Beyond Narrative - Poetry, Emotion and The Perspectival View
Beyond Narrative - Poetry, Emotion and The Perspectival View
Beyond Narrative - Poetry, Emotion and The Perspectival View
The view that narrative artworks can offer insights into our lives, in particular, into the nature of
the emotions, has gained increasing popularity in recent years. However, talk of narrative often
1. Introduction
In recent years, there has been an increased interest in narrative and how engaging with
narratives can help us to understand ourselves and our emotional lives.1 For instance,
Alasdair MacIntyre famously argues that we can only understand our actions and those of
others as part of a narrative life.2,3 Peter Goldie also argues for the importance of under-
standing our lives as narratives; he writes, ‘our lives have narrative structure—roughly
speaking, they comprise an unfolding, structured sequence of actions, events, thoughts
and feelings, related from the individual’s point of view’.4 Within debates on the value of
literature, this interest in narrative has resulted in a tendency to focus on narrative fic-
tion, thereby neglecting non-narrative literary works, such as poetry.5 This has led to an
incomplete picture of the potential for literature to offer insights into the emotions.
1 For a good example, see Noël Carroll and John Gibson (eds), Narrative, Emotion and Insight (Pennsylvania, PA: The
Pennsylvania State University Press, 2011).
2 Alasdair MacIntyre, After Virtue (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1984).
3 For an excellent critique of MacIntyre’s claims, see Bernard Williams, ‘Life as Narrative’, European Journal
of Philosophy 17 (2009), 305–314. In this paper, Williams alludes to the importance of looking at the
perspectival nature of narrative: ‘We must have a conception of what invites interpretation in these terms’
(ibid., 308). Elisabeth Camp also gestures at the limitations of such narrative understanding of ourselves in her
‘Wordsworth’s Prelude, Poetic Autobiography, and Narrative Constructions of the Self’, Nonesite.org 3 (2011).
4 Peter Goldie, The Emotions: A Philosophical Exploration (Oxford: OUP, 2002), 4.
5 Throughout this article, where I talk of poetry, I intend this to refer to lyric poetry, understood as poetry that
is expressive and relies on the formal features of the work and the effects they produce. Although a lyric poem
British Journal of Aesthetics Vol. 55 | Number 4 | October 2015 | pp. 497–513 DOI:10.1093/aesthj/ayv041
© British Society of Aesthetics 2016. Published by Oxford University Press on behalf of the British Society of Aesthetics.
All rights reserved. For Permissions, please email: journals.permissions@oup.com
498 | Karen Simecek
In this article, I argue that by reflecting on our emotional responses to lyric poetry
(which is non-narrative in structure and promotes perspectival engagement), we can
see the potential for art and literature to offer more than an appreciation of narrative
structures as relevant to understanding our emotional lives. In particular, by drawing
on Bennett Helm’s theory of emotion, I will argue that such non-narrative works can
enhance our understanding of the evaluative nature of our emotional responses by mak-
ing clear the influence of perspective.6 Consequently, at the same time as showing the
importance of engaging with works of poetry, I will also show that exclusive focus on
narrative in any discussion of the emotions, as a way of arguing for the value of literature,
is misleading.
may include elements of narrative, the narrative is not of primary relevance to how we are to understand and
appreciate the work. Our focus is not just on the story, but also on what is expressed. In particular, this focus on
lyric poetry aims to exclude works where there is a clear and dominant narrative structure that is essential to our
appreciation of the work, such as in the case of epic or dramatic poetry.
6 I will not be arguing for a cognitive theory of the emotions but assuming a much less contentious view that
evaluations are part of an emotional experience, allowing for the possibility that emotions are connected in some
way to evaluative judgements.
7 Other examples of this kind of thought include Amy Mullin, ‘Narrative, Emotions, and Autonomy’, in Carroll and
Gibson, Narrative, Emotion and Insight, 92–108 and John Gibson, Fiction and the Weave of Life (Oxford: OUP, 2007).
8 Martha Nussbaum, Love’s Knowledge (Oxford: OUP, 1990), 40.
9 Nussbaum develops this idea in Love’s Knowledge.
10 Nussbaum, Love’s Knowledge, 41. For detailed criticism of the cognitive theory of emotion, see Julien A. Deonna
and Fabrice Teroni, The Emotions: A Philosophical Introduction (London: Routledge, 2012), 52–62.
Beyond Narrative | 499
long or short duration, and a narrative can be more or less coherent in the way that
the various episodes hang together.11
Narratives are a particular kind of organization of events, consisting of thoughts, feelings
and actions that are represented as part of a spatio-temporal sequence. We construct nar-
ratives to represent connected individual events, by selecting those episodes that appear
relevant to this organizational structure, which help to form the sense of coherence of
the set of episodes, that is, they can be made sense of from a spatio-temporal perspective.
Nussbaum views the emotions as having narrative structure because, she argues, the emotions
are tied to our personal history.12 In other words, our beliefs and concern for the objects of our
emotions develop through the course of one’s life in the way that they have promoted or harmed
11 Peter Goldie, ‘Narrative Thinking, Emotion, and Planning’, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 67 (2009), 97–106,
at 98. Noël Carroll also emphasizes the causal component of a narrative, see ‘On the Narrative Connection’, in his
Beyond Aesthetics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001), 118–133. For Carroll, there being a causal relation
between events is what makes a temporal sequence a narrative rather than an annal or chronicle. For criticism of this
focus on cause in narrative, see J. David Velleman, ‘Narrative Explanation’, Philosophical Review 112 (2003), 1–25.
12 Martha Nussbaum, Upheavals of Thought: Intelligence of Emotions (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001), 236.
The idea that the emotions have narrative structure is supported by others, such as Ronald de Sousa, The Rationality of
Emotion (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1987); Annette Baier, ‘What Emotions Are About’, Philosophical Perspectives 4
(1990), 1–29; Robert Roberts, Emotions: An Essay in Aid of Moral Psychology (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
2003); and Peter Goldie, The Mess Inside: Narrative, Emotion, and the Mind (Oxford: OUP, 2012); ‘Narrative Thinking,
Emotion, and Planning’; The Emotions.
13 Nussbaum, Upheavals of Thought, 175.
500 | Karen Simecek
response we have to the novel. In addition, novels engage the reader in an emotional activ-
ity that relates to the very emotional responses of the characters contained in the novel.
For example, while reading a novel such as Cormac McCarthy’s The Road, a reader may
respond emotionally to a character’s situation, such as the boy’s fear, and may become
frightened for him. But the reader’s response also relates to the narrative the character
is embedded in—the reader sees the boy’s emotional response as arising from the story
alongside an awareness of their own response. Consequently, this awareness of the rela-
tionship between the narrative and the character’s emotional response enables the reader
to appreciate how their own response relates to the narrative in the work.
This example seems to capture an important experience we can have by engaging with
14 This point is acknowledged by Goldie: ‘Narratives can involve internal and external perspectives or points of view
... the external perspective is always there, in spite of sometimes seeming evanescent, always shaping and
colouring the narrative and indicating the narrator’s own evaluation and emotional response to what happened’
(‘Narrative, Emotion, and Perspective’, in Matthew Kieran and Dominic Lopes (eds), Imagination, Philosophy, and
the Arts (London: Routledge, 2003), 55–69, at 55–56). See also his The Mess Inside, where he makes clear the role
of perspective in forming narratives.
Beyond Narrative | 501
‘tool for thought’ means at least two things here. First, a perspective helps us to do
things with the thoughts we have: to make quick judgements based on what’s most
important, to grasp intuitive connections, and to respond emotionally, among other
things. And second, it provides us with a ‘way to go on’, incorporating new thoughts
about the focal topic and often about related topics as well.15
A perspective captures a particular complex orientation (a general evaluative attitude)
towards experience, which acts as a ‘tool for thinking’, since such an orientation will
govern how we go about making sense of our experience as well as directing the thoughts
and feelings we have in response to what we experience. Such a perspective will be shaped
by (i) our location in space and time (and the information we have access to); (ii) what
15 Elisabeth Camp, ‘Two Varieties of Literary Imagination: Metaphor, Fiction, and Thought Experiments’, Midwest
Studies in Philosophy 33 (2009), 107–130, at 111.
16 For a similar notion of a perspective, see A. W. Moore, Points of View (Oxford: OUP, 1997), 4–6. Focusing
on the nature of our imaginative engagement with fiction, Elisabeth Camp relates the notion of perspective to
‘seeing-as’, which captures how we imagine certain content as well as what that content is. Camp, ‘Two Varieties
of Literary Imagination’). For further discussion about the notion of perspective and its importance in shaping
understanding, see also Elisabeth Camp, ‘Slurring Perspectives’, Analytic Philosophy 54 (2013), 330–349.
17 The notion of perspective I am developing here is influenced by Bennett W. Helm’s notion of an evaluative
perspective (Emotional Reason: Deliberation, Motivation, and the Nature of Value (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 2007)), which forms a pattern of background values of the individual, those things a person is committed
to holding as significant.
18 Medbh McGuckian, ‘The Butterfly Farm’, in The Flower Master (Oldcastle: The Gallery Press, 1982). This poem is
reprinted with kind permission from the publisher, The Gallery Press.
502 | Karen Simecek
19 Ruth Padel, 52 Ways of Looking at a Poem (London: Vintage Books, 2002), 95–97.
Beyond Narrative | 503
ideas, concepts, which connect in such a way that makes the experience of the whole
poem meaningful with a deep sense of significance.20 This shows that the perspective can
come apart from a narrative structure. A perspective does not need a narrative structure
to sustain it, but a narrative structure always requires a perspective.
In order to understand a poem, we must work out what the perspective on offer is.
This does not just involve working out what the focus is on but how we ought to focus on
the subject, which involves attending to the formal features of the work in conjunction
with the words, images, associations, etc. The perspective offered in the poem is what
binds and organizes the different aspects of the poem, which helps us to forge a network
of coherent and consistent connections across the whole poem. The themes of the poem
20 The other poems in Padel’s anthology demonstrate that this non-narrative structure is common to a great deal
of contemporary poetry; ‘The Butterfly Farm’ is not atypical. For example, see Helen Dunmore’s ‘The Surgeon
Husband’ (which juxtaposes images of preparing salmon and performing surgery), Paul Muldoon’s ‘Quoof’
(which brings together private language and private sexuality), or Selima Hill’s ‘The World’s Entire Wasp
Population’ (which centres on a particular feeling).
21 It is important to note that I am not suggesting that a theory of metaphor will serve well as a theory of poetry, but
there are a number of important connections, in particular the relationship between images and how that impacts
our understanding.
22 Troy Jollimore, ‘“Like a Picture or a Bump on the Head”: Vision, Cognition, and the Language of Poetry’,
Midwest Studies in Philosophy 33 (2009), 131–158, at 146. Richard Moran also views metaphor as inherently
perspectival (‘Seeing and Believing: Metaphor, Image, and Force’, Critical Inquiry 16 (1989), 87–112).
23 Jollimore, ‘Like a Picture or a Bump on the Head’, 132.
24 Ibid., 144.
25 Max Black, ‘Metaphor’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 55 (1954–1955), 273–294.
504 | Karen Simecek
short, organizes our view of man’.26 Developing this thought, Jollimore argues that it is
through such a filter that we may be able to come to see things that are ordinarily hidden
or at least, partially hidden. This is because the perspectival character of metaphor can help
show something as significant by bringing some elements to the centre of our awareness
(that we would not normally attend to) and leaving others at the periphery. The metaphor
offers up a particular organizational framework, which imparts a way of making sense of the
thoughts and feelings that emerge from our focus on certain features as significant in relation
to other features of the image.
When we read the poem, we are invited to see this significance in the perspective of the
poem (those things presented as the focus of attention) but through our own perspective (with
important feature of our experience of reading a poem is its ability to explore the nature
of the perspectives that underwrite certain emotional responses, that is, how a particular
organization of information can give rise to a particular emotional response.29
The experience of reading a poem can isolate elements of our perspectives (what we
believe, value, find important), in part by showing emotions emerging in contexts that
highlight just those elements without needing a narrative structure. The activity of engag-
ing emotionally with poetry can help us to explore the nature of the evaluative aspect
at the heart of our emotional experiences. Through our engagement with poetry, we
can come to see how these evaluative thoughts arise and how they are embedded in our
experiences.
29 There are a number of theories of emotion which build in something like a perspective, for instance Robert Roberts
argues that emotions should be thought of as concern-based construals, which relates to the Wittgensteinian notion
of ‘seeing-as’ (Roberts, Emotions). Bennett Helm has a strongly perspectival account of the emotions, invoking the
notion of felt evaluations, and so I will be using his theory to develop my view in relation to poetry.
30 Helm, Emotional Reason, 34. For a good sympathetic discussion of Helm’s view see Jan Slaby, ‘Emotional
Rationality and Feelings of Being’, in Joerg Fingerhut and Sabine Marienberg (eds), Feelings of Being Alive (Berlin:
De Gruyter, 2012), 55–78.
31 Helm, Emotional Reason, 71.
32 Ibid., 35.
33 Ibid., 69.
34 Helm, ‘Emotions as Evaluative Feelings’, Emotions Review 1 (2009), 248–255, at 253.
35 Jenefer Robinson, Deeper Than Reason: Emotion and its Role in Literature, Music, and Art (Oxford: OUP, 2005), 126.
506 | Karen Simecek
Helm argues that ‘something’s having import is intelligible only in light of a sub-
ject’s evaluative perspective’,36 which is shaped by a broad pattern of emotions and
judgements, rather than by any single emotional response or evaluative judgement. This
relates to my account of perspective as shaped by a set of background (or implicitly held)
beliefs, values and commitments: ‘a person normally has a single evaluative perspec-
tive instituted by the commitments he makes to import, both explicitly in evaluative
judgement and implicitly in his felt evaluations’.37 When I explicitly judge something as
something I care about, it carries normative force, therefore it will only be something
I care about if I respond emotionally in a way that is consistent with this judgement.
A single evaluative perspective therefore requires coherence between our judgements
packed buckets
of tulips, of lilies, of dahlias
the streetlights
in pieces
on the floor.
In this poem, there is a neatness and care expressed by the division of the stanzas on the
page. When we see these words laid on the page, we recognize that this is something that
has been crafted. The lack of words on the page (which almost seem like petals falling ‘in
pieces on the floor’) communicates visually that this poem is composed of compressed and
condensed language.
The space created on the page has a dramatic effect; it represents silence in which
the reader can reflect and helps intensify the experience. Every word is visually equally
weighted and so we take it that they are of equal importance to our reading experience.
The white space that surrounds the words represents the silence experienced on hear-
ing the poem. The words break the silence, which leaves us—the readers—exposed to
the violent language of the poem. The white space encourages us to focus on the images
intensely, and therefore the violent language strikes the reader as shocking. The short
stanza and line lengths act to slow down the description of the florist’s shop. This ‘slowing
down’ highlights the distinct images in the poem, which encourages us to dwell on the
images thereby enabling the reader to see the poem’s particular organizational framework
as impressing on them.
508 | Karen Simecek
The poem presents two distinct kinds of images: the flowers and the human body.
This suggests a connection between flowers and human beings, an idea which may evoke
certain thoughts, feelings, memories and associations. We then consider this connection
alongside the particular way the flowers are described. We leave aside some of those
thoughts, feelings, memories and associations that were evoked in the first instance in
order to accommodate the new thoughts, feelings, memories, and associations evoked.
The process of assimilating these elements helps to shift our perspective because it re-
prioritizes certain thoughts, feelings, memories, associations and emotions in our experi-
ence, i.e. the structure of the poem directs the reader in the ‘way to go on’ in organizing
their thoughts and feelings that arise in their experience of reading the poem.
reference to the flowers; they have disappeared from the poem. All we are left with are
the urban images of the dark of the tarmac and the streetlights—and even they are not
left undamaged, ‘in pieces/on the floor’ (32–33).
Although I have focused so far on forging connections as we read, the emergence of themes is
not a product of a linear engagement, but of how connections are forged across the whole expe-
rience itself. The poem gets the reader to move back and forth between their ideas and feelings
about people and about flowers. This is achieved by mixing human images into the description
of the flowers and focusing on aspects of the flowers that connect with human concerns, such
as a desire to reproduce. The consequence of such shifting between domains is that we do not
think about the flowers in the poem as we would ordinarily think of flowers in a florist’s shop.
are engaging with imaginatively. For instance, a narrative structure cannot capture the role of the
connection between the use of emotive words (‘bleed’) and the white space, which we respond
to immediately in addition to appreciating their wider significance. These features do not merely
occur within the imaginative space of the poem (e.g. the florist’s shop that we are imagining),
they impact on how we receive the words of the poem, before we have entered into imaginative
engagement with the work. The narrative merely provides one of a number of different pos-
sible complex organizational structures, but, crucially, such a way of organizing our thoughts in
response to the poem fails to capture the importance of the affective aspects of the poem.
There is value in attending to narratives, but only in the same way that rhythm, rhyme
and other formal features play an important role in the reading experience. We should
41 Peter Lamarque, ‘On Not Expecting Too Much From Narrative’, Mind and Language 19 (2004), 393–408, at 393,
my emphasis.
42 Gregory Currie, Narratives and Narrators: A Philosophy of Stories (Oxford: OUP, 2010), 8–9.
512 | Karen Simecek
formal features of the work in addition to any narrative present. We are responding to the poem
as an organized whole, as something to engage emotionally with, which includes the images and
aesthetics of language and is not conducted merely in an imaginative space within a story (in the
sense that we respond emotionally to imagining characters in a structured sequence of events).
By attending to how our interaction with the perspective of the poem can affect our
interpretation, we can come to appreciate the role of perspective in our understanding.
In relation to the emotions, this is important because it can help us to understand why we
respond emotionally in the way we do by revealing aspects of our evaluative perspectives.
Forging connections in a coherent and consistent way is necessary to get to an inter-
pretation of a poem. If we merely forge connections without coherence and consistency,
43 Charles Taylor, Human Agency and Language (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985), 47.
Beyond Narrative | 513
poem. This is because the poem offers a perspectively structured experience that tests the
limits of our grasp of meaning and its significance for us. For instance, in the example of
‘The Florist’s at Midnight’, our encounter with the language of the poem—with the words
and our responses to them—leads us to make sense of our emotional response in connection
with uprooted people, that is, the way the poem presents this as significant. We can only see
that there is value or significance for us if we have made sense of some action or experience,
which involves describing. The language of the poem helps to express the loss of value in
uprooting and this articulation helps us to get clearer about our own feelings. This is because
of the negative relationship between our perspective and that of the presentation of the flow-
ers: ‘Language articulates our feelings, makes them clearer and more defined; and in this way
7. Conclusion
We have seen good reason to look beyond a narrative view of the role of literature in giv-
ing insight into the nature of the emotions in favour of a perspectival view, which takes
perspective as conceptually prior to narrative. We have also seen reason to attend to the
perspectival nature of the emotions as separate from any narrative structure they may
have in order to appreciate fully the nature of the emotions.
The important feature that emerged from the discussion of both ‘The Florist’s at
Midnight’ and ‘The Butterfly Farm’ was how a poem presents the reader with a particu-
lar organization of thoughts, feelings and sense of significance—the perspective of the
work—that the reader needs to make sense of from their own perspective. Poetry can
help us to understand the nature and structure of the emotions by exploring the nature of
perspective itself; it enriches our emotional lives by allowing us to explore how our emo-
tions arise from the particular perspective we have. From this experience, we gain a sense
of how we focus and forge connections and how this affects our worldview.
Despite casting doubt on the narrative view as applied to poetry, I have shown that our emo-
tional engagement with poetry has real value. As well as helping us to have a richer experience
when reading, our emotional engagement also presents us with the opportunity to explore
different perspectives and gain an appreciation of what is involved in our emotional processes
more generally. This experience provides an opportunity to build perspectives, examine the
perspectival structures that shape our emotional responses and fine-tune our own perspec-
tives through a back and forth between our felt evaluations and evaluative judgements.45
Karen Simecek
Department of Philosophy, University of Warwick
k.d.simecek@warwick.ac.uk
44 Ibid., 65.
45 I would like to thank Eileen John, Anna Christina Soy Ribeiro, Katy Thomas, Rafe McGregor and audiences at
the European Society for Aesthetics Conference (Dublin, 2015) and the European Philosophical Society for the
Study of Emotions Conference (Edinburgh, 2015) for their helpful comments on earlier drafts. I am also grateful
for the immensely useful suggestions from two anonymous reviews of this journal.