set of the medieval man
thus:
We have some trouble in picturing the mind of
man of olden times who firmly believed that the
earth was the centre of the world and that all the
stars turned round it. He felt under his feet the
souls of the damned writhing in flames, and
perhaps he had seen with his own eyes and
smelled with his own nostrils the sulphurous
fumes of Hell escaping from some fissures in the
rocks. Lifting his head he contemplated the
twelve spheres of the moon, of Mercury, of
Venus, which Dante visited on Good Friday of the
year 1300, then those of the Sun, of Mars, of
Jupiter, and of Saturn, then the incorruptible
firmament from which the stars were hung like
lamps. Beyond his mind’s eye discerned the
Ninth Heaven to which saints were rapt, the
premium Mobile or Crystalline, and finally the
Empyrean, abode of the Blessed, toward which,
he firmly hoped, after his death two angels robed
in white would bear away, as it were a little child,
his soul washed in baptism and perfumed with the
122
oil of the last sacraments. In those days God has
no other children than men, and all his creation
was ordered in a fashion at once childlike and
poetic, like an immense cathedral. Thus
imagined, the universe was so simple that it was
represented in its entirety with its true shape and ,
motions in certain great painted clocks run by
machinery (cited in Onigbinde 106).
. . It was a great shock when Copernicus challenged and
upturned this familiar view of the world by his new science
of astronomy. Copernicus is regarded as “the first great
modem astronomer and founder of a new system of the
celestial orbs” (Burtt 35). It should be mentioned that
though Copernicus was primarily an astronomer, his
scientific discoveries brought about an intellectual
upheaval that has come to be regarded as the Copernican
revolution.
Copernicus employed mathematical arguments to
substantiate his theory. For him, a scientific theory consists
of a group of ideas deduced from certain assumptions
(hypotheses). A true assumption must meet two conditions,
namely, it must account for the observed motions of the
heavenly bodies, and it must not contradict the Pythagorean
preconceptions that the heavenly bodies have circular and
uniform motions. It is in view of the failure of the PtolemaicA
system to meet the latter condition that Copernicus?
dismissed it as grossly insufficient to please the mind.
Ptolemy had assumed that the heavenly bodies move in
circles with angular speeds whicji were uniform relative not
to the centres of their circles, but only to points outside such
centre. Another important objection Copernicus raised ,
against ancient astronomers is that they failed to explain
what was observed in the heavens and unnecessarily
complicated their systems of the universe. He argued that in
123
their quest to postulate a scheme that make the earth to be at
rest at the centre of the universe, the ancient astronomers
added three motions of the earth to each of the heavenly
bodies, thereby unnecessarily complicating the Greek
schemes. Copernicus eliminated these by assuming that the
earth rotates on its axis daily and revolves round the sun in
an annual orbit. Thus, Copernican system threw the facts of
astronomy into a simpler and more harmonious
mathematical order. It was simpler because in place of
eighty or so epicycles of the Ptolemaic system, Copernicus
was able to ‘save the phenomena’ with only thirty-four, all
those which had been required by lbs assumption thatrthe
earth remained at rest being now eliminated. It was more
harmonious because the major part of the planetary
phenomena could now fairly well be represented by a series
of concentric circles around the sun, our moon being the
only irregular intruder (Burtt 38)
Whereas in the old system the motions of the
heavenly bodies were east-west, and their rotations in the
opposite direction, in the Copernican system all the planets
(including the earth) moved in the same direction with
speeds that decreased with distance from the sun, while the
sun and the fixed stars are at rest at the center and the
periphery of the universe respectively. With this, it became
clear why the planets appeared to approach and recede from
the earth. According to Mason, “By an ingenious
combination of epicycles, Copernicus accounted for the
fact that the apparent diameter of the moon does not vary
widely, whilst the epicycles assumed by Ptolemy required
that the apparent diameter of the moon should vary by a
factor of four” (131). Mason also observes that though
astronomical computations were made simpler by the
Copernican scheme due to the smaller number of circles
involved, the prediction of planet places was not more
124
accurate than with the Ptolemaic scheme, as both involved
error of about one per cent.
Conclusion
In spite of the criticisms leveled against the
Copernican system, its achievements cannot be dismissed
with a wave of the hand. With Copernicus, a new set of
cosmic values emerged. The universe was no longer
governed by a prime mover at the periphery of the universe
but by the sun at the centre of the universe.
As Onigbinde observes, the Copernican revolution
clearly illustrates two basic features.that must characterize
any major revolution in science. The first is that it must be
able to reorient the ways in which scientists think about a
domain of natural phenomena and propose new lines of
126
research. For example, the astronomical theory of
Copernicus set new tasks for other astronomers such as
Tycho Brahe (1546 - 1601),. who undertook extensive
observational studies on the positions of the planets; Kepler
(1571 - 1630), who embarked upon a series of theoretical
researches in his quest for a more adequate planetary
theory; and Isaac'Newton (1642 - 1727), who initiated a
series of investigations in trying to systematize and unify
the laws of the whole field of terrestrial and celestial
physics. For Onigbinde, a second result of the Copernican
revolution consists in its philosophical implications.
Specifically, it forced a basic rethinking of man’s
conception of the world and his place in if. Of course,' it was
only the first of many scientific revolutions, which had
similar broad impacts. Other examples include the
biological theory of evolution developed in the 19th
century, Einstein’s theory of relativity and quantum
mechanics developed in the early part of the 20th century,
and the results are now beginning to emerge from the
science of molecular biology in genetic research (108
-109)..
i
127
CHAPTER 13
THE SCIENTIFIC METHOD OF GALILEO,
DESCARTES AND NEWTON
Galileo Galilei
Galileo Galilei (1564 -1642) was born at Pisa, Italy
where he studied and taught for a brief period at the
university there. He moved to the university of Padua in
1592, where for eighteen years he embarked upon the more
important of his researches on mechanics. In 1610 he
moved to Florence where he carried out his investigation in
astronomy with the telescope. In 1632 he published his first
influential work titled Dialogues Concerning the Two
Chief World Systems: Ptolemaic and Copernican^ In
1638, he published his second great work titled Discourses
on Two New Sciences. Both works, which were written in
form of dialogues, were aimed principally at discrediting
Aristotelian cosmology and mechanics. His work on
mechanics was inspired by the problems experienced in
engineering, while his studies on the gravitational fall of
bodies was stimulated by the problem of the flight of
projectiles (Mason 153).
Galileo’s main interest was in the role of
mathematics in scientific methods, particularly the
problem of the degrees to which physical objects
correspond to geometrical figures. His mathematical
theory of motion, which was a substantial improvement of
Bacon’s method of inquiry, grew out of his use of
mathematical facts to empirical facts about motion. His
inductive method was a huge success because through it he
was able to discover the laws of change. Bacon’s method
was concerned with ‘forms’ as its objects, while Galileo’s
128
method was concerned with establishing the mathematical
relationships that control the simplest, most fundamental
phenomenon of motion. In addition to his method of
induction (i.e. analysis), Galileo introduced the method of
mathematical deduction (i.e. synthesis), which proved very
fruitful in ascertaining the movement of astral bodies,
which were not amenable to observation in an experimental
laboratory. By means of a rational principle, which he
formulated, Galileo was able to place the laws of nature1 in a
universal form. He successfully applied the principle of
Plato and Democritus to resolve the age-long problem of
‘Being’ and ‘Becoming’. Thus, “the world is indebted to
Galileo for correcting the vagaries of Empiricism by means
of mathematical calculations, replacing the steri.lt
Pythagorean number philosophy of the Humanistic period
with an empirically valid mathematical theory” (Sahakian
130). •? :
Another area of interest for Galileo had to do with the
fall of bodies under gravitational force. After dismissing as
wrong Aristotle’s view that heavy bodies fall faster than
light ones, he proposed a theory of inertia which urged that
the unimpeded motion of a body is a uniform speed in a
straight line. From this position of Galileo, there arose the
problem of explaining heavenly bodies in mechanical
terms. The problem narrowed down to two questions,
which agitated the minds of the men of that period. They
included:
1. What is the law governing centripetal force, which is
necessary in order to bend linear motions into
circular or elliptical ones?
2. How do we demonstrate that gravity is capable of
providing the centripetal force, which makes planets
move in close orbits?
129
Of course, this required the derivation of law
responsible for variation of gravitational force with the
distance of gravitational bodies (Onuobia 15 - 16). Here,
credit must go to Newton who discovered this law.
Before discussing Newton’s scientific method, one
more area in which Galileo made important contribution to
science needs to be adumbrated, and that is, his support for
the Copernican heliocentric theory of the universe.
Contrary to the view of the Catholic Church at that
s time that the Copernican system was a mere instrument for
calculation, Galileo insisted that the Copernican system
, was more than that. He agreed with Copernicus that the sun
was at rest at the centre of the universe and all other
heavenly bodies including the earth revolved round it.
From the centre of the universe the stationary sun
illuminated the parts of the planetary bodies, which were
turned towards it.
Despite the attempt by the church to make Galileo to
recant his claims, he insisted that Copernicus was correct
because he himself had viewed Jupiter and its moon with
the telescope and they constituted a miniature model of
what Copernicus said about the solar system, that is, that the
universe housed planets, which were like moons to the sun.
Galileo also claimed to have viewed through the telescope
that the inner planets appeared to be like moon when
viewed from the earth, as Copernicus had predicted. All
, attempts by Galileo to make the church representatives to
see for themselves through the telescope were defied
because they believed that the scientific equipment was
meant to enable you see what it was designed for, and not
any objective reality. The church opposed the Copernican
130
U
system because it contradicted what it stood for, that is,
that the sun and other planets revolved round a stationary
earth at the centre of the universe. As Galileo insisted on
fostering the new system, he was called before the-
inquisition, which tried him, found him guilty and
compelled him to abjure, curse, and defest the aforesaid -
errors.
Rene Descartes
Rene Descartes (1596-1650) is French most eminent
; philosopher and the father of modem philosophy. He was '
- bom in La Haye, Touraine. He was trained in Scholastic
philosophy under the tutelage of the Jesuits in La Fleche.
Here he also studied Mathematics, in which he
distinguished himself by founding analytical georifetry.
' From 1629 to 1649 he lived in the Netherlands, where he,
wrote his important works, namely, Discourse on Method
■ (1637), Meditations of the First Philosophy (1641),
' Principles ofPhilosophy (1644), The Passions ofthe Soul
" (written during 1646-1649, and published posthumously in.
- 1650), and The World (written during 1630-1632, and
published posthumously in 1664).
Z Despite being a Roman Catholic, Descartes’ books
were placed upon the index by the Roman Catholic Church.
Oxford University prohibited the teaching of his
philosophy (Sahakian 133).
Descartes’ main vision was to find a single all-
encompassing science of Mathematical Physics that would
make the entire physical universe intelligible. In using
mathematics as the paradigm of knowledge, Descartes
followed the legacy of Plato. But unlike Plato whtf
131 1.1
believed that mathematics can yield the knowledge of
forms without the admixture of anything material or
sensible, Descartes proposed that it is mathematical
physics and not ‘pure’ mathematics that can yield both
rational, demonstrative knowledge and knowledge of the
material sensible. Descartes was a creative mathematician
who is credited with the discovery of the fundamental
principles and techniques of analytic geometry. He it was
who succeeded in merging geometry, and arithmetic and
algebra into a single discipline. As a result of his effort in
this direction, it became possible to write algebraic
equations for geometric curves and other spatial figures.
In the field of physics, Descartes held that the ideal
mathematical language for describing physical phenomena
is analytic geometry. His assumption is that it is possible to
bring the whole sphere of physical phenomena under the
purview of the science of mechanics, that is, the aspect of
physics that is concerned with the motion of bodies. His
views about physics and motion included the following
theses:
1. All of physical nature is a plenum. This implies that
there is no empty space in the universe.
2. The so-called indivisible particles of matter (atoms)
do not exist.
3. All motions of bodies can be explained in terms of
whirlpools of material particles (vortices) that vary
in size and speed.
4. Extension is the essential attribute of matter. This is
his most fundamental claim (Onigbinde 112-113).
132
In summary, the achievements of Descartes include:
1. Contribution to the development of mathematical
techniques.
2. Invention of coordinate geoi ; etry.
3. Extension of geometry to measurable quantities - a
process that remains clumsy because algebra is more
suited to the task.
4. Development of the view that motion and extension
is the key to understanding reality.
5. The view that all space is filled with matter and
therefore there is no void.
6. The view that motion is relative.
7. The view that God governs reality as a whole using
the rules of mechanics (Onuobia 15).
Descartes’ hypothesis that all of physical nature is a
single, mathematically unified intelligible mechanism, all
of whose motions and phenomena can be explained in
terms of a single set of principle was a task too enormous
for him to implement. As a result of this, Descartes’
proposals were shelved in favour of a more superior and
convincing principle of Newtonian mechanics.
Isaac Newton
Sir Isaac Newton (1642-1727) is credited with the
feat of successfully carrying out Descartes’ proposal of a
mechanization of physics. In his influential work The
Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy, he tried
to show that his three laws of motion and gravitational law
have made it possible to deduce, and hence explain, the
whole range of physical phenomena observed over the
133
centuries. In particular, he showed that the concepts of
mass and force were crucial to the explanation of the
acceleration of bodies. For him, his language of calculus
was the precise mathematical tool needed for the
formulation of laws of motion of bodies. Thus, the
Newtonian synthesis was able to accomplish what
Cartesian system could not - a universe made intelligible to
a science of mathematical physics (Onigbinde 144).
Newton’s mechanics was based on the common
belief that conceptual truths, laws and theories of natural
sciences are derived from observation or sense experience
by the method of induction rather than sheer imagination.
Newton himself stated that the truth of his theory could be
determined from certain observational statements, similar
to those from which the theory was logically derived.
Thus, for him, the inductive method of scientific inquiry is
indispensable to the natural sciences, and is preferable to
the deductive method because it enables the Scientist to
move from effects to causes. This is so, more so that, the
conclusion of a deductive argument cannot extend our
knowledge beyond the information already provided by the
premises, whereas the conclusion of inductive argument
does. In fact, the premises of an inductive inference
provide weighty evidence, which renders the truth of the
conclusion probable.
Newton first found the law of centripetal force of the
universe, and then the connector between the decrease of
gravitational force between two bodies with the square of
the distance separating them. He agreed with Descartes
that the starting point for mathematical demonstration in
natural philosophy should be the observed effects and laws
134
of mechanical motion. He also shared Galileo’s view-that -
mathematical deductions should be based upon
experimentally given principles. But he differed in that he'
was able to see- the "difference between experimental
principles and intuitive principles. In so doing, he differed
from Descartes who suggested that scientific
demonstrations should be based on intuitively given ideas.
Newton believed that intuitively given ideas had the status
of hypotheses only. Speculative and experimental
philosophizing belonged to separate chambers in
Newtonian system (Onuobia 16).
Newton was criticized by some of his
contemporaries, and their work helped to strengthen the
Cartesian system in Europe for many years. They
attempted mechanical explanations of gravity, either by
invoking the action and pressure of subtle matter
permeating the entire universe, or looking back to the idea
of magnetism. The English generally supported Descartes,
while the French supported Newton. The consequence
was a controversy, which continued well into the 18th
century. According to Butterfield,
Both Descartes and Newton were in the first rank
of geometers; but the ultimate victory of Newton
has a particular significance for us in that it
vindicated the alliance of geometry with the
experimental method against the elaborate
deductive system of Descartes. The clean and
comparatively empty Newtonian skies
ultimately carried the day against a Cartesian
universe packed with matter and agitated with
whirlpools, for the existence of which scientific
observations provided no evidence (170).
135
CHAPTER 14
A Summary of Relativity
Building upon the works of Galileo and Newton, the
19th century scientists were convinced that space
everywhere was filled by a medium called the ether. They
reasoned that light rays and radio signals were waves in this
ether the same way as sound is pressure waves in air. The
interest of the physicists of this era yas how to measure the
elastic properties of the ether with the hope that when this
was done, every other thing would fall into place. Yet a
series of experiments failed to find or unravel the exact
nature of the ether.
In 1905, Albert Einstein, in a paper, pointed out that
because we could not detect whether or not we were
moving through the ether, the whole notion of ether was
redundant. Instead, Einstein started from the postulate that
138
the laws of science should appear the same to all freely
moving observers. In particular, observers should all
measure the same speed for light, no matter how they were
moving. This dealt the first blow on Newtonian physics
which held that there was a universal quantity called ‘time’
that all clocks measure. Instead, every one would have his
personal time. The clock of two people would agree if they
were at rest with respect to each other but not if they are
moving. Einstein’s postulate that the laws of nature should
appear the same to all freely moving observers was the
foundation of the theory of relativity, so called because it
implies that only relative motion is important. This
overthrew two of the absolutes of nineteenth century
science: Absolute rest as represented by the ether and
absolute or universal time that all clocks would measure.
A very important consequence of relativity, according to
Einstein, is the connection between the mass of an object
and its energy (Relativity: Special and General theory
211). The equivalence of mass and energy is summed up
in his famous equation E= MC3 (energy equals mass
multiplied by the speed of light squared)
Among the consequences of this law is that if the
nucleus of a Uranium atom fission (split) into two nuclei
with slightly less total mass, a tremendous amount of
energy is released. It should be noted or remembered that
this led to the Manhattan project and the atomic bomb that
exploded in Hiroshima Nagasaki, Japan in 1945.
Although the theory of relativity fitted well with the
laws that govern electricity and magnetism, it was not
compatible with Newton’s law of gravity. This law states
that if we change the distribution of matter in one region of
139
space, the change in the gravitational field would be felt
■rnstantaheously everywhere else in the universe. This
means that we could send signals faster than light (which is
forbidden by relativity), and it also required the absolute or
universal time that relativity had abolished in favour of
personal or relativistic time. Einstein realized that there is a
close relationship between acceleration and a gravitational
field: “Some one in a close box cannot tell whether he is
sitting at rest in the earth’s gravitational field or being
accelerated by a rocket in free space” (Hawkings 33).
J The equivalence between acceleration and gravity
did not seem to work for a round earfh, however, people on
the other side of the world have to be accelerating in the
opposite direction but staying at a constant distance from
us. Einstein realized that the equivalence of gravity and
acceleration would work if there were some give and take
1 in the geometry of reality. What if ‘space-time’, an entity
invented by him to incorporate the three familiar
dimensions of space with a fourth dimension “time” was
curved, and not flat, as had been assumed? His idea was
that mass and energy would warp space-time in some
manner yet to be determined. Objects likp apples or planets
would try to move in straight lines through space-time, but
their path would appear to be bent by. a gravitational field
because space-time is curved. In 1915, Einstein published
his General Theory of Relativity, which borders on the
relation of the curvature of space-time to the mass in it. The
new theory of curved space-time was called the General
Theory of Relativity to distinguish it from the original
theory without gravity, which was now known as Special
140
Relativity.
These theories were confirmed in 1919, when a
British expedition to West Africa observed a slight shift in
the position of stars near the sun during an eclipse. Their
light, as Einstein had predicted, was bent as it passed the
sun. It was direct evidence that space and time are warped,
the greatest change in the perception of the universe since
Euclid wrote his Element about 300 B.C. Genera!
relativity also predicted that time comes to a stop inside
black holes regions of space-time that are so warped that
light cannot escape them. But both the beginning and end of
time are places where equations of general relativity fall
apart. Thus, the theory cannot predict what should emerge
from the big bang. Scholars such as J. H. Jauncey, see this as
an indication of God’s freedom to start the universe off any
way God wanted (Science Returns To God 20)
The basic tenets of relativity could be listed as
follows:
1. A moving clock runs slower than a stationary one
from the perspective of a stationary observer.
2. A moving object appears to shrink in the direction of
motion, as seen by a stationary observer.
3. According to relativity, gravity is not a force. It is a
warping of space-time (which happen to be an
amalgam of time and space) that happens in the
presence of mass. The warping is analogous to the
bending of a rubber sheet when weight is placed on ■
it.
4. Without external clues, it’s impossible to tell if one is
being pulled downward by gravity or accelerating
141
upward.
Confirmation of the Theory of Relativity
Arthur Eddingtion, an authority on the subject of
relativity was very much concerned with the astronomical
consequences of Einstein’s theory of relativity and the
possibility of confirming it by astronomical observations.
Paul Dirac has adumbrated Eddington’s three confirmatory
tests, (the fourth being a recent one) as follows:
1. The Motion of Mercury:
Through astronomical observations, Eddington
discovered that the perihelion of Mercury (i.e. the point in
the planet’s trajectory nearest to the sun) was advancing
about 43 seconds of arc more than it should be according to
the Newtonian theory, a fact that had worried astronomers
for a long time. Einstein’s theory predicted exactly this
effect and Eddington’s tests confirmed this prediction.
Conclusion
Einstein’s theory of relativity not only upended
physics, it shook the underpinnings of society. Indirectly,
144
relativity paved the way for a new relativism in ethics, arts
and politics. After the publication of the theory of
relativity, there was less faith in absolutes, not only of time
and space but also of truth and morality. But relativism,
that is, the idea that moral or ethical truth exists in the point
of view of the beholder, owed nothing to Einstein.
Finally, relativity is significant because it
demonstrates that imagination is capable of coming to
terms with experience. By gazing into existence Einstein
concluded that time and space could be warped, and that
mass and energy are interchangeable. D. P. Gribanov sums
up the significance of Einstein’s theory of relativity in the
following words:
The theory of relativity is one of the most
fundamental theories of nature that still, at the
present time, calls for further philosophical
substantiation. Its mathematical and physical
aspects do not give rise to substantial
disagreement among researchers. It has a
leading position by right among the
achievements of the advanced physical
thought of the twentieth century. It has had
broad application in many 1 experimental
programmes (7).
As Paul Dirac puts it, Einstein alone changed the
course of scientific history. His theory of relativity came in
with a terrific impact. It presented the world with a new
style of thinking, a new philosophy (in Brown, Fauvel and
Finnegan 89)
145
CHAPTER 15
QUANTUM MECHANICS
The term ‘quantum’ was originally used in Latin in
an interrogative sense to refer to ‘how much’ or ‘how
many’. Before the 20th century it was occasionally used in
English to denote a definite amount of something.
Obviously, it was in this sense that Planck im 1-900
• spoke of the elementary quantum of electricity ‘e’, which
meant ‘the electric charge of a positive univalent of ion or
an electron'. It was from this he derived his famous law of
thermal (or ‘black body’) radiation that now carries his
name. The model he employed was a collection of many
linearly oscillating monochromatic resonators encased in a
cavity with reflecting walls, and he assumed that the energy
of the resonators oscillating with a particular frequency “v”
was an integral multiple of the quantity. '
Ev = hv
Where ‘h’ is a constant of nature with a dimension of
action (energy x time), later known as ‘Planck’s constant’.
We are not too sure this was a general hypothesis or a
peculiarity of his fictitious model. Planck himself did not
call “h” an elementary quantum of action nor did he refer to
Pv as one of energy. It was while Einstein was trying to
build on Planck’s work a few years later that he (Einstein)
guessed that all electromagnetic radiation consisted of
energy quanta localized at points in space, which moved
undivided, and could only be absorbed as general wholes
satisfying the condition contained in the equation above.
Subsequently, the term ‘quantum’ was used more often as a
noun to refer to the minimum amount in which some
146
physical quantity is found in nature by multiples of which it
increases or decreases. It was also used as an epithet for
hypotheses, theories, and the like, that imply the reality of
such Quanta, and particularly the ‘quantization’ of energy
in accordance with the equation above. Thus, we can speak
of Quantum Physics (QP) in. this general sense, and
Quantum Mechanics (QM) as the theory developed in the
late 1920’s from the comBmation of Heisenberg's ‘matrix
mecHanics’ of 1925 and SchxodjngerTs~rw'ave ffiechanics’
of 1926. --------------- -----
Quantum mechanics represents a new way of
understanding the basic purpose and concepts of physics,
which has become a subject of endless, philosophical
controversy. This is surprisingly so in spite of its
impeccable experimental success. It should be stated that
the equations of quantum mechanics are not Lorentz
invariant and hence can hold well only in situations where
relative speeds are small, but most authors believe that the
philosophical problems inherent in Lorentz invariant
quantum theories developed at its outset. These problems
have generated the current interest in philosophy of
physics, especially since the philosophical problems
associated with the theory of relativity have been tackled
(Torrenti 307-308) (
151
The validity of quantum theory becomes obvious
when we realize that on extremely fine'scale, space-time,
and thus reality itself becomes grainy and discontinuous.
At this level, the laws of cause and effect break down and
particles can jump from point A to point B without going
through space in between. In such a world, you can only
calculate what will probably happen next - which is just
what quantum theory is designed to do. Instead of knowing
something by simply observing it, quantum theory is
saying that something is not just there until you observe it.
Unlike classical physics, which conceived reality as a three
coordinates or dimensional phenomenon, quantum
mechanics regards space and time as separate entities.
To conclude, in the words of Alozie, despite the
difficulties and controversies over the interpretation of
quantum theory, a lot of new grounds have been broken,
using the theory as the basis. For him, the new fields,
which have emerged as a result of the theory, include,
among others, electrical conductivity, quantum theory of
solids, quantum chemistry and molecular biology. He
concludes that the scientific enterprise appears to be
advancing and giving birth to new technologies, despite
some difficulties with popular logic, metaphysics,
epistemology and axiology (POP 115). And in the words
of Karl Popper, although quantum mechanics was at first a
theory of the motion of the (negative) electron in the
positive field of the nucleus, nevertheless, this formalism
has changed very considerably, as it is more and more
widely applied (Quantum Theory 13).
.152
-----------------------------------------i------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------- ,
PART FOUR:
SOME PHILOSOPHICAL
‘ISMS’ IN SCIENCE
CHAPTER 16
Rationalism
Rationalism is the philosophical school that stresses
the primacy of reason over any other faculty in the
acquisition of knowledge. It holds that reason is the
primary means of determining truth and of justifying
knowledge. Rationalists subscribe to the view that ideas
originate from the mind. Rationalists stress the primacy of
mind over senses, the a priori over the a posteriori.
Rationalists are mostly foundationalists who hold that there
are first principles of knowledge, the absence of which no
knowledge is possible. They affirm that reason arbitrates
truth, and truth is objective.
Aristotle is often regarded as the father of Western
rationalism. Although he holds that knowledge begins in
the senses, his emphasis on reason and logic qualified him
for this honour.
It is said that modem rationalism begins with a
reaction against scholastic Aristotelianism, a reaction that
elevates mathematics as a model of human knowledge.
Following this, it is held that our knowledge of ourselves, of
God and the world ought to be organized into a deductive
system, in which all truths are derived from a relatively
154
small number of axioms and definitions, whose truth is
assured by their self-evidence. Only if our starting points
are absolutely certain, and we proceed by careful, certainty
preserving, deductive steps from them, can we achieve
certain knowledge. Following this picture of knowledge,
experience is to be counted as essentially irrelevant because
it cannot provide the certainty we requires (Curley, 411).
This is the central thesis of rationalism to which Rene
Descartes (1596-1650), Benedict Spinoza (1632-1677),
and Gottfried Leibniz (1646-1716) subscribed. These
three philosophers are regarded as the chief modem
rationalists. With his thesis T think, therefore, I am’,
Descartes, often regarded as the father of modern Western
rationalism, raised a new insight into the qualities of the
human mind and established a new foundation for
knowledge (Oyeshile and Ugwuanyi 69). Spinoza is
regarded as a pantheist philosopher who believes that
reason is independent and that God and nature are one.
Leibniz subscribes to theism. In short, most worldviews
have some forms of rationalism because as an
epistemology, rationalism is a means of discerning truth.
Most worldviews have at least one prominent proponent of
rationalism who uses rationalism to determine and defend
truth as he sees it.
Although there are many versions of rationalism,
there are certain central premises shared commonly by
virtually all rationalists. They include the following
factors:
Empiricism
Empiricism is an epistemological movement which
holds that nothing around us can be known to be real unless
its existence is revealed in or inferable from information we
gain directly in sense experience or in introspection of our
subjective states or later recall; and genuine, intelligible
differences in our claims about this world must express
these knowable differences in experience. Because of their
constraints on knowledge and meaning, empiricists tend to
be skeptical about necessary truths that are independent of
mind and language, and of putative external abstract
entities (e.g. universals). In particular, they are skeptical of
faculties of intellectual, non-sensuous intuition through
which such things are allegedly known. Like any
philosophical movement, empiricism is often challenged to
show how its claims about the structure of knowledge and
meaning can themselves be intelligible and known within
the constraints it accepts (Hunter 115).
For the traditional empiricists, only what is
immediately presented to us in consciousness is non-
inferentially knowable. In present sense- experience, this
consists of the occurrence of particular sensible qualities
157
such as shape, size, texture, flavors, colour, odour, and the
1 ike, while from past experience, it consists of those we can
immediately recall, though less vividly. Thus, for the
empiricists, the five modes of sensation of seeing, feeling,
hearing, tasting and smelling are reliable sources of
knowledge. The data that come through these senses in
form of impressions on the mind feed the mind with ideas,
which are the objects of knowledge. John Locke, the
British philosopher, is often regarded as the father of
modern Western empiricism. Other notable modem
/ empiricists include Bishop George Berkeley and David
Hume. Since then it has continued to attract influential
advocates and sympathizers such as Mill, James, Russell,
Lewis, Ayer, Carnap and Quine. Locke’s ambition was to
explore the origin, sources, and scope or limits of
knowledge. His extreme empiricism made him to treat
knowledge and sensation as though they are synonyms.
On his part, Hume argues that all knowledge is based
on sense experience. He divides what we know into two,
' namely, matters of fact and relation of ideas, which is the
realm of logic and mathematics. The truths of logic and
mathematics are known a priori. They are by definition,
necessary. They are not part of this world. On the contrary,
matters of fact belong to the realm of sense- experience.
They are contingent truths. They are a posteriori, and
hence can be known only by direct experience. They
provide genuine knowledge of the world and can be used to
ascertain what is claimed on the basis of experience.
Contrary to the commonsense belief that we have ideas,
eoncepts and sense-experience, Hume contends that these
ideas or concepts either are relations of ideas, or are capable
158
of being analysed into having sensation or reflecting on
them. According to him, impressions are the actual content
of the mind in the moment of perception. For him, ideas are
less vivid copies of impressions, which can be combined
into complex ideas by means of imagination. In the final
analysis, empiricism holds that there is nothing in the mind
which was not first in the sense.
It is said that empiricism provides both an acceptable
answer to the skeptic and a unified source of all knowledge.
This has developed in two ways. The search for certainty
has resulted in the analysis of experience into irreducible,
infallible units of experience known as sense-data. These
are the raw materials or basics of our experience about
which we cannot be mistaken. This approach highlights the
reality of the external world and of the self. A
contemporary analytic movement in philosophy - logical
positivism - has converted empiricism into a search for
meaning based on ostensive definition, which sees
knowledge as like learning a language, in which we give a
name and point out an object, so that no other understanding
is possible. Verifiability has been the other criterion of
meaning, in which a statement is meaningful only if it can
be verified by sense-experience. This has been modified by
Karl Popper and his followers to become a ‘principle of
falsifiability’, which bases knowledge on the failure to
disprove, falsify or refute. However, empiricism is still
based on verification by sense-experience, using the
methods of empirical and inductive sciences as a solution to
skepticism. It has created doubt about the truth and validity
of religious statements and doctrines, based on a narrow
view of experience being reducible to sense-experience
alone (Cook 223).
159
To conclude this section, it must be mentioned that
attempts have been made to reconcile rationalism and
empiricism. It is argued that both movements share in a
common debate over the origin of human knowledge, both
employ rational and scientific approaches, and both aim at
achieving certainty. Furthermore, both are responses to the
skeptical challenge to knowledge. The skeptic doubts the
possibility of knowledge, but the rationalists and
empiricists attempt to cure that doubt. Immanuel leant offers
a bridge between reason and sense-experience with his
emphasis on synthetic a priori categories of understanding
which make knowledge possible. For Kant, knowledge of
these categories is not based on experience, yet it is a
condition of the comprehensibility of experience.
Objections have, however, been raised against kant’s
synthetic a prior claims. G.E. Moore and Ludwig
Wittgenstein have downplayed the issues of doubt and
analyzed knowledge in terms of meaning through linguistic
usage. For them, ordinary language and commonsense
have little problem with philosophical doubt and offer a-
simple solution to it. The logical positivists, as indicated
above, have converted empiricism to verificationism and
falsificationism as means for determining the truth claims
and knowledge, often using data as the ultimate source of
certainty. A.J. Ayer offers an analysis of knowledge in
terms of its being justified true belief. For him, the key
issues in epistemology seem to border on the role of
justification and its nature, ways of setting aside, or coping
with, doubt, and whether the skeptic’s position makes any
sense, the nature of the known, an adequate theory of truth,
and the relationship between objectively and to what extent
160
subjectivity intrudes or is seen to be problematic (Cook
225).
163
CHAPTER 17
REALISM IN SCIENCE
Introduction
According to W.E. Hocking, “realism as a general
temper of mind is a disposition to keep ourselves and our
preferences out of our judgment of things, letting the
objects speak for themselves....” (Cited in Titus and Smith
225).
With its assumption of an external world existing
quite independent of the human mind, realism was widely
accepted among Western philosophers until it was first
seriously questioned about the 17"' century. Most of us
think we exist in the midst of a world of objects that are
independent of us. Thus it is our belief that though our
mind interacts with the external world, nevertheless, this
interaction does not in any way affect the basic nature or
structure of the world. The world predates the mind and
will continue to exist after the mind has ceased to be aware
ofit.
The aim of this chapter is explore the place of realism
in the field of science. But before this can be judiciously
done, it will be germane to discuss the meaning, history and
types of realism.
164
to events or things that exist in their own right, as opposed
to events or things that are fictitious or imaginary. In a
nutshell, real refers to what is. Reality is the state or
quality of being real or actually existent, as opposed to
being a mere appearance. In popular usage, realism refers
to devotion to fact, to what is the case, in contrast with what
is desired, wished or hoped (Titus & Smith 442). Any view
can qualify for the name ‘realist’ if it emphasizes the
existence of some kind of thing or object (e.g. material
objects, propositions, universals), as opposed to a view,
which dispenses with the things in question in favour of
words (nominalism), ideas (idealism, conceptualism), or
logical constructions (phenomenalism) (A.R.. Lacey 180).
In philosophy, the term 'realism' is used in a more technical
sense.
In its strictly philosophical sense, realism refers to
the position that the objects of our senses are real in their
own right, and that they exist independent of their being
known to, perceived by, or related to the mind. In other
words, realism is the doctrine that there is a real world of
things behind and corresponding to the objects of our
perception (Sharma & Hyland 52; Titus & Smith 442;
Ozumba91).
Realism holds that there is a world really ‘out there’
that we just have to come to terms with, but not to attempt to
interpret it with the special hope of unveiling its secrets.
For the realist, we cannot mn away from the fact that there
is a marked distinction between things and ideas. Even
commonsense reveals to us that an idea is an idea or a
thought of something in our mind, which represents the
thing, it is an idea of. In that case, the idea is merely how the
165
thing appears to us, while the thing is the reality. Therefore,
if our idea is to be true, it must adapt itselfto things. An idea
is false or useless if it fails to correspond with the thing of
which it is the idea.
A notable realist A. N. Whitehead is said to have set
forth some good reasons for believing that the things we
* experience are different from our knowledge of them. In
defending his objectivist position, he makes three
«, affirmations. First, we are within a world of colours,
sounds and other sense objects, a world that is neither
within us, nor is dependent on our sense perception.
Second, historical evidence abounds that long before living
beings surfaced on the earth, important happenings were
taking place therein. Third, one’s activity seems to
transcend the self and to find and to seek ends in the known
world. Things pave way for our awareness. A common
world of thought seems to imply and require a common
world of sense (Titus & Smith 443). Many notable
philosophers, especially of idealist and -pragmatic
orientations have argued that the object as it is and the
object as it is experienced or known are entirely different
things. For them, since we can never know an object except
it is experienced or known by us, the object being
experienced or known invariably forms an integral part of
the object known. The realist sees this line of reasoning as
fallacious because, according to him, we cannot know a
thing except we have experience of it. In other words, only
known things are known.
Realism has a tendency toward other trends or
philosophies. We can point to at least three tendencies in
modern realism. First, there is an apparent tendency
166
toward materialism - “a view that everything is to be
accounted for in terms of material causes” (Popkin & Stroll
121). For example, mechanistic or naturalistic materialism
is both realism and materialism.
Mechanistic/naturalistic materialism holds that
nature and the physical world are one and the same. And by
the physical world is meant the collection of facts, events,
and the .things that have space, time and motion as their
sufficient . and fundamental defining characteristics.
Nature is the sum of all events and things that are
quantitatively measurable (Randall & Buehler 195;DagIish
75 - 78). Second, there is a tendency toward idealism, the
view that the most importantelement in the nature of reality
is the mind or spirit or idea (Popkin & Stroll 120); or to put
it in the Hegelian way, the doctrine that thoughts within
one’s brain are not more or less abstract pictures of actual
things and processes, but, conversely, things and their
evolution are only the realized pictures of the ‘Idea’,
existing somewhere from eternity before the world was
(Engels 35). Third, many realists have a tendency toward
pluralism - the view that reality consists of many kinds of
entities of which mind and matter may only be two.
Because this is the dominant view today, this type of
realism occupies much of our attention in this chapter.
There are three basic tenets of realism. A. J. Knight
has stated these tenets to include the following:
1.. Ultimate reality is not in the realm of the mind but
matter. The universe is composed of matter in motion, so it
is the physical world in. which man lives that constitutes
reality. The vast cosmos rolls on despite man and his
knowledge. This position constitutes the philosophic base
of much of modem science
167
2. Truth is through observation. Realism resorts to the
correspondence theory for validating its conception
of truth. It holds that truth is that which conforms to
the actual situation as perceived by the observer.
3. Values emanate from nature. The realist believes
that values are obtained by the observation of nature.
Through the study of the natural order, one comes to
know the laws that provide the basis for ethical and
aesthetic judgment. Values that come from this
source are permanent, since they are grounded in a
universe that is stable, even though, from the human
viewpoint, it is being more fully understood all the
time (Philosophy & Education 103-154).
174
According to scientific realism, reality is beyond
what we see and there are degrees of perception of reality
that are akin to the scientific enterprise. It holds that the
real may be the posited, the scientifically perceptible, the
scientifically, real (Ozumba 91). Scientific realism thrives
on the view that there are certain objects or entities that are
not amenable to perception with the naked eyes but with
scientific instruments such as microscopes, telescopes,
stethoscopes, thermometers, and so on. Consequently,
what may be real to the naive realist and critical realist may
not be real to the scientist who depends on instruments,
theories and standards set by the scientific community. A
few examples or illustrations will help to buttress this point.
Let us take the table right in front of one, for
example. Naive realist would claim that the table is what it
appears to be - a solid block of matter that occupies some
particular position, say a fixed three - dimensional space.
' But modern science states that what we call a table is a
series of events that occur in a four-dimensional region of
space - time. None of the atomic particles involved in the
events can be called solid, coloured, hard, warm, etc. The
atomic events take place without my being aware of them,
just as radio waves continually pass me without my being
aware of their presence.
Now, consider the example of the colour of my table,
naive realist tells us that if the colour of my table is brown, it
is really brown. However, physics tells us otherwise.
What really happens when I say am perceiving the colour of
table as brown is that electromagnetic radiations of various
frequencies are being constantly released from the sun
which stream through my window and strike on the surface
175
of my table, and some of these, by means of my brain and
optic nerve cause me to perceive the table as brown. This
equally holds for all sensible qualities.
Thus, scientific realism holds that it is the particular
modifications of sensory faculty that causes us to perceive
what are called commonsense qualities. If all sentient
beings were annihilated, such qualities would accordingly
disappear. What would, however, be left would be the
atomic and sub-atomic events that make up the physical
world and cause us to have the particular perceptions we do
have. To that extent, the physical world has a real existence
of its own ?md is in no way dependent on a perceiver for its
existence (Halverson 97 - 98). To this end, scientists
formulate theories based on their own perception of the
world. Perception here goes beyond our being aware of the
observable. It includes all ideas, conjectures, organized
imaginations and all possibilities, which strike our minds.
This informs why scientific realism debunks the
theory/observation distinction or demarcation proposed by
the logical positivists. The reason for this is that it is
difficult to ascertain where a theory ends and where
observation begins. What is unobservable today may
become observable in future. It will therefore be senseless
to establish in a priori fashion the language that will
constitute sentences about observables. For a realist like
Paul Feyerabend, the proper method is “anything goes”
(f eyerabend 296), and what should concern the scientist
should be the formulation of theories in form of bold
conjectures (hypotheses) and attempting to rise above them
through bolder and more intelligible conjectures (Karl
Popper 231).
176
Now, what is the status of theoretical entities in
relation to the position of scientific realism? Theoretical
entities, simply put, are existents beyond the physical.
Their existence may only be attested to with the help of
scientific apparatus. They are names, concepts or
expressions, which help scientists.to properly define and
explain what they are doing. Scientists have at least three
levels of observation, namely, ordinary, instrumental and
theoretical. Theories, as generalizations based on
hypotheses, do not constitute wholly the observable. They
have in their constitution certain entities which represent
reality, but which are only acceptable to members of the
scientific community upon an observable definition that
will enable people to verify them. These unobseryabj,e
entities (theoretical entities) constitute the ‘not- given’
aspects of the theory which are made meaningful by being
consistent with the ‘given’ (observable, concrete). To
make these unobservable meaningful, the scientist employs
correspondence rules, making sure that they yield to inter-
subjective verification. Take for example, Newtonian
mechanics. In our context, Newtonian mechanics is to be
regarded as a calculating device that enables the observable
positions and velocities of billiard balls at some instant of
time to be deduced from their observable positions and
speeds at some different times. The forces involved in
these and similar calculations (the impulsive forces due to
impact, frictional forces, etc.) are really not entities that
exist, rather they are inventions of the physicist. Similarly,
the atoms and molecules involved in the kinetic theory of
gases are convenient theoretical fictions (Chalmers 148).
In this case, theoretical entities are to be justified by their
177
usefulness in connecting one set of observation of a
physical system involving gases (the height of the mercury
in a manometer, the reading of a thermometer, etc.) with
another similar set (Ogar 103).
Conclusion
The focal question addressed generally by realism is
- Is the physical world in any degree dependent on a
perceiver for its existence? The meeting point of all the
trends or versions of realism highlighted in this chapter is
their unanimous ‘No’ answer. They are all agreed that the
physical world existed long before the emergence of
sentient life on earth and will continue to exist long after all
such life has disappeared from the scene. Commonsense
(naive) realism, in particular holds that our unaided senses
reveal to us the shapes, ^izes, colours, sounds, solidities, etc
that are really ‘out there’.
Modem physics reveals to us that by the use of
magnifying instruments (e.g. microscopes, telescopes,
amplifiers, etc) we can transcend the limits of our unaided
senses to perceive certain features of the world that are
indiscernible to the senses. It is the opinion of this author
that the account of the physicist does not in any way
contradict that of the commonsense, rather it augments,
supplements or complements it. It will therefore be
arbitrary to claim that the position of the commonsense is
invalid while the observations of the physicist are valid.
i
f.
178
CHAPTER 18
IDEALISM IN SCIENCE
What is Idealism?
Idealism is the philosophical school that stresses the
central role of the ideal or the spiritual in man’s
interpretation of his experiences. It holds that reality exists
mainly as spirit or mind, and that abstraction and law are
more central to our knowledge than sense experience. We
can know that a thing exists only through mind or ideas.
Idealism is thus opposed to materialism, the view
that matter is real and mind is its byproduct. Idealism
denies the materialist view that the world is a great machine
to be interpreted as matter, mechanism or energy alone.
Idealism is also opposed to realism, the doctrine that in
human knowledge objects are perceived or known as they
really are. For idealism, nothing is known or understood
outside or independently of the mind.
The essential features or tenets of idealism are as
follows:
1. Truth is the whole, or the Absolute.
2. To be is to be perceived, meaning that the being of an
object depends in its being perceived by the human
mind.
3. Reality reveals its ultimate nature more faithfully in
its highest qualities (mental) than its lowest
(material).
4. The ego is both subjective and objective (Sharma &
Hyland 45).
Idealism lays great stress on supernatural or
transcendental ideas. As a world-view, it holds that the
basic reality consists of mind, ideas, thoughts, or selves.
179
For the idealist, the world has a meaning beyond its surface
appearance. In short, the world can be understood and
interpreted not exclusively by the methods of the natural or
physical sciences, but by studying the laws of thought and
consciousness. Since the universe is purposive and
a^eapingful, there is an inner harmony between man
(microcosm) ;and the external world (macrocosm). Thus,
what is highest in spirit is ipso facto deepest in nature. Man
is not an alienor a creature of chance, since the universe is
id some sense a logical arid a spiritual system that is
reflected in man’s search forthegood life. Theselfisnotan
fshlat^'q oV'ilni^al entitv. but a genuine part of the world
rnEHKdDl LLoimoinva snfljfuff? .dhe.ujsi ?.i_
1 hls prt<css al "s hl8h lcvcls manifests itself as
Persons. Man, as. a part of the
cosmos, expresses its structure inWown life (TiW&
Smith 42.3(7t 424).bav ieoiaq orn yfu'jjdo ogbolwonM nnmuri
bo< ) - .Idealism .stresses organic wholeness !as ,a central
principle. It holds that the world process exhibits organic
unity. As a result of this unity, it will be difficult to separate
the parts from the whole without causing damage to the
equally important excludednspects.rlThisjinner! unity can
be seeni inlthe unfolding series of levels through vegetable
liferand lower animals to mail, mind! and spirit^ Idealists
subscribe to the coherence theory of truth, which holds that
a statement or judgment is true if it coheres/agrees with
.other statementSior j udgments that are acceptedias true.
Historically, the origin of idealism; can.he traced to
early Greek philosophy. Specifically,; it began with
Socrates when he dialogued with Pythagoras,aPatmenides
and,other early Greek thinkers. (Socrates’ disciple, Plato,
held that there arc two worlds, namely, the world of forms
or ideas, w hich are real and lasting, and the world of objects
or senses which are transitory and imperfect. In hiS'1
immortal work The Republic, Plato holds that the sensible
world is a shadowy world, a pale reflection of the world of
forms, and that in order to grasp pure idea, we seed td's^fl
aside sense experience and rely on pure intellect. No
wonder Plato is not only regarded as the father of WesWh
idealism but also an idealist par excellence.
St. Augustine reflected on idealistic tradition dtn‘iiig •
the 4"' century. However, the beginning of mbd^rn
idealistic revival came after the renaissance. Through liik
principle of‘cognito ego sum’ (1 think, therefore, 1 dm’), ■
the French thinker, Rene Descartes, held that the self Was 1
the basic reality and the existence of God was necessary.
Benedict Spinoza, the pantheistic idealist, reflected that
there existed eternally a substance in the world, wlficli Iid4
identified as God. For Leibniz, the cosmos is mad^’iip of
simple, indivisible entities, which he calls monads. These
monads, for him, are points of mental force. . /iryjjdu?.
Bishop George Berkeley continued and developed
the idealistic tradition. He is fondly remembered lor his. .
idealistic statement: ‘esse estpercipi’, which means,?To bg i
is to be perceived’. In the late 18"' century, Kant, the
founder of objective idealism, postulated a formalistic or
transcendental introspection of the main idealistic'themes.
He believes that the self or transcendental ego coridtrucTs
knowledge out of sense impressions upon wliiih lire laid
universal concepts, which he calls categories. In the early'i
19th century, Hegel was inspired by this Kantian pdsition to J
postulate the idea that the world consisted of man-made,
objects with corresponding structures, examples; ptjwhich/
are language and practical art (e.g. medicine)^ which -
constituted mental achievements. In his celebrated
response to the question of why there is a world of nature at
all, Hegel answered: *for the sake of mind’. The German
181
idealist, Arthor Schopenhauer, held that the world was
merely a conception of man’s will. His idealistic thought
greatly influenced the English, French and American
philosophers who came after him.
From the foregoing historical analysis, it is clear that
though idealist philosophy has taken many and varied
forms, the underlying assumption in all is that mind, or
spirit, or self is the basiQ world-stuff, and that true reality is
of a mental character. In order to fully understand the
various forms of idealism underlying this common
principle, a brief discussion of the various strands of
idealism, which have been proposed over the centuries, is
necessary.
Types of Idealism
1 Subjective idealism:
Also called mentalism or phenomenalism,
subjective idealism conceives reality in terms of the
experiences of the individual mind. It holds that all that
existxare minds or spirits and their ideas or perceptions.
Things such as buildings, trees, rivers, human beings exist
only in a mind that perceives them. Both Berkeley and
Leibniz were subjective idealists. Preferring to call his
philosophy immaterialism, Berkeley adopted a position
that reduced reality to spirit and the ideas entertained by
spirits. He explained the apparent objectivity of world
outside self in terms of ideas in God’s mind. For Leibniz,
monads or souls were the true atoms of nature and nothing
exited in the world apart from minds.
2. Objective Idealism.
_ 1 This is the view that the universe is one all-
embracing order, an organic whole, whose basic nature is
182
mind. For the objective idealist, the mind discovers what
there is in the order of the universe.
Plato is the father of objective idealism in the
Western world. For him, behind the empirical world of
change, the phenomenal world that we feel and see, the
world of individual thkgs, there is a supersensible world of
forms, eternal essences, ideas, universals, or concepts. The
former is concrete, temporal and perishable, while the
latter is permanent and eternal. Forms or ideas are the
original, transcendent patterns and perceptions, while
individual things are mere copies, imitations, or shadows
of these forms. While affirming that reality is immaterial,
Plato held that there is nothing real except mind and its
experiences. The unchanging forms or ideas, which are
real, are known only through reason.,
Hegel was an objective idealist. (His version is
sometimes called evolutionary idealism . /or logical
idealism. Hegel held that thought is the essence of the
universe and that nature is the whole of mind objectified.
Nature is Absolute Reason or Spirit expressing itself in
outward form. For him, when we say that the total world
order embraces all of the inorganic, organic and spiritual
levels of existence in a single all-inclusive order, we are
speaking in terms of the Absolute Spirit or God.
3. Personafldealism, or Personalism
This view arose as a result of the protest against
mechanistic materialism and monistic idealism.
According to this version, reality does not consist of
abstract thought or a particular thought process, but a
person, a self, or a thinker. In other words, reality consists
of the nature of conscious personality. The personalists
find support for their position in the recent developments in
modern science, especially the formulation of the theory of
relativity with its emphasis on the perspective of the
183
observer. For them, because reality is a system of personal
self, it is pluralistic. Thus, personalists stress the reality and
worth of individual people, moral values, and human
freedom. They believe that though nature is an objective
order, it does not exist in and of itself. People rise above
nature when they interpret it. Science transcends its
material through its theories, and the world of meaning and
values transcends the world of nature as final explanation.
The chief proponents of this point of view include Rudolf
Hermann Lotze (1817 - 1881), Borden P. Bowne (1847 -
1910), Edgar Sheffield Brightman (1884- 1953), and Peter
Bertocci (1910 -) (Titus & Smith431).
4. Scientific Idealism:
Hermann Cohen who applied Kant's critical methods
to humanistic and scientific studies founded this School. It
got a boost under the leadership of Ernest Cassirer who is
noted for his definition of man as that who creates culture
through a unique capacity for symbolic representation.
This brand of idealism is said to play a significant role in
shaping Russian culture and society.
5. Theistic Idealism
According to this school, there is a ‘world ground’ in
which all phenomena find their unity. This "world ground’,
which is both mechanical and teleological, is the
transcendental synthesis of evolutionary world process. T.
H. Green and F. H. Bradley are exponents of this view.
They employed the classical proofs and recent advances in
the natural and behavioural sciences to support their
arguments for the existence of God. In particular, they
restated the cosmological proof as a continuing relation of
the cosmos to a world ground that is essentially spiritual.
Idealism in Science
Idealism holds that the universe is a purposive
184
universe whose real nature is spiritual. While accepting
the interpretations of modern empirical sciences, idealists
however argue that they are limited by the ; methods
employed and the fields investigated. The sciences tend to
eliminate all mental aspects of the world and construct a <•
world that is devoid of mind. The idealists are willing to
allow the physical scientists tell us what matter is, provided
in trying to do that they do not reduce everything in the
world to that category. They are willing to allow the
biologists tell us what life is and its processes, provided
they guard against the temptation to reduce all other levels
to the biological.
For the idealists, the world of. nature that men
perceive is undoubtedly a world of appearances whose real
nature is different from what it appears to be. But in man’s
attempt to explain the various transformations that take
place in matter, he has pushed his analysis from molecules
to atoms, and from atoms to protons and electrons. For
idealists, what the scientists call molecules, atoms, protons,
electrons and neutrons are nothing but mental constructs
arrived at through a reasoning process or logical analysis.
Evidently, the fundamental character of matter is not that of
its outward appearance, and when we try to determine just
what this fundamental character is, we came back to energy
of some kind. If we try to stop at this point in pur
interpretation, the idealist might suggest that psychical
energy is that which is most real to us. Even though we
may start with so-called physical things, when we push our
investigation far enough, we are forced into what appears
to be a mental world. In any event, we are forced to the
conclusion that there are mental forces within and behind •
the world of nature (Titus & Smith 433).
For the idealist, the mind is not just a stranger
appearing suddenly and accidentally in the universe. The
185
fact that men’s minds work and understand the same way
show that they are fundamentally the same, and governed
by the laws of logic and intelligibility. Again, the fact that
man is progressively coming to understand and interpret
nature shows that the mind is at work in nature. Thus
“order, intelligibility, meaning, and law seem to be at the
basis of both mind and nature” (Titus & Smith 433).
Finally, unlike modern empirical sciences, which do
not accommodate religion, idealism accepts the scientific
account and indeed mak(e§ room for religion. It holds that
moral and religious values are part and parcel of the world
of nature. It gives men the assurance that mind and values
are structurally part of the world. Thus, men can feel at
home and live confidently in the world.
186
CHAPTER 19
MATERIALISM IN SCIENCE
Materialism is the philosophical doctrine that all is
matter or reducible to matter. There are .basically two
versions of materialism, namely, hard or rigid materialism
and soft materialism. Hard materialism holds'that mind
does not really exist, only matter, while soft materialism
holds that though mind exists, its existence depends on
matter the same way a shadow of a person depends on the
person.
Strict materialism, which is also called materialistic
naturalism, holds that nature and the physical world are one
and the same. And by the physical world is meant “the
collection of facts, events, and things that have space, time,
and motion as their sufficient and fundamental defining
characteristics. Nature is the sum of all events and things
that are quantitatively measurable” (Randall & Buehler
195). Thus, in defining nature, materialism holds that what
is natural or real is material or physical in character,
irrespective of the way it may appear to us.
In trying to interpret the world, a philosopher is
confronted with its diversity. There are gigantic celestial
bodies and planets, including the habitable earth, and there
are also minute, invisible particles in our world - molecules,
atoms and elementary particles. A vast number of animate
beings and inanimate beings such as mountains, the land
and vast expanses of water bodies surround us. Man builds
houses and lives in them, uses buses, trains, ships and
aircrafts to move from place to place, which he has
designed with his hands. But he also sees objects around
him, which have been there before he surface4 on the earth.
The important question is - Is there a unity in the midst of
187
diversity? Or, is the universe a cosmos or chaos? Better
still, are there universal laws, which bind the world into a
single whole?
At first, the idea about the existence of universal laws
in the world was just a matter of conjecture. The early
materialists of ancient Greece made some crude attempts to
discover these laws. Thales, the father of Greek
philosophy, hypothesized that water is the primary
foundation of the world; Anaximenes claimed it is air;
Anaximander claimed it is a combination of the basic
elements (water, air, fire and earth), which he called the
Aperion or ‘indeterminate boundless’; Heraclitus held that
the world is a unity because it reposes on a single base - fire,
which kindles in measure and extinguishes in measure. It
was Leucippus and Democritus who first formulated the
principles of materialism in the late 4th and early 5th century
B.C. Both philosophers theorized that the single primary
base of things were tiny, moving particles called atoms.
Thus, all things could be reduced by scientific analysis into
their material constituents. For them, all that exist in reality
are atoms and void (i.e. empty space). Every other thing is
just the product of a subjective, human way of viewing
things. In the late 4'h and early 3rd century B.C. Epicurus
restated the atomic principles of Democritus, while in the 1st
century the Roman poet Lucretius restated the materialist
thesis that what we call mind and soul are ultimately
material. In the seventeenth century AD the English
materialist Thomas Hobbes stated that every part of the
universe is body, and that which is not body is no part of the
universe. For him, all that exists is body, and all that occurs
-is motion. Based on the scientific mood of the 19th century,
and the pronouncements of materialists in past centuries,
Ludwig Buchner summed up the main thesis of materialism
thus:
188
Thinking can and must be regarded as a special
mode of general natural motion, which is as
characteristic of the substance of the central
nervous elements as the motion of contraction
is of the muscle - substance, or the motion of
light is of the universal ether.... The words
mind, spirit, thought, sensibility, volition, life,
designate no entities and no things real, but
only properties, capacities, actions of living
substance, or results of entities, which are
v based upon the material form of existence
(Randall & Buehler 197)
Although there are variations in the views of
materialists, all materialists share some common beliefs.
These include the following:
1. Everything is made of matter (energy) or is reducible
to it.
2. Matter is eternal. In other words, matter has no
beginning and no end.
3. There is neither a Creator nor a Maker of the world.
The world is self - explanatory or self - expressive.
4. Humans are mortal. There is no soul separate from
the body. In fact, what we call soul or mind is just a
chemical reaction in the brain. When matter
disintegrates at the death of the body, the soul or
mind is also destroyed.
5. Humans are not unique. Human beings differ from
the lower animals not in kind but only in degree.
Although each of these tenets is.subject to standard
criticisms, we will not go into that here.
Materialism in Science
In order to fully grasp the impact of materialism on
science, it will be necessary to restate the main thesis of
189
i
materialism, and that is, that all realities can be reduced to
material properties undergoing change of motion in space.
This implies first, that the objects of all the sciences -
biology, physics, chemistry, psychology, sociology,
economics, and others - are only causally connected
material phenomena so that all sciences can be subsumed
under the parent - discipline of mechanics. Second, what
we call mind and its activities are simply brain or nervous
processes. Third, What we call values, ideals or purposes
are simply subjective human tags for different physical
situations in which physical organisms find themselves.
Thus, all phenomena, whether physical, physiological or
social are simply disguised forms of a basic physical reality
and its causally changing relations (Randall & Buehler
202).
In contrast to the crude speculative atomism of the
early Greek materialists, modem materialists were inspired
by the general discoveries and theories of modem physical
science to show that a materialist account of all we know is
possible. Using as their premises the physics of Descartes,
the atomism of Descartes’ contemporary Gassendi and
subsequently the theories of Newton, the materialists tried
to explain all events in the universe in terms of
mathematically describable motions of extended, solid
features of the universe.
The initial appeal to the materialist theory came as a
result of the growing disenchantment about skepticism of
previous metaphysical theories and the rapid growth of the
physical sciences, especially physics and astronomy. The
emergence of the social sciences in the 18th century, the
advances in modem chemistry of the 19th century, and the
tremendous progress in biology and psychology in more
recent times have given greater authority to the materialist
190
i
in his belief that even if the task has not been fully achieved,
there is hope that it will soon be possible to explain all
events in physical terms and laws. Since Descartes’ day
materialists have tried to make good their assertion that all
living processes like digestion, growth, reproduction can be
accounted for in purely mechanical terms, and that mental
events can be given a similar explanation (Popkin Stroll
124).
In the field of biology, the bone of contention has
been between the mechanists and the vitalists. The
mechanists believe that since it is now possible to show that
the various processes of animals and plants can be
accounted for in physical and chemical terms, nothing stops
us from believing that it will soon be possible to do so with
all questions of biology. On the contrary, the vitalists
contend that it is the case that either we are constrained to
jettison materialist concepts and introduce certain other
concepts (e.g. life-force), which are irreducible to physical
and chemical notions, or that this will occur. For them, in
the absence of such non-materialists ideas, the attempt to
account for the information we already have about the'
behaviour of living things will be a practical impossibility.
In the field of psychology, the bone of contention is
between those who believe that a materialist science of
human behaviour is possible and those who believe that it is
not possible. Here, the value of each case will depend on
the direction to which the pendulum of future experimental
research will swing.
In the field of physics, as scientific theories move
further away from the simple Newtonian theory that holds
that science is capable of providing accurate accounts of the-
intimate secrets of nature to “a more empirical conception
of science as a hypothetical model of what the world may be
like, that suffices for predicting the future course of
191
experience, a materialism based on the development in
scientific research has become less attractive. Those who
base their theories about the fundamental character of the
world upon an interpretation of our scientific knowledge
have tended to adopt a positivistic or pragmatic, or less
materialistic form of naturalist theory, than the classical
forms of materialism” (Popkin and Stroll 125)
193
CHAPTER 20
PRAGMATISM IN SCIENCE
Although pragmatism is a contemporary movement
in philosophy, its roots can be traced to the early Greek
philosophers. The Ionian thinkers such as Thales,
Heraclitus, Parmenides and Democritus brought empirical
considerations to bear on man’s speculation about the
world. The sophist, Protagoras, defined knowledge in
terms of sense perception and reflected that man is the
measure of all things. During the modern period, this mode
of thought was re-emphasized in the empiricist philosophy
of Bacon, Locke, Hume and Berkeley. Bacon in particular
introduced inductive logic to the scientific method. In the
19"' century, Auguste Comte introduced positivistic
•thinking, tracing the evolution of human thought from its
theological and metaphysical stages to its positive stage
characterized by the systematic methodology of science.
Modem pragmatism developed in the 19,h century as
a protest against the barren and useless metaphysics of that
time. Pragmatism originated in the United States of
America and received its principal formulations in the
hands of American philosophers such as Charles S. Peirce,
William James, John Dewey and Mead. Peirce is regarded
as the father of modern pragmatism because he directly or
indirectly influenced the others.
What is Pragmatism?
Pragmatism is essentially a method of solving
intellectual problems. It holds that theorizing should have
194
practical results and truth could be of tremendous utility in
solving intellectual problems of all kinds and in fostering
social progress. James emphasized the case-value of ideas
and theories, that is, their usefulness’in solving problems
and overcoming difficulties. For him, ideas, theories and
thinking are instruments employed in the practical business
of solving the problems we experience in our daily life.. For
Peirce, the meaning of an idea consists in putting the-idea
into practice in the objective world of activities and,
whatever its consequences prove to be. Contrary to the
traditional philosophical view that truth is a property
independent of human experience, Peirce and James
asserted that an idea is true if it works. Both of them agreed
that once an idea is tested in the world of affairs? it’s
meaning could be depended upon. Unlike Peirce and
James, who believed that once ideas are tested they have a
degree of permanence, Dewey regarded truth as relativistic.
Dewey held that the universe is in a state of perpetual flux,
so that there is no ultimate truth or reality. For him, reality
is born out of man’s experience of the world and, hence,
when there is a change in his experience of the world,
reality also changes.
195
1. The Pragmatic Conception of Truth
The pragmatists shared in the general apathy of
Americans towards theoretical activity that has no cash
value. By cash-value they meant the use to which ideas
could be put. Whether a theory is believed to be true or false
is irrelevant, what is important is whether it affects one’s
actions. Theories are mere instruments of solving
problems in practical living, and their success is appraised
in terms of performing this function. Thus, a theory is true
if and only if it works, it is useful, it satisfies us, or it solves
one’s problems. In testing a theory, a scientist designs an
experiment that determines whether the theory works under
specified conditions. The theory can only be true if the
experiment is successful. Truth is what works in practice
now. Ideas remain true as long as they work, and false as
long as they fail to work (Nenty 9). According to Peirce,
truth is the consequence of the experimental method, which
is agreed upon by the scientific community. For James,
truth is determined by consequences. A statement is true if
it meets the criterion of practical test. For Dewey, truth is
‘warranted assertibility’. Truth is what happens to an idea
when it is warranted or verified.
2. Peirce’s Experimentalism
Peirce’s pragmatism consciously uses the method of
science as its model in formulating the rule of significance
for terms in general. For Peirce, to define terms
experimentally is to employ a means by which meanings
can be communicated without ambiguity. For instance, if
one claims that he does not understand the meaning of a
word, all we need to do is to explain the experimental
conditions which define the word. When this is done, we
196
have established a standard of agreement and of universal
understandability. Peirce believed that by this way, the
pragmatic rule helps us to achieve clarity. We can thus
begin to appreciate the merit of pragmatism if we can
imagine a situation where such words as ‘atomism’,
‘right’, and ‘equality’ are so clarified that it will be very
easy for us to identify the state of affairs they denote.
According to Peirce, all meaningful statements must
conform to the standard of scientific verifiability. For a
statement to satisfy this standard means that it can be
investigated by the scientific method. We may say, then,
that a factual statement is genuine or significant, if it is
possible to investigate its truth or falsity, that is, if it is
possible to collect or adduce evidence for it. Some
statements are directly verifiable, while others are
indirectly verifiable.
Pierce’s pragmatism is to show that the meaning of a
statement is in the sum of its verifiable consequences.
Following this, it is possible to have two statements
containing different words yet having the same meaning.
The reason is simply that they both have the same factual
consequences. Again, the only way to distinguish the
meaning of two opinions, which appear to be verbally
similar, is to show their consequences and observe closely
the different facts implicitly referred to by each of them.
The main aim of Peirce’s pragmatism was basically to
show us the way out of intellectual verbalism by providing
objective criteria of distinction.
For Peirce, when we say that a statement is
scientifically or experimentally verifiable, we can give this
expression a narrow or a broad meaning. It must be stated
197
that Peirce rejected a narrow or sensationalistic conception
set up as standard for the broad canons of science. The
logical positivists, for instance, expressed distrust for
indirect verification and restricted ‘experience’ to sense
experience. But, again, we must guard against the
temptation of narrowing down Peirce’s pragmatism in such
a way as to think that he used the terms ‘experiment’ and
‘experience’ to refer to physical experiment or physical
experience alone. Such narrow interpretation is bound to
render unverifiable any theory that is speculative in nature.
Peirce’s idea of experiment gives room for verification of
such theories. For Randall and Buehler,
The complexity and difficulty of the process is
immeasurably greater but is of essentially the
same kind. In a given science, say psychology,
the facts verifying psychological theories
' would be specific instances of behaviour by
the individual organism. In a general theory of
civilization, on the other hand, the verifying
facts would include not merely these but
psychologically accepted theories as well, or a
combination of facts and hypotheses of
psychology and physics and biology, and in
general the entire set of scientific results. The
kind of facts serving as evidence for
speculative philosophic theories is thus of a far
broader and more complex character than that
serving as evidence within a given science.
Yet the process of verification may be called
“scientific”, for while we are no longer
concerned with verification in a special
198
science, we can employ the scientific method.
The pragmatic standard of Peirce thus requires
that all hypotheses purporting to be about fact
be verifiable, but avoid a narrow conception of
verifiability (131).
Peirce’s experimentalism exhibits a marked
difference from Kantianism and positivism both of which
rejected as unintelligible the unknowable supersensible
reality. Unlike these two philosophies,- Peirce’s
experimentalism introduced the factor of meaning in the
analysis of knowledge, and a more exact conception of
experience and scientific method. As opposed to
positivism, which lumped together all speculative theories
and regarded them as metaphysical, experimentalism
discriminated speculative theories as verifiable or
unverifiable. Again, it differs from positivism “in its more
liberal interpretation of science and its avoidance of
legislation on scientific method; and its substitution of a
specific criterion of the intelligibility of theories as
opposed to the vague positivist criterion of their
“usefulness” or “fruitfulness” (Randall and Buehler 132).
3. James’ Practicalism
Although James initially set out to elaborate on the
pragmatism of Peirce, he (James) ended up formulating
something quite different. For James, pragmatism is a
manifestation of the empiricist attitude, which can be
interpreted in the following way. The pragmatist
Turns away from abstraction and insufficiency,
from verbal solutions, from bad a priori
reasons, from fixed principles, closed systems,
and pretended absolutes and origins. He turns
199
towards concreteness and adequacy, towards
facts, towards action and towards power. That
makes the empiricist temper regnant and the
rationalist temper sincerely given up. It
means the open air and possibilities of nature,
as against dogma, artificiality, and the
presence of finality in truth” (cited in Randall
and Buehler 133).
For James, truth is what happens to an idea. After
examining the traditional theories of truth and finding that
they virtually took the opposite view, namely, that truth is a
fixed or a static relation, James took exception by arguing
that truth must be the cash-value of an idea. Something is
true if it can provide guides for practical behaviour. An
idea is made true by events. An idea is true if it has
satisfactory consequences. Truth is relative and it grows.
Ideas, doctrines and theories are not just answers to riddles
but instruments to help meet life situations. The only
satisfactory criterion of truth of a theory is that, it suits
human purpose and it brings about beneficial results. Thus,
lor James the key words in the pragmatic conception of
truth are workability, satisfactions, results and
consequences.
The essential point of difference between James’
practicalism and Peirce’s experimentalism is that the term
‘practical’ as used-by James has a looser and more popular
meaning than it has for Peirce. The general pragmatic view
that a statement is significant if it has practical
consequences may mean two things, namely, (I) that it has
consequences capable of empirical or experimental
investigation, and (ii) that belief in the statement can serve
200
as a guide to human behaviour. Whereas the first meaning
refers to the standard of Peirce, the second refers to that
James.
For Peirce, the terms we employ should be defined
by means of a scientific procedure with which they are
associated, while James urged that what really matters is
that the terms should be capable of influencing our
behaviour. On Peirce’s principle, to speak cf “purpose” or
“design” in the universe, or of “God”, is to speak of nothing '
significant unless these terms are capable of being
experimentally defined in accordance with scientific
standards. For James, however, it will appear that such
terms need not be thus defined in order to be
“pragmatically” significant” (Randall and Buehler 134).
Thus, for James, when we are faced with a speculative
problem, say that of rationalism versus empiricism, the
difference in meaning of these two epistemological
theories is not determined by their experimental
consequences but by the different effects they have on
human conduct and experience.
4. Dewey’s Instrumentalism
For Dewey and many of his followers, the term
‘instrumentalism’ is preferred to pragmatism, though both
are used interchangeably. Dewey tells us that men have. •
applied two methods in escaping danger and obtaining ’.
security. One is to appease the powers around them
through rites, rituals, sacrifices and prayers, while the other
is to design tools to control the forces of nature to man’s ,
benefit. The latter is the way of science, technology and the
arts, and this is the one approved by Dewey. The purpose of
philosophy, according to Dewey, is to better man’s life here
201
and now. Thus, philosophy’s interest has shifted from
traditional metaphysical problems, to the methods and
techniques for scientific and social progress. The method
is that of experimental inquiry guided by empirical research
in the sphere of values.
The key word in instrumentalism is experience.
Experience, on this view, is the whole process of interaction
of living organism with its social and physical
environment. The present world is the world of
experience. We should strive to understand it and then try
to construct a society in which man can freely express his
freedom and intelligence.
Dewey believed that man lives in an unfinished
world. This can best be understood by examining the three
aspects of Dewey’s instrumentalism. The first is the notion
of lemporalism, which holds that since there is real
movement and progress in time, men should no longer hold
a spectator view of reality. Our knowledge is not just a
mirror of the world but also a means of reshaping it. The
second is the notion of futurism. This urges us to look to the
future and not the past because the future promises to be
novel. The third is meliorism - the view that human efforts
can transform the world and make it a better and safer place
to live in.
Finally, an important aspect of Dewey’s philosophy
is the instrumental theory of ideas. For him, thinking is a
biological process because it has to do with the adjustments
between an organism and its environment. All thinking is
part of the protective equipment of the human race in its
struggle for existence. Thinking arises out of problematic
situations and man’s reasoning in response to these
202
situations follows a certain pattern. The pattern takes the
following steps:
1. A problem or difficulty to be overcome presents
itself.
2. The perplexity caused by the problem stimulates
thought, leading to the proposal of solutions to the
problem.
3. These solutions are tested in practice.
4. Finally, one solution sticks out as the most effective
and hence is approved,for future use. _
This shows that all learning is an adaptation of the
organism to its environment by means of problem solving.
Dewey thus “insisted on the direction of thinking and
theorizing towards the solution of practical and social
problems, and went on to link his^philosophy with the
democratic ideal in which individual members of society
cooperate to realize the full potentialities of each, thus
bringing about mutual progress and general social advance
(Sharma and Hyland 59).
CHAPTER 21
DETERMINISM IN SCIENCE
What is Determinism?
Determinism is the general philosophical thesis that
everything that happens is determined. In other words,
A everything that happens is caused and nothing happens by
chance. Laws of nature govern all events. These laws are
*
not the type passed by a legislature; rather they are
statements of conditions under which certain events or
effects inevitably occur. Likewise there are conditions that-*
determine the conditions of that effect, conditions that
determine those conditions, and so on backwards ad
infinitum (Geisler & Feinberg 195).
There have been many versions of determinism in
the history of philosophy, some of which overlap
considerably. J. I. Omoregbe has identified five versions or
theories of determinism in the following order.
1. Metaphysical Determinism
'This is the view that the whole universe is an
interrelated whole or system in which everything is
connected with another thing. A version of this is
pantheistic determinism, the view that God, man and the
universe are ultimately one and the same thing, and that all
actions and events are self-manifestations of God.
2. Psychological Determinism s
This is the view that all our actions are determined by
certain instinctive drives or impulses (mostly sexual in
nature), some of which were previously inhibited but
204
eventually found outlets in various ways and manifest
through our actions.
3 Theological Determinism
This is the view that God determined in advance the
way every man will live and all that he will do in life? He
has determined or predestined in advance those to go to
heaven and those to go to hell.
4. Fatalism
This is the view that what happens is inevitable,
regardless of what we do or do not do.
5. Economic Determinism
This is a Marxist theory, which holds that human
activities in any society are determined by the economic
situation of the society (39 - 42)
Taylor adds three more versions to the ones given by
Omoregbe. They are: ethical determinism, logical
determinism and physical determinism (359-371). '
6. Ethical Determinism
' This is the view that all man’s actions are determined
by the ‘Summum bonunT or ‘highest good ’.
7. Logical Determinism
This is the view that a given event must either occur
or not occur. Whichever happens, the prediction that it
would happen will turn out to be correct, whether or not we
knew it. Therefore, since one statement about the apparent
future alternatives is already true, nothing we can do will
alter matters (Lacey 71).
8. Physical Determinism
This is the view that eternal and inviolable laws of
nature determine all events and human actions. Since this
last version is the most scientific of all the versions, and
205
since our topic is centred on determinism in Science, we
shall devote the remaining part of this discussion to it. We
shall consider in turn its history, tenets, problems and the
resolution of the problem.
The theory of physical determinism was inspired by
development of the natural sciences, particularly in the
15th, 17th and 18th centuries. It was discovered that the
motions of the heavenly bodies did not only follow a
regular pattern but also obeyed certain laws, which could
be expressed with mathematical accuracy. Gradually, the
old approach to the study of nature, which was basically
speculative and profusely Aristotelian, began to give way
to observation, experimentation and the search for kaws.
Philosophers were compelled to revise the content of the
deterministic theories, which they were accustomed to.
They more or less ceased to think of human actions and
events as determined by moral considerations (ethical
determinism) or by an eternal and immutable God
(theological determinism) and began to think of them as
determined by eternal and inviolable laws of nature
(physical determinism). Much earlier the atomists
(Leucippus and Democritus), the Epicureans and Stoics
had somewhat held this view, though their approach was
highly philosophical and speculative.
A central presupposition of the emerging science
was the idea of universal causation - the belief that every
event has an antecedent cause and that there are no
uncaused events. Furthermore, it w as assumed that events
occur in orderly patterns, which makes the formulation of
causal or natural laws possible. On the basis of these laws
and knowledge of the actual causes at work in a situation, it
206
is possible to predict with great exactness what will occur.
Concerning events about which such prediction cannot be
made presently, there is in principle no reason why we
could not. Our lack of knowledge about both the laws and
the present causes are our only hindrances. As we learn
more about the causes of such events and develop methods
to detect when these causes are at work, then we will be able
to predict both the time and severity of their occurrence.
These theories about universal causation and total
predictability have been traditionally called ‘determinism’
(Geisler & Feinberg 194)
The question that follows is: if physical determinism
oruniversal causation is the case, it would inevitably follow
that man’s behaviour is causally determined and
predictable, since man is also an object in the real world.
How, then, do we account for freedom and moral
responsibility? Physical determinism seems to be in
conflict with free will.
There have been philosophers who have argued that
there is no real conflict between physical determinism and
free - will. Thomas Hobbes belongs to this group of
philosophers. Hobbes opined that physical determinism is
consistent with free - will or human liberty. He defined
liberty as simply the absence of external constraints or
impediments and, hence as something which even
inanimate objects can possess. It is Hobbes’ own
contention that any unobstructed moving body can be
considered free. For instance, water naturally flows
downward and freely, though it is not free to ascend or flow
across the riverbed.
As can be seen, Hobbes’ theory represents a
substantial departure from some of his predecessors. For
instance, unlike the Epicureans who assumed that
behaviour that is physically determined is unfree, Hobbes
claimed that although all human behaviour is physically
determined and necessitated, man is still to be held
responsible for his actions. For Hobbes, a voluntary act is
simply one that is caused by an act of will. It is rendered no
less voluntary to assert that acts of will are caused.
Generations of philosophers while debunking
Hobbes’ materialism have however toed his line in this
conception. A good example is Arthur Schopenhauer.
Schopenhauer affirms Hobbes’ position, giving the same
reason Hobbes gave. In the 20th century, the logical
positivists Moritz Schlick and A. J. Ayer (and in fact many
others) have argued in line with Hobbes that freedom is not
contradicted by causation but by constraint. These ideas
are significant because they provide a means of reconciling
the apparent conflict between determinism and free - will.
Specifically, they have been able to show that there is really
no problem of free will.
Conclusion
Like Hobbes and his supporters, I strongly believe
and hold that determinism and freedom are compatible.
My reason is that before an action is done there are always
some conditions sufficient to cause or determine that
action, and yet that action can be free. In other words, there
are always contingently sufficient antecedent conditions
before a person decides to act in one-way and not another.
PART FIVE
SOME PHILOSOPHIES/
METHODS OF SCIENCE
CHAPTER 22
POSITIVIST METHODOLOGY OF SCIENCE
Social Positivism:
Prominent among the many social positivists is
Auguste Comte, a French philosopher who is said to have
been the first to coin the word ‘positivism’ to designate his
own system of philosophy. But the fact is that Comte’s
adoption of positivism was due largely to the scientific or
positivistic spirit or attitude of the age, already discussed
above. The attitude was derived from the belief that
adequate knowledge of the world could only be achieved
through the scientific method of carrying out empirical
investigation of reality and subjecting theories derived
from such investigation to empirical verification. D. P.
Johnson in his Sociological theory: Classical Founders
and Contemporary Perspectives writes:
Although Comte coined the term “positivism”,
the ideas that this word conveys were not
original with him. The positivist beliefs that
society was part of nature and that empirical
methods of investigation could be used to
discover its laws were widespread in Comte’s
intellectual climate” (77).
Following this method, metaphysical knowledge
211
was regarded as invalid. The scientific mood of the age
must have influenced Comte to suggest the initial rigor of
positivism when he stated that any proposition that is not
reducible to a simple enunciation of facts, particular or
general, does not make any sense. Comte writes:
All investigation into the nature of beings,
and their first and final causes, must always
be absolute; whereas the study of the laws of
phenomena must be relative, since ii supposes
a continuous progress of speculation subject
to gradual improvement of observation,
without the precise reality beiiig ever fully
disclosed; so that the relative character of
scientific conceptions is inseparable from the
true idea of natural laws... (452).
This was the attitude Comte brought to the study of
social life and religion. In the end, he created a new science
of society (which he called sociology) by which the whole
activities of man could be explained, using scientific
principles. His assumption was that if science had
succeeded in dealing with physical reality, the knowledge
derived from science and dogmas associated with the
theological and metaphysical stages of development,
political order needed to work out a science of society,
which he (Comte) did not find available and which he,
therefore set out to create, calling it ‘sociology’. For him,
sociology is the queen of all sciences; the summit of
knowledge, for it makes use of all previous information and
coordinates it for the sake of a peaceful and orderly society.
It was the aim of Comte to provide a comprehensive
analysis of the underlying philosophical and
(212
methodological unity between the so-called natural science
and social science (Stumpf344 - 345).
In siim, all social positivists (Auguste Comte,
Jeremy Bentham, James Mill and John Stuart Mill) agreed
that positivism must be the basis of ethics, religion,
politics, public education, and in short, the perfect social
reform to which progress based on science must lead. For
them, social positivism would seek to use the methods and
findings of science to promote a more just social
organization (Essiet 25).
Evolutionary Positivism:
Prominent among the founders of this movement are
Herbert Spencer, Ernest Haeckel (the German
philosopher), Cesare Lambroso (the founder of the
positivist school of penal law), and Wilhelm Wundt (the
founder of the first laboratory of experimental
psychology). Evolutionary positivism has left as a legacy
to contemporary philosophy the idea of a universal,
unilinear, continuous, necessary, and necessarily
progressive evolution. This idea of a universal evolution is
central to the philosophies of Charles Sanders Peirce,
William James, John Dewey, George Santayana, Samuel
Alexander and Alfred North Whitehead (Essiet 26 - 27). A
mention must be made of Charles Darwin who is one of the
immediate forefathers of the doctrine of biological
evolution.
From the foregoing, it can be seen that evolutionary
positivism resembles social positivism in a certain respect
and is different from it in a certain respect. Both are centred
on man and are inspired by faith in progress based on
213
science. However, they are dissimilar because while
evolutionary positivism is based on nature, which is the
concern of physics and biology, social positivism is based
on society or history.
Critical Positivism:
This version of positivism is also known as empirio-
criticism. It emerged during the last decade of the 19lh
century through the works of Ernest Mach and Richard A.
Avenarius. Both scholars admitted that there is no real
difference between the realms of the physical and psychical
because a thing is both a set of sensations and the thought of
it. Although a thing is a set of sensations, it is the thought of
the thing that enables us to talk of it as being ‘perceived’ or
‘represented’. Avenarius and Mach believed that science
(and knowledge in general) is an instrument for
confronting and reacting to the infinite mass of sensations
and its end is the progressive adaptations of the human
organism to its environment. Following this, scientific law
is to be seen as a description, not a prescription. Scientific
laws have only logical necessity, not physical necessity.
This necessity lies in the world of conceptions and is
merely unconsciously transferred to the world of
perceptions (Essiet 25).
Logical Positivism:
The movement called ‘logical positivism’ is the
immediate offspring of critical positivism. A. E. Blumberg
and H. Feigl to designate a set of philosophical ideas
postulated by members of the movement who styled
themselves the “Vienna Circle” coined the term ‘logical
214
positivism’ in 1931. Logical positivism “is also referred to
as ‘logical empiricism’, ‘consistent empiricism’ and
scientific empiricism. It is often, but misleadingly,
extended to include the ‘analytical’ or ‘ordinary language’
philosophies developed at Cambridge and Oxford” (Essiet
25).
Members of the group included Moritz Schlick,
Hans Hahn, Otto Neurath, Philipp Frank and Friedrich
Waismann, Edgar Zilsei, Bela Von. Juhos, Felix Kaufmann,
Herbert Feigl, Victor Kraft, Karl Menger, and Kurt Godel.
They were either scientists, or mathematicians or
philosophers. Because many of them had scientific
orientation, their approach was rigorously empirical or
scientific. It was their view that the success and growth of
science was- due largely to the restriction of the scientific
endeavour to the sphere of experience or matters of fact.
In their discussion of the issue of how laws and
theories are formulated, the logical positivists adopted the
verification principle, according to which, a proposition is
meaningful, if it can be verified directly or is capable of
being verified in future experience. This principle was to
serve a dual purpose. Firstly, it was to serve as a criterion of
demarcation between science and non-science or pseudo
science. Secondly, it was to enhance the unity of science
and in the process rid science of all metaphysical notions.
In pursuance of these goals, the positivists ended up
debunking metaphysical, epistemological ethical
assertions as meaningless. According to them, these
assertions do not live up to the condition of empirical
verifiability; only claims of empirical sciences do.
The logical positivists identified hypotheses and
215
propositions, as two dimensions of verificationism. A
hypothesis is a proposed law connecting various
observations or many different immediate experiences. A
hypothesis is potentially testable or verifiable, and when it
is eventually verified it becomes a law. Each record of an
observation is a proposition. A hypothesis consists of
many propositions, which are many verifications of it.
Hypotheses are confirmed only by an appeal to the
verifying propositions. This method of basing general
statements or laws on accumulated verifying propositions
is known as induction and is seen by the logical positivists
as the hallmark of science.
Conclusion
The meeting point of all the different strands of
positivism examined above is the belief that enquiry should
be confined to the sphere of what can be firmly established
and, that is, what is immediately given to the senses.
Following this, metaphysics and theology are to be counted
as meaningless and nonsensical; much of ethics and
aesthetics is, as much as possible, assimilated to sciences
like psychology, while what is left of them is usually
categorized as emotive, evaluative or prescriptive. They
sometimes give room for verifiability in principle, not in
practice. But all positivists face the same internal
difficulties, some of which are: the possibility of translating
a person’s internal experience into a statement about a
physical object and vice-versa without falling into the trap
of solipsism; the problem of whether to accept either
physicalism (the view that every statement including
psychological ones can be translated into physicalist
216
statements) or the physicalist language, or reject both; the
problem as to whether laws which are the basis of scientific
prediction can be considered as meaningful in view of the
fact that my present experience or experiment cannot
authoritatively and conclusively tell us anything about the
future; the question as to why sense -experience should be
the criterion of meaning; and the fact that in their own way
positivists can be and are metaphysicians too - they can and
do investigate and try to find answers to genuinely
ontological questions.
217
CHAPTER 23
Law
In the empirical sciences, the word Taw’ is used in
terms of Taw of nature’. Laws of nature or scientific laws
are generalizations. They are descriptive and not
prescriptive. In other words, they describe how nature
works and do not prescribe anything. For instance,
Kepler’s law« of planetary motion only describe how
planets actually do move, they do not prescribe how planets
should move, and the penalties they would suffer if they
fail. Laws in this sense describe certain uniformities in
nature. These uniformities exist whether or not human
beings are there to describe them. This is the reason it is
sometimes said that Taws are discovered, not made’. But
218
this is not to say that the formulation of these uniformities is
not the work of men. Indeed, it is the work of men.
A statement expressing a scientific law differs from a
singular empirical statement (i.e. a statement expressing a
fact) in the sense that while the truth of the latter can be
tested by an observation of the world, the truth of the former
cannot be tested by an observation of the world. A scientific
law is a true universal empirical proposition. That means
that it applies to all members of a given class without
exception. For example, the proposition ‘All iron rusts
when exposed to oxygen’ is a true universal empirical
proposition. But the proposition ‘This piece of iron rusts’ is
simply a statement of fact.
Theory
A theory may be defined as a unified system of laws
or hypotheses, with explanatory force. Scientific theories
are normally constructed to explain laws of nature.
Although it is sometimes difficult to make a clear-cut
distinction between a law and a theory, it is clear that while
it is the case that scientific law is discovered, it is the case
that scientific theories are constructed or devised. One
important feature of a scientific theory is that it normally
contains a term that denotes an unobservable entity. For
example, the proposition ‘There are protons and electrons',
is a theory. The reason we call this proposition a theory is
that evidence about the existence of protons and electrons is
unavoidably inconclusive. Indeed, in all of empirical
sciences, the belief in the ‘smallest particles of matter’ is
the most thoroughly worked out theory.
219
Having distinguished between the fact, law and
theory, we shall now attempt to provide an answer to the
question: How, if at all, are fact, law and theory related?
The principal task of science is to discover facts.
But science does not go about the business of collecting
facts haphazardly. The scientist searches for more general
truths of which isolated facts are mere instances. Not only
are the isolate facts instances of these more general truths,
they also constitute the evidence for these truths. Isolated
particular facts are discoverable by direct observation of
the world. For example, the proposition ‘A particular
released object falls’ and the proposition ‘This piece of iron
rusts’ are matters of fact open to direct observation. But the
scientist does not only record such phenomena, he
formulates general laws, which state the pattern of such
occurrences. But he does not just stop there. Just as he is
challenged by particular facts to discover their lawful
connections, so also he is challenged by a plurality of
general laws to try to discover a still more general principle
of which the several laws are special cases. The attempt to
seek to unify and explain the systematic relationship
between laws leads the scientist to devise theories.
From the foregoing, we can see that while particular
facts lead the scientist to discover scientific laws, the need
to unify and explain scientific laws leads the scientist to
construct or devise theories. Thus, while scientific laws
unify and explain facts, theories are devised to unify and
explain both laws and facts.
220
Inductivism
How are scientific laws arrived at? According to
some scientists, science is principally concerned with
establishing general laws. These general laws are derived
rigorously from a great number of particular observations
or facts of experience. For instance, if we represent the
various facts that have been established as r, s, t, u, and let T,
stand for the theory (or general law) derived from them, the
supposed relationship between the facts and the theory ma>
be put schematically thus:
r is a fact
s is a fact
t is a fact
u is a fact
Therefore, T is a valid theory.
The above gives us a true picture of what scientific
knowledge is and what scientists do. Specifically, it shows
that science is not based on speculative imaginations, but
on what we can observe (i.e what we can see, touch, hear,
etc). Thus, it shows that “Scientific Knowledge is reliable
knowledge because it is objectively proven knowledge”
(Chalmers 1). This conception of how scientific laws or
theories are arrived at is called inductivism. This popular
conception of science first gained currency during the great
scientific revolution of the 17th century, which was brought
about by the pioneering works of scientists such as Galileo
and Newton. Francis Bacon was obviously adumbrating
the scientific attitude of many of his contemporaries when
he said that in order to understand nature we must consult
the “textbook” of nature and the treatises of ancient
philosophers such as Aristotle. Encouraged by the
221
successes of Galileo’s experiments, Bacon and his
colleagues dismissed as mistaken the view of the medieval
natural philosophers that the Holy Bible and Aristotle’s
writings constituted the chief sources of scientific
knowledge, and argued that the source of reliable
knowledge is experience. J. J. Davis seemed to have lent
weight to this as he is quoted by Chalmers to have said that
“Science is a structure built on facts”[ 1 ]
Naive inductivism is an attempt to formalize the
picture of science given above. According to naive
inductivism, under normal conditions the scientific
observer unprejudicially records what he observes by
means of his senses. The statements he arrived at as a result
of his observation are called observation statements or
singular statements. A singular statement is a statement
that refers to a particular occurrence at a particular place at
a particular point in time. A good example is ‘That stick,
half immersed in water, appears bent’.
Apart from singular statements, which can be said to
be particular, there are also general statements. General
statements are statements that make claims about the
behaviour or properties of some aspects of the universe.
Unlike singular statements which refer to particular
occurrences or state-of -affairs, general statements report
about all events of a particular kind at all places and at all
times. Consider the example, ‘All planets move in ellipses
around the sun’. This statement is a general statement
because it claims that all planets, irrespective of where they
are situated, will always move around the sun. Because of
their generality, general statements constitute the laws and
theories, which constitute scientific knowledge and are
also called universal statements.
222
Having drawn a distinction between singular
statements (i.e. statements of observation or experience)
and general statements (i.e. universal statements), it
becomes pertinent to ask: What makes it possible for the
inductivist to infer a general statement from singular
statements? In other words, what makes it possible for the
inductivist to generalize from a finite number of
observation statements to a universal law or theory?
The inductivist might answer this question by saying
that provided the number of observations are repeated
under a wide variety of conditions, and provided no
accepted observation statement conflicts with the derived
universal law or theory, it is legitimate to infer a universal
law or theory from a limited list of statements. Referring to
heated metals, we can legitimately draw the universal law
that ‘All metals expand when heated’.
It is quite obvious that when we are asked why we
believe that the sun will rise tomorrow or in the future, we
will naturally answer, “Because it has always risen in the
past.” But if we are further challenged as to why we firmly
believe that it will rise tomorrow or in the future, we may
appeal to the laws of motion to buttress our claim. We
know that the earth is a body that rotates freely and that it
can only cease to rotate if it is interfered with by another
body. But we know that nothing will interfere with the
rotation of the earth between now and tomorrow. And so
we feel we are justified in saying that the sun will rise
tomorrow because sunrise is a fulfillment of the laws of
motion and experience or the past teaches us that the laws of
motion will continue to operate as they have operated until
now.
223
This kind of reasoning discussed so far is called
inductive reasoning. Inductive reasoning involves moving
from a limited number of observation statements to the
justification of a universal statement and the process is
called induction. Science, for the naive inductivist, is
based on the principle of induction. Chalmers states the
principle of induction as: “If a large number of As have
been observed under a wide variety of conditions, and if all
these observed A’s without exception possessed the
property B, then all A’s have the property B” [5]. The naive
inductivist thinks of scientific knowledge as a building
resting on the secure basis provided by observation, a
position hotly criticized by Popper. To quote Chalmers in
some details:
As the number of facts established by
observation and experiments grows, and as the
facts become more refined and esoteric due to
improvements in our observational and
experimental skills, so more and more laws
and theories of ever more generality and scope
are constructed by careful inductive reasoning.
The growth of science is continuous, ever
onward and upward as the fund of
observational data is increased [5]
Inductive and Deductive Reasoning
Inductive reasoning is often contrasted with
deductive reasoning. In short, while induction is regarded
as the hallmark of science, deduction is regarded as the
hallmark of Logic. Both modes of reasoning proceed by
means of rigorous arguments. Thus, we sometimes speak of
inductive arguments and deductive arguments.
224
In inductive arguments, if the premises are known to
be true, then it is probable that the conclusion will be true.
Here we see that inductive reasoning does not hold that if
the premises of an argument are true, then its conclusion
must be true. It is as a result of this that inductive
arguments are not judged as valid or invalid, sound or
unsound. Of course, they can be appraised to the degree of
probability, which the premises provided for the
conclusion.
A deductive argument, on the other hand, is one in
which it is claimed that if the premises are true, it follows
that the conclusion must be true. For this reason, deductive
arguments are judged as valid or invalid, sound or unsound.
In a valid deductive argument, the premises and the
conclusion are so logically connected that it will be
impossible for the former to be tine and the latter false.
This does not however mean that we cannot have a valid
deductive argument, which has false premises. Indeed, we
can have a perfectly valid deductive argument with false
premises. A sound deductive argument is one which has
true premises and hence a true conclusion.
In inductive reasoning, we move from particular
assertions to general assertions and we know that the
inference of a general proposition from particular
assertions is never conclusive. On the other hand, in
deductive reasoning, we move from assertions about a
whole class of things to assertions about some of them. For
example, from assertions about all planets, we can move to
assertions about the planet earth. Briefly, we can say that
whereas we move from ‘some’ to ‘all’ in inductive
reasoning, we move from “all” to “some” in deductive
reasoning.
225
Advocates of the principle of induction hold the view
that a distinctive feature of scientific method is the use of
inductive reasoning. They claim that the inductive method
of scientific inquiry is superior to the deductive method
because it is integrally connected with the discovery of
scientific laws and theories. They buttress their claim by
saying that whereas the inductive method enables us to
make a leap from the finite data of observation to a law
covering all that are (i.e. known present) and all that will or
could be (i.e. predicted future), deductive method can never
advance to knowledge of the hitherto unobserved. Max
Black seemed to be in support of this when he said: “The so-
called ‘inductive leap’ (from ‘some’ to ‘any’ and ‘all’)
seems indispensable in science no less than in ordinary life”
(cited in Chalmers 5).
239
conjoined with, custom and habit. Popper observes that
this psychological fact can itself be described as a custom,
or habit and it will not be surprising to hear that this custom,
or habit must be explained as due to or conjoined with, a
custom or habit, though a different one. For Popper, it is
only when we realize that Hume used the words ‘custom’
and ‘habit’ to theorize about, rather than describe, the origin
of regular behaviour ascribed to frequent repetition that the
need to reformulate Hume’s psychological theory in a more
reformed way becomes obvious. We may thus reformulate
this theory by saying, to use the language of Popper, that
“like other habits, our habit of believing in laws is the
product of frequent repetition”(43).
Popper argues that even if Hume’s theory is
reformulated in such a revolutionary way, it is nevertheless
mistaken about the origin of habits and most importantly,
the character of those experiences we may describe as
believing in laws or expecting regularities. Popper says
that as a rule, habits do not originate in repetition. Habits
begin before repetition can play its part. For instance, the
habit of eating at certain hours begins before repetition
plays any part. Popper says that Kant was right to say that
our intellect imposes its laws upon nature, though he (Kant)
did not take cognizance of the fact that our intellect does fail
us in most cases in the attempt. Popper writes that: “The
regularities we try to impose are psychologically a priori,
but there is not the slightest reason to assume that they are a
priori valid, as Kant did” (Popper 22).
The need to try to impose regularities upon nature is
obviously inborn. We generally expect that our world
conform to our expectations. This, according to Popper,
would lead us to conclude that expectations may arise
before or without repetition. For Popper, repetition
presupposes similarity, and similarity presupposes a point
240
of view or a theory or an expectation. On the basis of this
claim, Popper dismissed Hume’s inductive theory of our
reformulation of beliefs as false. Popper concludes: “The
idea of induction by repetition must be due to an error - a
kind of optical illusion. In brief there is no such thing as
induction by repetition” (Popper 6-7)
Popper’s argument against Hume’s principle of
induction by repetition can be couched in the following
way: The cases that Hume had in mind can never be cases of
perfect sameness; at best they are cases of similarity. For
logical reasons, we can therefore say that there are
repetitions from a certain point of view, such as: “a system
of expectations, anticipations, assumptions, or interests -
before there can be any repetition; which point of view,
consequently cannot be merely the result of repetition”
(Popper 23). Hume, having dismissed induction as
logically invalid 'and rationally unjustifiable proposed a
non-inductive procedure for science without giving serious J
thought to it. Having pushed aside the logical principle of
induction, Hume struck a secret deal with commonsense by
cleverly introducing induction by repetition in the guise of
a psychological theory. Popper tries to turn the table upon-
this theory of Hume by saying that repetition - for us can be
best explained as the result of our propensity to expect
regularities and not vice-versa. He says that we do not wait
passively for repetition to impose regularities upon the
world. For him. without waiting for premises, we jump to
conclusions, though these may be discarded later if
falsified by observation.
Here we see that Popper is trying to stress the priority
of theories to observations. This runs contrary to the
traditional belief that observation precedes theory. For
241
Popper, scientific theories are not the product of
observations, they are bold conjectures to be tested by
observations with the aim of obtaining a decisive
refutation; hence science is conjectures and refutations^
Thus, for Popper, there is nothing like scientific certainty.
He summed up his devastating critique of science in his The
Open Society and Its Enemies when he wrote: “Thus the
belief in scientific certainty and in the authority of science
is just wishful thinking. Science is fallible, because science
is human” (375).
In the foregoing, we have limited our examination of
Popper’s critique of inductivism to his evaluation of
Hume’s discussion of induction. In the next chapter, we
examine Popper’s critical rationalist methodology of
science.
242
CHAPTER 24
CRITICAL RATIONALIST
METHODOLOGY
OF SCIENCE
(KARL POPPER & IMRE LAKATOS)
In this chapter, we explore the critical rationalist
methodology of science. Our analysis will be confined to
Karl Popper and Imre Lakatos.
243
The standards of rationality put forth by the
Popperian school are simply standards of criticism. Paul
feyerabend has summarized these standards as follows:
rational discussion consists in the attempt to criticize, and
not in the attempt to pfove or make probable. Every step
that protects a view from criticism, that makes it safe or
‘well-founded’, is a step away frOitbtetionality. Every step
that makes it more vulnerable is welcome. In addition, it is
recommended that w£ abandon ideas which have been
found wanting and forbid to retain them in the face of strong
and successful criticism. We are to develop our ideas so
that they can be criticized or attacked felentlessly. We
should not try to protect them, but exhibittneir weak points.
Finally, we are to eliminate them when sucll weak points
have become noticeable (173).
What prompted Popper to adopt the critical
rationalist method of science? In a nutshell, the turning
point in Popper’s career was the introduction to the new
physics by Einstein. In 1919, Popper attended a lecture by
Einstein in Vienna, where, according to him, he was dazed
by Einstein’s introduction to the new physics. As if to
buttress his faith in Einstein, Einstein’s eclipse predictions
were tested in May of the same year and were found to be
successful. These tests ushered in a new theory of
gravitation and. of course, a new cosmology. What made
Einstein's new physics peculiar was that it was a real
improvement on Newton’s, in fact, a better approximation
to the truth. Popper was so impressed by this development
that he now considered Einstein as the most dominant
influence on his thinking. Einstein’s, new discoveries
explained all of Newton’s and even went beyond Newton’s.
244
As Popper claimed, what impressed him most was
Einstein’s declaration that he would regard his general
theory of rel^ivity as untenable if it failed crucial tests.
Popper saw in this a critical attitude totally different from
the dogmatic attitude of Marx, Freud and Adler. He came
to realize that Marx’s theory of history, Freud’s
psychoanalysis and Adler’s individual psychology failed to
make precisely formulated predictions that could be
subjected to direct (or indirect] empirical test.
Under the influence of Einstein, Popper came to the
conclusion that falsifiability or refutability is the criterion
of the scientific status of a theory. In other words, it is the
demarcating line between what is and what is not science.
Thus, the hallmark of the scientific status of a theory is that
empirical findings, which would refute it, are logically
possible. Any such theory is said to be empirically
‘falsifiable’ in the sense that actual occurrence of findings
contrary to it would be the warrant of its falsity (Logic of
S.D. 112).
Popper based his method on the hypothetico-
deductive method (the method of trial and error, or
conjecture and refutation, as he later called it), claiming
that enumerative induction was impossible.
Criticism
In spite of the fact that Popper’s views have
contributed in no small way to revolutionize twentieth
century science and philosophy of science, it must be said
that his whole programme of critical rationalism is to be
accounted as not too successful because of the standard
criticisms it is open to.
Below are outlined some of the standard criticisms
which the Popperian system is open to
1. By postulating his single criterion of falsifiability, he
has committed the fallacy of oversimplification; he
has oversimplified the forms that scientific theories
take and the methods used in testing them.
2. By his concept of corroboration, he has cleverly
250
-
introduced induction through the back door. There
seems to be a resemblance between his model and the
inductivist model which he had set forth to debunk.
Thus, his claim that he has succeeded in
circumventing the problem of induction is a false
claim.
3. As shown by Tichy, it is not possible to satisfactorily
compare the verisimilitudes of two theories. This
puts a question mark against Popper’s notion of
verisimilitude.
4. Popper’s view that a theory is all conjecture is not
completely correct. The fact is that a theory is not all
conjecture because some parts of it may have
become very well established. Conjecture may only
come in at what one may call the experimental and
growing points of science.
5. Popper is ensnared by his own view that all
knowledge is provisional. If all knowledge is
provisional, then it is arguable that Popper’s own
critical rationalist methodology is ‘ipso-facto’
provisional.
6. History seems to falsify the falsificationist principle.
History abounds with examples of scientific
theories, which were not rejected even though
anomalies were found in them right from the start.
In the face of the objections to which the Popperian
system is exposed, there have been attempts by some .
of Popper’s former friends and colleagues to either
develop or modify Popper’s position. Of note is
Imre Lakatos whose attempt to improve on the
Popperian system we shall now examine.
251
Imre Lakatos (1922-1974)
He was a Hungarian by birth. In his early years, he
belonged to an anti-Nazi resistance movement. Later in
life, he moved to the London School of Economics, where
he came under Popper’s influence. He eventually occupied
a chair in this school. His most widely read and influential
paper is entitled “The Methodology ofScientific Research
Programme". Lakatos was no doubt greatly influenced by
Popper. In his The Rationality of Science, W.H. Newton-
Smith,described Lakatos as “TheRevisionaryPopperian”
(77 - 79). Lakatos himself declares that:
Popper’s ideas represent the most important
development in the philosophy of twentieth
century; an achievement in the tradition and on
the level of Hume, Kant and Whewell.
Personally my debt to him is immeasurable,
more than anyone else, he changed my life. I
was nearly forty when I got into the magnetic
field of his intellect ...”(139).
JJke Popper, Lakatos is a rationalist in that he
believes that the central problem in the philosophy of
science is that of stating the universal conditions under
which a theory can be regarded as scientific and when to
decide whether the acceptance of a theory is rational or
irrational. Although Lakatos’ model is not as simplistic as
Popper’s, it is indeed a remarkable improvement.
Lakatos ’ main obj ection to Popper is that Popper tends
to represent the scientific endeavour as a kind of two-
comered fight between a theory and the world in the sense that:
1. A test is or must be made a two-cornered fight
between theory and experiment so that in the final
confrontation only these two face each other; and
252
2. The only interesting outcome of such confrontation
is (conclusive) falsification: the only genuine
discoveries are refutations of scientific hypotheses.
However, history of science suggests that (i) tests are
at least three-cornered fight between rival theories
and experiments; and (ii) some of the most
interesting experiments result prima facie, in
confirmation rather than falsification (Lakatos 31)
In proposing his alternative view to that of Popper,
Lakatos maintains that we should regard the
scientific endeavour as a kind of three-cornered fight
between rival theories with the world acting as the
referee. Consequently, he suggests that we should
only regard theory T as having been falsified if and
only if another theory T1 has been proposed with the
following characteristics:
(1) T1 has excess empirical content than T: that
is, it predicts novel facts, that is, facts
improbable in the light of, or even forbidden
by T; (2) t explains the previous success of T,
that is, all the unrefuted content of T, and (3)
some of the excess content of T‘ is
corroborated (Lakatos 32).
In criticizing Popper, Lakatos argues that theories
have not been abandoned simply because they resulted in
predictions which were not fulfilled. Indeed, to jettison a
theory just because it generates anomalies is to undermine
the scientific enterprise. Lakatos further argues that in a’
two-cornered fight, victory would normally go to the
world. He contends that there has never been a scientific
theory, no matter how successful, that has not generated
253
* /
some anomalies right from its cradle to its demise. For
* him, the generation of anomalies is not sufficient a
condition to warrant our rejection of a theory. For, to have a
theory with anomalies is far better than not to have a theory
at all. So, Lakatos does not subscribe to Popper’s view that
' a theory is to be immediately abandoned once it has
generated some anomalies. It is his view that:
An assessment of ’the relative merits of
competing theories should be delayed until
proponents of the theories have had time to
explore modifications in their theories which
might make them better able to cope with
anomalies (Newton-Smith 79).
This line of reasoning led Lakatos to surmise that the
unit of appraisal in science must not be a single theory but
many related theories arranged in such a sequence that each
one is generated by modifying the one preceding it.
Lakatos calls such a sequence Scientific Research
Programme. In proposing this programme, Lakatos thinks
that:
The appraisal of large units like research
programmes is in one sense much more liberal
and in another much more strict than Popper’s
appraisal of theories. This new appraisal is
more tolerant in the sense that it allows a
research programme to outgrow infantile
diseases, such as inconsistent foundations and
occasional ad hoc moves (Lakatos ! 49).
In an attempt to answer the question as to which
theories actually constitute a particular research
programme, Lakatos individuates research programme by
254
specifying its three main components: the ‘hard-core’, the
‘negative heuristic’ and the ‘positive heuristic’. The hard
core is made up of theoretical assumptions, which any
theory that is part of the programme must share from. The
positive heuristic consists, pf rough guidelines, which
indicate how the research programme might be developed.
It gives guidance as to wljat is to be done in the face of
anomalies. The negative heuristic consists of a
methodological principle, which stipulates that, the basic
assumptions underlying the research programme, its hard
core, must not be rejected or modified when confronted
with anomalies. Its protection from falsification is ensured
by a “protective belt” of auxiliary hypotheses, initial
conditions, and so on.
Lakatos avers that the aphievement of Scientific
Research Programmes can be evaluated in terms of
progressive and stagnating probleip-shifts. According to
him, a research programme is progressive if its theoretical
growth anticipates its empirical growth, that is, as long as it
keeps predicting new facts with some measure of success.
On the other hand, a research programme is stagnating pr
degenerating if its theoretical growth lags behind its
empirical growth. For Lakatos, it is only when a research
programme progressively explains more than its rival that
the said rival ought to be shelved.
Conclusion
In closing this chapter, it is pertinent to pinpoint the
salient similarities and differences between Popper and
Lakatos. Both of them agree that the goal of science is to
' 255
• I
increase verisimilitude (i.e. truth-content) and
corroboration. Whereas Popper stresses that the unit of
appraisal is a single theory, Lakatos is of the view that the
unit of appraisal is a sequence of related theories each of
which is generated by modifying its predecessor. Whereas
Popper stresses the need for crucial experiments between
rival theories, Lakatos does not stress the need for crucial
experiment between rival programmes. Whereas Popper
urges that a theory should be mercilessly abandoned if an
observation contradicts it, Lakatos urges that a theory
should not be immediately dropped in the face of
contradiction by an observation, but its “protective belt”
should be strengthened or modified. Lakatos, however,
enjoins us to drop a theory if and only if the research
programme of which it is a part is no longer generating
novel predictions, which are corroborated. Finally, it has
been widely claimed that the Lakatosian model is much
richer than the Popperian model. To quote Newton-Smith:
Lakatos’ conception of the scientific enterprise
is much richer than that of Popper. For
Lakatos’ notion of a heuristic, in spite of its
problem, does direct our attention to important
aspects of scientific practices not adequately
stressed by Popper (99).
256
CHAPTER 25
HISTORICAL AND REVOLUTIONARY
SCIENCE OF THOMAS KUHN r .
Criticism •
Many standard criticisms have been leveled against
Kuhn’s conception of science. The first criticism is against
his notion of paradigm. It has been argued that the notion of
a paradigm is ambiguous. Dudley Shapere describes
Kuhn’s paradigm as a blanket term. Masterman claims he
could point out about twenty-one ways in which Kuhn uses
the term ‘paradigm’ all of which is incompatible with, one
another. The second criticism is against his
incommensurability thesis. The thesis seems to suggest
that science is not concerned with discovering ‘the truth’.
Going by the Kuhnian model, what counts as the truth is
' 259
what a scientific community allows, rathef than the
relationship between a theory and the world. ^Orpe critics
have, gone as far as accusing Kuhn of suggesting that
science is an irrational enterprise, governed by shared
commitments, rather^uian struggles with nature in an
attempt to discover tKe^uth (Oldroyd 323). Thirdly,
Kuhn’s notion of ‘normal science’ has been found to be
distasteful. On the one hand, the notion of‘normal science’
does not tally with lji§torical evidence. On the other hand,
the notion runs contrary to critical discussing and the
testing of hypotheses and theories to death, ldrrl Popper
fias made'this second observation. It must befmentkrtied ,
that Kuhn has' made successful respons^s^o some xVf~
criticisms of this kind in his ‘postscript’ to the sgsofra
edition of The Structure ofScientific in a
paper entitled “Second Thought on Paradigms
To conclude this discussion, it must be .■
that although Kufftw^t^^cw that there is a^ftrong social
component to scientifu^knowledge lpfe ;been widely
accepted (Oldroyd 324), navMhfcJess, hZhas not succeeded
in formulating a more convijsyng approach to replace the
Popperian approach. In attempt to solve some of the
problems created by Pepper, he Zpded up creating more
problems, the most obvious bei$gs>the problem of ‘normal
science’. It is, therefore, a thing of relief to hear that Paul
Feyerabend made an iirgeiydus attempt to solve not only the
Popperian problem, but also the Lakatosian and Kuhnian
problems. Feyerabend’s position will be examined in
chapter twenty-six
260
CHAPTER 26
MARXIST/LENJNIST DIALECTICAL
ME1JIODOLOGY OF SCIENCE
I
269
A community of such members will not have need
for any form of government. It is a society without rulers.
We can discern an anarchistic model of thought here! Let’s
try to answer the often-asked question: How scientific is
Marx’s scientific socialism?
No doubt the question of the scientific character of
the Marxist theory of society and history is a controversial
one. It is, however, not the preoccupation of this chapter to
go into the controversies that have been generated by the
question. Suffice it to say that if it is the main business of
science (and I think it is) to transform the world for the good
of man, then we can say that Marx’s primary aim was to
change the human situation in the world in accord with
what history told him that situation was to be. Of course,
Marx’s theory was based on the political, economic, social
and religious factors, which he observed to be
characteristic of the 19* century industrial Europe in which
he lived. His second aim was to accomplish this
transformation of society on the basis of a scientific method
for the construction of a new society where man could
become what history had destined him to be. Or as Quentin
Lauer remarked in his article entitled “The Marxist
Conception ofScience',
Marx himself intended a historical process,
which was neither teleological nor rigidly
deterministic and yet susceptible of the kind of
scientific knowledge, which would enable him
not only to criticize the aberrations of society
but also to remedy them (393).
Science, for Marx, then, is “critical knowledge of
historical movement” (Lauer 389).
270
Before we consider objections to Marx’s dialectical
materialism, it will be pertinent to say a few things about
Lenin since Leninism is often linked with Marxism, and
more so that in the caption of this chapter the words
‘Marxist’ and ‘Leninist’ are lumped together.
V. I. Lenin (1870-1924)
V. I. Lenin was a theoretical Marxist and a Russian
political leader who was the chief architect of the
philosophy of dialectical materialism after Marx and
Engels. His chief philosophical work Materialism and
Empirio-Criticism (1909) was directed against a group of
Russian critics of Marx. These critics wanted to supplant
Marxism with the phenomenalistic positivism of Avenarius
and Mach. Castigating their position as a form of
subjectivist idealism, Lenin argued that rather than being a
construct of sensations, matter is ontologically primary to
and exists independent of consciousness. Showing a high
regard for Hegelian dialectics, Lenin considered dialectics
as the heart of Marxism. He defined dialectics as the study
of contradiction in the very essence of objects. Like Marx,
Lenin was concerned with issues regarding historical
materialism. In particular, he was interested in the
economic and political aspects of the revolutionary
transition from capitalism to communism. In his work
Imperialism: The Highest Stage of Capitalism (1916).
Lenin maintained that capitalism had reached its highest
stage but that because of uneven development of capitalism
in different countries of the world, socialism would not
triumph at the same time all over the world, as Marx
envisaged. In another work titled State and Revolution
(1918), Lenin elaborated some of the points not fully
271
stressed by Marx. In particular he developed the Marxist
theory of the state as a tool of class domination. He
advocated the destruction of the bourgeois state machinery
and the establishment, in its place, of the dictatorship of the
proletariat. He also made a distinction between a lower
stage of communism in which the state is still needed and
hence reward will be commensurate with work, and a
higher stage in which the state is withered away completely
and hence reward will be based on need. Like Marx, Lenin
is so revered by the Soviets that “contemporary Soviet
philosophers consider Lenin a philosophical luminary of
the first magnitude and commonly call their over-all
intellectual outlook “Marxism-Leninism” (Edwards 435).
Criticism
The main objection to Marx’s dialectical
methodology of science stems from his claim that the
socialism he is offering to us is advanced on a scientific
viewpoint. Marx believes that socialism is proved
scientifically, made evident by a careful observation of
nature. He buttresses this point by saying that socialism is
the result of the laws of reality, especially the laws of human
history and progress. The theory holds basically that
everything, in reality, undergoes change in a revolutionary
fashion, in accordance with the dialectics of nature. From
the start, whatever exists generates its opposite (or
negation). When this clashes with its opposite, a brand new
item emerges, which then produces its own opposite. The
process continues throughout nature until a point of total
harmony is reached. Marx believes that the point of
harmony in the operation of the dialectics in society is
272
socialism, which will finally culminate in communism.
Thus, Marx’s dialectical process proceeds along an upward
-moving continuum.
Now, it can be objected that Marx’s socialism is not
scientific enough and hence his view that socialism is
scientific is untenable. There is no rational justification for
any attempt to establish broad general laws of history or
human society. This may serve as a useful guide to know
the past but it certainly cannot provide any valid basis for
predicting the future, as Marx tried to do. Marx sees
historical process as an inevitable process, which will
ultimately lead to the establishment of a classless society.
The validity of this kind of interpretation of history and the
claim that the process will terminate along the line is
doubtful. T.R. Machan has rightly observed that:
The dialectical principle, whereby everything
develops its opposite and then, through their
clash, resolves into a new kind of thing, is
difficult to confirm. The process simply does
not appear to occur with sufficient regularity
to qualify as a scientifically supportable law
of nature and human development (270).
This quotation aptly shows that it is very difficult to
find any strict regularity in social phenomena. No one
doubts the fact that physics and chemistry are reputable
kinds of understanding, but intelligent thinkers have argued
that the employment of the method of the natural sciences
in the analysis of social life and society is misguided and
that any theories that may be formulated do not correspond
to social and political reality. For one thing, social
phenomenon is too complex for analysis and
273
quantification. If this is the case, which actually cannot be
denied, then the whole strand of‘scientificity’, which Marx
boldly claimed to be inbuilt in the dialectic process is a false
proclamation.
It can also be argued that dialectical materialism is a
metaphysical notion. The Hegelian element in it makes it
so. Although Marx’s partner, Friedrich Engels, tried to
show that all aspects of nature exhibit the operation of the
dialectical principle, he did not quite succeed in the task.
This is understandable when we realize that principle was
borrowed from Hegel who did not view it as a scientific law
of nature. It could be recalled that Hegel viewed this
principle as a fundamental feature of reality, established by
metaphysical inquiry. But Marx rejected Hegel’s
metaphysics for a scientific analysis. And without the
metaphysics of Hegel it is difficult to imagine how the
dialectical idea can be defended; without the dialectical
principle the very basis of communist theory is
substantially lost. According to Bertrand Russell, “all the
elements in Marx’s philosophy which are derived from
Hegel are unscientific in the sense that there is no reason
whatever to suppose them true” (754).
What all this boils down to is that Marx’s dialectical
materialism is plagued by metaphysics. If this sounds well,
then communism amounts to nothing more than a figment
of imagination. It becomes an image to which reality
cannot conform. Communist society, becomes utopia,
which people try to desperately impose upon the people of
the world. Stalinism in the former Soviet Union, which was
filled with complete tyranny and massive brutality, was the
inevitable outcome of trying to make communism realistic
(McBride 159).
274
CHAPTER 27
FEYERABEND’S ANARCHIC
CONCEPTION OF SCIENCE
276
historical conditions, which influence
scientific change.
... Case studies such as those reported in the
preceding chapters ... speak against the
universal validity of any rule. All
methodologies have their limitations and the
only ‘rule’ that survives is ‘anything goes’
(296).
Feyerabend’s criticism against Method is directed
against the positivists’ inductivistic methodology, the
conventionalists and transcendental idealists, Karl
Popper’s falsificationist methodology, Imre Lakatos’
methodology of Scientific Research Programme and
Thomas Kuhn’s methodology of Science. In criticizing
inductivism, Feyerabend considers as no longer popular the
view that science works by collecting facts and inferring
theories from them. It is his contention that theories never
follow from facts in the strict logical sense. He asks, for
instance, to what extent is the theory of relativity supported
by facts?
Feyerabend’s sledge-hammer is also directed against
the conventionalists or transcendental idealists who
maintain that theories shape and order facts and can
therefore be retained no matter what happens. They can be
retained so far as it is the function of the mind to
consciously or unconsciously carry out the ordering
process. But Feyerabend argues that the conventionalists *
commit a category - mistake because they assume for the
mind what is actually the case about the world, that is, it
works in a regular manner. Feyerabend maintains that this
difficulty has been overcome by Mill in his immortal essay
277
“On Liberty” and by some followers of Darwin who
extended Darwinism to the realm of ideas in the 19th
century. According to these thinkers, theories cannot be
justified and their excellence cannot be shown without
reference to other theories. In essence, what this means is
that the success of a theory is best explained by reference to
a more comprehensive theory or by comparing it with other
theories. But, argues Feyerabend, such a comparison does
not show the intrinsic excellence of the theory chosen, since
the theory chosen may still be unclear, cumbersome and full
of contradictions. The fact is simply that the theory chosen
may be the best of all lousy theories available at the time.
Feyerabend also used the sledge - hammer of
criticism on Popper’s falsificationist methodology. His
main objection to the Popperian system is that its standards
of comparison are rigid and fixed and as such eliminate
competitors once and for all. Theories that are not
falsifiable or have been falsified are inadmissible in
science. Only theories that are falsifiable or have
withstood crucial experimental tests are acceptable. In
reaction to this view of Popper’s, Feyerabend maintains
that many revolutionary theories are unfalsifiable. He
admits that falsifiable versions exist, but he is quick to
point out that such versions are scarcely in agreement with
accepted basic statements. Moreover, he argues that many
theories contain contradictions, formal flaws, ad-hoc
adjustments, and so on. He, therefore, argues that if the
Popperian standards were applied strictly, they “would
wipe out science as we know it and would never have
permitted it to start” (Feyerabend 176) in the first place.
Feyerabend further argues that “the principles” take
278
falsifications seriously; increase content; avoid ad hoc
hypotheses; ‘be honest’ ... give an inadequate account of
the past development of science and are liable to hinder
science in the future. They give an inadequate account of
science because science is much more ‘slopy’ and
‘irrational’ than its methodological image. And they are
liable to hinder it, because the attempt to make science
more ‘rational’ and more precise is bound to wipe it out...
The difference between science and methodology which is
such an obvious fact of history, therefore, indicates a
weakness of the latter ...”(179). For all these reasons,
Feyerabend concludes that the Popperian standards cannot
aid the growth of science but its destruction.
Feyerabend’s searchlight of criticism is also pointed
at Kuhn’s ideas about science. He maintains that although
Kuhn’s ideas are interesting, they are too vague to result in
anything but lots of hot air. He finds particularly distasteful
Kuhn’s idea of normal science. He argues that Kuhn’s idea
of normal science is not in consonance with the history of
science.
Before criticizing Lakatos’ methodology of science,
Feyerabend confesses that Lakatos is immeasurably
superior to Kuhn. The first reason being that in place of
theories, Lakatos considers research programmes which
are sequences of researches or theories conducted by
investigators, in which certain methodological rules are
adhered to. The sequences of researches or theories are
connected by what he called ‘heuristics’ (which means
methods of modification). While some of the
methodological rules tell us what paths of research to avoid
(negative heuristics), others tell us what paths to pursue
279
(positive heuristics). What count is not the many faults,
which a theory in the sequence may contain, but the
tendency displayed by the entire sequence. The second
reason, according to Feyerabend, for the superiority of
Lakatos to Kuhn is that he (Lakatos) tends to bind history
and methodology into a single enterprise. By this,
historical developments and achievements are to be judged
over a period of time, rather than the situation at a particular
time. A research programme may be progressive or
degenerating. A research programme is progressive if it
keeps predicting novel facts, otherwise it is degenerating.
Feyerabend points out that a decisive feature of Lakatos’
methodology of Science is that it does not stipulate
methodological rules that tell the scientist to either retain or
reject a research programme. Feyerabend writes:
Scientists may stick to a degenerating
programme, they may even succeed in
making the programme overtake its rivals and
they therefore proceed rationally with
whatever they are doing (provided they
continue calling degenerating programmes
degenerating and progressive programmes
progressive). This means that Lakatos offers
words, which sound like the elements of a
methodology; he does not offer a
methodology. There is no method according
to the most advanced and sophisticated
methodology in existence today (How to
Defend S.A.S. 161).
By implication, what Feyerabend is saying is that
Lakatos does not offer a methodology and as such he is a
fellow anarchist.
280
Having dismissed all scientific methodologies as
inadequate, Feyerabend goes on to discuss the relationship
between science and other forms of knowledge. He
observes that many methodologies of science present
science as though it is the paradigm of rationality. In
criticizing Lakatos’ methodology of science, in particular,
he points out that, “Having finished his “reconstruction” of
modem science, he (Lakatos) turns it against other fields as
if it had already been established that modem science is
superior to magic or to Aristotelian science, and that it has
no illusory results. However, there is no shred of an
argument of this kind. “Rational reconstructions” take
“basic scientific wisdom” for granted; they do not show
that it is better than the “basic wisdom” of witches and
warlocks (Feyerabend, A. M. 205).
Feyerabend maintains that science is one of the
many ideologies that should be treated as fairytales. It is
his view that all ideologies must not be taken seriously but
should be treated as fairytales because of the many wicked
lies they contain. He complains that proponents of the
‘superiority’ of science do not take time to investigate other
forms of knowledge. Feyerabend is not prepared to accept
this attitude. For him, ifjustice is to be done in comparing
science with other forms of knowledge, a thorough
investigation of the nature, methods and aims of science
must be carried out simultaneously with those of other
forms of knowledge. This, according to him, can be done
by studying “historical records - textbooks, original
papers, records of meetings, and private papers, letters and
the like”(A.M.. 253). Feyerabend claims that his
preoccupation is to defend (or rather free) society and its
281
inhabitants from the strangling hold of science. Thus,
Feyerabend defends what he calls humanitarian attitude,
according to which, individual humans should be free and
allowed to possess liberty so they can lead a full and
rewarding life. From this humanitarian viewpoint,
“Feyerabend’s anarchistic view of science gains support
because, within science; it increases the freedom of
individuals by encouraging the removal of all
methodological constraints, whilst in a broader context it
encourages a freedom for individuals to choose between
science and other forms of knowledge”(ChaImers 142).
Feyerabend believes that the institutionalization of science
is totally against the humanitarian attitude he seeks to
defend. In schools, science is taught as a compulsory
subject, and whereas an American is free to belong to any
religion of his choice, he is not free to demand that his
children be allowed to study magic, astrology, or legends at
school. Whereas there is a formal separation between state
and church, there is no formal separation between state and
science. State and science work closely together. The state
spends immense sums on the improvement of scientific
ideas.
Feyerabend’s recommendation for the
demythologization of science is the formal separation
between state and science as there is now a formal
separation between state and church. He writes: "... as
accepting and rejecting of ideologies should be left to the
individual, it follows that the separation of state and church
must be complemented by the separation of state and
science, that most recent, most aggressive, and most
dogmatie religious institution. Such a separation may be
282
our only chance to achieve a humanity we are capable of,
but have never fully realized”(A.M. 295).
Feyerabend concludes his anarchistic programme by
saying that science, myths, dogmas of theology and
metaphysics are some of the many ways of constructing a
world-view. He maintains that a fruitful exchange between
science and such ‘non-scientific’ world-views will be in
even greater need of anarchism than is science itself. Thus,
to him, anarchism is not only possible, it is necessary both
for the internal growth of science^nd for the development
of our culture as a whole (A. M. 180). Indeed, the
realization that science is not perfect calls for an anarchistic
epistemology. He writes: “The realization that science is
not sacrosanct, and that the debate between science and
myth has ceased without having been won by either side,
further strengths the case for anarchism” (A. M. 171).
How far Feyerabend’s argument is correct will be seen after
some objections have been raised against it.
Criticism
The following standard objections can be leveled
against Feyerabend’s argument against method.
1. If methodologies of science are to be understood in
terms of providing ruies to guide scientists in their choices
and decisions, then it will seem that Feyerabend’s
anarchistic stand against all methodologies of science is
correct. However, if the strategy of separating the problem
of theory change from that of theory choice is adopted, then
problems concerning rules for guiding theory choice does
not constitute problems for an account of theory change
(Chalmers 136).
283
In his book “What is this thing called Science!, A.
F. Chalmers points out that an objectivist account of theory
change in physics is immune from Feyerabend’s critique of
method. For him, the account is based on the assumption
that in any society where physics is actually practised, there
are bound to be scientists or groups of scientists with the
appropriate physical and mental resources who will use the
available experimental or theoretical techniques to develop
science. If this sociological assumption is fulfilled,
Chalmers argues (ceteris paribus), then we can presume
that,
If an objective opportunity for development
of a programme is present, then sooner or later
some scientists or group of scientists will take
advantage of it. The net effect will be that a
programme that offers more objective
opportunities for development than its rival
will tend to forge ahead of its rival as those
opportunities are taken advantage of. This
will be the case even if the majority of
scientists happen to choose to work on the
programme with small degree of fertility. In
the latter case, the minority choosing to work
on the programme offering many
opportunities will soon meet with success
whilst the majority, those representing the
majority view, will struggle in vain to take
advantage of non-existent opportunities (128
-129).
What this position of Chalmers shows is that, with
this sociological requirement satisfied, a programme with a
284
higher degree of fertility than its rival will tend to oust its
rival.’ He is, however, quick to point out that it is possible
for a programme with a high degree of fertility to come to
naught, especially as there is no absolute guarantee that
opportunities will bear fruit when pursued. He cites as his
example the vortex theory of William Thomson, whose aim
was to explain the properties of atoms and molecules by
representing them as vortices in perfectly elastic, non-
viscous ether. This theory met with abysmal failure and
was soon overtaken by other programmes that met with
success. For Chalmers, therefore, an objectivist account of
theory change will need to take account both of the relative
"degrees of fertility of rival programmes and their success in
pfiactice (129 — 130). Chalmers thinks that if his account of
thebry change is ..correct, “the process of theory change
transcends the conscious intentions, choices and decisions
of physicists. In particular, it is not determined by the
methodological decisions of the physicists”! 131)
2. Feyerabend’s comparison of science with myth,
' " voodoo, witchcraft, astrology and the like is ‘unholy’. The
first reason for saying this is that these ‘non-scientific’
subjects do not have well defined objectives and the
methods for achieving those objectives, as does science.
The second reason is that these ‘non-scientific subjects do
not constitute a pressing problem to our contemporary
society as do science and technology. So, the question of a
free choice between science and witchcraft or astrology or
voodoo is irrelevant.
3. In a society where ‘anything goes’, that is, where
everyone is free to follow his own inclinations and do his
own thing in his own way, the principle that will be at work
285
is “everything stays”. Politically, this can lead to
authoritarianism, as those in power will do everything
possible to remain in power.
4. Considering the errors in Feyerabend’s position, we
may (despite the merits of his position) agree with him that
he is not to be taken seriously. We have already mentioned
that Feyerabend presents himself not only as an anarchist
but as a ‘dadaist’ and as an exponent of irrationalism. If we
are to go strictly by the usual twenty first - century norm of
critical analysis and rigorous application of the canons of
logic, a position that favours irrationalism is not to be taken
too seriously.
I.
286
PART SIX
290
(d) It does not explain the transition from the plant world
• to animal and then to human.
(e) It does not show how the present universe is a
cosmos and not chaos.
(f) It fails to account for why evolution has ceased?
Why is there no continuity of evolution? How does a
goat produce a goat and no an evoluted specimen?
Why have monkeys and apes ceased to
evolve to man?
All these show that there is a serious missing link in
the evolutionary theory. Modern attempts to supply this
missing link have led to the birth of another kind of
evolution called theistic evolution. This is different from
organic evolution discussed above. While organic
evolution is naturalistic or atheistic, theistic evolution finds
a place for God’s intervention. While the former holds that
evolution is a chance process, the latter posits that evolution
is guided by God’s design. Let us elaborate theistic
evolution further.
According to theistic evolution, God created the
prime matter and endowed it with certain laws and powers
of development, which would result in all the living forms,
which He purposed to inhabit the earth. Instead of creating
a seed for every kind of life, as the Bible teaches, theistic
evolution claims that God created a seed capable of
producing every kind of life. On the origin of man, theistic
evolutionists are of the view that God used evolution to
produce an animal with all the bodily features of man and
291
that when that stage was reached, God breathed into this
animal body the Divine Spirit thus giving to it the Divine
image and making man more than mere animal. Many of
those who hold this view today are mostly liberal
theologians.
To me, theistic evolution is as ridiculous as organic
evolution. Both are contrary to fact. Does this not show
that evolution is a mere fabric of hypothesis, a pure fiction
or a figment of imagination? Does it not show the collapse
of evolution under the very weight of its own inherent
difficulties and absurdities? Should we not therefore
believe the word of God and accept the simple but true story
of creation revealed in Genesis chapters 1 & 2? Personally,
I take my stand with God and the Bible against this
erroneous and heretical theory called evolution. Before we
consider the more authentic view (i.e. the biblical view), let
me adumbrate some other theories that are opposed to
Biblical creation.
2. Materialism:
This is the doctrine that holds that nothing exists
except matter. It postulates the eternity of matter. It
holds further that at one time in the universe all
matter existed as a huge cloud of atomic particles.
This super-heated cloud of atomic particles
experienced a big bang about 10 billion years ago,
throwing matter in all directions, which upon
cooling formed into planets, stars and galaxies. Kant
and Laplace supported this theory.
3. Dualism:This doctrine posits the eternity of God and
matter.
292
4. Emanationism:
This is the view that the universe has been produced
by successive emanations from the substance of
God. It is supposed that the emanations from God’s
substance, being separated from Him by greater and
greater distances produced a world of spirit, the
intensity of which varied inversely with its distance
from the source until at length it vanished in matter.
5. Creation from Eternity:
The view that creation is from eternity cannot be
correct. Creation is an act, which brings something
into being, but since eternity had no beginning, an
eternal creation could have had no beginning.
6. Life from Outer Space:
This is the view that life on earth may have
originated from bacteria carried to earth by a
meteorite from outer space. Because there is no
shred of evidence supporting this idle speculation, it
has fallen into disrepute.
All these so-called scientific theories cannot account
for the origin of the earth and man. They all point to
the pre-existence of matter. The earth was made
from some kind of primordial stuff, either by a
divinity or by the blind forces of nature.
7. Creation:
The only authentic source book of the creation of the
world is the Bible. The Bible is unique in its doctrine
of creation. The beauty, brevity, logic and simplicity
of the story of creation, particularly when contrasted
with existing human accounts of creation, is worthy
of admiration. The Biblical doctrine of creation is
293
the substructure upon which subsequent revelations
concerning God’s nature and His relationship to the
Bible and man are laid. The importance of the
doctrine, according to Baker (1971), can be judged
from the following points:
(a) The amount of space given to the doctrine in
the Bible is to a large degree indicative of the
importance of the subject. Read Genesis 1 &
2; Isaiah 40-42; John 1:1-3; Romans 1:19-20;
Colossians 1:15-17; Hebrews 1:2,etc.
(b) The doctrine is important to the proper
worship of God (Romans 1:19-23; Rev. 4:11).
(c) The doctrine is important because it reveals
the transcendence of God (Eph. 4:6; Rom. 9:5;
Deut 4:39; Psalm 57:5). It reveals the
sovereignty of God (Rom 9:21).
(d) It is the basis of the unity of the human race
and cosmopolitanism (Acts 17:24,26).
(c) It is the basis of universal sinfulness of
humanity (Rom 5:12-21; 1 Corinthians 15:21,
22,45-50).
(f) It reveals the unity of the marriage
relationship and the headship of the husband
(Gen 2:18-24; Matt 19:3-9; 1 Corinthians
11:3,8,9).
(g) It adequately answers the age-old question:
where did man come from?
(h) It affirms the trustworthiness of scriptures.
The creation:
(a) There was a beginning before which God existed.
294
The beginning could not have been the beginning of
God, but the beginning of the heavens and the earth.
(b) God created the heavens and the earth in the
beginning. The material from which man was
created had been created by God from the beginning
(Gen. 2:7).
(c) Before the creation of the heavens and the earth there
must have been a condition before the beginning
when the heavens and the earth did not exist. This
provides a strong basis for the doctrine of creation ex
nihilo (out of nothing).
(d) After God created The heavens and the earth, the
earth was without form and void, and darkness was
upon the face of the deep (Gen. 1:2). But Isaiah has
shown that “He created it not in vain” (Isaiah 45:18).
(e) It is. quite-ev-ident that the work of the six days called
the “days of creation” was mainly that of making the
earth a suitable place for vegetable, animal, and
human life and the creation of such life upon it. Each
of the six days is the literal 24-hour day (Baker,
1971)
297
36:25-27; Eph. 4:23,24). The author of regeneration is
God; the channel is Christ; the executive or executor is the
Holy Spirit; the medium is through receiving Christ by
believing the word of God. Results of regeneration are: the
heart is changed; sin is hated; Christ is loved; the life is
changed; new and holy desires spring up like a well of
living water. The new creation contains all you need to
make life meaningful and worth living.
298
--------------------------------- —-------------------------------------------
2 Naturalism or Nihilism:
This is the doctrine that man is simply a highly
developed organism that has evolved out of earlier and
simpler forms of life as a result of natural processes
working upon the matter of which the universe is
composed. For the Nihilist, man is an accidental product of
a blind process in a universe that neither knows him nor
cares about his existence. Man is thrown into existence and
it behooves him to try to make the best of it. What is certain
about his existence of which he is particularly aware is that
existence will terminate one day. While still living, he
must decide on how to live his life, .what to live for, what to
work for, how to occupy the few or many days left for him
on earth.
3. Ethical Theism:
This is the ethical doctrine that man is the steward of
the universe endowed by his Creator with an immortal
spiritual soul and destined for immortal life. After his
stewardship on earth, man must appear before his Maker to
give account of his stewardship and to be judged
accordingly to his deeds.
299
4. Transcendentalism:
This is the view that there is a dimension of depth in
everything that exists. Every finite thing points beyond
itself to that which is infinite. Man is a physical entity
illuminated by the spirit or consciousness. But deep within
man, at level that external observers cannot fathom, man is
a bearer of hopes, fears, dreams and aspirations.
5. Existentialism:
This is the view that man carves his own destiny
through his actions and behaviour. Man is free to choose
what he wants to be, but he is also responsible for what he
does. Man’s anxiety is precipitated by the fear of death.
Life makes sense only because of the certainty of death.
Man's activities, plans, decisions and actions are affected
by the inevitability of death.
2 The Hydrosphere:
This is the liquid water realm. It simply refers to
land or ground water and surface water. Water resource is
stored in three states, namely, liquid, solid, and gaseous.
Liquid water is commonly found around. Solid water is
ice, while gaseous water is vapour.
3 The Lithosphere:
This is the solid mineral realm. This is made up of
crustal rocks and materials, which in turn constitute the
continental blocks. Earthquakes normally have their roots
from these rocks and materials. In recording the shock
waves produced by earthquakes, seismographs are used.
4 The Biosphere:
This is the life layer of the earth interfaced between
the other layers!*
303
that they are measured in light years - the space displayed
by an object at the speed of light in one year. Aside from the
planets, there are small bodies lying between Jupiter and
Mars, which perpetually move randomly, colliding with
one another. They are called asteroids. Their fragments
occasionally hit our earth as meteorites.
Contrary to the earlier widely held view that the earth
was flat, it has been proved beyond reasonable doubt that
the shape of the earth is spherical. The earth moves in two
different ways. First, it rotates on its axis from west to east
in every 24 hours, resulting in day and night. Second, it
revolves round the sun in an orbit once in every 365% days,
resulting in the seasons and the year.
304
ft is however a model of explanation in the social sciences
where, Marxist and Freudian theories, among others, are
held to be tenable explanatory hypotheses (Aigbodioh 78-79).
2. Functional or Teleological Explanation:
This has to do with a statement of purpose or
intended goal, which underlies the actions of men, the
activities of animals, God or some supernatural powers.
In many contexts of inquiry, especially in biology
and human affairs, functional explanation takes the form of
showing one or more functions (or even dysfunctions) that
a unit performs in achieving certain traits of a system to
which the unit belongs, or of stating the instrumental role an
action plays in bringing about some goal. A characteristic
of this mode of explanation is that it often employs such
typical locutions as ‘in order that’, ‘for the sake of’, and the
like. Another characteristic is that there is an explicit
reference to some still future state or event, in terms of
which the existence of a thing or the occurrence of an act is
made intelligible (Nagel 337).
In what has been said so far, two subsidiary cases of a
functional explanation are discernible. Number one is that
a functional explanation may be sought for in a particular
state, thing or act that occurs at a particular time. Number
two is that a functional explanation may be ascribed to a
feature that is common to all systems of a certain kind, at
whatever time those systems may exist. Thus, the
annulment of the marriage between Prince Charles of
England and Lady Diana may be explained by indicating
that it was done to allow Prince Charles to many another
Lady (i.e. Ms Bowles) who had won his affection. The
presence of lungs in the human body may be explained by
indicating that they operate in a stated manner so as to
maintain a certain chemical process and thereby assuring
that bodily existence continues into the future.
309
3. Genetic Explanation:
This mode of explanation sometimes sets out the
sequence of major events through which some earlier
system has metamorphosed into a later one. For instance,
historical analysis frequently is undertaken to explain why
a given discipline lias certain features, by describing how
the discipline grew out of some earlier one. . A good
example here is philosophy, which is generally regarded as
the mother-subject or parent-stock of other disciplines.
Such mode of explanation is often given for both
animate and inanimate objects, for traits of an individual
and characteristics of a group. The explanatory premises of
such explanation usually contain a large number of singular
statements about past events in the system under review.
Two more points about the explanatory premises of
genetic explanation need to be pointed out. The first is that,
it is not every past event in the career of the system that is
mentioned. The second is that the events mentioned are the
ones selected on the assumption that they are causally
relevant to the development of the system. Thus, the
premises will include, in addition to singular statements,
general assumptions about the causal dependencies of
various kinds of events. These assumptions may either be
fairly precise developmental laws for which independent
inductive evidence has been found, or only vague
generalizations, perhaps statistical in content, containing
no reference to some of the highly specific features of the
subject matter under inquiry. However, in none of the cases
do the explanatory premises in familiar examples of genetic
explanation state the sufficient conditions for the
occurrence of the event stated in the ‘explanandum’ (i.e.
event or fact that needs explanation), though the premises
often do state some of the conditions which, under
circumstances generally taken for granted, are. necessary
310
for the latter. The safest conclusion, therefore, is that
genetic explanation is by and large probabilistic (Nagel 338
-339).,
4. Reductive Model of Explanation:
This model of explanation involves “the reduction of
a strange, unusual puzzling or a complex event (process or
phenomenon) to terms which describe familiar (or
commonplace) occurrence” (Aigbodioh 78). In other
words, what earlier appeared strange is reduced to what we
are very familiar with. This not only dispels our fears or
douses our curiosity, but also makes the former intelligible.
For example, in a real life situation, when we seek to know
why some persons manifest a bizarre form of behaviour, we
may be told that they behave the way they do because of
certain feelings aroused in them by certain events. Such
explanation will render what initially looked like a strange
behaviour to be accepted as a normal thing. Again, the
unusual phenomenon of seeing balloons rising up instead
of falling like other objects when dropped (in accordance to
the gravitational law) can be explained by saying that the
weight of the gas in the balloon is less than the weight of the
normal atmospheric air around, and hence the balloon is
forced to rise in the same way that light objects rise and
float in water, while heavy objects (e.g. lead or stone) sink.
When explained this way, the phenomenon, which earlier
appeared surprising, has been rendered familiar and
intelligible. Thus, we have shown that the same principle,
which renders the familiar intelligible, is embedded in the
unfamiliar event. Some philosophers of science including
Campbell and Bridgman subscribe to this model of
explanation.
Objections have been raised against this model of
explanation. Chief among them is that, although some
events are amenable to this pattern of explanation, it is
possible to point out a number of unfamiliar events or
occurrences, which cannot be reduced, to familiar ones
through explanation. It is also argued that what is familiar
to one person may not be so to another, what is familiar in
one place may not be so in another, and what is familiar at a
particular point in time may not be so at another point in
time. That is simply to say that the concept of familiarity is
relative.
5. Deductive Model of Explanation:
The deductive model of explanation is one that
enjoys a position of near-orthodoxy amidst competing
accounts. Both as an object of attack and defense, and both
as an object of interest among scientists and philosophers,
the so-called ‘hypothetico deductive’ or deductive-
nomological theory of explanation enjoys a position of
dominance in the field. As the name implies, the theory
holds that “explanations require the adducing of general
laws, with the status of empirical hypotheses about the
natural order, from which, in conjunction with statements
of initial conditions, we can deductively infer statements
about empirical consequences” (Ryan 46).
The elements of this theory have a long history.
Traces of it run from Aristotle of early Greek philosophy
through the medieval period down to the modern period.
However, it was not until the 19"’ century before it assumed
almost canonical status, defended at that time by such great
philosophers as Laplace, Whewell and Mill, and in our day
by Popper, Hempel and Nagel.
The deductive model is commonly found in the
natural sciences, though not exclusively limited to those
disciplines. It has a formal structure akin to a deductive
argument, in which the explanation is a logically necessary
consequence of the explanatory premises. Accordingly, in
this kind of explanation, the premises state the sufficient
312
organisms. In terms of origin and composition,
sedimentary rocks are classified into three categories,
namely, those that are mechanically formed, those that are
organically formed and t^ose that are chemically formed.
Metamorphic rocks refer to changed rocks. All
rocks whether igneous or sedimentary may become
metamorphic when subjected to great heat and pressure as a
result of earth’s movements. '■
/.
Unmistakable evidence abounds, showing that the crust is
spreading • apart along the rift at the rate of one to two inches
per year It must, however, be pointed out that there is no
strong evidence supporting the theory of Plate tectonics.
More research needs to be done to either confirm it or
falsify it. ,
306
CHAPTER 29 IGTIT
THE NOTION OF SCIENTIFIC
EXPLANATION
307
example, various reasons have been given in response to
the question - why do people worship God? The Marxists
believe that religion is the opium of the masses. The reason
given for this belief is simply exploitation or oppression of
the masses in the capitalist system. The masses that are
suffering under the oppressive capitalistsystem invent the
idea of God who will come and deliver them from the hands
of their exploiters. Thus, religion is the product of
exploitation, the sigh or cry of the oppressed in the
capitalist system. This explains why the bulk of those who
practice religion are the poor, the oppressed, the suffering
masses, the Marxists argue. The Freudians' or
Psychoanalysts give a psychological explanation as to why
people worship God. For them, religion is childhood
neurosis brought into adult life. Realizing his
powerlessness in the face of the odds of life such as poverty,
disease, death, etc, man spontaneously seeks the help of a
father, and finding none he invents one (i.e. God) for
himself. Thus, for the Freudians, religion is the obsessive
neurosis of humanity.
Apart from these two examples that appeal to some
general principles undergirding certain beliefs, there are
other reasons often offered which do not appeal to
principles. In the case of why people worship God, it could
be asserted that people worship God because of their family
background, others because of personal conviction after
listening to preachers, and yet others because of problems
in life. The believer may be conscious of the reasons
..undergirding his belief or he may not. Where he is not
conscious of the reasons, the reasons are said to be latent
and can only be discovered by investigating the primitive
factors, which underlie the belief in question. On the
whole, this mode of explanation is generally not supposed
to provide an ideal form or model of scientific explanation.
308
(though sometimes necessary) condition for the truth of the
‘explanandum’. We can illustrate this by citing an
example. Suppose you wake up one morning to discover to
your dismay that the rear windscreen of your car is
damaged. You naturally would like having an explanation
as to what caused it. Suppose on enquiry you discovered
that your son mistakenly broke it while hauling stone at
lizards. At this point you claim you have got the
explanation; you can piece together the conditions - your
son pursuing lizards, the use of a big stone - and from these
you can infer the result, the shattering of the rear
windscreen of your scar. Thus, you have succeeded in
producing an argument whos.e premises have to do with the
causal antecedents, while the conclusion states the present ’
sad results.
Some people might argue that what is presented here
is not a deductive argument as such but a sequence. If we
take the event of the car windscreen being destroyed as our
conclusion [C], and the antecedent events as our premises
(A and B), what we have is not a deductive argument but a
sequence: Event A - lizards are being pursued by my son;
Event B - a big stone is thrown which accidentally hits the
windscreen; So Event C - the rear windscreen is damaged.
Thus, we have a sequence A, B, so C, which does not look
like a valid deductive argument.
In response to the objection above, the deductivist
might argue that in a case such as the one under
consideration, the general law that governs the explanation
is usually taken for granted, but once it is made explicit the
result is a valid argument. The singular statement ‘My
son’s throwing a stone caused the car windscreen to be
destroyed’ obviously rests on a causal law of a general kind,
which states the effects or impacts of hard objects on sonef
ones. The generalization that hard objects will cause
313
damage to softer ones on impact, whether stated or not, is
logically necessary to the explanation. If stone were not to
be a hard object, but a soft one, we could not cite the impact
of the stone on the windscreen of the car as the causal
explanation, since it would no longer enjoy the backing of
the generalization, which renders it relevant.
When an event is explained causally by pointing to
its causal antecedents or what Popper refers to as ‘initial
conditions’ of the events, this makes sense simply because
we appeal to a general law which states that these causal
antecedents are sufficient to bring about the event. Thus, “a
fully spelled out explanation takes the form of adducing a
general law or laws, some set of initial conditions, and
deducing from these the statement describing the event to
be explained. The logical relationship is thus: Laws (L,....
Ln), Conditions (C,.... Cn), so Event(s) (E,.... En); and as in
any valid deductive argument the explanans must entail the
explanandum” (Ryan 49), corresponding to what some
scholars, for example Nagel, prefer to call explicans and
explicandum. The explanandum (as indicated earlier)
refers to the statement, which describes the event to be
explained, whereas the explanans refers to the entire set of
statements, which are adduced for the purpose of
explaining the phenomenon.
From these distinctions, the general characteristics
of true deductive explanation can be summarized as
follows:
1. The explanandum must be a logical consequence of
the explanans.
2. The explanans must contain some covering (or
general) laws from which the explanandum is truly
derived. .
3. The explanans must contain some empirical facts if
the phenomenon? described by the explanandum is
3T4
to be inferable from it.
4. All statements of the entire explanans must be true,
otherwise the inference from them to the
explanandum would be unsound (Hempel as cited
by Aigbodioh 87 - 88).
These four items are considered by some scholars as
the necessary requirements for true scientific explanation.
Hempel’s deductive-nomological explanation can be
represented in the following schema:
315
By showing that the antecedent conditions and
the general laws described by the two sub-sets
of statements in the explanans, are responsible
for the occurrence of the phenomenon
described in the explanandum, or simply that
the explanandum follows from (or is inferable
from] the explanans, the deductive model
implies that we could have predicted the
occurrence of the explanandum if, at an earlier
period, we had known about the logico-
empirical connections which the explanans
■ has to the explanandum. Hence, now that we
know of those possible connections, we can
predict that if similar antecedent conditions
described in the explanans should prevail in
the near future, then a phenomenon of the sort
described in the explanandum would occur,
given that the general laws cited in explanans
still hold (89).
In spite of the privileged status accorded the
deductive model of explanation, it is not immune to
criticism. The first objection is that, it cannot satisfactorily
answer the question of whether laws can be characterized
simply as presumptively true universal statements, or
whether in o$er to serve as a premise in a satisfactory
explanation a universal statement must in addition have a
distinctive type of relational structure. Secondly, while it is
trfiq that highly integrated and comprehensive systems of
explanation are achieved in science through the use of so-
called ‘theoretical assumptions’, it is still necessary to
inquire more closely what are the traits that differentiate
316
I.
theories from other laws, what features in them account for
their power to explain a wide variety of facts in a systematic
manner, and what cognitive status is to be assigned to them
(Nagel 335).
6 Inductive-nomological Explanation:
Although it is a moot question whether this model
constitutes a distinctive type, evidence abounds that ii is
sometimes used in the sciences. It is a known fact that
many explanations in practically every discipline in science
do not follow the deductive pattern adumbrated above, as
their explanatory premises (explanans) .do not npriTially
entail the explanandum. Since their premises are logically
insufficient to secure the truth of the explanandum. the
latter can be said to be' probabilistic. Probabilistic
explanations result from a situation where the explanatory
premises contain a statistical assumption about some class
of elements, while the explanandum is a singular statement
about a given individual member of that class. An
illustration will help to clarify this: Consider the example:,-
Why did Dimka plot the death of General Murtala
Mohammed? Here we have an individual fact in need of
explanation. To be able to explain this we may need to
appeal to general psychological principles about why our
big people in politics behave the way they do, especially
when they harbour hatred for one another. That is to say that
we can point to a general principle that during successive .
military regimes in Nigeria, the relative frequency was high
that individuals belonging to the upper strata of society and '
possessed by great hatred of tyranny would plot to
eliminate men who were in position to secure tyrannical
317
power [Explanans (1)]. Dimka was such a Nigerian and
Murtala Mohammed was such a potential tyrant
[Explanans (2)]. So, though it does not follow that Dimka
plotted to kill Murtala Mohammed, it is highly probable he
did so (Explanandum).
In this explanation, it is obvious that the explanans
do not imply the explanandum. Rather it is only made more
or less probable to be the case because of the presence of the
statistical law-like statement in the explanans (1) coupled
with the historical antecedent expressed in explanans (2).
A few objections have been raised against the
inductive model. The first is that the inductive model is just
the reverse of the deductive model, and hence does not
constitute a distinct type. It is suggested that all that we
need to do is to replace the statistical assumptions in the
premises of probabilistic explanations by a strictly
universal statement. The inductivist might counter this
objection by arguing that though there is some merit in it, as
a matter of fact it is extremely difficult in many subject
matters to assert with even moderate plausibility strictly
universal laws that are not trivial and hence otiose. For him,
often the best that can be established with some warrant is
statistical regularity. Accordingly, probabilistic
explanations cannot be ignored, on pain of excluding from
Jhe discussion of the logic of explanation important
areas of investigation (Nagel 336).
Secondly, it is objected that, it is still an unsettled
question whether an explanation must contain a statistical
assumption in order to be a probabilistic one, or whether
non-statistical premises may not make an explanandum
probable in some non-statistical sense of the term. Nor are
students of the subject generally agreed on how the relation
between premises and explanandum is to be analyzed, even
318
in those probabilistic explanations in which the premises
are statistical and the explanandum are statements about
some individual (Nagel 337).
322
CHAPTER 30
324
traditional tests of truth (the other being the correspondence
test). Rationalist metaphysicians such as Spinoza, Leibniz,
Hegel and F. H. Bradley held the coherence theory of truth.
It enjoyed, though briefly, some support among the
scientifically minded logical positivists such as Otto
Neurath and Carl Hempel.
According to the coherence theory of truth, a
statement or theory is true if and only if it agrees or is
logically consistent with other statements or theories of the
system. Each statement or theory of the system is related to
every other statement or theory by implication. Various
arguments have been given in support of this theory. First it
is commonly used in evaluating the truth content of
statements or ideas we are confronted with. Very often, we
reject the claims of others when we find them to be
inconsistent with our experience. For instance, if a person
told us that he saw a witch flying across his room, we would
not accept such a story because it does not agree with the
rest of our experience. The same holds for scientific
investigation. For instance, if someone told us that he
dropped a ball which instead of falling to the ground
remained suspended in the mid air, we would reject his
claim because it is not consistent with what science tells
about the law of gravitation and with our common
experience of what is possible. The coherence test also
holds in the systems of pure mathematics. The test for the
truth of any new proposition is its coherence with other
propositions of the system and ultimately with the axioms
of the system. This test is not merely a practical one, it is a
logical one. A statement is coherent with other
propositions of the system when it is logically deducible •
from them.
A few objections can be raised against the coherence
test for truth. First, it is possible to have a statement or
325
/
theory, which is consistent with one system but inconsistent
with another. If this is permitted in science, it is going to
create serious difficulties. Second, a statement may be
coherent with a system of judgment, yet not applicable to
the real world. For instance, in mathematics, we can show
that 2 + 2 = 4 is deduced from a given set of statements or
rules. Of course, no one will question the non-applicability
of a mathematical statement to the real world. But
empirical statements of science and everyday experience
purport to tell us about the world, and thus require some
stronger meaning to be true. What all this shows is that
coherence test only guarantees that a statement may ,
possibly have application to the real world; it does not
demonstrate that any statement actually has application to
the world (Ozumba 127). Finally, it is logically possible to
have two coherent systems, which are mutually
incompatible so that both cannot be true without sacrificing
the law of non-contradiction. If the coherence theory is
true, then there is no way to decide between the two
systems. We do not reject empirical statements because
they fail to cohere, but because they are inconsistent with
what we believe to be true. Thus the coherence of a new
statement or judgment is simply a practical test, not a
determination of truth.
3. Pragmatic Test:
Pragmatism was a dominant force in American
philosophy during the first half of the twentieth century.
The central figures in pragmatism are Charles Sanders
Peirce (1839 - 1914), William James (1842 - 1910), and
John Dewey (1859 - 1952). The pragmatists shared in the
general apathy of the Americans towards theoretical
activity, which has no cash-value. By cash-value, they
meant the use to which ideas can be put. Whether a theory is
believed to be true or false is unimportant, what matters is
whether it affects one’s actions. Theories are mere
instruments of solving one’s problems and their success is
evaluated in terms of performing this function. Thus a
theory is true if and only if it works or is useful or it satisfies
us. In testing a theory, the scientist designs an experiment,
which determines whether the theory works under specified
conditions. The theory can only be true if the experiment is
successful. Truth is what works in practice now. Ideas
remain true as long as they work, and false as long as they
fail to work (Nenty 9).
According to Peirce, truth is the consequence of the
experimental method, which is agreed upon by the
scientific community. For William James, truth is
determined by consequences. A statement is true if it
satisfies the criterion of practical interest. For Dewey, truth
is ‘warranted assertibility’. Truth is what happens to an
idea when it is verified or warranted.
A few objections have been raised against the
pragmatic theory of truth. The first objection stems from
the view that a statement or theory is true if its empirical
consequence meets our expectations. The que'stion one
may ask is - whose expectation? Is it the individual or
society? This introduces subjectivity into the process of
testing objective truth. Individual or societal interests or
values thus become the standard for determining truth. A
corollary objection to the first objection is that the attempt
to verify truth has to await its consequences. This tends to
confuse the truth with the good. The truth is not necessarily
the good or socially desirable. This is the realm of
philosophy (Ozumba 245).
4 Performative Test:
The Chief proponent of the performative theory of
truth is P.F. Strawson. Strawson challenged the age-long
327
view that terms like ‘true’ and ‘false’ were descriptive
expressions. Strawson argued rather that the term ‘true’ is
a performative expression. In using a performative
definition one is not just making a statement but performing
an act. To prefix a statement with ‘It is true that...’ we are
simply expressing our agreement with, acceptance or
endorsement of the statement. Thus, if I say ‘it is true that
the sermon is timely’, is simply to say that ‘I agree that the
sermon is timely’.
Like any other theory of truth, the performative
theory is not exempt from criticism. The main criticism
against it is that it does not distinguish among performative
expressions. Even if we concede that ‘true’ is sometimes
used as a performative, it differs from such other
performatives as I accept ...; I insist ...; I admit ...; etc.
Apart from that, we need to distinguish a performative such
as ‘yes’ from ‘it is true that... ’. While the former indicates
what philosophers call ‘bare assent’, the latter indicates a
considered opinion, as in, ‘I have studied the evidence and
concluded that...’.
Conclusion
All said and done, it can be concluded that science
aims at searching for truth about nature. This it does in a
systematic manner. An area of study can only be called
science if and only if it applies the scientific procedure to
create knowledge about nature. Knowledge is simply
validated truth about one form of nature or another, and
science is the only authentic method of creating empirical
knowledge. The natural sciences have judiciously
employed this method to unravel a lot of truth about
physical phenomena. This has added a lot to our stock of
knowledge of physical nature and has also found numerous
applications in the applied science as well as in technology.
The various theories of truth discussed are agreed that the
job of science is merely to uncover truth (not to invent it),
though they do not share in common the means or method
of attaining this truth.
332
CHAPTER 31
Explanans
E *■ Explanandum
334
Lr stands for general laws. These two sets of statements put
together form the/explanans’. The letter ‘E’, which is the
conclusion, is a statement describing the ‘explanandum’
event. As in any valid deductive argument the ‘explanans’
must entail or imply the explanandum’.
What the above shows is that the' 'explanatory
function of science has to do with establishing general laws
and the behaviour of the empirical events or objects with
which science is concerned and thereby, our knowledge of
the separately known events and to make predictions of
events which are yet unknown (Braithwaite 2).
337
The aim of scientific research has been stated by
Robert Merton to involve the achievement of a set of
conditions. Merton avers that science gs a social institution
has four norms or rules which, when put together, constitute
the ethos ofmodern science. They are:
Conclusion
Now, how commensurate are the merits and demerits
of scientific progress? The balance sheet of the brief
discussion of the merits and demerits of science carried out
above is that science is a gift of mixed blessing. Like wild
fire, its rapid social changes bring with them
maladjustments and misery (Johnson 359). Science has
particularly destroyed our cherished traditional, moral and
religious values and replaced them with technological
development, which does not consider human factor but
machine factor as the important thing. This can be
understood from the fact that empiricism, a philosophical
school upon which science is built, holds that only
empirical and logical statements are meaningful. This
school considers metaphysical statements, ethical
statements and all value judgments as meaningless and
nonsensical. But it must be mentioned that science does not
represent the whole of experience, it represents just an
aspect of it. To see life holistically, we need science plus
ethics, religion, philosophy, art and other disciplines. Since
development is a multi-dimensional process involving man
in all spheres of life, a combination of all will not only help
mankind to regain its lost sense of humamvalues of morality
and traditional culture caused by the deification of science,
it will also go a long way in putting society on the pftth of
balanced development.
342
CHAPTER 32
TECHNOLOGY IN NIGERIA :
TRANSFER AND APPROPRIATENESS
Issues to be addressed here are the merits and
demerits of technological development, the absurdity of
technology transfer, and the need for appropriate
technology. But before these issues are discussed, it will be
pertinent to first clarify the meaning of the term
‘technology’
What is Technology?
Technology is a term describing the use of both
primitive and highly advanced tools and methods of work.
Ever since man appeared on the planet earth, he has had to
work to satisfy the basic necessities of life, which are food,
clothing and shelter, and his desire for leisure and com foi l.
Through the ages, man has invented numerous tools,
machines, materials and techniques to make his work easier
and faster. He has also discovered waterpower, electricity
and other sources of power that have helped to increase the
rate at which he could work. Technology thus involves
man’s use of tools, machines, materials, techniques and
sources of power to make his work easier and more
productive (World Book E. 58). Although many people
call the age we are the age of technology, it is clear from the
definition of technology given above that man has always
had a form of technology or lived in a technological age 01
some sort because he has always had to work in order m
satisfy his various life’s needs. However, when people
speak of technology today, they tend to refer to industrial
technology. Industrial technology began about 200 years
ago with the development of power - driven machines, the
growth of factories, and the mass production of goods. As
industrial technology advances, it affects more and more all
aspects of man’s life (World BookE. 58).
344
used to further the progress of man and its destruction. No
doubt technological development has brought many good
things to man. Specifically, it has improved his living
standards and consumption habits.
Merits:
It is true that science and technology have reached a
pyramidal stage of development in this century. In the field
of engineering, for example, the automobile has been
invented as a means for easier, comfortable and faster
movement from one place to another. Airplanes, ships,
motor vehicles and other machineries like tractors testify of
increased knowledge in the field of engineering research.
Apart from that, methods and instruments of diagnosing
diseases and promotion of hygiene and sanitation have
helped to reduce mortality rate and improved living
conditions. In the field of agriculture, large acres of land
have been cultivated with the aid of tractors; expanses of
land formerly overtaken by water have been reclaimed; and
through the method of irrigation arid lands have been made
fertile. Mechanization in agriculture has no doubt boosted
food production. Israel now boasts of the largest quantity
of food production as a result of development in
agricultural technology. In the field of electronic
technology, the invention of the computer is a remarkable
achievement. The use of computers in business, education,
administration and economic activities has helped to
reduce the exertion of human energy as more activities can
be earned out faster and in a very short time. Yemi
Osinbajo writes:
There can be no doubt that computers have
assumed a new and phenomenal role in
virtually all aspects of human activity.
Probably no other technological device has
had such a pervasive effect on the human life.
345
Even in Nigeria where the revolution is in its
foundations, the intensity and spread of private
and commercial use in the past few years have
certainly exceeded all projections. By its very
nature, computer use means a radical change in
the speed and quality of transactions in which
it is engaged and assumes less direct human
intervention (11).
Apart from the use of the computer, the invention of
audiovisual sets like radio and television has added more
comfort to human life. According to Ralph A. Uttaro, “As
a result of the outstanding technological advances of the
20th century, earth has become and will continue to become
an ever-smaller planet. For centuries, man communicated
by word of mouth or by written word. In modem times,
marvels such as radio and television have become
commonplace, and now the vast majority of world’s
information is disseminated electronically. This trend is
not likely to abate” (1).
In sum, the benefits of technology are increased
production of food, goods and services, reduced and easier
labour and improved living standards.
Demerits:
It must be mentioned that in spite of the laudable
contributions and lofty accomplishments of technology, it
has nevertheless, succeeded in introducing several
anomalies and. in some cases, reduced or even eradicated
the value attached to human life. In our age, socio
political life has been greatly altered by technological
changes such as the invention of nuclear warheads. Those
who support the continued manufacture, testing and
stockpiling of nuclear warheads claim that the only way to
maintain peace is by war. The dictum is: ‘if you want peace,
be prepared for war’. In other words, peace is the result of
346
war. Humanity is greatly threatened and terrorized by
stockpiles of nuclear warheads. Men now live in dread of
the hour, as no one knows when a conflict may arise
between nations that may lead to the use of nuclear bombs
assumed to possess the capacity of wiping out humanity in a
twinkle of an eye. The nations that have succeeded in
acquiring this deadly weapon have become like children
who, by some paradox of nature, have been bestowed with
great power. They must therefore be petted, flattered and
coerced, lest they destroy the whole of humanity at any
venture.
The mass drift of people from rural areas to the
highly industrialized urban cities in quest of jobs in
factories has produced significant changes in many aspects
of social life. Also, the pollution of air, water and land by
industrial wastes is another problem, which the highly
industrialized society has to grapple with. W. Friedmann
vividly portrayed this situation when he wrote:
‘Technology Transfer’
Technology transfer, simply put, is the buying or
importation of technology by a particular country or state
without due regard to the question of whether or not it suits
the environment of the buying country or state.
There are problems associated with ‘transferred
technology’. The first is that, although it may be possible
for Nigeria to buy technology from the technologically
advanced countries of the West, the very act of buying
means that the buying nation is not independent. No
country will be willing to sell technology to another if she
feels that that will be detrimental to her industry back home.
Apart from that, the Western world depends very much on
the so-called Third World for the marketing of their
manufactured products.
Another problem about ‘transferred technology’ is
that there is really nothing like transferred technology.
What we have is transfer of equipment, or machinery.
Pitiably, we do not have a single idea of how some of the
equipment is made. This is due to the problem of lack of
trained scientists and technologists. Consequently, when
there is a breakdown due to climatic and other conditions,
foreign expertise and spare parts have to be brought in.
This leads to further drain of our nation’s foreign currency
earnings.
It must be mentioned that technology is better
acquired than bought. The acquisition can be done by
either copying or stealing it from industrialized countries
and then adapting or modifying it to suit our environment,
or by developing our own. Since no one nation is self-
sufficient, a synthesis of both modes of acquisition will
constitute a solid substructure or foundation upon which a
strong edifice of technological development will
eventually be erected. Professor G. O. Ezekwe, one time
Minister of Science and Technology was obviously lending
support to this view when he said:
Technology transfer does not work and will not
succeed in entrenching technological
capability in Nigeria. Technological
competence is only reliably achieved by a
people’s own effort. No country has achieved
real economic progress by total dependence on
other countries for its technology needs.
However, isolation from the rest of the world
would retard our progress in technology
acquisition. We must reach out to the world’s
wealth of knowledge and practice. We must
pursue the solution of our problems of
industrial manufacture and economic progress
with dedication, conviction and patriotism ...
(in Newswatch. Feb. 12,1990.14).,
Other African countries look up to Nigeria as their
pace-setter in technological revolution because of her being
in possession of the largest pool of scientific and
technological manpower in black Africa today. Nigeria
faces the danger of a grave future if she cannot put herself
on the path of self-reliance in technological development.
It is saddening that very few Nigerians are seriously
committed to issues of indigenous technology. This is,
indeed, unfortunate, considering the fact that most of the
economic problems being faced by the country today are
350
due largely to the stark technological illiteracy of a
substantial proportion of the Nigerian populace. The
Nigerian Government must, through the appropriate
agencies, create a certain level of scientific and
technological awareness or consciousness for the citizenry,
for this is the very first step towards real scientific and
technological development. Of course, the best medium
for inculcating scientific consciousness is the educational
system.
If we must have real scientific and technological
development, what we need is scientific consciousness and
not just scientific knowledge. While the former denotes
knowledge about science, the latter denotes knowledge of
science. To quote Andrew Efemini,
Appropriate Technology
Another term for ‘appropriate technology’ is
‘alternative technology’, ‘intermediate technology’ or
‘small-scale technology’. The essence of appropriate
technology is that “technology and industry should be
designed for the benefit of both the community at large and
the local community. This means that industry works for
the people rather than the opposite. The approach used is to
identify needs and find the most appropriate means of
solving them, taking account of all features involved, such
as the effect on the local population, employment needs,
pollution, etc (Andrews 1). Often, appropriate technology
is more practicable, using local skills and techniques in
small factories, rather than large-scale production in big
factories. This does not, however, mean that advanced
scientific skills and techniques should not be used. As a
matter of fact, a great deal of research is necessary before
appropriate technology can be efficiently and successfully
executed (Andrews 2).
Like any other form of technology, appropriat e
technology has political undertones. It must be conceded
352
that the dominant economic system in most countries of the
world today is capitalism. Since appropriate technology is
not in terms with capitalism, the bourgeoisie will mount
serious campaign against it. David Andrews writes:
In most countries of the world, the dominant
economic system is capitalism. In order that
capitalism can work effectively, the control has
to be in the hands of a small proportion of
society, which it is when industry is large. If
the industry is developed as a large number of
small units, each individual has more say in
what happens, which means that power is
removed from the large-scale industrialists.
Therefore, there will be great pressure against
developing appropriate technology (2).
What Andrews is saying is that, since appropriate
technology is a venture that will lead to the control of the
industry by a large number Qf people, it will break the
monopoly of the capitalists. In order that this will not
happen, the capitalists will endeavour to nip the project in
the bud by mounting great pressures, against its
development. But there are advantages to be derived from
appropriate technology. Let us briefly consider some of
them.
The first advantage of appropriate technology is that
it removes monotony and boredom associated with large
scale industries where many people are made to work on a
production line, do the same work daily with little or no
control over the line of operation. Since the main reason for
doing such a job is to eke a living, it is not uncommon to see
workers engage in strikes, work-to-rule and industrial
action, to back up their demands for better remuneration.
Appropriate technology will no doubt overcome this
353
problem because the workers jn a small scale industry are
few, have much to do, have more say, and so can determine
their remuneration and the success of the venture.
The second advantage of appropriate technology is
that it reduces some of the hoards associated with large-
scale industrial ventures to a manageable level. A good case
in point is the problem of environmental pollution. Large-
scale industries produce industrial wastes, which very often
find their way into the environment. The result is
widespread pollution which poses a threat to both human
and plant lives. With small-scale industries, this problem is
drastically reduced, and can easily be curtailed.
The third important advantage of appropriate
technology is that it solves the problem of depopulation of
rural areas, since it is particularly applicable to rural
problems. Because of the problem of rural unemployment
caused by absence of industries in our rural areas, our
youths (most of whom are school leavers) troop in
thousands yearly to urban centres in search of the Golden
Fleece. Appropriate technology will, to a large extent, solve
this problem since it will ensure even development.
Corollary to the point above is the fact that, although
appropriate technology is applicable everywhere, it is
nevertheless, easier to execute in developing countries of
the world collectively called the Third World. Happily, the
advantage that the Third World countries already have over
the industrialized countries {United States of America,
Great Britain, Germany, France, Japan and Russia] is that
there is little industry already there, so that small-scale
industry can start more easily. The Third World can,
therefore, attempt to avoid some of the mistakes of the First
World [Andrews 2],
Finally, when fully developed, appropriate
technology will enable a country like Nigeria to break all
ties of neo-colonialism. The consequence of this will be
that Nigeria will be able to compete with the West on equal
terms.
Conclusion
In concluding this chapter, 1 would like to remark
that appropriate technology should be of benefit to people
everywhere, but it has particular applications in the Third
World. However, if it is to be at all successful, it requires the
cooperation of all sorts of people, such as economists,
sociologists, scientists, geographers, engineers, etc, so that
the total problem and its solution can be properly
investigated.
356
f------
PART SEVEN
ENERGY RESOURCES
AND ENVIRONMENT
<_______ j
CHAPTER 33
ENERGY RESOURCES
Introduction
Ever since man appeared on planet earth, he has
always sought for some forms of energy to modify his
environment. The quest has led him to exploit and develop
various sources of energy. What then is energy?
The Oxford Advanced Learner’s Dictionary defines
energy variously as the ability to put effort and enthusiasm
into an activity, one’s work; a person’s physical and mental
powers available for work or other activities; the ability of
matter or radiation to do work because of its motion, its
mass, or its electric charge, etc.; fuel and other resources of
power used for operating machinery, etc. (381). In the same
vein, Ekine defines energy as “a measure of the ability or
capacity to do work” (128). Inyang Abia equally defined
energy as “the power by which material body or radiation
uses to do any form of work” (127).
The implication of all this is that energy is
indispensable to everything (living and other forms) that
needs to perform any form of work. Food, assimilated into
their systems, is what helps animals to work. Machines are
able to work because of the source of energy in them (e.g.
electricity or fuel).
There are two characteristics of energy. The first is
that energy can be transferred. For example, heat energy
can become fire, solar energy can give rise to light and heat
energy, and chemical energy stored up in plants. When
animals eat such plants, the energy is transferred to them,
and when human beings or other animals eat such animals,
358
the energy is transferred to them. Secondly, energy can be
converted but can never be destroyed. This is referred to as
the law of conservation. For example, when an animal dies,
its energy is returned to the earth.
There are basically two types of energy in the motion
of bodies. They are kinetic energy and potential energy.
Kinetic energy is the energy a body has while in
motion. Good examples here are a running person, a flying
aircraft or bird, wind and a moving car. On the other hand,
potential energy can simply be defined as stored energy.
Good examples here include compressed gas in a cylinder,
a fruit on the branch of a tree, water in the overhead tank or
on top of a waterfall, runnfrig water, wind, and fossilized
plants that come in form of petroleum, lignite, etc. Thus all
around us abound different forms of energy. The major
ones, as identified by Ekine, include the following.
1. Chemical energy, which is derived from
chemical substances due to the reactions taking
place in them or induced by them.
2. Electrical energy, which is derived from the
motion of charged particles and that of electrons
due to some driving force.
3. Heat energy, ■ which is derived from
thermodynamic processes in a system, which
cause changes ih the internal energy of the
system.
4. Light energy, which is derived from the
interaction of magnetic and electrical fields, <
which oscillate and propagate with a certain
range of frequency and velocity.
5. Magnetic energy, which is derived from the
atomic structure of the material.
359
6. Mechanical energy, which generally involves
motion (e.g. Kinetic and potential energies).
7. Nuclear energy, which is conserved in the nucleus
of the atom.
All these forms of energy are mutually
interconvertible (130).
Sources of Energy
Broadly speaking, there are two sources of energy,
namely, renewable (replenishable) and non-renewable. We
shall briefly consider them.
1. Renewable Sources of Energy:
Renewable sources of energy are the permanent or
infinite sources of energy. They are called primary sources
because they give rise to other sources. Examples of
renewable sources would include the sun, wand or tide,
water, wood, nuclear fusion and synthetic fuels. Let us
briefly consider each of these.
(a) Solar Energy:
The sun is the primary and most enduring source of
energy available to man. It is considered the ultimate source
of energy because all life forms derive their energy needs
from it. Huge amount of energy released from the sun is as a
result of the nuclear fusion of hydrogen into helium within
the interior of the sun. Of this huge amount only a very
insignificant fraction gets to the earth. Unfortunately, the
interior of the sun cannot be accessed for direct
experimentation. All we can know about it is based on
theoretica]considerations.~ai’ KliCv'. auUu! h
The second law of thermodynamics states that heat
always flows from hotter to cooler regions. Heat transfer
occurs by three basic modes, and these include conduction,
convection and radiation. Conduction involves the transfer
of heat through matter. In this case, energy and not mass is
360
little ones with the release of neutrons and some amount of
thermal energy. But since spontaneous natural fission is a
rare process, the usual way of producing fission is to excite
the nucleus by bombarding the neutrons. For example,
when a neutron bombards Uranium-238, it undergoes
fission reaction and breaks up releasing more neutrons and
a large quantity of thermal energy. With the release of more
neutrons, it is possible to arrange the process to occur in
rapid succession bringing about a chain reaction. This
chain is controlled to provide a large amount of useful
energy in nuclear reactors. However, in an uncontrolled
state the number of fission increases exponentially as the
number of neutrons produced, which results in a divergent•
chain reaction as in the atomic bombs (136 - 137).
Although Nigeria has shown some level of interest in the
acquisition of nuclear fission technology, it has not been
able to acquire it partly because of non-availability of raw
materials and partly because of the very high cost of
procurement and maintenance. Above all, Nigeria is
signatory to Nuclear Non-proliferation Treaty and so
cannot have it.
365
CHAPTER 34
ENVIRONMENTAL POLLUTION
Introduction
The word ‘environment’ simply refers to the totality
of what surrounds us and this includes the land, air, water
and all the physical structure around us. Man depends on
the abundant resources of the earth for his survival. In his
quest to satisfy his needs and to harness the environment to
meet these needs, man has altered his natural environment
thereby causing untold damage to the biosphere - the life
support system. The biosphere comprises the lithosphere
(land), atmosphere (air), and hydrosphere (water).
Pollution has to do with the release into the land, air,
water or biota of physical and chemical agents capable of
adversely affecting man and other living organisms. The
release of pollutants may be direct or indirect. Carbon
fumes, rock dusts, oil fumes, raw material dusts,
smokestacks and municipal sewage outfalls come under
the category of direct pollution. Also to be placed under
this category are the less detectable mechanisms such as the
release of toxic substances into food by contaminating
micro-organisms and moulds in the ordinary process of
food spoilage. Under the category of indirect pollution
come the more difficult to detect forms. For example,
potentially harmful substances may be concentrated at
locations very far away from the original source of release.
For example, “DDT, polychlorinated biphenyls, heavy
metals, and other chemicals that are poorly metabolized
and excreted by animals tend to be concentrated in
biological food chains” (Okpokwasili 154).
Environmental pollution refers to the unfavourable
alteration of our surroundings partly due to man’s actions
366
and partly due to abundance of organisms and changes in
radiation levels, chemical composition and energy
patterns. These changes may affect man through various
mechanisms and routes. Man has become increasingly
aware of the enormous damage that pollution can cause to
human life, animals and plants. Indeed, the need to arrest
this predicament is becoming one of the most important
global challenges of the 21st century.
Our main concern in this chapter is to highlight the
various types of environmental pollution and proffer
solution to the endemic problem.
Types of Pollution
Air Pollution
When the air we breathe is contaminated by human
activities, the result is air pollution. Air becomes polluted
when it is mixed with poisonous gases and particles of
liquid and solid nature, and when the atmosphere is
overloaded with these harmful substances. The
appropriate body responsible for atmospheric quality
determines the degree to which such substances being
released into the air can be considered harmful to public
welfare. However, according to Okpokwasili, air is
368
transferred. In convection, mass is transported through
matter in form of liquids, not solids. In radiation, heat
transfer is simply a product of electromagnetic waves.
Here, matter is not required. Since the sun energy that
reaches the surface of the earth is mainly heat, all the three
modes are very useful in the exploitation of heat energy.
Solar energy, according to Ekine, can be converted to
various forms of energy for immediate use or conserved for
future use. For example, green plants can through the
process of photosynthesis convert solar energy to chemical
energy and stored in the plants. Solar heat collectors are
now used in heating homes, driving industrial machinery,
and preservation of agricultural products. Also available
today are solar air-conditioners,, and solar refrigerators
used for long-term preservation of food, drugs and
vaccines.
Furthermore, it is now possible to convert solar
energy directly to electrical energy using Silicon or other
solid-state solar cells. These cells now provide power for
navigation, machinery, domestic and industrial lighting
and spacecrafts (132).
(b) Wind and Tidal Energy:
Wind and tidal energy results from the movements
of ocean waters and atmospheric air mass. These
movements are caused by the rotation of the earth and the
activities of the sun. For example, the kinetic energy in
winds can be converted to the mechanical energy for
generation of electricity and ship sailing. Tidal energy is
very useful in transporting heavy logs.
(c) Water Energy (Hydropower): This uses the
kinetic energy of massive water to generate electricity.
(d) Wood and Biomass Energy:
Wood has ever been a major source of heat and light
energy for domestic and industrial uses. Biomass, which is
made up of animal, forest, agricultural, and municipal
361
wastes, is an important source of heat energy in certain parts
of the world; India, for example.
(e) Nuclear Fusion:
Nuclear fusion, which is the combination of
massive amount of hydrogen and a little amount of helium,
plus a neutron and some amount of energy, can be gotten in
large quantity from the rivers and oceans of the world.
Because of its cost and the high level technology required to
obtain it, nuclear fusion is presently within the reach of only
a few wealthy countries.
(f) Synthetic Fuels:
Also known as Synfuels, their major sources are
alcohol, coal and shale. Only the first is actually a
renewable source of energy. Like nuclear fusion, the huge
capital and high technology involved have made synthetic
fuels the exclusive reserve of a few privileged countries of
the world. South Africa has developed synthetic fuel
industry, producing gasoline, aviation gas oil,
petrochemical intermediates etc. from coal.
2. Non-Renewable Sources of Energy
Non-renewable sources of energy are so called
because they are exhaustible and unreplenishable. They
are called secondary sources because they are derived
largely from the primary sources. They have a finite
recoverable quantity and take millions of years to recover.
Good examples here include fossil fuels, geothermal
energy and nuclear fission. We shall briefly consider these
in turn.
(a) Fossil Fuels:
These are mineralized remains, which have been
converted into hydrocarbons due to high temperature, and
they occur in form of sediments or sedimentary rocks.
Good examples here are coal, petroleum and natural gas.
Coal is an example of fossil fuel in solid form. It is
formed from mineralized remains of plant debris buried in
362
swampy areas. Prolonged heating and compression leads
to the gradual transformation of the original materials into
coal. The classification of coal as peat, lignite, bituminous
and anthracite is based on its percentage of carbon or
volatile content. Carbons bum with hot smokeless and
steady flame, while volatiles produce long smoky flame.
Peat contains much water and volatiles but little carbon.
Because of its high carbon dioxide output, peat burning is a
major source of environmental pollution. Also called
brown coal, lignite has much water but low percentage of
carbon. Lignite bums easily, and in some countries it is a
major source of thermal power. Regarded as the most
common form of coal, bituminous coal is black, shinny
coal, which bums with smoky flame. Its carbon content is
low. Today its importance has declined because of decline
in the use of steam engine and availability of petroleum as
an alternative and cheaper source of fuel. Anthracite is
hard coal with high carbon content. It produces, hot and
smokeless flame and least ash. It has various commercial
uses.
Fossil fuels can also occur in liquid form as
petroleum. Petroleum is formed from decayed marine
micro-organisms and is found in marine sedimentary rocks.
As the micro-organisms die, they are converted to some
organic substances and subsequently to petroleum
hydrocarbons under high temperature and pressure over a
long period of time. Crude oil, which is a product of the
hydrocarbons, is converted to various products by means of
fractional distillation. Petroleum is produced in large
quantity in the Niger Delta region of Nigeria. Nigeria’s
estimated oil reserve is about 28 billion barrels. Because of
its low sulphur content, Nigeria’s Bonny Light crude oil is
one of the finest and high grades crude in the world. There
are low-performing refineries in Port Harcourt, Warri and
363
Kaduna. Because of their low and erratic performance,
Nigeria still imports refined petroleum products from other
countries. An irony indeed!! With the present rate of
global fuel consumption, it is feared that the present world
oil reserves would be used up in about 60 years.
Finally, fossil fuels can occur in gaseous form.
Natural gas is a mixture of hydrocarbons or flammable
gases. Although it may occur on its own without a close
association with crude oil, it is sometimes found on top of
crude oil or dissolved within it. They are the major cause of
blowouts during oil exploration and mostly flared up in oil
fields. In Nigeria, natural gas is a major source of energy.
Usually cleaner, cheaper and more environmentally
friendly, natural gas is very useful for domestic and
industrial purposes. In Nigeria, there are three forms of
processed natural gas, and these include Compressed
Natural Gas (CNG), Liquefied Natural Gas (LNG), and
Liquefied Petroleum Gas (LPG). Nigeria presently has an
abundant reserve of natural gas, which can last for many
years. However, with the steady rise in the awareness of its
uses, the consumption rate is gradually rising. Today some
parts of the Niger Delta region are able to generate
electricity through gas turbine.
(b) Geothermal Energy:
This is derived from migrating or trapped hot water
in thick sedimentary rocks under very high temperature and
pressure. Heat is produced in these rocks as a result of the
activity of radioactive elements. Water, which circulates
through cracks in these rocks, is known to have a high
temperature. The over-heated ground water or hot springs
can be tapped for electricity generation.
(c) Nuclear Fission:
According to Ekine, nuclear fission is the
spontaneous or induced disintegration of heavy nuclei into
364
otherwise known as ‘the green house effect’, and the
depletion of the ‘protective’ ozone layer.
Water pollution
Like air, water is an indispensable natural resource.
Though found almost everywhere, fresh water is hard to
come by. Water is almost synonymous with life. Water is
needed for almost everything - for the survival of human,
plant and aquatic life, for drinking and domestic uses; for
agriculture, processing, manufacturing, transportation, and
so forth.
Water pollution is one of the greatest environmental
problems in the world today. Water pollution is simply
defined as the contamination of water used for drinking and
other purposes. When substances such as toxic wastes,
human and animal wastes, domestic and industrial wastes,
organic chemicals, oil spillage, pesticides and micro
organisms (viruses and bacteria) find their way into water,
they cause pollution. Water pollution is responsible for
water-related diseases such as guinea worm, dysentery,
typhoid, cholera, bilharzias and infectious hepatitis.
When chemical pollutants are released into water,
they constitute health hazards to human and aquatic life. '
These materials are either dispersed in immense bodies of
water or buried in rivers or streams. The sediment may
continue to leak toxic compounds without disturbance,
thereby posing a health hazards for years. Water containing
excessive salts may be unsafe for drinking, industrial and
irrigation purposes. Water infested with pathogenic
organisms such as bacteria, viruses, worms, protozoa and
fungi is not safe for human use. The presence of these
organisms in water may be Traced to either contamination
by human wastes (e.g. faeces), or swimming in water
bodies by people carrying infections. Water-borne diseases
still constitute major killers in the developing world.
369
Agricultural Pollution
Agricultural pollution results generally from
agricultural activities. Agricultural wastes in form of crop
and animal refuse and excess fertilizers and pesticides
carried by surface drainage to water bodies pose serious
environmental dangers. Chemical fertilizers are now
required in large quantities to ensure high crop yields, but
they also pose a great danger to the environment. Problems
arise when excess fertilizers find their way through various
routes to water bodies. Today, man resorts to use of
poisonous chemicals (pesticides) to tackle fungi, insects
and other pests, which compete seriously with him over
who should reap the benefits from crops. The use of
manual means in earlier times to remove weeds and drive
away pests has since been displaced by the use of
pesticides. It is now that the eyes of man are beginning to
open to the fact that the continued indiscriminate use of
these chemicals is disastrous. It has been discovered that
chlorinated hydrocarbon pesticides have the capacity to
remain in the biosphere in appreciable quantities for nearly
a century. Some of these pesticides that are carried to lakes
and streams may be incorporated into algae and plankton
and eaten by small fish and aquatic insects. These poisons
at the end of the food chain may end up in the bodies of
predatory animals, birds of prey and large fish.
Under this section we may also include the perennial
solid waste pollution. The disposal and management of
solid wastes has remained a perennial problem in Nigeria
and other developing countries. In many Nigerian cities,
residential buildings, markets, abattoirs, offices, schools
and hospitals are an eye-saw to behold. Past and present
370
efforts by the three-tiers of government to arrest the low
levels of sanitation have only yielded negligible results.
Noise pollution
According to Okpokwasili, sound caused by the
vibration of molecule waves travels in pressure waves'.- •
emanating from the source of disturbance much like the
ripples in a pond. For him, these pressure waves can be
described in two measures, namely, the frequency of the
waves and the amplitude or magnitude of the pressure, d
Frequency, he maintains, determines the pitch of the sound
(how high or low it is) and amplitude is a measure of its
loudness. He says further that the universal measure of
loudness is referred to as decibel (dB). Zero decibel is the
threshold of hearing, while 85 dB is usually considered loud
enough to result in the damage of the ear if the noise is
prolonged. The pin threshold is 140dB(178).
Although we generally detest complete silence, the
same sound that is generally needed can become unwanted
or unpleasant sound (noise). Sound has both positive and
negative characteristics. Positively, the sounds we like are
considered as melodious, soul - lifting, inspiring, soothing,
pleasant, and interesting. Negatively, the sounds we hate
are described as loud, unpleasant, irritating, disturbing,
annoying, and so on. For example, we enjoy the sound of
good music and laughter, but detest the sound of crying or
the squeal of tyres. Menkiti has identified the
characteristics of noise to include the following:
1. Localization: When the source of sound is not
steady,- it tends to invoke in us a feeling of fear aqd
insecurity., u
2. Echoes: Reverberating sounds cause us to repeat
ourselves unduly when we are talking. They hinder
us from having a relaxed conversion. This irritates.
3. Irregularity and Intermittence: Irregular and
371
V
374
PART EIGHT
NUTRITION, DISEASE
AND HEALTH
CHAPTER 35
NUTRITION
BY
FRIDAY UBOH, Ph. D
Department of Biochemistry, College of Medical
Sciences, University of Calabar
What is Nutrition?
Nutrition can be defined as the science which deals
with foods a living organism requires, how it utilizes them
and how it deals with waste products of its activities. Put
differently, nutrition is the study of the food an organism
eats and the use of this food in the body. As an academic
discipline, it is the science of food nutrients and substances
therein, their actions, interaction, and balance in relation to
health and disease, and the process by which the organism
ingests, absorbs, transports, utilizes and excretes food
substances.
Unlike medicine, whose purpose is to help a sick
person get well or, in case of a chronic illness, to keep him
alive, the purpose of nutrition is to maintain health and to
prevent illness. Nutrition, therefore, is an aspect of
preventive medicine.
FOOD
Food is defined as any liquid or solid substance
which when taken into the digestive tract serves one or
more ofthe following functions: provides energy or heat;
supplies materials to be used for growth, repair and
replacement of worn - out tissues, sustenance of metabolic
processes and reproduction; regulates body processes; and
provides protection against disease.
376
By convention, only substances that enter the body
through the alimentary canal are regarded as food.
Consequently, a 5% dextrose solution administered
intravenously, though a liquid and supplies energy, may not
be regarded as food; whereas, alcohol, a ‘non-nourishing’
substance can be regarded as food, because it is not just a
liquid, but is taken orally and at least provides some amount
of heat (7 kcal/g) on metabolism in die body.
Food is complex in composition - a mixture of
chemical constituents both organic and inorganic, which
belongs to two major categories: Nutrients and Anutrients
(Non-nutrients).
• ■ r;
Food Nutrients:
Nutrients are the active principles or the ultimate
nourishing chemical substances in food. They constitute
the functional units/entities in food, which actually perform
the above-listed functions of food (in its definition).
Traditionally, there are six main nutrients present in notrqal
diet, namely: carbohydrates, lipids, proteins, mineral
elements, vitamins and water.
Carbohydrates
Carbohydrates are compounds composed mainly of
the elements, carbon, hydrogen and oxygen. They
constitute the major proportion of a typical African diet.
Sources include roots and tubers (cassava, yam,, cocoyam,
potatoes-sweet and Irish), cereal grains (rice, corn, wheat,
millet, sorghum), legumes (beans, pigeon-pea, soybean,
banbara, groundnuts, African yam bean, etc), and starchy ■
fruits (plantain and banana). *
Carbohydrates provide a primary and mqjor source
of fuel for the body and body processes, on average 4kcal/g,
In daily diet, carbohydrates provide between 45“ 55% of
377 ,
the total calorie/energy needed. Hence the tag name
‘energy-giving’ foods.
Total carbohydrates in foods are made up of the
available (dietary carbohydrates) and unavailable (dietary
fiber) carbohydrates. The former denotes digestible
carbohydrate portion, which yields energy, while the latter
tends to resist digestion by the animal’s conventional
digestive enzymes and may rather play mechanical roles in
the diet.
Based on complexity, carbohydrates can be
classified into simple sugars, oligosaccharides and
polysaccharides.
1. Simple Sugars: These are made up of the
monosaccharides (‘mono’, meaning one and ‘saccharide’,
sweet) and disaccharides. Monosaccharides include^
glucose, galactose and fructose (fruit sugar]. The
disaccharides are - sucrose (cane or table sugar), maltose
(malt sugar) and lactose (milk sugar).
Simple sugars can be absorbed unchanged, or with
only mild digestion, then converted to glucose, the
principal monosaccharide of choice, by the body to form
the well known blood glucose. Blood glucose level is a
vital concept throughout the entire life of mammals, needed
exclusively by the brain, nerves and red blood cells for
energy supply. A slight decrease in the amount of glucose
available to the brain is enough to cause ‘slowed’ thinking,
dizziness, confusion and eventually seizures (coma), if
prolonged.
Although excess of simple sugars (hence glucose)
can be converted into storage forms - glycogen and fats, in
normal individuals, their consumption should be done in
moderation. Persistent high-sugar diets pose the risk of
obesity, dental caries, high glycemic index (potential for
diabetes and atherosclerosis) and the like. Nutritionists
suggest that simple sugars added to foods should provide
378
no more than about 10% of total energy intake daily, that is,
maximum of about 50g (10 teaspoons) per day, based on a
2000kcal diet.
Natural honey, composed of sucrose, fructose and
glucose has of recent gained preference to synthetic sugars
as a food sweetener.
2. OIigosaccharides:This group’ of carbohydrates
contains three to about ten single sugar units (‘oligo’ means
‘scant’ or few). Classical examples of oligosaccharides of
nutritional importance include, raffinose (a triose) and
stachyose [a tetrose], which are found in beans and other
legumes. They are both indigestible by the intestinal
enzymes, but may be fermented by micro-organisms in the
large intestine to produce gases and short chain fatty acids
(SCFAs), responsible for the flatulence effect felt by some
individuals after consuming legume meals. Because
raffinose and stachyose are highly concentrated in the seed
coats, less of the flatulence effect is experienced on
consumption of ‘moi-moi’ whose processing removes the
covering.
A commercial enzyme preparation from mold called
Beano, which can digest these oligosaccharides, is used to
prevent these side effects, if taken before the meal.
Nevertheless, some individuals are allergic to Beano, so
should avoid its u^age.
3. Polysaccharides: Polysaccharides are the most
abundant carbohydrates in man’s diet. They are polymers
containing several units from 12 up to as much as 3000
monosaccharides. While some are digestible, others are
resistant to digestion (indigestible).
Digestible polysaccharides are comprised mainly of
starch (of plant origin) and glycogen (animal starch), built
exclusively from a single monomer, glucose. On digestion
or hydrolysis these polysaccharides yield glucose only.
379
The indigestible polysaccharides come under
various nomenclatures - unavailable carbohydrates, non-
starchy polysaccharides (NSP), dietary fiber and/or non
toxic anutrients. They have their origin from cell wall
material (intrinsic or associated) and some storage
polysaccharides. Examples include, cellulose,
hemicellulose, pectins, gums, pentosans and mucilage.
Lignin is also present but chemically it is a complex alcohol
derivative rather than a polysaccharide.
Dietary fiber is non-nourishing but performs a great
deal of vital functions in human diet, namely:
(a) Helps to form softer bulky stool, hence a mild
laxative.
(b) Protects against colon and rectal cancers.
(c) Decreases blood cholesterol levels and by so
doing the risk of developing gallstone is
reduced.
(d) Slows glucose absorption from the small
intestine, an effect helpful in the management
of diabetes.
(e) Helps in weight control and reduces the risk of
developing obesity.
(f) Decreases the risk of developing coronary
heart disease and heart attack.
Some food sources rich in dietary fiber include,
whole wheat bread, vegetables, bran, cereals, starchy roots,
mature leguminous seeds, nuts and fruits.
PmMns/Amino Acids
The term protein is derived from the Greek word
‘protos* which means ‘to come first’. Proteins are highly
complex nitrogenous organic compounds occurring
^naturally in all living matter. They are polymers whose
building blocks or monomers are called amino acids. The
380
elements contained in proteins-'are - carbon, hydrogen,
oxygen and nitrogen, and to a smaller extent, sulphur
and'/or phosphorous.
Aside from water, proteins form the major pail of
lean body tissue, totaling about 17% of body weight. Our
body is largely made up of proteins: skin, muscles, internal
organs, nails, hair, brain and the base of our bones. Hence
they aje referred to as ‘the stuff of life’.
proteins can be obtained from plant, animal and
mierobial sources. Plant sources include dottonseed,
wheat, legumes, maize and soybeans. On the other hand,
animal proteins are obtained from meat, fish, milk, egg
white and yolk, horn, hair and cartilage, while microbial
sources are yeast, fungi and algae.
In the body, proteins are known tcTperform the
following functions: “
[a] Supply energy to the body (4kcal/g) like
carbohydrates and lipids
[b] Provide the materials for growth, repair and
maintenance of body cells and tissues.
[c] Regulate the chemical processes within the cell
through enzymes and hormones, which are protein
in nature.
[d] Transport of materials in the body e.g. albumin and
hemoglobin.
[e] Help the body combat infection (antibodies are
proteins).
[f] Provide structural support for the body e.g. muscles,
collagen, elastin, etc.
[g] Aid in movement (actin and myosin of muscles).
[h] Formation of most of the blood clotting factors.
[i] Control the distribution of substances in* the body
(osmotic balance) by blood protein (predominantly,
albumin).
381
[j] pH buffering mechanism by ionized intracellular
proteins.
Amino Acids
Amino acids are building blocks of proteins and
constitute digestion products of proteins. They form the
raw materials for tissue synthesis. Classically, twenty (20)
amino acids have been identified. Of the twenty, the body
has the machinery to synthesize some, while others cannot
be synthesized by the body in sufficient quantity and so
must be taken in diets. The former constitutes the so-called
non-essential (dispensable) amino acids and the latter,
essential (indispensable) amino acids (see table 1 for
details).
A particular protein may differ greatly in proportions
of essential and non-essential amino acids. A protein that
provides all the essential amino acids in their correct
proportion is regarded as a first class protein. Animal
proteins (except gelatin) are first-class, high quality or
complete proteins because they contain ample amounts of
all eight (8) essential amino acids. On the other hand, plant
proteins (except soybeans) are second-class, lower quality
or incomplete proteins due to limited presence of the
essential amino acids in their structures. For instance,
cereal proteins rich in sulphur amino acids are limiting in
lysine; legumes and beef proteins, with abundant lysine, do
not contain sufficient amounts of sulphur containing amino
acids (cystine, methionine and cysteine]; and maize protein
shows limitations in tryptophan content. It is obvious,
therefore, that excessive reliance on one source of protein
could result in insufficient dietary supply of some of the
essential amino acids.
Diet complementation or supplementation is the key
to adequate protein intake and a good nutrition practice.
382
The capacity of a protein to make good one another’s
deficiencies is known as supplementary value or
complementation and the protein a complementary protein.
A combination of legumes and cereals in a meal [e.g. rice
and beans] is encouraged. Plant proteins can also be
improved by the addition of some quantity of animal
proteins/foods; for example, gruel meal and milk or gruel
meal and crayfish.
Note however, that the word ‘essential’ as used in
this classificatfea is a misnomer. That some amino acids
are essential does not mean that others are unnecessary.
They also take part in protein building in the body, only that
the body can make up for their inadequacies.
383
* Arginine and * histidine are commonly called
'Growth Promoting factors’ since they are not synthesized
in sufficient amounts during growth. They become
essential in growing children, pregnancy and lactating
mothers
Proteins Needs
The contribution made by proteins to the energy
value of a balanced diet should be 10 - 15% of the total
energy. Adults need about 1 g of protein per kilogram body
weight daily. A 65kg man therefore requires 65 grams of
proteins in his diet daily. In sharp contrast to the traditional
belief of African societies, infants require more proteins in
their diets than adults; about 1.5 to 1,85g per kilogram body
weight, i.e. between 13.5 to 16.5 grams in the diet of a 9kg
infant. Pregnant and lactating women in addition to the
normal adult requirement need an extra 6 to 17.5 grams for
the first 6 months of pregnancy, and 3g. during the last 6
months of lactation. Their diets should also be rich in or
enriched with histidine and arginine needed for growth at
the early stage of life.
A ready supply of amino acids from those already
present in body cells and in blood exist in adults i.e. protein
turnover. Adults, therefore, need only about 11% of their
total protein requirement to be supplied in diets. For the
human infant, about 30% of the dietary protein must be
provided as essential amino acids. Consequently, diets for
infants and pre-school children must be carefully planned
to make sure enough protein is present to yield high-quality
protein intake. As a necessity too, these supplied proteins
should have a high digestibility value (from 0.8 and above).
Protein deficit in the diet accounts for retarded
growth in children and weight loss in the adult. Delayed
wound healing and decreased resistance to infection is
observed. Hemoglobin synthesis may be impaired with
consequent anemia. Marked deficiency decreases plasma
384
albumin levels, hence edema.}, fibrosis and cirrhosis of the
liver, and lots more.
It is worth noting that no ‘warehouse’ exists in
humans for breakdown products of proteins, unlike
carbohydrates. Excess or high-protein intake may unduly
burden the liver and kidneys by forcing them to deaminate
and excrete the resulting excess nitrogen as urea^ If
prolonged, this situation may wear and tear these organs
and is potentially risky for individuals with marginal liver
and kidney problems overtly or covertly. Infants are at
increased risk than adults. Their kidneys have difficulty
excreting large amounts of urea and minerals; therefore,
their diets should be limited in proteins. Regular cow milk
[formulations] must not be used for feeding young infants,
since it is too high in protein and other nutrients.
Excess of animal protein in diet is also known to
increase calcium loss in urine, hence increased risk of
osteoporosis - a form of bone disease. Africans are said to
have an increased protection from osteoporosis due to their
protein source [plants].
If too little protein in diet can be as harmful as too
much, where then lies the answer/solution? Moderation!
LIPIDS
Lipids are a diverse and heterogeneous group of\
chemical compounds having little in common with each
other except that they are generally insoluble in water but
readily soluble in organic [non-polar] solvents, such as
chloroform, ether and benzene. Like carbohydrates and
proteins, lipids are made up of the elements: carbon,
hydrogen and a fewer atoms of oxygen. Some also contain
phosphorus and nitrogen.
Lipids provide the major source of energy, yielding
on average 9kcal of energy per gram when completely
‘burnt’. Also, they are the forms for energy storage in the
body [mostly in the adipose tissue beneath the skin].
385
X1 •
Generally speaking, lipids perform the follow mg
functions:
[a] Provide energy for the body [9kcal/g].
[b] Serve as carriers of the fat-soluble vitamins: A, D, E
and K, and some provitamins e.g. provitamin A
[carotene].
[c] Serve as energy reserve for the body.
[d] Add flavour to a wide variety of foods.
[e] Are important lubricants to bread and cereal
products, e.g. bread and butter, yam and oil, etc.
[f] They comprise a large component of membrane of
cells and membranous organelles, e.g. nucleus,
mitochondria, lysosome, etc.
[g] Insulate and protect [cushion] vital internal organs
[kidney, heart, liver, etc.] from injury.
[h] Serve as precursors of some hormones and vitamins,
e.g. sex hormones and vitamin D [primed by
cholesterol].
Examples of lipids include, fats, oils, waxes,
phospholipids and steroids. Fats and oils are of utmost
interest in food and nutrition. Roughly speaking, while fats
are lipids that are solid at room temperature, oils are liquid
lipids at room temperature [25°c], Basically, fats and oils
are triglycerides or triglycerols whose structures are built
from glycerol [a 3-carbon alcohol] and fatty acids. These
fatty acids are the functional units of fats and oils and to a
large extent determine their properties.
Fatty Acids:
These are long chains of carbon atoms linked
together and flanked by hydrogen. Depending on the
carbon chain length, fatty acids can be short-chain [5 or few
carbon atoms], medium-chain [6-10 carbon atoms] or long-
chain [12 carbon-atoms and above]. The short-chain fatty
386
• \ ' -
acids are found mainly in milk fat, medium-chain fatty
acids in animal and most vegetable fats, while the long-
chain fatty acids are found in fish oils.
Fatty acids can be classified into - saturated
and unsaturated [i.e. mono- and polyunsaturated]. These
terms respectively refer to absence or presence of double
bond[s] in the carbon-carbon linkages of the fatty acid
chain. The degree of unsaturation and chain length of fatty
acids present in any fat are important in determining its
physical properties. For instance, fats consisting
predominantly of saturated or long-chain fatty acids [or
both] are solid at room temperature [e.g. animal fat],
whereas those with high proportions of unsaturated or
short-chain fatty acids [or both] are usually liquid [e.g.
whale oil, olive oil, soybean oil, etc].
Like amino acids of proteins, fatty acids can be
essential or non-essential. Unsaturated fatty acids [e.g.
linoleic acid and ?-linolenic acid] are of special interest as
they cannot be produced in the body and are, therefore,
known as essential fatty acids. For purposes of good
health, these must be supplemented in diet, unlike saturated
fatty acids [e.g. Palmitic acid and stearic acid], which can
be produced by the body.
Essential fatty acids form part of vital body
structures, perform important roles in immune system
function and vision. Also, they are used in forming *!ell
membranes and in the production of hormone-like
compounds called embolden, important in inflammatory
response. Alpha linolenic acid, in particular, is known to
lower the risk of heart disease and circulatory problems.
The Eskimos are believed to have lower prevalence of heart •
disease than other populations, not because fats are absent
from their diets, but because fats in their diets contain
predominantly unsaturated fatty acids.
387
Deficiency of essential fatty acids and/or excess
saturated fatty acids in diets has been found to be
responsible, for disturbances of fat transport causing their
raised concentration in the blood. A raised concentration
of saturated fats in blood has an attendant risk of developing
cardiovascular disease, diabetes, hypertension, and the like.
- Oils are better sources of dietary lipids than solid fats.
Cholesterol (Steroids] .
Cholesterol is a derived lipid, a major constituent of
cell membranes and bile acids, and a precursor of sex
hormones [steroids] and vitamin D. It is present in
reasonable concentrations in most foods [meat, cream, egg
yolk, etc] and can also be synthesized by the body. Its level
in blood is an important diagnostic index.
Cholesterol is highly implicated in the onset of
degenerative diseases, such as, heart attack, hypertension
[eventually, stroke], arteriosclerosis, obesity and diabetes.
A diet rich in saturated fatty acids increases cholesterol
levels in blood. Foods with abundance of cholesterol
should be taken in moderation. FAO/WHO recommends
dietary cholesterol intake not exceeding 300mg per day
[NOTE: two eggs a day exceed this limit]. Fifteen percent,
20% and 30’40% of energy from fat have been
recommended by the same agencies for adults, women of
reproductive age and 6-24 months infants, respectively.
Vitamins
Vitamins are essential carbon-containing substances
needed in small amounts in the diet for the normal function,
growth, and maintenance of body tissues. Although
vitamins themselves provide no energy to the body, they are
needed to unlock the energy stored in proteins,
carbohydrates and lipids. Hence their role in metabolism is
regulatory in nature.
There are about 13 vitamins in all, which are divided
into two groups: [a] Fat soluble - A, D, E and K. and [b]
Water-soluble - C and the B vitamins [about 9, i.e. the sb-
389
called B-complex]. The fat-soluble vitamins are not
soluble in aqueous medium of the body, hence not readily
excreted. A significant reserve exists in the body, which
often times can accumulate to toxic amounts. Conversely,
the water-soluble vitamins are readily lost in an aqueous
medium. Cooking alone renders them non-available, if the
sauce is discarded.
Generally, vitamins are indispensable in human
diets, so must be supplemented. If vitamin intake is
insufficient to meet needs, a deficiency occurs
accompanied by a measurable decline in health. Table 2
shows the deficiency diseases associated with the various
vitamins as well as their physiologic and biochemical
functions and dietary sources.
Certain food practices such as, excess heating,
excess alcohol intake, parboiling of vegetables, etc. are
known to render insufficient some vitamins in the diet.
Anti-vitamins, a typical example of anutrients, in some
food items poses similar problems. An anti-vitamin is
defined as any organic substance whose biological effects
are identical to those caused by the lack of a given vitamin
and whose action is reversible, that is, it can be neutralized
by the administration of a given vitamin. Examples
include:
[i] Thiaminase, an enzyme present in raw fish, aquatic
animals and mushroom, is known to render vitamin B,
[thiamine] inactive hence unavailable in the diet.
[ii] Ascorbic oxidase, an enzyme in cabbage,
cucumbers, pumpkin, apples, lettuce, carrots, potatoes,
tomatoes, bananas, etc, limits the availability of vitamin C
[ascorbate] in diets.
[iii] Avidin, present in raw egg white, chelates biotin in
diet and renders it unavailable. Habitual taking of raw eggs
will lead to nutritional trouble.
390
Table 2: Vitamins, Functions, Sources and Deficiency Diseases
i
391
00
O
3
Minerals
Minerals refer to elements other than carbon,
hydrogen, oxygen and nitrogen. Normally, they form salts,
which remain after the body had been cremated and
converted into ash. Structurally, minerals are inorganic
and contribute about 4% of the total weight in man. Like
vitamins, minerals are basically regulators of metabolic
processes and do not contribute to energy yield in
themselves.
Essentially, minerals perform the following
functions in the body:
[i] Are important in water balance [osmolarity] of body
fluids.
[ii] Take part - in muscle contraction, e.£. Ca2'; buffer
systems of the body [e.g. K', Na, etc]; waste
removal; and transfer of respiratory gases.
[iii] Are components of most enzymes, hence regulate
metabolic reactions.
[iv] Form the structural framework of the body, for
example, calcium and phosphorus in bones.
Depending on the amount needed" per day, minerals
required in diet are grouped into two: Major and
Trace minerals.
A. Major (Macro) Minerals: These minerals are
required in amounts of about lOOmg [1/50 of a
teaspoon] or more per day. These include
calcium, sodium, phosphorus, potassium,
chlorine), magnesium and sulphur, etc.
B. Trace (Micro) Minerals: Are minerals required in
small amounts of less than lOOmg per day,
including iron, manganese, copper, zinc, cobalt,
iodine, selenium, fluorine and molybdenum.
Almost all foods - plants and animals, except sugar,
contain some amounts of one or more minerals. Fruits,
vegetables, cereals, legumes and animal foods are,
392
however, better sources. Because of their simple structure,
minerals are not easily destroyed during cooking but they
can be lost if they leak into the water used for cooking and
then are discarded. Processing can also well diminish the
mineral content of foods.
Accumulation of any of these minerals in the tissue
may be toxic. This may arise from an overwhelmed
controlling mechanism, and/or entry into tissue by an
alternative route, e.g. iron toxicity through frequent blood
transfusion.
Some minerals are toxic even in trace concentration
and so foods known to contain these should be avoided with
passion. They include, cadmium, lead, and mercury.
Water
Water is the largest component of the human body,
making up to 50 to 70% of the body’s total weight (about 40
litres). The body requires water to survive. A typical adult
can survive for about 8 weeks without food; but can survive
only a few days without water intake. This is so because
water reservoir does not exist in the body unlike some
nutrients. The study of life itself is a ‘wet science’.
In the body, water belongs to either intracellular
(within the cells) or extra-cellular (water which bathes the
cells) fluids, and both serve specific and vital purposes.
Some functions of water in the body include:
[a] Serves as a solvent for many chemical compounds.
[b] Provides a medium in which many biochemical
reactions occur.
[c] Actively participates as a reactant or becomes a
product in some reactions e.g. Krebs’s cycle
reactions.
[d] It is the transport medium of the body, e.g. waste
removal in urine.
393
[e] It contributes to temperature regulation.
[f] Serves as lubricant in joints and between internal
organs.
[g] Aids in mastication and softening of food.
[h] Is the base for saliva, bile, and amniotic fluid (fetal
shock absorber).
[i] Helps in pH regulation through electrolyte
compartmentalization.
Source of Body Water:
Liquid- Water, tea, coffee, soups, milk, juice, fruits, etc.
Solid foods- cooked.
Metabolic water - amount formed by the metabolism of
different food variety. About 0.06g/g; 1.07g/g and 5.41g/g
for carbohydrates, fats and proteins, respectively. Donkeys
and horses make long journey on the desert without water,
pot because of supply from reservoir (hump), but from the
breakdown of fat reserves.
Water Needs
Adults need roughly 1 ml of water per kcal of energy
expended and about 2.4 litres per day or 40ml per kg body
weight. A 65kg man would require 2600ml (2.61itres) per
day. This requirement, however, varies with environment
and activity. More water might be required in an arid
environment than a humid one. Likewise an active person
•Mil need more water than a sedentary individual.
Daily intake is necessary to compensate for water
loss in urine, sweat, expired air and faeces. Too much
water, whatever amount the kidneys are unable to excrete,
constitutes a hazard - water toxicity or water intoxication.
This usually results in headache, nausea, blurred vision,
cramps, convulsions and ultimately death.
394
CHAPTER 36
Introduction:
A disease is any condition that affects the normal functioning of
one or more systems in an organism. In other words, it may be
described as any condition that impairs normal body function(s).
It is medically considered to a clinical condition associated with
specific symptoms and signs. In a generalized term, disease is
often used more broadly to refer to any condition that causes
pain, dysfunction, distress, social problems, or death to humans,
or other animals. Under this broader description, injuries,
disabilities, disorders, syndromes, infections, abnormal
behaviors, may be regarded as diseases. Diseases generally
affect people physically, mentally, emotionally, etc. Mental
disease is a broad, generic nomenclature for a category of
illnesses that may include affective or emotional instability, and
cognitive dysfunction or impairment. Specific diseases that are
usually considered as mental illnesses include major depression,
generalized anxiety disorder, schizophrenia, attention deficits,
etc. Mental illness can be of biological (e.g., -anatomical,
chemical, or genetic) or psychological (e.g., trauma or conflict)
origin. It can impair the affected person's performance at work $r
school, as well as affect interpersonal relationships.
Diseases may be caused by several factors originating ;
from external or exogenous source (such as microbial-related or
infectious diseases), or internal dysfunctions (such as
autoimmune diseases). Other lion-infectious diseases include
cancer, most heart diseases, genetic diseases (such as sickle cell
395
anemia, albinism, etc.). Apart from infection, various
environmental challenges that result in physical trauma, pain,
physical inactivity, hormonal activation from stress or menstrual
cycle, as well as exposure to chemicals, toxins, mold, allergens,
drugs, radiation or airborne particulate matter, extreme
temperature, may also be considered as exogenously caused
diseases.
Some diseases are known to be contagious, while others
are not. Most contagious diseases (such as influenza) are
commonly believed to be infectious. The micro-organisms that
cause these diseases are known1 as pathogens and include
varieties of bacteria, viruses, protozoa and fungi. Generally,
these contagious, infectious diseases can be transmitted via
several routes. Among the commonest routes include-hand-to-
mouth, contact with infectious material on surfaces, bites of
insects or other carriers of the disease, blood-to-blood contacts,
and ingestion of contaminated foods, water or other drinks. Also,
some infectious diseases can be transmitted via sexual
intercourse, and these types of diseases are referred to as
sexually transmitted diseases (STDs). Examples of sexually
transmitted diseases include gonorrhea, syphilis, HIV/AIDS,
ebola, etc. Among these sexually transmitted infectious
(microbial -related infection) diseases, HIV/AIDS and ebola
may be considered newer infectious diseases in Nigeria.
A. Nutrition-Related Diseases
Nutrition-related diseases are generally manifestation(s) of
abnormalities of molecules,-chemical reactions and processes.
When the abnormality can be traced to nutrition, it is referred to
as nutritional disorder, and can result from malnutrition, nutrient
toxicity and defect in absorption of nutrients or defects in
biochemical process within the cell. Malnutrition appears to be
the most important public health problem due mainly to
misconceptions as to its meaning to different sets of people.
396
»
In a strict sense, malnutrition could be any of the following:
• Starvation-an almost zero intake of food.
• Under-nutrition- pathological condition(s) resulting
from consumption of inadequate amounts of food over an
extended period of time.
• Over-nutrition - consumption of excessive amounts of
foods over an extended period of time [e.g. accumulation
of fat-soluble vitamins],
• Imbalance - a disproportion in intake and utilization of
nutrient(s) in the staple diet [e.g. obesity],
• Specific nutrient deficiency- a pathologic condition that
results from relative or complete absence of an individual
nutrient in the staple diet [e.g. beriberi due to thiamine
deficiency].
Obesity:
Obesity may be defined as the presence of large amounts of fat in
the subcutaneous tissues of the body. Mean values of body fat in
the total body weight for normal young men are about 12%, and
for young women about 26%. A man whose body fat amounts to
over 20% of his total body weight may be considered obese, and
for women a figure of over 40% represents obesity.
Diabetes mellitus:
This is a condition in which excessive amounts of some
substances are excreted or 'siphoned' from the body. It is due
primarily to a lack of or functional deficiency in glucose
-regulatory hormone, insulin, leading to excessive and
chronically high levels of glucose in the blood, that is,
hyperglycemia.
399
'&
Hyperglycemia is responsible for the clinical features
characteristic ofthe diabetic:
• Glycosuria - excessive excretion of sugar in urine, the
cardinal diagnostic sign of diabetic mellitus.
• Polyuria- excretion of large quantity of urine.
• Polydipsia- intense appetite both for food and water.
• Polyphagia - constant and excessive eating.
Hypertension:
Hypertension is defined as a condition in which blood
pressure remains persistently elevated. Precisely, it is sustained
systolic pressure [when the heart actively pumps blood]
exceeding 140mmHg and diastolic pressure [when the heart is
relaxed] exceeding 90mmHg [i.e. 140/90mmHg].
Hypertension has been described as a 'silent disorder'
because it usually does not cause any symptom before overt
manifestation.
The disorder is of two main types:
• Primary or essential or idiopathic hypertension,
• Secondary hypertension
Cancer:
■ Essentially, cancer is a condition in which cell division is
abnormal and uncontrollable. A spontaneous new tissue growth
that serves no physiological function is called a tumor. Most
cancers take this form, although not all tumors are cancers.
Cancer cells are characterized by three properties: diminished or
unrestrained growth, invasion of local tissues, and spread or
metastasis to other parts of the body.
402
Currently, cancer is the second-leading cause of death for
American adults. It is not a single disease but exists in at least
100 different forms; hence we talk of breast cancer, skin cancer,
cancer of the lungs, etc. About 35% of cancers are related to
diets. Some of the risk factors related to diet are: high fat diet;
low fibre intake; low consumption of fruits and vegetables; high
intake of meat and protein products; excess alcohol
consumption and smoking; Benzof?] pyrene and nitrosamines
in smoked foods; mycotoxins produced by micro-organisms
that may contaminate foods.
Control and avoidance of these risk factors and practices
would well prevent cancers or at least delay their onsets
HIV/AIDS:
Of all the illnesses that have ever plagued humanity,
HIV/AIDS has been the most devastating. To worsen the whole
matter, no known cure has so far been found for HI V/A1DS. Like
polio, chickenpox, measles, common cold, rabipf and hepatitis
A, B and C, AIDS is caused by a virus. The Human
Immunodeficiency Virus (HIV) that causes AIDS is so small
that it can only be seen with a very powerful microscope. It takes
just a few of these viruses to enter a person's body to be infected
and later develop the condition called AIDS. HIV belongs to a
group of viruses known as retroviruses. There are two sub-types
of HIV namely: HIV-I and HIV-2. In Nigeria, HIV-1 accounts
for 97.5% of HI V infection, while HIV-2 accounts for 0.4%. The
rest of the infected people have both viruses. One who is infected
with any type of HIV will almost certainly develop AIDS and die
within 2-10 years. As an acronym, the letters HIV stand for the
following:
403
H- Human, the virus is found in humans, not in animals or
insects.
I- Immunodeficiency, the virus attacks the immune system
of the infected person and reduces it.
V- Virus, being the smallest of all micro-organisms, viruses
can only be seen with a powerful electron microscope.
1
At the moment, there is no known cure or vaccine for
AIDS. However, some drugs known as antiretroviral drugs have
been developed to fight HIV virus directly. Some of the common
antiretroviral drugs include: Lamivudine, Combivir, Nevirapine
and Zidovudine (AZT). These drugs do not cure but help to keep
the virus under control for a long time. These drugs are very
expensive. Here we commend the efforts of National Action
Committee on AIDS (NACA) and their counterparts in the
various states [State Action Committee on AIDS (SACA)] in
setting up antiretroviral centers where those who are lucky to be
registered can obtain these drugs and get treatment at a very
minimal cost. The only cure for HIV/AIDS epidemic is
abstinence from premarital and extramarital sex. A condom does
not give full-proof protection from HIV/AIDS.
EBOLA
412
CHAPTER 3 7
416
WORKS CITED/FURTHER READING
417
l ABOUT THE AUTHOR
A native of Eme-Ora in Owan
B
West Local Government Area of
Edo State, Nigeria, Dr. Andrew F.
Uduigwomen graduated from the
Department of Philosophy,
University of Calabar, in 1984.
with a First Class Degree in
Philosophy. This was foilowea oy
a Master of Arts Degree in Philosophy of Science
(1988) and a ^Ph.D Degree in Philosophy of Law
(1992). He is a distinguished Academic, a reputable
public speaker and a minister of a fast growing
churcn. He has taught History and Philosophy of
Science for a number of years.