Nas 4 PDF
Nas 4 PDF
Nas 4 PDF
2020
Torkel Opsahl Academic EPublisher
Brussels
Front cover: Sir Thomas More (1478-1535) painted by the German artist Hans Hol-
bein the Younger (1497-1543) in the late 1520s. Sir Thomas More is discussed exten-
sively in this book as a symbol of integrity in justice.
This and other publications in TOAEP’s Nuremberg Academy Series may be openly
accessed and downloaded through the web site http://www.toaep.org/, which uses
Persistent URLs for all publications it makes available (such PURLs will not be
changed). This publication was first published on 19 November 2020.
© Torkel Opsahl Academic EPublisher, 2020
All rights are reserved. You may read, print or download this publication or any part
of it from http://www.toaep.org/ for personal use, but you may not in any way charge
for its use by others, directly or by reproducing it, storing it in a retrieval system,
transmitting it, or utilising it in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical,
photocopying, recording, or otherwise, in whole or in part, without the prior permis-
sion in writing of the copyright holder. Enquiries concerning reproduction outside the
scope of the above should be sent to the copyright holder. You must not circulate this
publication in any other cover and you must impose the same condition on any ac-
quirer. You must not make this publication or any part of it available on the Internet
by any other URL than that on http://www.toaep.org/, without permission of the pub-
lisher.
ISBNs: 978-82-8348-190-7 (print) and 978-82-8348-191-4 (e-book).
Be grateful as your deeds become less and less associated
with your name, as your feet ever more lightly tread the earth.
Dag Hammarskjöld
FOREWORD BY THE SERIES EDITOR
The Nuremberg Academy Series seeks to cover relevant and topical areas in
the field of international criminal law, and includes work that is interdisci-
plinary or multidisciplinary, bringing together academics and practitioners.
Grounded in the legacy of the Nuremberg Principles – the foundation of
contemporary international criminal law – it addresses persistent and press-
ing legal issues, and explores the twenty-first century challenges encoun-
tered in pursuing accountability for core international crimes. The Series
was established in April 2017 by the International Nuremberg Principles
Academy, in co-operation with the Centre for International Law Research
and Policy (‘CILRAP’), to produce high-quality open access publications
on international law published by the Torkel Opsahl Academic EPublisher
(‘TOAEP’).
The first volume in the Series, Two Steps Forward, One Step Back:
The Deterrent Effect of International Criminal Tribunals, 1 explored the de-
terrent effect in international justice, including case studies of deterrent ef-
fect in ten situations of four different international tribunals. The second
volume, Islam and International Criminal Law and Justice, 2 focused on
Islamic perspectives and criminal law, and examined the relevancy and ap-
plicability of the Nuremberg Principles to notions of justice in the Muslim
world. The third volume in the Series, The Tokyo Tribunal: Perspectives on
Law, History and Memory, 3 presented a contemporary rereading of the In-
ternational Military Tribunal for the Far East (‘IMTFE’), combining per-
spectives from law, history and social science.
This book, the fourth volume in the Series, revisits integrity in inter-
national justice through different perspectives, addressing primarily indi-
vidual integrity within international justice institutions, but also including
1
Linda Carter and Jennifer Schense (eds.), Two Steps Forward, One Step Back: The Deterrent
Effect of International Criminal Tribunals, Torkel Opsahl Academic EPublisher (‘TOAEP’),
Brussels, 2017 (http://www.toaep.org/nas-pdf/1-carter-schense).
2
Tallyn Gray (ed.), Islam and International Criminal Law and Justice, TOAEP, Brussels,
2018 (http://www.toaep.org/nas-pdf/2-gray).
3
Viviane E. Dittrich, Kerstin von Lingen, Philipp Osten and Jolana Makraiová (eds.), The
Tokyo Tribunal: Perspectives on Law, History and Memory, TOAEP, Brussels, 2020 (http://
www.toaep.org/nas-pdf/3-dittrich-lingen-osten-makraiova).
i
the dimension of institutional integrity. The volume advances new under-
standings of integrity in international justice, and includes important poli-
cy-relevant insights. The volume is of paramount relevancy in light of the
environment of increased scrutiny of international justice institutions, in-
trospection on how institutions operate, their values and purposes, and ex-
amination of a wider commitment to effective multilateralism and a rules-
based international order.
The anthology draws on a number of papers that were presented at an
international conference organized by CILRAP and the International Nu-
remberg Principles Academy in the Peace Palace in The Hague, on 1-2 De-
cember 2018. I express my gratitude to the Nuremberg Academy and CIL-
RAP teams that made the conference possible, with the support of the
Academy’s Director as well as its Foundation Board and Advisory Council.
I am also grateful to TOAEP and especially to my co-editor of this volume,
Morten Bergsmo, for agreeing to publish the book in the Nuremberg Acad-
emy Series, and for his generous support and commitment to the topic of
integrity.
Viviane E. Dittrich
Editor, Nuremberg Academy Series
Deputy Director, International Nuremberg Principles Academy
ii
PREFACE BY THE CO-EDITORS
The seeds of this book were sowed in 1994-95 when one of its two co-
editors, Morten Bergsmo, asked himself why the team that was forming in
the Office of the Prosecutor of the International Criminal Tribunal for the
Former Yugoslavia (‘ICTY’) was characterized by such a strong and con-
structive team-spirit that lasted for almost a decade. Was it caused by the
mandate of the Tribunal? Or the circumstances surrounding its creation in
1993 by the United Nations Security Council acting pursuant to consensus?
Was it the personality of the first Chief Prosecutor, Richard J. Goldstone,
that set the tone for the team? Was it the dedication of the group of 23
United States (‘US’) prosecutors, investigators and other professionals who
had been seconded to the Office by the US government? Or perhaps the
awareness that a powerful country was supporting the work of the Tribunal?
Or was it the character of specific colleagues, such as Terree A. Bowers
(now Partner, Arent Fox) who in his former function as US Attorney in
California led an agency of more than 300 lawyers and now accepted to sit
in an open office-space as a member of one of several ICTY investigative
teams without complaining? Or was it a combination of some of these and
other factors?
At that time, the ICTY Office of the Prosecutor (‘OTP’) was doing
poorly on equitable geographical distribution of staff and had a very rudi-
mentary normative infrastructure, so diversity and strong formal ethics
framework were obviously not the factors that created the remarkable mo-
rale, sense of common purpose, and unity within the Office in those early
years. Understanding this particular period of contemporary international
criminal justice more clearly – as a positive example from which lessons
may be drawn – is important in order to assess how improvements can be
made in other international justice agencies. We are therefore very pleased
that several authors in the present anthology were involved with the work
of the ICTY-OTP at that time, including Julija Bogoeva, Andrew T. Cayley,
Hans Corell, Richard J. Goldstone, Hanne Sophie Greve, Karim A.A. Khan,
Teresa McHenry and Christopher Staker, in addition to co-editor Bergsmo.
The next step in the process to conceive this anthology occurred in
2003. Bergsmo participated in the negotiation process to create the Interna-
tional Criminal Court (‘ICC’) between 1996 and 2002, and he had been
iii
appointed the first Senior Legal Adviser of the ICC-OTP. Working together
with Klaus Rackwitz (now Director of the International Nuremberg Princi-
ples Academy), Salim A. Nakhjavani (author of Chapter 22 below), and
others, Bergsmo had led the preparatory team to establish the ICC-OTP, at
the request of the States Parties and the Advance Team. 1 By October 2003,
Bergsmo looked back to the early days of the ICTY-OTP in 1994-95, to the
monumental efforts of states between 1996 and 2002 to construct a detailed
ICC normative infrastructure, the comprehensive work programme of the
ICC-OTP preparatory team during 2002 and 2003, and the challenges that
had already arrived in the ICC-OTP in the autumn of 2003. It was apparent
that, although the process to create the ICC was led by States, more than
anything, lawyers steered the process and they had crafted a very sophisti-
cated normative framework within which the Court was being constructed.
But why was the atmosphere so fundamentally different from when the
ICTY-OTP was established? What, if anything, was lacking? Bergsmo con-
cluded that there was disproportionate attention placed on legal means, and
not enough on the integrity of the individuals who would fill the legal and
physical structures of the Court:
It is an intriguing case study of the sharp contrast between the
elaborate legal infrastructure of the ICC and the limitations of
those individuals who were elected to first run the Court. On
the one hand, the legal infrastructure was developed through a
massive, collective effort of the international community. On
the other hand, the first Prosecutor of the Court was elected in
an almost careless manner. 2
Before the end of 2003, Bergsmo resolved to undertake a broadly-
based research project on ‘integrity in international justice’, with a view to
zooming in on the role of the individual within international justice institu-
tions and individual integrity.
The next step towards the present book was taken in Nuremberg on
29 April 2017, when the anthology Historical Origins of International
Criminal Law: Volume 5 – co-edited by the Nuremberg Academy’s Direc-
1
For a detailed overview of the work of the preparatory team, see Morten Bergsmo, Klaus
Rackwitz and SONG Tianying (eds.), Historical Origins of International Criminal Law:
Volume 5, Torkel Opsahl Academic EPublisher (‘TOAEP’), Brussels, 2017 (http://www.
toaep.org/ps-pdf/24-bergsmo-rackwitz-song), in particular Morten Bergsmo, Chapter 1, “In-
stitutional History, Behaviour and Development”, pp. 1–31.
2
Ibid., p. 25. This strong statement does obviously not apply to all representatives of states
who were involved in the process, for example the German diplomats. Bergsmo was in fre-
quent contact with diplomats in the months leading up to the appointment of the first ICC
Prosecutor, in his capacity as head of the preparatory team of the ICC-OTP.
iv
tor Rackwitz, SONG Tianying, and Bergsmo – was launched during an
event in Courtroom 600, just above the permanent premises of the Nurem-
berg Academy. Section 1.6. of the book (“Hammarskjöld, Integrity and the
Election of Prosecutors”) observes that Dag Hammarskjöld (the second
United Nations Secretary-General)
saw service as “self-oblivion”, as striving towards “an unhesi-
tant fulfilment of duty”. When a team of international civil
servants recognises this higher dimension of the customary
requirement of “persons of high moral character”, it leaves no
stone unturned to make the foundations of their organisation
as strong as possible. Such recognition creates a sense of unity
of purpose, reducing the energy and time spent on conflict.
[…] If States Parties do not elect persons of adequate integrity,
a young international organisation may be stillborn for many
years and taxpayers’ money may be wasted before it meets
basic expectations of functionality. 3
It pointed out that even if a government doubts the integrity of a can-
didate for prosecutor of an international criminal court,
it may still be tempted to back him if it predicts that he will be
sympathetic to its interests, perhaps out of indebtedness for
being elected or established co-operation over some years.
Worse, a government may possess information that the candi-
date does not have the requisite integrity, but nevertheless
support him – or fail to raise objections when his candidacy is
discussed – because it expects that he will be weak or com-
promised and therefore a pliant instrument should its interests
become threatened during his term. Both modes of thinking
are short-sighted. In effect, both make a mockery of the statu-
tory requirements of “high moral character”, “integrity” and
“the highest standards of […] integrity”. If States Parties do
not take these standards for what they are – binding legal re-
quirements – we cannot expect that the high officials of inter-
national organisations like the International Criminal Court
will give them proper effect when they fill the organisation
with staff. If we want international organisations to work ac-
cording to their design, ethics cannot be an afterthought in
their construction and management. 4
The passage links the need to take integrity in international justice
more seriously, to the manner in which States Parties exercise their role in
3
Ibid., p. 30 (footnotes omitted).
4
Ibid., pp. 30–31 (footnotes omitted).
v
the election of high officials of international courts and tribunals. It places
the responsibility for failures to elect judges and prosecutors with high in-
tegrity squarely at the feet of diplomats. Three years later, in 2020, the de-
mand that the third ICC Prosecutor possess the highest integrity became a
watchword for a process that was reaching a climax around the time this
book was published. While this link between concern for integrity and the
election of the ICC Prosecutor is appropriate, it is only one part of the need
for a broader discourse on the ‘binding legal requirement’ of integrity in
international justice. The quoted passage amounted to a public statement of
intention to pursue an ‘integrity project’, which the Nuremberg Academy
and the Centre for International Law Research and Policy (CILRAP) grad-
ually resolved to undertake together, with a wider focus than simply the
election of high officials.
It was, however, the question of the ICC Prosecutor that attracted
vigorous attention a few months later in 2017, particularly with various
media revelations in October 2017 based on the hacking of an e-mail ac-
count of the first ICC Prosecutor. 5 A few weeks later, on 22 November
2017, the process was jolted by the policy brief “A Prosecutor Falls, Time
for the Court to Rise” by four directors of independent organizations work-
ing on international justice issues: Wolfgang Kaleck (General Secretary,
European Center for Constitutional and Human Rights), Alexander S. Mul-
ler (Chief Executive Officer, The Hague Institute for Innovation of Law),
William H. Wiley (Director, Commission for International Justice and Ac-
5
The media outlets included Mediapart, Der Spiegel, NRC Handelsblad, The Sunday Times,
El Mundo, L’Espresso, Le Soir, ANCIR, Nacional and The Black Sea. For their articles, see,
inter alia, Mediapart, “Former ICC prosecutor’s lucrative links with Libyan billionaire and
ex-ally of Gaddafi”, 1 October 2017 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/895f3b); Spiegel
Online, “Ex-Chefankläger Ocampo beschützte libyschen Milliardär”, 29 September 2017
(http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/bdb5ca/); The Sunday Times, “Insight: Luis Moreno Ocam-
po, war crimes prosecutor, tipped off Gadaffi crony Hassan Tatanaki”, 1 October 2017
(http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/26c605/); NRC Handelsblad, “Medewerker van Strafhof be-
taald voor lobby bij het hof”, 1 October 2017 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/b0cc4f/); Me-
diapart, “The secret double-dealing in Kenyatta ‘crimes against humanity’ case”, 6 October
2017 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/939caf/); Mediapart, “The devious manoeuvres behind
ex-Ivorian leader Laurent Gbagbo’s trial at ICC”, 8 October 2017 (http://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/0c5a22/); Mediapart, “Angelina Jolie, Omidyar et le Qatar: le cabinet cache du
procureur Ocampo”, 6 October 2017 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/ea4930/); and Media-
part, “How chief prosecutor at International Criminal Court owned companies in tax ha-
vens”, 29 September 2017 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/56cfa8/).
vi
countability), and co-editor of this volume, Morten Bergsmo (Director,
Centre for International Law Research and Policy). 6 They pointed out that
an international court will not be better than the integrity of its
leaders. The Statute of the ICC requires high integrity or
“moral character”. International prosecutors such as Richard J.
Goldstone and Louise Arbour – the first and second Chief
Prosecutors of the ex-Yugoslavia and Rwanda Tribunals –
show that this is a realistic qualification. In fact, integrity is a
legally binding requirement to serve as Judge or Prosecutor at
the ICC. States Parties are obliged to be as responsible when
they elect the next chief Prosecutor as they were during the
highly deliberate creation of the Statute in 1998. If the norma-
tive framework of the Court is its chassis, the OTP is the en-
gine. It is equally important that both function well. 7
The directors reminded us that the states that assembled in Rome’s
Capitol at the end of the ICC Diplomatic Conference “took an oath, not to
an omniscient Jupiter, god of the sky [whose temple had stood where they
met], but to an equally all-seeing humankind, pursuant to whose collective
aspirations the States claimed to act, in the name of peoples, of victims”. 8
They called for an “inquiry” by use of “external expert[s]” to help “turn
every stone to restore trust” in the Court.
It took just over two years before the Court’s Assembly of States Par-
ties ordered an external review on 6 December 2019, with the mandate to
“making concrete, achievable and actionable recommendations aimed at
enhancing the performance, efficiency and effectiveness of the Court and
the Rome Statute system as a whole, […] and submit those to the Assembly
and the Court for consideration”. 9 This Independent Expert Review (‘IER’)
delivered its final report on 30 September 2020. 10 The report amounts to a
systemic review, not an inquiry into allegations of misconduct by high offi-
6
See Morten Bergsmo, Wolfgang Kaleck, Alexander S. Muller and William H. Wiley, “A
Prosecutor Falls, Time for the Court to Rise”, FICHL Policy Brief Series No. 86 (2017),
TOAEP, Brussels, 2017 (http://www.toaep.org/pbs-pdf/86-four-directors/).
7
Ibid., p. 3 (footnotes omitted).
8
Ibid.
9
ICC, Assembly of States Parties, Review of the International Criminal Court and the Rome
Statute System, ICC-ASP/18/Res.7, 6 December 2019, para. 6 (https://www.legal-tools.org/
doc/d1fyfk/).
10
See Independent Expert Review, “Review of the International Criminal Court and the Rome
Status System, Final Report”, 30 September 2020 (‘IER Report’) (https://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/cv19d5/).
vii
cials, as explained by authors in this anthology. 11 But it is an immensely
useful report, with numerous insightful recommendations, and pages 83-
105 deal with “Ethics and Prevention of Conflicts of Interest” and “Internal
Grievance Procedures”, as touched upon in the introductory chapter below.
The policy brief of the four directors was influential also in other di-
rections. Importantly, they pointed out that formalized oversight mecha-
nisms are
not the ultimate overseer of the Court, nor is the Assembly of
States Parties. The aspirations of individuals and communities
made the Court and continue to provide its foundation. If the
leaders of the Court cannot retain their trust, their aspirations
will move on to other instruments for the betterment of hu-
mankind. 12
This broadening of the perspective influenced the more detailed con-
ceptualization of the Integrity Project of the Nuremberg Academy and
CILRAP in the months following the publication of the policy brief. It was
decided that the project would consider integrity in international justice
from more perspectives than mere codes and compliance mechanisms –
that it would also consider our understanding of integrity; historical, philo-
sophical and religious backgrounds to the evolution of the concept of integ-
rity in international justice frameworks; what builds awareness and cultures
of integrity; the roles of States, international organizations as well as inter-
national courts in increasing respect for integrity in international justice;
what (work on) specific cases can tell us about integrity in international
justice; and the relationship between the principles of integrity and inde-
pendence.
This wider approach was reflected in the policy brief “Revisiting In-
tegrity in International Justice” 13 and programme 14 of the international ex-
pert conference, which the Nuremberg Academy and CILRAP held in the
Peace Palace in The Hague on 1-2 December 2018. The presentations at the
event were made available on the project web page as films and podcasts
11
See, for example, Jan Fougner, “On Whistle-Blowing and Inquiry in Public Institutions”,
Chapter 16 below.
12
See Morten Bergsmo, Wolfgang Kaleck, Alexander S. Muller and William H. Wiley, “A
Prosecutor Falls, Time for the Court to Rise”, supra note 6.
13
See Morten Bergsmo, “Revisiting Integrity in International Justice”, FICHL Policy Brief
Series No. 93 (2018), TOAEP, Brussels, 2018 (http://www.toaep.org/pbs-pdf/93-bergsmo/).
14
The project web page contains links to the programme and related resources: https://
www.cilrap.org/events/181201-02-the-hague/.
viii
shortly after the event. 15 They have been extensively referred to by authors
in this book and used in the discourse leading up to the establishment of the
IER and the publication of this volume.
We are pleased to publish this anthology on the heels of the submis-
sion of the IER report, shortly before the Nineteenth Session of the ICC
Assembly of States Parties in December 2020. But we do not see the book
against a short-term horizon. Scrutinizing and strengthening integrity in
international justice is not a fleeting moment in the history of international
law. It should be a constant feature of the process to build an international
legal order. It is an activity and a discussion that should occur every day
within international justice institutions, and also involve outside stakehold-
ers. Our hope is that this anthology will aid such discussions – that it will
become a living reference book in international courts and tribunals, and
that it will inspire further analysis, research and writing.
Should there be sufficiently strong interest, we will consider whether
a second, expanded edition of the anthology should be published sometime
in the future. We would have liked to include even a greater variety of per-
spectives and experience in this first edition. We have deliberately invited
different views on issues, including critical contributions. It is through such
clashes of opinion that we may see the spark of truth and new ideas emerge.
Needless to say, we do not necessarily agree with all views expressed by
the authors, nor do they represent positions of the Nuremberg Academy or
CILRAP.
Two of the premises of the Integrity Project have been that individual
integrity in international justice institutions is the main focus, and that in-
tegrity is a legally binding standard in international courts and tribunals.
None of the chapters disagree with the latter, but several authors have gone
beyond individual integrity to also discuss institutional integrity. This is
understandable: the normative and systemic context of the institutions
frame the conduct of individuals serving in international courts to a consid-
erable extent. The book therefore includes both perspectives.
Considering the scarcity of international law sources on integrity in
international justice, the volume delves into a wide range of understandings
of integrity, going into philosophical, religious and cultural traditions,
viewing integrity as a moral authority, an ethical component, and a behav-
ioural norm. Beyond theoretical reflections on integrity as a concept, the
book addresses practical fringes for the implementation of integrity in in-
15
Ibid.
ix
ternational justice, while examining those actors who have a particular re-
sponsibility to uphold integrity and cultivate a culture of integrity due to
their leadership roles. The ethical-legal framework on integrity in interna-
tional justice and its relationship with independence is a cross-cutting topic
of the anthology.
We would first of all like to thank the authors who have contributed
to this volume, some of whom have spent several weeks of their time to
research and draft very comprehensive chapters. We thank the Director of
the Nuremberg Academy, Klaus Rackwitz, who has consistently supported
the Integrity Project over the past years. We also thank those who contrib-
uted to the international expert conference in The Hague in December 2018.
Furthermore, let us thank CHAN H.S. Icarus, Subham Jain and Antonio
Angotti of the Torkel Opsahl Academic EPublisher and Marialejandra
Moreno Mantilla and Marilena Stegbauer of the Nuremberg Academy for
outstanding assistance in the making of this book.
Their dedication and enthusiasm remind us that individual integrity –
or the human quality of rectitude – cannot entirely be reduced to statutory
provisions, judicial codes of ethics, or grievance and oversight mechanisms.
At the end of the day, integrity is about personal conduct and its motivation.
That is why we quote Dag Hammarskjöld in the place of the dedication of
this book: “Be grateful as your deeds become less and less associated with
your name, as your feet ever more lightly tread the earth”. 16 Hammarskjöld
was a mere 51 years old when he wrote this on 31 December 1956. He had
only served as United Nations Secretary-General for three years and eight
months at this time, and his tragic, premature death was five years into the
future. At the height of his power, he nevertheless expressed profound in-
sight into what should motivate our conduct. It is not recognition, reward,
election, appointment and promotion. By inviting us to tread the earth ever
more lightly, Hammarskjöld speaks to what should motivate our individual
service in international justice institutions (he is not suggesting that such
institutions should not leave deep footprints). 17 Several authors recognize
16
Dag Hammarskjöld, Markings, Ballantine Books, New York, 1983, p. 125. The Swedish
original – Vägmärken – was first published by Albert Bonniers Förlag AB in 1963. Dag
Hammarskjöld was Secretary-General of the United Nations Organisation from 1953 to
1961.
17
The footprints of international justice institutions are of direct relevance for legacies and
legacy building, on which there is recent literature, see, for example, Viviane E. Dittrich,
“Legacies in the Making at the ICTY”, in Carsten Stahn, Carmel Agius, Serge Brammertz
and Colleeen Rohan (eds.), Legacies of the International Criminal Tribunal for the Former
Yugoslavia: A Multidisciplinary Approach, Oxford University Press, 2020, p. 83; Viviane E.
Dittrich, “Legacies in the Making: Assessing the Institutionalized Legacy Endeavour of the
x
the importance of Hammarskjöld’s perspective in subsequent chapters of
this book. Hans Corell – former Under-Secretary-General for Legal Affairs
and the Legal Counsel of the United Nations – offers his insights in Chap-
ter 5 dedicated to “The Dag Hammarskjöld Legacy and Integrity in Interna-
tional Civil Service” and in his foreword to this volume.
Individual integrity cannot be artificially disconnected from the op-
eration of international organizations. The success of international justice
institutions depends on the individual integrity of their high officials and
staff members. If anything, the integrity-related challenges in the early life
of the ICC offer us an opportunity to realise the significance of integrity
provisions in statutory instruments of international courts and tribunals, as
we strive to strengthen these institutions and the international legal order in
the coming years and decades.
Morten Bergsmo and Viviane E. Dittrich
Florence and Nuremberg,
October 2020
Special Court for Sierra Leone”, in Charles C. Jalloh (ed.), The Sierra Leone Special Court
and Its Legacy: The Impact for Africa and International Criminal Law, Cambridge Univer-
sity Press, 2014, p. 663; and Viviane E. Dittrich, Present at the Completion: Creating Lega-
cies at the International Criminal Tribunals, book manuscript, October 2020.
xi
FOREWORD BY HANS CORELL
This book is the fruit of a remarkably interesting seminar on integrity in
international justice, co-organised by the Centre for International Law Re-
search and Policy and the International Nuremberg Principles Academy on
1-2 December 2018 in the Peace Palace in The Hague. In the seminar the
participants delivered addresses that were to be developed in light of the
discussions and published for the benefit of a wider audience. In the pro-
cess of editing these contributions the editors received additional articles.
This means that the book is now an impressive anthology that will serve as
a helpful reference book for judges, prosecutors, defence counsel, registrars
and other staff members of different kinds in international courts in the
coming years.
The book will also be of great importance for international organisa-
tions in general. A question that often comes to my mind is: why is it so
difficult to transfer wisdom from one generation to another? The book is an
important source of inspiration to facilitate the spreading of knowledge
from the past and from different religions and cultures. It contains valuable
lessons from ancient Greece and the Roman Empire via Thomas More’s
focus on the need for continuous learning in integrity to contributions from
individuals with personal experience from present day international courts
and organisations. No doubt, the anthology will broaden the readers’ per-
spectives.
The anthology also points to a central aspect in the process, namely
the importance of leading by example. One thing that I never forget from
the time when I served as a judge in my own country – see Chapter 5 on
the Dag Hammarskjöld Legacy – is the seriousness with which the senior
judges in the courts where I served carried out their daily duties. That
taught me a lesson for life. It became a lodestar for me in all my future
functions.
The book should also stimulate discussions that may lead to new or
improved codes of conduct or rules on ethics and perhaps innovative
mechanisms to ensure respect for the integrity standards. The analyses in
Part IV will be of assistance here. And, hopefully, states will realise the
great importance of giving appropriate weight to the integrity criterion
xiii
when filling positions in international courts. Another indispensable criteri-
on here, especially with respect to criminal courts, is courtroom experience.
This brings to the forefront the methods of staff recruitment in gen-
eral in international courts and other international organizations. The im-
portance of identifying individuals with the right qualifications and compe-
tences cannot be stressed enough. Ultimately, this will influence the institu-
tional integrity of the organization.
An additional advantage, resulting from the fact that the chapters of
the book will be freely available on the web in digital form, is that it should
be of great assistance in raising the awareness of the importance of integri-
ty in the courts at the national level. Therefore, national judges’ associa-
tions, prosecutors’ associations and bar associations should be made aware
of the book. This will also put them in a position to inform their members
of the same and to draw particular attention to and disseminate chapters
that are of special relevance to their profession and to their country. Anoth-
er obvious addressee at the national level is academia.
The articles in the book also make clear the connexion between Sus-
tainable Development Goal 16 on equal justice for all with its targets focus-
ing on the need for the rule of law and anti-corruption and the need for im-
plementing this goal also at the international level. In this context the re-
sponsibility that politicians have should be highlighted. Whether they serve
in the executive or the legislative branch they should find guidance in the
book.
Finally, all readers of the book will no doubt ask themselves what
lessons they can learn from its contents and come to the conclusion that it
may influence their understanding and provide guidance in their daily ac-
tivities. Against this background the book should be a must-read in wide
circles both at the national and international level.
Ambassador (ret.) Hans Corell
Former Under-Secretary-General for Legal Affairs and
the Legal Counsel of the United Nations
xiv
FOREWORD BY RICHARD J. GOLDSTONE
It was my privilege and pleasure to attend and participate in the conference
on Integrity in International Justice that was convened at the Peace Palace
in The Hague on 1-2 December 2018. This anthology is the outcome of the
papers and discussions that were held on that occasion. Morten Bergsmo
and Viviane E. Dittrich are to be congratulated for pursing this endeavour
with their usual efficiency, insight and vigour.
The integrity of any court system lies at the very core of its mission.
Without it, inevitably, there will be an absence of confidence in the judges
and the outcome of cases that come before them will be questioned. Judges
have no police or military force to ensure the implementation of their or-
ders. They must perforce rely on the respect for their decisions by the other
branches of government. Their allegiance must be owed solely to the appli-
cation of the law and adhere to an ethical code to guide their work. This
applies to all national systems of justice.
International courts are staffed by women and men from many coun-
tries around the globe. They represent different systems and traditions of
legal practice. They are required to put aside those national systems and
join a comparatively new endeavour. One of their most important tasks is
to build confidence in their new institutions and that includes abiding by a
code of ethics and a culture of integrity.
The Independent Expert Review Group appointed by the Assembly
of States Parties to review the working of the International Criminal Court
and the Rome Statute system recently submitted its report. It is significant,
in the present context, that its many findings and recommendations include
a number on “Ethics and Prevention of Conflict of Interest” and “Internal
Grievance Procedures”. I firmly believe that the present anthology will
contribute to the momentum around the tremendous importance of integrity
in international justice.
Richard J. Goldstone
Formerly, Justice of the Constitutional Court of South Africa and
Chief Prosecutor, International Criminal Tribunals
for the former Yugoslavia and Rwanda
xv
TABLE OF CONTENTS
Foreword by the Series Editor .......................................................................... i
Preface by the Co-Editors .............................................................................. iii
Foreword by Hans Corell ............................................................................. xiii
Foreword by Richard J. Goldstone ................................................................. xv
PART I:
MEANING OF INTEGRITY
1. Physically Upright, Morally Sound: Recreating Ancient ‘Integrity’ ..... 47
By Emiliano J. Buis
1.1. Introduction ................................................................................ 47
1.2. Origins of ‘Integrity’?................................................................. 48
1.3. Recreating Integrity in Classical Athens .................................... 56
1.4. Recreating Integrity in Republican Rome .................................. 70
1.5. Ancient Integrity Today: A Reappraisal of Classical Values
in Times of Moral Crisis? ........................................................... 81
xvii
2. Integer Vitae: Christian Sources and Reflections on Integrity in
Justice..................................................................................................... 85
By Hanne Sophie Greve
2.1. Introduction ................................................................................ 85
2.1.1. Definition ....................................................................... 85
2.1.2. Ethics ............................................................................. 86
2.2. Basic Concepts ........................................................................... 86
2.2.1. Human Faculties ............................................................ 86
2.2.2. Controlling Powers ........................................................ 87
2.3. The Cardinal Virtues ................................................................... 88
2.3.1. Prudence ........................................................................ 88
2.3.2. Justice ............................................................................ 89
2.3.3. Temperance .................................................................... 90
2.3.4. Fortitude ......................................................................... 90
2.4. The Theological Virtues.............................................................. 91
2.4.1. Faith ............................................................................... 91
2.4.2. Hope ............................................................................... 91
2.4.3. Charity ........................................................................... 92
2.5. Some Concluding Remarks ........................................................ 92
3. Sharí‘ah Sources and Reflections on Integrity ...................................... 93
By Adel Maged
3.1. Introduction ................................................................................ 93
3.2. Methodology ............................................................................... 98
3.3. Adab Al-Qāḍī: A Comprehensive Resource in Sharí‘ah on
the Judiciary .............................................................................. 101
3.4. Methodological Consideration Regarding the Meaning of
Adab Al-Qāḍī ............................................................................ 102
3.5. The Concept of Judicial Integrity? ........................................... 103
3.6. The Status of Sharí‘ah: An Overview....................................... 104
3.7. The Importance of Justice in Sharí‘ah...................................... 105
3.8. The Status of the Judiciary in Sharí‘ah .................................... 106
3.8.1. Sharí‘ah on the Appointment of Judges....................... 108
3.8.2. The Status of Judges in Sharí‘ah ................................. 109
3.8.3. The Gravity of the Function of Al-Qāḍī in Sharí‘ah ... 110
3.9. Qualifications of Judges in Sharí‘ah ........................................ 113
3.9.1. Prerequisite Qualifications of the Al-Qāḍī ................... 114
3.10. Meaning of Integrity in the Arabic Language........................... 117
3.11. Meaning of Judicial Integrity in Sharí‘ah ................................ 117
3.12. Why Judicial Integrity Is Significant in Sharí‘ah ..................... 119
3.13. Reflections in Sharí‘ah Sources on Judicial Integrity .............. 120
xviii
3.14. Personal Judicial Integrity of the Al-Qāḍī in Sharí‘ah ............. 122
3.15. Professional Judicial Integrity of Al-Qāḍī in Sharí‘ah ............. 126
3.15.1. Integrity and Recognised Professional Qualities ......... 129
3.15.2. Sharí‘ah Perspectives on the Emotional Integrity of
Al-Qāḍī ........................................................................ 134
3.15.3. A Proposed Definition of Judicial Integrity Derived
from Sharí‘ah Sources ................................................. 138
3.15.4. Some Indications of Judicial Integrity from a
Sharí‘ah Perspective .................................................... 139
3.15.5. Loss of Integrity........................................................... 140
3.16. Conclusion ................................................................................ 144
Appendix I: The Message of Caliph Umar Ibn Al-Khaṭṭáb
on the Judiciary......................................................................... 148
Appendix II: The Message of Alī Ibn Abī Ṭālib to Mālik Al-
Ashtar on the Judiciary ............................................................. 150
4. Sir Thomas More and Integrity in Justice ............................................ 151
By Gunnar M. Ekeløve-Slydal
4.1. Integrity Failures in International Political Institutions ............ 153
4.1.1. Biased Election Observation........................................ 154
4.1.2. Corruption in the Parliamentary Assembly of the
Council of Europe ........................................................ 158
4.1.3. Integrity Issues in International Police and Judicial
Institutions ................................................................... 160
4.2. Typology of Integrity Issues ..................................................... 167
4.2.1. Politicization or Instrumentalization of Institutions .... 169
4.2.2. Professional Integrity ................................................... 174
4.2.3. The Role of Exemplary Stories and Personalities........ 179
4.3. Civilizing Politics ..................................................................... 181
4.3.1. The Ever-Present Danger of Tyranny .......................... 183
4.3.2. The Fundamental Question of Integrity ....................... 189
4.4. More as Statesman .................................................................... 195
4.4.1. Uncorrupted Fairness ................................................... 197
4.4.2. Why Did More Hunt Heretics? .................................... 198
4.5. More’s Conflict with Henry VIII .............................................. 203
4.5.1. The Ultimate Test of Integrity ..................................... 206
4.6. More’s Integrity Lessons .......................................................... 209
4.7. Integrity in Justice .....................................................................211
xix
5. The Dag Hammarskjöld Legacy and Integrity in International Civil
Service ................................................................................................. 213
By Hans Corell
5.1. Dag Hammarskjöld on the International Civil Servant in
Law and in Fact ........................................................................ 213
5.2. The Conclusions in Dag Hammarskjöld’s Lecture ................... 216
5.3. Integrity in International Justice ............................................... 219
5.4. Dag Hammarskjöld’s Waymarks – Also Named Markings....... 222
5.5. Conclusion ................................................................................ 226
6. Multicultural Understanding of Integrity in International
Criminal Justice ................................................................................... 229
By Juan Carlos Botero
6.1. Introduction .............................................................................. 229
6.2. Judicial Integrity and Independence in the ‘Western’ Legal
Tradition – Historical Divergence ............................................ 238
6.3. Judicial Integrity and Independence in the ‘Western’ Legal
Tradition in Historical Perspective ........................................... 240
6.4. The Bangalore Principles of Judicial Conduct: A ‘Universal’
Understanding of Integrity and Independence in Justice .......... 242
6.5. A Multicultural Understanding of Integrity and
Independence as Viewed by Citizens........................................ 245
6.6. Judicial Integrity from the People’s Perspective:
Implications for the ICC ........................................................... 249
6.7. Judicial Integrity and Independence under the ‘African
Tree’: Customary Justice as Perceived by Users ...................... 251
6.8. The Bangalore Principles of Judicial Conduct and Articles
36(3)(a) and 42(3) of the Rome Statute, under the ‘African
Tree’ .......................................................................................... 256
6.9. Is There a Truly Universal Understanding of Judicial
Integrity and Independence? ..................................................... 260
6.10. People Need Justice: Integrity Also Means Timeliness ............ 265
6.11. Implications for International Criminal Justice and the ICC .... 265
7. Ethics, Integrity and the Bemba Acquittal ........................................... 269
By Shannon Fyfe
7.1. Introduction .............................................................................. 269
7.2. Individual Integrity ................................................................... 271
7.2.1. Integrity for Individual Actors ..................................... 271
7.2.2. Prosecutorial Ethics and Individual Integrity .............. 280
xx
7.2.3. Judicial Ethics and Individual Integrity ....................... 285
7.3. Institutional Integrity ................................................................ 288
7.3.1. Integrity for Institutional Actors .................................. 288
7.3.2. Integrity of the OTP ..................................................... 293
7.3.3. Integrity of the Judiciary .............................................. 296
7.3.4. Integrity of the Court and International Criminal
Law .............................................................................. 297
7.4. Case Study: The Bemba Acquittal ............................................ 298
7.4.1. Bemba Judgment and Appeal....................................... 299
7.4.2. Integrity of the Prosecutor and the OTP ...................... 302
7.4.3. Integrity of the Judges and the Appeals Chamber ....... 303
7.4.4. Integrity of the Court ................................................... 304
7.5. Conclusion ................................................................................ 304
PART II:
AWARENESS AND CULTURE OF INTEGRITY
8. Conformity, Leadership and the Culture of Integrity at the
International Criminal Court ................................................................ 309
By Brigid Inder
8.1. Introduction .............................................................................. 309
8.2. Mandate and Significance of the ICC........................................311
8.3. Credibility in Question ............................................................. 313
8.4. Relationship between the ICC and the United Nations ............ 315
8.4.1. Independence of the ICC ............................................. 315
8.4.2. Relationship Agreement............................................... 317
8.5. Building the Institution ............................................................. 319
8.5.1. ICC Staff Regulations and Rules ................................. 319
8.5.2. International Civil Servants ......................................... 322
8.5.3. Prohibited Behaviour: Sexual and Other Forms of
Harassment .................................................................. 327
8.5.4. Office of the Prosecutor ............................................... 332
8.5.5. An Enabling Political Environment ............................. 335
8.6. Ethical Challenges at the ICC ................................................... 340
8.6.1. Public Crises Exposed by the Media ........................... 342
8.6.2. Checks and Balances ................................................... 345
8.6.3. Limited Infrastructure to Support and Ensure the
Court’s Institutional Integrity ...................................... 357
8.7. Case Study: ReVision ............................................................... 360
8.7.1. Background .................................................................. 363
8.7.2. Examination ................................................................. 365
xxi
8.7.3. Exercise of the Registrar’s Authority ........................... 376
8.7.4. Duty of Care and Treatment of Colleagues.................. 378
8.7.5. Internal Oversight System ........................................... 379
8.7.6. Misleading Data ........................................................... 384
8.7.7. Governance .................................................................. 390
8.8. Conclusion ................................................................................ 395
9. Effective Leadership, Management and Integrity in International
Criminal Investigations ........................................................................ 397
By William H. Wiley
9.1. Introduction .............................................................................. 397
9.2. The Roots of International Criminal Investigative
Insufficiency ............................................................................. 400
9.3. Leadership and Management in International Courts and
Tribunals ................................................................................... 404
9.3.1. Leadership.................................................................... 405
9.3.2. Management ................................................................ 406
9.3.3. OTP Leaders, Managers and Followers ....................... 407
9.4. Institutional Loyalty ................................................................. 408
9.5. Failures of Discipline and Integrity at the ICTR, the ICTY
and the ICC ............................................................................... 411
9.5.1. ICTR ............................................................................ 411
9.5.2. ICTY ............................................................................ 413
9.5.3. ICC ............................................................................... 416
9.6. Leadership at the OTPs of the ICTY, the ICTR and the ICC ... 417
9.6.1. ICTR ............................................................................ 417
9.6.2. ICTY ............................................................................ 419
9.6.3. ICC ............................................................................... 420
9.7. Leadership, Professional Integrity and Their Intersection
with International Investigative Processes................................ 423
9.7.1. Investigators ................................................................. 423
9.7.2. Analysts ....................................................................... 424
9.7.3. Counsel ........................................................................ 424
9.7.4. Case-Building Arrangements at the ICTY and the
ICTR During Their Formative Years ........................... 425
9.7.5. Investigations Division Reforms at the Ad Hoc
Tribunals ...................................................................... 427
9.7.6. The Effective Management of Case-Building
Processes ...................................................................... 429
9.8. Conclusion ................................................................................ 429
xxii
10. Decency as a Prerequisite to Integrity in International Proceedings.... 433
By Andrew T. Cayley
10.1. Introduction .............................................................................. 433
10.2. The Prosecutor v. Radislav Krstić ............................................ 438
10.3. The Prosecutor v. Nikola Šainović, Dragoljub Ojdanić,
Nebojša Pavković, Vladimir Lazarević, Sreten Lukić and
Milan Milutinović ..................................................................... 453
10.4. Conclusion ................................................................................ 464
11. Only the Best Should Prosecute and Judge in International Justice .... 467
By Julija Bogoeva
11.1. Introduction .............................................................................. 467
11.2. The Context: These Are Not Times of Integrity ....................... 468
11.3. The Best Are Needed ................................................................ 473
11.4. Impunity of the Most Powerful Must End ................................ 477
11.4.1. Culture of Untruth and International Criminal
Justice .......................................................................... 477
11.4.2. Full Protection for Whistle-Blowers ............................ 480
11.5. Without Integrity, International Justice Is a House of Cards .... 483
11.6. Conclusion ................................................................................ 486
12. The Role of Aesthetics in Furthering Integrity .................................... 489
By Marina Aksenova
12.1. Aesthetics, Integrity and the Internal Values of International
Criminal Justice ........................................................................ 489
12.2. Theoretical Frameworks for Discussing the Role of
Aesthetics in Promoting Integrity ............................................. 494
12.2.1. Natural Law Theory ..................................................... 494
12.2.2. Visual Methodology in the Age of the Digital
Baroque ........................................................................ 496
12.2.3. The Connection Between Ethics and Aesthetics.......... 499
12.2.4. The Role of Art in Evoking the Truth-Content ............ 500
12.3. Art as a Vehicle of Transformative Change .............................. 502
12.3.1. Viewing International Criminal Proceedings as an
Aesthetic Experience ................................................... 502
12.3.2. Methodological Advantages of Using Art in the
Field of International Justice ....................................... 507
12.3.3. Practical Example of Using Art in International
Criminal Law ............................................................... 508
12.4. Conclusion .................................................................................511
xxiii
PART III:
ROLE OF INTERNATIONAL ORGANIZATIONS AND STATES
13. Institutional Ethics, Individual Integrity, and Sexual Harassment:
Recent Developments in Ethics Standard-Setting and Mechanisms
at the United Nations ........................................................................... 515
By Dieneke T. de Vos
13.1. Introduction .............................................................................. 515
13.2. The UN’s ‘Regulatory’ Ethics Infrastructure ............................ 518
13.3. The UN’s ‘Institutional’ Ethics Infrastructure .......................... 527
13.4. Ethics Infrastructure and Sexual Harassment ........................... 536
13.5. Conclusion: Redistributing Power and Culture Change ........... 548
14. Sexual Harassment ............................................................................... 551
By Matthias Neuner
14.1. Impact on Target’s Health and Thus on Work Environment ..... 552
14.2. History ...................................................................................... 553
14.2.1. International and Domestic Efforts to Define Sexual
Harassment .................................................................. 553
14.2.2. Standard-Setting Phase ................................................ 560
14.3. Evolution of the Definition of Sexual Harassment ................... 564
14.3.1. First Element: Twofold Evolution................................ 564
14.3.2. Second Element: Unwelcome ...................................... 570
14.4. Case Law on Sexual Harassment .............................................. 574
14.4.1. First Judgment on Sexual Harassment at the UN ........ 574
14.4.2. A Close Friendship with Sexual Overtones Went
Cold.............................................................................. 575
14.4.3. UNHCR Case in Budapest ........................................... 578
14.4.4. Bagot v. S-G ................................................................. 580
14.4.5. Perelli v. S-G ................................................................ 582
14.5. Superiors ................................................................................... 584
14.5.1. Acting Twofold upon Receiving Information .............. 584
14.5.2. Training in Informal Mediation to Become A ‘Role
Model’.......................................................................... 586
14.5.3. Senior Position Demands a Higher Level of
Sensitivity .................................................................... 587
14.5.4. Heads of Department, Office or Mission ..................... 588
14.6. Conclusion ................................................................................ 591
xxiv
15. Integrity and the Work of the European Ombudsman ......................... 593
By Marta Hirsch-Ziembinska and Vieri Biondi
15.1. Introduction .............................................................................. 593
15.2. Ombudsmen Institutions and the Principle of Integrity ............ 593
15.3. The European Ombudsman ...................................................... 594
15.4. Fostering the Integrity of EU Administration ........................... 597
15.4.1. The So-Called Revolving Doors Phenomenon ............ 598
15.4.2. The Transparency of the Expert Groups Advising
the European Commission ........................................... 600
15.4.3. Lobbying...................................................................... 602
15.5. Conclusion ................................................................................ 603
16. On Whistle-Blowing and Inquiry in Public Institutions ...................... 605
By Jan Fougner
16.1. Introduction .............................................................................. 605
16.2. Do Whistle-Blowing Procedures and Inquiries Constitute
Means to Guarantee Integrity? ................................................. 607
16.3. How May Such Means Effectively Achieve the End of
Inculcating the Virtue of Integrity in Justice Institutions? ........ 610
16.4. Closing Remarks ...................................................................... 612
17. Private International Criminal Investigations and Integrity ................. 615
By Alexander Heinze
17.1. Introduction .............................................................................. 615
17.2. The Occurrence of Private Investigations in International
Criminal Justice ........................................................................ 619
17.2.1. Historical Observations ............................................... 619
17.2.2. Special Focus: Private International Criminal
Investigations in Syria ................................................. 624
17.3. Advantages of Private International Criminal Investigations ... 627
17.4. Terminological Remarks........................................................... 631
17.5. Private Investigations: A Matter of Ethics and Integrity .......... 634
17.5.1. The Ethical Problem with Private Investigations ........ 634
17.5.2. Integrity as the Central Value for Private
Investigators................................................................. 641
17.5.3. Consequences for Private Investigators at the
International Level ....................................................... 732
17.6. Conclusion ................................................................................ 737
xxv
PART IV:
ROLE OF INTERNATIONAL COURTS
18. Codes of Judicial Ethics: An Emerging Culture of Accountability
for the Judiciary?.................................................................................. 741
By Bettina Julia Spilker
18.1. Introduction .............................................................................. 741
18.2. Regulation of Judicial Ethics – A Beginning ............................ 742
18.3. Codes of Judicial Ethics – Applicable Standards...................... 751
18.3.1. Preamble and Legal Basis ............................................ 752
18.3.2. Applicable Standards ................................................... 759
18.4. Codes of Judicial Ethics – Disciplinary Procedures ................. 773
18.4.1. Disciplinary Offences .................................................. 774
18.4.2. Procedure before the KSC and the IRMCT ................. 777
18.4.3. Procedure before the ICC ............................................ 783
18.4.4. Conclusion ................................................................... 788
18.5. Final Remarks ........................................................................... 790
19. Reflections on Integrity in International Criminal Justice and
Regional Human Rights Courts ........................................................... 795
By Erik Møse
19.1. Introduction .............................................................................. 795
19.2. General Remarks ...................................................................... 796
19.3. Inefficiency ............................................................................... 798
19.4. Personal Integrity – Some Illustrations..................................... 801
19.5. The Way Forward ..................................................................... 803
19.6. Final Remarks ........................................................................... 808
20. Integrity and Independence in the Delivery of Accountability:
Harnessing International and Domestic Frameworks in Pursuit of
Justice for ISIL Crimes ........................................................................ 811
By Karim A.A. Khan and Jonathan Agar
20.1. Introduction .............................................................................. 811
20.2. The Normative Integrity Framework for the Establishment
of a United Nations Criminal Accountability Mechanism........ 816
20.2.1. The Crimes of ISIL and a Response by the
International Community ............................................. 816
20.2.2. The Normative Integrity Framework of the United
Nations Investigative Team to Promote
Accountability for the Crimes Committed by
Da’esh/ISIL.................................................................. 818
xxvi
20.3. The Development and Implementation of Integrity Policies
in the Operationalization of an International Criminal Justice
Mechanism ............................................................................... 828
20.3.1. Building a Team Aligned with Principles of Integrity
and Independence ........................................................ 830
20.3.2. Integrity in Engagement with Survivors, Witnesses
and Impacted Communities ......................................... 834
20.3.3. Institutional Integrity and Independence as an
Operational Tool .......................................................... 840
20.4. Conclusion: The Central Role of Integrity in the Delivery of
Justice ....................................................................................... 842
21. The Wider Policy Framework of Ethical Behaviour: Outspoken
Observations from a True Friend of the International Criminal
Court .................................................................................................... 845
By Cyril Laucci
21.1. Introduction .............................................................................. 845
21.1.1. Five Examples ............................................................. 847
21.2. Overview of the Structure of the Internal Legal and Policy
Framework of the International Criminal Court ....................... 848
21.2.1. Instances of Non-Observance of the Terms of the
Presidential Directive of 2003 ..................................... 849
21.2.2. The Rank of the Presidential Directive of 2003 .......... 852
21.3. Main Areas of Policy Gaps and Their Potential Impact on
the Perception of Integrity at the ICC ....................................... 854
21.3.1. Selection of Staff Members ......................................... 855
21.3.2. Field Operations .......................................................... 857
21.3.3. Staff Appeal and Disciplinary Procedures, Including
the Independent Oversight Mechanism ....................... 863
21.3.4. Anti-Fraud and Whistleblowing Policies ..................... 868
21.3.5. Protection of Information ............................................ 870
21.4. Conclusion ................................................................................ 873
22. Does the International Criminal Court Really Need an Ethics
Charter?................................................................................................ 875
By Suhail Mohammed and Salim A. Nakhjavani
22.1. Introduction .............................................................................. 875
22.2. Does the Existing Ethical Framework Communicate a
“Moral Message”? .................................................................... 880
22.2.1. The Lubanga Trial ....................................................... 882
22.2.2. The Darfur Situation and the Prosecutor’s Editorial.... 884
xxvii
22.2.3. The Ruto and Sang and Gbagbo Trials ........................ 887
22.2.4. Reflection ..................................................................... 890
22.3. Entrenching the ICC’s “Moral Message” in Practice ............... 890
22.4. Double Deontology: Desperately Seeking Coherence.............. 898
22.5. What Might the External Auditor Have Hoped to Achieve? .... 901
PART V:
INTEGRITY AND THE LENS OF CASES
23. Reflections on Integrity in the Prosecution of International Cases ...... 905
By Teresa McHenry and Ann Marie Ursini
23.1. Introduction .............................................................................. 905
23.2. International Justice: Inside and Outside Perspectives ............. 906
23.3. Investigations and Resources .................................................... 907
23.4. Witnesses .................................................................................. 909
23.4.1. Witness Preparation ..................................................... 909
23.4.2. Witness Statements ...................................................... 910
23.4.3. Witness Security and Privacy ...................................... 911
23.5. Discovery and Disclosure ......................................................... 912
23.6. Institutional Ethics Advice and Support ................................... 912
23.7. Courtroom Conduct and Personnel ........................................... 914
23.8. Conclusion ................................................................................ 916
24. Individual Integrity and Independence of Judges: The Akay Saga ...... 919
By Antonio Angotti, Basil Saen and Shan Patel
24.1. Introduction .............................................................................. 919
24.2. Reflections on Questions of Integrity of the Concerned
Individuals ................................................................................ 921
24.2.1. The Akay Saga ............................................................. 921
24.2.2. Questions of Integrity for Selected Individuals ........... 927
24.3. Institutional, Professional and Personal Integrity: One and
the Same? .................................................................................. 947
25. The Disqualification of Judge Frederik Harhoff:
Implications for Integrity ..................................................................... 951
By Mohamed Badar and Polona Florijančič
25.1. Disqualification without Bias ................................................... 952
25.2. Was Judge Harhoff Really Wrong about a Change in
Jurisprudence? .......................................................................... 962
25.2.1. Specific Direction ........................................................ 962
xxviii
25.2.2. The Case of Gotovina and Joint Criminal Enterprise .. 970
25.3. Punishment for Questioning the Court’s Independence?.......... 972
25.3.1. Claims of Pressure Exerted on Fellow Judges ............. 974
25.4. Conclusion ................................................................................ 980
26. Integrity in International Criminal Law: Post-Conviction
Proceedings .......................................................................................... 983
By Gregory S. Gordon
26.1. Introduction .............................................................................. 983
26.2. Proceedings at the ICTR ........................................................... 986
26.2.1. The Prosecutor v. Nahimana: Background .................. 986
26.2.2. The Trial Chamber Proceedings .................................. 988
26.2.3. The Appeals Chamber Proceedings ............................. 989
26.2.4. Meron’s Dissent ........................................................... 992
26.3. Developments Post-ICTR Proceedings .................................... 994
26.3.1. Judge Meron’s Nomination to the MICT..................... 994
26.3.2. Nahimana’s Incarceration and Application for Early
Release ......................................................................... 994
26.3.3. Examination of the Early Release Decision ................ 996
26.4. Overall Analysis of the Early Release Decision ..................... 1003
26.4.1. Failure to Comply with MICT RPE Rules 151
and 150 ...................................................................... 1003
26.4.2. Failure to Comply with Principles of Integrity .......... 1010
26.4.3. The Integrity Deficits Placed in Perspective: The
Residual Special Court for Sierra Leone ................... 1014
26.4.4. Summary of Integrity Deficits in the Nahimana
Early Release Decision .............................................. 1016
26.5. Recommended Reforms ......................................................... 1016
26.5.1. Providing for Broader Deontological Coverage
Within the Existing MICT Governing Documents .... 1017
26.5.2. Fixing Early Release Decision Protocols and
Procedure ................................................................... 1017
26.6. Conclusion .............................................................................. 1021
PART VI:
INDEPENDENCE AND INTEGRITY
27. Judicial Independence and Accountability at International Criminal
Courts and Tribunals .......................................................................... 1027
By Ivana Hrdličková and Adrian M. Plevin
27.1. Introduction ............................................................................ 1027
xxix
27.2. The Integrity-Accountability Paradigm .................................. 1030
27.3. Judicial Independence and Accountability ............................. 1034
27.4. International Standards Regulating the Accountability of
Judges ..................................................................................... 1043
27.4.1. Early Efforts to Regulate Judicial Accountability
and Independence ...................................................... 1043
27.4.2. UN System: Towards Possible Universality .............. 1046
27.4.3. Regional Initiatives .................................................... 1048
27.4.4. Judicial Regulation in the Twenty-First Century ....... 1049
27.5. Regulating Judicial Conduct at International Criminal
Courts and Tribunals ............................................................... 1053
27.5.1. Litigation as a Means of Ensuring Accountability ..... 1053
27.5.2. Codes of Conduct and Accountability
Mechanisms ............................................................... 1057
27.5.3. The Paris Declaration: A Vision of the Future? ......... 1059
27.6. Conclusion .............................................................................. 1063
28. Prosecutorial Language, Integrity and Independence ........................ 1065
By Richard J. Goldstone
28.1. Introduction ............................................................................ 1065
28.2. The Political Pressure on Prosecutors from Outside the
Institution and Contact with Governmental Officials ............. 1066
28.3. Relationship with the United Nations Secretary-General ....... 1069
28.4. The International Criminal Tribunal for Rwanda ................... 1073
28.5. Civil Society ........................................................................... 1075
28.6. Conclusion .............................................................................. 1077
29. Integrity and the Preservation of Independence in International
Criminal Justice ................................................................................. 1079
By David Donat Cattin and Melissa Verpile
29.1. Introductory Notes: An NGO’s Perspective ........................... 1079
29.2. Towards the Inception of an International Rule of Law:
The Creation of the Rome Statute of the ICC ......................... 1081
29.3. The Statutory Requirement of Integrity: The Mere
Application of the Rome Statute? ........................................... 1082
29.4. The Preservation of Independence and Integrity at the ICC
Despite its Assembly of States Parties (ASP) ......................... 1084
29.5. Reconciling Ideals and Reality: A Functional Approach ........ 1086
29.6. Ailments Stemming from the Functioning of the ICC Are
Not a Fatality .......................................................................... 1091
xxx
29.7. Moving Forward to Protect the Integrity of the
Rome Statute .......................................................................... 1092
30. Integrity and Independence: Common Standards and Uneven Cost
of Implementation .............................................................................. 1095
By Adedeji Adekunle
30.1. Introduction ............................................................................ 1095
30.2. Ethical Gaps in the Prosecutorial Function of the Court ........ 1097
30.3. Uniform Standards of Integrity and Ethics Code ................... 1099
30.3.1. Judges .........................................................................1101
30.3.2. Office of the Prosecutor ..............................................1102
30.4. Pressures ..................................................................................1102
30.4.1. Political Pressure ........................................................1103
30.4.2. Economic Pressure .....................................................1104
30.4.3. Historical Pressure ......................................................1106
30.4.4. Socio-Cultural Pressure ..............................................1107
30.4.5. Post-Employment Pressures .......................................1109
30.5. An Ethics Compliance Mechanism ......................................... 1111
30.6. Conclusion ............................................................................... 1115
31. Integrity and the Inevitable Political Exposure of International
Criminal Justice .................................................................................. 1117
By Christopher Staker
32. Some Reflections on Integrity in International Justice .......................1125
By David Re
32.1. No International Justice System Exists ...................................1125
32.2. Some Personal National Experiences ......................................1126
32.3. The Institutions of International Justice ..................................1128
32.4. As an International Prosecutor: Some Institutional Integrity
Issues .......................................................................................1129
32.5. As an International Judge: Some Institutional Integrity
Issues .......................................................................................1131
32.6. The Political Dimension ..........................................................1133
32.7. Are There Too Many Structural Impediments to Achieve
Institutional Integrity? Some Suggestions ...............................1136
32.8. Conclusion: Cautious Optimism Tempered by Realism ..........1138
Index ...........................................................................................................1141
TOAEP Team ..............................................................................................1159
Other Volumes in the Nuremberg Academy Series .....................................1161
xxxi
______
3
See multi-disciplinary literature review surveying seven disciplines (public administration,
organizational science, sociology, political science, law, philosophy and international rela-
tions): Thomas Robinson, Lucinda Cadzow and Nikolas Kirby, “Investigating Integrity: A
Multi-Disciplinary Literature Review”, Oxford University Working Paper, May 2018.
4
See also Andrew Stark, “Public Integrity (Book Review)”, American Political Science Re-
view, 2001, vol. 95, no. 1, pp. 203-4.
5
James G. March and Johan P. Olsen, Rediscovering Institutions: The Organizational Basis of
Politics, The Free Press, New York, 1989.
6
See, for example, Peter Verheezen, “The (Ir)relevance of Integrity in Organizations”, Public
Integrity, 2008, vol. 10, no. 2, pp. 133-49.
7
Given the conceptual continuum described above, Sections 1 through 8 below deliberately
draw on elements of the Integrity Project concept paper, see Morten Bergsmo, “Revisiting
Integrity in International Justice”, FICHL Policy Brief Series No. 93 (2018), Torkel Opsahl
Academic EPublisher (‘TOAEP’), Brussels, 2018 (http://www.toaep.org/pbs-pdf/93-
bergsmo/). We are pleased that more than 40 authors have agreed to contribute within this
conceptual framework, the objective of which is to stimulate a discourse on integrity in in-
ternational justice, eventually growing into a sub-discipline of ethics of international justice.
8
Statement by the United Nations Secretary-General Kofi Annan at the Ceremony Held at
Campidoglio Celebrating the Adoption of the Statute of the International Criminal Court, 18
July 1998 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/8b0ab6/).
China, India, Russia and the United States (‘US’) are all standing
outside the ICC, watching attentively its every move, noting any weakness
that could serve their perceived future interests. 9 Anne-Marie Slaughter
claims that some of these leaders “support a return to an era of unfettered
state sovereignty. They would dismantle international and supranational
organizations of all kinds and return to multipolar ‘Great Power’ politics, in
which alliances shift and are transactional”. 10 While time may or may not
verify Slaughter’s fear, on 10 September 2018, just a few weeks after her
article was published in the Financial Times, US Ambassador John Bolton
delivered
a clear and unambiguous message on behalf of the President
of the United States. The United States will use any means
necessary to protect our citizens and those of our allies from
unjust prosecution by this illegitimate court. We will not co-
operate with the ICC. We will provide no assistance to the
ICC. We will not join the ICC. We will let the ICC die on its
own. After all, for all intents and purposes, the ICC is already
dead to us. […] We will respond against the ICC and its per-
sonnel to the extent permitted by U.S. law. We will ban its
judges and prosecutors from entering the United States. We
will sanction their funds in the U.S. financial system, and, we
will prosecute them in the U.S. criminal system. We will do
the same for any company or state that assists an ICC investi-
gation of Americans. 11
Bolton continued:
The ICC’s Assembly of States Parties cannot supervise the
Court any more than the United Nations General Assembly
can supervise the UN bureaucracy. Recent allegations of mis-
management and corruption among ICC personnel make this
perfectly clear. The first Prosecutor elected by the Assembly
9
This risk was flagged in the policy brief published on 6 August 2018 articulating the concep-
tual basis of the Integrity Project, see Morten Bergsmo, “Revisiting Integrity in International
Justice”, supra note 7.
10
See Anne-Marie Slaughter, “Donald Trump and Vladimir Putin want to create a new world
order: We should take their vision of unfettered state sovereignty seriously”, in Financial
Times, 22 July 2018. She warns in the same article that it is “incumbent upon those of us
who see an arc of progress bending towards peace and universal human rights to appreciate
the full scope of the threat posed to our 20th-century global architecture”.
11
United States, Ambassador John Bolton, Statement, Federalist Society, 10 September 2018
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/84c2b4/).
12
Ibid. (italics added).
13
United States, Department of State, Remarks to the Press, Michael R. Pompeo, Secretary of
State, 15 March 2019 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/cifgr1/).
14
United States, President Donald J. Trump, Executive Order on Blocking Property of Certain
Persons Associated With The International Criminal Court, E.O. 13928 (https://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/dfkvpn/).
15
United States, Department of State, “Secretary Michael R. Pompeo at a Press Availability
with Secretary of Defense Mark Esper, Attorney General William Barr, and National Securi-
ty Advisor Robert O’Brien”, Remarks to the Press, William Barr, US Attorney General, 11
June 2020 (italics added) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/h4dsqa/).
16
Ibid. (italics added).
17
Ibid. (italics added).
18
United States, Department of State, “Actions to Protect U.S. Personnel from Illegitimate
Investigation by the International Criminal Court”, Remarks to the Press, Michael R. Pom-
peo, Secretary of State, 2 September 2020 (applies to all three quotations in the paragraph)
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/2hljlk/).
19
See also ICC, President of the Bureau of the Assembly of States Parties, “ASP President,
O-Gon Kwon, rejects US measures against ICC”, Press release, 2 September 2020
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/xaduvf/).
20
Claus Kress, “Editorial: An Unusual and Extraordinary Assault on International Justice”,
Journal of International Criminal Justice, 2020.
21
United Nations General Assembly, “Adopting Draft Upholding International Criminal
Court’s Goal to End Impunity, Calls for Cooperation in Arresting Fugitives”, Statement by
Christoph Heusgen (Germany), seventy-fifth session, 2 November 2020, Meetings Coverage
no. GA/12280. The full statement is available on the web site of the Permanent Mission of
the Federal Republic of Germany to the United Nations.
22
United States, The American Service-Members’ Protection Act (ASPA), Title 2 of Pub.L.
107–206, H.R. 4775, 116 Stat. 820, enacted 2 August 2002 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/
9e61d9/).
23
See Carlos Vasconcelos, “Draft Regulations of the Office of the Prosecutor”, in Morten
Bergsmo, Klaus Rackwitz and SONG Tianying (eds.), Historical Origins of International
Criminal Law: Volume 5, TOAEP, Brussels, 2017, pp. 834–93 (https://www.legal-tools.org/
doc/09c8b8/).
24
See Salim A. Nakhjavani, “The Origins and Development of the Code of Conduct”, in ibid.,
pp. 964–77. See also Suhail Mohammed and Salim A. Nakhjavani, “Does the International
Criminal Court Really Need an Ethics Charter?”, Chapter 22 below.
25
Supra note 15.
26
See the conference “UN at 75: Effective Multilateralism and International Law” organized
by the UN Office of Legal Affairs and the Federal Foreign Office of Germany, 9 October
2020 (https://www.un75-berlin-international-law-conference.de).
it cannot be ruled out that the situation will get worse for the ICC and the
ICC system, and that other states will articulate positions similar to those of
the US government. We cannot take the achievements in multilateralism
during the past century for granted. It is not so long ago that Dag Hammar-
skjöld cited Nikita Khrushchev’s statement that “while there are neutral
countries, there are no neutral men”, and lamented that were this view of
the international civil servant to be proven true, “we would be thrown back
to 1919”. 27 We have no guarantee that one or more of the great powers will
not, at one stage, take a similarly dim view of international civil service,
also of international justice.
2. Conceptual Structure and Direction
However uncomfortable at times, an environment of increased scrutiny al-
so provides a welcome opportunity to revisit the role of the individual in
international justice institutions, not only the institutions and their systemic
context. This is what the Integrity Project and this book seek to do. They do
so in a forward-looking manner with a view to contributing towards pro-
gress, while cognizant of the saying that, “[t]hough talk about ethics is
cheap, silence about ethics is far too expensive”. 28 When serious integrity
problems within international courts become manifest, they tend to affect
the external reputation of and support for the institution, and erode morale
among staff. We have also seen that high-maintenance integrity problems
can lead to shifts in work priorities within the agency concerned (in at-
tempts to cover up or distract attention), thus undermining internal quality-
control mechanisms. 29 Quite apart from such crisis-management after the
damage is done, focusing on the standard and practice of integrity is an
open-ended necessity for international justice institutions, none of which is
exempted from the common challenge of professionalisation. All interna-
tional justice institutions face vicissitudes from time-to-time, as the policies
27
See Dag Hammarskjöld, “The International Civil Servant in Law and Fact: Lecture deliv-
ered to Congregation at Oxford University, 30 May 1961”, in Wilder Foote (ed.): The Serv-
ant of Peace: A Selection of the Speeches and Statements of Dag Hammarskjöld, Secretary-
General of the United Nations, 1953-1961, The Bodley Head, 1962, p. 329 (http://www.
legal-tools.org/doc/64bcae/).
28
See Deborah L. Rhode and David Luban, Legal Ethics, Fifth Edition, Foundation Press,
New York, 2009, p. 1074.
29
See the emphasis on consistency of investigation planning in Xabier Agirre Aranburu,
Morten Bergsmo, Simon De Smet and Carsten Stahn (eds.), Quality Control in Criminal In-
vestigation, TOAEP, Brussels, 2020.
of States Parties are dynamic and do not always evolve along rational lines.
The institutions require vigilance in their defence. Erosion of the ‘high
moral character’ standard indicates lack of progress as much as an ap-
proach of rigid moralism does. Both can undermine our mindful ability to
balance moral concern with a sensitivity to complex situational differences
and dilemmas.
One of the main points made by the important 1944 report “The In-
ternational Secretariat of the Future: Lessons from Experience by a Group
of Former Officials of the League of Nations” was that no “attribute is
more essential for an international secretariat than ability to gain and hold
the confidence of member Governments and of public opinion”. 30 As Hans
Corell has highlighted, “international judges are operating under the eyes
of the whole world, and the impression they give and the way in which
they perform their work will directly reflect on the standing of the institu-
tion that they serve”. 31 For this reason, he argues that “the standards that
international judges must uphold must be set even higher than at the na-
tional level”, 32 while it should be recognized, he would agree, that “judges
must first and foremost apply the law and not use it to pursue their own
ethical agendas”. 33
Against this background, this book has been conceived as a contribu-
tion towards the crystallisation of a sub-discipline of ethics of international
justice. This is ambitious, but it also reflects that ethics of law is taught as a
subject at the domestic level in several countries, in particular in the US.
The textbook by Deborah L. Rhode and David Luban 34 is an example of a
broadly-based approach at the national level. Alexander Heinze and Shan-
non Fyfe 35 have called for a more systematic approach to ethics in interna-
tional criminal justice, as do several authors in this anthology.
30
See “The International Secretariat of the Future: Lessons from Experience by a Group of
Former Officials of the League of Nations”, Royal Institute of International Affairs, London,
March 1944, p. 17 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/53ecbb/).
31
Hans Corell, “Ethical Dimensions of International Jurisprudence and Adjudication”, 10 June
2002, p. 6 (an excerpt from the report of the 2002 Brandeis Institute for International Judges)
(http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/5eb7d4/).
32
Ibid.
33
See “The Judiciary as a New Moral Authority?”, p. 3 (an excerpt from the report of the 2006
Brandeis Institute for International Judges) (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/ad4d13/).
34
See Deborah L. Rhode and David Luban, Legal Ethics, supra note 28.
35
See Alexander Heinze and Shannon Fyfe, “Prosecutorial Ethics and Preliminary Examina-
tions at the ICC”, in Morten Bergsmo and Carsten Stahn (eds.), Quality Control in Prelimi-
36
Morten Bergsmo, “Integrity as Safeguard Against the Vicissitudes of Common Justice Insti-
tutions”, CILRAP Film, The Hague, 1 December 2018 (https://www.cilrap.org/cilrap-
film/181201-bergsmo/).
Part II:
Awareness and Culture of Integrity
Organizations and States
Role of International
International Courts
Part IV:
Part III:
Role of
Part V: Part VI:
Integrity and Independence
the Lens of Cases and Integrity
Part I:
Meaning of Integrity
3. Meaning of ‘Integrity’
In international justice, the term ‘integrity’ is often used in connection with
the expression ‘high moral character’. In the ICC Statute, for example, Ar-
ticle 36(3)(a) mentions both standards, whereas Article 42(3) only men-
tions ‘high moral character’. Thus, for the purposes of the Integrity Project
both are considered legal terms. At the same time, ‘integrity’ is used as
37
Ibid.
38
See Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 9 July 2018 (https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/
integrity/).
39
See “Report on Standards of Conduct in the International Civil Service”, 8 October 1954
(http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/d94c61/).
40
See Dag Hammarskjöld, “The International Civil Servant in Law and Fact: Lecture deliv-
ered to Congregation at Oxford University, 30 May 1961”, supra note 27, p. 348.
41
See Jacques Lemoine, The International Civil Servant: An Endangered Species, Kluwer
Law International, The Hague, 1995, p. 257.
42
See Chapter 8 of his Legal Ethics and Human Dignity, Cambridge University Press, 2007.
of the law, but disregards the Global South’s ideal of justice with its em-
phasis on restoration and community harmony (he develops an ‘African
Tree’ consideration). He concludes that the legitimacy of international
criminal tribunals, particularly the ICC, could be enhanced in the Global
South by an interpretation of international criminal justice beyond what he
sees as predominantly Western perspectives.
Shannon Fyfe explores theoretical approaches to the concept of ‘in-
tegrity’ in Chapter 7 (“Ethics, Integrity and the Bemba Acquittal”). She
dwells on the ICC Appeals Chamber’s decision in the Bemba case and the
Prosecutor’s reaction thereto. Fyfe argues that this decision reflects that an
institution must not only follow integrity standards, but it should also ap-
pear to be doing so. The chapter presents an overview of integrity as identi-
ty, as wholeness and integration, and as standing for something, concluding
that the integrity of the ICC goes beyond its Prosecutor. She observes that
the individual ethical obligation of prosecutors can be understood in deon-
tological and consequentialist terms. Fyfe presents an incisive reflection on
the institutional integrity of the judiciary based on an analysis of judicial
ethics and individual integrity. She contributes normative tools to under-
stand the relationship between institutions and individuals in international
criminal law through the lens of integrity.
4. Awareness and Culture of Integrity
At the individual level, it is necessary to ask whether international civil
servants and high officials in international courts have sufficient awareness
or understanding of what ‘integrity’ and ‘high moral character’ refer to. It is
problematic if these legal terms are largely seen as slogans or empty shells
to which everyone is free to give equally valid content as may be conven-
ient. The terms require interpretation according to the same methodology
that applies to other binding language in the statute of the international
court in question, even if there is relative scarcity of relevant international
law sources.
In his biography on Dag Hammarskjöld, Brian Urquhart explains
how Hammarskjöld left a personal impression on most of the people who
dealt with him. He highlights Hammarskjöld’s “integrity, disinterestedness
and purity of intention”, 43 while never questioning his practical judgment
in matters of government, politics or international civil service. Hammar-
43
See Brian Urquhart, Hammarskjold, Harper & Row, New York, 1972, p. 33.
44
Quoted in W.H. Auden, “Foreword”, in Dag Hammarskjöld, Markings, Ballantine Books,
New York, 1983, p. vii. Fair-minded readers of Markings can hardly perceive Hammarskjöld
as naïve – he was obviously not a Brand-like character (as in the uncompromising figure in
Henrik Ibsen’s celebrated play Brand from 1866).
45
Ever since the establishment of the Secretariat of the League of Nations and the Internation-
al Labour Office in 1920, the international civil service’s performance as regards “independ-
ence from any authority external to the organization, and the highest standards of efficiency,
competence and integrity” has been “fragile and […] repeatedly called into question” (Mar-
cel A. Boisard, “Preface”, in Lemoine, supra note 41, pp. v-vi). Boisard maintains that the
preservation of these requisites “implies a continuing struggle” (ibid.).
46
Brandeis University’s International Center for Ethics, Justice and Public Life has produced
several short reports on aspects of this problematique, see the collection at https://www.
legal-tools.org?search=cajc9qcu.
47
This is elaborated by Morten Bergsmo in his chapter “Institutional History, Behaviour and
Development”, in Morten Bergsmo, Klaus Rackwitz and SONG Tianying (eds.): Historical
Origins of International Criminal Law: Volume 5, TOAEP, Brussels, 2017, pp. 25-27
(http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/09c8b8/).
48
Morten Bergsmo, Wolfgang Kaleck, Alexander S. Muller and William H. Wiley, “A Prose-
cutor Falls, Time for the Court to Rise”, FICHL Policy Brief Series No. 86 (2017), TOAEP,
Brussels, 2017 (http://www.toaep.org/pbs-pdf/86-four-directors/).
sive analysis of the case law on sexual harassment, including more than 40
judgments issued by the UN Administrative Tribunal, the UN Dispute Tri-
bunal, and the UN Appeals Tribunal. Neuner concludes that the UN efforts
to investigate and adjudicate cases of sexual harassment are decades-long
and ongoing, pursuing a ‘zero tolerance’ approach to the matter.
In Chapter 15 (“Integrity and the Work of the European Ombuds-
man”), Marta Hirsch-Ziembinska and Vieri Biondi present the role of in-
tegrity in the work and functioning of the European Ombudsman. The
chapter describes how integrity is integral to the right to good administra-
tion as enshrined in Article 41 of the European Charter of Fundamental
Rights, and how it has been implemented by the European Ombudsman in
practice. Hirsch-Ziembinska and Biondi elaborate on the European Om-
budsman’s efforts to ensure transparency and accountability. These efforts
include addressing potential and actual conflicts of interest while being
mindful of the so-called ‘revolving doors’ phenomenon, ensuring the trans-
parency of the expert groups advising the European Commission, and the
maintenance of transparent and well-regulated lobbying. The chapter con-
cludes that the European Ombudsman places respect for integrity near the
concept of good administration, ensuring the integrity of EU institutions in
a reactive and safeguarding manner.
Whistleblowing and its implementation procedures in public institu-
tions are explored by Jan Fougner in Chapter 16 (“On Whistle-Blowing
and Inquiry in Public Institutions”). He argues that whistle-blowing is con-
ducive to eradicating misconduct, as it introduces a culture of transparency
and freedom of expression. Fougner highlights that whistle-blowing proce-
dures and private inquiries as ways to ensuring integrity and fighting mis-
conduct and unethical behaviour also in the judiciary. Implementation of
whistle-blowing procedures and appropriate mechanisms to combat corrup-
tion and violations of professional and ethical standards is, however, essen-
tial to preserve integrity. For Fougner, such implementation seeks to create
conduct of openness and deterrence of wrongdoing, but it will ultimately
depend on the institution’s willingness. He closes by arguing that the ICC
should implement such mechanisms, in order to impede absolute power,
hinder corruption, and re-establish the virtue of integrity.
In Chapter 17 (“Private International Criminal Investigations and In-
tegrity”), Alexander Heinze offers a comprehensive analysis of private in-
ternational criminal investigations and integrity. He examines their previ-
ous occurrences and advantages (such as efficiency and immediacy), and
49
A statement of the Women’s Initiatives for Gender Justice expressed concern that media
revelations about the first ICC Prosecutor “could be considered emblematic of an underlying
culture within the Court, rather than exceptional to the overall environment”, see “A critical
time for the ICC’s credibility”, 12 October 2017 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/e2fbc7/)
(italics added). It observed that this “is an important moment for the ICC’s evolution as a
permanent court built for longevity, worthy of public trust and focused on the ethical fulfil-
ment of its mandate”.
50
This paraphrases Deborah L. Rhode, “Where is the Leadership in Moral Leadership?”, in
idem (ed.), Moral Leadership: The Theory and Practice of Power, Judgment, and Policy,
John Wiley & Sons, San Francisco, 2006, pp. 22-33.
51
See the influential report “The International Secretariat of the Future: Lessons from Experi-
ence by a Group of Former Officials of the League of Nations”, supra note 30, p. 61. The
bracketed word “integrity” replaces “loyalty” in the original.
52
In a statement, the International Criminal Court Bar Association (‘ICCBA’) observes that the
first ICC Prosecutor, “as a former elected official, falls outside the IOM’s investigative
mandate”, see “ICCBA Statement on Allegations Against Former ICC Prosecutor”, 29 No-
vember 2017 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/a8cdcb/).
might impact the upholding of integrity at the ICC. In doing so, Laucci
elaborately reflects on the administrative and labour law frameworks in
place at the ICC, practically assessing their gaps and subsequent impacts
on the staff and recruitment policies, particularly those concerning the se-
lection of staff members, the conditions of field operations, disciplinary
procedures, anti-fraud and whistle-blowing policies, and the protection of
information. The chapter argues that whereas strong legal and policy
frameworks alone are not a guarantee of integrity, gaps are pitfalls for in-
tegrity and ethical behaviour within the institution. For this reason, the in-
stitution needs to provide guidance in line with its duty of care.
The question whether the ICC really needs an ethics charter is the fo-
cus of the reflections by Salim Nakhjavani and Suhail Mohammed in
Chapter 22 (“Does the International Criminal Court Really Need an Ethics
Charter?”). The chapter critically assesses the external auditor’s 2018 rec-
ommendations on the need for a new ethics charter by highlighting the ex-
istence of six codes of ethical and professional conduct at the ICC. Arguing
that the problem lies in that transmission does not imply reception, the au-
thors examine whether the ICC’s existing ethical framework communicates
a ‘moral message’, considering specific incidents arising during the
Lubanga trial, some actions by the Prosecutor in the Darfur situation, and
the Ruto and Sang and Gbagbo trials. Concluding that the ‘moral message’
is already present in the ICC’s ethical framework, the authors further re-
flect on its permeation at the level of culture. They conclude that the adop-
tion of an additional ethics charter might be counter-productive or self-
defeating because of double deontology, arguing that the real question is on
the implementation of such ethical framework, which calls for an honest
reading of the reality at the level of culture and persistent conversations on
ethics among the Court’s staff.
7. Integrity and the Lens of Cases
Part V contains four chapters which either look at specific cases notorious
for how they engage issues of integrity, or consider how integrity relates to
some central, case-related work-processes in international courts. The au-
thors chose to focus on certain cases, which had already been the object of
much scrutiny and outside commentary in the media and public arena. It is
clear that more cases deserve attention and more careful analysis is needed
at any given international court or tribunal and also across courts and tribu-
53
Lemoine, The International Civil Servant: An Endangered Species, supra note 41, p. 54.
54
There are two sides to instrumentalisation of such feelings of indebtedness: “international
civil servants are, as much as governments, guardians of their own integrity”, see ibid., p. 47.
“[U]sing knowledge and skills acquired by virtue of official position to concoct tactical
moves” in “connivance with national authorities […] is not unknown”, see ibid., pp. 58-59,
where he continues: “Lobbying, approaching delegations in an unofficial and unauthorized
capacity, is another failing some international officials are prone to”.
theless, they caution that the Assembly must perform its tasks of proper
oversight, and restate the system of nomination and elections of judges and
prosecutor recommended by Parliamentarians for Global Action.
Adedeji Adekunle provides reflections on the standards and chal-
lenges on integrity and independence at the ICC in Chapter 30 (“Integrity
and Independence: Common Standards and Uneven Cost of Implementa-
tion”). Even though the concepts of integrity and impartiality are consid-
ered universal and necessary in international justice, Adekunle argues that
the cultural, social or economic background or orientation of the diverse
staff may play a role in their understanding and implementation. Consider-
ing this potential dissonance, he emphasizes the need for evenness and ob-
jectivity in enforcement, implying codification and a clear understanding
thereof through the proper contextualization of the concepts as part of an
institutional framework of beliefs and norms. Adekunle perceptively con-
strues the different types of threats and pressures faced by prosecutors,
judges and other staff at international criminal justice institutions that
might require additional guidance to be dealt with, such as political, post-
employment, economic, socio-cultural and even historical pressure. He
concludes by suggesting an ethics compliance mechanism at the ICC be-
yond the Independent Oversight Mechanism that may reflect practices such
as the EU Ombudsman or the UN Ethics Office.
Christopher Staker offers personal reflections addressing the anathe-
ma of political exposure of international criminal tribunals in Chapter 31
(“Integrity and the Inevitable Political Exposure of International Criminal
Justice”). While political influence in the judiciary is generally condemned,
Staker argues that this exposure is necessary when the totality of criminal
justice is considered. International criminal justice is probably more vul-
nerable to such influence given the role of states as sovereign decision-
makers. ICC proceedings are often marked by political decisions made by
states – from the triggering of the Court’s jurisdiction, to withdrawal from
the Statute. States might also seek to persuade the Court regarding prosecu-
torial policies. Bearing in mind the unavoidability of the Court’s political
exposure, Staker notes that a common understanding of the appropriate role
of political decision-makers and its limitations is required for prosecutors
and judges to know in light of their independence and integrity.
In concluding Chapter 32 (“Some Reflections on Integrity in Interna-
tional Justice”), Judge David Re rounds off Part VI of this anthology with
an appropriately sober analysis of the systemic factors that make it more
ficials of international courts – are public figures and their work should
therefore be subjected to direct critical review. That comes with the job and
this is one of the reasons why such high officials are highly remunerated. In
order to execute their weighty responsibilities under the statutory instru-
ments of international courts, the States Parties need to be assisted by clear-
ly articulated, critical assessments that are not artificially constrained by
fear of sanction or a desire to be cited in decisions or submissions. It is in
the institutional interest of international courts that critical analysis not be
impeded by a deference which may be appropriate within legal fraternities
and their practice, but do not apply in the same way outside. As it turns out,
the high officials who are mentioned by some authors in this anthology are
in most cases so accomplished that their long-standing merits and
achievements are well established.
Integrity is certainly lamented if it is seen as missing. It is also often
referred to when discussing prescriptions for institutional reform. Interest
in the integrity and ethics of governance has increased significantly in the
last years, given a growing commitment of international organizations to
fight corruption and safeguard integrity. More recently, the International
Bar Association’s ‘2019 International Principles on Conduct for the Legal
Profession’ sets out ten relevant principles for legal professionals to guide
their professional duties, including independence, honesty, integrity and
fairness. 56 Committees and conferences are organized and full-blown integ-
rity programmes created. 57 Networks and institutional bodies and policies
with an explicit focus on integrity are established. For example, the
UNODC’s Global Judicial Integrity Network was officially established in
Vienna in April 2018. In March 2020, over 700 participants from 118 coun-
tries and 50 judicial associations and organizations, met for a high-level
event of the Network. This shows the interest in integrity-related topics and
the appeal of sharing experiences. Another example beyond the judicial
arena is the High Level Panel on International Financial Accountability,
Transparency and Integrity for Achieving the 2030 Agenda launched in
56
See International Bar Association, IBA International Principles on Conduct for the Legal
Profession, approved on 25 May 2019 by the Council of the International Bar Association
(available on the IBA web site).
57
Integrity programmes may include various measures, such as a code of conduct, an integrity
office(r), integrity training, whistle-blowing procedures, policies for misconduct, and pre-
employment screening. See, for example, Alain Hoekstra and Muel Kaptein, “The Integrity
of Integrity Programs: Toward a Normative Framework”, Public Integrity, 7 July 2020,
pp.1-13.
April 2020 by the Presidents of the UN General Assembly and the Eco-
nomic and Social Council. Furthermore, NATO’s Building Integrity Pro-
gramme has been in place since 2007 and a Building Integrity Policy has
been endorsed since 2017. Put simply, a key challenge often observed is
getting from talking the talk to walking the walk.
In his Foreword to this book, Justice Richard J. Goldstone refers to
the final report of the Independent Expert Review Group (‘IER’) appointed
by the Assembly of States Parties to review the working of the International
Criminal Court and the Rome Statute system, and his hope that “the present
anthology will contribute to the momentum around the tremendous im-
portance of integrity in international justice” (see above). As described in
our Preface to this book, the Assembly’s 2019 establishment of the IER
mandate 58 followed a recommendation at the early stages of the Integrity
Project. On 30 September 2020, the IER published its final report, which
runs to 348 pages and includes 384 recommendations, of which 76 are
summarised as “prioritised recommendations” in Annex I. 59
Following a description of its terms of reference, 60 the IER report
first addresses Court-wide matters, such as governance, human resources,
ethics and prevention of conflicts of interest, and internal grievance proce-
dures; before addressing organ-specific matters of Chambers, the Office of
the Prosecutor and Registry, delving into their working methods, the Code
of Judicial Ethics, defence-related matters and victim participation, repara-
tions, and assistance. The report also examines matters such as the Court’s
external governance, oversight bodies and mechanisms, and the system of
nomination of judges.
The notion of integrity – its different meanings and relevancy for the
legitimacy of international justice institutions – is visible throughout the
report, particularly where ethical and appropriate behaviour is discussed.
The report states that “ethics has been identified as an important topic for
58
See, ICC, Assembly of States Parties, Review of the International Criminal Court and the
Rome Statute system, ICC-ASP/18/Res.7, 6 December 2019 (https://www.legal-tools.org/
doc/d1fyfk/). The task was assigned to a Group of Independent Experts comprised of nine
members and chaired by Justice Richard J. Goldstone, who has also contributed Chapter 28
below (“Prosecutorial Language, Integrity and Independence”).
59
See Independent Expert Review, “Review of the International Criminal Court and the Rome
Status System, Final Report”, supra note 2, p. 331 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/cv19d5/).
60
Review of the International Criminal Court and the Rome Statute system, ICC-ASP/
18/Res.7, 6 December 2019, Annex I, p.4 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/d1fyfk/).
61
IER report, supra note 2, para. 254.
62
Ibid..
63
Ibid., para. 255.
64
Ibid., paras. 265-268, 284-289.
65
Ibid., para. 72.
66
Ibid., paras. 63, 72-74, 298.
The integrity of any court system lies at the very core of its
mission. Without it, inevitably, there will be an absence of
confidence in the judges and the outcome of cases that come
before them will be questioned. Judges have no police or mili-
tary force to ensure the implementation of their orders. They
must perforce rely on the respect for their decisions by the
other branches of government. Their allegiance must be owed
solely to the application of the law and adhere to an ethical
code to guide their work. This applies to all national systems
of justice.
Corruption or other forms of integrity-deficit in a justice system,
whether actual or perceived, is potentially fatal. Doubts about integrity can
delegitimize and paralyze organizations and individuals – even institutions
whose mandate enjoys broad public support can become overwhelmed by
critique. Indeed, it is discernible that the integrity performance of interna-
tional justice has come to weigh directly on the will of states to further
strengthen the rule of international law. 67
Strengthening the culture of integrity is important to prevent integrity
violations and, when they do occur, to address them effectively. Integrity,
impartiality and independence are core requirements for a functioning, ef-
fective, and meaningful judiciary or justice system. Using accountability is
also necessary to restore public confidence in justice institutions where
there has been erosion. There is an expectation of acknowledgment of what
went wrong – often referred to as truth-telling in international criminal jus-
tice – and that one or more individuals take responsibility or are held ac-
countable. This is all the more important for international justice institu-
tions which depend on the continued support of a diverse group of States
Parties, the public, and victims of wrongdoing.
Nurturing integrity within international justice institutions requires
careful and critical contemplation on the functioning of institutions, values,
rules and purposes, and a wider commitment to the international legal order.
Such introspection is not easy, but there would seem to be a direct interest
for international lawyers and high officials within and around these courts
to do so, with a view to improving the institutions from within and ena-
67
Performance of international courts is being subjected to more scrutiny, see Theresa Squatri-
to, Oran R. Young, Andreas Føllesdal and Geir Ulfstein, The Performance of International
Courts and Tribunals, Cambridge University Press, 2018; Stuart Ford, “How Much Money
Does the ICC Need?”, in Carsten Stahn (ed.), The Law and Practice of the International
Criminal Court, Oxford University Press, 2015.
68
Rhode and Luban, supra note 28, p. 1074.
69
Salim A. Nakhjavani and Suhail Mohammed, “Does the International Criminal Court Really
Need an Ethics Charter?”, Chapter 22 below (italics added).
70
Ibid. (footnotes omitted; italics added).
71
The sentence in the Judgment reads: “Crimes against international law are committed by
men, not by abstract entities, and only by punishing individuals who commit such crimes
can the provisions of international law be enforced”, see International Military Tribunal,
Judgment, 1 October 1946 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/f21343/).
72
See Jan Fougner, “On Whistle-Blowing and Inquiry in Public Institutions”, Chapter 16 be-
low. See also the Norwegian Helsinki Committee, Letter to the President of the Bureau of
the Assembly of States Parties of the International Criminal Court, 26 October 2020 (https://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/jo7vkx/).
73
See Dieneke T. de Vos, “Institutional Ethics, Individual Integrity, and Sexual Harassment:
Recent Developments in Ethics Standard-Setting and Mechanisms at the United Nations”,
Chapter 13 below.
74
See Morten Bergsmo, “Integrity as Safeguard Against the Vicissitudes of Common Justice
Institutions”, CILRAP Film, The Hague, 1 December 2018 (https://www.cilrap.org/cilrap-
film/181201-bergsmo/).
75
Ethics and integrity as moral virtues and philosophical concepts have recently been revisited
as the foundations of international justice. See Amartya Sen, “Ethics and the Foundation of
Global Justice”, in Ethics and International Affairs, 2017, vol. 31, no. 3, pp. 261-270; Ste-
ven Ratner, “Ethics and International Law: Integrating the Global Justice Project(s)”, in In-
ternational Theory, 2013, vol. 5, no. 1, pp. 1-34.
76
See Martti Koskenniemi, The Gentle Civilizer of Nations: The Rise and Fall of International
Law 1870-1960, Cambridge University Press, 2002.
1.1. Introduction
In recent times, international justice has been the object of harsh criticism.
The question concerning the ways to overcome this disapproval is a com-
plex one. In any case, it seems quite clear that, in times of institutional cri-
sis, a good bottom-up starting point is reassessing the role of those individ-
uals who are personally involved in international tribunals. The standard
and practice of ‘integrity’ become therefore an essential threshold to im-
prove the proper functioning of courts and organizations; it is of the utmost
importance to raise awareness about the high moral character that is (or
should be) required when electing or appointing professionals expected to
hold public office. 1 And, in this vein, a historical approach to the meaning
of ‘integrity’ is essential. We are much better placed to discuss the sensi-
tivities of ethical principles if the ancient values underlying our modern
conception are properly understood.
The purpose of this chapter is to understand the logics behind the no-
tion of ‘integrity’ in ancient Greece and Rome – including terminology and
*
Emiliano J. Buis received his Ph.D. from the University of Buenos Aires, Argentina, and is
Professor of Public International Law, International Humanitarian Law, the Origins of Inter-
national Law in Antiquity and Ancient Greek Language and Literature at the University of
Buenos Aires and the Central National University in Azul, Argentina. He is also a Research-
er at the National Research Council for Science and Technology (CONICET). He is a former
fellow at the Department of Classics, Brown University, the Max-Planck Institut für euro-
päische Rechstgeschichte, the Harvard University Center for Hellenic Studies, the Alexander
S. Onassis Public Benefit Foundation, the Center for Epigraphical and Paleographical Stud-
ies (Ohio State University), and the Center for Hellenic Studies at Princeton University. I
wish to thank Morten Bergsmo, Viviane Dittrich and all the organizers, speakers and partici-
pants at the international expert conference on ‘Integrity in International Justice’ (Peace Pal-
ace, The Hague, 1-2 December 2018), for their extremely useful comments and suggestions.
I am indebted to all of them. All mistakes and inexactitudes which remain in the text are ob-
viously my own.
1
Morten Bergsmo, “Revisiting Integrity in International Justice”, FICHL Policy Brief Series
No. 93 (2018), Torkel Opsahl Academic EPublisher, Brussels, p. 1 (http://www.toaep.org/
pbs-pdf/93-bergsmo).
semantical scopes – taking into account its rhetorical elements. In the con-
text of the project conference held in The Hague and this edited volume
dealing with integrity in international justice, my aim here is to offer a suc-
cinct introduction to the physical and moral, and thus, political, dimensions
of integrity in some Greek and Latin texts that can be relevant to appreciat-
ing its implications. In that sense, although there does not seem to be in
antiquity a single notion that can deliver the complex meaning of integrity,
my intention is to explain how ancient sources dealing with physical and
ethical values may contribute to a better understanding of the multifaceted
relationship between integrity and the administration of justice today.
The first part of my chapter will deal with the pre-classical image of
justice and rightness as related to truth, which becomes relevant when ex-
ploring the nature of ethical integrity. Ancient texts show a close associa-
tion between telling lies and corruption, which would be later developed in
the politics of integrity laid in classical Greek and Roman testimonies, as
examined in the second and third part of the chapter. In my conclusions, I
will reveal why I believe that revisiting these pre-Christian sources be-
comes a useful exercise in the quest for a comprehensive view of integrity
as a key concept in modern international law.
1.2. Origins of ‘Integrity’?
In a ground-breaking book published in Paris in 1967, Marcel Detienne
focused his attention on what he called the ‘masters of truth’ (les maîtres de
vérité) in archaic Greece. He stated that figures of authority such as the
prophet, the poet, and the king-judge, always spoke the truth because they
represented the voice of the gods; an inspired ruler could never act in a
wrongful manner. According to this reading, in pre-classical times, these
three leading figures – the diviner, the bard, and the king of justice – shared
the privilege of dispensing truth purely by virtue of their qualities: they
could tell ‘what was’, ‘what is’ and ‘what will be’ because of their posses-
sion of a similar type of speech. By means of the religious power of
memory, Mnemosýne, they had direct access to the divine authority. 2
In ancient Greece, the notion of truth (ἀλήθεια, alétheia) was directly
related to justice (δίκη, díke), since it asserted a parole efficace which con-
2
Marcel Detienne, Les maîtres de la vérité dans la Grèce archaïque, Maspero, Paris, 1967,
pp. 15–16.
tributed to the creation of the world. 3 In the archaic world, the judicial sen-
tences, or θέμιστες (thémistes), were possessed by the king, who acted as
judge and had been granted authority directly through a divine agent. 4 The
judicial word, in this context, constituted an authorized statement about
good and evil: the judge, inspired or plunged into enthousiasmós, simply
dictated a verdict that was enunciated to his mind by a higher power. Sen-
tences, far from constituting a human manifestation, derived from the ex-
clusive will of the gods – they were a means of reproducing Olympic deci-
sions among mortals. 5
This close contact between judicial activity and religious support led
Louis Gernet, one of the most recognized experts in Greek legal anthropol-
ogy, to postulate a strong bond between legal institutions and ritualism,
based on what he denominated pre-law (pré-droit). In that context, deci-
sions pronounced by a king-judge – through whom the gods expressed
themselves – had the character of obscure revelations or self-imposing ora-
cles. 6 It was because of the association with the goddess Thémis (a divinity
usually related to oracular discourse) that the discussion of law (θέμις,
3
Jean-Pierre Levet, Le vrai et le faux dans la pensée grecque archaique, Étude de vocabulaire,
Les Belles Lettres, Paris, 1976, pp. 1–3, points out that in Greek the notion of truth is ex-
pressed through terms presented as negative: the most frequent words – the adjective ἀληθής
and the noun ἀλήθεια (lit. ‘lack of remembrance’) – show that obtaining the truth implied
etymologically a concrete activity destined to unveil, to get out of oblivion, to bring some-
thing to memory as an act of justice. From that place, then, ἀ-λήθεια conceptually implies an
active movement and expresses a step of discovery: the truth does not seem to be given in
the abstract for its knowledge or apprehension. From the pre-philosophical thinking of the
archaic world onwards, the notion of truth has been associated with discourse, stories, and
verbal expression of thought. I have explored the notiong of legal truth in ancient Greece el-
sewhere; see Emiliano J. Buis, “Ficciones y p(ersu)asiones de la verdad: la retórica judicial
de la alétheia en el derecho griego arcaico y clásico”, in Germán Sucar and Jorge Cerdio
Herrán (eds.), Derecho y verdad II “Genealogía(s)”, Tirant lo Blanch, Madrid, 2015,
pp. 247–320.
4
Henry Sumner Maine, Ancient Law. Its Connection with the Early History of Society and its
Relation to Modern Ideas, John Murray, London, 1861, considered with certain exaggera-
tion that every single aspect of ancient law was dependent, in its first manifestations, on di-
vine authority.
5
Karl-Joachim Hölkeskamp, Schiedsrichter, Gesetzgeber und Gesetzgebung im archaischen
Griechenland, Franz Steiner, Stuttgart, 1999.
6
Louis Gernet, “Droit et pré-droit en Grèce ancienne”, in L'année sociologique, 1951, no. 3,
pp. 21–119.
7
On thémis and its relationship to its particular statutes (thémistes), see Jean Rudhardt, Thé-
mis et les Hôrai. Recherches sur les divinités grecques de la justice et de la paix, Droz, Ge-
nève, 1999.
8
Arnaldo Biscardi, Diritto Greco Antico, Giuffrè, Milano, 1982, pp. 352–354, argues that
thémistes were public expressions of the ineluctable will of the gods.
9
Here and elsewhere, the Greek text of Hesiod and its translation are taken from Hugh G.
Evelyn-White, Hesiod. The Homeric Hymns and Homerica, Harvard University Press and
William Heinemann, Cambridge (MA) and London, 1914.
as presented in epic poetry. 10 In Book XVI of the Iliad, for instance, Pa-
troclus fails to comply with Achilles’ request to return to the ships. Instead,
he attacks the Trojans, forcing them to escape. The snorts of the horses of
the enemies fleeing from Patroclus are compared, with a typically Homeric
simile, with the excess of those who sentenced incorrectly and deserved
divine punishment (Iliad XVI.384-393):
ὡς δ᾽ ὑπὸ λαίλαπι πᾶσα κελαινὴ βέβριθε χθὼν
ἤματ᾽ ὀπωρινῷ, ὅτε λαβρότατον χέει ὕδωρ
Ζεύς, ὅτε δή ῥ᾽ ἄνδρεσσι κοτεσσάμενος χαλεπήνῃ,
οἳ βίῃ εἰν ἀγορῇ σκολιὰς κρίνωσι θέμιστας,
ἐκ δὲ δίκην ἐλάσωσι θεῶν ὄπιν οὐκ ἀλέγοντες
τῶν δέ τε πάντες μὲν ποταμοὶ πλήθουσι ῥέοντες,
πολλὰς δὲ κλιτῦς τότ᾽ ἀποτμήγουσι χαράδραι,
ἐς δ᾽ ἅλα πορφυρέην μεγάλα στενάχουσι ῥέουσαι
ἐξ ὀρέων ἐπικάρ, μινύθει δέ τε ἔργ᾽ ἀνθρώπων˙
ὣς ἵπποι Τρῳαὶ μεγάλα στενάχοντο θέουσαι.
As the whole dark earth bows before some tempest on an au-
tumn day, when Zeus rains his hardest to punish men for judg-
ing crookedly in their courts, and arriving justice there from
without heed to the decrees of heaven – all the rivers run full
and the torrents tear many a new channel as they roar head-
long from the mountains to the dark sea, and it fares ill with
the works of men – even such was the stress and strain of the
Trojan horses in their flight. 11
10
On the debates surrounding justice in archaic Greece, see Michael Gagarin, “Dikē in Archaic
Greek Thought”, in Classical Philology, 1974, no. 69, pp. 186–197; Matthew W. Dickie,
“Dike as a moral term in Homer and Hesiod”, in Classical Philology, 1978, no. 73, pp. 91–
101; Joanna Janik, “Dike and themis in the works of Homer”, in Eos, 2000, no. 87, pp. 5–31,
and more recently Christos Antypas, “Dike in a pre-polis society: the evidence from Homer-
ic epic”, in Menelaos Christopoulos and Machi Païzi-Apostolopoulou (eds.), Crime and
Punishment in Homer and Archaic Epic (Proceedings of the 12th international Symposium
on the Odyssey, Ithaca, September 3-7, 2013), Center for Odyssean Studies, Ithaca, 2014,
pp. 39–46. A study on the vocabulary of justice in archaic Greek literature can be found in
Joanna Janik, Terms of the Semantic Sphere of δίκη and θέμις in the Early Greek Epic (Stud-
ies of the Commission on Classical Philology, vol. 30), PAU, Krakow, 2003.
11
The Greek text has been taken from A.T. Murray, Homer. The Iliad, Cambridge
(MA)/London, Harvard University Press/William Heinemann, 1924. The translation corre-
sponds to Samuel Butler, The Iliad of Homer, Longmans, Green & Co., London, 1898.
Set in the agora – the public square understood as a space for verbal
exchange 12 – the image contained in these verses describes those who solve
cases against the guidelines established by the gods. These men alluded in
the passage are the Homeric kings (βασιλῆες, basilées) who were in charge
of the task of imparting justice. Achilles himself had mentioned them be-
fore (Iliad I.237-239), asserting that the sons of the Achaeans behaved as
administrators of justice (δικασπόλοι, dikaspóloi) and were guardians of
the decrees of Zeus (θέμιστας πρὸς Διὸς, thémistas pròs Diòs). Since the
agora was the open area in which men proclaimed their statements (as can
be seen in the verb ἀγορεύειν, agoreúein, ‘to give a speech’), and this abil-
ity to judge may imply telling the truth or lying, those kings who behaved
in an excessive manner, who issued unjust sentences, were frowned upon
by the angered gods. To pronounce crooked decisions meant, in short, to
advocate for a lack of truth and thus represented a disruption of the magi-
cal-religious continuity that pervaded the archaic vision of truth-telling as a
result of endorsing the will of the gods. Human rulers, through their speech,
were therefore able to alter the will of Zeus. They could behave incorrectly,
breaking the inherent link between justice and truth, hence endorsing cor-
rupted decisions. When judging according to their own interests or lying to
the people, they could walk away from the path of divine justice.
Another passage in the Iliad is relevant to complement these reflec-
tions. When Achilles’ shield is depicted in Book XVIII, the poem mentions
the representation of two cities in the centre, one in peace and the other be-
sieged by enemies. In the first of the two póleis, the daily scenes that were
crafted by Hephaestus are described in detail: on the one hand, weddings
and parties; on the other hand, a judicial process mentioned in the follow-
ing terms (Iliad XVIII.497-508):
λαοὶ δ᾽ εἰν ἀγορῇ ἔσαν ἀθρόοι· ἔνθα δὲ νεῖκος
ὠρώρει, δύο δ᾽ ἄνδρες ἐνείκεον εἵνεκα ποινῆς
ἀνδρὸς ἀποφθιμένου· ὃ μὲν εὔχετο πάντ᾽ ἀποδοῦναι
12
Already in epic poetry, the agora constituted the place in which justice was administered
and quarrels among litigants were dealt with: ἦμος δ ἐπὶ δόρπον ἀνὴρ ἀγορῆθεν ἀνέστη /
κρίνων νείκεα πολλὰ δικαζομένων αἰζηῶν, / τῆμος δὴ τά γε δοῦρα Χαρύβδιος ἐξεφαάνθη
(Odyssey, XII.439-441). This explains, for example, the opposition between the civilized
world of the Greeks and the land of the Cyclops, which lacked an agora to hold councils and
implement rules from the gods (τοῖσιν δ᾽ οὔτ᾽ ἀγοραὶ βουληφόροι οὔτε θέμιστες, Odyssey
IX.112). Few verses later, in the same book, Polyphemus himself was presented by similar
expressions as a savage, ignorant of judicial processes and norms: ἄγριον, οὔτε δίκας εὖ
εἰδότα οὔτε θέμιστας (Odyssey IX.215).
Achilleus. Zur Pflege des Rechts in homerischer Zeit”, in Peter Steinmetz (ed.), Politeia und
Res Publica. Beiträge zum Verständnis von Politik, Recht und Staat in der Antike, dem An-
denken Rudolf Starks gewidmet, Franz Steiner, Wiesbaden, 1969, pp. 11–38; Gerhard Thür,
“Zum dikazein bei Homer”, in Zeitschrift der Savigny-Stiftung für Rechtsgeschichte, 1979,
no. 87, pp. 426–44; Øivind Andersen, “Some thoughts on the shield of Achilleus”, in Sym-
bolae Osloenses, 1976, no. 51, pp. 5–18; Raymond Westbrook, “The Trial Scene in the Ili-
ad”, in Harvard Studies in Classical Philology, 1992, no. 94, pp. 53–76; Eva Cantarella,
“Dispute Settlement in Homer: Once Again on the Shield of Achilles”, in Droits antiques et
société. Mélanges en l'honneur de Panayotis D. Dimakis, Sakkoulas, Athènes, 2002,
pp. 147–164; Henri van Effenterre, “Un mort parle toujours”, in Gerhard Thür and Francisco
Javier Fernández Nieto (eds.), Symposion 1999 (Akten der Gesellschaft für griechische und
hellenistische Rechtsgeschichte, vol. 14), Böhlau Verlag, Köln, Weimar and Wien, 2003,
pp. 21–26; Giuseppe Lentini, “La scena giudiziaria dello Scudo di Achille e l'immaginario
della giustizia nella Grecia arcaica”, in Materiali e Discussioni per l'analisi dei testi classici,
2016, no. 76, pp. 15–31; Sima Avramovic, “Blood money in Homer – Role of istor in the
trial scene on the shield of Achilles (Il. 18.497-508)”, in Zbornik PFZ 67/5, 2017, pp. 723–
756.
16
On the figure of these old kings, see Pierre Carlier, “Les basileis homériques sont-ils des
rois?”, in Ktèma, 1996, no. 21, pp. 5–22.
17
Michael Gagarin, “The Poetry of Justice: Hesiod and the Origins of Greek Law”, in Ramus,
1992, no. 21, pp. 61–78. See also Michael Gagarin, “Dikē in the Works and Days”, in Clas-
with straight sentences (ἰθείῃσι δίκῃς) which, coming from Zeus, were the
best (αἵ τ’ ἐκ Διός εἰσιν ἄρισται). Among men there were corrupt judges –
considered as “devourers of gifts” (δωροφάγους) – who were willing to
make a decision (οἳ τήνδε δίκην ἐθέλουσι δίκασσαι) after being flattered.
These outraged Dike when they sentenced in a crooked way (τῆς δὲ Δίκης
ῥόθος ἑλκομένης, ᾗ κ ἄνδρες ἄγωσι / δωροφάγοι, σκολιῇς δὲ δίκῃς κρίνωσι
θέμιστας, vv. 220-221), whereas good rulers gave fair sentences to foreign-
ers and allowed the city to prosper and the people to flourish (Οἳ δὲ δίκας
ξείνοισι καὶ ἐνδήμοισι διδοῦσιν / ἰθείας καὶ μή τι παρεκβαίνουσι δικαίου, /
τοῖσι τέθηλε πόλις, λαοὶ δ ἀνθεῦσιν ἐν αὐτῇ, vv. 225-227). This distortion,
as Hesiod seems to confirm, had clear political effects. 18 Contrary to what
happened in the past, during the new iron age, evil people would forget
about truth and pronounce false oaths in a crooked manner (vv. 190-194):
οὐδέ τις εὐόρκου χάρις ἔσσεται οὔτε δικαίου
οὔτ᾽ ἀγαθοῦ, μᾶλλον δὲ κακῶν ῥεκτῆρα καὶ ὕβριν
ἀνέρες αἰνήσουσι· δίκη δ᾽ ἐν χερσί· καὶ αἰδὼς
οὐκ ἔσται, βλάψει δ᾽ ὁ κακὸς τὸν ἀρείονα φῶτα
μύθοισιν σκολιοῖς ἐνέπων, ἐπὶ δ᾽ ὅρκον ὀμεῖται.
There will be no favour for the man who keeps his oath or for
the just or for the good; but rather men will praise the evil-
doer and his violent dealing. Strength will be right, and rever-
ence will cease to be; and the wicked will hurt the worthy man,
speaking crooked words against him, and will swear an oath
upon them.
The corrosive effects of wrongful acts were a symbol of political de-
terioration. Overcoming the idea that archaic values were endorsed by ab-
solute principles derived from the authority of gods – as suggested by Mar-
cel Detienne – a relativistic opposition rather implied the acknowledgment
of moral limits in human behaviour. The corrupt intervention of judges and
sical Philology, 1973, no. 68, pp. 81–94; Robert J. Bonner, “Administration of justice in the
age of Hesiod”, in Classical Philology, 1912, no. 7, pp. 17–23.
18
Daniel Malamis, “Crimes of the Agora: Corruption in Homer and Hesiod”, in Philip Bosman
(ed.), Corruption and Integrity in Ancient Greece and Rome, Classical Association of South
Africa, Pretoria, 2012, pp. 17–29, identifies in this Homeric and Hesiodic passages a refer-
ence to political degradation, what he calls “institutional corruption”: “Institutional corrup-
tion may then take the form of advice within a deliberative council that should operate in the
community’s interest, but advice that actually promotes the interest of the adviser, either be-
cause it is personally beneficial or because the council member in question has been bribed”
(p. 22).
rulers did not only generate the fury of the Olympians, but also the rejec-
tion of those poets who supported communal solidarity and fairness. This
axiomatic system set the ground for the endorsement of a politics of integ-
rity, which held physical rectitude and moral righteousness as positive so-
cial values both in classical Greek and ancient Rome.
1.3. Recreating Integrity in Classical Athens
Rude, lewd and bad-mannered, Thersites is said to have disturbed the as-
sembly of the Achaean army in Book II of the Iliad (II.211-218):
ἄλλοι μέν ῥ᾽ ἕζοντο, ἐρήτυθεν δὲ καθ᾽ ἕδρας·
Θερσίτης δ᾽ ἔτι μοῦνος ἀμετροεπὴς ἐκολῴα,
ὃς ἔπεα φρεσὶν ᾗσιν ἄκοσμά τε πολλά τε ᾔδη
μάψ, ἀτὰρ οὐ κατὰ κόσμον, ἐριζέμεναι βασιλεῦσιν,
ἀλλ᾽ ὅ τι οἱ εἴσαιτο γελοίϊον Ἀργείοισιν
ἔμμεναι· αἴσχιστος δὲ ἀνὴρ ὑπὸ Ἴλιον ἦλθε·
φολκὸς ἔην, χωλὸς δ᾽ ἕτερον πόδα· τὼ δέ οἱ ὤμω
κυρτὼ ἐπὶ στῆθος συνοχωκότε· αὐτὰρ ὕπερθε
φοξὸς ἔην κεφαλήν, ψεδνὴ δ᾽ ἐπενήνοθε λάχνη.
The rest now took their seats and kept to their own several
places, but Thersites still went on wagging his unbridled
tongue – a man of many words, and those unseemly; a monger
of sedition, a railer against all who were in authority, who
cared not what he said, so that he might set the Achaeans in a
laugh. He was the ugliest man of all those that came before
Troy – bandy-legged, lame of one foot, with his two shoulders
rounded and hunched over his chest. His head ran up to a
point, but there was little hair on the top of it.
Unlike the rest of the Greek warriors, Thersites is described as bow-
legged and lame, a grotesque figure of wickedness. His shoulders are caved
inward, and his head is covered with few hairs. 19 When he launches an
abusive attack against Agamemnon in the assembly (II.225-242), he is
called greedy and coward. His physical representation was therefore cou-
pled with moral depravation. Not surprisingly, he is the only one in the pas-
sage to lack a patronymic. 20
19
On his poor bodily condition and the possible puns intended in the Iliad, see R. Clinton
Simms, “The Missing Bones of Thersites: A Note on Iliad 2.212-19”, in American Journal
of Philology, 2005, no. 126, pp. 33–40
20
Andrea Kouklanakis, “Thersites, Odysseus, and the Social Order”, in Miriam Carlisle and
Olga Levaniouk (eds.), Nine Essays on Homer, Rowman & Littlefield, Lanham, 1999, p. 40.
Some centuries later, Greek sources would rely again on this physical
and moral construction of characters as an efficient rhetorical technique.
Through the technique of ethopoíia, for example, forensic speechwriters
such as Lysias delineated personalities, opposing their own clients, por-
trayed as pure and undamaged, to their rivals, constantly presented as ethi-
cally corrupted. If speakers endorsed moral qualities, such as altruism and
integrity, the disposition of their bodies corresponded to required upright-
ness, as opposed to crookedness presented in their corrupt and perverse en-
emies in court.
The symbolic value of body language in communication deserves
special attention. 21 Gestures such as the position of hands, the inclination
of the head, and the movement of the eyes are significant ways of express-
ing intention, and can therefore transmit relevant evidence on attitudes. 22 A
number of recent contributions have attempted to offer some insights into
the role of gestures and their meaning in classical civilizations. 23 However,
in spite of the obvious political character of gestures as a means of express-
ing personal relationships within a society, the relevance of gestures has
also been neglected in the study of judicial administration, due again to the
See Norman Postlethwaite, “Tersites in the Iliad”, in Greece and Rome, 1992, no. 35,
pp. 123–136.
21
See Pierre Guiraud, Le langage du corps, Presses Universitaires de France, Paris, 1980.
22
According to Keith Thomas, “Introduction”, in Jan Bremmer and Herman Roodenburg
(eds.), A Cultural History of Gesture. From Antiquity to the Present Day, Polity Press, Cam-
bridge, 1991, p. 1, gestures include any kind of bodily movement or posture (including faci-
al expression), which transmits a message to the observer. This definition seems to presup-
pose the existence of at least two bodies interacting with each other: one of them performing
the gesture, and the second one decoding its explicit or implicit significance. On the cultural
importance of gesture and its relationship to speech, see Adam Kendon, “Gesture”, in Annu-
al Review of Anthropology, 1997, no. 26, pp. 109–128. Gerhard Neumann, Gesten und Ge-
bärden in der griechischen Kunst, Walter de Gruyter, Berlin and Boston, 1965, pp. 10–12,
uses the expression “rhetorische Geste” to indicate the “geformte und schalgkräftig pointier-
te Geste”. According to Carolin Hahnemann, “A Gesture in Archilochus 118 (West)?”, in
Geoffrey W. Bakewell and James P. Sickinger (eds.), Gestures. Essays in Ancient History,
Literature and Philosophy presented to Alan L. Boegehold on the occasion of his retirement
and his 75th birthday, Oxbow, Oxford, 2003, p. 55, rhetorical gestures include any motion of
head and hand that accompany a speech-act. These gestures will be relevant in the context of
legal proceedings.
23
Anthony Corbeill, Nature Embodied. Gestures in Ancient Rome, Princeton University Press,
Princeton and Oxford, 2004, and Douglas L. Cairns, “Introduction”, in Douglas L. Cairns
(ed.) Body Language in the Greek and Roman Worlds, Classical Press of Wales, Swansea,
2015, pp. ix-xxii.
biased nature of our sources. 24 I argue that, both in Greek and Roman
sources, the information that can be obtained from the identification and
observation of different gestures and corporal postures can greatly contrib-
ute to the ancient perception of integrity in public fora.
Aristotle discussed the symbolic value arising from the difference be-
tween straight and crooked bodies. In his Politics, the unbent body repre-
sents the ideal physical support of the male citizen, whereas crooked or
curve figures are deemed useless for civic activities, and become therefore
associated to slaves (1254b 27-31):
βούλεται μὲν οὖν ἡ φύσις καὶ τὰ σώματα διαφέροντα ποιεῖν
τὰ τῶν ἐλευθέρων καὶ τῶν δούλων, τὰ μὲν ἰσχυρὰ πρὸς τὴν
ἀναγκαίαν χρῆσιν, τὰ δ' ὀρθὰ καὶ ἄχρηστα πρὸς τὰς τοιαύτας
ἐργασίας, ἀλλὰ χρήσιμα πρὸς πολιτικὸν βίον.
The intention of nature therefore is to make the bodies also of
freemen and of slaves different – the latter strong for neces-
sary service, the former erect and unserviceable for such oc-
cupations, but serviceable for a life of citizenship. 25
Bodies which were erect (ὀρθὰ, orthá) seemed prepared for a life de-
voted to the pólis. Body language helps to understand the relationship be-
tween social status and physical disposition, since curved anatomies meant
submission as opposed to self-sufficiency and autonomy. 26
24
An interesting contribution by Anthony Corbeill, “Gesture in Early Roman Law: Empty
Forms or Essential Formalities?”, in Cairns, 2015, pp. 157–171, see above note 23, has dis-
cussed the importance of gesture and body contact in early Roman law considering that, far
from being symbolic adjuncts, they were truly constitutive elements of some legal processes.
Another exception is the recent book by Peter A. O’Connell, The Rhetoric of Seeing in Attic
Forensic Oratory, The University of Texas Press, Austin, 2017, which, although focused on
the importance of sight, refers to the relevance of non-verbal expressions and physical
movements in classical Greek forensic oratory.
25
The Greek text corresponds to W.D. Ross (ed.), Aristotle. Politica, Clarendon Press, Oxford,
1957. The translation has been taken from H. Rackham (ed.), Aristotle, vol. 21, Harvard
University Press and William Heinemann, Cambridge (MA) and London, 1944.
26
On the difference between “normal” and “deviant” bodies in antiquity and its relationship to
social values, see also Christopher Goody and Martha Lynn Rose, “Mental states, bodily
dispositions and table manners: a guide to reading ‘intellectual’ disability from Homer to
late antiquity”, in Christian Laes, Christopher Goodey and Martha Lynn Rose (eds.), Disa-
bilities in Roman Antiquity: Disparate Bodies; a Capite ad Calcem, Brill, Leiden and Bos-
ton, 2013, pp. 17–44. On the deformed and disabled body and its figured “otherness”, see
more recently Lisa Trentin, The Hunchback in Hellenistic and Roman Art, Bloomsbury,
London, 2015.
27
The overlapping of personal economic motives and public interests was frequently seen as a
symbol of corrupt behavior. See Barry Strauss, “The Cultural Significance of Bribery and
Embezzlement in Athenian Politics: The Evidence of the Period 403–386 B.C.”, in The An-
cient World, 1985, no. 11, p. 73.
28
The Greek text of the play corresponds to the edition of Zachary P. Biles and S. Douglas
Olson (eds.), Aristophanes. Wasps, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2015. Translations are
taken from Alan H. Sommerstein (ed.), The Comedies of Aristophanes, vol. 4. Wasps, Aris &
Phillips, Warminster, 1983.
29
Mariel Vázquez, “ʻCuerpos curvados’ en Asambleístas de Aristófanes: la postura corporal y
sus implicancias biológico-políticas”, in Alicia Atienza, Emiliano J. Buis and Elsa Rodrí-
guez Cidre (eds.), Anatomías poéticas. Pliegues y despliegues del cuerpo en el mundo grie-
go antiguo (Colección Saberes), Editorial de la Facultad de Filosofía y Letras de la UBA,
Buenos Aires, 2020, pp. 205–232, has recently worked on the political implications of the
female image of crooked bodies in Aristophanes’ Ecclesiazusae.
30
Guiraud, 1980, see above note 21, considers that the interpretation of this connection of
bodies is part of proxemics, since it is related to the physical communication between people
in a specific spatial environment.
31
Biles and Olson, 2015, p. 259, see above note 28. On this verb, see Diphilus fr. 42, 23-24
and Herodotus 1.130.1, 6.25.2 and 109.3.
32
Jon Hesk, “The Rhetoric of Anti-rhetoric in Athenian oratory”, in Simon Goldhill and Robin
Osborne (eds.), Performance Culture and Athenian Democracy, Cambridge University Press,
Cambridge, 1999, pp. 220–226, has coined the expression ‘physiognomic interpretation’ in
order to describe the ways in which orators matched some physical traits to specific charac-
ter types in their speeches.
33
Claire Taylor, “Corruption and Anticorruption in Democratic Athens”, in Ronald Kroeze,
André Vitória and Guy Geltner (eds.), Anti-corruption in History: From Antiquity to the
Modern Era, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2017, pp. 21–33, at p. 29.
34
The Greek text and its translation are taken from Charles Darwin Adams (ed.), Aeschines,
Harvard University Press and William Heinemann, Cambridge (MA) and London, 1919.
35
Philip Bosman, “Corruption and Integrity: A Survey of the Ancient Terms”, in Bosman,
2012, p. 2, see above note 18.
36
Bosman, 2012, pp. 5–6 and 10-14, see above note 18. On the legal and political implications
of these terms, see Mark Philp, “Defining Political Corruption”, in Political Studies, 1997,
no. 45, pp. 436–62, at p. 442; F. David Harvey, “Dona Ferentes: Some Aspects of Bribery in
Greek Politics”, in History of Political Thought, 1985, no. 6, pp. 76–117, at p. 105, and Lisa
Hill, “Conceptions of Political Corruption in Antiquity”, in History of Political Thought,
2013, no. 34, at pp. 567–568.
Crooked Straight
Self-
Altruism
interest
Antithetical
Corruption “political” Integrity
perspective
Putrefaction, degeneration, Purity, wholeness,
decay, deterioration, completenesss,
contamination uncorruptibility
Physical
Moral
Guilt, depravity, perversion, Innocence, honesty,
lying sincerity, truth, uprightness
37
William J. Prior, Virtue and Knowledge: An Introduction to Ancient Greek Ethics, Routledge,
New York and London, 2016 [1991], pp. 261–275.
38
The Greek text and the English translation correspond to the edition prepared by Charles
Darwin Adams, Aeschines, Harvard University Press and William Heinemann, Cambridge
(MA) and London, 1919.
39
Ryan K. Balot, “The Virtue Politics of Democratic Athens”, in Stephen Salkever (ed.) The
Cambridge Companion to Ancient Greek Political Thought, Cambridge University Press,
Cambridge, 2009, at pp. 284–285.
had always acted with zeal, loyalty, eagerness, generosity, and well-
informed rationality, in order to pursue the city’s welfare (18.62-71).
Together with the Assembly, the judicial arena was a crucial setting
in classical Athens, where citizens could display their virtuous characters
and show their normatively appropriate feelings in front of others. This was
the case of Socrates’ famous prosecution under the charges of impiety
(ἀσέβεια, asébeia) and corruption of the youth, maybe the best-known ex-
ample of the need for a philosopher to inform of his ethical integrity. Ac-
cording to Plato’s Apology, Socrates claimed to have acted in a proper way,
respecting both law and religion: μηδὲν ἄδικον μηδ ̓ ἀνόσιον ἐργάζεσθαι
(“I should do nothing wrong or contrary to the sacred”) (Apology 33c-d).
Interestingly, in Socrates’ words there was an insistence in the maintenance
of unity and harmony within the soul, a correspondence between word and
action which, again, implied that integrity could not only be achieved by a
mental disposition, but also involved tangible behaviour. 40 In the case of
Socrates, it has been stated that his integrity derived mainly from negativity,
since he departed from ignorance (instead of knowledge), and he knew
what injustice was (rather than what virtuous excellence was). 41 His integ-
rity only turned out to be positive when caring for others. 42 In this sense,
moral integrity was seen as an individual virtue related to a social envi-
ronment because of the effects it could produce on the rest of the citizens.
Socrates’ integrity also entailed the civic courage of opposing the Atheni-
ans when the dêmos decided to infringe the law. 43
Similar to comedy and forensic oratory, Athenian tragedy made fre-
quent allusions to this set of opposing core values as well. In ancient
Greece, in spite of the close nexus between corporal deportment and ethical
40
Bosman, 2012, pp. 9-10, see above note 18.
41
George Kateb, Patriotism and Other Mistakes, Yale University Press, New Haven, 2006,
p. 216.
42
Kateb, 2006, p. 241, see above note 41: “The whole image of Socrates as a model of intel-
lectual and moral integrity, as a supreme hero of self-denial and self-sacrifice, as a master of
negativity, needs one, if only one, positivity, and that must be a positive commitment to oth-
ers. He cared for them more than he cared for himself. He lived and died for them. He made
them his superiors by deeming them worthy of his self-sacrifice. But he did not think that
they were his equals, and this is precisely why he had to care for them and in the way that he
did”.
43
Claude Mossé, Le procès de Socrate. Un philosophe victim de la démocratie?, André Ver-
saille, Bruxelles, 2012, p. 69 argues that “Socrate demeurait fidèle à lui-même et à ses con-
victions, et n’hésitait pas à braver ceux dont les ordres lui paraissent injustes et contraires
aux lois”.
44
The Greek text is taken from Gilbert Murray, Euripidis Fabulae, vol. 3, Clarendon Press,
Oxford, 1913. The translation is taken from Martin L. West, Euripides. Orestes, Aris & Phil-
lips, Warminster, 1987.
45
The Greek text and its translation are taken from Herbert Weir Smyth (ed.), Aeschylus, vol. 2,
Eumenides, Harvard University Press, Cambrige (MA), 1926.
46
We do not have any ancient source transmitting the text of the oath. Nevertheless, following
possible reconstructions, it may well have included these provisions according to Alan H.
Sommerstein, “The Judicial Sphere”, in Alan H. Sommerstein and Andrew J. Bayliss, Oath
and State in Ancient Greece, Walter de Gruyter, Berlin and Boston, 2013, p. 79: “I will vote
according to the laws and decrees of the Athenian people and of the Council of Five Hun-
dred; and on matters about which there are no laws, I will vote according to the justest opin-
ion. And I will give an equal hearing both to the accuser and to the defendant, and I will cast
my vote upon the actual matter which is the subject of the charge. And I will not accept any
gift on account of my service as a juror, neither I nor any other man or woman with my
knowledge, by any means or device whatsoever. And I am not less than thirty years old. I
swear this by Apollo Patroios, Demeter, and Zeus the King; if I transgress any of these pro-
visions, then may I be utterly destroyed, myself and my house, but if I keep my oath may I
have many blessings”. The most famous reconstruction is owed to Max Fränkel, “Der at-
tische Heliasteneid”, in Hermes, 1878, no. 13, pp. 452–466, and has been extensively stud-
ied by David C. Mirhady, “The Dikast’s Oath and the Question of Fact”, in Alan H. Som-
merstein and Judith Fletcher (eds.), Horkos. The Oath in Greek Society, Liverpool Universi-
ty Press, Liverpool, 2008, pp. 49–51. On the nature of the dikastic oath under the light of Ar-
istotle’s Politics, see the recent contribution by Anders Dahl Sørensen, “Hippodamus of Mi-
letus and the Character of the Athenian Dikastic Oath (Arist. Pol. 2.8)”, in Greek, Roman,
and Byzantine Studies, 2018, no. 58, pp. 324–348.
47
See Giuseppe Cambiano, “Pathologie et analogie politique”, in François Lasserre and Phi-
lippe Mudry (eds.), Formes de pensée dans la Collection Hippocratique (Actes du IVe Col-
loque international hippocratique, Lausanne, 21-26 septembre 1981), Droz, Genève, 1983,
pp. 441–458. On the overlapping between medicine and politics, see also Roger Brock,
“Sickness in the body politic: medical imagery in the Greek polis”, in Valerie M. Hope and
Eireann Marshall (eds.), Death and Disease in the Ancient City, Routledge, London and
New York, 2000, pp. 24–34.
frain from giving deadly medicine to anyone if asked, and to abstain from
every voluntary act of mischief and corruption. 48
In sum, integrity was part of what a city would endorse as general
patterns of social behaviour in different professions and activities. This cor-
rectness also included intellectual pursuit, which was an activity related to
political performance as well. For example, moral considerations would be
attributed to virtuous historians many centuries later by Lucian, with a sim-
ilar vocabulary placing emphasis on integrity and rightness (How to write
History, 41):
τοιοῦτος οὖν μοι ὁ συγγραφεὺς ἔστω, ἄφοβος, ἀδέκαστος,
ἐλεύθερος, παρρησίας καὶ ἀληθείας φίλος […] οὐ μίσει οὐδὲ
φιλίᾳ τι νέμων οὐδὲ φειδόμενος ἢ ἐλεῶν ἢ αἰσχυνόμενος ἢ
δυσωπούμενος, ἴσος δικαστής, εὔνους ἅπασιν ἄχρι τοῦ μὴ
θατέρῳ ἀπονεῖμαι πλεῖον τοῦ δέοντος, ξένος ἐν τοῖς βιβλίοις
καὶ ἄπολις, αὐτόνομος, ἀβασίλευτος, οὐ τί τῷδε ἢ τῷδε δόξει
λογιζόμενος, ἀλλὰ τί πέπρακται λέγων.
This, then, is the sort of man the historian should be: fearless,
incorruptible (adékastos), free (eleútheros), a friend of free
expression and the truth (parrhesías kaì aletheías phílos), […]
giving nothing to hatred or to friendship, sparing no one,
showing neither pity nor shame nor obsequiousness, an impar-
tial judge (ísos dikastés), well disposed to all men up to the
point of not giving one side more than its due, in his books a
stranger and a man without a country, independent, subject to
no sovereign, not reckoning what this or that man will think,
but stating the facts. 49
48
The Greek text can be found in W.H.S. Jones (ed.), Hippocrates Collected Works, vol. I,
Cambridge (MA), Harvard University Press, 1868. On its importance for the history of med-
ical thought, see Robert M. Veatch, Hippocratic, Religious, and Secular Medical Ethics: The
Points of Conflict, Georgetown University Press, Washington, DC, 2012. On the ‘legal’
character of this oath and the obligations which arise from its text, see Lisa R. Hasday, “The
Hippocratic Oath as Literary Text: A Dialogue Between Law and Medicine”, in Yale Journal
of Health Policy, Law, and Ethics, 2002, no. 2, pp. 299–324.
49
The Greek text is taken from Karl Jacobitz (ed.), Luciani Samosatensis Opera, vol. II, B.G.
Teubner, Leipzig, 1913. The translation corresponds to K. Kilburn, Lucian, vol. VI, Harvard
University Press, Cambridge (MA), 1959.
The ethical and political centre was the vir, the adult male citizen. In the
social hierarchy of status, the role of Roman men was heavily dependent
on the nature of their body: a Roman citizen was seen in sexual terms as an
agent of penetration, whereas in the political and legal dimensions he was
expected to enforce domestic authority as a pater familias. Since defending
the body from external assault was the cornerstone of masculinity, the ide-
alized image of Roman men involved a sexual protocol based on the clear
establishment of physical boundaries, which turned their bodies into im-
penetrable constructions. 50 Manhood therefore meant, at the same time,
immunity from physical invasion, and civic autonomy. Once again, at the
crossroad between physicality and ethics, integrity was definitely a signifi-
cant feature of these two complementary dimensions.
Following the Greek tradition, external and internal connotations also
conflated in the Latin vocabulary involving integrity and corruption. Thus,
the word corruptio meant “dishonest conduct, seduction, harm, bribery”
and the related verb corrumpere similarly translatable as “to utterly destroy,
ruin, spoil, damage, adulterate”. Integrity, on the other side, was expressed
through nouns such as temperantia, “self-control”; innocentia, “blameless-
ness” and integritas, “intactness, completeness, wholeness”, which origi-
nated our correspondent words. 51 Significantly, integritas came from in-
tangere (“not to touch”) and therefore remained close to the Greek
ἀκεραιότης (akeraiótes), which, according to Bosman, also derived from a-
keránnymi (“not to mix”).
Unlike our modern perception, in which integrity seems to relate to
innocence and honesty – and more recently became associated with interi-
ority, autonomy, and reflection – in Republican Rome the idea of integritas
involved strong physical traits. 52 This can be noted when examining the
relevant passages, where the concept is placed next to adjectives indicating
purity and intangibility. Expressions such as integer intactusque, which is
ubiquitous in Livy, 53 integer et incorruptus, 54 integer et inlibatus, 55 or inte-
ger et inviolatus 56 easily demonstrate the nature of this semantic scope.
50
Jonathan Walters, “Invading the Roman Body: Manliness and Impenetrability in Roman
Thought”, in Judith P. Hallett and Marilyn B. Skinner (eds.), Roman Sexualities, Princeton
University Press, Princeton, 1997, pp. 29–46.
51
Bosman, 2012, pp. 3–5, see above note 18.
52
Robert A. Kaster, Emotion, Restraint and Community in Ancient Rome, Oxford University
Press, Oxford, 2005, pp. 135–137.
53
Livy 5. 38. 7, 10.14. 20, 10. 27. 9, 10. 36. 3, inter alia multa.
In fact, the adjective integer was mostly used with physical entities
in order to refer to those characteristics which made it entirely what they
were: this implied that something which was described as integer remained
unaltered since it had not suffered from any addition (which might eventu-
ally spoil its purity) or subtraction (which would undermine its whole-
ness). 57 The idea behind this material sense of integrity is clearly seen in
the way the Romans referred to the movement of rivers in which waters
were deemed to be neither contaminated nor compromised. In Tacitus’ His-
tories, for instance, the river Jordan “is not received by the open ocean but
flows integer through one lake, then another, and is captured by a third”
(nec Iordanes pelago accipitur, sed unum atque alterum lacum integer per-
fluit, tertio retinetur, 5.6). 58 When defined as integer, a river was conceived
as both pure and complete, in accordance with its original essence.
The transferal of the material implications of integritas to the moral
realm keeps this idea of purity and completeness. Not surprisingly, Cicero
explicitly mentioned the close relationship between physical qualities and
spiritual virtues. Bodies and minds could become impure and crooked
when altered. Corruption was in fact a sort of disease affecting both the
body and the soul, but the mind could be as beautiful as the body if charac-
terized by equality, constancy of opinions and judgments, firmness and sta-
bility, as suggested in Tusculan Disputations 4.28-31:
morbum appellant totius corporis corruptionem,
aegrotationem morbum cum imbecillitate, vitium, cum partes
corporis inter se dissident, ex quo pravitas membrorum,
distortio, deformitas (…) Atque ut in malis attingit animi
naturam corporis similitudo, sic in bonis. sunt enim in
corpore praecipua, pulchritudo, vires, valetudo, firmitas,
54
Cicero, For Marcus Fonteius 3, De Natura Deorum 2. 71, etc.
55
Seneca, Dialogue 2. 6. 7; Pliny, Panegyricus 25. 1.
56
Cicero, Against Verres 2. 4. 130, Livy 6. 3. 10.
57
Bosman, 2012, pp. 4–5, see above note 18.
58
Similarly, Pomponius Mela – the first Roman geographer – explained that the Rhône “main-
tains its course, passing unaltered (integer) through the middle of the lake and emerging
with its volume undiminished” (tenet impetum, seque per medium integer agens quantus ve-
nit egreditur, 2.79). Speaking of the Tigris, Seneca stated that its course was restored with its
full size (integrae magnitudinis redditur, Ad Lucilium Epistulae Morales 104. 15). Also, in
his Dialogues, the spring Arethusa was said to remain unchanged (integrum) beneath many
seas, saved from mingling with water of lesser quality (inlapsum terris flumen integrum sub-
ter tot maria et a confusione peioris undae servatum, 6.17.3).
59
The Latin text is taken from the edition prepared by Max Pohlenz (ed.), M. Tullius Cicero.
Tusculanae Disputationes, Teubner, Leipzig, 1918.
60
The translation belongs to C.D. Yonge (ed.), Cicero’s Tusculan Disputations, Harper &
Brothers, New York, 1877.
61
Valentina Arena, “Fighting Corruption. Political Thought and Practice in the Late Roman
Republic”, in Kroeze, Vitória and Geltner, 2017, pp. 35–47, at p. 40, see above note 33.
summo imperatore), referring later to his pudor, integritas, religio, and dili-
gentia and his well-known castitas, sanctitas and moderatio. In political
terms, integrity comprised a wide range of private and public virtues relat-
ed to the essential qualities of “wholeness” and “purity”. As with rivers,
these positive values were described as essential in the characterization of
an individual, who possessed them in spite of the many changing circum-
stances surrounding his life. 64
Civic virtues were extremely useful to distinguish good and bad citi-
zens. In Against Verres, Cicero stated that – unlike his rival – he cherished
fides, pudor, pudicitia, religio and ius aequum (2.3.6). He then described
Verres’ corrupt way of acting by accusing his listeners of not being able to
appreciate values which were inherent to Roman citizens, such as virtue,
trustworthiness (integritas), hard work, frugality, and modesty (2.3.7-8):
illa quae leviora videntur esse non cuiusvis animum possunt
movere, quod ad tuam ipsius amicitiam ceterorumque
hominum magnorum atque nobilium faciliorem aditum istius
habet nequitia et audacia quam cuiusquam nostrum virtus et
integritas? odistis hominum novorum industriam, despicitis
eorum frugalitatem, pudorem contemnitis, ingenium vero et
virtutem depressam exstinctamque cupitis: Verrem amatis! Ita
credo; si non virtute, non industria, non innocentia, non
pudore, non pudicitia, at sermone, at litteris, at humanitate
eius delectamini. Nihil eorum est, contraque sunt omnia cum
summo dedecore ac turpitudine tum singulari stultitia atque
inhumanitate oblita. 65
What? cannot even those matters, which seem more trifling,
move any one’s mind, – that the worthlessness and audacity of
that man should have a more easy access to your own friend-
ship and to that of other great and noble men, than the virtue
and integrity of any one of us? You hate the industry of new
men; you despise their economy; you scorn their modesty;
you wish their talents and virtues to be depressed and extin-
guished. You are fond of Verres: I suppose so. If you are not
gratified with his virtue, and his innocence, and his industry,
and his modesty, and his chastity, at least you are transported
at his conversation, his accomplishments, and his high breed-
64
Kaster, 2005, pp. 137, 142, see above note 52.
65
The Latin text is taken from William Peterson (ed.), M. Tvlli Ciceronis Orationes, Clarendon
Press, Oxford, 1917.
ing. He has no such gifts; but, on the contrary, all his qualities
are stained with the most extreme disgrace and infamy, with
most extraordinary stupidity and boorishness. 66
Other relevant passages in the Verrine Orations complemented this
axiological model by providing us with a larger picture of ‘integrity’: on
some occasions we see that several references were made to identify the
public display of virtues by jury members and even by women. As far as
the first group is concerned, unlike other magistrates, both Quintus Manlius
and Quintus Cornificius were presented by Cicero under a positive light
that pointed directly to their ethically “upright” comportment (1.1.30):
Q. Manlium et Q. Cornificium, duos severissimos atque
integerrimos iudices, quod tribuni plebis tum erunt, iudices
non habebimus; P. Sulpicius, iudex tristis et integer,
magistratum ineat oportet Nonis Decembribus.
We shall not have Quintus Manlius and Quintus Cornificius,
two most severe and upright judges, for judges, because they
will then be tribunes of the people. Publius Sulpicius, a sol-
emn and upright judge, must enter on his magistracy on the
fifth of December.
With regards to women, when presenting Philodamus’ unmarried
daughter, she was described by Cicero as “a woman of extraordinary beau-
ty, who was judged to be exceedingly modest and virtuous” (mulierem ex-
imia pulchritudine; sed eam summa integritate pudicitiaque existimari,
2.1.64). In this case, integritas corresponded to a female value, since it was
connected to pudicitia with the purpose of showing her virginal purity and
respectability. 67
These examples show that integritas, as an abstract notion which
could adapt to different contexts, mainly conveyed the idea of physical and
moral “wholeness”, implying not only strictness in public performances but
also chastity and honesty. 68 It encompassed then a large set of personal dis-
66
With slight modifications, the translation belongs to C.D. Yonge (ed.), The Orations of Mar-
cus Tullius Cicero, George Bell & Sons, London, 1903.
67
In Cicero – and elsewhere in Roman oratory – it was a common strategy to present the mo-
rality of individuals in relation to their families. Nobility and excellence (virtus, dignitas)
were intertwined to shape one’s reputation, as examined by Susan Treggiari, “Ancestral Vir-
tues and Vices: Cicero on Nature, Nurture, and Presentation”, in Emma Gee (ed.), Myth,
History and Culture in Republican Rome: Studies in Honour of T.P. Wiseman, University of
Exeter Press, Exeter, 2003, pp. 139–164.
68
Kaster, 2005, p. 138, see above note 52.
positions, which had made their way into the public sphere when a consci-
entious behaviour had to be shown in front of others, but in reality re-
sponded to an individual nature which was generally seen as all-embracing
and unadulterated. 69 Also in a highly political context, a passage of Sal-
lust’s Conspiracy of Catiline, where Caesar and Cato are compared and
judged, complements our reading of the private and public dimensions of
integritas by alluding to self-containment and firmness (54.2-6):
Caesar beneficiis ac munificentia magnus habebatur, integri-
tate vitae Cato. Ille mansuetudine et misericordia clarus fac-
tus, huic severitas dignitatem addiderat. Caesar dando suble-
vando ignoscundo, Cato nihil largiundo gloriam adeptus est.
In altero miseris perfugium erat, in altero malis pernicies.
Illius facilitas, huius constantia laudabatur. Postremo Caesar
in animum induxerat laborare, vigilare; negotiis amicorum
intentus sua neglegere, nihil denegare quod dono dignum
esset; sibi magnum imperium, exercitum, bellum novom
exoptabat, ubi virtus enitescere posset. At Catoni studium
modestiae, decoris, sed maxume severitatis erat; non divitiis
cum divite neque factione cum factioso, sed cum strenuo
virtute, cum modesto pudore, cum innocente abstinentia
certabat; esse quam videri bonus malebat: ita, quo minus
petebat gloriam, eo magis illum [ad]sequebatur. 70
Caesar grew eminent by generosity and munificence; Cato by
the integrity of his life. Caesar was esteemed for his humanity
and benevolence; austereness had given dignity to Cato. Cae-
sar acquired renown by giving, relieving, and pardoning; Cato
by bestowing nothing. In Caesar, there was a refuge for the
unfortunate; in Cato, destruction for the bad. In Caesar, his
easiness of temper was admired; in Cato, his firmness. Caesar,
in fine, had applied himself to a life of energy and activity; in-
tent upon the interest of his friends, he was neglectful of his
own; he refused nothing to others that was worthy of ac-
ceptance, while for himself he desired great power, the com-
mand of an army, and a new war in which his talents might be
displayed. But Cato’s ambition was that of temperance, discre-
69
According to Kaster, 2005, p. 140, see above note 52, “taken together, these personal and
social behaviors and dispositions are constitutive of integritas: being ethically integer just
means that you possess these dispositions and display these behaviors”.
70
The Latin text has been taken from Axel W. Ahlberg (ed.), C. Sallusti Crispi. Catilina,
Iugurtha, Orationes et epistulae excerptae de historiis, Teubner, Leipzig, 1919.
71
The translation is taken from John Selby Watson (ed.), Sallust. Conspiracy of Catiline, Har-
per & Brothers, New York and London, 1899.
72
Even the expression of the antithesis is relevant when the Catonian subordination of self to
ethics is presented. This subordination is paralleled with a chiasmus, which allows integritas
vitae to be placed in a privileged position. See William W. Batstone, “The Antithesis of Vir-
tue: Sallust’s ‘Synkrisis’ and the Crisis of the Late Republic”, in Classical Antiquity, 1989,
no. 7, pp. 1–29. On this passage, see also Myles Anthony McDonnell, Roman Manliness.
Virtus and the Roman Republic, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2006, p. 341.
73
Malcolm Schofield, “Republican Virtues”, in Ryan K. Balot (ed.), A Companion to Greek
and Roman Political Thought, Blackwell, London, 2009, pp. 199–213, at p. 204.
74
The English translation is taken from J.T. Ramsey (ed.), Sallust’s Bellum Catilinae, Oxford
University Press, Oxford, 1984.
had diverted me, and write a history of the Roman people” (sed, a quo in-
cepto studioque me ambitio mala detinuerat, eodem regressus statui res
gestas populi Romani carptim, 4.2).
In Sallust’s wording, therefore, pudor, abstinentia and virtus should
not be overcome by audacia, largitio and avaritia. A good citizen needed
to uphold the pure values of virtus, pietas, iustitia, modestia and integritas,
thus rejecting being contaminated or altered by corruptio and ambitio. 75 A
final comment should be made on this effort to circumvent the pollution of
venality.
The idea of corruption pervaded ancient Rome since early times, 76 so
the moral qualities of Roman men were expected to protect the public in-
terests from the selfish desires of worthless politicians. So far, little differ-
ence can be seen when comparing this experience with the ethical condem-
nation of corruption that we portrayed for classical Athens. However, un-
like the Athenian practice, in ancient Roman law, one of the best-recorded
crimes of political corruption was ambitus, which consisted mainly of a
candidate’s effort to influence the result of an election through bribes or
other subtler methods of soft power. Since “going around” in order to ap-
peal to the people could easily lead to unethical excesses, the moral risks
involved in ambitus soon led to the emergence of legislation aimed at crim-
inalizing electoral bribery. 77 Once again, the need to endorse the high
standard and practice of integrity fostered an institutional reaction to fight
bribery. The moral idea behind these legal-political measures was to curb
75
These Republican virtues can be explored in contemporary Roman theater as well. Not un-
like its Athenian precedent, drama engaged with a variety of these expected qualities; see
Gesine Manuwald, Roman Republican Theater, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge,
pp. 294–295.
76
Carlo Alberto Brioschi, Corruption: A Short Story, Brookings Institution, Washington, DC,
2017, pp. 39–50.
77
The so-called Lex Baebia was the first law against ambitus, instituted by M. Baebius Tam-
philus during his consulship in 181 BCE. On the reactions to ambitus and electoral corrup-
tion in Republican Rome, see for instance Georges Chaigne, L’ambitus et les moeurs électo-
rales des Romains, E. Larose, Paris, 1911; Élisabeth Deniaux, “De l’ambitio à l’ambitus : les
lieux de la propagande et de la corruption électorale à la fin de la République”, in L’Urbs,
espace urbain et histoire (Ier siècle av. J.-C. – IIIe siècle ap. J.-C.) (Actes du colloque de
Rome, 8-12 mai 1985), École française de Rome, Rome, 1987, pp. 279–304; Tammo Wal-
linga, “Ambitus in the Roman Republic”, in Revue Internationale des Droits de l’Antiquité
41, 1994, pp. 411–442; Peter Nadig, Ardet Ambitus. Untersuchungen zum Phänomen der
Wahlbestechungen in der römischen Republik, Peter Lang, Frankfurt am Main and New
York, 1997, and Brahm H. Kleinman, Ambitus in the Late Roman Republic (80-50 B.C.),
MA Thesis, Department of History and Classical Studies, McGill University, Montreal, 2012.
78
Arena, 2017, pp. 35–47, at p. 47, see above note 61.
79
On Cicero’s texts, see Thomas N. Mitchell, “Cicero on the moral crisis of the late Republic”,
in Hermathena, 1984, no. 136, pp. 21–41.
80
Barbara Levick, “Morals, Politics, and the Fall of the Roman Republic”, in Greece and
Rome, 1982, no. 29, pp. 53–62.
81
Ramsay MacMullen, Corruption and the Decline of Rome, Yale University Press, New Ha-
ven, 1990, has argued that a key factor in Rome’s fall was the steady loss of focus and con-
trol over government as its aims were thwarted for private gain by high-ranking bureaucrats
and military leaders.
82
Hill, 2013, p. 587, see above note 36. Further reading on ancient corruption should include
Wolfgang Schuller (ed.), in Korruption im Altertum, R. Oldenbourg Verlag, München/ Wien,
1982; Carine K. Doganis, Aux origines de la corruption : démocratie et délation en Grèce
ancienne, Presses Universitaires de France, Paris, 2007; Arlene W. Saxonhouse, “Corruption
and Justice: The View from Ancient Athens”, in William C. Heffernan and John Kleinig
(eds.), Private and Public Corruption, Rowman & Littlefield, Lanham, 2004, pp. 25–51;
and Cristina Rosillo López, La corruption à la fin de la république romaine (IIe-Ier s. av. J.-
C.): aspects politiques et financiers, Franz Steiner, Stuttgart, 2010.
87
See Morten Bergsmo, Wolfgang Kaleck, Sam Muller and William H. Wiley, “A Prosecutor
Falls, Time for the Court to Rise”, FICHL Policy Brief Series No. 86 (2017), Brussels, 2017
(http://www.toaep.org/pbs-pdf/86-four-directors/), pp. 1, 4.
Integer Vitae:
Christian Sources and Reflections on
Integrity in Justice
Hanne Sophie Greve *
2.1. Introduction
2.1.1. Definition
In his poem “Integer Vitae”, Quintus Horatius Flaccus describes his hero as
“Integer vitae scelerisque purus” – a man of uprightness and stainless in-
tegrity”. 1 In antiquity, integer was not used with the meaning as later given
to it. Integer means ‘whole’, ‘unimpaired’ and ‘untouched’. Its specific
meaning is evinced by its context. In relation to political activity, it may be
read as ‘incorruptible’, in friendship as ‘loyal’, and in love as ‘faithful’.
I shall here define integer to denote a person not lacking in any ca-
pacity needed for moral or ethical behaviour in providing justice.
Intellectual virtues – the five ways the soul arrives at truth by affir-
mation or denial – make the human mind a more efficient instrument of
knowledge and promote intellectual flourishing, critical thinking and the
pursuit of truth. The three speculative intellectual virtues are understanding,
scientific knowledge and wisdom. The two practical ones are art and prac-
tical wisdom.
A measure of intellectual virtues is an ‘obvious’ requirement for legal
office. I will pay no further attention to them, as my focus is moral or ethi-
cal behaviour in providing justice.
*
Hanne Sophie Greve is Vice President of the Gulating High Court, Norway, and member of
the International Commission against the Death Penalty. She has previously served, inter
alia, as an Expert in the UN Commission of Experts for the Former Yugoslavia established
pursuant to UN Security Council resolution 780 (1992) (1993–94); and Judge at the Europe-
an Court of Human Rights (1998–2004). She has served as UNHCR Assistant Protection Of-
ficer (1979–1981, Bangkok), and as a mediator for the UN Transitional Authority in Cam-
bodia (1992–beginning of 1993, Phnom Penh). She has had several consultancies in and lec-
tured extensively on international law (human rights, refugee law, law of war and criminal
justice).
1
Quintus Horatius Flaccus (Horace), “Integer Vitae”, in Odes, Book 1, 23 BC.
2.1.2. Ethics
So God created man in his own image, in the image of God
created he him; male and female created he them. 2
Thus, the extraordinary simplicity and absolute complexity of our
shared human existence. The human person partakes of the divine nature of
God by the act of creation. In this, all human beings are equals and the hu-
man worth is inherent. Human plurality has the dual character of equality
and distinction.
Human life is a conditioned reality. The individual is a party to con-
ditioning her or his own circumstances, and a party to conditioning the cir-
cumstances of fellow human beings.
Each person is both ‘self’ and ‘the other’. I am both I and – in rela-
tion to everyone else – I am the Other, You. For a human being to be mind-
ful of the human condition and to understand the reality of life is to recog-
nise her or his dual character as living as a human being among humans –
all subjects.
The Golden Rule – “Do unto others as if you were the others” – is
the epitome of ethical action articulated in almost every religion and cul-
ture. 3
Normative ethics is concerned with developing moral standards that
regulate right and wrong conduct. Virtue ethics are one of the oldest nor-
mative traditions in Western civilization.
2.2. Basic Concepts
2.2.1. Human Faculties
Human faculties are abilities. The four human faculties contributing to our
moral acts are:
• the intellect;
• the will;
• the appetite of desire; and
• the appetite of aversion.
2
Genesis 1:27, King James Version (the publisher’s preferred version). An alternative transla-
tion from the English Standard Version and the Revised Standard version reads as follows:
“So God created man in his own image, in the image of God he created him; male and fe-
male he created them”.
3
In the Bible referred to in Leviticus 19:18, Matthew 7:12 and Luke 6:31.
4
Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologica, Fathers of the English Dominican Province (trans.),
Notre Dame, IN, 1981 [1265-1274].
5
Ibid., II-II, q. 47, a. 2
reality of the human existence, every human being created in the image of
God, ordained for a divine order. Prudence guides the judgment of con-
science.
Prudence is called ‘the charioteer of the virtues’ because it steers the
other virtues by setting rule and measure. 6
The principal act of prudence is the practical executive command of
right reason. Within its orbit come good counsel and sound judgment, and
the ability to deal with exceptional cases.
Prudence as such is not in search of a mean between behaviouristic
extremes. The core is that prudence has to be utilised within a reasonable
time considering the circumstances. Developing the habit of applying right
reason – reaching the understanding needed for the correct choices – is
what is sought for. Prudence may, nevertheless, be construed as a mean be-
tween being insensible and overly thorough.
2.3.2. Justice
My focus here is the cardinal virtue known as ‘justice’. ‘Justice’ and ‘integ-
rity in international justice’ are not interchangeable.
The functions of the cardinal virtue ‘justice’ is summarised in the
word age – to act, to live, to work, to deal with and to defend a cause. It is,
moreover, deliberate inactivity such as to wait and to restrain. Justice is
premeditated human behaviour.
First, there is prudence – light for the mind, both of principles and
practical knowledge – and then there must be rectitude for the will to have
it tend naturally to the Good as defined by reason. Justice is the moral vir-
tue that consists in the constant and firm will to give everyone their due,
and to establish in human relationships the harmony that promotes equity
with regard to persons and to the common Good.
The Scriptures frequently refer to ‘the just person’ as being distin-
guished by habitual right thinking and the uprightness of her or his conduct
toward fellow human beings.
The one innate right of every human being is freedom, the freedom
that is compatible with the freedom of everyone else. The virtue of justice
must imply that one acts to promote the freedom of every human being by
working for the three main – and intertwined – common Goods as known
6
Ibid.
enables the person to defeat fear. The functions of fortitude may be summa-
rised in the word sustine – to bear up with and endure, to hold in check and
to sustain. Confidence is part of fortitude as is the patience that keeps an
unconquered spirit.
2.4. The Theological Virtues
The Greek list of virtues has been supplemented with three Christian ones:
faith, hope and charity. These theological virtues have God for their origin,
their motive and their object. God known by faith, God hoped in, and loved
for His own sake. They inform the moral virtues and give them life. That is,
the grace of God animates and enhances the moral virtues as well – the vir-
tues cardinal in human conduct, but penultimate and subordinate to the fi-
nal end of human beings as created in the image of God. The theological
virtues bring the ethics of the Genesis into full understanding. Aquinas be-
lieves that a person in the state of grace, or divine friendship, possesses cer-
tain enduring powers, the infused virtues and gifts, that raise her or him to
an orbit of a superior existence and that give abilities of thought and opera-
tion that are of God. An approach distinctively theological but strongly
conversant with philosophy. The theological virtues have a centre of gravi-
ty – a mean in the sense that a human being should exercise these virtues
according to the measure of her or his condition. Aquinas teaches that the
theological virtues faith, hope and charity correspond in the supernatural
order to natural knowledge, hope and love.
2.4.1. Faith
Faith is the theological virtue by which we believe in God. By faith, the
human being freely commits itself to God and seeks to know and do God’s
will. Natural law as dictated by human nature – the eternal law – is instilled
in the human being as endowed with reason, and is inclining the person
towards its right action and end. Aquinas argues that divine wisdom’s con-
ception has the character of ‘law’ insofar as it moves all things to their ap-
propriate ends. The gift of faith should not be deprived of hope and charity.
The gift of faith is intertwined with, or rather it is, meaning – the meaning
of the human existence and the natural order.
2.4.2. Hope
Life is change, constant change – it is unpredictable. The first Christians
depicted hope as an anchor fixed to the shores beyond, to God. Hope is a
8
1 Corinthians 13:13. Another translation would be: “As it is, these three remain: faith, hope
and love, the three of them; and the greatest of them is love”.
9
1 Kings 3:9.
3.1. Introduction
In most nations, judges, and other judicial officials, such as prosecutors,
play a vital role in dispensing justice and upholding the rule of law. As il-
lustrated in the Bangalore Principles of Judicial Conduct:
A judiciary of undisputed integrity is the bedrock institution
essential for ensuring compliance with democracy and the rule
of law. Even when all other protections fail, it provides a bul-
∗
Adel Maged is the Judge and Vice President of the Egyptian Court of Cassation (Criminal
Chambers). He was appointed Public Prosecutor in April 1987, and served as a Judge at the
Courts of First Instance, Chief Prosecutor at the Criminal Division of the Court of Cassation,
Judge at the Egyptian Court of Appeals, and for several years on secondment to the Ministry
of Justice of the United Arab Emirates as a Legal Advisor on International Law and Treatise.
Justice Maged is also a lecturer in criminal law and criminal procedural law at the Faculty of
Sharí‘ah and Law, al-Azhar University in Cairo, and founding member of the research
group ‘Islám, Law and Modernity’ at Durham Law School. He has advised the ICC Office
of the Prosecutor and the Arab League of States on international criminal law issues. His
publications include books and articles, in Arabic and English, on international criminal law,
Islámic law, justice reform, transitional justice, combating extremism, terrorism and combat-
ing human trafficking. He holds a Bachelor of Law from Alexandria University; LL.M. on
Internationalization of Crime and Criminal Justice from Utrecht University; and a Diploma
on International Law and Organisation for Development from the Institute of Social Studies,
The Hague. The author thanks co-editor Morten Bergsmo for his conceptual input. The au-
thor also thanks Fathi M. Abdelraouf Ahmed, Arabic translator and reviser, for his advice on
the translation of the Caliphs’ Letters on the Judiciary referred to in this chapter, and Ms.
Rawan Maged, Bachelor of Political Science, the American University in Cairo and LL.B.
Cairo University, for her research assistance. TOAEP has adopted the Transliteration System
approved at the 10th International Congress of Orientalists held in Geneva in 1894, and that
has been implemented here for Arabic terms to the extent feasible.
1
Al-Tirmidhi, Sunan al-Tirmidhi, Sheikh Saleh Al-Sheikh (ed.), Saudi Ministry of Islamic
Affairs, Dawah and Guidance, ḥadíth no. 1325, p. 321.
2
United Nations Office on Drugs and Crime (‘UNODC’), Commentary on the Bangalore
Principles of Judicial Conduct, Vienna, 2011, p. 5.
3
Ibid., p. 117.
4
UNODC, Resource Guide on Strengthening Judicial Integrity and Capacity, Vienna, 2007,
p. 127.
5
Basic Principles on the Independence of the Judiciary, adopted by the Seventh United Na-
tions Congress on the Prevention of Crime and the Treatment of Offenders held at Milan
from 26 August to 6 September 1985 and endorsed by General Assembly resolutions 40/32
of 29 November 1985 and 40/146 of 13 December 1985 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/
rnabsy/).
6
The Bangalore Draft Code of Judicial Conduct of 2001, adopted by the Judicial Group on
Strengthening Judicial Integrity, as revised at the Round Table Meeting of Chief Justices
held at the Peace Palace, The Hague, November 25–26, 2002 (‘Bangalore Principles of Ju-
dicial Conduct’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/xwake8/).
7
Ibid., Value 3.
8
Courts and Tribunals Judiciary, “Guide to Judicial Conduct – Revised March 2018 (Updated
March 2020)”, Judiciary UK (available on its web site).
9
Sharíʿah, in general terms, also contains the rules by which the Muslim nation, in the broad-
est sense of the word, is organised, and it provides all the means necessary for resolving
conflicts among individuals, between individuals and the state, as well as between the states
themselves.
10
Various justice systems have drafted Codes of Judicial Conduct. In some Member States,
violations of the code may result in sanctions, including in Italy and in the United States
(both at the federal and state levels). In other Member States, the codes of judicial conduct
are not conceived as a set of enforceable rules, but rather as an ideal guide of judicial behav-
iour.
11
The Qur’án is the words of God conveyed to the people by his Messenger (Prophet Mu-
hammad ()ﷺ, the earliest and the central religious text of Islám. Many Western scholars con-
sider the Qur’án – in addition to containing timeless moral and spiritual injections – as a
rich repository of guidance on real-life situations, with injunctions regulating a vast field,
that also covers rules on adjudication and the responsibility of the judiciary. See, for exam-
ple, Onder Bakircioglu, “The Principal Sources of Islamic Law”, in Tallyn Gray (ed.), Islam
and International Criminal Law and Justice, Torkel Opsahl Academic EPublisher, Brussels,
2018, p. 20.
12
The Sunnah is Prophetic ḥadíth (sayings) as well as practices and deeds attributed to the
Prophet Mohammad, that were narrated to us via the Prophet’s companions and their succes-
Both the Qur’án and the Sunnah are the principal primary sources of
Sharí‘ah. 15 Noticeably, Sharí‘ah’s jurisprudence (fiqh) 16 has vividly as-
sembled and interpreted those provisions to formulate such code. As we
will see below, early-classical Muslim jurists require ‘extra judicial quali-
ties’ more than the ‘standard criteria’ embedded in national and internation-
al instruments for the appointment in judicial positions, and integrity comes
at the top of this list of qualities. In fact, integrity in Sharí‘ah is a legally
binding requirement to be able to serve as a judge.
An international high-ranking civil servant has noted that “while
there are neutral countries, there are no neutral men”. 17 In this chapter, I
argue that in Islamic traditions such men do exist. We will see examples of
judges who disobeyed great rulers to protect their integrity and independ-
ence, without any regard of indebtedness towards anyone.
sors. The Sunnah constitutes the normative pattern of life established by the Prophet Mu-
hammad ()ﷺ. The Sunnah in the form of ḥadíth is supplementary to the Qur’án itself. It
helps to explain and clarify the Qur’án and provides practical applications of its teachings.
13
Ijmā‘ is the consensus of the Companion of the Prophet and later on the Muslim jurists on a
certain issue.
14
Qiyās (analogy) is a recognised source of Sharí‘ah that can be utilised by Muslim jurists and
scholars to reach legal norms.
15
For more information, see Adel Maged, “The Impact of Religion on Military Self-Interest in
Accountability: A Sharí‘ah Perspective”, in Morten Bergsmo and SONG Tianying (eds.),
Military Self-Interest in Accountability for Core International Crimes, Torkel Opsahl Aca-
demic Publisher, Brussels, 2015, pp. 141–166 (http://www.toaep.org/ps-pdf/25-bergsmo-
song-second).
16
Fiqh is a process by means of which jurists derive sets of guidelines, rules and regulations
from the rulings laid down in the Qur’án and the teachings and living example of the Proph-
et Muhammad ()ﷺ, the Sunnah. The science of fiqh is a discipline, intellectual-
methodological application, and a set of tools for other sciences that is used to reach rulings
in Sharí‘ah questions, mostly through ijtihád. Over the centuries, fiqh has been formulated
and elaborated upon by successive generations of learned jurists, through interpretation,
analogy, consensus and disciplined research. While the principles of the Qur’án and the
Sunnah are permanent, it is the nature of Islámic jurisprudence to facilitate for human beings
the application of those principles to their daily-life activities and dealings. In other words,
Sharí‘ah fiqh is the human understanding and implementation of Sharí‘ah and the process
by which Muslim jurists (fuqaha) extract legal rulings (ahkam) from the primary sources of
Islám (Qur’án, Sunnah, Ijmā and Qiyās). It encompasses the vast corpus of juristic scholar-
ship and jurisprudential texts produced by early and modern Muslim jurists.
17
See Morten Bergsmo, Wolfgang Kaleck, Alexander Muller and William H. Wiley, “A Prose-
cutor Falls, Time for the Court to Rise”, FICHL Policy Brief Series no. 86 (2017), Torkel
Opsahl Academic Publisher, Brussels, 2017, p. 4 (https://www.toaep.org/pbs-pdf/86-four-
directors/).
18
Ibid., p. 3.
19
Ibid., p. 2.
20
ICCBA Statement on Allegations Against Former ICC Prosecutor, 29 November 2017.
3.2. Methodology
It is admitted among the majority of Western legal scholars that there is no
consensus on the meaning of judicial integrity, nor on its functioning in
practice. Conspicuously, some contend that integrity discourses differ from
one jurisdiction to another, and that the meaning of the term itself, differs
significantly per profession and, in the case of judges, per jurisdiction. 21
This has had a great impact on the comprehension and the adoption of the
term at the international level. The term has not yet been comprehensively
addressed in a single document issued by existing international courts.
To address this loophole, I will revisit Sharí‘ah sources to see how
they approach the judiciary in general, and, specifically, how they address
the concept of judicial integrity. Hence, I will carefully inquire into those
sources to explore whether Sharí‘ah is a norm of its own or a holistic con-
cept that encompasses other norms and/or values; and examine whether
integrity is a legally binding requirement and a prerequisite quality for a
person to assume the judicial position. This requires delving into early-
classical and original literature by eminent Sharí‘ah jurists (hereafter,
‘classical Sharí‘ah literature’), as experience has proven that intermediary
references on Sharí‘ah, especially those written in non-Arabic languages,
may not have authenticity and confidence, and could disrupt the real mean-
ing of the original sources, or at least “evaporate their authentic aroma”. 22
Unfortunately, the intermediary non-Arabic literature on Sharí‘ah very of-
ten cannot fully convey the letter and spirit of the text to the reader. Ac-
cordingly, it is preferable for those who research Sharí‘ah’s sources and
jurisprudence (fiqh) to have an excellent command of the Arabic language
and to be well acquainted with Sharí‘ah sciences in order to be able to
search and interpret provisions in accordance with required scholarly
standards. As we will see below, there is ijmā‘ among Muslim jurists that
one who practices ijtihád 23 should be skilful in the Arabic language, as the
original sources of Sharí‘ah are in Arabic. Unfortunately, a very small por-
tion of the tools of knowledge required for ijtihád is available in other lan-
guages.
21
See Jonathan Soeharno, “Is judicial integrity a norm? An inquiry into the concept of judicial
integrity in England and the Netherlands”, in Utrecht Law Review, vol. 3, no. 1, 2007, p. 8.
22
Jeffrey Einboden, Nineteenth-Century U.S. Literature in Middle Eastern Languages, Edin-
burgh University Press, 2013, p. 55.
23
Ijtihád is an individual and independent juristic reasoning exercised to provide answers to
legal or other religious questions that there is no basis in the Qur’án and Sunnah.
27
See Appendix II for further details. To review the original texts of the Message in Arabic,
see Alī Al-Salaby, Alī Ibn Abī Ṭālib: shaghsyaton wa asroh (Alī Ibn Abī Ṭālib: His Personal-
ity and Era), in History of Rashid Caliph Series, Maktabat Al-Sahaba, UAE, 2004, vol. 2,
p. 369. This Letter is to be considered as an original reference for those who study Sharí‘ah
jurisprudence, and is found under ‘Letter 53’ of the famous Nahj al-Balāgha collection (The
way of Eloquence), which contains 240 sermons given by Caliph Alī Ibn Abī Ṭālib dealing
with a wide variety of topics including human existence, relationship with God, building a
God-fearing personality, and other reflections upon historical incidents.
28
Imam Abú Bakr Aḥmad Ibn Umar Ibn Mahir al-Shaybānī, known as Al-Khaṣṣāf, an early-
classical Muslim scholar, belongs to the Hanafite School of fiqh, and author of voluminous
compendiums of early Islámic history.
29
Imam Ahmmad Ibn Abi Ahmmad Abú Abbas Al-Ṭabarī, known as Ibn Al-Kāss, an early-
classical Muslim scholar, belongs to the S̲h̲āfi School of fiqh, and author of large compendi-
ums of early Islámic history and Qurʾānic exegesis.
30
Imam Abū Ishāq S̲h̲ihāb Al-Dīn Ibrāhīm Ibn ʿAbd Allāh al-Ḥamawī, better known as Ibn
AbīʾAl-Dam , an early-classical Muslim scholar, belongs to S̲h̲āfiʿī School of Islámic fiqh,
and was the chief Islámic judge in his native Ḥamāt, Syria. F. Rosenthal, “Ibn AbīʾAl-Dam”,
in P. Bearman, Th. Bianquis, C.E. Bosworth, E. van Donzel and W.P. Heinrichs (eds.), Ency-
clopedia of Islám, second edition, Brill Academic, 1986.
of the holy text. Hence, I will try my best to simplify the meaning of its
verses to the reader, without disrupting its original connotations. 31
3.3. Adab Al-Qāḍī: A Comprehensive Resource in Sharí‘ah on the
Judiciary
Adab Al-Qāḍī refers to a compendium of early-classical Islamic jurispru-
dential literature written by renowned Muslim jurists belonging to all Is-
lamic schools of thought. The authors of Adab Al-Qāḍī gathered and com-
mented on various legal and judicial issues in light of the primary sources
of Sharí‘ah, with detailed explanation, in accordance with established rules
of research in Islamic fiqh.
Adab Al-Qāḍī is an important original jurisprudential source of Sha-
rí‘ah that studies in depth the institution and discipline of judgeship in
Muslim societies. It expounds the basic principles of the Islamic judicial
system and the function of the judiciary, for instance, court proceedings,
litigations, and the taking of testimony. It also addresses issues related to
the qualifications and qualities of the judges, 32 their appointment, and re-
moval from office. It goes further to explore the relationship between al-
qāḍī and a ruler, and sheds some light on judicial integrity questions, such
as the nature of judgeship, the manners and propriety of judges, in particu-
lar, what they must do, what they may do, what is forbidden to them, and
what is abhorred. Noticeably, it covers the ethics and conduct of judges and
is designed to enable judges to administer justice on the foundations of
Sharí‘ah sources. 33
Indeed, early-classical Muslim jurists have left great treasures of le-
gal knowledge, awaiting to be explored. The wealth of knowledge on al-
qāḍī behaviour in his daily life and conduct while undertaking his judicial
function that Adab Al-Qāḍī presents is broad, comprehensive and needs
more in-depth research. Each treatise is interspersed with actual cases and
models that cover these topics. As stated in one contemporary English
31
The author used several translations of the Qur’án on a case-by-case basis depending on his
agreement on the strategy used in transferring the meaning of each verse.
32
Ibn AbīʾAl-Dam, Adab Al-Qāḍī, 1984, first edition, Iraqi Ministry of Endowments and Reli-
gious Affairs, Bag̲h̲dād, vol. 1, p. 6.
33
Ibid., pp. 136–137.
source commending Adab Al-Qāḍī: “It is important for the wealth of mate-
rials it offers the practitioner in terms of both procedures and substance”. 34
3.4. Methodological Consideration Regarding the Meaning of Adab
Al-Qāḍī
Some authors have endeavoured to write commentaries on Adab Al-Qāḍī in
contemporary Western scholarship. However, some have committed a
methodological mistake by referring to Adab Al-Qāḍī as “etiquette of the
judge”. Unfortunately, this translation does not reflect the true meaning or
the content and subject-matter of Adab Al-Qāḍī.
In classical Arabic dictionaries, the word ‘adab’ has two connota-
tions. First, in literature which mainly refers to the products of the human-
thinking in different fields of knowledge. In other words, it refers to sophis-
ticated collections of spoken and written works on certain or particular sub-
jects, that may be classified according to a variety of systems and fields of
knowledge, which are deemed to have artistic or intellectual value. 35 It may
also refer to articulated works of poetry and prose of lasting artistic merits,
which require the knowledge of Arabic and Sharí‘ah sciences. 36 Second,
literally, it means politeness and propriety. 37 In his renowned Arabic dic-
tionary al- Qamous al-Muheet, al-Fairūzābādī refers to the word ‘adab’ as
“good manners”. 38
Adab Al-Qāḍī refers to sophisticated collections and literature written
on the art of adjudication that focus on the conduct of Al-Qāḍī. As one au-
thority explained, Adab Al-Qāḍī refers to a “compendium of the principles
of adjudications”. Therefore, the title Adab Al-Qāḍī does not reflect only
the etiquette or manners of al-qāḍī, but it covers different branches of sci-
ences related to the judiciary and legal proceedings before the courts.
Linguistically, the word ‘etiquette’ in English literature refers to a set
of rules or customs for polite behaviour in particular in social groups or
34
Chibli Mallat, “Comparative Law and the Islámic (Middle Eastern) Legal Culture”, in Ma-
thias Reimann and Reinhard Zimmermann (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Comparative
Law, second edition, Oxford University Press, 2019, p. 630.
35
See Al-Waseet Dictionary, second edition, Arabic Language Academy, vol. 2, 1985, pp. 9–
10.
36
See Ibn Khaldun, 2004, vol. 2, p. 376, see above note 24.
37
Ibid., pp. 9–10.
38
Al-Fairūzābādī, Al- Qamous al-Muheet, third edition, The General Egyptian Book Organisa-
tion, vol. 1, 1977, p. 36.
39
“Etiquette”, Encyclopaedia Britannica (available on its web site).
40
See, for example, Mohamed Emam, Ausoul Al-Hesba in Islám, Dar Al-Hedayah, 1986, p. 71.
41
See, René David and John E.C. Brierley (eds.), Major Legal Systems in the World Today: An
Introduction to the Comparative Study of Law, second edition, Stevens and Sons, London,
1978, p. 421; Mashood A. Baderin, “Effective Legal Representation in ‘Shari’ah’ Courts as
a Means of Addressing Human Rights Concerns in the Islámic Criminal Justice System of
Muslim States”, in Eugene Cotran, Martin Lau and Victor Kattan (eds.), Yearbook of Islámic
and Middle Eastern Law, vol. 11, no. 1, Brill, Leiden, 2004, pp. 135–67.
42
Maged, 2015, p. 142, see above note 15.
tions on the concept of judicial integrity and their implications for the in-
ternational justice system.
Succinctly, classical Muslim jurists have formulated a coherent sys-
tem of Islamic legal jurisprudence that covers issues related to justice and
the qualifications of judges, and, interestingly, addressing the core issues of
integrity in justice. Accordingly, it is imperative to look at the sources of
Sharí‘ah when examining this central concept. Before doing so, as a logical
development of the topic under research, I will first shed some light on the
status of the judiciary as such in Sharí‘ah.
3.7. The Importance of Justice in Sharí‘ah
Justice in Islam means giving equal rights and treatment to others. The
meaning of justice in Arabic is close to ‘equality’ in the sense that it creates
a state of equilibrium in the distribution of rights and duties. Justice in Is-
lam is a religious duty, and it is a cornerstone of the tenets of Islam. It is
also a basic objective and a supreme virtue, as stipulated in the Qur’án and
Sunnah. No wonder that al-ʿAdl (The utterly just) is one of the 99 divine
Names of God, stipulated in the Qur’án and the Sunnah, called in Arabic
asmāullah al-ḥusnā.
It is forbidden in Islam to punish unjustly or to do injustice to others. It is
narrated by the Prophet Muḥammad ( )ﷺthat God said:
O My worshipers, I have forbidden injustice for Myself and
forbade it also for you. So, avoid being unjust to one anoth-
er. 43
Upholding this concept, Imam Ibn Taymiyyah 44 said: “God upholds
the just State even if it is disbelieving, and does not uphold the unjust one
even if it is a Muslim believing State”. 45
As we will see below, God commanded the Prophet Muḥammad ()ﷺ
to promote and observe justice, as a divine duty and an attribute of human
personality, which carries a great burden. In this context, the Prophet
43
Sahih Muslim, Sharh al-Nawāwy, Kortoba Foundation Publisher, Cairo, first edition, 1999,
vol. 16, ḥadíth no. 2577, p. 199.
44
Taqī Ad-Dīn Aḥmad Ibn Taymiyyah, early-classical Sunni Muslim scholar.
45
Imam Ibn Taymiyyah, majmou fatawa Ibn Taymiyyah (The Compendium of Juristic Opin-
ions of Emam Ibn Taymiyyah), Abdelrahman Kassem (ed.), King Fahd Complex for Print-
ing The Holy Quran, Saudi Ministry of Islámic Affairs Dawah and Guidance, KSA, 2004,
vol. 28, p. 63.
46
Sahih Muslim, Sharh Al-Nawāwy, Egyptian Press Al-Azhar, Cairo, first edition, 1930, vol.
12, p. 4–6; Imam Mālik Ibn Anas, Al-Muwatta, Dar Al-Taeseel, first edition, 2016, vol. 2,
p. 183.
47
Qur’án, surat Al-Ma’idah, 5:8.
48
Al-Mawardi, 1989, p. 100, see above note 24.
49
Ibid., p. h.
50
Imam Ibn Qudāmah Al-Maqdīsī Muwaffaq Al-Dīn Abū Muḥammad ʿAbd Allāh Ibn Aḥmad
Ibn Muḥammad is an early renowned Sunni Muslim jurist who contributed many important
treatises on jurisprudence and religious doctrine, including one of the classical works of
Hanbali school of jurisprudence, Al-Mug̲h̲nī.
lowing ḥadíth of the Prophet Muḥammad ( )ﷺas another base for the ne-
cessity of the judiciary in the Muslim community:
When a judge delivers a judgement, having striven to decide
correctly and is right, then he will receive double the reward,
and if he delivers a judgement, having striven to decide cor-
rectly but erred, then he receives a single reward. 51
This means that a fair and righteous judge is rewarded in all cases; yet, he
has to exert his best efforts to reach a judgement.
Captivatingly, the Prophet ( )ﷺdescribed the judicial function as one
of the blessings for which envy is permitted, as he said:
There should be no envy except in two cases: a man to whom
God has given wealth and granted him the authority to spend
it in a rightful manner and a man to whom God has given wis-
dom and he judges and acts on the basis of it. 52
Acknowledging the importance of the judiciary and its supreme sta-
tus and solemn message, Umar Ibn Al-Khaṭṭáb used to send messages to
the judges he had appointed all over the Muslim nation, 53 which included
advice to them. 54 He addressed the function of the judiciary and the con-
duct of judges in his famous message to Abú Moussa Al-Ash‘ari. The ma-
jority of Islamic scholars consider it as the judges’ charter, and some call it
‘the Book of Judicial Policy’. In the first paragraph of this message, Caliph
Umar Ibn Al-Khaṭṭáb stated that: “The right to adjudication is an absolute
(religious) duty and a followed Prophetic Tradition”. In his renowned
“Message to the Judiciary”, Ibn Khaldun asserts the divine nature of judg-
ing between people, which requires a complete devotion to God and His
support. 55
51
Sahih Muslim, Sharh al-Nawāwy, Dar al-Shāb, vol. 4, ḥadíth no. 13, p. 310; Imam ibn
Qudāmah, Al-Mug̲h̲nī, commentary by Sheikh Mahmoud Fayed, Cairo Library, Cairo, vol.
10, p. 32.
52
Al-Shahīd al-Sadr, 1977, p. 72, see above note 26.
53
For more information, see, Mahe Abd Elmajid Aboud, “The Juridical Bases in the Letter of
Umar Ibn al-Khattab”, vol. 1, Dar Al-Kotob Al-Ilmiyah, Beirut, 2009, p. 11.
54
Sliman Mohamed El-Tamawy, Judicial Policy in the Umar Ibn Al-Khaṭṭáb Epoch and its
Impact on our Modern Era, Dar Elfekr El-Araby, Cairo, 1969, p. 329.
55
See Ibn Khaldun, mozil al-malam an hukam al-anam, Foad Abdelmonem Ahmed (ed.), first
edition, Dar al-Watan, Riyadh, 1996, p. 105.
56
Ibn Qudāmah, p. 32, see above note 51.
57
Qur’án, surat An-Nisaa’, 4:58.
58
Qur’án, surat Al-Ma'idah, 5:42.
59
Qur’án, Surat Sad, 38:26.
60
Al-Syuti al-Raihabany, mataleb oly al-nahy fe sharh ghayet al-montha, Sheihk Hassan al-
Shaty (ed.), first edition, the Islámic Bureau, Damascus, 1961, vol. 6, p. 454.
61
Ibid.
62
AbīʾAl-Dam, 1984, p. 126, see above note 32.
who was responsible for selecting and appointing judges, governing their
affairs, supervising their work, as well as protect their independence. Sub-
sequently, the appointment and removal of judges was the responsibility of
the Muslim nation’s ruler. He was responsible for supervising their behav-
iour and monitoring their performance. In all cases, it was considered a re-
ligious duty for the ruler to provide for the administration of justice
through the appointment of judges. 63
At that time, the al-qāḍī court was a single-judge court with general
jurisdiction, hence al-qāḍī was competent to adjudicate all kinds of litiga-
tions brought before him. His basic function was to settle disputes and allo-
cate rights to litigants, in accordance with the injunctions (both command-
ments and prohibitions) of the divine rules of Islamic law. In other words,
al-qāḍī must apply the rules stipulated mainly in the Qur’án and Sunnah,
or resort to ijtihád when the Qur’án and Sunnah are silent.
As mentioned before, one of the most comprehensive, while succinct,
instruments in Sharí‘ah that contains the required criteria for the appoint-
ment of judges is the Message of Caliph Alī Ibn Abī Ṭālib to his commis-
sioner in Egypt, Malik al-Ashtar on the Judiciary, in which he instructed
him of the qualities that he should observe when selecting a person to act
as qāḍī. 64
3.8.2. The Status of Judges in Sharí‘ah
The foregoing has established that the existence of a functional judicial
system is imperative for the Muslim nation. However, such judicial system
requires highly qualified judges. The existence of judges is considered by
Islamic law to be both a religious duty and a necessity for the functioning
of society. Reflecting this fact, God says: “We have sent Messengers with
clear proofs, and sent down with them the Scripture and the balance that
mankind can establish justice”. 65
Upholding justice is considered in Islam as a divine mission compen-
sated by God. In this context, the Prophet ( )ﷺsaid: “A day of just leader-
ship is better than sixty years of worship”. 66 261F
63
Rulers of the Muslim nation who were appointed after the Prophet Muhammad and subse-
quently in medieval Islám.
64
Alī Al-Salaby, 2004, p. 369, see above note 27.
65
Qur’án surat Al-Hadid, 57:25.
66
Al-Shahīd Al-Sadr, 1977, vol. 1, p. 127, see above note 26.
67
Imam Al-Baihaqi, “Al-Sunan Al-Kobrá”, Abdallh Al-Turkey (ed.), first edition, Hagar Cen-
tre for Research, Arabic and Islámic Studies, Cairo, 2011, vol. 20, p. 245.
68
Imam Ibn Qudāmah, Al-Mug̲h̲nī yalih al-sharh al-kabeer, Dar al-Kitab al-Araby, Cairo, vol.
11, p. 374.
69
Ibn AbīʾAl-Dam, 1984, p. 6, see above note 32.
70
Al-Tirmidhi, ḥadíth no. 1322, p. 321, see above note 1.
71
Sahih Muslim, Darussalam, 2007, vol. 7, ḥadíth no. 1031, p. 76.
72
Ibn Majah, Sunan Ibn Majah, Centre of Research and Information Technology, Dar al-
Taseel, 2014, first edition, vol. 2, no. 2312, p. 455.
73
Ibn Qudāmah, Al-Mug̲h̲nī, vol. 10 p. 35, see above note 51.
74
Onder Bakircioglu, “The Principal Sources of Islamic Law”, in Tallyn Gray (ed.), Islam and
International Criminal Law and Justice, Torkel Opsahl Academic EPublisher, Brussels,
2018 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/0528c5/).
75
Imam Abú Isaaq Al-Shatby, Al-Muwafaqat, Dar Ibn Afan for Publication and Disruption,
KSA, 1997, vol. 3, p. 213.
in order to avoid assuming this position and they bore it with patience.
Some of them even accepted being beaten and imprisoned instead of being
appointed, and others fled from their homelands in order to avoid being
appointed as judges. He explained that “[t]hey feared the serious responsi-
bility of judging between people, in the assumption that they did not fulfil
the required conditions”. 76 Some others feared the grave danger of passing
incorrect judgements, as indicated in many of the ḥadíth of the Prophet ()ﷺ,
in which a stern warning is issued to the one who is appointed as a judge
and does not fulfil the obligations and requirements needed to be a judge.
The gravity of the responsibility of al-qāḍī is illustrated in a famous
ḥadíth by the Prophet Muḥammad ()ﷺ, in which he mentioned how God
would hold al-qāḍī accountable for all his deeds. He said: “Al-qāḍī, though
the just one, will be brought (before God) in the day of Resurrection, due to
the severe accountability he will face, he would have wished that he did not
decide between two (even in half a date)”. 77 27F
76
Sheikh ‘Ala Al-Deen Al-Taraabulsi, Mu’een al-Hukkaam fima yataraddadu bayna al-
Khasmayni min al-Ahkaam, p. 9.
77
Al-Baihaqi, 2011, p. 275, see above note 67.
78
Al-Shahīd al-Sadr, 1977, vol. 1, p. 127, see above note 26.
79
Ibn Qudāmah, Al-Mug̲h̲nī, vol. 10, p. 33, see above note 51.
his heart and make his tongue steadfast. When two litigants sit
in front of you, do not decide until you hear what the other has
to say as you heard what the first had to say; for it is best that
you should have a clear idea of the best decision. Alī said: I
had never doubted about a decision that I made between two
(people) ever after. 80
The foregoing reflects the meaning of the Prophet’s ḥadíth that was
situated at the beginning of this chapter: “He who is appointed as a judge is
slaughtered without a knife”. In his treatise on Adab Al-Qāḍī, Imam Ibn
AbīʾAl-Dam recounted two meanings reported by an early-Muslim jurist.
He who has appointed as qāḍī is like a man who is slaughtered because (1)
he has to suppress his desires, defeat his inclinations and prevent himself
from social life; and (2) he is exposed to great danger, as he cannot fulfil
the necessities of this job. 81
Imam Ibn AbīʾAl-Dam goes further in explaining that the word
‘slaughter’ should be understood metaphorically to mean that al-qāḍī
should exert his utmost efforts to ensure that he justly adjudicate cases
brought before him according to the highest standards of Sharí‘ah. 82
As explained by Imam Al-Syuti, this ḥadíth of the Prophet ( )ﷺwarns
of the gravity of al-qāḍī’s duties, and the word slaughter is used as a meta-
phor which refers to the grave consequences that a judge could suffer if he
erred in his judgement. 83 278F
80
Al-Baihaqi, Ahmed Ibn El-Hussein, Al-sunan we al-athar (The Sunah and Traces), Sayed
Kasrawy Hassan (ed.), Dar Al-Kotob Al-Ilmiyah, Beirut, first edition, 1991, vol. 7, Book of
Adab Al-Qadi, ḥadíth no. 5874, p. 368; Sunan Abī Dāwūd, Abī Trab Adel Ibn Muhammad
and Abi Amr Ibn Abbas (eds.), Dar al-Taseel, first edition, 2015, vol. 5, no. 3537, pp. 578–
588; Alī Al-Salaby, 2004, p. 153, see above note 27.
81
Ibn AbīʾAl-Dam, 1984, p. 259, see above note 32.
82
Ibid., pp. 260–261.
83
Al-Syuti al-Raihabany, 1961 p. 454, see above note 60; See also Ibn Qudāmah, Al-Mug̲h̲nī
yalih al-sharh al-kabeer, vol. 11, p. 374, see above note 68.
the post were strict. A person selected to act as al-qāḍī should be suitably
qualified to fulfil such a position and fulfil the prerequisite qualifications
required by Sharí‘ah law.
3.9.1. Prerequisite Qualifications of the Al-Qāḍī
Sharí‘ah rules on the judicial function are stringent when it comes to the
qualifications that a qāḍī should possess. In order to be appointed as qāḍī,
early-classical Muslim jurists identified basic requirements that a person
should enjoy: he must be a free Muslim of legal capacity, be of sound mind,
with full sensory perception, and possess high moral probity or rectitude.
This means that al-qāḍī should be one of upright character, of a mature and
balanced personality, with no ulterior motives, physically and psychologi-
cally healthy, of sound hearing and sight, and is able to communicate ver-
bally in the language used in court.
Besides the above-mentioned requirements, the majority of Muslim
jurists agree that it is a prerequisite in Sharí‘ah that any individual seeking
to act as a qāḍī should possesses sound knowledge of Qur’án, Sunnah and
fiqh, as his work must be totally congruent with Islamic law. Therefore, he
should have the capacity to exercise ijtihád. This requires that the al-qāḍī
must be sufficiently educated and knowledgeable about the law that he ap-
plies, and able to perform ijtihád to extract legal rulings from original
sources. 84
This approach was illustrated in the tradition of the Prophet Mu-
hammad ( )ﷺnarrated by his companions. It was narrated by Mu’adh Ibn
Jabal when the Prophet appointed him as al-qāḍī in Yemen. Some compan-
ions of Mu’adh Ibn Jabal said: “When the Messenger of God ( )ﷺintended
to send Mu’adh Ibn Jabal to Yemen”, he asked: “What will you do if a mat-
ter is referred to you for judgement?”. Mu’adh said: “I will judge according
to the Book of God”. The Prophet asked: “What if you find no solution in
the Book of God?”. Mu’adh said: “Then I will judge by the Sunnah of the
Prophet”. The Prophet asked: “And what if you do not find it in the Sunnah
of the Prophet?”. Mu’adh said: “Then I will delicately exert ijtihád to reach
a resolution”. The Prophet patted Mu’adh’s chest and said: “Praise be to
84
Ibn AbīʾAl-Dam, 1984, pp. 134–135, see above note 32.
God who has guided the messenger of His Prophet to that which pleases
His Prophet”. 85
Asserting the responsibilities of al-qāḍī attached to this religious duty,
in his message to Abú Moussa Al-Ash'ari, Caliph Umar Ibn Al-Khaṭṭáb in-
structed him as follows:
If a case is brought before you and you cannot find applicable
rule(s) neither in the Qu’ran nor in the Sunnah, then you must
resort to logical reasoning, and use analogy, comparison and
parallelism (to reach a judgement). Consequently, apply the
ruling that you consider closest to what is right and fair and
that would please God Almighty.
Numerous early-classical literature is written on ijtihád as a prerequi-
site to occupy the judicial office. According to a contemporary Muslim
scholar, as stated in his article on “The Requirement of Ijtihád to Occupy
the Judicial Office”: “The majority of early Muslim jurists regard ijtihád as
inevitable quality”. 86 Thus, according to Sharí‘ah provisions, judges are
chosen from among people who already have a consolidated experience in
the interpretation and application of Sharí‘ah. However, Muslim jurists be-
longing to modern jurisprudential schools argue that in the modern eras, it
is difficult to find judges who have the skills to exercise ijtihád, as recog-
nised in Sharí‘ah. 87 Thus, in many Arab countries nowadays, the require-
ment of ijtihád is no longer a prerequisite for the appointment in the judici-
ary, it suffices that the judge has commendable legal knowledge, and judi-
cial skills necessary for the proper performance of his judicial duties.
Further, to assume the judicial function, al-qāḍī should possess the
highest standards of integrity. Ibn Qayyim al-Jawziyyah 88 asserted that the
person appointed for this task should be the best of the nominees. He
should also be religious and pious. 89 Alī Ibn Abī Ṭālib said: “A person
85
Sunan Abī Dāwūd, vol. 5, no. 3547, pp. 584–585, see above note 80; Al-Shaid al-Sadr, Al-
Khaṣṣāf, 1977, vol. 1, p. 127; Al-Mawardi, 1989, p. 90, see above note 24.
86
Abd Al-Aziz Al-Meshal, Shart al-ijtihád fiman yaly al-qada, Megalat Al-Adel (Justice
Journal), 2009, vol. 43, p. 127.
87
Al-Shahīd Al-Sadr, 1977, vol. 1, p. 206, see above note 26.
88
Ibn Qayyim al-Jawziyyah (691/1292-751/1350) was born in a village near Damascus, Syria.
His contributions to Islámic writings are extensive, dealing most with Qur’ánic commen-
taries and prophetic traditions. He was a student of Ibn Taymiyyah, but did not restrict him-
self to the Hanbali madhab and sometimes took view from other madhabs or no madhab.
89
Ibn Qayyim al-Jawziyyah, I’lam al-Muwaqqi’in a̒ n Rabb al ̒Alamin, Narrated by Abd El-
Rahman El-Wakeel, vol. I, Dar Ehya al Turath al Araby, Beirut, p. 114.
90
Ibn Qudāmah, Al-Mug̲h̲nī, vol. 10, p. 40, see above note 51.
91
Ibid.; Ibn Qudāmah, vol. 11, p. 386, see above note 68.
92
Muhammad Taher, al-garh we al-taeddl, al-Dar al-Arabia Llketab, 1997, p. 249.
93
Ibn Qudāmah, vol. 22, pp. 380–384, see above note 68.
94
UNODC, 2011, p. 79, see above note 2.
95
Al-Waseet Dictionary, p. 952, see above note 35.
er and acts as an umbrella for many other virtues required to hold a judicial
position.
It seems that occasional contemporary scholars and practitioners
started to support the same approach of Sharí‘ah towards judicial integrity
as a ‘virtue’ and a ‘moral’ character required for appointment in a judicial
position. For example, Andrzej Rzeplinski, the President of the Constitu-
tional Tribunal of Poland, admits that a judge without morals or integrity is
no judge at all. He stated that:
The profession of being a judge is not a good career for per-
sons who do not possess a sufficiently well-established sense
of personal and professional dignity, the virtue of personal in-
tegrity, impeccable past, professional and practical knowledge,
social and family maturity, and personal maturity to be able to
assume full responsibility for each ruling passed in accordance
with the law and with their own conscience. 96
96
UNODC, Judicial Conduct and Ethics, Self-Directed Course, Vienna, 2019, p. vii.
97
R.N. Prasad and P. Chakraborty, Administration of Justice and the Judicial Administration in
Mizoram, Mittal Publications, New Delhi, 2006, p. 4.
98
Md. Manjur Hossain Patoari et al., “The Desired Qualities of a Good Judge”, in Academic
Journal of Interdisciplinary Studies, MCSER Publishing, Rome-Italy, vol. 3, no. 1, March
2014, p. 97.
99
Bangalore Principles of Judicial Conduct, Article 1.6, see above note 6.
100
Ibid., Value 3.1.
101
Ibid., Value 3.2.
102
Ibid., Value 3.2.
Those who had the opportunity to read the most renowned literature
on Adab Al-Qāḍī, would recognise that Sharí‘ah requires extra judicial
qualities that the al-qāḍī should possess. In his treatise on Adab Al-Qāḍī,
Ibn AbīʾAl-Dam addressed the qualities that the al-qāḍī should possess,
and the environment that should surround him in court, classifying them
under the title Adab Al-Qāḍī. He divided such qualities and conditions into
three categories: the first category includes forms of conduct attached to
the personality of the al-qāḍī (personal qualities); the second category co-
vers traditions and formalities that surround the judicial function, mostly
attached to the judicial institution itself (judicial institutional formalities);
and the third category covers specific professional qualities required for the
proper execution of al-qāḍī judicial duties (professional qualities). 105
As I have already mentioned, judicial integrity is a holistic term that
encompasses various qualities that al-qāḍī should possess. Those qualities
reflect intrinsic values that are manifested in the al-qāḍī’s personal charac-
teristics, such as ‘piousness’, ‘conscientiousness’, ‘righteousness’, ‘up-
rightness’, ‘propriety’, ‘dignity’, ‘esteem’, ‘firmness’, ‘patience’ and ‘cour-
tesy’. Some of these qualities are purely personal qualities that every Mus-
lim should practice, while some other qualities are attached to the conduct
of judges. Other qualities are associated to the al-qāḍī’s professional con-
duct during the performance of his judicial duties, such as ‘independence’,
‘impartiality’, ‘equality’, and ‘competence and diligence’, as affirmed in
the Bangalore Principles of Judicial Conduct.
Bearing in mind the purpose of this chapter, and for the sake of sim-
plicity, I will examine how Sharí‘ah sources address judicial integrity ac-
103
Qur’án, surat An-Nisaa’, 4:135.
104
Qur’án, surat Al-Ma’ida, 5:49.
105
Ibn AbīʾAl-Dam, 1984, vol. 1, p. 136, see above note 32.
106
UNODC, Resource Guide on Strengthening Judicial Integrity and Capacity, Vienna, 2011,
p. 127.
107
Imam Ibn Farhoun, Tabsrat Al-Hukam fe Osool Al-Akdiah we Manaheg Al-Ahkam (Insight
the Rulers of Fundamentals of Cases and Methodology of Judgements), Gamal Marashly
(ed.), Dar Alam Al-Kotob, Riyadh, 2003, vol. 1, p. 28.
108
Ibid., p. 28.
109
UNODC, 2011, p. 127, see above note 106.
110
Qur’án, surat Al-Hujurat, 49:11.
111
Ibn AbīʾAl-Dam, 1984, vol. 1, pp. 367–370, see above note 32.
112
Imam Ibn Al-Kāss, Adab Al-Qāḍī, Hussein Khalaf Al-Jobory (ed.), Maktabat Al-Sedeek,
KSA, 1989, vol. 1, p. 99.
113
Al-Shahīd al-Sadr, 1977, vol. 2, p. 66–69, see above note 26.
114
Ibn AbīʾAl-Dam, 1984, p. 137, see above note 32.
115
Al-Mawardi, 1989, p. 100, see above note 24.
116
Ibn Farhoun, 2003, vol. 1, p. 26, see above note 107.
117
Al-Shahīd al-Sadr, 1977, vol. 2, p. 65, see above note 26.
118
Ibid., p. 34–37.
119
Ibn Farhoun, 2003, vol. 1, p. 100, see above note 107; see also Al-Shahīd Al-Sadr, 1977, vol.
1, pp. 353–354, see above note 26.
120
Ibn Farhoun, 2003, vol. 1, p. 26, see above note 107.
cast doubts upon his demeanour and open the door for bribes or show fa-
vouritism to any party to a dispute before him. 121
The prohibition of accepting gifts and other privileges offered to al-
qāḍī is affirmed in various classical Islamic sources, as it raises suspen-
sions and subjects him to covet”. 122 Moreover, this type of conduct may
open the doors for the public to question his integrity and may consider
such gifts as bribes or favours. 123 In his treatise on Adab Al-Qāḍī, Imam Al-
Khaṣṣāf classifies such acts as pure bribes. 124 In all cases, the al-qāḍī
should never accept money from litigants to adjudicate between them, as
this is considered in Islam as a form of bribe. 125 It goes without saying that
he must not accept bribes in any forms. In this context, it is reported that
the Prophet Muḥammad ( )ﷺsaid: “May the curse of God be upon the one
who pays a bribe and the one who takes it”. 126 Bribery is a major sin in
321F
Sharí‘ah, and falls under fisq (a term that will be explained later).
However, there is a consensus among Sharí‘ah jurists that the al-qāḍī
may accept gifts from his relatives, except for those having cases pending
before him. As stated above, he may also continue to accept gifts from
those who gave him gifts before his appointment as qāḍī, but if they in-
crease the value of the gift after his appointment, then he should cease ac-
cepting such gifts. As such, the al-qāḍī should never compromise his value
for any reason. Thus, he must not appear to use his judicial position to per-
sonal advantage, nor must he act in a manner that raises suspicions about
his conduct.
On the basis of the foregoing, it is clear that, in Islam, the personality
of the al-qāḍī and his uprightness are traditionally viewed as being subor-
dinate to his judicial function. Bearing in mind the social discrepancies in
the early Islamic era, and for the proper administration of justice as exists
in our modern era, I can infer from Sharí‘ah sources that the following per-
sonal integrity values are required in order to assume a judicial position as
121
Ahmed Sharkawy, Haibat al-qāḍī fe al-fiqh al-Islámy wa al-kanoon al-wadey (Judge's Pres-
tige in Islámic Jurisprudence and Positive Law), al-Wafaa Library, first edition, 2018,
pp. 70–72.
122
Ibn Qudāmah, Al-Mug̲h̲nī, vol. 10, p. 68, see above note 51.
123
Al-Mawardi, 1989, p. 100, see above note 24.
124
Al-Shahīd al-Sadr, 1977, vol. 2, p. 37, see above note 26.
125
Ibid., p. 100.
126
Ibn Majah, 2014, vol. 2, no. 2316, p. 456, see above note 72.
127
Al-Tirmidhi, ḥadíth no. 3472, p. 782, see above note 1.
128
Imam Mālik, 2016, vol. 2, no. 1492, p. 392, see above note 46; Sunan Abī Dāwūd, 2015,
vol. 7, no. 4695, p. 291, see above note 80.
129
Al-Baihaqi, 2011, p. 315, see above note 67.
130
Ibn Qudāmah, vol. 11, p. 386, see above note 68.
131
Alī Al-Salaby, 2004, p. 369, see above note 27.
132
See, for example, David Klein and Darby Morrisroe, “The Prestige and Influence of Indi-
vidual Judges on the U.S. Courts of Appeals”, in Journal of Legal Studies, 1999, vol. 28, no.
2, p. 371.
that prestige only exists where justice and equality prevail. 133 Thus, judges
should aspire to preserve their judicial prestige, in order to increase the
amount of respect, regard and esteem to their courts. This requires that they
maintain order and decorum in all proceedings before the court and be pa-
tient, dignified and courteous in relation to litigants, jurors, witnesses, law-
yers and others with whom the judge deals in an official capacity. 134
To preserve his prestige, the al-qāḍī should present himself in a dig-
nified manner that commands the respect of others, even in his way of sit-
ting, dressing and grooming. 135 Dignity and esteem should be manifested in
al-qāḍī conduct in his private life and at court, as these qualities boost re-
spect of the public toward those who hold the judicial office and strengthen
the judicial function.
According to Sharí‘ah sources, it is important that the al-qāḍī should
be paid handsomely to preserve his dignity and prestige, Caliph Alī Ibn Abī
Ṭālib instructed Malik al-Ashtar accordingly:
Pay al-qāḍī handsomely enough, this removes his necessity
and there remain no occasion for him to go to others for his
need. Confer on him such a high stature so that persons who
are most close to you could not covet. Consequently, he would
be protected from their malign and back-biting.
From his side, the al-qāḍī should avoid with care any behaviour that
demeans his prestige and high office or diminish his chivalry. Accordingly,
the al-qāḍī in Islam should avoid laughing in the courtroom, 136 or being
humorous with the parties as this could diminish his esteem. 137 The al-
qāḍī’s esteem also requires that he should observe his demeanour inside
and outside the courtroom. The al-qāḍī should neither lend the prestige of
the judicial office to advance his private interests, to show off; nor should
he allow others to convey the impression that they are in a special position
to influence the judge. 138 In any case, according to the majority of early-
classical Muslim jurists, the al-qāḍī should never aspire to judicial prestige
as a modality to brag. 139
133
Ahmed Sharkawy, 2018, p. 3 see above note 121.
134
Ibn Farhoun, 2003, vol. 1, pp. 30–32, see above note 107.
135
Ibid., p. 26.
136
Ibid., p. 33.
137
Al-Shahīd al-Sadr, 1977, vol. 1, p. 343, see above note 26.
138
Ibid., pp. 16–17.
139
Al-Mawardi, 1989, p. 99, see above note 24.
This illustrates that dignity, esteem and firmness are important safe-
guards against improper influences, inducements, pressures, threats or in-
terferences, direct or indirect, in the judicial affairs, from any quarter or for
any reason.
As seen before, ‘independence’, ‘impartiality’, ‘equality’ and ‘com-
petence and diligence’ are recognised qualities, both in Sharí‘ah and con-
temporary international standards. Below I will explore how Sharí‘ah ad-
dresses these qualities.
3.15.1. Integrity and Recognised Professional Qualities
3.15.1.1. Equality
As recognised in current international standards, a judge in the perfor-
mance of his duties shall ensure the principle of equality before the courts
and the law, and pay the same attention to all participants in the process
regardless of their gender, race, nationality, property and social status, reli-
gion, or membership in public associations. 140
The virtue of equality requires the al-qāḍī to treat both parties to liti-
gation equally from the beginning to the end of the proceedings. According
to Sharí‘ah principles, the al-qāḍī has to treat litigants at his court equally,
so that people could never doubt his impartiality. 141 He should invite them
to his court at the same time, allow them to enter together, and let them sit
before him at similar places and listen to them equally without any distinc-
tion. 142 Imam Al-Khaṣṣāf, had addressed in details the manner in which the
litigants should sit before the al-qāḍī. 143
Equal treatment should apply to both the strong and the weak, the
ruler and the subjects, and so on. 144 Acknowledging that equality is an es-
sential principle for due performance of the judicial office, in his message,
Caliph Umar Ibn Al-Khaṭṭáb advises the al-qāḍī to be aware of that princi-
ple in the way he treats all litigants who appear before him. In the third
paragraph of his message, Caliph Umar Ibn Al-Khaṭṭáb (may God be
pleased with him) instructed Abú Moussa Al-Ash'ari on the qualities that he
140
Draft Codes of Ethics of Judges in the Republic of Kazakhstan, Venice Commission, Stras-
bourg, 2 April 2016, CDL-REF(2016)023, p. 4 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/klnjt7/).
141
Ibn AbīʾAl-Dam, 1984, p. 137, see above note 32.
142
Ibid., p. 353.
143
Al-Shahīd al-Sadr, 1977, vol. 2, pp. 84–87, see above note 26.
144
Al-Mawardi, 1989, p. 95, see above note 24.
should administer concerning the litigants who will appear before him. He
wrote to him:
Be equal to the parties appearing before you, and let your fair-
ness be manifested in the way they seat in your divan (court-
room), in your face (facial expressions) and in your judgement,
so that no noble person can ever hope that you will favour
him/her unfairly, nor can a layman ever doubt your fairness;
Caliph Umar Ibn Al-Khaṭṭáb went beyond the required standard of
equality to ask the al-qāḍī to observe his demeanours as a crucial element
to maintain his impartiality during the proceedings, because it is what oth-
ers see. In this respect, Caliph Umar Ibn Al-Khaṭṭáb advises the al-qāḍī to
observe his conduct, which appears in his facial expressions or even in the
way the litigants are seated before him. This approach of Caliph Umar Ibn
Al-Khaṭṭáb demonstrates his aim to preserve public confidence in the in-
tegrity of the judiciary.
The highest standards of equality and impartiality are manifested in
the following statement of Caliph Umar Ibn Al-Khaṭṭáb on the Judiciary:
“let your fairness be manifest in your face”.
Imam Al-Khaṣṣāf emphasises that the al-qāḍī should be equal to the
parties who appear before him, even in the way he looks at them. 145 Ac-
cording to Ibn Qayyim al-Jawziyyah, this clause elaborates how the al-qāḍī
should treat all parties who appear before him on equal terms, without any
distinction. The al-qāḍī should not smile at one of the litigants or give
him/her special attention, as this may manifest a sense of impartiality. 146
According to Imam Al-Khaṣṣāf, al-qāḍī should speak to all litigants in the
same tone of voice. 147
A famous case in the Islamic tradition that illustrates how equality is
well-observed among early Muslim judges is the case of Caliph Alī Ibn Abī
Ṭālib v. the Jew. Caliph Alī lost his armour during the war. When the war
was over and he returned to Kufah-Iraq, he came across the armour in the
hands of a Jew. The Jew said to Caliph Alī: “It is my armour and it is in my
hand”. Caliph Alī brought a claim before the appointed qāḍī (the famous
judge Shuraih) alleging that the Jew had stolen his shield. The al-qāḍī
145
Al-Shaid al-Sadr, 1977, vol. 1, p. 218, see above note 85.
146
Ibn Qayyim al-Jawziyyah, I’lam al-Muwaqqi’in ‘an Rabb al ‘Alamin, Narrated by Abd El-
Rahman El-Wakeel, vol. I, Dar Ehya al Turath al Araby, Beirut, p. 96.
147
Al-Shaid al-Sadr, 1977, vol. 2, p. 92, see above note 85.
asked Caliph Alī to produce his witnesses to prove his claim. Caliph Alī
presented his son and then his emancipated slave. According to al-qāḍī
Shuraih, the testimony of a son in favour of his father or of the emancipat-
ed slave was not admissible, before him; hence he ordered Alī to present
another witness. When Caliph Alī was unable to do so, al-qāḍī Shuraih
dismissed his original claim to the armour. Caliph Alī, the caliph of the
time, emerged from the court cheerfully, even though the judgment went
against him. Then, the Jew said: “The Amir al-Muminin (Caliph Alī)
brought me before his qāḍī, and his qāḍī gave a judgement against him. I
witness that this is the truth, and I witness that there is no god but God and
I witness that Muḥammad is the messenger of God, and that the armour is
your armour”. Caliph Alī responded: “I have made it a gift for you”. 148
3.15.1.2. Impartiality
It is admitted nowadays that improper demeanour by members of the judi-
ciary can undermine the judicial process by conveying an impression of
bias or indifference to the litigants or other persons attending the trials. 149
As such, impartiality is essential to the proper discharge of the judicial of-
fice. It applies not only to the decision itself but also to the process by
which the decision is made. 150 Article 2 of the Basic Principles on the In-
dependence of the Judiciary specifies some of the qualities of the judge,
which reflects some elements of judicial integrity, related to the principle of
impartiality. Accordingly, the judiciary shall decide matters before them
impartially, on the basis of facts and in accordance with the law.
Acknowledging that impartiality is the cornerstone of any judicial
system, Lord Denning once said:
Justice is rooted in confidence, and confidence is destroyed
when the right-minded go away thinking that the judge is bi-
ased. The judge shouldn’t be diverted from their duties by any
extraneous influences, nor by any hope of reward, nor by the
fear of penalties, nor by flattering, nor by indignant reproach.
It is the sure knowledge of this that gives the people confi-
dence in judges.
Accordingly, all partisan political activities should cease upon the
holding of the judicial office, as this may undermine the judge’s impartiali-
148
Ibn Abīʾl-Dam, 1984, p. 258, see above note 32.
149
UNODC, p. 112, see above note 2.
150
See Bangalore Principles of Judicial Conduct, Value 2, p. 3, see above note 6.
ty and lead to public confusion about the nature of his relationship with
other authorities. This approach was recognised in Sharí‘ah more than 14
centuries ago. According to Sharí‘ah’s different sources, judges are re-
quired to exercise maximum discretion in the courts’ proceedings, in order
to preserve their image of impartiality. While in judicial office, a judge
should not choose, in public, one side of a debate over another. In addition,
to preserve integrity, a judge must be careful to avoid, as far as possible,
entanglements in controversies that may reasonably be seen as politically
partisan.
In surat Sad, God advises his messenger David to avoid his own
whims when judging between people:
O David, verily we have placed you as a successor on Earth,
so judge between people in truth, and do not follow your de-
sires – for it will mislead you from the path of God. Verily,
those who wander stray from the path of God (shall) have a
severe punishment, because they forgot the day of reckon-
ing. 151
According to these verses, those who are in positions of authority
should judge according to truth and justice impartially, without any distinc-
tion between litigants.
Certain personal qualities like piety, sobriety and propriety are inter-
acting with the professional quality ‘impartiality’ to keep the al-qāḍī unbi-
ased. A judge will have to excuse himself, if he feels that his judgement
might benefit one of his acquaintances, such as a member of his family,
close relatives or friends.
In addition, the al-qāḍī must not favour one party, for example, by
showing any sign or gesture towards any party to a dispute before him,
which might give suspicion that he is in favour of that party. The foregoing
shows that established rules by Sharí‘ah, assert that the al-qāḍī should per-
form his judicial duties without favour, bias or prejudice.
3.15.1.3. Independence
It is understood that judicial independence is not an exclusive privilege ac-
corded to judges in the performance of their duty, but it is also a right en-
joyed by citizens when they seek justice in courts. There is no doubt that
the concept of ‘integrity’ and the principle of ‘independence’ are comple-
151
Qur’án, surat Sad, 38:26.
152
For more details, see Ibn Al-Atheer, Asad al-ghaba fe merefat al-sahaba, Dar ibn Hazm,
2012, no. 2792, p. 630.
153
For more details, see Al-Mawardi, 1989, pp. 89–91, see above note 24.
154
Michel Cabanac, “What Is Emotion?”, in Behavioural Processes, 2002, vol. 60, no. 2, p. 2.
155
See Paul Ekman and Richard Davidson (eds.), The Nature of Emotion: Fundamental Ques-
tions, in Series in affective Science, Oxford University Press, 1994.
156
Terry A. Maroney, “The Emotional Intelligent Judge: A New (and Realistic) Ideal”, in Court
Review: The Journal of the American Judges Association, November 2013, vol. 49, no. 2,
p. 100.
157
See Damian Cox, Marguerite La Caze and Michael P. Levine, Integrity and the Fragile Self,
Routledge, 2018.
which will negatively affect the judicial performance of the al-qāḍī and
compromise his judgements.
As a Western scholar recently observed, like any other persons, judg-
es have emotions, and their emotions may influence the decision-making
process. 158 Therefore, a judge with emotional integrity, has strong core val-
ues, such as serenity and honesty, that subsequently influence his judicial
‘outer’ conduct.
As stated several decades ago by a renowned judicial authority:
Deep below consciousness are other forces, the likes and the
dislikes, the predilections and the prejudices, the complex of
instincts and emotions and habits and convictions, which
make the man, whether he be litigant or judge. 159
While existing codes of judicial conduct, both at the international and
national levels, do not address certain emotional characteristics of judges,
such as hatred, anger, empathy and patience, Sharí‘ah addressed such emo-
tions, in details, in its different sources. Moreover, as we will see below,
when addressing the al-qāḍī’s emotions, Sharí‘ah does not only deal with
his expressions, anger and what he likes, but it does also address his deep
inner state of mind, to guarantee his emotional balance and harmony.
As we have seen before, the Qur’án encourages the believers to do
justice in all circumstances, without regard to their emotional inclinations
for others or vice versa. It is inspiring to see how the Qur’án addressed this
issue 1,400 years ago in surat Al-Ma’idah, in which God commanded the
believers to conquer their emotional inclinations and do justice, even to-
wards their enemies. 160
In his letter to Mālik Al-Ashtar, Caliph Alī Ibn Abī Ṭālib addressed
the al-qāḍī’s emotions and inner-feelings in the context of the judicial pro-
cess. He advised him to select for the position of the al-qāḍī “one who does
not have any tendency to covetousness”. And to guarantee ample emotional
balance and serenity of the al-qāḍī during his work Caliph Alī Ibn Abī
Ṭālib asked Mālik Al-Ashtar to appoint “one who does not vain to flattery
158
Maroney, 2013, p. 100, see above note 156.
159
Benjamin N. Cardozo, The Nature of the Judicial Process, Yale University Press, 1921,
p. 167.
160
See Tafsir Ibn Kathir (interpretation of Noble Qur’án in English), Darussalam, Riyadh, Jan-
uary 2000, vol. 3, p. 122.
and who is not easily tempted”. 161 This shows how Sharí‘ah is not only
concerned with the outer expressions of the judge during adjudication, but
also with his inner emotions. In this context, early Muslim jurists required
the al-qāḍī to have a balanced attitude with peace of mind and serenity. 162
Acknowledging the fact that the al-qāḍī’s emotions could affect his
conduct towards the litigants, and therefore could be very detrimental to
the cause of justice, Sharí‘ah instructs the al-qāḍī to avoid anger, anxiety
and weariness during the performance of his judicial duties. 163 He should
also avoid to be annoyed by litigants. The Prophet Muḥammad ( )ﷺunder-
scored this in one of his famous ḥadíth: “Let al-qāḍī not pass a judgment
when he is angry”. 164 359F
161
Alī Al-Salaby, 2004, p. 369, see above note 27.
162
Ibn Farhoun, 2003, vol. 1, p. 32, see above note 107.
163
Al-Baihaqi, 2011, p. 307, see above note 67.
164
Sunan Abī Dāwūd, the Book of Judgements, vol. 5, no. 3544, p. 582.
165
Al-Shahīd al-Sadr, 1977, vol. 1, p. 340–341, see above note 26.
all internal issues within the judge’s mind-set, which relate to his disposi-
tion and conscience”. 166
However, if such emotions are established, any party to the dispute
can challenge the judge’s eligibility to perform his judicial function, with
respect to the case over which he is presiding, because of a possible lack of
impartiality. In such instance, the judge can recuse himself from the case.
Integrity requirements oblige the judge to disqualify himself in any pro-
ceeding in which his impartiality might reasonably be questioned. However,
in some jurisdictions, unless the legislator has left the matter of determin-
ing the existence of such emotions to the judge’s discretion, to what reas-
sures him and to what rests his sentiment. 167
Interestingly, Sharí‘ah does not limit the conditions that prevent the
al-qāḍī from deciding a case to emotional disturbance or strain only. It goes
further to prevent the al-qāḍī from deciding cases when his physical condi-
tions could affect his well-being, feelings or reactions. In this regard the
Prophet Muḥammad ( )ﷺsaid: “Let the judge not pass a judgment unless he
is comfortable (should not be in state of hunger or thirst)”. 168 36F
166
Appeal No. 25649 before the Egyptian Court of Cassation, Judicial Year 64, Technical Bu-
reau 47, p. 1362.
167
Ibid.
168
Al-Baihaqi, 2011, pp. 306–307, see above note 67.
169
Imam Ibn Al- Kāss, 1989, pp. 157–159, see above note 112.
the emotions they are bound to feel. 170 Of course, this requires skilful emo-
tional management and strong emotional integrity. Apparently, a judge with
emotional integrity is a judge who can control his demeanours.
Evidently, Sharí‘ah is well equipped to tackle judges’ emotions dur-
ing the performance of their duties. Recalling the divine nature of Islam, its
affiliation with inner peace (iṭmīnān), and its call for contentment (riḍā)
and serenity (sakīna), a faithful Muslim judge would rely on his religious
convention and Prophetical teachings to manage his anger, anxiety, weari-
ness and impatience.
We can infer from the foregoing that Sharí‘ah does not only inspire
certain emotions in the al-qāḍī, such as serenity and peace of mind, which
lead to emotional balance and harmony. It also asks the al-qāḍī to detach
himself from any type of personal emotions that may influence his judg-
ment. It even gives regard to the al-qāḍī’s inside inclinations, such as a
tendency towards avariciousness and temptations.
To summarise, according to Sharí‘ah, a ‘good judge’, is one who is
not influenced in his decisions by personal desires, or by fear or hope, one
who has no inclination towards favouritism, but takes a neutral attitude to-
wards all that comes before him, and finally, one who could manage his
anger, anxiety, weariness, and impatience.
3.15.3. A Proposed Definition of Judicial Integrity Derived from
Sharí‘ah Sources
As shown in this chapter, in Sharí‘ah, the basis of judicial integrity, as an
ethical value, is found in the conscientiousness of the person concerned, as
a virtue derived from the religion itself.
The approach of Sharí‘ah towards integrity as a moral value is re-
flected in the approach of the second United Nations Secretary-General
Dag Hammarskjöld’s understanding of integrity, in which he associates it
with purity of intention and equates it with conscience. 171
One important character of judicial integrity as established in this
chapter is that it motivates the person in question to adhere to certain quali-
170
Maroney, 2013, p. 113, see above note 156.
171
See Dag Hammarskjöld, “The International Civil Servant in Law and Fact: Lecture deliv-
ered to Congregation at Oxford University, 30 May 1961”, in Wilder Foote (ed.), The Serv-
ant of Peace: A Selection of the Speeches and Statements of Dag Hammarskjöld, Secretary-
General of the United Nations, 1953-1961, The Bodley Head, 1962, p. 348 (https://www.
legal-tools.org/doc/64bcae/).
ties, mainly uprightness and propriety, thus it distances the person con-
cerned from malice and suspicion.
On the basis of the provisions of Sharí‘ah sources stipulated in this
chapter, judicial integrity can be defined as: a core judicial value, which
reflects a holistic concept incorporating intrinsic core personal virtues that
those who hold a judicial office should possess, such as ‘conscientiousness’,
‘uprightness’, ‘propriety’, ‘dignity’, ‘esteem’, ‘firmness’ and ‘courtesy’,
requiring them to distance themselves from malice and avoid suspicion, by
refraining from any conduct that could cast any doubt on their behaviour,
while fully respecting other professional qualities such as ‘independence’,
‘impartiality’, ‘equality’, and ‘competence and diligence’.
An in-depth comprehension of the concept, from an Arab Sharí‘ah
perspective, reveals that judicial integrity is based on and revolves around
the core value of distancing oneself from malice and avoiding attracting
suspicion, thus freeing oneself from any corrupting influences. A person
who possesses such quality is, ultimately, expected to discharge his judicial
duties according to the highest standards of integrity. Furthermore, adher-
ence to the ‘elements of integrity’ stipulated in this definition, would allow
those who are appointed in any judicial position to preserve their sacred
judicial function.
As we have seen, emotions might have a great impact on the al-
qāḍī’s judicial performance. This raises the question whether there is a re-
quirement of ‘emotional integrity’ for those who occupy judicial positions
whether at the national or international levels.
3.15.4. Some Indications of Judicial Integrity from a Sharí‘ah
Perspective
The existence of a judicial performance-indicator mechanism may be im-
portant to assess judges’ conduct, and ensure the independence, impartiality
and fairness of the judiciary.
From my analysis and interpretation of Sharí‘ah sources specified in
this chapter, I can infer the following indications of the existence of judicial
integrity:
• abide by Islamic judicial traditions and courts’ practice;
• acquaintance with the jurists, as well as with the pious;
• avoid malicious and corrupt behaviour;
172
Court of Cassation, Civil Chamber, Appeal no. 5, Judicial Year 52, Session 18/1/1983, Tech-
nical Bureau Year 34, p. 5.
be on the ‘wholeness’ of the person concerned and on all his past and pre-
sent acts, by examining both his personal and judicial integrity. In the final
analysis, the question that must always be asked is whether in the particular
social context and in the eyes of a reasonable observer, the judge has en-
gaged in an activity that could objectively compromise his or her inde-
pendence or impartiality or that might appear to do so. As stipulated in Ca-
liph Alī Ibn Abī Ṭālib Letter on the Judiciary, Islamic rulers used to period-
ically evaluate the professional performance and behaviour of the judges
they had previously appointed. 173 In case of biased judgements, 174 or estab-
lished corruption or misconduct, the judge could be removed from office.
3.15.5.1. Fisq (Corruption): A Flagrant Threat to Integrity
Corruption of members of the judiciary undermines the rule of law and af-
fects public confidence in the judicial system. 175 Therefore, the United Na-
tions Convention against Corruption, in its Article 11, obliges States Parties,
in accordance with the fundamental principles of their legal systems and
without prejudice to judicial independence, to take measures to strengthen
integrity and to prevent opportunities for corruption among members of the
judiciary, including rules with respect to the conduct of members of the
judiciary. 176 Since the mid-1990s, the interplay between corruption, good
governance, and integrity has become a crucial issue in the global setting.
Situations and abuses can challenge one’s personal integrity and create a
conflict between the person and the judicial institution. Therefore, a judge
acting in a way that is corrupt (for example, through accepting bribes or
other favours to make favourable judicial decisions), acts without integri-
ty. 177
Sharí‘ah despises corruption and the corrupted, and has attributed
prodigious emphasis on issues related to the incorruptibility of the al-qāḍī.
To ensure that a judge’s behaviour and conduct is acceptable to the public,
and does not provide an opportunity for people to doubt his integrity or im-
173
Alī Al-Salaby, 2004, p. 369, see above note 27.
174
Ibn Farhoun, 2003, vol. 1, p. 15, see above note 107.
175
See the Economic and Social Council, Strengthening basic principles of judicial conduct, 27
July 2006, ECOSOC 2006/23 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/yiyqyy/).
176
UN General Assembly, United Nations Convention against Corruption, 21 November 2003,
A/RES/58/4 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/hwuihi/).
177
Agata Gurzawska, Institutional Integrity, SATORI, European Commission’s Seventh Frame-
work Programme, June 2015, p. 5.
partiality, Muslim jurists require that a judge should refrain from any con-
duct that could cast doubt in his behaviour. Therefore, a judge should avoid
any activities that may attract criticism or rebuttal from the public.
In his famous letter to Mālik Al-Ashtar on the Judiciary, Caliph Alī
Ibn Abī Ṭālib had eloquently used a short paragraph reflecting a specific
character that should not exist in al-qāḍī that might lead him to corruption.
As mentioned before, he advised Mālik Al-Ashtar to select: “One who does
not have any tendency to covetousness”. 178 Moreover, he advised him to:
“pay him handsomely enough, that removes his necessity and there remain
no occasion for him to go to others for his need”, a theme touched on
above. The aforementioned approach of Caliph Alī Ibn Abī Ṭālib could be
considered as a preventive measure of graft and corruption of judges.
3.15.5.2. Disciplinary Measures in Sharí‘ah
Sharí‘ah has recognized forms of disciplinary measures for judges, such as
disqualification and removal from office, in case they lose their judicial
integrity.
3.15.5.2.1. Disqualification
The meaning of the term ‘disqualification’ might vary in the Arab and Is-
lamic States and differ from the meaning prevalent in Western States. The
term ‘disqualification’ in the Arabic language is not only restricted to los-
ing impartiality, competency of other professional qualifications, as it ex-
tends to cover some personal qualities. In general, a judge could be dis-
qualified only for any conduct that could undermine the judiciary or the
judicial institution.
In a book titled ‘Fair Trial, and Values and Traditions of the Judici-
ary’, a renowned Egyptian judicial authority stated:
The value of the eligibility/qualification, in the judicial do-
main, means that the judge or the prosecutor possesses good
manners and reputation, absolute objectivity, in his judicial
convection and the application of the law, impartiality mani-
fested in avoiding inclination towards personal desires and
178
Alī Al-Salaby, 2004, p. 369, see above note 27.
179
Serry Siam, Al-muhakamah al-monsifa wa keiam wa takaleed al-qadaa, Dar al-Shorouk,
first edition, 2017, p. 67.
180
Ibn Farhoun, 2003, vol. 1, p. 15, see above note 107.
181
See Özpınar v. Turkey, no. 20999/04, 19 October 2010.
182
Muhammad Taher, al-garh we al-taedeel bayen al-mutashadedin we al-mutasahlin, Al-Dar
Al-Arabia Llketab, Tunis, 1997, p. 366.
183
Imam Al-Shawkani, Fath Al-Qadir Al-Jame, Youssef Al-Ghoush (ed.), Dar Al-Marefah,
Beirut, vol. 1, pp. 40–41.
184
Al-Shaid al-Sadr, 1977, p. 129, see above note 85.
185
Ibn Farhoun, 2003, p. 15, see above note 107.
In-depth research in Sharí‘ah sources has revealed that the term ‘in-
tegrity’ refers to a combination of values intrinsic in a person’s character
and is an established norm in Sharí‘ah. In the context of the judicial func-
tion, it refers to certain qualities manifested in the al-qāḍī’s personal and
professional characteristics during the performance of his judicial duties.
One important core value that reflects the concept of judicial integrity in
Sharí‘ah is to distance oneself from malice and avoid attracting suspicion,
thus freeing oneself from any corrupting influences.
This chapter has also affirmed that integrity is essential to the proper
administration of justice, and that Sharí‘ah provisions adopt a high stand-
ard approach to judicial integrity and considers it as a moral value and a
legal requirement for the discharge of the judicial function. Further, it has
asserted that integrity is a condition of general ethical conduct and virtue
both before and after appointment, in Sharí‘ah, which is honoured in na-
tional legal systems of Islamic countries.
Interestingly, the research in this chapter has revealed that the rules
of Sharí‘ah on integrity converge with the ancient Roman/Greek ‘virtue
ethical theory’. Further research may show the interactions between these
traditions. Apparently, the meaning of judicial integrity does not differ sig-
nificantly between various traditions, and should be recognised as a com-
mon, universal legal quality-requirement to hold judicial office.
However, notwithstanding this, Sharí‘ah would seem to be more en-
compassing than contemporary approaches to judicial integrity, stipulated
in modern international documents, and granted special attention to the
management of judges’ emotions during the performance of their judicial
function, acknowledging that inadequate emotional integrity may undesira-
bly influence the judicial decision-making process.
In my view, the qualities of judges required in the Messages on the
Judiciary of the two guided Caliphs Umar Ibn Al-Khaṭṭáb and Alī Ibn Abī
Ṭāleb, exceed those that exist in contemporary international documents. As
stipulated in those messages, we should ask ourselves whether we nowa-
days find judges whose fairness is manifested in their face? One who is
cautious of anger, anxiety, weariness, and impatience when adjudicating
people’s disputes? One who does not have any tendency to covetousness?
One who is immune to flattery and elation? I think there are very few who
have such characteristics and are thus qualified for the appointment to such
a sacred position as judge.
The Message of Caliph Umar Ibn Al-Khaṭṭáb on the Judiciary (may God be
pleased with him) to Abú Moussa Al-Ash'ari upon entrusting him with the
mandate of adjudicating on people’s disputes; which should be considered
a judge’s charter.
In the Name of God the Merciful and the Gracious
• Adjudication in (Islam) is based on a precise obligation (Qur’án) and a
followed Prophetic Tradition (sayings and practices of Prophet Mu-
hammad, peace be upon him);
• Comprehend any dispute brought before you, and note that it is futile
to reach a right judgement without executing it;
• Be equal to the parties appearing before you, and let your fairness be
manifested in the way they seat in your divan (courtroom), in your
face (facial expressions) and in your judgement, so that no noble per-
son can ever hope that you will favour him/her unfairly, nor can a
layman ever doubt your fairness;
• The burden of proof is on the plaintiff, and if the defendant denies,
he/she must take the oath;
• He who claims an infringed entitlement or missing evidence should be
allowed to provide the evidence within a deadline. If he/she supplies
the evidence, grant him/her the right he/she claims, otherwise rule
against him/her. In that way, you give the plaintiff a fair chance to
prove his/her right/entitlement and place the case under proper scruti-
ny;
• If you render a judgment and then later find out, after re-visiting it,
that you were not right, do not hesitate to renounce that judgment in
order to establish justice, as justice is primordial and should not be de-
viated from. A revision of unfair judgement is better than establishing
injustice;
• Muslims are credible witnesses whose testimony should be admitted,
except those proven to have committed punishable sins, those known
to have given false testimony, or those suspected of bias due to loyalty
or kinship. Only God Almighty knows what is in the minds of people.
Appendix II: The Message of Alī Ibn Abī Ṭālib to Mālik Al-Ashtar on
the Judiciary
The Message of Alī Ibn Abī Ṭālib to his commissioner in Egypt, Mālik Al-
Ashtar on the Judiciary is to be considered as one of the most comprehen-
sive Sharí‘ah instruments on the concept of judicial integrity:
For adjudicating on people’s disputes, select one whom you
trust, is by far the best among your subjects in your view; one
who is patient and imperturbable; one who is not influenced
by the importunity of the litigants; one who does not persist if
he commits an error, and hold back the truth once he knew it;
one who does not have any tendency to covetousness, nor is
satisfied with cursory understanding (of a matter brought be-
fore him) without going thoroughly into it (scrupulously goes
beyond that to contemplate the case before him to the maxi-
mum extent); one who stops whenever he is faced with doubts
and only approves reliable evidence; one who is least repined
at the quarrel of litigants; one who is most patient at probing
into matters, and is most decisive once the truth is revealed
and the verdict becomes clear in his mind; and one who does
not vain to flattery and is not easily tempted. Few are those
who meet all of these criteria. Thereafter, check regularly his
judgements, and pay him handsomely enough, that removes
his necessity and there remain no occasion for him to go to
others for his need. Confer on him such a high stature so that
persons who are most close to you could not covet. Conse-
quently, he would be protected from their malign and back-
biting.
This letter is to be considered as a model of the qualities that a per-
son should have to be selected as al-qāḍī – all components of ‘integrity’.
While it speaks of both personal and professional judicial qualities, it plac-
es more emphasis on the intrinsic values of the person in question. Accord-
ing to Caliph Ali’s letter, the al-qāḍī should be the most qualified, yet vir-
tuous, patient, honest, truthful and pious person in order to be selected for
this position. Indeed, the al-qāḍī’s criteria enumerated in Alī Ibn Abī
Ṭālib’s Letter to Mālik Al-Ashtar fulfil the judicial integrity requirements.
The Letter covers certain safeguards that protect the al-qāḍī from
malice, corruption and temptations. Specifically, it requires the governor to
observe certain virtues for judicial office, including pure intention, having
an upright character, and immunity from greed.
*
Gunnar M. Ekeløve-Slydal is Acting Secretary General, Norwegian Helsinki Committee,
and Adjunct Lecturer at the University of South East Norway. He studied philosophy at the
University of Oslo and worked for many years for the Norwegian Centre for Human Rights
at the University of Oslo and as Editor of the Nordic Journal on Human Rights. He has writ-
ten extensively on human rights, international institutions, and philosophical themes, includ-
ing textbooks, reports, and articles. The author wants to extend his gratitude to Berit Linde-
man for input to Section 4.1.1. on election observation and Section 4.1.2. on corruption in
the Parliamentary Assembly of the Council of Europe.
1
“Blessed are the undefiled in the way, who walk in the law of the Lord.” Book of Psalms
119:1, King James Version. An alternative translation from the New International Version
reads as follows: “Blessed are those whose ways are blameless, who walk according to the
law of the Lord”.
2
For a short account of the issues, see Pierre Hassan, “Scandals rocks international criminal
court”, Justiceinfo, 8 October 2017 (available on its web site). For the broader issues, see
Morten Bergsmo, Wolfgang Kaleck, Sam Muller and William H. Wiley, “A Prosecutor Falls,
Time for the Court to Rise”, FICHL Policy Brief Series No. 86 (2017), Torkel Opsahl Aca-
demic EPublisher, Brussels, 2017 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/41b41a/). At the heart of
many of the issues related to the ICC Office of the Prosecutor may be Mr. Moreno-
Ocampo’s unwillingness to follow-up on the ground-breaking work of the ICC preparatory
team, see Morten Bergsmo, Klaus Rackwitz and SONG Tianying (eds.), Historical Origins
ty’, being well aware of the concept’s both classical and biblical roots. 6 For
him, integrity signifies consistency in thought, word and action, based on
conscience and comprehensive understanding. It is the fruit of a successful
struggle to be just one person, rather than to be several. It is “what makes a
person a unity rather than a duplicity. Integrity makes a particular life re-
semble a good poem rather than a dubious collection of fragments, with
doubtful authorship”. 7
This chapter deals with the arguments and stance of Thomas More,
situating them in a context of modern integrity. The first section deals with
integrity issues recently faced by international organizations, such as biased
election observation, lack of quality control and transparent procedures in
both the Council of Europe and the International Criminal Police Organiza-
tion (‘INTERPOL’), acquittals in the international tribunals, as well as mis-
conduct by members of the ICC Office of the Prosecutor (Section 4.1.). To
ground the discussion of More’s relevancy for current integrity discussions,
I provide a typography of these problems, focusing on individual versus
institutional integrity, politicization or instrumentalization of institutions,
and the specificities of professional integrity (Section 4.2.). These chal-
lenges to integrity form the basis upon which we turn to More for guidance,
which is the subject of the following sections. The chapter progresses with
a discussion on More’s thoughts on tyranny and how to confront it (Section
4.3), before turning to More as a statesman and his views on heresy (Sec-
tion 4.4.). Finally, the chapter turns briefly to More’s conflict with Henry
VIII (Section 4.5.), before concluding with More’s lessons as well as re-
turning to the topic of integrity in justice (Sections 4.6. and 4.7.).
4.1. Integrity Failures in International Political Institutions
My organization, the Norwegian Helsinki Committee, has a history of ad-
dressing integrity issues publicly, rather than only raising them discretely
behind the scenes. Maybe it is part of a wider Nordic tradition that to
demonstrate your support for an institution, you do not shy away from pub-
licly criticizing it and appeal for effective measures to address failings.
6
“Conscience and Integrity”, in Gerard B. Wegemer and Stephen W. Smith (eds.), A Thomas
More Sourcebook, Catholic University of America Press, Washington, DC, 2004, pp. 212–
214.
7
Stephen W. Smith, “Thomas More: Patron Saint of Leading Citizens”, in Travis Curtright
(ed.), Thomas More: Why Patron of Statesmen? Lexington books, New York, 2015, p. 145.
8
Budapest Summit Declaration, Towards a genuine partnership in a new era, 21 December
2004, paragraph 3.
9
Conference on the Security and Co-operation in Europe, Document of the Copenhagen
Meeting of the Conference on the Human Dimension of the CSCE, 29 June 1990, para. 6
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/f85146).
10
ODIHR, Election Observation Handbook, sixth edition, OSCE/ODIHR, Warsaw, 2010. An
extensive library of election related guidelines and tools are available at the OSCE web page.
11
For a compelling account of the main methods used to ‘control’ democracy, see Andrew
Wilson, Virtual Politics: Faking democracy in the Post-Soviet World, Yale University Press,
2005. He argues that the post-Bolshevik culture of ‘political technology’ is the main obstacle
to better governance in the region. There is no real popular participation in public affairs,
and no systematic modernization of the political economy.
12
This term may be inspired by the concept of ‘guided democracy’, coined by the American
journalist Walter Lippmann in his influential book Public Opinion from 1922. In such a sys-
tem, a formal democratic government function as a de facto autocracy. For an early criticism
of Putin’s managed democracy, see Masha Lipman and Michael McFaul, “Managed democ-
racy in Russia”, in Harvard International Journal of Press/Politics, 2001, vol. 6, no. 3,
pp. 116–127.
13
Prime Minister Orbán proclaimed Hungary as an illiberal democratic State in a speech at the
Tusványos Summer University and Student Camp on 26 July 2014. “Proclamation of the Il-
liberal Hungarian State”, The Orange Files, 1 August 2014 (available on its web site).
14
Freedom House has since 1995 run a project called “Nations in transit”, which according to
a certain methodology survey democratic reforms in 29 former communist countries. The
report covering developments in 2018 registered the most score declines in the project’s 23-
year history: 19 of the 29 countries had declines in their overall Democracy Scores. For the
second year in a row, there were more Consolidated Authoritarian Regimes than Consolidat-
ed Democracies (Freedom House, “Nations in Transit 2018” (available on Freedom House’s
web site)).
15
Council of Europe, Report of the Independent Investigation Body of the allegations of cor-
ruption within the Parliamentary Assembly, 15 April 2018 (available on the Parliamentary
Assembly’s web site). For extensive coverage of the so-called ‘caviar diplomacy’ in PACE,
see European Stability Initiative thematic web site on corruption problems in the PACE.
16
Members of the coalition include Helsinki Citizens’ Assembly Vanadzor, Election Monitor-
ing and Democracy Studies Centre (EMDS), Belarusian Helsinki Committee, International
Society for Fair Elections and Democracy, European Exchange, International Elections
Study Centre, Promo-LEX Association, The Norwegian Helsinki Committee, Stefan Batory
23
Ibid.
24
For a short description of the problems, see Organized Crime and Corruption Reporting
Project (‘OCCRP’), “Council of Europe Expels 13 in Azerbaijan Bribe Case”, 3 July 2018
(available on OCCRP’s web site).
28
European Stability Initiative (‘ESI’), “Human Rights with Teeth (I) – Battle of Europe”, ESI
Newsletter, 2018, no. 9, p. 2.
29
Ibid.
30
Amy Mackinnon, “The Scourge of the Red Notice: How some countries go after dissidents
and debtors”, Foreign Affairs, 3 December 2018 (available on its web site). See also, David
Satter, “Russia’s abuse of Interpol”, Russia Studies Centre Policy Paper No. 6 (2015), The
Henry Jackson Society, July 2015. The figures were taken from Interpol’s web site.
31
Constitution of the International Criminal Police Organization-INTERPOL, 1956 (2017),
Article 1 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/07a066).
32
Ibid., Article 3
33
Fair Trials International, Strengthening respect for human rights: Strengthening Interpol,
2013 (available on Fair Trials’ web site). The report documented abuse in specific cases and
recommended measures to detect and prevent such abuse. It also referred to resolutions and
statements by international organizations since 2010 about the need to strengthen control
mechanisms within the organization.
34
Fair Trials, “How to end the abuse of INTERPOL: insights from America and Europe”, 18
December 2018 (available on Fair Trials’ web site). On measures to strengthening safe-
guards against abuse, see INTERPOL: “New measures approved to strengthen INTERPOL
information sharing system”, 9 November 2016 (available on its web site).
35
Fair Trials, “How to end the abuse of INTERPOL: insights from America and Europe”, see
above note 34.
36
PACE, Abusive use of the INTERPOL system: the need for more stringent legal safeguards,
Doc. 14277, 29 March 2017. It should be noted that even if PACE has had serious integrity
issues of its own to deal with, it often played strong and beneficial external roles in promot-
ing and securing adherence to human rights, democracy, and integrity norms.
37
Commission of Security and Co-operation in Europe, “Helsinki Commission leaders intro-
duce translational repression accountability and prevention (TRAP) act”, 12 September
2019 (available on its web site). Recognizing the extent of the problem, the leaders of the
US Helsinki Commission on 12 September 2019 introduced the Transnational Repression
Accountability and Prevention (TRAP) Act in the House of Representatives. The Act de-
clares that it is the policy of the United States to pursue specific reforms within INTERPOL
and use its diplomatic clout internationally to protect the rights of victims and denounce
abusers. The bill requires the Departments of Justice, Homeland Security, and State, in con-
sultation with other relevant agencies, to provide Congress with an assessment of autocratic
abuse of INTERPOL, what the United States is doing to counteract it, and how to adapt
United States policy to this evolving autocratic practice. The State Department would also
be required to publicly report on the abuse of INTERPOL in its annual Country Reports on
Human Rights to create a transparent, public record of these violations of the rule of law.
POL alerts. The result is often that their freedom of movement becomes
severely restricted. 38
In an exposé of recent international integrity failures, acquittals in
2012–2013 by the Appeals Chamber of the International Criminal Tribunal
for the former Yugoslavia (‘ICTY’), and media revelations about a deep
split among its judges should also be mentioned. The acquitted included
high-ranking Croat and Serb officials, such as Ante Gotovina, Mladen
Markač, Momčilo Perišić, Jovica Stanišić and Franko Simatović, and gen-
erated concerns about the quality of the legacy of the ICTY. Much of the
criticism focused on the role of the then ICTY President Theodor Meron,
thus challenging his impartiality and alleging that he sought to unduly in-
fluence other Tribunal judges. According to diplomatic cables released by
WikiLeaks, he was close to the US government, being characterized by US
diplomatic personnel as a pre-eminent supporter of specific government
interests. The criticism extended to the International Criminal Tribunal for
Rwanda (‘ICTR’) which shared its Appeals Chamber with the ICTY. 39 The
acquittals did not come as a result of new evidence, but rather as a conse-
quence of changes in judicial interpretation at a late stage in the life of the
ICTY affecting the ability of the Tribunal to hold leaders accountable.
Combined with revelations of an apparent power struggle between the then
American Tribunal President and the Danish judge Frederik Harhoff, lead-
ing to the exclusion of the latter, this not only revealed serious disunity
among the judges, but at the time reduced trust in the Tribunal in ways that
disoriented victims, their families, and the wider struggle against impunity.
According to Judge Harhoff, his main concern was undue influence by “the
38
A telling example is former hedge fund investor in Russia, William Browder, who since
2009 has led an international human rights campaign, ‘Justice for Sergei Magnitsky’. He has
been placed on Interpol’s red alert list seven times by Russia, which wants him extradited
for alleged tax evasion. See Reuters, “Russia asks Interpol to arrest Kremlin critic Bill
Browder: letter”, 9 April 2018 (available on Reuters’ web site). For Browder’s best-selling
auto-biographical book see William Browder, Red Notice: How I became Putin’s No. 1 En-
emy, Transworld Publishers Ltd., London, 2015.
39
Gunnar M. Ekeløve-Slydal, “ICTY Shifts Have Made Its Credibility Quake”, FICHL Policy
Brief Series 49 (2016), Torkel Opsahl Academic EPublisher, Brussels, 2016 (http://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/18ba48/) See also Julija Bogoeva, “International Judges and Gov-
ernment Interests: The Case of President Meron”, FICHL Policy Brief Series 48 (2016),
Torkel Opsahl Academic EPublisher, Brussels, 2016 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/
56a576/); and Frederik Harhoff, “Mystery Lane: A Note on Independence and Impartiality in
International Criminal Trials”, FICHL Policy Brief Series 47 (2016), Torkel Opsahl Aca-
demic EPublisher, Brussels, 2016 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/c2e5ad/).
40
Harhoff, 2016, p. 2, see above note 39.
41
Ekeløve-Slydal, “ICTY Shifts Have Made Its Credibility Quake”, p. 4, see above note 39.
42
Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court, 17 July 1997, Article 42(3) (‘ICC statute’]
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/7b9af9/).
and “intimidation” among staff members. 43 Within a few years, 22 top staff
members had left his office. These internal problems were known by sever-
al government officials and leaders of non-governmental organizations
since late 2003. 44
A further aggravating fact was that the ICC’s achievements in terms
of convictions of major war criminals have been very disappointing. There
have been only three convictions so far. Cases against 12 persons have col-
lapsed. 45
Two other factors were also at play. When created, the ICC received
widespread support from large parts of the international community, even
though some influential States showed reservation and sometimes acted in
a hostile manner to the institution. 46 For the human rights community, the
adoption of the Rome Statute and its rapid ratification by the required
number of States created widespread optimism that the ICC would help
create an effective system to fight impunity for core international crimes. In
general, institutions do create expectations and provide implicit promises.
The establishment of the ICC had created high expectations, some of them
perhaps unrealistic.
The second factor is linked to the concept of ‘professional integrity’.
As a physician is not evaluated only based on his or her personal integrity –
being a morally solid and consistent person – but as a person who honours
profession-specific requirements, the same goes for prosecutors in interna-
tional justice. During his time as ICC Prosecutor, Moreno-Ocampo was
often hailed in popular culture as a hero in the fight against unspeakable
crimes and criminal leaders. His fall due to his failure to uphold profes-
43
Morten Bergsmo, “Institutional History, Behaviour and Development”, in Bergsmo, Rack-
witz and SONG (eds.), 2017, p. 24, see above note 2.
44
Morten Bergsmo, Wolfgang Kaleck, Sam Muller and William H. Wiley, “A Prosecutor Falls,
Time for the Court to Rise”, FICHL Policy Brief Series No. 86 (2017), Torkel Opsahl Aca-
demic EPublisher, Brussels, 2017, page 2 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/41b41a/)
45
Morten Bergsmo, «La CPI, l’affaire Gbagbo et le rôle de la France», Le Monde, 18 January
2019 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/d499f6 and https://www.legal-tools.org/en/doc/693bee
(English version)).
46
For an overview and evaluation of US relations with the ICC since 2002, see William Pace:
“The Hague Invasion Act remains dangerous”, Diplomat Magazine, February 9, 2019
(available on Diplomat Magazine’s web site).
47
For portraits of Mr. Ocampo that build the hero-narrative, see for instance the films: Edet
Belzberg, Kerry Propper, Amelia Green-Dove and Taylor Krauss (Producers) and Edet
Belzberg (Director), “Watchers of the sky”, motion picture, 2014, United States, Propeller
Films; and Paco de Onis (Producer) and Pamela Yates (Director), “The reckoning: the battle
for the International Criminal Court”, motion picture, 2009, United States, Skylight Pictures.
48
Norwegian Helsinki Committee, “Letter to Mrs. Fatou Bensouda, Prosecutor of the ICC”, 12
March 2018 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/b745e4/).
49
Fatou Bensouda, “Letter to Messr Engesland and Ekelove-Slydal”, 22 May 2018 (available
on the Norwegian Helsinki Committee’s web site).
50
Norwegian Helsinki Committee, “Letter to Mrs. Fatou Bensouda, Prosecutor of the ICC”, 8
June 2018 (available on the Norwegian Helsinki Committee’s web site). Also Women’s Ini-
tiatives for Gender Justice argued for “external review of the practices relevant to the allega-
tions”, see Women’s Initiatives for Gender Justice, “A critical time for the ICC’s credibility”,
18 November 2017 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/e2fbc7). The ICC Bar Association (‘IC-
CBA’), urged in a statement, “States Parties and the ASP to initiate a thorough, effective and
independent investigation into the serious allegations raised in these recent public reports”,
see ICCBA, “ICCBA Statement on Allegations Against Former ICC Prosecutor”, 29 No-
vember 2017 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/a8cdcb).
improve and thereby strengthen the legitimacy of his rule. Overall, it seems
that his main goal was to promote peace and improve the lot of ordinary
people.
One of his best-known books, The History of King Richard the Third,
is a sharply formulated Christian humanist attack on tyrannical rule and a
King that personalized excesses connected with ruthless power-struggle
and disregard for the well-being of his people. 51
More’s world-famous Utopia (1516) criticizes the state of European
politics and exemplifies how politics governed by reason may function by
way of describing the state of affairs at a fictive island State. 52 Interestingly,
it also includes discussions on whether a wise person should separate him-
self from politics, or rather serve leaders who are less than ideal and at least
contribute to moderating their evils and mistakes.
According to More, a good leader has a duty to “take more care of
his people’s welfare than of his own, just as it is the duty of a shepherd who
cares about his job to feed the sheep rather than himself”. 53 If a King de-
parts from his duty, his servant should do what he or she could to minimize
the negative consequences of such departure.
More presented strong arguments against the execution of or other
harsh penalties imposed on thieves. He was behind legal reforms that
would ease access of the poor to justice. Stealing was the only way of sur-
viving for many poor people. Executing them would not contribute to solv-
ing any problems, More argued. Part of his progressive agenda was also
arguments that leaders should accept free speech, and that Parliament
should have a decisive say on legislation.
Even if realities were far from these ideals, More decided eventually
to serve for many years under one of the Kings he had both hailed and crit-
icized, Henry VIII. First serving in high legal positions in the city of Lon-
51
More probably started to write the book in 1513 and did never finish it. He wrote two ver-
sions simultaneously, one in English and one in Latin for a wider European audience. It was
published only after More’s death, in 1557. A modernised and easy to read version of the
book has been made available online by The Centre for Thomas More studies: Thomas More,
The History of King Richard the Third, Mary Gottschalk (ed.), 2012 [c. 1513]. This version
is based on the 1557-edition that inspired William Shakespeare (1564-1616) to write his
play ‘Richard III’. Whether More’s negative account of King Richard was wholly justified,
is another question, which I do not intend to discuss here.
52
More, Utopia, see above note 3
53
Ibid., p. 33
don, he had accepted prominent positions offered by the King from 1518.
He was Chancellor of England from 1529 to 1532.
When entering the King’s Council in 1518, More was well aware of
the conflicting demands such service would entail. What he did not know,
of course, was that Henry VIII would develop into a tyrant, killing wives,
high officials that had served him, among many others. He could not fore-
see that he himself would eventually be killed by the King because of a
conflict about fundamental principles concerning the relationship between
State and church. In 1535, More was beheaded after a show trial, on the
order of the King, for refusing to accept Henry VIII as head of the Church
of England. His vision was an internationally unified and independent
church.
More has been recognized as a saint by the Roman Catholic Church
(1935). Even more important in the context of integrity discussions, he has
been proclaimed as a Patron Saint of Statesmen (2000). 54 His example of
integrity is not only recognized by the Catholic Church, but by people be-
longing to different religions and beliefs.
His example remains to a certain degree controversial. The critics
claim that he was a fanatic responsible for the execution of heretics during
his tenure. It is undisputed that he was responsible for such executions, and
it is therefore mandatory in discussions about his enduring legacy to identi-
fy exactly what to keep and what to disregard from his thought and practice.
Before discussing further More’s relevancy for current integrity discussions,
though, I will return to the above examples of such issues within interna-
tional institutions, providing a categorization of the problems.
4.2.1. Politicization or Instrumentalization of Institutions
The examples include issues related to integrity both on institutional as
well as individual levels. There were issues related to both current and
former officials within the institutions, which enjoyed certain ‘privileges’
which they reportedly abused (that is, former members of PACE lobbying
for Azerbaijan and the first Prosecutor of the ICC).
By institutional integrity, I mean upholding institutional activities
and views in line with reasonable interpretations of the institution’s man-
54
Pope John Paul II, Apostolic Letter Issued Moto Proprio, Proclaiming Saint Thomas More
Patron of Statesmen and Politicians, 31 October 2000 (available on The Holy See’s web
site).
date. The mandate of the Council of Europe, for instance, is to promote and
protect human rights, democracy and the rule of law in its Member
States. 55 Mandates of institutions of international justice are typically to
“exercise […] jurisdiction over persons for the most serious crimes of in-
ternational concern”. 56 The institutions may have different rules concerning
that jurisdiction, but the core purpose remains the same: to hold persons (at
high places) accountable for international crimes they conducted, were re-
sponsible for, or failed to prevent.
If institutions fail to fulfil their mandates in specific cases or situa-
tions because of corruption, giving in to political pressure, or neglect, these
may amount to instances of institutional integrity failures. In international
justice institutions, the ICTY’s 2012–2013 acquittals may be a case at hand.
The point here is that failures to uphold integrity at a personal level may
translate into institutional failure.
Justice institutions are particularly vulnerable to such failure, since
the number of people taking binding decisions is limited. The example of
PACE’s failure to adopt a resolution on political prisoners in Azerbaijan
mentioned above indicate that also in bodies where decision-making in-
cludes hundreds of persons (PACE has 324 members), this risk is still pre-
sent.
4.2.1.1. Establishing Fake Institutions
As we have seen, one way of undermining genuine international institu-
tions is to establish alternative institutions with a similar mandate, but
which applies the mandate in a politicized or biased way.
The purpose may be to undermine the views of genuine institutions
in front of the international community or at domestic levels. By presenting
alternative views as if they were based on systematic and methodologically
sound research, the institutions serve to disorient public opinion and un-
dermine trust in genuine institutions.
The primary example given above was biased election observation.
There might, however, also be discussions about whether specific justice
institutions should be placed in this category. It is hardly controversial to
place highly politicized courts and prosecutorial services in authoritarian
55
Statute of the Council of Europe, 5 May 1949. For an updated presentation of the organiza-
tion’s aim and prioritized areas of activity, see the Council of Europe’s official web site.
56
ICC Statute, Article 1, see above note 42.
57
See among others, Maria Popova, Politicized Justice in Emerging Democracies: A Study of
Courts in Russia and Ukraine, Cambridge University Press, 2012. In particular, chapter 6
gives an instructive overview of how the integrity of the courts are jeopardized by so-called
informal practices of influence, such as ‘ex parte communication’ between judges and liti-
gants and ‘telephone justice’ between politicians (or other important players) and judges.
58
For examples of how high-profile defendants have challenged the legitimacy of the interna-
tional(ized) courts they were brought for, see Michael A. Newton, “The Iraqi High Criminal
Court: controversy and contributions”, in International Review of the Red Cross, 2006, vol.
88, no. 862, p. 405.
59
For a description and discussion of the problem of double standards in international justice,
see Wolfgang Kaleck, Double Standards: International Criminal Law and the West, Torkel
Opsahl Academic EPublisher, Brussels, 2015.
60
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, “Integrity”, 9 April 2001 (available on its web site).
61
Ibid.
62
Ibid.
63
Ibid.
In the case of More, it is clear that he thought the judges in the trial
against him to be both morally and legally wrong in convicting him to
death for treason. He had remained silent about his views, and the law pro-
tected silence in a case like his. At the same time, he did not denounce his
judges, some of whom were his long-term friends. One way of interpreting
this seemingly paradoxical situation might be to conclude that as he
thought the judges to be wrong, he still respected their right to be wrong in
the way they were. He knew, and the judges knew, that to oppose the will
of the King equalled endangering your life. 64
More fought for the unity and integrity of the Catholic Church.
While England’s bishops (except Bishop John Fisher (1469–1535)), uni-
versities and other institutions had given in to the demands of the King to
be the head of the Church of England, he would not. He fought for some-
thing he believed in very deeply. To give in would be to betray his own
convictions, but also to fail in upholding the integrity of a unified church
and the future of Christendom.
He fought both to uphold his own integrity and the integrity of an in-
stitution he deemed to be of unique importance to upholding the material
and spiritual existence of human beings. Dividing the church and placing it
under the leadership of Kings would weaken it, lead to violent conflict, and
eventually undermining the standing of the Christian States, which at his
time was under considerable pressure from the Ottoman Empire as well as
from internal conflicts in the Christian world. 65
The examples presented above primarily illustrated weakening of the
integrity of genuine institutions. While INTERPOL’s problem was the lack
of sufficient institutional safeguards to detect and prevent politicized alerts
from its Member States, the other examples showed how institutional in-
tegrity was undermined by individual actors within the institutions or by
external actors with a privileged access to the institutions. The methods
were among others bribing, exertion of pressure, and abuse of personal
relationships.
64
See Gerard B. Wegemer, “The Trial of Thomas More: July 1, 1535”, in Portrait of Courage,
Scepter, Cleveland, 1995, pp. 210–217.
65
For a vivid description of the challenging times of More for Britain and, in particular, for
Europe, see Robert Tombs, The English and Their History, Penguin Books, London, 2015,
pp. 157–160.
66
For a powerful account of the important role of leaders adhering to democratic norms and
functioning as gatekeepers to uphold democratic rule, see Steven Levitsky and Daniel
Ziblatt, How Democracies Die, Broadway Books, New York, 2018. While their analysis
mainly deals with the question of how to uphold democratic political institutions, their in-
sistence on the important role of leaders or gatekeepers is also highly relevant for discus-
sions on how to uphold and strengthen integrity of justice institutions.
67
Andreas Eriksen, “What is Professional Integrity?”, in Nordic Journal of Applied Ethics,
2015, vol. 9, no. 2, pp. 3–17.
68
Ibid., p. 10. Eriksen uses Ronald Dworkin’s figure of a “chain novelist” to illustrate this
interpretive view of professional integrity. The task of judges is like the task of authors en-
gaged in a “chain novel”. This novel is written one chapter at a time. Each finished chapter
is passed along to a new author, who writes the next one. The task of each author is to make
this the best novel it can be. According to Dworkin, the good judge views earlier decisions
“as part of a long story he must interpret and then continue, according to his own judgment
of how to make the developing story as good as it can be”.
69
Rikard Jozwiak, “PACE President Stripped of Powers After Meeting Syria’s Assad”, on
Radio Free Europe, 28 April 2017 (available on Radio Free Europe’s web site). A Motion
for dismissal was tabled by Ingjerd Schou, a Norwegian member of the PACE, on 30 June
2017, see PACE, Dismissal of Mr Pedro Agramunt, President of the Parliamentary Assem-
bly, Doc. 4383, 30 June 2017. The Motion reads: “We, the undersigned, consider that the
President of the Parliamentary Assembly no longer enjoys the confidence of the Assembly,
on the grounds that his behaviour seriously harms the reputation of the Parliamentary As-
sembly and tarnishes its image”. Agramunt, however, resigned on 6 October 2017 before the
Motion was scheduled to be decided on, see PACE, “Pedro Agramunt resigns as PACE Pres-
ident”, 6 October 2017 (available on PACE’s web site).
70
As an indicator of possible lack of integrity in national jurisdictions, I take low scores on
civil and criminal justice in the World Justice Project Rule of Law Index (available on the
World Justice Project’s web site). A further indication of issues of integrity being widespread
at the national level, is the renewed focus by the United Nations Office on Drugs and Crime
(UNODC) on integrity issues in the Criminal Justice System. See also above note 57.
71
The literature on Thomas More’s life and thinking is vast. For general introductions, I con-
sulted John Guy, Thomas More: A Very Brief History, Society for Promotion of Christian
Knowledge, London, 2017; Richard Marius, Thomas More: A Biography, Alfred A. Knopf,
New York, 1984; Raymond Wilson Chambers, Thomas More, Endeavor Press, London,
2017 (first published 1935); George M. Logan (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Thomas
More, Cambridge University Press, 2011; and Peter Berglar, Thomas More: A Lonely Voice
Against the Power of the State, Scepter Publishers, Cleveland, 2009 (first published in Ger-
man, 1999).
72
The London Charterhouse was a Carthusian Priory 1371-1537, when it was dissolved by
Henry VIII. The Carthusian order, also called the Order of Saint Bruno, is a Catholic reli-
gious order of enclosed monastics. It was founded by Bruno of Cologne in 1084 and in-
cludes both monks and nuns. The order has its own Rule, called the Statutes, rather than the
Rule of Saint Benedict, and combines eremitical and coenobitic monasticism. The motto of
the Carthusians is Stat crux dum volvitur orbis, Latin for “The Cross is steady while the
world is turning”; Wikiwand, “London Charterhouse” (available on its web site).
73
For a short discussion of More’s motivations to seek political engagement, see John Guy,
“Shaping a mind”, in Thomas More: A Very Brief History, Society for Promotion of Chris-
tian Knowledge, London, 2017, pp. 1–8.
74
James McComica, “Thomas More as Humanist”, in George M. Lugan (ed.), The Cambridge
Companion to Thomas More (Cambridge Companions to Religion), Cambridge University
Press, 2011, p. 22.
75
Ibid., p. 23.
76
Ibid. Several of More’s friends and teachers were prominent scholars and linguists who had
travelled to Florence and Rome to study Greek language and philosophy, such as William
Grocyn (1446–1519), Thomas Linacre (1460–1524), John Colet (1467–1519), and William
Lily (1468–1522).
77
Ibid., p. 26.
his works – such as The Republic and The Laws, but also many of the So-
cratic dialogues – focus on how to improve the less than perfect material
and political world. 78
A central point for Plato, resonated in the writings of Cicero (106–43
BC), one of the few Roman thinkers that More held in high esteem, was
that humans are not born for themselves alone, “but our country claims a
share of our being, and our friends a share”. 79 In developing this perception
of humans as socially inter-connected, More warned against misconstrued
views on human liberty.
False expectations of life arise from such views, namely that a free
person is the one that can do whatever he wants. Rather, inherent in liberty
are to be guided by constraints such as the high commandments of God, the
laws made by humans to rule society, and the commands of those with le-
gitimate power. Given human nature, persons may easily fall prey to en-
slavement by obsessions, sins, or by society and rulers. One part of society
often enslaves another.
An antidote to such enslavement is to connect liberty with law, as
advocated by Cicero and further developed by More. 80 In his early works,
More underlined that liberty without law, even if you are a rich person, is
tantamount to bondage. In particular, he points to the importance of ‘skilled
princeps’, ‘leading citizens’ respecting the law. These are leaders that have
the virtues, training and ingenuity needed to secure the safety of the people
and provide justice. Their integrity is of utmost importance for society.
Leaders who do not respect law and liberty, develop into tyrants. The
quality of a ruler is made clear only by the actual liberty, prosperity, peace,
and joy of his people. 81
4.3.1. The Ever-Present Danger of Tyranny
There is a strong continuity in More’s thinking about the duties of leaders,
from his first literary works until his last works written during his 14 and a
half months of imprisonment before he was beheaded. A main theme is that
78
See Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, “Plato”, 20 March 2004 (available on its web site).
79
Marcus Tullius Cicero, De Officiis, Walter Miller (trans.), Harvard University Press, Cam-
bridge, 1913 [44 BC].
80
More was shortly after his death called “the Christian English Cicero”, see Nicholas Harp-
field, Life and Death of Sir Thomas More, Early English Text Society, London, 1932, p. 217.
81
Gerard Wegemer, “Thomas More on Liberty, Law, and Good Rule”, in Curtright (ed.), 2015,
pp. 5–13, see above note 7.
true leading citizens have a duty to ensure that justice is done. To neglect to
do what the duty of his office requires is “like a cowardly ship’s captain
who […] deserts the helm, hides away covering in some cranny, and aban-
dons the ship to the waves”. 82
Even though More was a Christian thinker and statesman, many of
his ideas have resonated well beyond Christian circles. This is no surprise
since More’s humanist writings conveyed arguments and views which were
based on philosophical ideas. He held the view that reason and practical
wisdom led to conclusions that would not be contradicted but rather further
enlightened by Christian revelation.
More’s example has appealed to Christians, persons with other faiths,
as well as to non-believers. This is an important part of the reasoning be-
hind pope John Paul II’s proclamation of More as “Patron of Statesmen and
Politicians”. In the apostolic letter making the proclamation, the pope re-
ferred to support from “different political, cultural, and religious allegianc-
es”, indicating a “deep and widespread interest in the thought and activity
of this outstanding statesman”. 83
A fundamental issue for More and the tradition of thought he be-
longed to, was how a leading citizen, a statesman, or a philosopher should
respond to tyranny. Rulers developing into tyrants was seen as an ever-
present danger, given the temptations of power and the lack of strong insti-
tutional set-ups that could temper the ruler’s tyrannical inclinations. More
certainly realized that serving King Henry VIII could become precariously
difficult, given the Kings propensity to pass from mild rule into repressive
and arbitrary rule. In general, More favoured republican and consultative
government over that of a single ruler to avoid abuse of power. 84
More also favoured that members of Parliament should be given
freedom of expression, so that the King would know what they really felt
about his propositions. In April 1523 he was chosen as speaker of the
House of Commons, and in a speech there he made the first recorded peti-
tion for the exercise of freedom of speech in parliament. Effective govern-
ance depended on parliamentarians’ freedom to speak their mind without
82
Thomas More, De Tristita Cristi, in The Complete Works of St. Thomas More (CW), 15 vols.,
Yale University Press, New Haven, 1963–97, vol. 14, p. 265.
83
John Paul II, Apostolic Letter Issued Motu Proprio: Proclaiming Saint Thomas More Patron
of Statesmen and Politicians, section 1, see above note 54.
84
Cathy Curtis, “More’s public life”, in Logan (ed.), 2011, p. 74, see above note 71.
85
Ibid., p. 77.
86
More’s Declamation is available in: The Complete Works of St. Thomas More, 15 vols., Yale
University Press, New Haven, 1963–97, vol. 3, part 1. In 1505–1506, More and Erasmus
translated some of Lucian’s writing into Latin. More translated the Cynicus, Minippus,
Philopseudes and Tyrannicide, and both he and Erasmus wrote declamations replying to the
latter work.
92
Plato, 1991, 572d–575d, see above note 91.
93
Holloway, 2015, pp. 22–23, see above note 87.
94
Ibid.
95
More, Declamation, p. 101, see above note 86.
rape, and robbery. This is so because he may use objects of bodily desires
to ascertain his total dominance over his realm. To keep public order and
rule moderately, would not satisfy his lust for complete dominance. He
cannot accept any kind of equality between his subjects and himself. He
murders, robs, and rapes to manifest his supremacy and humiliate those he
rules over.
There is also an important impunity factor, explaining the tyrant’s
excessive abuses. Since he is placed totally above the law, he is free to ful-
fil any bodily desire. In his soul, the worst parts dominate the best (reason),
and this results in him being unhappy and “full of confusion and regret”. 96
He is therefore constantly seeking distractions by fulfilling his bodily de-
sires.
Fourthly, the resulting characteristics of tyrannical rule may be sum-
marized as a lawless form of rule in contrast to legitimate authority, that
governs by laws and obeys laws. The tyrant may call his directives ‘laws’,
but they hardly deserve the name since he can change them at any time. A
law is a settled rule superior to any single man’s will, and the tyrant there-
fore cannot accept it. His rule becomes unpredictable, spreading fear and
distress among his subjects. 97
Tyranny is also a regime devoid of any freedom. All of the tyrant’s
subjects evidently lack freedom, living at the mercy of the tyrant. However,
the tyrant himself also lacks genuine freedom. He cannot choose what is
good for human beings, namely to be governed by reason and laws. He
does not know real friendship; he reduces other human beings to become
tools of his own desires. His freedom is therefore empty and illusory. He is
enslaved by his own desires, dominated by forces within his own distorted
soul.
More’s teaching on tyranny is a dark tale. Not the least because of his
insistence that it is rooted in human nature and its strong desires. It is ex-
treme and evil, but it is not as rare as we would like to think. It tends to de-
velop from the normal functioning of the human soul, which is often not
properly regulated. When the man who killed the tyrant’s son claims to
have eradicated tyranny and demand to be rewarded, it is another example
of the spirited desire for public recognition beyond what is truly reasonable.
96
Plato, 1991, 577e, see above note 91.
97
More, Declamation, p. 101, see above note 86; Holloway, 2015, p. 24, see above note 87.
That means that the impulses – the inflated desire for honour and
public praise – that led to tyranny is also present in the attempted destruc-
tion of tyranny. In addition, there is a question about the motives: was the
attack on the tyrant based on a genuine will to eradicate tyranny or was it
done “in revenge or retaliation for some private injury done to you”?. 98
Those acting against the tyrant may include decent men who suffered under
brutal oppression, but it could also include selfish men who resented the
fact that the tyranny operated against their own benefit. There might even
be men included who want to replace the tyrant, while upholding tyranny.
According to More, in any society there is a part of the population
that must be categorized as wicked. Even if they form just a small part,
their views might influence the deliberations of the society if they are not
refuted. The recognition that wickedness is always part of politics, also in
non-tyrannical regimes, must make us realize that any regime carries the
seeds of tyranny. 99
In More’s own words, even “legitimate authorities, not only govern-
ing by laws but also obeying laws, and so very much milder than a tyranny,
are nevertheless so dominated by the desire for power that they spare not
the lives of intimate friends rather than allow them to share their rule”. 100
More’s conclusion is that it is naïve to think about the tyrant as an
exceptional person, a monster or a psychopath, and that lawful rulers could
not become tyrants. The same spirited motives that result in tyranny – love
of power and fame – are present even in legitimate rulers. The difference is
that they are present in more restrained forms.
Finally, it must not be forgotten that even if the tyrant does not toler-
ate co-rulers, there are plenty of enablers, supporters and henchmen. You
may succeed in killing the tyrant, but utterly fail in eradicating tyranny
which is brought forward by those who willingly benefited from his rule,
were protected by it and themselves committed outrageous crimes.
4.3.2. The Fundamental Question of Integrity
We have now reached the point in discussing tyranny where what could be
called the fundamental question of integrity should be asked: How to con-
98
More, Declamation, p. 107, see above note 86.
99
Holloway, 2015, p. 27, see above note 87.
100
More, Declamation, p. 101, see above note 86.
front tyranny in such a way that you don’t sow the seeds of further tyranny,
neither in your own soul nor in society?
According to More, the answer is that you should rebalance your
soul and leave the level of spiritedness. Reason should become the guide of
your actions, not motives of being recognized for courage, becoming fa-
mous and publicly praised. Since the cause of tyranny is the domination of
spirited desires, actions based on these desires cannot be the solution.
It does not mean, however, that there is no need for courage and oth-
er spirited desires in confronting tyranny. The problem arises, however,
when desires of fame, honour, and power remain uncontrolled. What is
needed is courageous actions under the direction of reason.
The fundamental question could thus be rephrased as how to ensure
that reason remain in control of spirit and appetite in confronting tyranny?
More makes this point clear by comparing the tyrannicide with a
doctor. The criteria by which to judge the professional quality of a doctor is
whether he heals or improves the condition of a patient, not how strongly
he wants or tries to do so. If he pretends to know how to heal me, without
being competent, he deserves only “condemnation for rashly meddling, to
my danger, in this matter in which he was unskilled”. 101
In a similar way, what the law seeks in rewarding killing of the tyrant
and eradicating tyranny, is a “resourceful man, one not only stronghanded
but (much more) strong-hearted; able in stratagem rather than in force; one
who knows how to lay plots, hide his traps, make the most of his opportu-
nities”. 102
Confronting tyranny effectively requires intelligence and skill. An
incompetent doctor may leave the patient in a worse condition than before
his intervention. Likewise, confronting tyranny without proper strategies
and skills may strengthen it and increase the suffering of ordinary people
who now may be targeted innocently by an enraged tyrant.
Even if Lucian’s character, claiming that he should be rewarded for
tyrannicide, had succeeded in killing the tyrant himself, the forces that had
enabled tyranny would still be operational. There would be men who had
been privileged by his rule, stealing from and suppressing their fellow citi-
zens, and who would be eager to find a successor to the tyrant. Even if they
101
Ibid., p. 109.
102
Ibid.
failed, there would be civil war or uprisings, people would die and the goal
of establishing a legitimate free public order would be hard to attain.
More returns to the question of how a leading citizen or a statesman
could confront tyranny or milder forms of corrupted politics in the first
book of Utopia, which was written about 10 years later than the Declama-
tion (in 1515-6). 103 Here the focus is on the problem of ensuring that rulers
receive – and take – appropriate advice. Given the corrupted nature of poli-
tics, from the point of view of a prospective councillor, the question is if he
should commit himself to public affairs at all. The discussion between the
philosopher-traveller, Raphael Hythloday (who in the second part recounts
his experiences from Utopia, an island State based on socialist, tolerant,
and equality principles), Peter Giles (a humanist official, based on a real
person), and Thomas More (the author, but not necessarily always present-
ing the author’s views) on this issue is revealing:
‘My dear Raphael’, he said, ‘I’m surprised that you don’t en-
ter some King’s service; for I don’t know of a single prince
who wouldn’t be very glad to have you. Your learning and
your knowledge of various countries and peoples would enter-
tain him while your advice and supply of examples would be
helpful at the counsel board. Thus you might admirably ad-
vance your own interests and be of great use at the same time
to all your relatives and friends.’
‘About my relatives and friends’, he replied, ‘I’m not
much concerned, because I consider I’ve already done my du-
ty by them tolerably well. While still young and healthy, I dis-
tributed among my relatives and friends the possessions that
most men do not part with till they’re old and sick (and then
only reluctantly, when they can no longer keep them). I think
they should be content with this gift of mine, and not insist, or
even expect, that for their sake I should enslave myself to any
King whatever.’
‘Well said’, Peter replied; ‘but I do not mean that you
should be in servitude to any King, only in his service.’
‘The difference is only a matter of one syllable’, said
Raphael.
‘All right’, said Peter, ‘but whatever you call it, I do not
see any other way in which you can be so useful to your
103
More, 1516, see above note 3.
caring for the people, More again concedes that such views will indeed be
met by deaf ears. Raphael should therefore refrain from giving advice that
he “knows for certain will not be listened to”. 109
In the councils of Kings, there is no room for lofty academic philos-
ophy, ill adapted to the situation, continues More.
But there is another philosophy, better suited for the role of a
citizen, that takes its cue, adapts itself to the drama in hand
and acts its part neatly and appropriately. This is the philoso-
phy for you to use. […] If you cannot pluck up bad ideas by
the root, or cure longstanding evils to your heart’s content,
you must not therefore abandon the commonwealth. Don’t
give up the ship in a storm because you cannot hold back the
winds. […] Instead, by an indirect approach, you must strive
and struggle as best you can to handle everything tactfully –
and thus what you cannot turn to good, you may at least make
as little bad as possible. For it is impossible to make every-
thing good unless all men are good, and that I don’t expect to
see for quite a few years yet. 110
In reply, Raphael explains that he cannot give up his convictions and
lie. He is not sure what More means by ‘indirect approach’ either. Besides,
in a council,
there is no way to dissemble or look the other way. You must
openly approve the worst proposals and endorse the most vi-
cious policies. A man who praised wicked counsels only half-
heartedly would be suspected as a spy, perhaps a traitor. And
there is no way for you to do any good when you are thrown
among colleagues who would more readily corrupt the best of
men than be reformed themselves. Either they will seduce you
by their evil ways, or, if you remain honest and innocent, you
will be made a screen for the knavery and folly of others. You
wouldn’t stand a chance of changing anything for the better by
that “indirect approach”.
This is why Plato in a very fine comparison declares that
wise men are right in keeping away from public business.
They see the people swarming through the streets and getting
soaked with rain; they cannot persuade them to go indoors and
get out of the wet. If they go out themselves, they know they
109
Ibid., p. 36
110
Ibid., pp. 36–37.
111
Ibid., p. 39.
112
Ibid., p. 35
113
Curtis, 2011, p. 70, see above note 84.
1518, reflected extensively on the costs and dangers for a wise and just
man in serving the King. 114 In accepting to do so, he kept to the main prin-
ciples he had formulated in his writings on how to civilize politics; by ap-
plying an ‘indirect approach’ and practical wisdom, always adapt to the
situation at hand, refraining from radical and sweeping actions. During his
conflict with the King he never conspired against him, plotted against him
or even denounced him publicly. Nevertheless, both while in office and af-
ter stepping down, he continued to work for what he thought was the best
for the commonwealth and its people.
More’s background as both lawyer, humanist scholar and a devout
Christian with inclinations for a life of contemplation and religious studies
seems to have prepared him well for the kind of uncorrupted office he be-
came known for. There are, however, considerable debate among scholars
about the reasons for him to enter the King’s council in 1518, and later
climb to ever higher positions. Initially, he expressed reservations about the
inconveniences and threats to reputation entailed in such service. 115
The simplest explanation may be that he felt obliged to contribute to
making things as little bad as possible, along the lines of the discussion in
Utopia rendered above. 116 Entering the King’s service would increase his
influence in reforming the English legal and political order in a way that
benefitted the people.
There might, however, also have been more specific reasons. Pope
Leo X hade proposed in a bull of 6 March 1518 a truce among European
powers, which would enable a united front against the Turks in response to
Ottoman successes in Egypt and Syria. More may have thought that by en-
tering royal service at this point, he could ensure that England supported
such a collective security initiative to European peace-making. England’s
role in entering the October 1518 Universal Peace Treaty (proclaimed in
London), created needs for additional skilled public servants to bring it to
fruition. The treaty represented an early and important attempt to address
114
More was appointed under-sheriff in 1510. As such, he was a permanent official who ad-
vised the sheriffs and sat as judge in the sheriff’s court. He received a generous stipend and
had a lucrative right to represent the City in the royal courts at Westminster.
115
Curtis, 2011, p. 73, see above note 84.
116
More, 1516, p. 35, see above note 3.
117
For further explanation, see Curtis, 2011, pp. 75–76, see above note 84. The treaty did not
succeed in securing long-term peace in Europe.
118
Guy, 2017, chap. 3, “The King’s servant”, see above note 71.
119
Ibid.
120
Ibid.
121
From More’s epitaph for the Tomb in Chelsea Old Church, which he wrote himself in 1532.
T.E. Bridgett, “Sir Thomas More’s Epitaph”, in Life and Writings of Sir Thomas More,
Burns & Oates, London, 1892, pp. 250–252.
122
Curtis, 2011, p. 71, see above note 84.
123
Ibid., p. 79.
124
Ibid., p. 72.
125
More was called a “man for all seasons” during his lifetime. Robert Bolt’s play “A Man for
All Seasons” (1954) about More’s life and conflict with Henry VIII, made the phrase famous.
The play was subsequently made into a multi-Academy Award-winning 1966 feature film
and a 1988 television movie, see Fred Zinnemann (Producer and Director), “A Man for All
Seasons”, motion picture, 1966, United Kingdom, Highland Films; and Robert Bolt (Pro-
Some would argue, however, that this is to give him too much praise.
He should rather be portrayed as a fanatic, responsible for the burning of
heretics, lacking in pragmatism and willingness to compromise. Such criti-
cism was mounted already during his lifetime and in the aftermath of his
conflict with Henry VIII. It has also found expression in contemporary
popular culture and scholarship. 126
To reconcile the dissonance between the tolerance demonstrated in
his humanist writings and his intolerance of Protestantism may not be easy
in our time, where freedom of religion is solidly anchored in international
law as well as in most national jurisdictions. 127 In Utopia, there is freedom
of religion (except for atheism), but More was strongly against such free-
dom in his native England.
He treated Luther and Protestantism very harshly. During his last 10
years of service for the King, he devoted considerable energy and time to
enforce England’s heresy laws. This was not an incidental part of his life
and work. It was central to his understanding of his professional duties. 128
He, however, denied any involvement in torture, although he was not
against the death penalty for heresy, which was part of the legislation and
culture of the time he lived in. Historians believe that six heretics were
condemned to be burned during More’s tenure as lord chancellor. 129
Heretic dissent from the dominant catholic Christianity was known in
England from the late fourteenth century, when John Wycliff (1330–1384)
preached a theology anticipating Protestantism. The movement became
ducer) and Charlton Heston (Director), “A Man for All Seasons”, motion picture, 1988,
United States, Turner Network Television.
126
The most important early example is John Foxe’s (1516–1587) famous Book of Martyrs
(1563), a graphic and polemic account of those who suffered for the cause of Protestantism,
including in the hands of Thomas More: John Fox, Book of Martyrs, John Day, London,
1563. In 2009 a novelist won the Man Booker Prize for Fiction with a story in which she has
More admit in conversation the allegations of torture he denied in print: Hilary Mantel, Wolf
Hall, Fourth Estate, London, 2009, pp. 628–9. Wolf Hall is also the title of a widely seen TV
series by the BBC2, based on the book.
127
Although far from being practiced everywhere, as documented by among others, Pew Re-
search Centre.
128
Richard Rex, “Thomas More and the heretics: statesman or fanatic?”, in Logan (ed.), 2011,
p. 94, see above note 71. The modern tradition of portraying More as an unbalanced inquisi-
tor derives chiefly from Marius, 1984, see above note 71; and from Geoffrey Elton, Studies
in Tudor and Stuart Politics and Government, 4 vols., Cambridge University Press, 1974–92.
129
Ibid.
130
More was, nevertheless, in favour of the church producing an English translation of the Bi-
ble. It should, however, be without all the mistakes that the reformers’ translations contained.
A true English translation should be undertaken as soon as possible. Guy, 2017, chapter
three: “The King’s servant”, see above note 71.
131
Ibid.
132
Rex, 2011, p. 95, see above note 128.
133
CW, vol. 10, p. 30, see above note 82.
134
Rex, 2011, p. 98, see above note 128.
135
Thomas More, Dialogue Concerning Heresies, in CW, vol. 6, see above note 82.
136
Thomas More, Confutation of Tyndale’s Answer, in CW, vol. 8, see above note 82.
137
Thomas More, Apology, in CW, vol. 9, see above note 82.
138
Rex, 2011, p. 105, see above note 128.
During his last 10 years of service, both before and during his period
as lord chancellor, “heresy was the single most time-consuming issue
Thomas More dealt with”. 139 He was very concerned, however, that actions
against heretics should be in compliance with the laws. When accused of
transgressing legal bonds in heresy cases, he refuted that strongly.
The policies More implemented were also in line with what the bish-
ops of the Catholic church wanted of him. At the time, it was highly unusu-
al that a layman played such an important role as theological polemist,
demonstrating the church leaders’ unusual confidence in him.
His role in confronting heresy in the service of the King was more
conventional. It was first and foremost a function of his public position.
“Since the time of Henry V, the oath sworn by every man who took office
under the crown had included an undertaking to assist the Church in the
struggle against heresy.” As lord chancellor, being the head of the judiciary,
he was under an obligation to repress heresy. 140
However, More’s motivation to write extensively against Protestant-
ism was also based on personal conviction. He perceived that Protestantism
represented a serious threat to the existing order in England and Europe. It
rapidly attracted support from learned men such as himself. The Refor-
mation introduced a new version of Christianity, which would lead to vio-
lent social and political revolutions in Europe.
Regardless of how convincing such justifications may appear, diffi-
cult questions remain. Could such beliefs justify that he acted against here-
tics in the way he did? Should he rather have made efforts to temper the
bishops’ and the King’s wishes for repressive measures? Did More stay
governed by reason in his actions against heretics or did he let spirited de-
sires rule?
In answering such questions, one must take into account the context
of More’s thinking and actions. One’s judgment should not be based on
solely modern prepositions. By taking a contextual stand, I believe the con-
clusion must be that More remained governed by reason. He acted like a
first citizen and not as a fanatic.
This conclusion does not imply that his reasons should not be criti-
cized. We should not endorse his intolerance, even if we can understand his
139
Ibid., p. 107.
140
Ibid., p. 108.
reasoning. It does, however, mean that we can still learn about integrity
from More. He stayed a man of reason, even if his reasons were wrong.
His mistake entails important lessons. Even if you preserve integrity
in the More-sense by letting your reason and faith rule, following your con-
science, you may be wrong. Infallible religious or philosophical truths are
unattainable, even though, at a personal level, you may choose to base your
life on them. At the State level, however, you should not operate according
to such convictions. You should refrain from appealing to the consensus of
any institution, such as the church, as something that cannot be criticized.
States that present themselves as built on infallible truths lead to tyranny
and oppression, even if they treat all but the heretics nice.
The full meaning of religious tolerance in the affairs of the State may
not have been explicitly taught by More at any time, although his humanist
writings pointed in that direction. In Utopia, at least, he showed that a soci-
ety could function well even if it practised a lot more tolerance than Eng-
land and himself as a State official.
4.5. More’s Conflict with Henry VIII
The main controversy with Henry VIII was about the independence of the
English Church. The King wanted The English Church to depart from the
Catholic Church because of the Pope’s unwillingness to accept his divorce
from his first wife, Catherine of Aragon, who did not give him a son. The
King wanted to marry Anne Boleyn and did so secretly on 25 January 1532,
when she was already pregnant with his child. Because of the pregnancy,
divorce with Catherine to avoid bigamy and his child to be born outside
wedlock became urgent. An independent English Church, under the King’s
own leadership, would help formalize divorce and re-marriage.
To accomplish the break with Rome and destroy the power of the
medieval church, the so-called Reformation Parliament played a vital role.
It first met in November 1529 and lasted seven years, enacting 137 statues
of which 32 were of vital importance. In addition, the King also pressured
the church Convocation to accept his demands.
Some of the most important acts and submissions that ensured that
Henry VIII became head of the English Church and separated England
from the Pope’s influence was:
141
Parliament of England, Act in Conditional Restraint of Annates (23 Hen. VIII c. 20), 1532
(Annates Statute).
142
The document was adopted in Convocation on 15 May 1532 under intense pressure from
Henry VIII and handed to the King on the following day. It contained a submission to the
King’s demands, promising,
in verbo sacerdotii, here unto your highness, submitting ourselves most humbly to the
same, that we will never from henceforth [enact], put in use, promulge, or execute, any
[new canons or constitutions provincial, or any other new ordinance, provincial or syn-
odal], in our Convocation [or synod] in time coming, which Convocation is, always has
been, and must be, assembled only by your highness’ commandment of writ, unless your
highness by your royal assent shall license us to [assemble our Convocation, and] to
make, promulge, and execute [such constitutions and ordinances as shall be made in] the
same; and thereto give your royal assent and authority.
Henry VIII, The Reign, “Submission of the Clergy 1532” (available on its web site).
143
Parliament of England, An Acte that the Appeles in suche Cases as have ben used to be pur-
sued to the See of Rome shall not be from hensforth had ne used but within this Realme (24
Hen. VIII c. 12), April 1533 (Act of Restraint of Appeals).
144
Parliament of England, Act of Succession (25 Hen. VIII c. 22), March 1534.
145
Parliament of England, Act in Absolute Restraint of Annates (25 Hen. VIII c. 20), November
1534.
146
Parliament of England, Act of Treason (26 Hen. VIII c. 13), December 1534.
147
The overview is based on: Patrick Joyce, Ralph Charles Atkins and Others, “United King-
dom: The Break with Rome”, Encyclopædia Britannica (available on its web site).
148
Ibid.
149
Peter Marshall, “The last years”, in Logan (ed.), 2011, p. 116, see above note 71; Curtis,
2011, p. 69, see above note 84.
150
Travis Curtright, “Sir Thomas More and his Opposition to Henry VIII in 1533”, in Curtright
(ed.), 2015, pp. 111, see above note 7.
151
Ibid., p. 112.
prophecies against Henry’s divorce. More was, however, able to prove his
innocence.
In April 1533, More refused the Oath of Succession because it trans-
gressed on the freedom of the English Church. He was imprisoned on 17
April 1534 and tried on 1 July 1535, for denying the King’s title as su-
preme head of the Church of England. In the trial, he was found guilty of
treason despite his denial of what he considered perjured evidence. He was
beheaded five days later.
4.5.1. The Ultimate Test of Integrity
What More endured after his arrest may be termed as his ultimate test of
integrity. Pressure mounted against him because of his unwillingness to
state his acceptance of the King’s new power over the Church – from rep-
resentatives of the King in the forms of threats, interrogations, and traps;
from friends and former colleagues in the form of appeals of giving in; and
from family members who suffered because of his imprisonment and his
loss of income and estate.
The indictment comprised of four counts: 152
1. More had maliciously refused on 7 May 1535, to accept the King’s
supremacy over the Church of England;
2. He had conspired against the King by writing treasonous letters to
bishop John Fisher;
3. He had stirred up sedition by describing the Act of Supremacy as a
two-edged sword, that is, a law that if disobeyed would mean bodily
death, and if obeyed would mean spiritual death;
4. He had “maliciously, traitorously, and diabolically” denied Parlia-
ment’s power to declare the King to be head of the Church. 153
In his defence, which he had to present himself without written notes,
More underlined that he had remained silent on whether the King could be
the head of the English Church. His argument was based on a legal norm
established by English precedent, that “silence is not a crime; in fact, si-
lence means consent”. 154
152
This section is based on Wegemer, 1995, see above note 64.
153
Ibid., p. 210.
154
Ibid., p. 211.
155
Ibid.
156
Ibid., p. 213.
English Church shall be free, and shall have its rights undiminished and its
liberties unimpaired”. 157
He knew, however, that even if there were no evidence against him,
this would not be enough to save him. His real opponent was the King, and
the King could not accept anything but surrender.
He did not surrender. Nor did he try to escape. He referred to his
conscience, which was bound by faith and reason to defend the unity of the
church. He stood the test of integrity as a lawyer, providing a solid defence
for himself in line with ethical and professional standards.
He also stood the test of integrity as a person, not making conces-
sions conflicting his personal views, while caring for his family and friends,
expressing gratitude to those who supported him, and forbearance to those
who facilitated the injustice that caused his death.
Few persons could have done so well in terms of upholding his integ-
rity – being ruled by reason and faithful to his professional and personal
convictions – under such pressure, knowing that death was a certain out-
come. It is a remarkable story about skill and courage.
However, in my view, the main lesson to take from More is not that
we shall never give in to pressure when confronted with lethal threats. We
should rather follow More’s own reasoning in his humanistic writings and
learn how courage and other spirited desires should always be governed by
reason. A well-trained and educated reason.
What we should learn from him is how he did what he thought rea-
sonable to avert the King’s measures that would undermine justice and
peace in England and in Christian States in Europe.
According to his view of the world, this could be summarized as be-
ing more faithful to God than to the King. He ended his life by stating that
“I die the King’s faithful servant, but God’s first”. 158
157
England, Magna Carta Libertatum, 15 June 1215, clause 1.
158
Quoted from Peter Marshall, “The last years”, in Logan (ed.), 2011, p. 133, see above note
71. Some scholars doubt the authenticity of the quote, which was reported first by the Paris
News Letter, 4 August, 1535. It is, however, little doubt that it reflects More’s understanding
of his relation to the King; an understanding he had believed the King shared. Cf. the Center
for Thomas More Studies, “About Famous Quotes” (available on its web site).
159
Wegemer, 1995, see above note 64.
160
This is a prevailing view in Peter Berglar, Thomas More: A Lonely Voice Against the Power
of the State, Scepter Publishers, Cleveland, 2009 (First Published in German, 1999), summa-
rized in the foreword as follows: “More generally, what was involved was the breaking
away of society and the state from the medieval political order and the birth of the modern
concept of independent nationhood. But something else also was implicated in these events,
namely, the state’s ambition to impose not just de facto obedience but also active assent.
Now, for the first time in history, simply tolerating the unilateral decisions of an establish-
ment was not enough; explicit approval was demanded, and not only defiance but personal
opinion was subject to persecution, with nonconformity treated as the equivalent of rebellion.
In the cradle of modern Europe, then, we witness a power struggle to preserve the freedom
of the individual in the face of organized power, something not always or necessarily identi-
fied with the state”.
161
The tower works include: Thomas More, A Dialogue of Comfort Against Tribulation, in CW,
vol. 12, 1534, see above note 82; Thomas More, Treatise Upon the Passion, in CW vol. 13,
1534, see above note 82; Thomas More, Treatise on the Blessed Body, in CW, vol. 13, 1535,
see above note 82; Thomas More, De Tristitia Christi, in CW, vol. 14, 1535, see above note
82.
162
Thomas More to his daughter, in prison, August 1534. Quoted from Curtright (ed.), 2015,
beginning of book, before pagination, see above note 7.
163
Gerard B. Wegemer and Stephen W. Smith, A Thomas More Source Book, The Catholic
University of America Press, Washington, DC, 2004, p. 334.
He did not perceive his courage as entirely a gift of grace. It also had
to be nurtured through imagination, internalization of words and prepara-
tions, and to be controlled by reason.
More exemplified integrity as self-integration and consistency
throughout his career. He stood for something, not giving in to pressure, at
the same time always willing to reason and provide his arguments.
More is not an example of ‘civil disobedience’ based on personal
convictions, I would argue. His reasoning and practice during the ultimate
integrity test are instead closer to modern conceptions of professional in-
tegrity. As outlined above, professional integrity is characterized by a mode
of reasoning that calls for the role holder to engage critically and creatively
with the varied and sometimes conflicting demands of professional practice.
More as a ‘first citizen’ was a professional, applying legal and theological
arguments in line with professional standards and practice of his time.
His defence of the unity of the church and church doctrine may be
seen as a reference to authoritative theological practice. In his conflict with
Henry VIII, he makes efforts to give his best reading of that practice.
The same goes for his acting as a lawyer, throughout his career, and
certainly in his own final case. In his defence, he provides what he believes
is the best reading of English jurisprudence in a treason case like his.
It may seem paradoxical, but because More is not a modern in the
sense that he linked his conscience to private opinion, he becomes interest-
ing in terms of professional integrity, which primarily refers to institutional
practice and not to personal opinion.
More favoured reforms, that is, improving the standards and practice
of church, law and politics gradually. Concerning church doctrine and prac-
tice, he referred to the General Council of Christendom as the final arbiter.
He argued that new legislation should be adopted by Parliament,
while judges should have discretion to apply written and unwritten law ac-
cording to circumstances and their own interpretation.
4.7. Integrity in Justice
There are thus several ways in which More is relevant for discussions on
how to strengthen integrity in justice.
For individuals considering the fundamental integrity question –
whether to enter the world of justice professionals – there is great inspira-
tion to take from him. He would tell them that there is a fundamental ques-
tion anyone who considers working for justice institutions have to ask
themselves: Will I be able to honour the promises of my profession, despite
all the pressure, cynicism and temptations I will be exposed to? Will I be
able to hold my spirited desires and appetite (for money, sex, luxury) gov-
erned by reason?
From More’s writings, we know that he believed that an initial de-
termination to live up to integrity standards is not enough. His method was
to continuously train himself in integrity by binding his conscience to the
standards and promises of his profession, and by reflecting on how to mod-
erate the effects of wickedness and evil.
Safeguarding the integrity of the church, justice institutions, and Par-
liament was a central part of More’s efforts as a statesman and lawyer. He
knew well that institutions could be corrupted and manipulated, and how
important leadership were in setting and practising high standards. Well-
functioning institutions could improve societies and human affairs vastly.
They should be protected.
The catalogue of integrity failures listed in Section 4.2.2.1. above
would not be unknown to More. I suspect he would respond that to let un-
due pressure, material temptations, personal relationships, or lack of pro-
fessional and moral convictions lead you away from professional duties
would be the result of the lower parts of your soul being too dominant. The
antidote would be to rebalance your soul and let reason rule. He would
know well that this is easier said than done. To succeed may require hard
work over a long time.
However, if you are going to make advances in confronting tyranny
and injustices that is what is necessary. This is also what an institution such
as a court promises. Maintaining professional integrity as a leader or staff
member of such institutions requires conforming your conscience to the
promises and aims of justice – and follow it.
That seems to me to be the essence of Thomas More’s thoughts and
practice of integrity.
*
Hans Corell is the former Under-Secretary-General for Legal Affairs and the Legal Counsel
of the United Nations, Ambassador and Under-Secretary for Legal and Consular Affairs in
the Swedish Ministry for Foreign Affairs, Chief Legal Officer of the Swedish Ministry of
Justice, and a judge in Sweden. The present chapter is based on an oral presentation that the
author gave at the Peace Palace in The Hague on 1 December 2018. There were a few foot-
notes in that presentation. All additional footnotes have been added by the editors.
1
Dag Hammarskjöld, “The International Civil Servant in Law and in Fact”, Oxford, 30 May
1961 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/64bcae/).
2
Ibid., sect. II, p. 329.
3
Ibid., pp. 330 ff.
4
Ibid., sect. III, pp. 332–33.
Article 98
The Secretary-General shall act in that capacity in all meet-
ings of the General Assembly, of the Security Council, of the
Economic and Social Council, and of the Trusteeship Council,
and shall perform such other functions as are entrusted to him
by these organs. The Secretary-General shall make an annual
report to the General Assembly on the work of the Organiza-
tion.
Article 99
The Secretary-General may bring to the attention of the Secu-
rity Council any matter which in his opinion may threaten the
maintenance of international peace and security.
It is also important to note that, according to Article 101 of the UN
Charter, the staff shall be appointed by the Secretary-General under regula-
tions established by the General Assembly. “The paramount consideration
in the employment of the staff and in the determination of the conditions of
service shall be the necessity of securing the highest standards of efficiency,
competence, and integrity.” 8 Due regard should be paid to the importance
of recruiting the staff on as wide a geographical basis as possible. 9
5
See Charter of the United Nations, 26 June 1945 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/6b3cd5/)
(‘UN Charter’).
6
Hammarskjöld, 1961, p. 334, above note 1.
7
See ibid., pp. 334–38.
8
UN Charter, Article 101, see above note 5. See also Hammarskjöld, 1961, p. 337, above note
1.
9
Ibid.
10
Ibid., p. 334.
11
Ibid., p. 335.
12
Ibid.
13
Ibid.
14
Ibid.
15
Ibid., p. 337.
16
Ibid., sect. V, p. 342.
17
Ibid.
18
See ibid., pp. 343 ff.
19
Ibid., p. 344.
20
Ibid., p. 345.
21
Ibid.
22
Ibid., p. 346.
23
Ibid.
24
Ibid.
25
Ibid., p. 348.
26
Ibid.
27
Ibid.
28
Ibid.
29
Ibid.
30
Hans Corell, “The Need for the Rule of Law in International Affairs – Reflections on Dag
Hammarskjöld’s address at Oxford University on 30 May 1961, ‘The International Civil
Service in Law and in Fact’”, in Henning Melber (ed.), The Ethics of Dag Hammarskjöld,
Dag Hammarskjöld Foundation, Uppsala, 2010, p. 15.
rather step back for a moment and reflect. Is this situation not,
rather, a sign of health – that the Secretary-General is doing
his or her job? On second thoughts, maybe the firm stand of
the Secretary-General is in both the short and long term inter-
est of the member states, including those that may have been
displeased in the particular situation. 31
31
Ibid., p. 16.
32
In Swedish: ämbetsmannatraditionen.
33
Statute of the International Court of Justice, 26 June 1945 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/
fdd2d2/).
34
Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court, 17 July 1998 (http://www.legal-tools.org/
doc/7b9af9/).
ferent settings over the years since I was involved in the establishment of
the International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia, the Interna-
tional Criminal Tribunal for Rwanda, the International Tribunal for the Law
of the Sea, the Special Court for Sierra Leone, and the Extraordinary
Chambers in the Courts of Cambodia. I was also the Secretary-General’s
Representative at the Rome Conference in 1998, and was involved in the
initial stages of the establishment of the International Criminal Court. And,
of course, the International Court of Justice is one of the six main organs of
the United Nations. This means that I have interacted with international
judges in many contexts.
Of particular interest were the discussions with the judges who at-
tended the Brandeis Institutes for International Judges, to which I was in-
vited 35 and asked to deliver a keynote address in June 2002 as the United
Nations Legal Counsel. 36
On that occasion, I made two specific points that can be seen as re-
flecting the legacy of Dag Hammarskjöld. I first pointed out that interna-
tional judges must uphold standards which are set even higher than at the
national level. The reason is that international judges are operating under
the eyes of the whole world. The impression they give and the way in
which they perform their work will directly reflect on the standing of the
institution that they serve.
I then pointed to a classic dilemma at the international level: Quis
custodiet custodes? Who supervises the supervisors? This must always be
present in the minds of judges who serve at the international level. I said
that I could think of no higher calling for a lawyer than to serve as an inter-
national judge. But precisely because it is a high judicial office with limited
ways of establishing accountability, it must be assumed with a humble
mind. What is required is a deep insight that a competent, independent, and
impartial international judiciary is an indispensable element when we are
making our best efforts to establish the rule of law in international relations.
Against this background, it is clear that Dag Hammarskjöld’s analy-
sis of neutrality and integrity in his 1961 lecture is an important part of his
legacy with respect to international justice.
35
See Brandeis University’s web site.
36
Hans Corell, “Ethical Dimensions of International Jurisprudence and Adjudication”, Wal-
tham, Massachusetts, 10 June 2002 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/5eb7d4/).
37
Dag Hammarskjöld, Markings, Leif Sjöberg and W.H. Auden (trans.), Faber & Faber, Lon-
don, 1964, p. 7.
38
Bernhard Erling, A Reader’s Guide to Dag Hammarskjöld’s Waymarks, St. Peter, Minnesota,
1999 (updated Introduction in 2009).
39
Reference can also be made to Inge Lønning, “Politics, Morality and Religion – The Legacy
of Dag Hammarskjöld”, and Henning Melber, “Dag Hammarskjöld’s zeitgemäße Betrach-
tungen – Reflections on Inge Lønning’s Dag Hammarskjöld Lecture”, both in Henning Mel-
ber (ed.), The Ethics of Dag Hammarskjöld, Dag Hammarskjöld Foundation, Uppsala, 2010.
that those who serve in the field of international justice have unique obliga-
tions here.
When I first read the Waymarks, one of them caught my attention in
particular. In fact, it became a lodestar to me. (Among other things, I would
quote it when greeting new staff members welcome to the United Nations
Office of Legal Affairs.) This ‘waymark’ reads, in my own translation:
Openness to life grants a swift insight – like a flash of light-
ning – into the life situation of others. A must: to force the
problem from its emotional sting into a clearly conceived in-
tellectual form – and act accordingly. 40
This waymark reflects the fact that we are constantly exposed to var-
ious impressions depending on what we do, where we are, and the circum-
stances of the time. A common experience is hearing in the news and read-
ing in the papers about atrocities that human beings are exposed to, in par-
ticular in connection with armed conflicts. Most people react very strongly
against this, getting upset and condemning the actions by the perpetrators.
Lawyers are no different in this respect. We react in the same manner here
as other people do.
However, there is a tremendous difference if the lawyer all of a sud-
den finds him- or herself involved in a law enforcement process, dealing
with the criminal acts that caused the human suffering. Whether we act in
this context as an investigator, a prosecutor, a defence counsel or a judge,
we must be absolutely certain that we act in a professional manner as de-
scribed in the waymark. We have to force the problem we are confronted
with from its emotional sting into a clearly conceived intellectual form –
and act accordingly.
For me, this became clear already when I served as a law clerk and as
a young judge. A common experience is that one reads in the local press
about crimes committed and gets upset. However, in a matter of time, the
case will appear before the court where one serves, and then one has to act
in a professional manner. I would suggest that this is the typical situation at
the international level, in particular in international criminal courts. The
waymark should therefore serve as an important lodestar here.
Another waymark that caught my attention at an early stage was the
following in Sjöberg and Auden’s translation:
40
Dag Hammarskjöld, Vägmärken, Albert Bonniers Förlag, Stockholm, 1963, p. 16 (the pre-
sent author’s translation).
Never look down to test the ground before taking your next
step: only he who keeps his eye fixed on the far horizon will
find his right road. 41
This waymark came back to me when I observed the work of the
United Nations during my tenure as UN Legal Counsel. Of particular con-
cern to me was the fact that the Security Council often fails to fulfil its
foremost obligation laid down in Article 24 of the UN Charter: the primary
responsibility for the maintenance of international peace and security. The
waymark also tallies with my experiences serving as a sailor in the Swe-
dish merchant marine during 12 months across four summer holidays when
I was a student: the importance of looking to the horizon.
What all this boils down to is the need for statesmanship. What the
world needs is statesmanship – statesmen and -women who realize that we
need an international order based on the rule of law, and who can look to
the future with determination based on this conviction. They must look to
the horizon to understand that they must define the interests of their coun-
tries in a manner that protects the world population, and that international
co-operation must be based on international law.
A third waymark that caught my attention in later years is the follow-
ing, in my own translation:
You will never return.
Another man
will find another city. 42
The message here is true, in particular if one serves in an internation-
al organization. One is constantly confronted with new experiences and
impressions. This is of tremendous importance. In a sense, it is a learning
process that is of great value since it teaches one to view questions with
which one is confronted from different perspectives. It also broadens one’s
knowledge and may cause one to view one’s impressions from back home
in a new light.
Furthermore, the privilege of working with colleagues from other
countries is great. It also means that one should listen carefully to what the-
se colleagues say, not least if they express opinions that are different from
one’s own. In the final analysis, one must of course make one’s own deci-
sion with independence and integrity.
41
Hammarskjöld, 1964, p. 32, see above note 37.
42
Hammarskjöld, 1963, p. 147, see above note 40 (the present author’s translation).
Upon re-reading the book to see whether there were other compo-
nents that could be of interest to lawyers serving in the field of internation-
al justice, I came across the following short components, all in Sjöberg and
Auden’s translation:
Our secret creative will divines its counterpart in others, expe-
riencing its own universality, and this intuition builds a road
towards knowledge of the power which is itself a spark within
us. 43
*
Never, ‘for the sake of peace and quiet’, deny your own expe-
rience or convictions. 44
*
Your position never gives you the right to command. It only
imposes on you the duty of so living your life that others can
receive your orders without being humiliated. 45
*
The only kind of dignity which is genuine is that which is not
diminished by the indifference of others. 46
*
A task becomes a duty from the moment you suspect it to be
an essential part of that integrity which alone entitles a man to
assume responsibility. 47
*
Do what you can — and the task will rest lightly in your hand,
so lightly that you will be able to look forward to the more
difficult tests which may be awaiting you. 48
*
Twice now you have done him an injustice. In spite of the fact
that you were ‘right’ or, more correctly, because you were, in
43
Hammarskjöld, 1964, p. 37, see above note 37.
44
Ibid., p. 85.
45
Ibid., p. 96.
46
Ibid., p. 97.
47
Ibid., p. 100.
48
Ibid., p. 109.
your conceit and your stupid pride in your powers you went
stumping on over ground where each step gave him pain. 49
*
Be grateful as your deeds become less and less associated with
your name, as your feet ever more lightly tread the earth. 50
*
You have not done enough, you have never done enough, so
long as it is still possible that you have something of value to
contribute.
This is the answer when you are groaning under what
you consider a burden and an uncertainty prolonged ad infini-
tum. 51
*
Did’st Thou give me this inescapable loneliness so that it
would be easier for me to give Thee all? 52
I leave it to the reader to reflect on these quotes from Dag Hammar-
skjöld’s Waymarks. They should speak for themselves. The main thing is
that we realize that they were produced by an extraordinary personality
with great moral integrity who lost his life in the service of the United Na-
tions. The best way in which we can honour his memory – and also the
memories of others who have paid the ultimate sacrifice in the service of
the Organization – is to contribute to establishing the rule of law at the na-
tional and international levels.
5.5. Conclusion
From the foregoing, it should be clear that the Dag Hammarskjöld legacy is
of great importance when the integrity in international justice is defined.
Both his legal analysis and his Waymarks should serve as lodestars here.
Integrity in international justice is an important component in world gov-
ernance which is facing major challenges in today’s world. Much could be
said about these challenges: genocide, war crimes and crimes against hu-
manity; terrorism and transnational crimes; the need for strengthening hu-
man rights and gender equality; the need to address poverty and disease;
49
Ibid., p. 119.
50
Ibid., p. 126.
51
Ibid., p. 135.
52
Ibid., p. 139.
53
Transforming our world: the 2030 Agenda for Sustainable Development, 25 September 2015,
UN Doc. A/RES/70/1 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/d52143/).
54
Ibid., p. 25.
6.1. Introduction
The International Criminal Court (‘ICC’) has been facing a legitimacy cri-
sis for a long time. 1 Serious allegations of integrity lapses by the ICC’s first
prosecutor, Luis Moreno-Ocampo, 2 have been compounded by a growing
perception among the international criminal justice community, that the
court is missing in action – with judges more concerned about raising their
already plentiful, tax-free salaries in The Hague, than in fulfilling the
*
Juan Carlos Botero (LL.M., S.J.D.) is Associate Professor, Department of Philosophy and
History of Law, Pontificia Universidad Javeriana Law School.
1
The ICC’s legitimacy crisis has multiple dimensions. See, for example, Jessica Hatcher-
Moore, “Is the world’s highest court fit for purpose?”, The Guardian, 5 April 2017 (availa-
ble on its web site). See also James A. Goldston, “Don’t Give Up on the ICC”, in Foreign
Policy, 8 August 2019; Yvonne Dutton, “Bridging the Legitimacy Divide: The International
Criminal Court’s Domestic Perception Challenge”, in Columbia Journal of Transnational
Law, 2017, vol. 56, no. 70; Mandiaye Niang, “Africa and the Legitimacy of the ICC in
Question”, in International Criminal Law Review, 2017, vol. 17, no. 4, pp. 615–624; Cathe-
rine Gegout, “The International Criminal Court: limits, potential and conditions for the pro-
motion of justice and peace”, in Third World Quarterly, 2013, vol. 34, no. 5, pp. 800–818;
Margaret M. deGuzman, “The Global–Local Dilemma and the ICC’s Legitimacy”, in Nien-
ke Grossman, Harlan Cohen, Andreas Follesdal and Geir Ulfstein (eds.), Legitimacy and In-
ternational Courts, Cambridge University Press, 2018, pp. 62–82; Jeff Handmaker, “The
Legitimacy Crisis Within International Criminal Justice and the Importance of Critical, Re-
flexive Learning”, in Bob Jessop and Karim Knio (eds.), The Pedagogy of Economic, Politi-
cal and Social Crises: Dynamics, Construals and Lessons, Routledge, London, 2018,
pp. 189–206; Mihret Getabicha, “Decolonizing the International Criminal Court: Consider-
ing Questions of Bias in the Prosecution of African Leaders”, in Rapoport Center Working
Paper Series, 2018, no. 1; Mathew Lee, “Bolton: International Criminal Court ‘already dead
to us’”, AP News, 11 September 2018; Ramesh Thakur, “The end of the International Crimi-
nal Court?”, The Japan Times, 17 May 2019; Michèle Laborde-Barbanègre and Roxane
Cassehgari, “Reflections on ICC Jurisprudence Regarding the Democratic Republic of the
Congo”, in International Center for Transitional Justice Briefing, 1 September 2014.
2
See, for example, Morten Bergsmo, Wolfgang Kaleck, Sam Muller and William H. Wiley,
“A Prosecutor Falls, Time for the Court to Rise”, FICHL Policy Brief Series No. 86 (2017),
Torkel Opsahl Academic EPublisher, Brussels, 2017 (https://www.toaep.org/pbs-pdf/86-
four-directors/).
court’s high mission. 3 Other chapters in this volume 4 deal with the causes,
operational and legal mechanisms, and potential solutions to the integrity
issues currently facing the ICC. This chapter does not primarily concern
itself with these questions. Instead, it takes a broader perspective on integ-
rity in international criminal justice and considers it from the perspective of
large segments of the world’s population – particularly in the Global
South – whose perception of judicial integrity may diverge from the stand-
ard consensus among the world’s legal elites.
This chapter explores how the principles of integrity and independ-
ence relate to each other in international criminal justice, in the multicul-
tural world of the twenty-first century. In particular, it explores if ‘Western’
notions of integrity and independence that have characterized international
criminal justice since the Nuremberg trials – which emphasize punishment,
retributive justice, and deterrence, 5 as opposed to customary justice’s long-
3
See, for example, Goldston, 2019, see above note 1 (“it is disconcerting that one-third of the
court’s judges are suing for a pay raise plus pension increases and damages that could run
into the millions. Why, when the court has been underperforming and the budget is strained,
are its judges dedicating precious time and energy to increase their already generous com-
pensation—which at around $200,000 tax-free exceeds that of judges on many national
courts?”); Hatcher-Moore, 2017, see above note 1; Thakur, 2019, see above note 1. But see
Elian Peltier and Fatima Faizi, “I.C.C. Allows Afghanistan War Crimes Inquiry to Proceed,
Angering U.S.”, The New York Times, 5 March 2020 (available on its web site); Declan
Walsh and Abid Latif Dahir, “Sudan’s Ex-Ruler May Face War Crimes Trial, Official Says”,
The New York Times, 11 February 2020; and Marlise Simons, “Myanmar Genocide Lawsuit
Is Filed at United Nations Court”, The New York Times, 11 November 2019 (available on its
web site).
4
The conceptual framework for this project on integrity in international criminal justice, is
developed in Morten Bergsmo, “Revisiting Integrity in International Justice”, FICHL Policy
Brief Series No. 93 (2018), Torkel Opsahl Academic EPublisher, Brussels, 2018 (https://
www.toaep.org/pbs-pdf/93-bergsmo/).
5
See, for example, David Wippman, “Atrocities, Deterrence, and the Limits of International
Justice”, in Fordham International Law Journal, vol. 23, no. 2, 1999, p. 474 (“the connec-
tion between international prosecutions and the actual deterrence of future atrocities is at
best a plausible but largely untested assumption. Actual experience with efforts at deterrence
is not encouraging”); Juan Carlos Botero and Mateo Merchán, “Rethinking Peace and Jus-
tice: Lessons from the Colombian Transitional Justice Experience”, Justice in Conflict, 27
April 2020 (https://justiceinconflict.org/2020/04/27/rethinking-peace-and-justice-lessons-
from-the-colombian-transitional-justice-experience/). But see Jennifer Schense and Linda
Carter (eds.), Two Steps Forward, One Step Back: The Deterrent Effect of International
Criminal Tribunals, Torkel Opsahl Academic EPublisher, Brussels, 2017 (https://www.
toaep.org/nas-pdf/1-carter-schense). On empirical evidence of the effectiveness of punish-
ment and deterrence of criminal sanctions in domestic jurisdictions, see Anthony Bottoms
and Andrew von Hirsch, “The Crime-preventive impact of penal sanctions”, in Peter Cane
and Herbert Kritzner (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Empirical Legal Research, Oxford
University Press, Oxford, 2010.
6
The notion of ‘community-harmonizing justice’ is described in Juan Carlos Botero, The
Three Faces of Justice: Legal Traditions, Legal Transplants and Customary Justice in a
Multicultural World, in SSRN Electronic Journal, 2013, on which this chapter draws. Ac-
cording to Zehr and Gohar,
[b]oth retributive and restorative theories of justice acknowledge a basic moral intuition
that a balance has been thrown off by the wrongdoing. Consequently, the victim de-
serves something and the offender owes something. Both approaches argue that there
must be a proportional relationship between the act and the response. They differ, how-
ever, on the currency that will fulfill the obligations and right the balance. Retributive
theory believes that pain will vindicate, but in practice that is often counterproductive
for both victim and offender. Restorative justice theory, on the other hand, argues that
what truly vindicates is acknowledgment of victims’ harms and needs combined with an
active effort to encourage offenders to take responsibility, make right the wrongs and
address the causes of their behavior. By addressing this need for vindication in a positive
way, restorative justice has the potential to affirm both victim and offender and help
them transform their lives.
Howard Zehr and Ali Gohar, The Little Book of Restorative Justice, Good Books, Inter-
course, PA, p. 59.
7
United Nations General Assembly (‘UNGA’), Basic Principles on the Independence of the
Judiciary, UN Doc. A/RES/40/146, 13 December 1985 (‘Basic Principles on the Independ-
ence of the Judiciary’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/rnabsy/).
8
United Nations Office on Drugs and Crime (‘UNODC’), The Bangalore Principles of Judi-
cial Conduct, 26 November 2012 (‘Bangalore Principles’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/
xwake8/).
9
Another authoritative standard is the notion of ‘high moral character’ in international crimi-
nal justice, which is explained in Morten Bergsmo’s concept paper for this research project,
see note 4 above. See also Chapter 18 by Bettina Spilker.
10
UNODC, Commentary on the Bangalore Principles of Judicial Conduct, 2007, pp. 1–6.
11
Ibid., pp. 5–6 (emphasis added).
less of legal tradition, and how this global perspective may influence the
way we see international criminal justice in the multicultural world of the
twenty-first century. Some tentative implications for the ICC and other in-
ternational courts and tribunals, of adopting a broader perspective of judi-
cial integrity and independence in international criminal justice, are sug-
gested at the end.
At a time when the ICC and the principles for which this institution
stands are under attack from so many fronts, 12 supporters of the principles
of international criminal justice should explore whether the legal profes-
sion’s narrow conceptions of judicial integrity and independence may be
undermining the Court’s legitimacy among the broader public in develop-
ing countries. But please do not misinterpret my words: I do not suggest
that the Rome Statute 13 needs to be amended, which would be impossible
in today’s highly polarized geo-political environment. I am only wondering
whether various ICC constituencies, particularly the Prosecutor, Judges,
and the Assembly of States Parties, might need to read the Statute in a dif-
ferent light – lessening the emphasis on legal process, punishment, retribu-
tive justice, and deterrence, while giving proper attention to customary jus-
tice’s long-established emphasis on restorative justice and community har-
mony or unity. 14 Three key findings of the International Nuremberg Princi-
12
For example, Lee, 2018, see above note 1; Hatcher-Moore, 2017, see above note 1; Thakur,
2019, see above note 1. Cf., Goldston, 2019, see above note 1.
13
Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court, 17 July 1998 (http://www.legal-tools.org/
doc/e5faa8/).
14
One of the main lessons from international criminal justice experiences over the past 75
years since the Nuremberg trials, is that its understanding of ‘justice’ mainly as retributive
justice, is not shared by large segments of the world’s population. For a comprehensive re-
view of the limits of retributive justice and its negative impact on global acceptance of in-
ternational criminal justice principles in developing countries, see Friederike Mieth, “Ac-
ceptance of International Criminal Justice A Review”, in Susanne Buckley-Zistel, Friederike
Mieth and Marjana Papa (eds.), After Nuremberg: Exploring Multiple Dimensions of the Ac-
ceptance of International Criminal Justice, International Nuremberg Principles Academy,
Nuremberg, 2016. Throughout this chapter, I refer mostly to ‘formal courts’ and ‘customary
justice’ as the two main mechanisms of justice in low and middle-income countries. The dif-
ference between them is sometimes blurred, as in some countries both systems are integrated
(see Botero, 2013, pt. 4, chap. 6, above note 6). I use the term ‘formal court’ to include the
civil and criminal court system inherited from Europe throughout the world, as well as any
other formal, State-governed dispute resolution institution. The term ‘customary justice’ is
employed here to include traditional justice, indigenous and ethnic dispute resolution, com-
munity-based dispute resolution, and in some cases also religious courts. The dividing line is
often blurred, as it is explained in pts. 3 and 4 of Botero, 2013, see above note 6. A major
limitation of this chapter is that Islamic law and courts are mostly outside of its scope. I
acknowledge that many of the same questions that arise out of the interplay among legal tra-
ditions, legal transplants and customary justice institutions in Africa, Asia and Latin America,
also apply to the interaction between Western and Islamic laws, procedures and courts, in
both Muslim majority and Muslim minority countries. Nonetheless, Sharia’s complexity and
sophistication – as explained in the chapter above by Judge Adel Maged – sets it apart from
other dispute resolution systems existing in the world today. Addressing these questions
properly would require an effort which is currently beyond my limited knowledge of various
Islamic legal traditions.
15
Susanne Buckley-Zistel, Friederike Mieth and Marjana Papa, “Acceptance of International
Criminal Justice in Situation Countries. 10 Key Findings”, International Nuremberg Princi-
ples Academy, Nuremberg, 2017 (available on its web site).
16
Ibid (emphasis added).
17
Botero, 2013, at pt. 4, chap. 7, see above note 6.
18
Botero, 2013, p. 3, see above note 6. The ‘African Tree’ justice is essentially a conversation,
which may last for a few minutes or several months. It is a dialogue between the contending
parties and the chief or mediator, whose overall objective is not only (or even mainly) to re-
solve a specific dispute among two parties – as it is among the ‘conflict-solving’ understand-
ing of justice – but more broadly to harmonize the broken bonds within the community. In
some instances, the whole village gets involved in the healing process. The African Tree no-
tion of justice is not exclusive of the African continent. Dispute resolution among indige-
nous communities in other latitudes show similar characteristics. The community-
harmonizing justice of the African Tree is explained in detail in pts. 4 and 5 of Botero, 2013,
see above note 6. I am grateful to Hassan Bubacar Jallow and Murtaza Jaffar, from the In-
ternational Criminal Tribunal for Rwanda, for insightful comments about the nature of dis-
pute resolution in Sub-Saharan Africa.
19
Mieth, 2016, p. 7, see above note 14.
20
UNODC, 2007, pp. 1–6, see above note 10.
21
Basic Principles on the Independence of the Judiciary, see above note 7.
22
Bangalore Principles, see above note 8.
partially true, 23 and it undermines the ICC’s legitimacy among the broader
public in the Global South. 24
From the perspective of large segments of the population in develop-
ing countries today, the ICC’s vision of justice – with its ‘Western’ empha-
sis on legal procedure, punishment, retribution, and deterrence – represent
the law of the European colonizers. 25 In contrast, restorative justice princi-
ples embedded in ancestral customary justice mechanisms in the four cor-
ners of the world, represent a more legitimate way to deal with conflict,
including grave crimes. 26 The ICC’s survival depends on its legitimacy, and
its legitimacy partly depends on its broader appeal to the public in develop-
23
Participation of legal elites from a large number of countries in the drafting of these interna-
tional instruments, confer global legitimacy to these documents among the legal elites of vir-
tually all countries in the world, whose laws are based on the European civil law and com-
mon law traditions. However, this fact does not automatically confer legitimacy of the same
documents across the wider population in the Global South. The low legitimacy of ‘Western’
institutions of justice among broad segments of the population in developing countries has
been extensively documented in the literature throughout Latin America, Sub-Saharan Afri-
ca, and Asia. See, for example, Julio Faundez, “Access to Justice and Indigenous Communi-
ties in Latin America”, in Yash Ghai and Jill Cottrell (eds.), Marginalized Communities and
Access to Justice, Routledge, New York, 2010, p. 83, (“the indigenous communities’ views
about legal institutions bear little resemblance to liberal views about law. Instead of seeing
them as friendly institutions that empower and liberate individuals, they regard them as the
cause and symbol of their longstanding economic and political oppression”); also pp. 93–94.
Hannah Irfan, Honor Related Violence Against Women in Pakistan, American Bar Associa-
tion, 2008, p. 19 (in Pakistan “one of the major reasons that women victims are reluctant to
take action against violence through the courts is that they fear the system of which they have
no knowledge. The inadequacy of knowledge and information about the legal processes
made the thought of even going to court frightening”); Deborah H. Isser, Stephen C. Lub-
kemann, and Saah N’Tow, Looking for Justice, Liberian experiences with and perceptions of
local justice options, United States Institute of Peace, Washington, DC, 2009, p. 3 (“Most
Liberians would still be unsatisfied with the justice meted out by the formal system, even if
it were able to deliver on the basics”).
24
The legitimacy crisis of the ICC among the broad public in developing countries is com-
pounded by a variety of factors, including the court’s many structural and operational limita-
tions, see above note 1.
25
Faundez, 2010, see above note 23; Irfan, 2008, see above note 23; Stuart Banner, How the
Indians Lost Their Lands, Harvard University Press, 2007; Lidsay Robertson, Conquest by
Law, at Preface, Oxford University Press, 2005; N. Bruce Duthu, American Indians and the
Law, Penguin, New York, 2008; Stephen Breyer, “'For Their Own Good”: The Cherokees,
the Supreme Court, and the Early History of American Conscience”, The New Republic, 4
December 2008.
26
A comprehensive review of alternative mechanisms available to deal with mass atrocities, is
available at Open Society Justice Initiative, Options for Justice: A Handbook for Designing
Accountability Mechanisms for Grave Crimes, Open Society Foundations, 2018.
27
See generally, for example, Hans Kelsen, What is Justice?, University of California Press,
Berkeley, 1957.
28
See generally, for example, Alan Watson, Legal Transplants: An Approach to Comparative
Law, University of Virginia Press, Charlottesville, 1974; Michele Graziadei, “Comparative
Law as the Study of Transplants and Receptions”, in Mathias Reimann and Reinhard Zim-
mermann (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Comparative Law, Oxford University Press, 2006.
29
See, for example, Rene David and John Brierley, Major Legal Systems in the World Today:
An introduction to the Comparative study of Law, The Free Press, New York, 1978; John
Dawson, The Oracles of the Law, William S. Hein, New York; Rudolph Schlesinger, Ugo
Mattei, Teemu Ruskola and Antonio Gidi, Comparative Law, Case- Text- Materials, The
Foundation Press, New York, 1988; Konrad Zweigert and Hein Kotz, Introduction to Com-
parative Law (vol. I – The Framework/vol. II – The Institutions of Private Law), Clarendon
Press, Oxford, 1987; John Henry Merryman, The Civil Law Tradition. An Introduction to the
Legal Systems of Western Europe and Latin America, Stanford University Press, California,
1985.
30
Merryman, 1985, p. 2, see above note 29 (emphasis added).
31
Ibid., p. 1: “There are three highly influential legal traditions in the contemporary world:
civil law, common-law, and socialist law”. With the fall of the Soviet Union, the third one
lost significance. On Islamic law, see above note 24.
32
“It is no exaggeration to say that, next to the Bible, no book has left a deeper mark upon the
history of mankind than the Corpus Iuris Civilis”, Justinian, “General Introduction”, in The
Digest of Roman Law, Penguin Classics, reprint edition, 1979, p. 8.
33
See generally, for example, William Sidney Gibson, On some Ancient Modes of Trial, espe-
cially the Ordeals of Water, Fire and other Judicia Dei: Communicated to the Society of An-
tiquaries., Nichols & Son, London, 1848.
common law was created by English royal courts and evolved gradually
until present times. 34
Through the process of European conquest and colonization, these
‘Western’ legal traditions were imposed by might of the sword on virtually
all peoples of the world. When European colonization ended in the nine-
teenth and twentieth centuries, ‘Western’ legal traditions were maintained
in all countries by local legal elites. Yet, vast segments of the population in
developing countries continued to perceive these ‘Western’ laws and pro-
cedures with contempt. The ‘original sin’ of violent conquest and coloniza-
tion, which underlies the ‘Western’ institutions of Justice, continues to un-
dermine the ICC’s legitimacy in the Global South today. 35
6.3. Judicial Integrity and Independence in the ‘Western’ Legal
Tradition in Historical Perspective
What are the implications of the historical evolution of justice in England
and continental Europe for current notions of judicial integrity and impar-
tiality? Renowned comparativists – Caenegem, Damaška, David, Dawson,
Glendon, Merryman, Schlesinger, Zweigert and Kotz – differ on a number
of issues related to the divide between civil law and common law, but they
all tend to agree on the fact that specific historical developments led to a
rather distinct view of the role of the judge in society. 36
34
Although some Roman elements continued to influence procedure well into the nineteenth
century. For example, R.C. van Caenegem, “History of European Civil Procedure”, in Mau-
ro Cappelletti (ed.), International Encyclopedia of Comparative Law: Volume XVI, Civil
Procedure, 1982, p. 15. See also, Mary Ann Glendon, Michael Gordon and Christopher
Osakwe, Comparative Legal Traditions, West Publishing, St. Paul, 1994; R.C. van Cae-
negem, European Law in the Past and the Future: Unity and Diversity over Two Millennia,
Cambridge University Press, 2002.
35
The legitimacy gap of ‘Western’ justice institutions between legal elites and the broad public
in developing countries, is not only documented in the literature (see, for example, above
note 23), but it is also supported by the author’s personal experience measuring people’s ex-
periences and perceptions of justice in over one hundred countries over the past two decades,
including hundreds of thousands of household surveys in over 300 cities around the world,
and hundreds of conversations and interviews with formal and customary justice authorities
from dozens of countries throughout Latin America, Sub-Saharan Africa and Asia. Botero,
2013, see above note 6. On the legitimacy crisis of the International Criminal Court, see
above note 1.
36
Juan Carlos Botero, “The delivery of justice in middle-income countries”, in Randall
Peerenboom and Tom Ginsburg (eds.), Law and Development of Middle-Income Countries,
Cambridge University Press, 2014, p. 196.
37
Carl Goodman, The Rule of Law in Japan, Kluwer Law International, the Netherlands, 2008,
p. 9.
38
See, for example, Benjamin Kaplan, “Civil Procedure—Reflections on the Comparison of
Systems”, in Buffalo Law Review, 1960, p. 431 (US system “exploits the free-wheeling en-
ergies of counsel and places them in adversary confrontation before a detached judge”;
“German system puts its trust in a judge of paternalistic bent acting in cooperation with
counsel of somewhat muted adversary zeal”).
39
Goodman, 2008, p. 504, see above note 37.
40
Mirjan Damaška, The Faces of Justice and State Authority. A Comparative Approach to the
Legal Process, Yale University Press, New Haven, 1986.
41
See generally, Caenegem, 2002, see above note 34; Caenegem, 1982, see above note 34;
Damaška, 1986, see above note 40.
42
Montesquieu, The Spirit of Laws, 1748 (“But as we have already observed, the national
judges are no more than the mouth that pronounces the words of the law, mere passive be-
ings, incapable of moderating either its force or rigor”).
thereof. Thus, a judge with integrity is a judge that follows the law. In this
context, judicial integrity means the strict application of the law.
Do these notions of judicial integrity correspond to the currently pre-
vailing notion of justice outside of the metropolis (Europe and North Amer-
ica)? For historical reasons, ‘Western’ adjudication has placed particular
emphasis on two relations: a dispute between two individuals (as in thir-
teenth century England), and the relationship between one individual and
the State (as in Imperial Rome or the Kingdom of France). In contrast, cus-
tomary justice throughout the Global South focuses on the multiple rela-
tions that are co-existing and evolving over time within a specific commu-
nity over time.
6.4. The Bangalore Principles of Judicial Conduct: A ‘Universal’
Understanding of Integrity and Independence in Justice
In July 2006, the UN Economic and Social Council adopted a resolution
that “[e]mphasizes that the Bangalore Principles of Judicial Conduct repre-
sent a further development and are complementary to the Basic Principles
on the Independence of the Judiciary, endorsed by UNGA in its resolutions
40/32 and 40/146”. 43 Taken together, these two documents – the UNGA’s
Basic Principles 44 and the Bangalore Principles of 2001, as revised in
2002 45 – represent two of the most authoritative international standards on
the notions of integrity and independence of justice available today.
The Bangalore Principles recognize integrity and independence of
justice as follows:
Value 1. Independence.
Principle: Judicial independence is a prerequisite to the rule of
law and a fundamental guarantee of a fair trial. A judge shall
therefore uphold and exemplify judicial independence in both
its individual and institutional aspects.
Application:
1.1. A judge shall exercise the judicial function independently
on the basis of the judge’s assessment of the facts and in
accordance with a conscientious understanding of the law,
43
United Nations Economic and Social Council, Strengthening basic principles of judicial
conduct, 27 July 2006, ECOSOC 2006/23 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/yiyqyy/).
44
Basic Principles on the Independence of the Judiciary, see above note 7.
45
The Bangalore Principles, see above note 8.
Value 3. Integrity.
Principle: Integrity is essential to the proper discharge of the
judicial office.
Application:
3.1. A judge shall ensure that his or her conduct is above re-
proach in the view of a reasonable observer.
3.2. The behaviour and conduct of a judge must reaffirm the
people’s faith in the integrity of the judiciary. Justice
must not merely be done but must also be seen to be
done.
The Bangalore Principles also recognize three closely related con-
cepts, impartiality, propriety and equality, as essential values that define the
conduct of judicial officers under international standards. These principles
are as follows:
Value 2: IMPARTIALITY.
Value 4: PROPRIETY.
Principle: Propriety, and the appearance of propriety, are es-
sential to the performance of all of the activities of a judge.
Value 5: EQUALITY.
Principle: Ensuring equality of treatment to all before the
courts is essential to the due performance of the judicial office.
Finally, the Bangalore Principles of Judicial Conduct recognize a
sixth value, competence and diligence, as follows:
Value 6: COMPETENCE AND DILIGENCE.
Principle: Competence and diligence are prerequisites to the
due performance of judicial office.
A central question of this chapter, as stated in the introduction, is
whether the Bangalore Principles command truly “universal acceptance”,
and whether they indeed “give expression to the highest traditions relating
to the judicial function as visualized in all cultures and legal systems” and
“all the great religious systems of the world”.
The detailed account of the process of creation of these principles, 46
suggests a bias in favour of the principles of judicial integrity and inde-
pendence of the common law tradition, by virtue of the overwhelmingly
majoritarian membership of judges from this tradition in the drafting group,
and the predominantly common law nature of the national codes used as
reference material in the drafting process. 47 As stated above, this common
law emphasis implies an understanding of judicial integrity primarily as a
function of judicial impartiality.
It is also clear that the drafting group made great efforts in 2002 to
socialize and integrate principles pertaining to the civil law tradition into
these ‘universal’ standards. 48 Thus, the civil law’s flavour of judicial integ-
46
UNODC, 2007, pp. 1–6, see above note 10.
47
Ibid., A detailed list of National Codes that were consulted is included in the Commentary.
48
There was significant agreement among the common and civil law judges who participated
in the meeting concerning core values, and some disagreement on the scheme and order in
which these values ought to be placed. For instance: “[…] (c) The statement in the preamble
of the Bangalore Draft that the “real source of judicial power is public acceptance of the
moral authority and integrity of the judiciary” was questioned. It was argued that the “real
source” was the Constitution and that placing too great an emphasis on the ultimate depend-
ence of the judicial power upon general acceptance could, in some circumstances, be dan-
gerous”. UNODC, 2007, pp. 6–10, see above note 10.
49
Huntington – whose work has spurred controversy – describes these differences between
two cultures (China and the USA), as follows:
At the broadest level the Confucian ethos pervading many Asian societies stressed the
values of authority, hierarchy, the subordination of individual rights and interests, the
importance of consensus, the avoidance of confrontation, ‘saving face,’ and, in general,
the supremacy of the state over society and of society over the individual. In addition,
Asians tended to think of the evolution of their societies in terms of centuries and mil-
lennia and to give priority to maximizing long-term gains. These attitudes contrasted
with the primacy in American beliefs of liberty, equality, democracy, and individualism,
and the American propensity to distrust government, oppose authority, promote checks
and balances, encourage competition, sanctify human rights, and to forget the past, ig-
nore the future, and focus on maximizing immediate gains. The sources of conflict are in
fundamental differences in society and culture.
Samuel P. Huntington, The Clash of Civilizations and the Remaking of the World Order,
Simon & Schuster, 1996, p. 225.
50
Botero, 2014, p. 196, see above note 36.
51
“In the United States and England […] there was a different kind of judicial tradition, one in
which judges had often been a progressive force on the side of the individual against the
abuse of power by the ruler”, see Merryman, 1985, p. 16, see above note 29. In contrast, in
colonies throughout the world “the indigenous communities’ views about legal institutions
bear little resemblance to liberal views about law. Instead of seeing them as friendly institu-
tions that empower and liberate individuals, they regard them as the cause and symbol of
their longstanding economic and political oppression”, see Faundez, 2010, pp. 83, 93-94, see
above note 23.
52
Botero, 2014, p. 196, see above note 36.
53
“Shamans’ newfound popularity in South Korea”, BBC News, 29 July 2012 (available on its
web site).
54
See, for example, Simon Kuper, “The revenge of the middle-class anti-elitist: Why the com-
fortably well-off voted for Trump, Brexit and Italy’s Lega”, Financial Times Magazine, 13
February 2020 (available on its web site).
55
Botero, 2014, p. 196, see above note 36.
56
See, for example, Banner, 2007, p. 1, see above note 25 (“The Indians were really conquered
by force […], but Americans and their British colonial predecessors papered over their con-
quest with these documents [treaties] to make the process look proper and legal”); Robert-
son, 2005, at Preface, p. IX, see above note 25 (“Over a succession of generations, Europe-
ans devised rules intended to justify the dispossession and subjugation of the native peoples
of the Western Hemisphere”); Duthu, 2008, p. xxii, see above note 25 (“on June 9, 1855,
Kamiakin rose last among his fellow tribal leaders, made his mark on the treaty and returned
to his seat with his lips ‘covered with blood, having bitten them with suppressed rage’”);
Breyer, 2000, p. 30, see above note 25 (“In 1836, the United States and the State of Georgia
forced the Cherokee Indian tribe to leave its home in Georgia and to move to the West. The
Tribe did not want to move. It believed it had a legal right to stay […] [The outcome of this
engagement is a] tragic story in the history of the Cherokee Tribe”).
57
Faundez, 2010, see above note 23.
58
Irfan, 2008, p. 19, see above note 23 (emphasis added).
59
French, Spanish and Portuguese descendants, Encyclopaedia Britannica on-line. “Creole,
Spanish Criollo, French Créole, originally, any person of European (mostly French or Span-
ish) or African descent born in the West Indies or parts of French or Spanish America (and
thus naturalized in those regions rather than in the parents’ home country)”.
60
Merryman, 1985, p. 2, see above note 29 (emphasis added).
61
Botero, 2014, see above note 36.
64
Mieth, 2017, p. 4, see above note 14 (citations omitted). Similarly, according to Laborde-
Barbanègre and Cassehgari, 2014, see above note 1, the ICC’s
results could be interpreted as disappointing when compared with the amount of re-
sources invested in the process. In particular, the proceedings were slow, complicated,
and expensive, and the court’s operations attracted serious criticism. For Congolese civil
society, the picture is more mixed or even negative. The main criticism of the court per-
tains to the prosecutorial and investigative strategy of the Office of the Prosecutor. One
of the primary criticisms of the ICC’s investigations in the DRC cases is that they lack
representativeness, reflecting only part of the conflict, in terms of both affected victims
and temporal scope.
65
The level of people’s satisfaction/legitimacy of civil and criminal justice institutions has
been measured by the World Justice Project through surveys conducted among a random
sample of 1,000 households per country, in over 100 countries. See, for example, “WJP Rule
of Law Index 2017-2018”, World Justice Project (available on its web site). The author led
the team that developed and deployed these surveys around the world for ten years.
66
Mieth, 2017, p. 8, see above note 14 (citations omitted).
67
Tilmann J. Röder, “Informal Justice Systems: Challenges and Perspectives”, in Juan Carlos
Botero, Ronald Janse, Sam Muller and Christine Pratt (eds.), Innovations in Rule of Law,
HiiL and The World Justice Project, Washington, DC, 2012, pp. 58–61 (emphasis added).
68
Rehman, I.A. Dark Justice, News Line, August 2002. Irfan, 2008, p. 24, see above note 23.
69
Ali Wardak, “Building a post-war justice system in Afghanistan”, in Crime, Law and Social
Change, Kluwer Academic Publishers, Netherlands, 2004, vol. 41, p. 319–341.
70
See, for example, Isser et al., 2009, see above note 23.
71
For example, Law and Justice in Timor-Leste: A Survey of Citizen Awareness and Attitudes
Regarding Law and Justice, USAID and Asia Foundation, 2008, p. 33; Informal Justice Sys-
tems, Charting a Course for Human Rights-Based Engagement, UN Women, the United Na-
tions Children’s Fund (‘UNICEF’) and United Nations Development Programme (‘UNDP’),
United Nations, New York, 2012, p. 321; Isser et al., 2009, see above note 23; World Justice
Project’s surveys in over 100 countries, described in Juan Botero and Alejandro Ponce,
Measuring the Rule of Law, The World Justice Project, 2011.
72
UN Women, UNICEF and UNDP, 2012, p. 321, see above note 71.
For most people around the world, the notion of ‘customary justice’
is more readily identified with the notion of the ‘African Tree’ – the friend-
ly meeting place where the community comes together to amend the bro-
ken bonds. 73 Skelton presents the South African variant of this notion as
follows:
The ‘African philosophy’ […] is known as ubuntu. It has been
described as an African worldview, which is both a guide for
social conduct as well as a philosophy of life. Archbishop
Desmond Tutu explains in his book about the TRC [Truth and
Reconciliation Commission] that during the negotiation pro-
cess, a decision had to be made about what form the commis-
sion to deal with South Africa’s past should take. The two
possibilities of the Nuremberg-type trials or an unconditional
amnesty process were overtaken by a third approach of condi-
tional amnesty, and that this approach was consistent with
Ubuntu. He explains further:
Ubuntu is very difficult to render into a Western
language. It speaks of the very essence of being
human. When we want to give high praise to some-
one we say ‘yu, u nobuntu’ (hey, he or she has ub-
untu). This means they are generous, hospitable,
friendly, caring and compassionate. They share what
they have. It also means my humanity is caught up,
is inextricably bound up, in theirs. We belong to a
bundle of life. We say, ‘a person is a person thought
other people’.
He goes on to clarify how ubuntu is linked to the idea of
forgiveness. He asserts that to forgive is not just to be altruis-
tic, it is the best form of self-interest because forgiveness
gives people resilience, enabling them to survive and emerge
still human despite all efforts to dehumanize them. He con-
cludes that even the supporters of apartheid were victims of
the vicious system which they implemented, because within
the context of ubuntu, our humanity is intertwined.
The concept of ubuntu has underpinned societal harmony
in Africa for many years, and guided traditional conflict reso-
lution. Traditional mechanisms to deal with problems arising
in communities have been effective structures for upholding
African customary law. It has been said that ‘reconciliation,
73
The notion of justice as the ‘African Tree’ is introduced at above note 18.
74
Ann Skelton, “Restorative Justice as a Framework for Juvenile Justice Reform: A South
African Perspective”, in British Journal of Criminology, 2002, vol. 42, no. 3, pp. 496, 498-
499 (emphasis added) (citations omitted).
75
Botero, 2013, see above note 6.
76
Mieth, 2017, p. 7, see above note 14 (citations omitted).
77
Botero, 2013, at Part IV, see above note 6.
78
Lars Waldorf, “Rwanda’s Failing Experiment in Restorative Justice”, in Carolyn Hoyle,
Restorative Justice: Critical Concepts in Criminology, Routledge, 2008, vol. 2, pp. 364–381.
79
“The Virtues of Tunnel Vision. The pure conflict-solving process demands more from the
decision maker than neutrality as between the parties; he must also be blind to any consider-
ations that transcend the resolution of the dispute before him”, see Damaška, 1986, p. 140,
see above note 40.
80
“The Ideal of Tabula Rasa. If in the conflict-solving process the decision is to emerge from
the dialectic of party debate, ideally the decision maker must enter the case unprepared, un-
aware of all matters specifically related to the issue. He should have a ‘virgin mind,’ to be
boxed’ within the legal process of the common law about seven hundred
years ago. 81 As it was explained above, these principles are by essence in-
compatible with the ‘African Tree’, which is the prevailing notion of Jus-
tice among vast segments of the population today, not only in Africa but
also in Asia and Latin America.
The Rome Statute is, by essence, incompatible with basic customary
justice tenets around the world. For instance, the personal, intimate relation
existing between the Mamo and each member of the community among the
Kogi people of Colombia – which constitutes the essence of the Kogi sys-
tem of fact-finding and adjudication – would not only be inappropriate, but
also highly indicative of bias under the lens of UNODC’s Commentary on
the Bangalore Principles of Judicial Conduct. 82 According to these princi-
ples:
90. Depending on the circumstances, a reasonable apprehen-
sion of bias might be thought to arise in the following cases:
[…] (b) If the judge is closely acquainted with any member of
the public involved in the case, particularly if that person’s
credibility may be significant in the outcome of the case;
111. Propriety and the appearance of propriety, both profes-
sional and personal, are essential elements of a judge’s life.
What matters is more not what a judge does or does not do,
but what others think the judge has done or might do. For ex-
ample, a judge who speaks privately and at length with a liti-
gant in a pending case will appear to be giving that party an
advantage, even if in fact the conversation is completely unre-
lated to the case. Since the public expects a high standard of
conduct from a judge, he or she must, when in doubt about at-
tending an event or receiving a gift, however small, ask the
question, “How might this look in the eyes of the public?” 83
In other words, when ‘Western’ notions of judicial integrity and in-
dependence – which emphasize legal process, punishment, retributive jus-
tice, and deterrence – demand a distant (blindfolded) judge, customary jus-
tice’s long-established emphasis on restorative justice and community har-
tutored only through the bilateral process of evidentiary presentation and argument.” Ibid.,
p. 138.
81
A detailed explanation of the notion of ‘black boxing’ of legal principles in the civil law and
common law traditions, is provided in Botero, 2013, pt. 5, chap. 3, see above note 6.
82
UNODC, 2007, see above note 10.
83
UNODC, 2007, pp. 57 and 69, see above note 10 (emphasis added).
84
“The law of Rome stood for reason, organization, and administrative efficiency under cen-
tral control. Embodied in the superb bodies of the Corpus Juris Civilis, it was rediscovered
and studied as a revelation, the lawyer’s ultima ratio”, see Caenegem, 1982, p. 11, see above
note 34.
85
“The last-mentioned method of ordeal, viz. that by cold water, was resorted to in England
for the detection of witches, until the beginning of the last [eighteenth] century”, see Gibson,
1848, p. 15, see above note 29.
86
See above note 18.
tice of the ‘Western’ legal tradition (which was embraced by legal elites in
the Global South), a mandatory requirement under the Rome Statute?
According to Article 36(3)(a) of the ICC Statute,
3. (a) The judges shall be chosen from among persons of high
moral character, impartiality and integrity who possess the
qualifications required in their respective States for appoint-
ment to the highest judicial offices.
And pursuant to Article 42(3) of the same statute:
The Prosecutor and the Deputy Prosecutors shall be persons of
high moral character, be highly competent in and have exten-
sive practical experience in the prosecution or trial of criminal
cases. They shall have an excellent knowledge of and be flu-
ent in at least one of the working languages of the Court.
Again, when ‘Western’ notions of judicial integrity and independence
demand a distant (blindfolded) judge, customary justice’s long-established
emphasis on restorative justice and community harmony require the exact
opposite – a deeply-rooted elder, a wise member of the community, who
must have intimate knowledge of the parties involved in the dispute. Un-
less ICC constituencies are able to reinterpret these standards under a
community-harmonizing Justice perspective, the ICC legitimacy crisis in
the Global South will not be remedied.
Nothing in the Rome Statute prevents the Office of the Prosecutor
(‘OTP’) to approach cases from the ground-up, in close contact with the
community, and from the perspective of the community. Nothing in the
Rome Statute prevents ICC judges to pay a bit less attention to the global
human rights movement (which played an invaluable role in the creation of
the ICC and have sustained it for two decades) and sharpen their ears to the
justice needs and aspirations of the community. Do Rohingyas, the Ken-
yans and the rural Colombians who face violations have the same justice
needs and aspirations? If the ICC only acts from The Hague, from the per-
spective of The Hague, and is ultimately unaccountable to the particular
community that was affected by grave crimes, the ICC will never achieve
truly universal acceptance. While this distance is in part a problem caused
by lack of resources, it is also a problem of perspective. 87
87
“[D]elays are a product of scarce investigative resources, a lack of state cooperation, and
other factors. But with limited communication and outreach, victims and members of affect-
ed communities have been left wondering what, if anything, the court is doing”, see Gold-
ston, 2019, see above note 1.
While the global criminal court has an important role to play as court
of last resort for mass atrocities, it cannot behave as the continuation of the
old judicial institutions of the European colonizers, as it is currently per-
ceived by vast segments of the population in the Global South.
6.9. Is There a Truly Universal Understanding of Judicial Integrity
and Independence?
This chapter’s second research question was whether a truly multicultural
understanding of integrity and independence in international criminal jus-
tice (not the specific standards of the ICC or other tribunals), implies a
move towards ‘relativizing’ these standards.
At a basic level, this research shows that adopting a broader cultural
perspective that goes beyond the narrow standpoint of the world’s legal
elites, necessarily implies a move towards relativizing the aforementioned
global standards of judicial integrity and independence. Indeed, if the no-
tions of judicial integrity and independence underlying the views on justice
and due process prevailing among the Navajo Nation in North America, 88
the Kogi community in Colombia, 89 or the Liberian chiefs, 90 are examined
under the light of the UN-sponsored standards of judicial integrity and in-
dependence, it becomes apparent that the meaning of ‘justice’ and ‘due
process’ among these communities does not match that of the civil law and
the common law traditions (that is, the ‘Western’ legal tradition), which un-
derlie the Bangalore Principles of Judicial Conduct. 91
Yet, at a higher level of abstraction, it is also argued that the core
components of integrity and independence transcend all legal traditions.
From time immemorial, dispute resolution systems were (at least in theory)
created to provide equal justice among unequal parties, that is, to protect
the weak – the strong did not need protection. This ideal is present in all
legal traditions of the world:
[I was called] to bring about the rule of righteousness in the
land […] so that the strong should not harm the weak.
Prologue, Hammurabi’s Code, 1772 BCE
88
See, for example, Paul Spruhan, “The Meaning of Due Process in the Navajo Nation”, in
The Indian Civil Rights Act at Forty, UCLA American Indian Studies Center Publications,
2012.
89
Botero, 2013, at pt. 4, chap. 5, see above note 6.
90
Ibid., at pt. 4, chap. 4.
91
The Bangalore Principles, see above note 8.
Treat the people equally in your court and give them equal at-
tention, so that the noble shall not aspire to your partiality, nor
the humble despair of your justice.
Judicial Guidelines from ‘Umar Bin Al-Khattab,
the Second Khalif of Islam, 634-644 CE
From time immemorial, the litmus test of a judge’s integrity is
whether he or she actually protected the weak, when he or she was called
upon to do so. Of course, holding the ‘strong’ accountable for violations, is
one way to protect the ‘weak’. A more culturally competent and inclusive
(less Euro-centric, legalistic and patronizing) reading of the Rome Statue,
could potentially tap into this common well of wisdom of all humanity.
Sine the Nuremberg trials, international criminal justice appears to
have converged around the notion that a court’s true measure is given by its
ability to bring about universal accountability for grave crimes. In the
words of Teitel:
Nuremberg established the principle of individual criminal ac-
countability for human rights violations perpetrated against
civilians in wartime: that certain crimes are so heinous that
they violate the “law of nations” and may be prosecuted any-
where. 92
The courts and tribunals established since Nuremberg, including the
International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia, the International
Criminal Tribunal for Rwanda, the Special Court for Sierra Leone, and,
ultimately, the ICC, all function under the same basic understanding. In
other words, the true measure of their integrity, from a ‘universal’ perspec-
tive, seems to be their ability to bring about accountability. Yet, accounta-
bility has many flavours. It can take the form of purely retributive punish-
ment, or more community-harmonizing, culturally competent restorative
justice.
92
Ruti Teitel, “Transitional Justice: Postwar Legacies”, in Cardozo Law Review, 2006, vol. 27,
no. 4, p. 1615.
Arguably, one of ICC’s greatest successes – its relentless push for ac-
countability in Colombia, gently implemented through positive comple-
mentarity 93 – is a manifestation of the OTP and the whole court’s commu-
nity-harmonizing and culturally-competent understanding of the justice
needs and aspirations of Colombian people, beyond black and white ac-
countability under immutable international standards. According to Gold-
ston:
Despite its problems, the ICC has had important impacts out-
side the courtroom. Even as it has refrained from pursuing its
own investigation of possible war crimes and crimes against
humanity in Colombia, the court’s quiet monitoring and over-
sight of postwar developments in the country have helped en-
sure that accountability is a critical part of a national peace
process following a decadeslong civil war. 94
Similarly, according to International Centre for Transitional Justice,
“Colombia’s obligations as a State Party to the Rome Statute appear to
have weakened domestic tolerance of impunity”. 95 Most informed observ-
ers in Colombia perceive the ICC’s role during the peace process with the
Revolutionary Armed Forces of Colombia (FARC) as a more culturally-
competent and inclusive (less Euro-centric, legalistic and patronizing) read-
ing of the Rome Statue. Perhaps this success is owed, at least in part, to the
Prosecutor’s ability to understand Colombia’s language and culture – in
contrast to his apparent inability to read Kenyan culture, and the justice
needs and aspirations of the Kenyan people during the same period. “The
Kenyan case shows how a government has consistently and effectively em-
ployed the rhetoric of ‘imposed international justice’ throughout its ICC
proceedings.” 96
The contrasting outcome of the Colombian and Kenyan cases re-
spond to a plurality of causes that would be impossible to explore within
the limited scope of this chapter. Nonetheless, at least in principle, these
two cases seem to suggest that unless international criminal justice moves
93
William W. Burke-White, “Proactive Complementarity: The International Criminal Court
and National Courts in the Rome System of International Justice”, in Harvard International
Law Journal, 2008, vol. 49, no. 53.
94
Goldston, 2019, see above note 1.
95
Amanda Lyons and Michael Reed-Hurtado, “Colombia: Impact of the Rome Statute and the
International Criminal Court”, in International Center for Transitional Justice, 2010, p. 1.
96
Mieth, 2017, p. 5, see above note 14.
97
For information on recent experiences with transitional justice in Colombia, particularly in
the context of the Special Jurisdiction of Peace created by the 2016 Peace Agreement with
FARC, and the Justice and Peace process created by Law 975 of 2005, regarding paramili-
tary groups, see, for example, Nelson Camilo Sánchez León, Acceptance of International
Criminal Justice - Country Study on Colombia, in International Nuremberg Principles Acad-
emy, 2017; Paul Seils, Squaring Colombia’s Circle: The Objectives of Punishment and the
Pursuit of Peace, International Center for Transitional Justice (‘ICTJ’), New York, 2015;
Botero and Merchán, 2020, see above note 5; El enfoque de macro criminalidad en el pro-
ceso penal de Justicia y Paz. Lecciones para la Jurisdicción Especial para la Paz, ICTJ,
New York, 2019; Institute for Integrated Transitions (‘IFIT’), Rethinking Peace and Justice
(available on its web site); Julieta Lemaitre and Lina Rondón, “La justicia restaurativa y la
escucha: un análisis del componente oral de los informes mixtos y de las versiones volunta-
rias en el Caso 01”, in Danilo Rojas Betancourth (ed.), La JEP vista por sus jueces (2018-
2019), Jurisdicción Especial para la Paz, Bogotá; Rafael A Prieto Sanjuán, “La jurisdicción
especial para la paz: internacional, a pesar de todo”, in Ruiz-Rico, Szegedy, Prieto and Gar-
zon (eds.), Retos en la implementación de los acuerdos de paz en Colombia, Tirant lo Blanch,
2018; Orlando Humberto de la Vega Martins, “Juicio al mal radical? Dos reflexiones acerca
de la justicia transicional en Colombia”, in Ruiz-Rico, Szegedy, Prieto and Garzon (eds.),
Retos en la implementación de los acuerdos de paz en Colombia, Tirant lo Blanch, 2018;
Carlos Ignacio Jaramillo, “El ‘derecho a no ser victima’, y su incidencia en el ‘posconflicto’
colombiano”, in Ruiz-Rico, Szegedy, Prieto and Garzon (eds.), Retos en la implementación
de los acuerdos de paz en Colombia, Tirant lo Blanch, 2018; Lorena Cecilia Vega Dueñas,
“Modelo de justicia transicional: el caso colombiano”, in Ruiz-Rico, Szegedy, Prieto and
Garzon (eds.), Retos en la implementación de los acuerdos de paz en Colombia, Tirant lo
Blanch, 2018; Open Society Justice Initiative, 2018, p. 362, see above note 26; Lorena Ceci-
lia Vega Dueñas and Alberto José Olalde Altarejos, “La justicia restaurativa como paradigma
orientador de paz: los encuentros restaurativos”, in Revista Icade: Revista de las Facultades
de Derecho y Ciencias Económicas y Empresariales, 2018; Gustavo Emilio Cote Barco,
“Responsibility for leadership in the Peace Agreement signed by the Colombian Government
and the FARC-EP: An analysis based on the Bemba case of the International Criminal
Court”, in Nuevo Foro Penal, 2019, vol. 15, no. 92; Laura Bernal-Bermudez and Daniel Ma-
rin Lopez, “Los empresarios en la guerra: verdad judicial sobre la complicidad empresarial
en Colombia”, in Cuentas Claras: El Papel de la Comisión de la Verdad en la develación de
la responsabilidad de empresas en el conflicto armado colombiano, 2018, pp. 39–66, Centro
de Estudios de Derecho, Justicia y Sociedad, Colombia; Comisión Internacional de Juristas,
99
Goldston, 2019, see above note 1.
100
Goldston, 2019, see above note 1 (and the familiar passage: “it is disconcerting that one-
third of the court’s judges are suing for a pay raise plus pension increases and damages that
could run into the millions. Why, when the court has been underperforming and the budget
is strained, are its judges dedicating precious time and energy to increase their already gen-
erous compensation—which at around $200,000 tax-free exceeds that of judges on many na-
tional courts?”).
101
Hatcher-Moore, 2017, see above note 1.
102
Peltier and Faizi, 2020, see above note 3.
these global perspectives may influence the way we see international crim-
inal justice in the multi-cultural world of the twenty-first century.
The growing disconnection between legal elites and the rest of the
people throughout the world, may also affect the ICC – an institution that
has been perceived as ‘foreign’ or ‘alien’ by large segments of the world’s
population. The time has come for friends of international criminal law
principles to give serious consideration to the ‘African Tree’. This does not
mean to question the validity of the Rome Statute in any way. It is rather a
gentle suggestion to try to read the same statute under the light of ancestral
notions of community-harmonizing justice.
Some criticize South Africa for depicting the ICC “as a so-called
Western institution imposing double standards”. 103 With all due respect for
these opinions – even though the Rome Statute was negotiated by judges
and lawyers from around the world, and the ICC’s staff comes “from more
than 90 countries, each with their own legal cultures and traditions” 104 – the
court is an expression of the European ideal of Justice, not a manifestation
of a truly global understanding of Justice; “if ideas and institutions about as
fundamental and personal a value as justice are imposed from outside
without an internal resonance, they may flounder, notwithstanding their
assertion of universality”. 105
At the very minimum, international criminal law experts should bear
in mind that the fact that the Bangalore Principles and the Rome Statute
were negotiated by High Court Justices and lawyers from over one hundred
countries does not mean that these global standards and rules represent the
cultural traditions of an increasingly interconnected, anti-elitist, and cultur-
ally self-assertive global population. Legal elites throughout the world find
it hard to acknowledge that the ‘Western’ legal tradition, in which they
were educated, does not necessarily reflect the Justice needs and aspira-
tions of people in the Global South of the twenty-first century.
In the context of the common law tradition, judicial integrity means
impartiality. In the civil law tradition, it means strict application of the law.
None of them reflects the ideal of justice of ordinary people in the Global
South. As it was explained above, customary justice is widely used by vast
103
Goldston, 2019, see above note 1.
104
Ibid.
105
Rama Mani, Beyond Retribution: Seeking Justice in the Shadows of War, Polity Press, Cam-
bridge, 2002, p. 49.
7.1. Introduction
On 8 June 2018, the Appeals Chamber of the International Criminal Court
(‘ICC’) acquitted Jean-Pierre Bemba Gombo (‘Bemba’) of the charges of
war crimes and crimes against humanity, overturning the decision of Trial
Chamber III to convict the defendant. 1 Three judges joined in the Judgment
issued by the majority, while two judges dissented. 2 The conviction had
been appealed on six separate grounds, but the Judgment overturning the
conviction focused on two grounds: first, that the conviction exceeded the
charges, and second, that Bemba was not liable as a superior. 3
On 13 June 2018, Prosecutor Bensouda released a statement 4 ex-
pressing concern with the Appeals Chamber’s decision. Notably, she stated
that she “must uphold the integrity of the Court’s processes and accept the
outcome”. 5 Yet, she went on to indicate her worries that the Appeals
Chamber’s judgment reflected radical interpretations of jurisprudence and
*
Shannon Fyfe is an Assistant Professor of Philosophy at George Mason University, where
she is also a Fellow at the Institute for Philosophy and Public Policy and an Adjunct Profes-
sor at the Antonin Scalia Law School. She holds both a Ph.D. in philosophy and a J.D. from
Vanderbilt University. Her prior work includes an internship with the International Criminal
Tribunal for Rwanda’s Office of the Prosecutor, the American Society of International Law’s
Arthur C. Helton Fellowship for international human rights law in Tanzania, and a fellow-
ship with the Syria Justice and Accountability Centre. She has published International Crim-
inal Tribunals: A Normative Defense, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2017 (co-
author with Larry May).
1
International Criminal Court (‘ICC’), Situation in the Central African Republic, Prosecutor v.
Jean-Pierre Bemba Gombo, Appeals Chamber, Judgment on the appeal of Mr Jean-Pierre
Bemba Gombo against Trial Chamber III’s “Judgment pursuant to Article 74 of the Statute”,
8 June 2018, ICC-01/05-01/08A (‘Judgment’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/40d35b).
2
Ibid.
3
Ibid., para. 32.
4
ICC Office of the Prosecutor (‘OTP’), “Statement of ICC Prosecutor, Fatou Bensouda, on
the recent judgment of the ICC Appeals Chamber acquitting Mr Jean-Pierre Bemba Gombo”,
13 June 2018.
5
Ibid.
6
Ibid.
7
Ibid.
8
See Bernard Williams, “Integrity”, in J.J.C. Smart and Bernard Williams (eds.), Utilitarian-
ism: For and Against, Cambridge University Press, New York, 1973, pp. 108–117; see also
Bernard Williams, Moral Luck: Philosophical Papers 1973-1980, Cambridge University
Press, Cambridge, 1981.
9
Bernard Williams, “Persons, Character and Morality”, in Williams, 1981, pp. 1–19, 12, see
above note 8.
10
Williams, 1973, p. 116, see above note 8.
11
Ibid.
12
A trait is a virtue if there is something about the trait itself that is intrinsically valuable.
13
Bernard Williams, “Utilitarianism and Self-Indulgence”, in Williams, 1981, pp. 40–53, 49,
see above note 8.
14
Gabriele Taylor, “Integrity”, in Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Vol-
ume, 1981, vol. 55, pp. 143–159, 143.
15
Ibid., p. 144.
and loyalty, but that “we ascribe integrity to him who behaves in socially
acceptable ways, or to him who sticks to his principles however adverse the
circumstances”. 16 We must assume, however, that someone who behaves in
these ways is someone who “keeps his self intact”, given our epistemic po-
sition with respect to an individual’s self. 17
But what does it mean for a self to be integrated or intact? Taylor’s
view of integrity requires that a person be rational: he “will not ignore rele-
vant evidence, he will be consistent in his behaviour, he will not act on rea-
sons which, given the circumstances, are insufficient reasons for action”. 18
Further, an individual with integrity is “not inconsistent in ways that some-
how matter”, and for Taylor this refers to inconsistencies that are connected
to a person’s identity (similar to Williams’ view above). 19 But Taylor gen-
erates further requirements related to identity, such as the condition that “a
person who keeps his self intact will be under ‘due’ influence of his past”. 20
In other words, a person must have a memory of his past and an under-
standing of how it relates to his identity in the present. 21
Like Williams, Taylor does not identify integrity as a virtue, but ra-
ther as something “we hope to get hold of through the virtues”. 22 She ex-
plicitly acknowledges that her view “seems to have the defect that it fails to
account for our thinking of it as some sort of moral quality”, since we are
“reluctant at least to think of the wholly wicked as candidates for integri-
ty”. 23 She contends that we want “to think that the whole or integrated per-
son is also the wholly good person”, but she admits that this is only an as-
sumption under her definition. 24
David Luban offers an alternative view of integrity based on the con-
cept of wholeness in the form of avoiding cognitive dissonance. He defines
integrity as “wholeness or unity of a person, an inner consistency between
16
Ibid.
17
Ibid.
18
Ibid., p. 148.
19
Ibid.
20
Ibid., p. 149.
21
Ibid.
22
Ibid., p. 152.
23
Ibid.
24
Ibid.
25
David Luban, “Integrity: Its Causes and Cures”, in Fordham Law Review, 2003, vol. 72,
p. 279.
26
Ibid.
27
Ibid.
28
This refers to an experiment in which volunteer undergraduate subjects were divided ran-
domly into ‘guards’ and ‘inmates’ in a mock prison. In less than a day, those labeled ‘guards’
began bullying and brutalizing the ‘inmates’, while the inmates began to exhibit the pathol-
ogies of real-life prisoners. Five of the inmates had to be released quickly due to “extreme
emotional depression, crying, rage and acute anxiety”. See Craig Haney et al., “Interperson-
al Dynamics of a Simulated Prison”, in International Journal of Criminology and Penology,
1973, vol. 1, p. 81. On the second day, the prisoners revolted and the guards put down the
rebellion by blasting them with fire extinguishers. See Philip Zimbardo et al., “The Mind Is
a Formidable Jailer: A Pirandellian Prison”, in New York Times, 8 April 1973, §6 (Magazine),
p. 41.
29
In the Milgram experiments, subjects were ordered to administer escalating electrical shocks
to another subject in an experiment on the effects of pain on learning. The victim was a con-
federate of the experimenter, and the shocks were fake, but almost two-thirds of the subjects
prove willing to go all the way to the end of the sequence of shocks, despite the fact that the
victim spends much of the time screaming for the experiment to stop, and eventually falls
ominously silent, while the label on the shock-generator reads ‘Danger: Severe Shock’. See
Stanley Milgram, Obedience to Authority: An Experimental View, Harper & Row, New York,
1974.
30
See Luban, 2003, see above note 25.
31
Ibid., p. 281.
32
Ibid.
33
Ibid.
34
Ibid.
35
Ibid., p. 298
36
Ibid.
37
Ibid.
38
Ibid.
39
Ibid., p. 299
40
Ibid.; see also Deborah L. Rhode, “If Integrity Is the Answer, What Is the Question?”, in
Fordham Law Review, 2003, vol. 72, pp. 335–36.
41
Luban, 2003, p. 299, see above note 25.
42
Ibid., p. 304.
43
Ibid.
44
Cheshire Calhoun, “Standing for Something”, in The Journal of Philosophy, 1995, vol. 92,
no. 5, p. 253.
45
Ibid., pp. 253–54.
46
Ibid., p. 254.
47
Ibid.
48
Ibid., p. 256.
49
Ibid., pp. 256–57.
50
Ibid., p. 257.
51
Ibid., p. 258.
52
Ibid., p. 259.
53
While they do not use the same terminology I use, other views that require two discrete
aspects of integrity include those espoused by Lynne McFall, “Integrity”, in Ethics, 1987,
vol. 98, pp. 5–20; and Rhode, 2003, see above note 40.
54
Greg Scherkoske, “Could Integrity Be an Epistemic Virtue?”, in International Journal of
Philosophical Studies, 2012, vol. 20, no. 2, p. 185.
lence do”, nor is it a virtue that is “necessary for that relation to oneself and
the world which enables one to act from desirable motives in desirable
ways”, as courage and self-control do. 55 Because Williams sees acting with
integrity as maintaining one’s identity-conferring commitments, integrity is
not tied to particular sorts of thoughts, as one might think would be re-
quired of a virtue.
One compelling way to respond to Williams is to claim that integrity
is a virtue, but that it is a ‘cluster concept’, representing “a cluster of mor-
ally praiseworthy attributes including such things as the sincerity and
steadfastness with which [an individual’s] moral beliefs are held, the strug-
gle [an individual] ha[s] undergone to achieve them, [an individual’s] will-
ingness and capacity to question them”. 56 Damian Cox, Marguerite LaCaze,
and Michael Levine defend such a view, and challenge Williams’ view as
incomplete without any requirement that an individual maintain second-
order moral commitments. 57 They argue that an individual who exemplifies
the virtue of integrity finds an Aristotelian mean between excesses of vir-
tues (such as steadfastness where integrity demands change) and vices
(such as hypocrisy) that stand to undermine integrity. 58
Conceiving of integrity as a virtue, as either an intrinsically valuable
feature or as a cluster of praiseworthy attributes, is compatible with the
structural constraints identified in the previous sub-section, and provides an
option for defeating claims of integrity where clearly immoral principles
have been upheld.
7.2.1.2.2. Moral Purpose
A more concrete way to undergird the moral substance of integrity is to
adopt a view about what sorts of commitments are acceptably defended on
a structural account of integrity. Mark Halfon describes an individual of
integrity as one who embraces “a moral point of view that urges them to be
conceptually clear, logically consistent, apprised of relevant empirical evi-
dence, and careful about acknowledging as well as weighing relevant moral
55
Williams, 1981, “Utilitarianism”, p. 49, see above note 13.
56
Damian Cox, Marguerite LaCaze, and Michael P. Levine, “Should We Strive for Integrity?”,
in Journal of Value Inquiry, 1999, vol. 33, no. 4, p. 521.
57
Ibid., pp. 521, 523.
58
Damian Cox, Marguerite LaCaze, and Michael P. Levine, Integrity and the Fragile Self,
Ashgate Publishing, Aldershot, 2003, p. 49.
59
Mark Halfon, Integrity: A Philosophical Inquiry, Temple University Press, Philadelphia,
1989, p. 37.
60
Ibid.
61
Elizabeth Ashford, “Utilitarianism, Integrity and Partiality”, in Journal of Philosophy, 2000,
vol. 97, p. 4.
62
Ibid., pp. 424–45.
63
Halfon 1989, pp. 134–36, see above note 59.
64
Morten Bergsmo, “Revisiting Integrity in International Justice”, FICHL Policy Brief Series
No. 93, Torkel Opsahl Academic EPublisher, 2018, p. 3 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/
e550f7).
65
For a comprehensive analysis of prosecutorial ethics at the ICC, see Alexander Heinze and
Shannon Fyfe, “Prosecutorial Ethics and Preliminary Examinations at the ICC”, in Morten
Bergsmo and Carsten Stahn (eds.), Quality Control in Preliminary Examination: Volume 2,
Torkel Opsahl Academic EPublisher, Brussels, 2018 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/
dff594), in which we call for a more systematic approach to ethics in international criminal
justice.
66
Immanuel Kant, Allen W. Wood (ed. and trans.), Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals,
Yale University Press, New Haven, CT, 2002, G4:429.
67
Heinze and Fyfe, 2018, p. 10, see above note 65.
68
David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity, Cambridge University Press, New York,
2007, p. 88.
69
Ibid.
70
Ibid.
71
Heinze and Fyfe, 2018, p. 9, see above note 65.
72
Again, this is a brief overview of these sources of legal ethical rules. For a more comprehen-
sive treatment, please refer to Heinze and Fyfe, 2018, see above note 65.
73
Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court, adopted 17 July 1998, entry into force 1
July 2002, Article 42(3) (‘ICC Statute’) (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/7b9af9/).
74
Ibid., Article 45.
75
This provision applies to the Prosecutor, the Deputy Prosecutors, staff and gratis personal;
see William A. Schabas, The International Criminal Court: A Commentary on the Rome
Statute, second edition, Oxford University Press, 2016, p. 740.
76
ICC Statute, Article 42(1) clause 3, see above note 73. Cf. also Yvonne McDermott, “Article
42”, in Mark Klamberg, Commentary on the Law of the International Criminal Court, Tor-
kel Opsahl Academic EPublisher, Brussels, 2017, para. 1 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/
aa0e2b/).
77
ICC, Situation in the Democratic Republic of the Congo, Pre-Trial Chamber, Prosecution’s
Reply on the Applications for Participation 01/04-1/dp to 01/04-6/dp, 15 August 2005, ICC-
01/04-84, para. 32 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/4aa811/); see also ICC, Staff Rules of the
International Criminal Court, adopted 21 April 2005, entry into force 3 December 2005,
Rule 101.3(a) (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/10f5c7/) (“Staff members shall ensure their
independence from any person, entity or authority outside the Court.”).
83
ICC, “OTP Code”, in Code of Conduct for the Office of the Prosecutor, 5 September 2013,
chap. 2 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/3e11eb/).
84
Ibid., chap. 3, sect. 2.
ther than at judges, 85 a judge who acts with integrity should also treat eve-
ryone who comes before her with dignity, and avoid acting in ways that
humiliate victims, defendants, or their representation.
Like prosecutors, judges are obligated to take into account both de-
ontological and consequentialist norms when making decisions. Individual
integrity for judges requires reflection on substantive moral values, and
deontological and consequentialist norms. Deontological constraints (and
the corresponding demands of individual integrity) will therefore always
apply, but sometimes a judge may also be obligated to take into account the
end-states that are reasonably expected to be produced by her decisions,
both in judgments and in the courtroom.
We now have established the two sources informing the decision-
making of judges, which are the same as those informing prosecutors: the
structural and substantive requirements of integrity, and consequentialist
and deontological considerations.
7.2.3.2. Legal Ethical Rules
Here, I add the legal ethics rules as the final piece of our normative frame-
work for judges. There are two main texts from which we can draw these
requirements as they pertain to individual judges: the ICC Statute and the
Judicial Code of Conduct. 86
7.2.3.2.1. ICC Statute
The ICC Statute contains specific ethical requirements for individual judg-
es at the ICC in several sections of the Statute. Article 36(3)(a) notes that
“judges shall be chosen from among persons of high moral character, im-
partiality and integrity who possess the qualifications required in their re-
spective States for appointment to the highest judicial offices”. 87
Judges are required to be independent in the performance of their ju-
dicial functions, as outlined in Article 40, which further explains that judg-
es “shall not engage in any activity which is likely to interfere with their
judicial functions or to affect confidence in their independence”, and that
they are not permitted to have any other professional occupation during
85
See Luban, 2007, see above note 68.
86
This is also a brief overview of the sources of legal ethical rules for judges.
87
ICC Statute, Article 36(3)(a), see above note 73.
their tenure on the Court. 88 If there are concerns about a judge’s impartiali-
ty with respect to a given case, he or she will be disqualified from the case
pursuant to the procedure outlined under Article 41. 89 Article 45 requires
that judges must “make a solemn undertaking in open court to exercise his
or her respective functions impartially and conscientiously” before begin-
ning their duties. 90
7.2.3.2.2. Judicial Code of Conduct
The Code of Judicial Ethics (‘Judicial Code’) has been adopted to further
regulate the ethical obligations of judges at the ICC. The Judicial Code,
like the OTP Code, includes many general deontological constraints on the
conduct of judges, and virtues that relate to individual integrity, such as
those related to impartiality, independence, diligence, proper conduct, and
confidentiality. 91 The Judicial Code contains other deontological con-
straints on or demands for individual integrity to ensure the “legitimacy
and effectiveness of the international judicial process”, including require-
ments to “avoid any conflict of interest, or being placed in a situation
which might reasonably be perceived as giving rise to a conflict of inter-
est”, 92 and to “conduct themselves with probity and integrity in accordance
with their office, thereby enhancing public confidence in the judiciary”. 93
In this section, I constructed a multi-level normative framework for
understanding the ethical obligations for individual prosecutors and judges
at the ICC. I generated the normative framework by working through the
meaning of individual integrity as a substantive and structural concept,
identifying both deontological and consequentialist constraints that inform
prosecutorial and judicial decision-making, and laying out the legal rules
that govern the ethical obligations of prosecutors and judges. When tasked
with making decisions as individuals, each level of the framework should
feature in ensuring that individuals at the ICC act with integrity. We will
turn now to understanding institutional integrity at the ICC.
88
Ibid., Article 40.
89
Ibid., Article 41.
90
Ibid., Article 45.
91
See ICC, Code of Judicial Ethics, 9 March 2005, ICC-BD/02-01-05 (https://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/383f8f).
92
Ibid., Article 4.
93
Ibid., Article 5.
94
John Stuart Mill, A System of Logic, book VI, chap. 7, §1.
95
See Christine M. Korsgaard, Self-Constitution: Agency, Identity, and Integrity, Oxford Uni-
versity Press, Oxford, 2009.
96
Williams, 1981, “Persons”, p. 12, see above note 9.
97
Taylor, 1981, p. 148, see above note 14.
98
Ibid., p. 149.
99
See Luban, 2003, p. 298, see above note 25.
100
Ibid.
101
Calhoun, 1995, p. 256, see above note 44.
102
Ibid., p. 259.
103
See Ronald Dworkin, Law’s Empire, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, 1986.
104
Ibid., p. 96.
sions” and thus “count as legal, not just when they are explicit in these de-
cisions but also when they follow from the principles of personal and polit-
ical morality the explicit decisions presuppose by way of justification”. 105
Individuals are entitled to this extension of past decisions, “even when
judges profoundly disagree about what this means”. 106
Judges, then, are required to “identify legal rights and duties, so far
as possible, on the assumption that they were all created by a single au-
thor – the community personified – expressing a coherent conception of
justice and fairness”. 107 Dworkin uses the analogy of a chain novel to de-
scribe this process of adjudication, and he sets up a scenario in which a
group of novelists seeks to write a novel together. 108 Each novelist is tasked
with interpreting the chapters that have been written previously before
writing a new chapter. 109 Dworkin depicts how each novelist “has the job
of writing his chapter so as to make the novel being constructed the best it
can be, and the complexity of this task models the complexity of deciding a
hard case under law as integrity”. 110 The novelists, according to Dworkin,
“aim jointly to create, so far as they can, a single unified novel that is the
best it can be”. 111 A judge, similarly, must try to create a single, unified sto-
ry about the law, and this means that
the actual political history of his community will sometimes
check his other political convictions in his overall interpretive
judgment. If he does not – if his threshold of fit is wholly de-
rivative from and adjustable to his convictions of justice, so
that the latter automatically provide an eligible interpretation –
then he cannot claim in good faith to be interpreting his legal
practice at all. 112
105
Ibid.
106
Ibid., p. 134.
107
Ibid., p. 225.
108
Ibid., p. 229.
109
Ibid.
110
Ibid.
111
Ibid.
112
Ibid., p. 255.
113
See Chris Steytler and Iain Field, “The Institutional Integrity Principle: Where are We Now,
and Where are We Headed”, in University of Western Australia Law Review, 2011, vol. 35,
pp. 227–264.
114
Ibid., p. 229; see also High Court of Australia, Kable v. Director of Public Prosecutions
(NSW), 12 September 1996, 189 CLR 51.
115
Steytler and Field, 2011, p. 229, see above note 113; see also High Court of Australia, Gypsy
Jokers Motorcycle Club Inc v. Commissioner of Police, 2007, 33 WAR 245, p. 268.
116
Peter Johnston and Rohan Hardcastle, “State Courts: The Limits of Kable”, in Sydney Law
Review, 1998, vol. 20, p. 220; see also Kable, 1996, p. 98, see above note 114.
culture of integrity that is promoted by the leadership. While this goes be-
yond individual integrity, especially with respect to collective decision-
making, it is still cashed out, in some ways, in terms of the virtues and eth-
ical considerations that are adopted by and reflected in the individual ac-
tions of the OTP. Additionally, the OTP is structured with the Prosecutor at
the top, thus she is in a position to individually overrule any decisions that
are made ‘collectively’.
The deontological and consequentialist considerations are the same
whether we think about the OTP as the Prosecutor or as an institution pre-
sided over by the Prosecutor and made up of deputy prosecutors and staff.
Thus, I do not rehash the normative ethical framework presented in Section
7.2.2.1. I also will not reiterate the specific rules outlining individual ethi-
cal obligations in Section 7.2.2.2., but I briefly identify some ethical rules
that could be seen as applying to the OTP as an institution rather than as
represented by an individual. This will also include a short discussion of
the OTP strategy and policy papers.
7.3.2.1. ICC Statute
The ICC Statute contains specific ethical requirements for the OTP as an
institution in several sections of the Statute. Article 44 provides for the ap-
pointment of staff, including the requirement that the OTP “shall ensure the
highest standards of efficiency, competency and integrity” in its employ-
ment of staff. 117 Article 54(1) relates to the investigations phase and re-
quires that the Prosecutor “investigate incriminating and exonerating cir-
cumstances equally”, 118 take measures to “respect the interests and person-
al circumstances of victims and witnesses, including age, gender as defined
in Article 7, paragraph 3, and health, and take into account the nature of the
crime, in particular where it involves sexual violence, gender violence or
violence against children” in the investigations, 119 and “[f]ully respect the
rights of persons arising under this Statute”. 120 The obligations under Arti-
cle 54(1) are deontological, where they correspond to specific procedural
requirements or the rights of individuals, and they also reflect the demands
of individual integrity regarding respect for the dignity of all persons. Yet
the OTP is also obligated to consider the results of the Prosecutor’s discre-
117
ICC Statute, Article 44(2), see above note 73.
118
Ibid., Article 54(1)(a).
119
Ibid., Article 54(1)(b).
120
Ibid., Article 54(1)(c).
121
Ibid., Article 55(1)(d).
122
OTP Code, chap. 3., see above note 83.
123
This corresponds to No. 17 of the UN Guidelines on the Role of Prosecutors (“In countries
where prosecutors are vested with discretionary functions, the law or published rules or reg-
The practice involves a broad ethical obligation on the part of the OTP,
which could be considered deontological, in that the duty might be seen as
reflective of an obligation to be transparent with the international commu-
nity, the general public, and all possible defendants that could come before
the ICC. Such a commitment to transparency can also be seen as conse-
quentialist, as one of its aims might be to support the appearance of the le-
gitimacy of the OTP and the Court as a whole. 124
7.3.3. Integrity of the Judiciary
Turning to the judiciary at the ICC, we can begin by thinking about its in-
stitutional integrity in terms of the integrity of the individuals who serve as
judges, in light of the culture of integrity that exists in Chambers. The insti-
tutional integrity will be, again, cashed out in some ways in terms of the
virtues and ethical considerations that are adopted by and reflected in the
individual actions of judges. Yet, collective decision-making will play a
much greater role in judicial settings than it does in the OTP. The institu-
tional integrity of the judiciary will involve more than just the aggregation
of the integrity of individual judges. Namely, it will require something akin
to Dworkin’s adjudicative theory of law as integrity. It is also worth noting
that there is a difference between the judges who sign on to a majority
opinion, which represents the decision of the judiciary as an institution, and
those who sign on to a dissenting opinion, who arguably maintain their sta-
tus as individual judges since they do not represent the institution.
The deontological and consequentialist considerations considered in
Sections 7.2.1. and 7.2.3.1. are largely the same whether we think about
judges as individuals or as institutions engaged in collective decision-
making, and the individual ethical rules are contained in Section 7.2.3.2. So,
I turn directly to identifying ethical rules that could be seen as applying to
the judiciary as an institution rather than as individual judges.
ulations shall provide guidelines to enhance fairness and consistency of approach in taking
decisions in the prosecution process, including institution or waiver of prosecution.”). An
example is ICC-OTP, OTP Report on Preliminary Examination Activities 2013, 25 Novem-
ber 2013 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/dbf75e/), which sets out the principles and criteria
of preliminary examinations (paras. 1 et seq.) and aims to promote transparency (para. 15).
124
Stahn appears to view transparency (including publicity) as involving consequentialist con-
siderations, when he points out: “Publicity is in line with the public nature of criminal pro-
ceedings. It may facilitate the alert effect and strengthen prevention”. Carsten Stahn,
“Damned If You Do, Damned If You Don’t: Challenges and Critiques of Preliminary Exam-
inations at the ICC”, in Journal of International Criminal Justice, 2017, vol. 15, no. 3, p. 18.
125
ICC Statute, Articles 60, 61, see above note 73.
126
Ibid., Article 64.
127
Ibid., Article 68.
128
Ibid., Article 69.
129
Ibid., Article 74.
130
Ibid., Articles 76, 78.
131
Ibid., Articles 83, 84.
It is here that we can see the need for a robust normative ethical
framework to guide individuals and institutions and offer assistance in
reaching deontic verdicts. For these decisions require more than broad
statements about virtue. How could a commitment to ‘act courageously’
help an individual decide whether or not to take a particular action? This
actually requires an individual or collective to make a prediction about the
future, which in turn requires courage, both structural and substantive in-
tegrity, balancing ethical considerations, and also an understanding of the
institution as a whole. The accounts that we have from Taylor and Luban of
integrity as wholeness are particularly salient here, applied to both the in-
dividual and the institution, in terms of demanding decisions that are un-
likely to threaten the continued existence of the institution. If the institution
is to remain, it must also remain focused on identity-conferring commit-
ments (in the vein of Williams), such as those listed in the Preamble to the
ICC Statute, including the idea that “the most serious crimes of concern to
the international community as a whole must not go unpunished and that
their effective prosecution must be ensured by taking measures at the na-
tional level and by enhancing international cooperation”, 132 the determina-
tion to “put an end to impunity for the perpetrators of these crimes and thus
to contribute to the prevention of such crimes”, 133 and the resolution to
“guarantee lasting respect for and the enforcement of international jus-
tice”. 134
Now that I have examined the complete normative ethical framework
for both individual and institutional integrity at the ICC, I consider what
the framework implies about the Bemba case introduced at the beginning of
the chapter.
7.4. Case Study: The Bemba Acquittal
My aim in this final section is to reveal the challenges inherent in a more
complex assessment of individual or institutional integrity, despite the ex-
istence of a comprehensive normative ethical framework. I do not intend to
offer a meticulous analysis of the Bemba judgement at the trial level or ei-
ther opinion issued by the Appeals Chamber. Rather, I sketch out the fea-
132
Ibid., Preamble.
133
Ibid.
134
Ibid.
tures of the appeal that bear directly on issues of individual and institution-
al integrity at the ICC.
7.4.1. Bemba Judgment and Appeal
As noted at the beginning of this chapter, the Appeals Chamber of the ICC
acquitted Bemba of the charges of war crimes and crimes against humanity
in June 2018, overturning the decision of Trial Chamber III to convict the
defendant. The majority adopted the standard of review on appeal that the
Appeals Chamber must overturn factual findings of the Trial Chamber if
they can reasonably be called into doubt. 135 The opinion of the majority of
the Appeals Chamber focused on two grounds of Bemba’s appeal: first, that
the conviction exceeded the charges, and second, that Bemba was not liable
as a superior. 136
7.4.1.1. Standard of Review – Dissenting Opinion
In the dissenting opinion, the judges challenged the majority’s view that
that Appeals Chamber must overturn factual findings of the Trial Chamber
if they can reasonably be called into doubt. 137 They viewed the adoption of
this standard as a significant and unexplained departure from the conven-
tional standard of review for factual errors applied to date by the Appeals
Chamber, as well as of all other international and internationalised courts
and tribunals. 138 The dissenting opinion states that it is not sufficient that
there are “serious doubts” about a factual finding entered by the Trial
Chamber. 139 In case of doubt, they argued that the Appeals Chamber should
review the evidence supporting the factual findings in question to itself de-
termine the issue or to remand the matter to a trial chamber for that pur-
pose. 140 The dissenting judges would have applied the conventional stand-
ard of appeal in assessing Bemba’s grounds of appeal, which accords some
deference to the Trial Chamber’s findings of fact, and they considered that
135
Judgment, para. 35 et seq., see above note 1.
136
See ibid.
137
ICC, Situation in the Central African Republic, Prosecutor v. Jean-Pierre Bemba Gombo,
Appeals Chamber, Dissenting Opinion of Judge Sanji Mmasenono Monageng and Judge Pi-
otr Hofmański to the Judgment on the appeal of Mr Jean-Pierre Bemba Gombo against Trial
Chamber III’s “Judgment pursuant to Article 74 of the Statute”, 8 June 2018, ICC-01/05-
01/08-3636 (‘Dissenting Opinion’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/dc2518).
138
Ibid., paras. 2–18.
139
Ibid., para. 10.
140
Ibid., para. 92.
this modified standard of review has led the majority of the Appeals
Chamber to an erroneous conclusion. 141
7.4.1.2. Second Ground of Appeal – Majority Opinion
On the second ground of appeal, the majority of the Appeals Chamber not-
ed that the Prosecutor provided a “non-exhaustive” list of alleged criminal
acts, including murder, rape, and pillaging, which was then confirmed by
the Pre-Trial Chamber in broad terms. 142 The Prosecutor went on to pro-
vide information on individual criminal acts which had not been expressly
stated in the initial charging document. 143 The Trial Chamber convicted
Bemba of a number of these criminal acts. 144 On appeal, Bemba alleged
that “[n]early two thirds of the underlying acts for which [he] was convict-
ed were not included or improperly included in the Amended Document
Containing the Charges and fall outside the scope of the charges”, 145 and he
asserted that the Trial Chamber erred in relying on these acts for the con-
viction. 146
The majority of the Appeals Chamber found that Bemba’s convic-
tions were for specific acts not substantiated in the Trial Chamber’s convic-
tion document, and that the charging document was too broad to amount to
a meaningful description of the charges against Bemba. 147 Despite the Ap-
peals Chamber’s acknowledgement of amended documents containing
more specific factual allegations against Bemba, the majority of the Ap-
peals Chamber concluded that both the formulation in the operative part of
the Confirmation Decision as well as that in the relevant parts of the Doc-
ument Containing the Charges are too broad to amount to a meaningful
“description” of the charges against Bemba. 148 An amendment to the
charges would have been required to effectuate the more specific factual
allegations. 149 The Appeals Chamber therefore granted this ground of ap-
peal and found, by majority, that the Trial Chamber erred when it convicted
141
Ibid., para. 1.
142
Judgment, para. 75, see above note 1.
143
Ibid., para. 76.
144
Ibid., para. 83.
145
Ibid., paras. 77–78.
146
Ibid., para. 74.
147
Ibid., paras. 116–118.
148
Ibid.
149
Ibid., para. 115.
Bemba of acts which did not fall within the “facts and circumstances de-
scribed in the charges”. 150
7.4.1.3. Second Ground of Appeal – Dissenting Opinion
The dissenting judges argued that the Prosecutor’s case against Bemba was
brought by geographical, temporal and other substantive parameters, and
the Pre-Trial Chamber confirmed the charges as such. 151 The Trial Cham-
ber therefore could consider any criminal acts that fell within these parame-
ters, subject to the requirement of proper notice to the accused. 152 The dis-
senting judges considered that the Prosecutor may set broad parameters for
the charges depending on the circumstances of the case she intends to
bring. 153 Therefore, if the Prosecutor formulates the charges broadly, this
means that additional individual criminal acts may be alleged for the pur-
pose of the trial, provided that they fall within the scope of the crimes con-
firmed and provided that the rights of the accused to notice and time for the
preparation of his or her defence are respected. 154 The dissenting judges
considered this description of the facts and circumstances described in the
charges to be adequate, and they would have found that Bemba’s convic-
tion did not exceed the facts and circumstances described in the charges
that were brought against him. 155
7.4.1.4. Third Ground of Appeal – Majority Opinion
With respect to the third ground of appeal, Bemba argued that the Trial
Chamber erred in finding that he failed to take all measures that were nec-
essary and reasonable to prevent or repress the crimes committed by MLC
(the Movement for the Liberation of the Congo) forces, or to submit the
matter to the competent authorities. 156 He made five separate claims re-
garding this error on the part of the Trial Chamber. 157 The majority of the
Appeals Chamber concluded that the Trial Chamber did err in concluding
that Bemba failed to take all necessary and reasonable measures in re-
150
Ibid., paras. 116–118.
151
Dissenting Opinion, para. 32, see above note 137.
152
Ibid., para. 36.
153
Ibid.
154
Ibid.
155
Ibid., para. 32.
156
Judgment, para. 137, see above note 1.
157
Ibid., para. 30.
sponse to MLC crimes in the CAR, was materially affected by these errors,
and that Bemba cannot be held criminally liable for crimes committed by
MLC troops during the CAR operation. 158 The majority of the Appeals
Chamber found, in several different instances, that the Trial Chamber ig-
nored significant evidence relevant to Bemba’s liability for the crimes
committed by MLC forces. 159
7.4.1.5. Third Ground of Appeal – Dissenting Opinion
The dissenting judges argued that the Trial Chamber’s conclusion that
“Bemba failed to take all necessary and reasonable measures within his
power to prevent or repress the commission of crimes or to refer the matter
to the competent authorities” was in fact supported by the evidence. 160
With respect to this ground of appeal, the dissenting judges could not iden-
tify any errors in the Trial Chamber’s findings or unreasonableness in the
overall conclusions, and thus they would have confirmed the Trial Cham-
ber’s finding that Bemba had failed to take all necessary and reasonable
measures. 161
7.4.2. Integrity of the Prosecutor and the OTP
Prosecutor Bensouda released a statement several days after the judgment
was handed down, in which she expressed concern with the Appeals
Chamber’s decision. 162 She stated that she “must uphold the integrity of the
Court’s processes and accept the outcome”, 163 yet she went on to indicate
her worries that the Appeals Chamber adopted a radical model of appellate
review of factual errors, and a radical view of the manner in which the
Prosecution ought to charge cases involving mass criminality. 164 Prosecutor
Bensouda closed her statement by acknowledging the victims of violence
in the CAR and proclaiming the solidarity of the OTP with these victims. 165
Based on what I have argued thus far, an assessment of Prosecutor
Bensouda’s integrity requires us to consider her structural and substantive
158
Ibid., para. 194.
159
Ibid., paras. 166–194.
160
Dissenting Opinion, paras. 185–191, see above note 137.
161
Ibid., para. 191.
162
See Statement of ICC Prosecutor, 2018, above note 4.
163
Ibid.
164
Ibid.
165
Ibid.
integrity in light of the relevant ethical norms and rules. It appears that the
Prosecutor sought to reassure the specific victims of violence in the CAR,
and the global community as a whole, that this outcome was undesirable
and that she (as both an individual and the face of the institution of the
OTP) would do everything she could to avoid such an unsatisfying out-
come in the future. At the same time, she attempted to avoid undermining
the institution of the Court by accepting the Appeals Chamber’s decision
and the validity of the processes that lead to the decision.
There is no indication that Prosecutor Bensouda acted based on im-
moral commitments; rather, it appears that she sought to ground the sub-
stance of her actions in the commitments of the ICC as an institution, such
as ending impunity, which is (by my lights) an objectively moral purpose.
She sought to align herself, the OTP, and the Court with arguably identity-
conferring commitments. Presumably, Prosecutor Bensouda made the
statement in light of these aspects of integrity, while considering the de-
mands of deontological and consequentialist norms, and as an intact reflec-
tion of her principles that require her to ‘stand up for’ and support victims.
She certainly aimed to treat victims of violence in the CAR with dignity,
thereby meeting one aspect of Luban’s requirements. In this light, she made
her statement with individual integrity.
Yet, it is not clear that she acted with institutional integrity from the
standpoint of wholeness or integration. But this does not speak to what her
individual integrity should be as the head of the OTP rather than an indi-
vidual, nor does it speak to keeping the principles or harmony of the insti-
tution intact. The OTP’s decisions must reflect reasoned deliberation, not
just loyalty or a commitment to consequentialist considerations. According-
ly, I ultimately conclude that, while the OTP should use its outreach capaci-
ty to assure victims of violence that the Court is not a futile source of inter-
national criminal justice, the Prosecutor should not use the OTP’s official
platform to suggest the opposite, with respect to individual cases or the
Court’s practices as a whole, thereby undermining the integrity of the Court
and the OTP.
7.4.3. Integrity of the Judges and the Appeals Chamber
Without engaging in an extensive analysis of either the majority opinion or
the dissenting opinion, based on the above summary, it may be the case that
some of the judges in the Appeals Chamber also failed to meet the re-
quirements for institutional integrity. We have no evidence that any of the
166
Dworkin, 1986, p. 225, see above note 103.
167
Ibid., p. 255.
the institution of the ICC, its sub-institutions, and the individuals who en-
gage in decision-making, with or without integrity, every day. Here, I have
considered two decisions related to this acquittal, disseminated by individ-
uals but purportedly, definitively, or in the face of strong dissent, represent-
ing their respective institutions. My aim has been to provide normative
tools for assessing the integrity of these decisions, and perhaps to better
understand the relationship between institutions and individuals in interna-
tional criminal law.
8.1. Introduction
For public institutions to succeed and to have long-term viability, they must
be motivated by mandate and driven by values. Above all, they must not
betray or compromise the trust and confidence of the public, whose interest
these institutions serve.
In the Policy Brief “Revisiting Integrity in International Justice”,
Morten Bergsmo describes a number of integrity-related challenges before
the International Criminal Court (‘ICC’). 1 Whilst acknowledging the pow-
erful external politics surrounding the ICC, the brief considers the concept
of integrity to be primarily an issue of leadership and recognizes the com-
plex interplay between the exercise of individual integrity and the culture
of an institution.
This chapter examines these issues from a practitioner’s perspective,
with a focus on the respective leadership roles of the ICC and States Parties
in addressing integrity issues within the challenging political, operational
and judicial contexts, which both affect and inform the Court’s work.
The chapter draws upon 16 years of institutional monitoring of the
ICC since its beginning, as well as advocacy efforts urging its development
as an institutionally sound and transparent Court. These initiatives were
based upon the premise that, without an ethical and robust foundation, the
*
Brigid Inder, OBE, a global pioneer of women’s human rights, has served as the co-founder
and Executive Director of the Women's Initiatives for Gender Justice. She is a former Spe-
cial Advisor on Gender to the Prosecutor of the International Criminal Court. She has been
awarded an Order of the British Empire (OBE) in 2014 by Her Majesty, The Queen, for ser-
vices to women’s rights and international justice. She is also the recipient of the inaugural
Bertha von Suttner Peace Prize.
1
Morten Bergsmo, “Revisiting Integrity in International Justice”, FICHL Policy Brief Series
No. 93 (2018), Torkel Opsahl Academic EPublisher, Brussels, 2018. (http://www.toaep.org/
pbs-pdf/93-bergsmo/).
ICC would not have the structural integrity needed to implement its chal-
lenging mandate, to withstand the inevitable attacks on its legitimacy, and
to ensure its long-term credibility in the eyes of the public, including the
victims of crimes within its jurisdiction.
The genesis of the ICC’s approach to integrating ethical considera-
tions within the core of its identity is revealed in a review of some of the
factors influencing the development of the Court’s regulatory framework.
This includes an analysis of the staggered and incomplete emergence of its
internal and external control systems, the complicated dynamics between
ICC officials and States Parties that shape the ethical terrain of the Court,
and the challenges associated with institution-building. The chapter relies
primarily on reports, documents and data in the public domain. This mate-
rial is supplemented by first-hand insights and accounts of debates and de-
cisions related to the Court’s organizational development; the chapter re-
calls interactions with former and current Court staff, officials and diplo-
mats over the past decade and a half, including decision-makers responsi-
ble for transforming the Rome Statute into a viable court. It also considers
some of the major institutional integrity-related crises to have affected the
Court in its first two decades.
We rarely examine or consider the ICC through an ethics, or con-
versely, a corruption lens. Its mandate is assumed to elevate the Court be-
yond prosaic questions of compliance, conduct and oversight. Such mana-
gerial aspects are assumed to be either inherent within or secondary to the
pursuit of the Court’s unimpeachable mandate. This chapter suggests that
long-term neglect of the ICC’s institutional integrity has led to practices
that have inevitably called into question the Court’s trustworthiness as a
public institution. Left unaddressed, this neglect may ultimately compro-
mise the ICC’s credibility to exercise its moral and legal authority and im-
plement its mandate.
Authored by a devotee of the Rome Statute and a supporter of the
Court, this chapter is offered in the hope that it may draw attention to the
urgency of the integrity crisis at the ICC and contribute, in some way, to-
wards its organizational transformation.
2
Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court (‘ICC’), 17 July 1998, in force 1 July 2002
(‘ICC Statute’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/7b9af9).
3
Ibid., Articles 5–8. The definitions and the conditions for the exercise of jurisdiction over
crimes of aggression were adopted by consensus at the 2010 Kampala Review Conference
by the States Parties to the Court. The adopted amendments to the Rome Statute included,
inter alia, deletion of Article 5(2) of the Rome Statute that formerly stated: “The Court shall
exercise jurisdiction over the crime of aggression once a provision is adopted in accordance
with articles 121 and 123 defining the crime and setting out the conditions under which the
Court shall exercise jurisdiction with respect to this crime. Such a provision shall be con-
sistent with the relevant provisions of the Charter of the United Nations.”, and additions of
Article 8bis and Article 15bis/ter that defined the “crime of aggression” and conditions on
the exercise of jurisdiction over the “crime of aggression”, respectively. The Court’s juris-
diction over the crime of aggression was activated on 17 July 2018.
is the highest in 30 years, while the number of people killed in conflicts has
risen tenfold since 2005. 4 The volume of “violent situations” classifiable as
wars, based on the number of casualties, has tripled since 2007. 5 In addi-
tion, “low-intensity conflicts” have risen by 60 per cent in the last decade. 6
A recent edition of the Global Peace Index, produced annually by the
Institute for Economics and Peace, found, based on an assessment of 163
States and territories, 7 that conflict levels in the last decade are in contrast
to the trends over the past century, which have moved towards an increase
in peacefulness world-wide. 8 Using 23 qualitative and quantitative indica-
tors, it measures three thematic domains: “Safety and Security”; “Ongoing
Domestic and International Conflict”; and “Militarisation”. 9 According to
the report, all three domains have worsened in recent years, 10 and the key
indicators of peace have deteriorated globally over the past decade, in
steady increments. 11 The current situation appears to be mostly due to long-
term and entrenched conflicts remaining unresolved, and conflicts that
have emerged in the last decade continuing unabated. 12
According to the UN Refugee Agency, 68.5 million people fleeing
conflict, violence and persecution were forcibly displaced in 2017, a record
number. 13 For the first time in history, 1 per cent of the world’s population
is displaced. 14
In light of the current levels of conflict, with a heightened need for
multilateral responses and recognizing the important role of justice within
4
UN News, “Rise in violent conflict shows prevention ‘more necessary than ever’: UN chief”,
Statement made to journalists at the Annual Retreat for International Conflict Mediators and
other high-level decision makers, Norway, 19 June 2018.
5
Ibid.
6
UN News, “Preventing and resolving conflicts must form ‘backbone’ of collective efforts –
UN chief”, Statement made to the United Nations Security Council on the issue of regional
conflicts, New York, 6 December 2018.
7
Institute for Economics and Peace, Global Peace Index 2018: Measuring Peace in a Com-
plex World, Sydney, June 2018, p. 2 (‘Global Peace Index 2018’).
8
Ibid.
9
Ibid.
10
Ibid., p. 10.
11
Ibid., p. 26.
12
Ibid., p. 7.
13
United Nations High Commissioner for Refugees (‘UNHCR’), Global Trends Report:
Forced Displacement in 2017, Geneva, 2018, p. 2.
14
Global Peace Index 2018, p. 33, see above note 7.
the global peace and security framework, the ICC’s mandate is more rele-
vant than ever. Its significance as an impartial arbiter of criminal justice for
the most serious crimes is without parallel in the international multi-lateral
system. There is no other entity in the world entrusted with the mandate to
stand uniquely and exclusively on the side of justice at the complicated in-
tersection of global politics, international humanitarian and criminal law,
and security challenges.
8.3. Credibility in Question
While the ICC’s moral and legal authority is derived from the Rome Statute,
its credibility comes from its perceived impartiality and the manner in
which it undertakes its statutory responsibilities. This is demonstrated pri-
marily in its judicial work – the selection of cases, the fairness of its pro-
ceedings, the demonstrable capacity of the Court to implement its man-
date – as well as in its organizational integrity as a global public institution
for justice. This chapter will focus on the latter aspect of the ICC’s credibil-
ity.
Although the relevance and necessity of the Court’s mandate are be-
yond dispute, its credibility, with respect to both its judicial achievements
and its institutional ethics, has been called into question. For the former,
this is due to its relatively modest impact, to date, concerning its prosecuto-
rial record within which the performance of the Office of the Prosecutor
(‘OTP’), as well as genuine complexities, demanding disclosure require-
ments and at times innovative jurisprudence have all played a part. 15
The ICC has also made an unsteady contribution to furthering the ju-
risprudence associated with international crimes with some notable excep-
tions, including the Judgement in the Prosecutor v. Bosco Ntaganda case, 16
and the earlier decisions in the same case by the Trial and Appeals Cham-
15
See, for example, Coalition of NGOs for the ICC, “Jean-Pierre Bemba Gombo acquitted by
ICC Appeals Chamber”, 13 June 2018; Women’s Initiatives for Gender Justice, “Appeals
withdrawn by Prosecution and Defence, Prosecutor v Germain Katanga”, 26 June 2014;
Women’s Initiatives for Gender Justice, “The Compendium: An Overview of Situations and
Cases Before the International Criminal Court”, 2017; Douglas Guilfoyle, “Part III - This is
Not Fine: The International Criminal Court in Trouble”, in European Journal of Interna-
tional Law, 25 March 2019; and Women’s Initiatives for Gender Justice, “Gender Report
Card on the International Criminal Court”, 2007–2014 and 2018.
16
ICC, Situation in the Democratic Republic of the Congo, Prosecutor v. Bosco Ntaganda
(‘Ntaganda’), Trial Chamber, Judgment, 8 July 2019, ICC-01/04-02/ 06-2359 (https://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/80578a/).
bers with respect to the charges of rape and sexual slavery committed
against children within Ntaganda’s own militia group. 17
For the latter credibility issue, its institutional integrity has been
called into question due to what appears to be improper, unethical or un-
lawful conduct by ICC staff, specifically senior leaders and Court officials.
Some of these incidents are in the public domain, several have been ex-
posed by the media. 18
Arguably, its institutional credibility has also been compromised,
perhaps most damagingly, by the more mundane but less widely known
repetitive breaches of ICC staff regulations, rules, policies and resolutions.
These violations, small and large, have been committed by those who have
both shaped and taken advantage of a culture of non-compliance and unac-
countability. This environment has been enabled and facilitated by the
manner in which the Assembly of States Parties (‘ASP’, or the ‘Assembly’)
has exercised its governance responsibilities.
Based on longitudinal monitoring of the Court, 19 there is now com-
pelling evidence to suggest that the ICC is in a precarious position with
17
Ntaganda, Trial Chamber, Second Decision on the Defence’s challenge to the jurisdiction of
the Court in respect of Counts 6 and 9, 4 January 2017, ICC-01/04-02/06-1707, para. 54
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/2de239/); Ntaganda, Appeals Chamber, Judgment on the
appeal of Mr Ntaganda against the “Second decision on the Defence’s challenge to the juris-
diction of the Court in respect of Counts 6 and 9”, 15 June 2017, ICC-01/04-02/06-1962
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/a3ec20).
18
Sven Becker, Marian Blasberg and Dietmar Pieper, “The Ocampo Affair: A Former ICC
Chief’s Dubious Links”, in Spiegel International, 5 October 2017; EIC Network, “Secrets of
the International Criminal Court Revealed”, in The Black Sea, 29 September 2017; EIC
Network, Stephanie Maupas, “Secrets of the International Criminal Court: The Kenya U-
Turn”, in The Black Sea, 6 October 2017; Barney Thompson, “Former ICC Prosecutor in
row over lucrative consultancy work”, in Financial Times, 6 October 2017; Stephanie Mau-
pas, “ICC Under Fire for Internal Mismanagement”, JusticeInfo.net, 26 February 2018; and
Morten Bergsmo, “Integrity as Safeguard Against the Vicissitudes of Common Justice Insti-
tutions”, Centre for International Law Research and Policy (‘CILRAP’), 1 December 2018,
at 8.53-11.44 mins (https://www.cilrap.org/cilrap-film/181201-bergsmo).
19
Between 2004 and 2017, the author was the Executive Director of the Women’s Initiatives
for Gender Justice. During this time, the organization monitored the institutional develop-
ment of the ICC regarding recruitment and the gender and geographical profile of the staff
of the Court, and its elected officials. It also conducted reviews of selected ICC policies and
training activities, analysed and advocated for the elaboration of the Court’s institutional
framework, including the development of the Independent Oversight Mechanism, and scru-
tinized the annual budget submissions of each of the organs of the ICC. The organization
provided briefings to States Parties, to the Committee on Budget and Finance (‘CBF’), and
the Assembly of States Parties (‘ASP’), specifically addressing issues associated with the in-
stitutional development of the Court. The Women’s Initiatives for Gender Justice produced
annual Gender Reports Cards on the ICC (‘Gender Report Cards’) that summarized im-
portant developments in the ICC’s substantive work, as well as providing assessments and
detailed recommendations on aspects of its internal control system, governance issues, the
budget, staff profile, and the election of Court officials. The Gender Report Cards also as-
sessed the implementation of the gender mandates of the Rome Statute with respect to the
institutional development of the Court. Since 2018, the author has, on an independent basis,
continued to monitor a select number of institutional development issues before the ICC.
20
Bergsmo, 2018, p. 1, see above note 1.
21
Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court, 17 July 1998, Article 12(3) (http://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/7b9af9/):
the Rome Statute and are members of the ICC. 22 This membership provides
a legal remedy for nationals of States Parties who are victims of crimes
within the ICC’s jurisdiction. It also subjects their citizens, including mili-
tary leaders and elected public officials, to potential prosecutions and the
judgments of the Court.
The ICC was created to be an independent institution driven by its
jurisdictional imperatives but operating in a clearly defined relationship
with the UN system. 23 The intention behind its unique status was to remove,
or perhaps more realistically reduce, the potential political influence of the
Security Council on this new global justice mechanism. The goal was to
establish a Court accessible to all States, beyond the power centres created
after the Second World War and subsequently instituted in the permanent
membership of five States on the Security Council, each with veto powers.
Whilst keenly aware that it would likely operate in highly politicized envi-
ronments, the Court was established on the basis that it would be driven by
the jurisdiction with which it was entrusted and in so doing act as an equal-
izer in the world of the powerful and powerless.
However, the notion that the Court is a politically neutral zone is an
ideal rather than a reality. All of the States Parties to the ICC are also all
UN members and therefore well versed in the economic relationships, con-
sensus-building activities, transactional co-operation and the geopolitical
and historic alliances that constitute international diplomacy. Two of the
five permanent members of the Security Council are States Parties of the
ICC – France and the United Kingdom. Although the three permanent
members of the Security Council that are not States Parties to the Court,
namely the United States of America (‘US’), Russia and China, do not have
If the acceptance of a State which is not a Party to this Statute is required under Para-
graph 2, that State may, by declaration lodged with the Registrar, accept the exercise of
jurisdiction by the Court with respect to the crime in question. The accepting State shall
cooperate with the Court without any delay or exception in accordance with Part 9.
22
States Parties to the Rome Statute (available on the ICC’s web site); ICC, “President of the
Assembly welcomes Malaysia’s accession to the Rome Statute”, 5 March 2019 (https://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/5f783c).
23
ICC, “Negotiated draft Relationship Agreement between the International Criminal Court
and the United Nations”, adopted at the third plenary of the Assembly of States Parties on 7
September 2004, entered into force on 4 October 2004, ICC-ASP/3/Res.1 (‘Relationship
Agreement’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/9432c6). There, Member States reminded
themselves that “in accordance with the Rome Statute, the International Criminal Court is
established as an independent permanent institution in relationship with the United Nations
system”.
any formal influence with the ICC, it would be fanciful to assume that at
least some of their interests are not readily communicated to the Court via
surrogate States or through direct communication between their diplomats
and Court officials.
As a permanent and independent entity within the multi-lateral com-
munity associated with the UN, the ICC is an important and irreplaceable
component of the international peace and security architecture.
8.4.2. Relationship Agreement
With its independence in mind and highly cognizant of its interface with
the Security Council, the negotiators of the Rome Statute designated two
specific statutory roles for the Security Council with respect to the potential
opening of investigations into crimes falling within the ICC’s temporal and
subject matter jurisdiction. These are outlined in Articles 13 and 16 of the
Rome Statute, respectively, and address the ability of the Security Council,
acting under Chapter VII of the UN Charter to: refer a situation to the ICC
Prosecutor in which one or more crimes within the ICC’s jurisdiction ap-
pear to have been committed; 24 or alternatively, to defer an ICC investiga-
tion or prosecution for up to 12 months, with the possibility of renewing
such a deferral. 25
With the specific roles for the Security Council defined and the juris-
dictional independence of the Court enshrined within the Statute, the ICC
and the UN entered into a relationship agreement (the ‘Agreement’), as re-
quired under Article 2 of the Rome Statute. 26 Within two years of the Stat-
ute coming into force, an agreement specifying and clarifying the relation-
ship between the new Court and the UN was adopted by both parties. 27
The Agreement recognizes the ICC as an independent permanent ju-
dicial institution and, reciprocally, the ICC recognizes the responsibilities
of the UN under the UN Charter. 28 It also addresses a range of pragmatic
issues and provides procedures, outlined in Article 17 of the Agreement,
regarding the use of powers designated to the Security Council to refer sit-
uations and defer investigations or prosecutions. The Agreement also de-
24
ICC Statute, Article 13(b), see above note 2.
25
Ibid., Article 16.
26
Ibid., Article 2.
27
Relationship Agreement, see above note 23.
28
ICC Statute, Article 2, see above note 2.
scribes the conditions under which the UN may provide documents or in-
formation to the Prosecutor on condition of confidentiality and solely for
the purpose of generating new evidence. 29
Overall, the Agreement defines the terms of “a mutually beneficial
relationship whereby the discharge of respective responsibilities of the
United Nations and the International Criminal Court may be facilitated”. 30
In practice, the Agreement has been readily and regularly utilized.
The UN has played important roles with the ICC in a number of ways and
has contributed to the Court’s work both in its prosecutorial activities as
well as operationally, including, but not limited to:
1. The voluntary participation of UN personnel as expert witnesses in
ICC cases;
2. Acting as a confidential source of information for the OTP from
which it could generate evidence during its investigations;
3. Providing assistance for the arrest of ICC indictees and their transfers
to the Court; and
4. The provision of logistic, operational and security support to ICC
missions and field offices.
In addition to the statutory independence of the ICC’s investigations
and cases, there is also an important institutional separation between the
Security Council and the Court, specifically in the area of governance. Un-
like, for instance, the International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugo-
slavia (‘ICTY’) and the International Criminal Tribunal for Rwanda
(‘ICTR’), which reported solely to the Security Council, 31 the ICC unique-
ly reports only to its membership of States Parties (except the Prosecutor’s
report to the Security Council on the cases the latter referred) and elects its
own officials. In this respect, the UN does not have a governance role or
decision-making responsibilities regarding the institutional development
and oversight of the ICC.
29
Ibid., Article 18.
30
Ibid., Preamble.
31
With the closure of both the ICTR in 2015 and the ICTY in 2017, all remaining cases and
appeals associated with these courts are dealt with by the International Residual Mechanism
for Criminal Tribunals (the ‘Mechanism’). The President of the Mechanism reports on a six-
monthly basis to the UN Security Council, and annual reports on the work of the Mechanism
are submitted to the General Assembly and the Security Council.
It was hoped that this structure would further protect the Court’s in-
dependence and that a nimble court unencumbered by UN bureaucracy
could design systems to suit its specific requirements and operational needs.
In practice, this means that the ICC is not obligated to comply with the
UN’s ethics-related policies and frameworks; it is not subject to its internal
control system, nor the UN’s conduct and accountability requirements.
This independence could have propelled the Court to become the
preeminent global institution demonstrating institutional authenticity in
harmony with the nobility of its mandate. Instead, the ICC stumbled into an
institutional void in which its ethical practices and internal control systems
lag behind international standards.
8.5. Building the Institution
8.5.1. ICC Staff Regulations and Rules
Since its beginning, the ICC appears to have been more mission-driven
than values-oriented. During the early years of its establishment, the ICC
and the ASP passed a number of policies and resolutions to transform the
Rome Statute into a working, viable Court. However, the strong focus on
its jurisdictional mandate largely overpowered attention to the regulatory,
organizational and ethics-related considerations necessary in building an
institution.
The starting point of an organization’s integrity always lies in its
foundations and internal architecture.
In developing its Staff Regulations in 2003, 32 and Staff Rules in
33
2005, the ICC closely followed the relevant regulations and rules of the
UN at that time. 34 For ease, to hasten ‘construction’ of the Court and per-
haps to take advantage of the experience of staff who were serving in the
UN-related tribunals, the ICC adopted the same professional categories,
32
ICC, Staff Regulations for the International Criminal Court, adopted at the second session of
the Assembly of States Parties, 8-12 September 2003, ICC-ASP/2/10 (‘ICC Staff Regula-
tions’) (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/3542d3/).
33
ICC, Staff Rules of the International Criminal Court, adopted by the Assembly of States
Parties on 3 December 2005, entered into force on 25 August 2005, ICC-ASP/4/3 (‘ICC
Staff Rules’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/10f5c7/).
34
The UN Staff Regulations and Rules relevant to this chapter and utilized in the comparison
with the ICC are contained within the United Nations Regulations Governing the Status,
Basic Rights and Duties of Officials other than Secretariat Officials, and Experts on Mission,
1 January 2002, ST/SGB/2002/1 (‘UN Staff Rules’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/
wv8h0w/).
35
United Nations General Assembly, by its resolution 58/262 of 23 December 2003, effective
1 January 2004.
36
ICC Staff Regulations, Regulation 2.1 and 3.1-3.4, see above note 32.
37
ICC Staff Rules, Rule 110.1, p. 64, see above note 33.
38
Conversations with former OTP staff members on file with the author.
39
ICC Statute, Article 42(2), see above note 2.
45
See, for example, below Section 8.7. (“Case Study: ReVision”).
46
UN Staff Rules, Rule 101.1, see above note 34; ICC Staff Regulations, Regulation 1.1(a),
see above note 32.
General of the United Nations, Dag Hammarskjöld. Perhaps more than any
other Secretary-General, Dag Hammarskjöld actively promoted and em-
bodied the identity and practice of the international civil service and equat-
ed the concept of integrity with “conscience” and “respect for law and re-
spect for truth’’. 47
According to the Standards,
international civil servants have a special calling: to serve the
ideals of peace, of respect for fundamental rights, of economic
and social progress, and of international cooperation. It is
therefore incumbent on international civil servants to adhere
to the highest standards of conduct; for, ultimately, it is the in-
ternational civil service that will enable the United Nations
system to bring about a just and peaceful world. 48
The Standards of 2001, available to the ICC at the time of its estab-
lishment, had been recently updated by the UN in response to new ethical
challenges not fully addressed by the earlier Standards and in order to re-
flect a more modern era with the evolution of new concepts and global ad-
vances. 49
The Standards issued at that time addressed a number of practical is-
sues, including ethical aspects of the role and the working relationships of
civil servants; 50 the obligation to report the commission of violations; 51
personal conduct and protection of information; 52 loyalty to the organiza-
tion and its vision; 53 and the requirement to place the interests of the insti-
tution above their own and ensure responsible use its resources. 54
47
Bergsmo, 2018, p. 2, see above note 1.
48
International Civil Service Commission, Standards of Conduct for the International Civil
Service, January 2002, para. 2, adopted by the United Nations General Assembly, A/RES/
56/244, December 2001, distributed 5 February 2002 (‘Standards of Conduct’) (https://www.
legal-tools.org/doc/y77yzh/).
49
Ibid.
50
Ibid., paras. 15–19, 31-33, 38-45.
51
Ibid., para. 19.
52
Ibid., paras. 35, 38–40.
53
Ibid., paras. 4 and 7.
54
Ibid., para. 4.
55
Ibid., para. 16: “It is natural for managers to be seen as role models and they have therefore
a special obligation to uphold the highest standards of conduct”.
56
Ibid., paras. 2, 4- 5, 8-9, 27, 30, and 48.
57
Ibid., para. 19.
58
Ibid., paras. 21, 22, and 41.
59
United Nations, Status, Basic Rights and Duties of UN Staff Members, 1 November 2002,
ST/SGB/2002/13, Section I, para. 7, p. 5 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/f9e724/).
60
ICC Staff Regulations, see above note 32 and ICC Staff Rules, see above note 33. The term
‘international civil servant’ appears eleven times in the ICC Staff Regulations and Rules, in-
cluding in their pre-eminent provisions where both declare that “ICC staff are international
civil servants”, see ICC Staff Regulations, 30 September 2016, Ref. ICC/PRESD/G/
2016/002, Regulation 1.1(a) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/bc0ddb) and ICC, Staff Rules
of the International Criminal Court, 2015, Rule 101.1 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/
b14f3a).
61
ICC, Code of Conduct for Staff Members, 4 April 2011, ICC/AI/2011/002, Introduction and
Section 1 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/75f9db).
years after the ICC began its judicial work and field operations. For exam-
ple, a broad range of conflicts of interest were eventually included in the
Court’s 2011 Code of Conduct. 62 A financial disclosure programme was
introduced at the Court in 2016 applicable to principals and staff involved
with specific finance and procurement activities, as well as staff associated
with the system of internal control and oversight. 63 The ICC’s Whistle-
blower Policy, adopted in 2014, addresses the duty to report violations and
provides protection from retaliation. 64 The creation of the Independent
Oversight Mechanism (‘IOM’), deemed fully functional in 2017, finally
addresses misconduct, encompassing both unsatisfactory and serious mis-
conduct. 65 Unfortunately, this staggered and piecemeal approach to the
ICC’s institutional development created an internal environment without
sufficient guidance and regulatory clarity, and delayed the conscious evolu-
tion of an ethics-based culture.
Despite references to its staff as international civil servants, the Court
does not appear to have fully accepted the responsibilities of this status
within its organizational culture or policy and legal frameworks. At the
same time, States Parties have not exercised oversight of the Court through
62
Ibid., Section 4, paras. 4.1-4.5.
63
ICC, Disclosure Requirements - Financial Disclosure Programme of the Court (ICC-FDP)
and IPSAS Related Party Disclosures, 6 October, 2015, ICC/AI/2015/05 (https://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/bbdb4c/). See also ICC, Report of the Court on Policy Issues (Anti-fraud,
Whistle-blower Policies, Financial Disclosure Programme, Longer-term Investment Options
and Employee Benefit Liabilities), 4 May 2015, ICC-ASP/14/17 (https://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/lpfxdi/). In para. 8:
The Court has identified the following classification of personnel required to file: (a)
The Prosecutor, Deputy Prosecutor, Registrar and Deputy Registrar; (b) All staff mem-
bers and officials at D-1 level or above; (c) All Certifying Officers; (d) All Procurement
staff members, or those whose principal occupational duties are the procurement of
goods and services for the Court; (e) All staff members whose principal occupational du-
ties are related to the investment of the assets of the Court; (f) Other staff members and
officials whose direct access to confidential procurement or investment information war-
rants the filing of disclosure statements; and (g) All staff members serving in the Inde-
pendent Oversight Mechanism and the Internal Audit Office.
64
ICC, Whistleblowing and Whistleblower Protection Policy, 8 October 2014, ICC/PRESD/
G/2014/003, Article 1.1–1.3 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/0c36ff).
65
The Independent Oversight Mechanism (IOM) was established by the Assembly at its eighth
session in accordance with Article 112, para. 4, of the ‘ICC Statute’. The IOM became fully
operational in 2017. It is an operationally independent office with the head of the IOM re-
porting to the President of the Assembly of States Parties. See also ICC, Establishment of an
Independent Oversight Mechanism, 26 November 2009, ICC-ASP/8/Res.1 (‘ICC-
ASP/8/Res.1’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/bf0e8c/).
the prism of the Standards, and the prestige of being an international civil
servant has perhaps been under-utilized by the ICC as a source of motiva-
tion for its employees. Nevertheless, the Court’s assertion of this status for
its staff carries with it the responsibility to adhere to the standards of ethi-
cal conduct expected of those in the international civil service.
Not relying on the Standards alone to fill some of the policy gaps, the
UN has continuously amended and updated its staff regulations and rules as
well as other workplace and ethics-related policies. By contrast, the ICC
has not.
Since the UN Regulations were first published in 1952, there have
been more than 60 amendments to the staff-related legal framework. 66 This
reflects an ongoing process of review, adaption, and possibly learning by
the UN, often preceded by crisis and scandals, as well as the adoption of
management practices normative in many parts of the world. For compari-
son with the ICC, in the first 17 years of UN operations (1952-1969), it
amended its staff regulations and rules on 17 occasions. 67 During the insti-
tutional lifespan of the Court, since the adoption of its Rules to the time of
writing (2003-2020), the UN has revised its Staff Regulations and Rules
more than 20 times. According to the ICC web site, in the same 17-year
period, it appears that the ICC has amended its Staff Regulations twice, 68
and its Staff Rules appear to have been amended three times. 69
Evidently, the ICC has not demonstrated the same attention and nec-
essary commitment to the ongoing evolution of its institutional framework.
Whereas one might have expected the ICC, as a modern and unprecedented
institution, to have adopted the highest standards possible in its founding
institutional documents, it opted instead for diminished versions of some
66
United Nations, “Staff Regulations and Rules of the United Nations”, 1 January 2018,
ST/SGB/2018/1 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/6d5d9j/).
67
Ibid., p. 7.
68
ICC, Amendment to the ICC Staff Regulations, 22 January 2014, ICC/PRESD/G/2014/001
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/d562a8/); ICC Staff Regulations, ICC-PRESD/G/2016/002,
30 September 2016 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/bc0ddb/).
69
ICC, Promulgation of the Amendments to the ICC Staff Rules, ICC/AI/2015/004, 24 July
2015 and related corrigendum, ICC Promulgation of the Staff Rules of the International
Criminal Court, 27 July 2015, ICC/AI/2015/004/Cor.1 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/
2a5274/); Promulgation of the Amended Provisional Staff Rules of the International Crimi-
nal Court, ICC/AI/2016/003, 30 December 2016 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/65ab39/);
Promulgation of the Amended Provisional Staff Rules of the International Criminal Court, 3
May 2017, ICC/AI/2016/003 Rev.1 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/f5e9c7/).
70
ICC, Sexual and Other Forms of Harassment, Administrative Instruction, 14 July 2005,
ICC/AI/2005/005 (‘Sexual Harassment Administrative Instruction’) (https://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/hyvqzp/).
71
Specifically, the ICC Policy does not sufficiently address the following issues: the identifica-
tion of focal points with expertise in this area; the intended dissemination of the Policy and
support for staff; the lack of preventive measures; the importance of prompt and concrete re-
sponses by managers to complaints under this Policy, with failure to do so possibly consid-
ered a breach of duty and/or a performance-related issue for the manager/supervisor; an ex-
pansive list of options available for reporting incidents; monitoring implementation and use
of the Policy; and the absence of any references to or definition of discrimination, one of the
potential precursors to the commission of conduct which is either intended to harass or could
be experienced as harassment.
72
Sexual Harassment Administrative Instruction, paras. 1.1 and 1.2, see above note 70.
bunals’ Statutes and the Geneva Conventions in this area. 75 Justice Gold-
stone’s view was that they would need to be inventive to address the lacuna
that existed around these specific crimes in the early 1990s. 76 Mindful of
his jurisdictional responsibilities and understanding the importance of or-
ganizational coherence between its prosecutorial approach and the culture
within the OTP itself, Justice Goldstone urged staff to be attentive to gen-
der issues in all spheres, believing that, “if we don’t get gender issues right
in the office, we’re not going to get it right out of the office”. 77
Unlike the UN’s comparable sexual harassment and discrimination
policies (in place at the time the ICC was drafting its Sexual Harassment
Administrative Instruction), 78 the Court’s policy differs in three key aspects:
1. The ICC’s policy does not include an explicit reference to sexual
harassment being particularly serious when behaviour of this kind is
engaged in by Court officials. Paragraph 2.2 of the ICC’s policy
closely reflects paragraph 2 of the relevant UN Administrative In-
struction, with the specific exception of the language expressing that
harassment is “particularly serious when behaviour of this kind is
engaged in by any official”. This phrase was omitted from the ICC’s
policy.
2. It does not acknowledge the barriers to reporting harassment created
by power differentials between the harassed person and the alleged
harasser. Recognizing and explicitly naming the issue of power em-
bedded in the acts of harassment and concomitantly inherent within
the challenges to report such violations, is an appropriate lens
through which to develop effective policies and practices in this area.
The power imbalance is magnified if the person allegedly responsible
for the harassment is more senior to the harassed person, which is of-
ten the reality. Reporting is exponentially more difficult if the alleged
harasser is the head of an organ or elected official of the Court or the
ASP or affiliated with one of these officials.
75
Richard J. Goldstone, “Prosecutorial Language, Integrity and Independence”, CILRAP, 2
December 2018, at 6.50-7.25 minutes (www.cilrap.org/cilrap-film/181202-goldstone/)
76
Ibid.
77
Ibid., at 8.50-9.12 minutes.
78
United Nations, Administrative Instruction, 29 October 1992, ST/AI/379 (https://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/juboyq/).
3.Paragraph 6.1 of the ICC policy states that staff members “shall have
reasonable grounds before making a complaint of harassment”, and
paragraph 7.6 indicates that if such a complaint is found to be base-
less or malicious, “the complainant may be subject to disciplinary
procedures”. These provisions, not within the UN’s Administrative
Instruction, could be considered intimidating for those contemplating
reporting harassment and may be indicative of an environment hos-
tile to, and inclined towards disbelief of, those reporting such con-
duct.
These policy gaps were subsequently reflected in the systemic indif-
ference demonstrated by the Court’s leadership regarding the lack of mean-
ingful implementation of the Policy and monitoring of its use and accessi-
bility. This inaction prevailed despite information that began to surface as
early as 2005 with respect to the alleged conduct of staff and some Court
officials in relation to possible harassment, especially of female staff and
interns. 79
In 2018, the ICC Disciplinary Advisory Board 80 determined that the
Sexual Harassment Administrative Instruction did not apply to support staff
members of either Defence Counsel or Victims Representatives, leaving
these ICC-related contractors without redress or policy protection. 81 Sup-
port staff are particularly vulnerable because their contracts are negotiated
directly with the Defence Counsel or Victims Legal Representatives who
are not obliged to ensure that these employment arrangements comply with
the standards or conditions within contracts issued directly by the ICC. The
Court does not require any minimum employment protections and stand-
ards within such contracts, thus leaving support staff at the whims of the
Counsel/Legal Representatives with little bargaining power and no contrac-
79
Conversations with former Court staff on file with the author.
80
ICC, “Disciplinary Procedure” (available on the ICC’s web site).
81
ICC, The Prosecutor v. Jean-Pierre Bemba Gombo, Aimé Kilolo Musamba, Jean-Jacques
Mangenda Kabongo, Fidèle Babala Wandu and Narcisse Arido, Trial Chamber, Request to
Review the Registry’s Decision to Neither Apply or Comply With Legal Service Agreements
with Defence Support Staff, 20 June 2018, ICC-01/05-01/13-2292, paras. 21–23 (‘Jean-
Pierre Bemba Gombo case’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/dd9acd); ICC, Jean-Pierre
Bemba Gombo case, Registry's Observations on the “Request to Review the Registry's De-
cision to Neither Apply or Comply With Legal Service Agreements with Defence Support
Staff”, Trial Chamber, 20 June 2018, ICC-01/05-01/13-2292, paras. 21–27 (https://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/d48f7e).
tual rights to sick leave, paid leave, and other standard conditions. 82 Alt-
hough they are acting on behalf of the ICC, the Court does not extend any
services to the Defence/Victims support staff and, as such, they may be un-
able to access the Court’s medical practitioners, staff welfare services or
the focal points indicated within the Policy to whom incidents of harass-
ment can be reported. These conditions magnify the vulnerability of sup-
port staff, predominantly female, in relation to their direct service on behalf
of the Court.
In 2018, 46 defence and victim’s support staff members raised spe-
cific concerns with the Registry regarding the lack of institutional protec-
tion against harassment and exploitation in the workplace. 83 In March 2018,
the International Criminal Court Bar Association issued a declaration re-
minding Defence Counsel of their obligations under the Code of Conduct
for Counsel. 84 Despite the Registry’s awareness of the policy gaps, the spe-
cific issues raised by support staff, and the associated vulnerability of these
actors, it has not initiated any remedies or interim arrangements establish-
ing minimum employment standards for these positions. In 2019, the Reg-
istry finally undertook a review of the Policy. However, as noted in the Fi-
nal Report of the Independent Expert Review on the International Criminal
Court and the Rome Statute System (the ‘Independent Expert Review’), the
new Administrative Instruction updating this policy area has been “stuck at
inter-organ consultations for too long and remains unissued”. 85
This is an alarming oversight in the era of the #MeToo movement
and unfathomably reckless with respect to the protection and well-being of
individuals as well as the institution.
It is perhaps all the more startling in light of advocacy by civil socie-
ty representatives between 2005 and 2014 noting the gaps in the training
and procedures associated with the Policy, and the lack of progress in creat-
82
Ibid., paras. 3, 4, 10, 17, 18a-c.
83
Ibid., para. 21.
84
International Criminal Court Bar Association, ICCBA Declaration on Obligations under the
Code of Conduct for Counsel and Proposed Amendments thereto, 2 March 2018 (https://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/tie947/).
85
ICC, Independent Expert Review of the International Criminal Court and Rome Statute Sys-
tem, Final Report, 30 September 2020, para. 214, p. 68 (‘Independent Expert Review’)
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/cv19d5/).
ing focal points. 86 Since 2008, these representatives have called on the ICC
Presidency to oversee an audit of the Policy and its implementation, includ-
ing: a review of the issues covered by the Policy; the adequacy of training;
the creation of focal points; and the inclusion of the Policy within the in-
duction process for new staff. 87 The civil society organization further sug-
gested that the results of the audit should be shared with the Bureau and the
ASP and called on the Court to develop recommendations to address any
incidents or patterns of harassment and to ensure that the ICC provided a
“non-discriminatory, equality-based, human-rights respecting work envi-
ronment”. 88
8.5.4. Office of the Prosecutor
Beyond individual gaps in the institutional platform, deficiencies across
multiple areas of employment suggest a systemic indifference within the
Court to developing robust, ethical standards and an aversion, perhaps in-
tentional, to complying with its regulatory framework, exercising oversight
and responding to deviations from these obligations.
During the Court’s first decade, this antipathy was perhaps most ex-
emplified by the Prosecutor and the positions assumed by his Office on key
policy issues including with respect to the creation and implementation of
internal control systems across the Court as well as within the OTP.
In hindsight, possibly one of the first signs of this penchant for non-
compliance within the OTP was the decision by the Prosecutor against
adopting the draft Code of Conduct (the ‘draft Code’ or simply the ‘Code’),
included within the OTP’s draft Regulations prepared by members of the
Advance Team. 89 This preparatory team was established by States Parties
86
Women’s Initiatives for Gender Justice, Gender Report Card on the International Criminal
Court 2005, Policy Section; Gender Report Card on the International Criminal Court 2006,
p. 9; and Gender Report Card on the International Criminal Court 2007, p.14.
87
Women’s Initiatives for Gender Justice, Gender Report Card on the International Criminal
Court 2008, para. 19, p. 107; Gender Report Card on the International Criminal Court 2009,
p. 161; Gender Report Card on the International Criminal Court 2010, p. 65; Gender Re-
port Card on the International Criminal Court 2011, p. 85; Gender Report Card on the In-
ternational Criminal Court 2012, p. 60; Gender Report Card on the International Criminal
Court 2013, pp. 243, 254; Gender Report Card on the International Criminal Court 2014,
p. 277.
88
Ibid.
89
Salim A. Nakhjavani, “The Origins and Development of the Code of Conduct”, in Bergsmo,
Rackwitz and SONG (eds.), 2017, pp. 951–952, see above note 74.
to assist in setting up the OTP and the ICC as a whole in advance of Court
officials assuming office. 90 According to Salim Nakhjavani in his analysis
of the origins and development of the draft Code, the decision by the Ad-
vance Team to include a Code of Conduct within the draft Regulations of
the OTP and therefore at the outset of the work of the Office, was an effort
to “establish a universalised, virtues-based framework to guide behaviour
and to contribute to establishing a genuinely international, professional le-
gal culture within a nascent Office”. 91 Amongst other features, the original
draft of the Code included the provision for an in-house adviser for stand-
ards of conduct. 92 Far from envisaged as a set of rules, the draft Code of
Conduct was intended to “unify the vision and harmonise the activities” 93
of a diverse body of staff members and ultimately to cultivate “coherence
between the being of prosecutors and the doing of prosecutions”. 94 Regret-
tably, although the Regulations were adopted by the first Prosecutor in Sep-
tember 2003, the OTP Code of Conduct was ignored for a decade until it
was promulgated by Prosecutor Bensouda in 2013 within her first 18
months in office, 95 although without the position of an in-house adviser. 96
Had it been adopted in a timely manner, the foresight of integrating a
Code of Conduct within the Regulations and at the outset of the OTP’s
work may have gone some way towards inoculating the Office from the
series of ethical issues that have confronted the OTP over the past 17 years,
or perhaps at least provided a framework for corrective action. 97 As noted
by Nakhjavani, with respect to the OTP, “effective, binding ethical and pro-
fessional standards of conduct would have been indispensable from an ear-
ly stage”. 98
90
Bergsmo, 2017, p. 2, see above note 74.
91
Nakhjavani, 2017, p. 962, see above note 89.
92
Ibid., p. 957.
93
Ibid., p. 955.
94
Ibid., p. 954.
95
Ibid., p. 952.
96
Ibid., p. 958.
97
See, for example, ibid., p. 952, fns. 5 and 6; Morten Bergsmo, Wolfgang Kaleck, Sam Mul-
ler and William H. Wiley, “A Prosecutor Falls: Time of the Court to Rise”, FICHL Policy
Brief Series No. 86 (2017), Torkel Opsahl Academic EPublisher, Brussels, 2017 (https://
www.toaep.org/pbs-pdf/86-four-directors/); Women’s Initiatives for Gender Justice, Gender
Report Cards on the International Criminal 2005-2014, 2018; Women’s Initiatives for Gen-
der Justice, “A critical time for the ICC’s credibility”, 2 October 2017.
98
Nakhjavani, 2017, p. 953, see above note 89.
99
ICC Statute, Article 42(1), see above note 2.
100
Bergsmo, 2018, p. 2, see above note 1.
101
Independent Expert Review, 2020, para. 202, see above note 85.
which it was attentive. There was an almost universal belief within the ICC,
amongst States Parties and other stakeholders, that the ICC’s legitimacy
would be achieved through the exercise of its jurisdiction alone, and not
also through its institutional integrity as a global publicly accountable insti-
tution. Its jurisdictional firepower was potentially formidable and perhaps a
little intoxicating, and the establishment of the Court was justifiably a
source of pride, excitement and anticipation.
Staff and external supporters wanted to close the ‘impunity gap’ 105
for the commission of international crimes as quickly as possible and ex-
pand the rule of law. Many were motivated by concern for the harm experi-
enced by victims of these crimes and the urgency to halt the ongoing com-
mission of mass violence. Some wanted to see how this new institution
would interface with the global peace and security agenda, its potential to
advance human rights more broadly and its effect, if any, on the pursuit of
accountability within the existing world order. A wide array of legitimate
and genuine motivations fuelled the significant expectations on the Court
when it was first established and may have added to the pressure to pro-
duce unrealistic results.
As early as August 2004, the CBF declared that the ICC was now
moving from the “start-up phase”, which they described as “designing sys-
tems and recruiting personnel”, into “an operational phase”. 106 The follow-
ing year, the staff strategy unit within the OTP was abolished because “the
initial stage of creating staff policies and guidelines was nearing its end”. 107
These decisions appeared to be somewhat premature given both the OTP
and the Court as a whole were in the throes of a voluminous hiring process.
For example, between March 2004 and August 2006, the number of ICC
staff members grew from 177 to 441 positions with a total of 624 posts ap-
proved for recruitment by the end of the 2006 financial year. 108 With insuf-
105
A term coined by Morten Bergsmo in 2002 which has become widely used in the interna-
tional justice field. Bergsmo, 2017, pp. 14–15, see above note 74.
106
ICC-ASP/3/18, para. 34, see above note 103.
107
ICC, Report of the Committee on Budget and Finance on the work of its fifth session, 21
October 2005, ICC-ASP/4/27, para. 37 (‘ICC-ASP/4/27’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/
gz9soy/).
108
ICC, Reports of the Committee on Budget and Finance, 19 August 2004, ICC-ASP/3/22,
para. 20 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/l66zci/); ICC-ASP/4/3, 15 April 2005, para. 45;
ICC, Report of the Committee on Budget and Finance on the work of its seventh session, 1
November 2006, ICC-ASP/5/23, para. 39 (‘ICC-ASP/5/23’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/
doc/l66zci/). These figures are based on staff employed by the ICC on fixed term contracts
ficient staff policies, training and workplace procedures in place and with
little time to establish the internal environment, operating methods, and
ethical culture, the ICC was propelled towards exercising its mandate.
A reconstruction of the timeline demonstrates how quickly the ICC’s
jurisdiction was activated. The Rome Statute came into force on 1 July
2002. The first set of judges to the ICC was elected in February 2003 and
quickly sworn in at the seat of the Court, in The Hague on 11 March of the
same year. A short time later, the Prosecutor was sworn in on 16 June 2003,
and the Registrar was appointed and sworn in by the judges on 3 July 2003.
Within six months of these appointments, the ICC received its first refer-
ral, 109 and by March 2005, the OTP had received four referrals from States
and non-States Parties within a 14-month period. 110
The Court faced mounting and unrealistic expectations, many of
which the OTP itself fostered and encouraged, including through its budget
projections to the CBF. At times, these submissions appeared to greatly ex-
aggerate the speed of its investigations, its readiness for trials and its pre-
diction about the length of the legal proceedings. 111 Inaccurate early projec-
tions would not ordinarily be worthy of attention. An error in assessment
does not demonstrate unreliability and mistakes are inevitable in undertak-
ings as audacious as the mandate of the ICC. But bold pronouncements by
the Prosecutor throughout the first decade often over-estimated the prepar-
edness of the OTP. They also seemed to be regularly at odds with effective
prosecutorial strategy and good management, as suggested by the results of
the cases launched during this period. In hindsight, these projections also
suggest four noteworthy aspects associated with the Prosecutor’s assertions.
First, there was a ready audience amongst stakeholders for ambitious
pronouncements by the Prosecutor, and in this area, he would not disap-
and exclude those hired on general temporary assistance, consultants, as well as interns and
visiting fellows.
109
ICC, The Prosecutor v. Dominic Ongwen, Case information Sheet, 16 December 2003, ICC-
PIDS-CIS-UGA-02-018/20 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/sn4msm/).
110
Referral by the Government of Uganda, 16 December 2003; referral by the Democratic Re-
public of the Congo, 3 March 2004; referral by the Government of the Central African Re-
public, 21 December 2004; referral by the United Nations Security Council of the situation
in Darfur, Sudan, 31 March 2005, UNSC Resolution 1593.
111
ICC-ASP/3/18, para. 35, see above note 103. “Situation 1, with a single case, would be
ready for trial in January 2005 and would last eight months. Investigations for two cases in
situation 2 would continue until May 2005, at which time they would be ready for trial. Tri-
als in situation 2 would continue for the rest of 2005”.
point. Although there is evidence that some people urged caution and en-
couraged the Prosecutor to take the time to build the institution, 112 the
Prosecutor, himself, believed that “the institution would be built through
activity, by doing cases and demonstrating that the Court could func-
tion”. 113 He felt he needed to show results as quickly as possible, 114 and
this was fuelled by the genuine intentions of supporters of the Court and
the indisputable needs of victims of mass crimes.
Second, the impulse to make extravagant statements appeared to sig-
nal a pattern of bravado that came to be associated with the Prosecutor and
many of the decisions of his office, some of which are considered to have
compromised the reputation of the Court with respect to the OTP’s prose-
cutorial performance. 115
Third, the decision-making by the Prosecutor and the Executive
Committee set an investigative and prosecutorial pace that the OTP (and
the Court) was ill-prepared for substantively, as well as in relation to its
staff levels and working methods. This extended to and impacted the or-
ganizational development of the Office.
Finally, in responding to these assertions, States Parties demonstrated
an appetite for public aggrandizement and an inclination to forego critical
evaluation. Concurrently, States also displayed a willingness to overlook
the Prosecutor’s professional conduct as an international civil servant, ei-
ther because they were not personally disturbed by it or because any indi-
vidual failings paled in comparison to the importance of the Court. 116
112
Alex Whiting, “Investigations and Institutional Imperatives at the International Criminal
Court”, in Martha Minow, C. Cora True-Frost and Alex Whiting (eds.), The First Global
Prosecutor: Promise and Constraints, University of Michigan Press, Ann Arbor, 2015,
p. 103. “Six months after my beginning I received a referral from Uganda. And some people
were advising me, be careful, you have to build an institution for the next two centuries. I
knew I had to run. I had to show very quickly, some outcome, some results”.
113
Ibid.
114
Ibid.
115
See, for example, Bergsmo, Kaleck, Muller and Wiley, 2017, see above note 97; Bergsmo,
2017, pp. 21–31, see above note 74; Scott Horton, “Unimaginable Atrocities: Six Questions
for William Schabas”, in Harpers Blog, 18 May 2012; Brigid Inder, “Launch of the Gender
Report Card for 2010”, Women’s Initiatives for Gender Justice, 6 December 2010; Women’s
Initiatives for Gender Justice, Gender Report Card on the International Criminal Court
2012, pp. 132–163; Women’s Initiatives for Gender Justice, Gender Report Card on the In-
ternational Criminal Court 2014, pp. 157–193.
116
Conversations with diplomats and civil society organizations on file with the author.
The first Prosecutor has been the subject of significant critique and
criticism, much of it arguably warranted and justified. But his decisions,
actions and conduct, while part of his professional responsibility as the
Prosecutor, existed within a system that allowed and enabled these factors
to occur. A balanced view of the Prosecutor immediately recognizes that he
brought significant energy and dynamism to the role and displayed an inde-
fatigable ability to generate ideas, interest and prosecutorial activity. His
personal communication and rapport-building skills were an undeniable
asset in his interactions with States Parties, NGOs and the media; his will-
ingness to be the public face of the ICC provided a ready focal point for a
court that may otherwise have seemed even more remote and unknowable.
The Prosecutor’s ability to inspire young people and their interest in inter-
national justice as well as his intuitive understanding of the allure of his
office and the associated ability to engage influencers and celebrities added
to the sense of momentum, purpose and global visibility of the Court. As
asserted in the Reckoning, one of the films made about the ICC and the
Prosecutor, he perhaps did more than anyone to put the Court on the
map. 117 However, if true, having galvanized attention, the Prosecutor was
unable to deliver on his promises to an expectant global audience.
Less ambition would not have been better. Timidity was not the way
forward for a new Court. But the provision of a counter-balance by States
Parties – insisting upon institution-building; being less focused on numbers
(of cases and arrest warrants) in favour of quality; requiring conduct befit-
ting international civil servants; using their oversight responsibilities to en-
sure a solid framework of ethical standards and compliance benchmarks;
and being prepared to use their statutory obligations to address miscon-
duct – could have brought some equilibrium to the Court and reduced the
gap between the expectations generated and the outcomes that materialized.
It would also have safeguarded the Court’s institutional integrity.
It is understandable that the ICC would assume a high level of focus
on its mandate. However, it is difficult for the Court to justify its almost
exclusive focus on the exercise of its jurisdiction with insufficient attention
also devoted to creating a solid and ethical foundation, ensuring the integri-
ty and sustainability of the institution and a reliable base from which it
could fulfil its jurisdictional responsibilities.
117
Pamela Yates and Paco de Onis, The Reckoning: The Battle for the International Criminal
Court, Skylight 2009; Whiting, 2015, see above note 112.
118
See M.E. Newhouse, “Institutional Corruption: A Fiduciary Theory”, in Cornell Journal of
Law and Public Policy, 2014, vol. 23, no. 3, Article 2, p. 560.
119
See, for example, Amy Rees Anderson, “Good Employees Make Mistakes, Great Leaders
Allow Them To”, Forbes, 17 April 2013; Brené Brown, Dare to Lead, Random House, 2018.
120
Karim A.A. Khan, “Integrity and the Limits of Internal Oversight Mechanisms”, CILRAP, 2
December 2018, at 14-14.18 minutes (www.cilrap.org/cilrap-film/181202-khan/).
121
Becker, Blasberg and Pieper, 2017; EIC Network, 2017; Maupas, 2017; Thompson, 2017,
see above note 18. In 2017, a series of media reports revealed allegations regarding improp-
er and potentially unlawful activity by the former Prosecutor, Moreno-Ocampo, and staff
employed by the OTP. The allegations involved the provision of confidential information
about the OTP’s ongoing investigation in Libya, by staff of the OTP, to Moreno-Ocampo
based on its relevance to one of his clients, a Libyan national. Amongst several issues, the
media reports also allege that OTP staff members provided communication and other assis-
tance to the former Prosecutor in relation to this same client. It is also alleged that the former
Prosecutor may have attempted to intervene in the OTP’s cases in the Kenya Situation.
122
Ibid.
123
Ibid.
124
Ibid.
125
Administrative Tribunal of the International Labour Organization (‘ILOAT’), A. v. ICC,
Judgment No. 4003, paras. 15 and 17 (‘Judgment No. 4003’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/
doc/iu7r5q/).
126
ILOAT, F. v. ICC, Judgment No. 3907, para. 26 (‘Judgment No. 3907’) (https://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/w87k12/).
127
Women’s Initiatives for Gender Justice, Gender Report Card on the International Criminal
Court 2013, pp. 235–241 (‘Gender Report Card 2013’).
128
ILOAT, Judgment No. 2757, paras. 2–20 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/73bd48/).
129
Judgment No. 4003, para. 16, see above note 125.
130
Ibid.
131
The Court’s report is no longer on the ICC web site; Gender Report Card 2013, pp. 238–241,
see above note 127.
involvement of the President of the ASP, and a few States Parties that
strongly urged the Court to address these issues and whose interventions
were triggered by civil society, the Court did not appear to have taken any
serious action to investigate and determine the systemic issues enabling the
rape of witnesses by ICC staff members. 132 States were alerted to this crisis
in a letter by civil society submitted to the Presidents of the ASP and the
Court along with a small number of selected States Parties, drawing their
attention to the serious incident and calling for an independent inquiry. 133
The prompt action of the ASP President and States successfully invoked a
response from the Court.
The second exception was the OTP’s response to the numerous alle-
gations made in the media between September and October 2017 involving
the former Prosecutor and two OTP staff members. 134 The current Prosecu-
tor referred these issues to the IOM for investigation as well as to the Dis-
ciplinary Advisory Board whose review and recommendations ultimately
resulted in the dismissal of the staff members involved for serious miscon-
duct. 135 A summary of the OTP’s response to the specific allegations as
well as steps taken by the office to strengthen standards of integrity and
personal conduct was presented to States Parties in The Hague Working
Group in November 2018 and subsequently made available to States Par-
ties in the context of the ASP later that same year. 136
However, for the most part, the Court, with the complicit agreement
of other stakeholders, has generally taken the position that acknowledging
and addressing wrongdoing would undermine the ICC’s reputation; and, as
a result, its pattern over many years has been to ignore, deny, conceal or
deflect. The challenge with this approach is that it further embeds impro-
priety into the organizational culture and prolongs the vulnerability of these
episodes for the Court because inevitably, as has been demonstrated by the
series of media revelations, these issues will eventually be exposed. While
132
Ibid., pp. 235–241.
133
Ibid., pp. 235–237. Letter from the Women’s Initiatives for Gender Justice.
134
Becker, Blasberg and Pieper, 2017; EIC Network, 2017; Maupas, 2017; Thompson, 2017,
see above note 18.
135
ICC, Briefing by the Prosecutor, 14 November 2018, ICC-ASP/17/INF.5, paras. 18, 24(a),
24(c) (‘Prosecutor’s Briefing’).
136
Ibid.; see also comments by Deputy Prosecutor, James Stewart, “The Legal Requirement of
Individual Integrity and the Prosecution of International Crimes”, CILRAP Film, The Hague,
1 December 2018 (https://www.cilrap.org/cilrap-film/181201-stewart/).
they exist, they are ripe for exploitation by those who may want to discredit
the Court. As many institutions, governments and private sector leaders
have learned the hard way, cover-ups, obfuscation and dishonesty are often
more damaging to public trust than the original error.
In addition to affecting its external reputation, integrity issues are al-
so demoralizing for ICC staff, 137 who are predominantly rule compliant and
exercise their personal ethics within the workplace. But they also take their
cues from those higher up. The ethical culture of an institution affects the
ability of good people to do the right thing. 138 This becomes increasingly
challenging when there are no consequences or inadequate consequences
for violations, or when the violations involve senior leaders and Court offi-
cials. A lack of healthy accountability both for individuals and the institu-
tion is one of the hallmarks of an ethically fragile system.
8.6.2. Checks and Balances
Leadership and oversight of the ICC are responsibilities shared between the
Court and States Parties. Put simply, the ICC, specifically through the
heads of organs, is responsible for the day-to-day leadership, decisions and
operations of the Court, whereas States, through the ASP, are responsible
for the overall governance of the ICC.
With respect to the Court’s functions, it has been slow and unrespon-
sive to the usual checks and balances essential to the effective internal
oversight of a complex organization. At times, these mechanisms have
lacked rigour and during critical periods for the Court, the independence of
the internal oversight mechanisms has been compromised or they have
been unable to fulfil their mandates. Similarly, the ASP and its key subsidi-
ary bodies have been narrowly focused with respect to their governance
responsibilities with the exception of the annual forensic budget review
process. Although the ASP adopted resolutions regulating the Court, it has
done little to monitor the Court’s compliance with the legal framework. It
has also consistently ignored and underfunded the oversight system.
137
Bergsmo, 2018, p. 1, see above note 1.
138
See, for example, Caterina Bulgarella, “Why good words can produce bad acts”, in FCPA
Blog, 26 June 2018.
142
ICC-ASP/4/4, para. 10, see above note 141.
143
Ibid., Annex 1, para. 7(i).
144
Ibid., Annex 1, para. 4(ii).
145
Ibid., Annex 1, para. 4(iv).
146
Ibid., Annex 1, para. 4(iii).
147
Ibid.
148
Ibid., Annex 1, para. 4(ii): “The Oversight Committee authorizes the dissemination of audit
reports, except for those requested by the Committee on Budget and Finance pursuant to
paragraph 29 of the report on the work of its third session, August 2003, or those requested
by the Assembly of States Parties”.
ated the potential to reduce the oversight of the Court’s institutional activi-
ties by the Assembly.
The stated intention of the Oversight Committee was to enhance co-
operation between the organs and the OIA. However, the provisions in the
Charter assigned a significant level of power to the heads of organs with
respect to the focus, findings and reporting of the internal audits. Although
the Charter was undertaken by the OIA in good faith, the use of the provi-
sions by the heads of organs marked a negative turning point for the Office
that contributed to undermining its full independence and curtailing the
robust exercise of its mandate.
Simultaneously in 2005, as the Court was establishing the Oversight
Committee, the External Auditor recommended the establishment of an
independent Audit Committee. 149 This recommendation was echoed by the
CBF. 150 It seems that the instigation of an Oversight Committee created by
the heads of organs and the recommendation to establish an Audit Commit-
tee by the Auditor and CBF were on two separate tracks with distinct and
different motivations. The former appears to have been intended to contain
the work and scrutiny of the OIA, reduce its independence, and avert its
ability to report to the ASP and the CBF on all of its findings. The intention
of the latter appears to have been to strengthen the ICC’s internal controls,
add further expertise and independence, and to work with the OIA. This
divergence led to an impasse between the ASP and the Court with respect
to the independent functioning of the OIA, and the expertise required on
the Oversight and Audit Committees to support these most fundamental
and important components of the system of internal oversight.
As early as 2006, major tensions had reportedly arisen between the
OIA and the heads of organs with the latter wanting to limit the OIA’s abil-
ity to report major findings of its internal audits to the CBF and ASP. 151
Observing these tensions, the CBF noted that:
While it was satisfied that the Office of Internal Audit had
now fully assumed its functions as confirmed by a peer review
carried out by the National Audit Office, the Committee could
not escape the impression that the relationship between the
Court and the Office of Internal Audit was adversely affected
149
ICC-ASP/4/27, para. 13, see above note 107.
150
Ibid.
151
ICC-ASP/5/23, para. 26, see above note 108.
152
Ibid., para. 25.
153
Ibid., para. 26.
154
Ibid., para. 27.
155
ICC-ASP/6/7, p.4, see above note 141.
156
Ibid., p. 5.
157
Ibid.
158
ICC, Report of the Committee on Budget and Finance on the work at its ninth session, 28
September 2007, ICC-ASP-6/12, para. 21 (‘ICC-ASP-6/12’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/
doc/1eamh2/).
159
Ibid., para. 22.
160
Ibid.
161
Ibid.
162
ICC, Amendments to the Finance Regulations and Rules, Assembly of State Parties Resolu-
tion, adopted on 14 December 2007, ICC-ASP/6/Res.5 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/
3a62e0).
Lastly, the CBF recommended that the OIA focus its work on provid-
ing the Registrar, as the ICC’s accounting officer, with assurances and ad-
vice regarding the effectiveness of the management and control systems. 163
Combined with the other changes, this had the effect of pulling the OIA too
close to the Registry and increasing the communication and eventual influ-
ence of the Registrar on the work of the OIA. In practice, the OIA came to
‘report’ to the Registrar by default, especially following the collapse of the
Audit Committee between 2012 and 2016, and in the absence of effective
oversight by the CBF. This further reduced the level of independence nor-
mally expected of an internal audit office.
These far-reaching changes were taken further by the Audit Commit-
tee in August 2008 when the heads of organs revised the Terms of Refer-
ence for the Audit Committee and established a model which according to
the CBF “differed from the one recommended previously by the External
Auditors, the ASP and the Committee on Budget and Finance” and ensured
that the balance of power was firmly with the heads of organs. 164 Contra-
dicting the 2006 recommendations from the Auditor and the CBF that the
Audit Committee should be composed of a majority of external members
and chaired by an external member, the Court insisted upon the composi-
tion of three Court members (the Principals) and two external members. 165
Going even further, the Court insisted that it would appoint the two exter-
nal members. 166 In addition, whereas the model advocated by the CBF
would provide “advice to management and add independent oversight to
the audit function”, according to the CBF the Audit Committee established
by the Court, “‘was a management committee with some external mem-
bers”. 167
All of these changes appear to demonstrate a level of determination
on the part of the principals, to strip the OIA of any independence and curb
the activities, scope, findings and dissemination of its reports. The OIA was
163
ICC-ASP-6/12, para. 22, see above note 158.
164
ICC, Report of the Committee on Budget and Finance on the work of its eleventh session,
31 October 2008, ICC-ASP/7/15, para. 24 (‘ICC-ASP/7/15’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/
doc/1q3lhk/).
165
Ibid., para. 25.
166
ICC, Report of the Committee on Budget and Finance on the work of its tenth session, 26
May 2008, ICC-ASP/7/3, para. 19 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/oe4mh7/).
167
ICC-ASP/7/15, para. 25, see above note 164.
the only internal mechanism providing any kind of oversight and acting as
a control function within the Court until 2016.
Failure to safeguard the independence and impartiality of the OIA
appears to have been one of the significant stumbling blocks for the ICC
regarding its institutional integrity. Many of the unlawful and unethical is-
sues it has faced may have been averted, and/or identified earlier had the
full independence of the OIA been preserved. The harm caused to the Court
by the patterns of impropriety, mostly by Court officials and senior manag-
ers, may have been reduced, and a culture of accountability could have
been fostered, had the OIA been properly supported and enabled to fulfil its
mandate.
The Audit Committee ceased to operate in 2012 and was formally
terminated in 2014. 168 New Terms of Reference were drafted by an ad hoc
Committee, and a new composition of membership was designed com-
prised of only external members and members of the CBF. 169 The Audit
Committee was reconstituted in 2015 and became operational with a new
charter in 2016. 170 Finally, after 13 years of ICC operations, the ASP insti-
gated a dedicated entity with responsibilities for: governance; risk man-
agement; values and ethics; internal control framework; oversight of inter-
nal and external audit; and financial statements and public accountability
reporting. 171
With the restoration of a credible structure for the Audit Committee,
the OIA now reports to this body. 172 In 2014, the OIA was elevated to a ma-
168
ICC, Report of the Committee on Budget and Finance on the work of its twenty-third ses-
sion, ICC-ASP/13/15, 18 November 2014, paras. 132–135 (‘ICC-ASP/13/15’) (https://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/iv9xys/). It was subsequently disbanded on 13 February 2015 by
Presidential Directive, ICC-ASP/PRESD/G/2015/001 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/
75fbb6/).
169
ICC, Report of the Committee on Budget and Finance on the work of its twenty-fifth, Char-
ter of the Audit Committee, 9 November 2015, ICC-ASP/14/15, Annex IV, Section E, pa-
ra. 10 (‘ICC-ASP/14/15’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/575aqd/).
170
Ibid., Section C, 2, paras. 140–141; ICC, Official Records of the Assembly of States Parties,
ICC-ASP/14/20, vol. II, Part B, B.3 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/156059/).
171
ICC, Charter of the Audit Committee, annexed to Report of the Committee on Budget and
Finance on the work of its Twenty-Fifth session, 9 November 2015, ICC-ASP/14/15, Sec-
tion B, paras. 2–3 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/575aqd/).
172
ICC, Resolution on the Programme budget for 2016, the Working Capital Fund and the Con-
tingency Fund for 2016, scale of assessments for the apportionment of expenses of the In-
ternational Criminal Court and financing appropriations for 2016, 26 November 2015, ICC-
jor programme within the Court’s budget with its own dedicated budget
line, further underscoring its independence. 173 The Audit Committee ap-
proves and monitors implementation of the OIA’s annual audit plans. In
practice, the agreement of the head of organ is still required to enable the
OIA to proceed with an audit into areas under their authority and leadership.
Their co-operation with the audits is an important part of the process.
With the active oversight being exercised by the Audit Committee,
the OIA has been directed to implement a significant backlog of urgent au-
dit recommendations. Since its re-establishment, the Audit Committee has
implored the Court to: provide the OIA with the timely information it needs
to perform its mandate: co-operate with it in addressing the high number of
unimplemented audit recommendations; 174 do more with respect to risk
management; 175 and allow the OIA to attend decision-making meetings
when issues of risk management and governance are discussed. 176 In re-
sponse, the ICC has made some concessions but mostly declined these
suggestions.
The Audit Committee has a critical role to play in raising the ethical
standards of the ICC as an international public institution through the pro-
vision of impartial, principled and objective oversight. The challenge for
the Committee will be in finding the right balance between respectful and
open communication with Court officials in which it is sincerely receptive
to the genuine challenges faced by the Court. At the same time, it is com-
pelled to remain objective and impervious to the ongoing reluctance dis-
played by the ICC with respect to addressing issues of risk management,
amongst other areas. It must also remain vigilant in exercising its own in-
dependent assessments rather than simply echoing or relying upon the CBF,
given this Committee has acquiesced to the demands of Court officials on
more than one occasion, whilst also recognizing the significant expertise of
this Committee, its institutional knowledge and its proximity to the detail
of the budget issues. The Audit Committee’s credibility and that of the
Court are closely aligned.
8.6.2.2. Independent Oversight Mechanism
Complementing the OIA, is the IOM. Article 112(4) of the Rome Statute
stipulates that:
The Assembly may establish such subsidiary bodies as may be
necessary, including an independent oversight mechanism for
inspection, evaluation and investigation of the Court, to en-
hance the efficiency and economy.
First proposed in 2005 by the ASP President, Ambassador Prince Zeid Al-
Hussein, a mandate establishing an IOM with investigative, evaluation and
inspection functions was eventually adopted by the ASP at its eighth ses-
sion in 2009. 177 However, it took until 2013 for the ASP to adopt a resolu-
tion establishing the operational components and parameters of its three-
pronged mandate; 178 and until 2015 for the IOM to be operational with the
hiring of a head of office. It took a further two years for the IOM to be fully
operational with the hiring of all of its designated staff positions. 179 It was,
therefore, not until 2017 that the ICC finally had in place a mechanism that
could address issues of misconduct and serious misconduct allegedly
committed by elected officials, staff, and contractors of the ICC. 180
The primary initial obstruction to the creation of the IOM emanated
from the OTP, specifically the Prosecutor, the Executive Committee, and
senior policy staff. The OTP’s opposition to the mechanism was active be-
hind the scenes for several years before coming into full view at the eighth
session of the ASP in 2009. As with earlier responses to oversight and ac-
countability initiatives, the main reason for the OTP’s opposition to the
proposed mandate of the IOM related to concerns about potential infringe-
ments upon the independence of the office. Specifically, the OTP argued
that: the IOM could interfere with the running of the Office and the Prose-
cutor’s autonomy over its management; the IOM’s proprio motu powers to
177
ICC-ASP/8/Res.1, see above note 65.
178
ICC, Independent Oversight Mechanism, 27 November 2013, ICC-ASP/12/Res.6 (‘ICC-
ASP/12/Res.6’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/64ebeb/).
179
Report of the Committee on Budget and Finance on the works of its twenty-ninth session, 3
November 2017, ICC-ASP/16/15, para. 136 (‘ICC-ASP/16/15’) (https://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/n4gove/).
180
ICC-ASP/8/Res.1, para. 6(c), see above note 65.
181
For a discussion on these issues, see Max du Plessis and Christopher Gevers, “The Inde-
pendent Oversight Mechanism Argument is not merely about Administration Functions, but
is Situated in a Boarder Debate Over the Role of the Assembly of States Parties”, ICCForum,
6 May 2011 (available on its web site); and ICCForum, Invited Experts on Oversight Ques-
tion, May –September 2011 (available on its web site).
182
Within civil society organizations, the American Coalition of NGOs for the ICC and the
Women’s Initiatives for Gender Justice were amongst the earliest, most vocal and most con-
sistent supporters of the IOM. See, for example, Women’s Initiatives for Gender Justice,
Gender Report Card on the International Criminal Court 2009, p. 35; Gender Report Card
on the International Criminal Court 2010, pp.71-72; Gender Report Card on the Interna-
tional Criminal Court 2011, pp. 339–340; Gender Report Card on the International Crimi-
nal Court 2012, pp. 285–287; Gender Report Card on the International Criminal Court
2013, pp. 17–24, 243-244; Gender Report Card on the International Criminal Court 2014,
pp. 17–27, 269-270.
183
See, for example, Human Rights Watch, “Memorandum for the Ninth Session of the ICC
Assembly of States Parties”, 16 November 2010, Section II, B; and International Federation
for Human Rights (‘FIDH’), “Position Paper Ninth Session of the ICC Assembly of State
Parties”, 30 November 2010, No. 551a, p. 18.
184
du Plessis and Gevers, 2011, see above note 181. It was widely known amongst civil society
advocates that the President and the Registrar did not support the OTP’s position that the
approval of a head of organ was necessary prior to the IOM initiating an investigation.
185
Conversations with diplomats on file with the author.
186
Becker, Blasberg and Pieper, 2017; EIC Network, 2017; Maupas, 2017; Thompson, 2017,
see above note 18.
187
Prosecutor’s Briefing, 2020, paras. 40–42, 45-47, see above note 135; Independent Experts
Review, 2020, paras. 256, R106, see above note 85.
188
Report of the Committee on Budget and Finance on the work of its thirtieth session, 31 May
2018, ICC-ASP/17/5, Annex II, p. 43 (‘ICC-ASP/17/5’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/
3037jc/).
189
ICC-ASP/16/15, Annex V, paras. 35,36, see above note 179; Report of the Committee on
Budget and Finance on its work of the thirty-first session, 29 October 2018, ICC-ASP/17/15,
Annex VI, para. 28 (‘ICC-ASP/17/15’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/34xy2r/).
190
See, for example, Lynn S. Paine, “Managing for Organizational Integrity”, in Harvard Busi-
ness Review, March-April 1994 Issue; Caterina Bulgarella, “Why good words can produce
bad acts”, in The FCPA Blog, 26 June 2018.
191
ICC-ASP/3/18, para. 15, see above note 103.
192
ICC-ASP/15/15, para. 198, see above note 174.
193
ICC Administrative Instruction, Risk Management, 31 March 2017, ICC/AI/2017/003 (‘AI-
Risk Management’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/e928d8).
194
International Organization for Standardization (ISO), Risk management — Principles and
guidelines, November 2009, ISO 31000:2009.
195
ICC-ASP/17/15, Annex VI, Section B, para. 8, see above note 189.
196
AI-Risk Management, para. 1.4, see above note 193.
197
Report of the Committee on Budget and Finance on the work of its thirty-first session, 2
October 2018, ICC-ASP/17/15, Advance version, para. 93 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/
oz48xe/); ICC-ASP/16/15, para. 196, see above note 179.
198
International Criminal Court Bar Association, “Legal Analysis: ICC Internal Accountability
Mechanisms and Policies”, ICCBA Legal Advisory Committee, February 2018.
199
ICC-ASP/15/15, Annex VII, Section II, para. 22, see above note 174.
200
Ibid., para. 19.
201
ICC-ASP/16/15, Annex V, Section II, paras. 11, 13, see above note 179.
202
ICC-ASP/4/4, para. 9, see above note 141; ICC-ASP/5/5, para. 11, see above note 141.
203
ICC, Assembly of States Parties, “Resolution of the Assembly of States Parties on the pro-
posed programme budget for 2019, the Working Capital Fund for 2019, the scale of assess-
ment for the apportionment of expenses of the International Criminal Court, financing ap-
propriations for 2019 and the Contingency Fund”, 12 December 2018, ICC-ASP/17/Res.4,
para. 1 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/obysgj/).
ics-oriented culture. The most recent and most striking example of this
leadership vacuum was with the Registry’s restructuring project (ReVision)
during which all three categories of ethical vulnerabilities were triggered
simultaneously.
8.7. Case Study: ReVision
ReVision was officially launched on 1 January 2014 and was completed on
31 July 2015. 204 During this 18-month period, the project surpassed any-
thing the Court had experienced before with respect to the volume and ra-
pidity of regulatory violations and breaches of ethical standards. ReVision
both exposed and took advantage of the weaknesses in the oversight and
governance system and brought the Court’s institutional integrity crisis to a
head.
This section will examine the restructuring project through an ethics
lens to assess whether the errors associated with ReVision were simply
genuine mistakes made within the context of an ambitious project or rise to
the threshold of institutional corruption.
The purpose of this case study is not to provoke paralysis or de-
spondency. Rather, it is to provide a clear diagnosis of the current status of
the ICC’s institutional integrity as motivation for change and transfor-
mation and to highlight the urgency of these issues. The ICC deserves our
forthright and sympathetic support as well as our candid and loyal criticism.
To examine this further, it is important to consider the tests of institu-
tional corruption and the definitions available to evaluate its existence.
Work in this relatively new field of research by ethicists and academics has
largely focused on public institutions, specifically institutional corruption
with respect to the legislative process of the US Congress, 205 as well as is-
sues of campaign finance of Congressional leaders and their decision-
making. 206
204
ICC, Audit Report of the ReVision Project of the International Criminal Court’s Registry, 9
November 2016, ICC-ASP/15/27, para. 10 (‘Audit Report of ReVision’) (https://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/80a7a5/); Comprehensive Report of the Reorganisation of the Registry of the
ICC, August 2016, p. 29 (‘Comprehensive Report’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/
cbc6cc/).
205
Dennis F. Thompson, Ethics in Congress: From Individual to Institutional Corruption,
Washington, DC, The Brookings Institution, 1995.
206
Lawrence Lessig, Republic, Lost: How Money Corrupts Congress- And a Plan to Stop It,
Twelve publishers, 5 October 2011.
Business Ethic”, in Journal of Business Ethics, Kluwer Academic Publishers, 2002, vol. 38,
pp. 119–131; Jan Tulberg, “Moral Compliance and the Concealed Charm of Prudence”, in
Journal of Business Ethics, 2009, vol. 89, pp. 599–612; and Lynn S. Paine, “Managing for
Organizational Integrity”, in Harvard Business Review, March-April 1994; Catherin Broad-
man and Vicki Klum, “Building Organisational Integrity”, in Peter Larmour and Nick Wola-
nin (eds.), Corruption and Anti-Corruption, ANU, 2013, pp. 82–96; Peter Roberts, A.J.
Brown and Jane Olsen, “Organisational Commitment”, in Peter Roberts, A.J. Brown and
Jane Olsen (eds.), Whistling While they Work: A good-practice guide for managing internal
reporting of wrongdoing in public sector organisations, ANU Press, 2011, pp. 17–35.
213
ICC Statute, Preamble, see above note 2
214
Audit Report of ReVision, paras. 15(a-h) and 16, see above note 204.
215
Ibid., para. 17.
216
Presentations by the Registrar to NGOs and States Parties; Conversations in 2013 with dip-
lomats on file with the author; Report of the Committee on Budget and Finance on its work
of its twenty-first session, 4 November 2013, ICC-ASP/12/15, para. 82 (https://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/kdybms/).
217
Presentations by the Registrar to NGOs and States Parties, respectively; conversations in
2013 with diplomats on file with the author.
218
ICC, Assembly of States Parties Resolution to the Rome Statute of ICC, adopted at the
twelfth plenary meeting on 27 November 2013, vol. I, part III, ICC-ASP/12/Res.1, Section
H, para. 3 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/7a9071/).
staff costs and 560 staff positions approved for 2014. 219 According to the
Audit Report of the ReVision Project of the International Criminal Court’s
Registry (the ‘Audit Report’) these objectives were changed at the follow-
ing ASP in December 2014, when the Assembly renewed the authorization
to reorganize the Registry but removed from the objectives, the intention to
generate savings and the need to eliminate duplication, increase efficiencies
and seek synergies with other organs. 220 That left, increasing efficiencies
within the Registry as the only formal objective of the restructuring.
However, the Official Records of the ASP in 2014 explain the objec-
tives differently and indicate that within the context of the restructuring, the
Registrar was tasked with continuing to identify savings “throughout the
[sic] 2014 and beyond”, to find additional synergies, as well as efficiencies,
and to report on these items, “after completion of the ReVision project”. 221
In contrast with the Audit Report of ReVision, there is a clear indication in
the Official Records that more than efficiencies were required and formed
part of the objective of the restructuring process.
Ambiguity about the objectives was reinforced by the Registrar who
at times asserted that savings were not a component of the ReVision project
whilst also continuing to talk to States Parties about savings up until two
months before the end of the project, including in the report on the results
of the restructuring submitted to States Parties on 4 May 2015. 222 It was
therefore understandable that most States Parties continued to expect sav-
ings as a result of the restructuring, 223 even though it was later claimed that
it had been eliminated as one of the formal objectives.
After ReVision was completed, the Registrar along with members of
his office, vehemently and repeatedly stated in meetings with NGOs and
219
Audit Report of ReVision, para. 6, see above note 204. The Audit Report notes that there
was a slight decrease in the approved budgets between 2014 (EUR 65,684,900,000) and
2015 (EUR 65,025,900,000). However, the critical figured approved by the ASP for the staff
costs related to the restructuring process was EUR 42,900,000. For clarity, see ICC, Official
Records, Fourteenth Session, ICC-ASP/14/20, 18-26 November 2015, vol. II, part B.2, pa-
ra. 10.
220
Audit Report of ReVision, paras. 6–8(a)(b), see above note 204.
221
Official Records of the Assembly of States Parties to the Rome Statute of the ICC, 8-17
December 2014, ICC-ASP/13/20, vol. I, Annex IV, Section F, para. 28 (https://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/8485ce).
222
ICC, Report on the review of the organizational structure of the Registry, 4 May 2015, ICC-
ASP/14/18, Executive Summary (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/omfqht/).
223
Conversations with diplomats in 2015 on file with the author.
States Parties, respectively, that savings in the Registry’s budget had never
been an objective of the restructuring. 224 Whilst a level of ambiguity about
this objective may have emerged, it was not accurate to deny its existence,
as indicated in the Official Records. In addition, the Registrar had actively
kept this probability alive, and in the minds of many States Parties it re-
mained a highly desirable expectation. Their assumptions on this issue
were abruptly refocused when the Registry submitted its post-restructuring
budget for 2016 requesting a 26 percent increase in funding to implement
the new structure designed as a result of the re-organization. 225
According to experts in the field of institutional corruption, setting
ambiguous and confusing workplace objectives and/or unrealistic expecta-
tions can facilitate an environment in which those responsible for meeting
the objectives may resort to exaggeration, carelessness or misrepresenta-
tion. 226
The ambiguity of the objectives and the creation of confusing or un-
realistic expectations by both States Parties and the Registrar was an im-
portant precursor, amongst other factors, with respect to the credibility of
the process and the manner in which this project was implemented.
8.7.2. Examination
Three specific decisions provide compelling examples against which to
apply the five test questions and transparency elements with respect to ex-
amining potential institutional corruption.
8.7.2.1. Decision 1: Circumventing Recruitment Policies
The Registrar established a Project Team comprised of three external
members and five internal members, all from within the Registry. 227 Later
224
Conversations with non-governmental organizations and diplomats on file with the author;
Women’s Initiatives for Gender Justice, “An Examination of the Registry’s 2016 Budget and
implications of the ReVision Project”, 17 September 2015, p. 11 (‘Examination of the Reg-
istry’s 2016 Budget’).
225
ICC-ASP/14/15, para. 53, see above note 169.
226
See Lynn S. Paine, “Managing for Organizational Integrity”, in Harvard Business Review,
1994; David Lehman and Rangaraj, “Selectivity in Organisational Rule Violations”, in The
Academy of Management Review, 2009, vol. 34, no. 4, pp. 643–657; Newhouse, 2014,
pp. 573–574, see above note 118.
227
Audit Report of ReVision, para. 10, see above note 204.
in the project, the internal members were increased to nine and included
staff from other organs of the Court. 228
According to the Audit Report of ReVision, the mandate of the Pro-
ject Team was to conduct audits of the structures and methods of the Regis-
try. 229 In assessing the decision to establish a project team, the Audit Report
noted that engaging an external audit or hiring a management consulting
firm, rather than the structure selected by the Registrar, would “clearly
have been better suited to a project as ambitious as ReVision whose terms
of reference laid down a wide-ranging scope of objectives”. 230 It also noted
that “it would probably have been at least as expensive as the solution se-
lected”. 231
According to the Audit Report, the Registrar considered several op-
tions and decided upon a hybrid model of a project team comprised of ex-
ternal experts and internal Registry staff. 232 The establishment of the pro-
ject team was part of a deliberative merit-based decision-making process,
and the model chosen was consistent with those utilised elsewhere for re-
organization processes. 233 It may have been a regrettable decision and in-
advisable, as indicated in the Audit Report, 234 but it was justifiable and not
unlawful.
However, in hiring the three external members of the Project Team
between November 2013 and January 2014, the Registrar violated the rules
governing recruitment that require all positions to be made on a competi-
tive basis. It also departed from the appropriate provision in the appendix
to the Staff Regulations, which states that selection panels ‘shall’ be estab-
lished. 235 Rather than complying with these well-established practices, all
of the external members of the project team were appointed directly by the
Registrar without “prior definition of role profiles, no call for applications
and no selection procedure”. 236
228
Ibid.
229
Ibid., para. 24.
230
Ibid., para. 31(b) and 32.
231
Ibid., para. 32.
232
Ibid., paras. 24, 25.
233
Ibid., para. 25.
234
Ibid., para. 32.
235
ICC Staff Regulations, appendix, para. 5, see above note 32.
236
Audit Report of ReVision, para. 25, see above note 204.
237
Ibid., para. 28.
238
Ibid.
239
Ibid., para. 29.
240
Only one member of the Project Team had previous experience in organizational restructur-
ing, and this was in relation to a relatively small re-organization project within a unit of the
ICTY. Conversations with former ICTY staff members in 2015 on file with the author.
241
Comprehensive Report, Foreword by the Registrar, pp. ix-x, August 2020, see above note
204.
242
Audit Report of ReVision, para. 29, see above note 204.
243
Ibid.
sion, another was recruited to the team from a junior post (P-2) at the ICTY,
and the third was in a mid-level management position at the STL. 244
Prior collegial relationships and other alliances may have also played
a role in other key appointments as well, including the recruitment of three
personnel within the Registry on the eve of, or early on in, the ReVision
project. Appointees to positions of the Head of Human Resources, the
Chief of the Legal Advisory Service Section and the Chief of Budget Sec-
tion, 245 were all individuals with whom the Registrar had worked at the
STL or was a fellow civil servant of the ministry of foreign affairs of the
host State. Each of these posts would subsequently feature prominently in
the restructuring process in roles that were instrumental to the project in the
core areas within which the meritocracy of the decision-making appears to
have been most questionable and the reliability of information least con-
vincing. The legal advice, human resource data and budget assumptions
with respect to ReVision are examined in the sub-sections ahead.
It is believed that questions were raised internally at the time of each
of these selections regarding the basis of their appointments in terms of the
prior professional experience and qualifications of the appointees. 246 Con-
cerns were also expressed about perceived anomalies in the recruitment
processes, including the extent to which, or whether, the Registrar had per-
sonally intervened in one or more of these appointments, possibly ignoring
the recommendations of the recruitment panel(s), which may have deemed
a candidate(s) unsuitable for interview.
244
Conversations with former ICC and ICTY staff on file with the author. In terms of State
representation on the team, the three external members were from Bulgaria, the Republic of
Ireland and the Netherlands.
245
The Budget Section was created as a result of the restructuring project. Prior to ReVision,
the functions of budget and finance operated together within one section. It would appear
that the appointment of Chief of Budget Section, whilst the restructuring was still underway
may have subverted the ‘priority candidate’ provision outlined in the Principles and Proce-
dures under which staff, whose posts were abolished, could apply for new positions created
within the Registry as a result of the restructuring, as well as other posts available within the
ICC. The Budget Section was a new section created by ReVision and similarly, the Chief of
Budget Section was a new position emerging from the restructuring project. At the time of
this appointment, the Registry was still undergoing the restructuring process and more than
110 staff were unaware that their posts would ultimately be abolished. This included staff
with potentially relevant financial and budget-related experience. Some of these individuals
may have qualified to apply for the Chief of Budget position but did not have the opportuni-
ty to contest this post because the position was filled before they were made aware that their
own posts were to be abolished.
246
Conversations with Registry staff on file with the author.
247
ICC, Principles and Procedures Applicable to Decisions Arising from the ReVision Project,
19 August 2014, ICC/INF/2014/011 (‘ICC/INF/2014/011’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/
36d086).
248
Ibid., Article 5.
249
ICC, Principles and Procedures Applicable to Decisions Arising from the ReVision Project,
13 June 2015, ICC/INF/2014/011 Rev.1 (‘ICC/INF/2014/011 Rev.1’) (https://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/d7a314).
250
ILOAT, Judgment No. 3907, para. 6, see above note 126.
ing to the ILOAT, the Registrar’s decision to promulgate the Principles and
Procedures by an Information Circular violated the Presidential Directive,
making the principles and the decisions derived from the application of the
principles “unlawful”:
As the promulgation of the Principles and Procedures by In-
formation Circular was in violation of the Presidential Di-
rective, they were without legal foundation and are, therefore,
unlawful as are the decisions taken pursuant to the Principles
and Procedures. 251
In effect, ReVision in its entirety was found by the ILOAT to be ille-
gal at its very foundations.
According to the same ILOAT judgment, the Principles and Proce-
dures included provisions which effectively changed some of the articles of
the ICC staff regulations and rules. Such significant policy changes are out-
side of the legal scope of an Information Circular. 252 The ICC asserted that
the Principles did not denote a change in the staff rules and regulations and
only applied to the Registry, and not to other ICC staff. 253 The ILOAT “re-
jected” this reasoning, 254 and noted that “a number of provisions within the
Principles and Procedures involve[d] regulatory matters”, 255 including sev-
eral substantive changes to the Staff Regulations. 256 In other ReVision-
related cases, the ILOAT also noted that several of the individual provi-
sions contradicted the ICC Staff Regulations and/or did not meet the stand-
ards of existing ILOAT jurisprudence, 257 including: the extension of ap-
pointments; 258 the enhanced agreed separation package; 259 and the ‘priority
candidate’ provision which did not meet the ICC’s obligation to explore
employment options prior to separation. 260
In addition, the ILOAT found that the changes to the Staff Regula-
tions outlined in the Principles, which were applicable only to decisions
251
Ibid., para. 26.
252
Ibid.
253
Ibid., paras. 13–15.
254
Ibid., para. 16.
255
Ibid., para. 17.
256
Ibid., paras. 18–23.
257
Ibid., para. 13.
258
Ibid., para. 18.
259
Ibid., paras. 19–24.
260
Ibid., paras. 13–19.
261
Ibid., para. 24.
262
Ibid., para. 25.
263
Ibid., para. 25.
264
Ibid., para. 25.
265
Ibid., para. 26.
266
ICC/INF/2014/011, see above note 247.
267
Comprehensive Report, p. 32, see above note 204. The timeline also indicates that in early
July, all Registry staff members were notified whether or not their post was to be abolished.
268
ICC/INF/2014/011, para. 5, see above note 247; ICC/INF/2014/011 Rev.1, para. 5, see
above note 249.
269
Ibid., para. 25.
270
Audit Report of ReVision, para. 66(a), see above note 204.
sions that violate the relevant legal framework. The procedural and legal
requirements were known, well established and available to the Registrar,
his team and the Project Board before, during and after each of the deci-
sions related to ReVision and at each of the six phases of the project.
8.7.3. Exercise of the Registrar’s Authority
In light of the serial breaches in the decision-making processes associated
with ReVision, it is relevant to consider the structure within which the Reg-
istrar functions. Article 43(2) of the Rome Statute states that:
The Registry shall be headed by the Registrar, who shall be
the principal administrative officer of the Court. The Registrar
shall exercise his or her functions under the authority of the
President of the Court.
The implementation of the restructuring project was, therefore, con-
ducted by the Registrar under the authority and oversight of the President.
Due to the conclusion of a presidential term during ReVision, two Presi-
dents were in office for different stages of the restructuring process. 282
They were, therefore, each responsible for the Registrar’s exercise of his
functions in relation to the specific ReVision activities which occurred
whilst they were in office.
The responsibility of the President of the ICC with respect to the ad-
ministration of the Court is underscored in Article 38(3)(a) of the Rome
Statute, which indicates that the President and the First and Second Vice-
Presidents of the Court are responsible for the proper administration of the
Court, with the exception of the Office of the Prosecutor.
On 24 June 2015, five Judges wrote to the Presidency expressing
concerns about the restructuring project, including its legality, cost, the po-
tential liability for the Court, the benefits of the exercise and the impact on
staff morale, amongst other issues. 283 In the letter, the Judges requested
that the project be suspended until these issues could be properly consid-
ered. On 24 July, the Presidency provided written reassurance to the Judges
282
President Song Sang-hyun was in office from 11 March 2009 – 11 March 2015; and Presi-
dent Silvia Fernández de Gurmendi was in office from 11 March 2015 – 11 March 2018.
283
ICC, Marc Perrin de Brichambaut, Sanji Monageng, Geoffrey Henderson, Chile Eboe-Osuji
and Cuno Tarfusser, “Concerns expressed by Judges on the ReVision project and request for
action to be taken”, 24 June 2015. These judges included the Presidents of the three Judicial
Divisions (Appeals, Trial and Pre-Trial); Audit Report of ReVision, para. 38, see above note
204.
in line with earlier material produced by the Registrar for States Parties,
regarding the legality of the process as well as the size and cost of the new
model of the Registry and reiterated the Registry’s claims about the impact
on the staff profile of the restructuring with respect to gender and geo-
graphical representation within the Registry. 284 The Presidency also shared
this communication with civil society networks. It was assumed that this
action was intended to inform and provide reassurance to a range of stake-
holders, including more than 110 staff within the Registry who by that time
had been notified that their posts were to be abolished in the second wave
of the restructuring.
With this endorsement, it was widely accepted and believed that the
process was legal. Despite questions about the legal underpinnings of the
restructuring, the cost and the lack of merit-based decision-making in fun-
damental aspects of the project, ReVision was resoundingly supported by
the Presidency, the senior leadership across the Court, as well as, resolutely
promoted and defended by States Parties. It had the seal of approval from
States Parties and the ICC President. Regardless of the questions and con-
cerns raised during the process, most stakeholders, including Registry staff,
assumed that the process must at least be legally compliant, even if it was
not being managed and implemented in a transparent and competent man-
ner. With the exception of the Registrar and the Chief of LASS, the extent
of the legal risks and violations were likely to have been largely unknown
to almost all other staff members and stakeholders until the issuance of
ILOAT decision 3907 in January 2018.
With recognition that the Registrar exercises his or her functions un-
der the authority of the President, and with presidential responsibility for
the proper administration of the Court, the Presidency held a positive obli-
gation to exercise oversight of the Registrar’s management of the ReVision
project. The mechanisms to do so existed. In addition to regular meetings
and updates between the President/Presidency and Registrar, the President
could have requested an IOM evaluation or investigation of the restructur-
ing project at various stages, or the Presidency could also have invited, in
284
ICC, Presidency note on the issues raised relating to the ReVision project, 24 July 2015,
paras. 4–15, 41-50, p.15; Audit Report of ReVision, para. 38, see above note 204. The Audit
Report of ReVision does not mention or address the Presidency’s note in response to the
judges’ letter, although it does make reference to the concerns raised by the five judges. Ex-
amination of the Registry’s 2016 Budget, 2015, pp. 2, 4, 8, 10, 11, 12, 14, 18, see above note
224.
co-operation with the CBF and/or the Audit Committee, an internal or ex-
ternal audit of the process. Utilizing one or more of these options may have
been a more appropriate response to the specific concerns raised in 2015 by
a number of fellow judges. It is unclear whether the President or Presiden-
cy were aware of the legal jeopardy for the Court regarding the Principles
and Procedures, prior to the ILOAT decision of January 2018. In spite of
the financial, legal and reputational risks, it seems evident that active steps
to ensure the proper administration of the Court were not taken.
8.7.4. Duty of Care and Treatment of Colleagues
States Parties were led to believe by the project team and in particular the
Registrar, that the concerns being raised about ReVision by staff within the
Registry were no more than the complaints and discomfort one would ex-
pect from employees going through a restructuring process. Substantive
concerns from staff were largely dismissed, and those who continued to
raise issues internally were problematized and ostracized. Most diplomats
amongst The Hague-based States Parties were unable to or chose not to
explore the concerns expressed by staff and did not seek verification of the-
se issues from other sources. Staff welfare in relation to the restructuring
process did not appear to be sufficiently or thoroughly considered in the
discussions amongst either internal or external stakeholders. With respect
to the treatment of Registry staff affected by ReVision, ILOAT judgments
to date have determined that the restructuring project amounted to: unequal
treatment for staff in general; 285 that the ICC had an obligation to deal fair-
ly with staff who occupied abolished positions and fell short of what was
required in specific areas; 286 subjected some individuals to specific experi-
ences of unequal treatment; 287 and failed in their duty of care. 288
Substantial concerns about ReVision including questions about the
veracity of the information being provided to the Court and States Parties
were often deflected by the Registrar and the States most closely involved
with the restructuring process. According to the Registrar, “undertaking a
reorganization doesn’t always make you very popular in organisations”. 289
Concerns raised, most of which have been subsequently vindicated by the
285
ILOAT, Judgment No. 3907, para. 24, see above note 126.
286
Ibid., paras. 16 and 19.
287
Ibid., para. 20.
288
Ibid., para. 21.
289
Video interview with the Robert H. Jackson Center, at 22:11 minutes.
ILOAT and other reviews, were perceived and bluntly filtered by the Regis-
trar through a personal, rather than a professional, lens. Whilst the Regis-
trar’s statement holds some truth in a general sense that restructuring pro-
jects are often inherently unpopular, the concerns raised about ReVision,
and later verified, were not about the popularity of the restructuring process
but rather, they reflected fundamental questions about the integrity of the
process and by implication, the institution.
8.7.5. Internal Oversight System
How did the ICC’s internal control system respond to ReVision? In the fol-
lowing sub-section, the role of three bodies will be sketched.
8.7.5.1. Office of Internal Audit
The prior weakening of the OIA and its proximity to the Registrar in the
absence of a functioning Audit Committee disempowered a key feature of
the Court’s minimalist internal control system. This had a significant im-
pact during the ReVision Project.
According to the Audit Committee, the OIA deviated from its preap-
proved audit plan for 2015 “as a consequence of the Registry’s reorganisa-
tion”. 290 The purpose of the OIA’s audit was to assess whether the ReVision
project plan was robust and in line with best practices in project manage-
ment with respect to the objective, planning, resources and the expected
benefits. It is apparent that undertaking a process audit whilst the restruc-
turing was ongoing would allow the project to incorporate findings and in-
tegrate any adjustments into the remainder of the process. This was a
much-needed safety valve enabling corrective action to be taken, if re-
quired, to ensure that the project was compliant and on track to achieve its
objectives. As with all internal audits, the OIA required the agreement of
the Registrar, as the head of organ, to be able to proceed with its work in
areas under their authority. On this occasion, it is clear from the Audit
Committee Report that the Registrar prevented the OIA from undertaking
an audit of ReVision; thus, it was forced to deviate from its preapproved
plan. The External Audit of ReVision, undertaken in 2016 after the comple-
tion of the project, did not identify this revealing and critical fact. It was
also not included in the Comprehensive Report on ReVision produced by
the Registry.
290
ICC-ASP/15/15, Annex VII, para. 28, see above note 174.
291
Conversations in 2015 with Registry staff and managers, on record with the author.
292
Ibid.
293
Ibid., The Head of Office assumed his duties on 15 October 2015.
294
Ibid.
295
ICC-ASP/12/Res.6, paras. 16, 18, see above note 178.
296
Women’s Initiatives for Gender Justice, Presentation to the Committee on Budget and Fi-
nance, pp. 7–8, September 2016.
297
Ibid.. Independent Expert Review, 2020, para. 285, see above note 85:
The IOM does not as yet enjoy the full confidence and trust of all staff. There is a disin-
clination to make complaints freely and willingly about, and to report officially, alleged
impeachable conduct, especially by elected or senior officials. In turn, this makes it
more difficult to assess the real extent of the occurrences of misconduct and misbehav-
iour, and could be a significant factor in the underreporting of reprehensible conduct.
298
Audit Report of ReVision, para. 102, see above note 204.
299
ICC-ASP/14/15, para. 57, see above note 169; ICC, Official Records, Fourteenth Session,
ICC-ASP/14/20, 18-26 November 2015, vol. II, part B.2, para. 12.
300
Conversations with diplomats on file with the author.
301
ICC, Official Records, Fourteenth Session, ICC-ASP/14/20, 18-26 November, vol. I, part III,
section C, para. 1.
302
Conversations with diplomats on file with the author.
is a highly valued party to the ICC system and its ongoing co-operation
with the Court is essential for the ease of some of its routine functions. It
also provides conditions and courtesies to the Court’s employees and civil
society organizations working on ICC-related issues. Capitals did not want
to strain their relationships and the host State appeared to be highly invest-
ed in assisting the Registrar, as a Dutch national, to deflect or avoid any
negative repercussions. The pressure was effective, and, in the end, the
ASP adopted a resolution addressing this issue in the weakest terms possi-
ble. 303
The protective impulse of States to defend the actions of their citi-
zens working as civil servants within global institutions was foreseen in the
Standards of Conduct of the International Civil Service.
In reaching out to a government to seek their support in order to
“block or reverse [an] unfavourable decision[s]” regarding his status, it is
possible that the Registrar breached the Standards of Conduct of the Inter-
national Civil Service (2013) specifically Article 29. 304 In coming to his
assistance, the host State may have also breached the same article within
the Standards, which require Governments to “safeguard the independence
of the international civil service” and as such, “it is understood that Gov-
ernment representatives and members of legislative bodies will neither ac-
cede to such requests nor intervene in such matters”. 305
The abrogation’s of duty and independence by the OIA, the IOM, the
CBF and the Assembly, are laid bare in light of the ILOAT judgment which
303
ICC-ASP/14/Res.1, para. 2, see above note 172: “Regrets that the Registry did not seek the
formal authorization of the Assembly before resorting to the Employee Benefit Liability
fund and calls for full transparency in any future such transactions and recalls the rules ap-
plying for such transactions”.
304
Standards of Conduct for the International Civil Service, UN Doc. A/RES/67/257, in effect
as of 1 January 2013, Section A.3., para. 29:
It is entirely improper for international civil servants to lobby or seek support from Gov-
ernment representatives or members of legislative organs to obtain advancement either
for themselves or for others or to block or reverse unfavourable decisions regarding their
status. By adhering to the Charter and the constitutions of the organizations of the Unit-
ed Nations system, Governments have undertaken to safeguard the independence of the
international civil service; it is therefore understood that Government representatives
and members of legislative bodies will neither accede to such requests nor intervene in
such matters. The proper method for an international civil servant to address such mat-
ters is through administrative channels; each organization is responsible for providing
these.
305
Ibid.
found the restructuring project to have been “unlawful” in its entirety, 306
the specifics of which could have been identified by a routine internal audit,
an IOM investigation or process evaluation, with more thorough scrutiny
by the Committee on Budget and Finance, and by proper oversight of the
ASP.
The entire internal control system, ill-prepared for the range and
scale of ethical and substantive violations committed during the ReVision
process, faltered and failed.
8.7.6. Misleading Data
When the restructuring project did not produce the outcomes expected and
promised, some of the data was manipulated to make it appear as if the
process had been valid, and the results had been met. This included provid-
ing misleading information to States Parties about: the legality of the pro-
ject; the fulfilment of the Court’s duty of care to staff during the process;
the negative impact on gender and geographical representation as a result
of ReVision; and the size, cost and alleged savings of the new Registry
structure. The following two sub-sections will address the latter aspects of
the misleading data provided to States Parties.
8.7.6.1. Gender and Geographical Representation
Gender and geographical considerations are live issues at the ICC. They
form part of the statutory requirements for the election of Court officials
and, through a complicated formula, each State Party is allocated a certain
number of nationals to professional posts within the Court. These data
points hold great value for the sense of collective ownership and positive
engagement by Member States within the ICC. Individual States and re-
gions are attentive to the levels of representation and under-representation
within the professional profile of the Court.
Through the Comprehensive Report produced after ReVision and a
series of Q&A papers on gender and geographical issues disseminated to
States Parties during the restructuring, the Registry sought to inform and
reframe the emerging results with respect to the abolishment of posts and
the subsequent appointments made to the new positions. This material in-
cluded the provision of misleading information to States Parties in order to
dilute the political impact of the restructuring process when it resulted in
306
ILOAT, Judgment No. 3907, para. 26, see above note 126.
fewer women and fewer nationals from African States in leadership and
management positions after ReVision than before the project. The provi-
sion of some of the data presented to States appeared to be intended to ob-
scure and downplay the politically sensitive negative results.
The geographical aspect was particularly delicate given the Africa
region had been the near exclusive focus of the Court’s prosecutorial work
until 2019 with the exception of its investigations in Iraq. Attention to the
regional impact was also heightened because the position of Deputy Regis-
trar (D-1), designated by the Rome Statute, 307 and at that time held by a
national from an African State, had been abolished at the end of 2013 at the
recommendation of the Registrar, in part as a cost-saving measure, in line
with the publicly stated intentions of the Registrar to create savings and
efficiencies. The abolition of this post was the first major change in the
landscape of the Registry.
According to the Comprehensive Report on ReVision, there were
more nationals from African States appointed to professional posts within
the Registry after the restructuring, than before. 308 Reviewing the tables
within the Report on ReVision it is clear that this is due to an alleged in-
crease in the representation of African nationals in the most junior level
professional positions (P-2). 309 This is the only category of professional
posts in which there may have been an increase in the representation of na-
tionals from African States. Unfortunately, the figures in the Report also
misrepresent and reduce the number of nationals of African States in lead-
ership and senior management posts (P-5) before ReVision. 310 The figures
utilised in the Comprehensive Report also do not reflect the first set of
posts abolished as part of the restructuring project in October 2014. In oth-
er words, a false picture was created through the selective and partial use of
data or the omission of relevant information.
Overall, there were fewer nationals from African States Parties in
management and leadership positions after ReVision than before the re-
structuring process. Although the numerical difference in representation at
307
ICC Statute, Article 43(3), see above note 2: “The Registrar and the Deputy Registrar shall
be persons of high moral character, be highly competent and have an excellent knowledge of
and be fluent in at least one of the working languages of the Court”.
308
Comprehensive Report, para. 567, see above note 204.
309
Audit Report of ReVision, para. 106, see above note 204; Examination of the Registry’s
2016 Budget, 2015, pp. 5, 6, 19-30, see above note 224.
310
Ibid.
the senior management level before and after ReVision is relatively small,
the political sensitivities and relational context of these changes were keen-
ly felt by African Member States whose distress and concerns appeared to
be undervalued by the Registrar. This was exacerbated by the series of
questionable human resource figures presented by the Registry and the de-
nials of any adverse impact on the representational profile of African na-
tionals as a result of the ReVision project.
Unlike geographical issues, few States Parties demonstrated any sus-
tained interest in the implication of the restructuring on the representation
of women in management, senior management and leadership positions
within the Registry. There were significant decreases in the number of
women in mid-level management positions (P-4) and a slight decrease in
the number of women in P-5 posts as a result of ReVision. There was also a
missed opportunity to appoint a woman, for the first time, to a head of divi-
sion with the creation of the new External Relations Division. To date, no
women have ever been appointed as a divisional head within the Registry.
These posts continue to be dominated by males from the Western Europe
and Others Region (WEOG). In the aftermath of ReVision, some States
Parties have become animated by concerns about the under-representation
of women in management and leadership positions within the ICC and are
now championing these issues at the Court as well as across a range of
multilateral organizations. 311 Whilst attention to these issues is always im-
portant, the depth of commitment to gender equality is unclear given the
silence of almost all States during the restructuring process even when in-
formed of the negative impact in real time on the representation of women
at mid-level and senior positions. Since the restructuring process, the CBF
has adjusted its approach to this issue by analysing more nuanced data re-
garding the representation of women in professional posts across the Court
and has noted their specific concerns about the need for the Registry in par-
ticular to “narrow the gender gap”. 312 In turn, the Independent Expert Re-
view devoted attention to this issue in their report with the inclusion of
numerous statements and recommendations urging the Court to address the
significant under-representation of women in leadership posts. 313
311
ICC, “ICC hosts launch of International Gender Champions Network’s New ‘Den Haag
Hub’”, press release, 5 February 2019, ICC-CPI-20190205-PRI1437 (https://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/a4a94c/).
312
ICC-ASP/17/5, part F, section 3, paras. 97 and 98, see above note 188.
313
Independent Expert Review, 2020, for example, paras. R15, R88, 138, 212.
314
Comprehensive Report, p. 26, see above note 204.
315
Ibid., para. 136.
316
Audit Report of ReVision, p. 8, see above note 204.
317
ICC-ASP/14/15, fn.11, see above note 169.
318
Ibid., para. 58 and fn. 11.
319
Audit Report of ReVision, para. 127, see above note 204; ICC-ASP/14/15, fn. 11, see above
note 169.
320
Ibid., para. 126.
321
Comprehensive Report, p. 25, see above note 204.
322
Examination of the Registry’s 2016 Budget, p. 11, see above note 224.
2016 budget request based on the new model, compared with the al-
leged savings in the new structure, do not seem strongly aligned. The
challenges in reconciling contrasting budget figures with respect to
ReVision was referred to in the Audit Report as “difficult to ex-
plain”, 323 and that while the increase in staff numbers to adjust to the
new premises was reasonable, the Registry’s explanations justifying
the effectiveness of the restructuring project, “warrant qualifica-
tion”. 324 It is relevant for the integrity of the budget, the verification
of the alleged savings, and the claims of adherence to the financial
envelope determined by States that all of the same positions (contrac-
tors, consultants, advisers, fellows, staff posts and so on) that were
counted before the restructuring, were also included in the headcount
related to the cost of the structure after ReVision. This question re-
mains open and unanswered.
(b) Whether the standard practice utilized by the Registry of budgeting
for each position based on the maximum cost of the post was applied
to the new structure. The practice of budgeting for the ceiling costs
per post ensures that, regardless of who is in the position, the post is
properly and adequately addressed within the budget. For example,
all of the professional posts at the ICC (P1-P5) have 13 steps in the
salary structure. Under the standard budgeting practice, each post
would be budgeted at Step 13 (the highest step) to ensure that the po-
sition is fully budgeted in case of changes in the post and the need to
recruit a new person into the position. If the new person is more ex-
perienced than the previous holder of the post, the ICC is able to
benefit from the additional experience by being able to offer the in-
coming appointee a higher step level than the previous occupant. If
this standard practice was applied to the restructuring, then it has a
sound budget. If not, and if instead the budget for ReVision deviated
from the standard practice and was based on budgeting only for the
actual step level of the incumbent, then the budget has been under-
estimated and misrepresented, and may not be reliable as the basis
for budget projections in the long term. This issue speaks to both the
integrity of the budget as well as the process.
323
Audit Report of ReVision, para. 111, see above note 204.
324
Ibid., para. 114.
8.7.7. Governance
Despite their governance responsibilities, States Parties were consistently
willing to forgo a critical analysis of the information they were provided as
long as what they were being told about ReVision was compatible with
what they wanted to hear, regardless of how unlikely or implausible it was.
What they wanted to hear was that the new structure would deliver savings
and efficiencies, and that the process was valid and complied with the legal
framework. This narrative was closely adhered to by all Court principals,
as well as States Parties, elected officials, and other stakeholders, with few
exceptions, throughout the entire project.
As time went by and the role of States Parties in the mismanagement
of ReVision began to surface, it was perhaps not in the interest of the States
to probe further.
In reality, it was likely that some of the diplomats, especially those in
small to mid-size embassies, were overworked and overwhelmed by their
duties to simultaneously cover a number of Hague-based multilateral insti-
tutions, including the ICC, the ICTY, the International Court of Justice as
well as the Organisation for the Prohibition of Chemical Weapons. Some
embassies simply did not have the bandwidth to interrogate the voluminous
restructuring information with which they were furnished by the Registrar
and his team. 325 Many States appeared to passively go along with the pro-
cess, whilst others seemed to be disengaged due to competing work priori-
ties. Some may have overly relied on the assessment of the States that were
actively involved in the restructuring process, and most seemed to assume
that the Registrar and his team were competently managing the project, or
at least ensuring that it was legally compliant.
During ReVision, the pressure experienced by individual diplomats
to forgo dissent and to conform to the group narrative was clear and tangi-
ble. Legal advisors of States Parties who raised questions or expressed an
alternative view about the restructuring were sometimes threatened by the
Registrar with being reported to their capitals if they persisted. 326 This was
a powerful disincentive. Diplomats on assignment do not like to be under-
mined to their capital or to have their reputations compromised. Inevitably,
as a result of this pressure, most of the issues were quickly dropped. In ef-
fect, individual diplomats may have been pressured or harangued by the
325
Conversations on file with the author.
326
Ibid.
person whose work in the context of the Court as a whole they were re-
sponsible for overseeing as States Parties. Individual diplomats were reluc-
tant or even afraid to express ideas that contradicted the Registrar and the
other group members (States Parties), especially those whose national and
individual reputations became entwined with the success of this reform
process.
The pressure also went the other way with some Court officials re-
portedly urged by States Parties to be more vocal and visible in their sup-
port for ReVision and the Registrar. 327 As an elected official, a request from
an influential State Party can quickly feel like a requirement.
The Registrar and States Parties were unwilling to consider or dis-
cuss discrepant or unsettling information about ReVision and were aggres-
sive towards discordant critiques about the process. Any data or analysis
that questioned or contradicted the group narrative was dismissed. Those
providing the analysis were treated with suspicion and disdain or, alterna-
tively, accused of threatening the reputation of the project. 328 The Registrar
and personnel in his immediate office who, according to the Comprehen-
sive Report, were responsible for external communication about ReVi-
sion 329 adopted a strategy of personally attacking those who critiqued Re-
Vision as a way of discrediting their analysis. This strategy, a now familiar
tool in the daily political discourse within the US, was not new to the ICC.
But the personalized attacks targeting both internal and external stakehold-
ers was unprecedented and as a tactic, it was effective in deflecting atten-
tion from the facts and the vulnerabilities within the ReVision process, at
least in the short term.
It is reasonable for States Parties to expect civil servants to be candid,
honest and transparent and that States will be provided with reliable infor-
mation upon which they make significant decisions as the governing body.
But when it became clear that some essential information about ReVision
was questionable at best and warranted a more critical evaluation given
what was at stake, States chose to remain with the group narrative and, by
doing so, they knowingly colluded with being deliberately deceived.
This dynamic prevented States Parties from making fully informed
decisions on issues affecting the overall budget of the Court and obstructed
327
Ibid.
328
Ibid.; Comprehensive Report, para. 567, see above note 204.
329
Ibid.
States from being made aware of the serial and serious violations of Court
rules and regulations as well as the breaches of the ICC’s duty of care to its
staff inherent within the restructuring project.
8.7.7.1. Decision-Making Processes
The factors that influence collective and deliberative decision-making pro-
cesses can be subtle.
In the case of ReVision, the chance to undertake institutional reform
of the Registry with 560 staff and with an annual budget of over EUR 60
million was ambitiously seductive for the Registry staff and diplomats most
engaged in the restructuring process. In addition to the genuine intentions
of the project and the legitimacy of the re-organization itself, there ap-
peared to be a significant level of State- and self-interest associated with
the opportunity to undertake an institutional reform process on this scale.
According to Thompson, one of the ways in which corruption of a
public institution occurs, is when interests, irrelevant to its purpose, un-
dermine the effective stewardship of the organization. 330 Personal ambition,
the interests of States Parties, and the preservation of bilateral relationships
are all legitimate and ethically neutral considerations. But each of these
interests was irrelevant to either the objectives of ReVision (to enhance the
efficiency of the Registry and generate savings) or to the mandate of the
ICC. Yet, such considerations appeared to qualify and shape the engage-
ment with and oversight of the project and facilitated the occurrence of a
series of violations, without consequence or accountability. These were in-
fluences that appeared to undermine and compromise the internal control
and oversight procedures of the Court. In the language of Lessig, these
were interests, irrelevant to the objectives of ReVision, that formed an
“economy of influence”, which in this context, weakened the purpose of
the restructuring, the trustworthiness of the institution and possibly the
credibility of the Court.
In hindsight, it was profoundly unwise for States Parties to have pro-
ceeded with a restructuring project in the absence of a functioning and in-
dependent Audit Committee. The Committee was dissolved in 2014 but
had not met since 2012. A credible Committee of external experts may
330
Thompson, 1995, pp. 20–25, see above note 205; Newhouse, pp. 584, 576, fn. 122, see
above note 118; Dennis F. Thompson, “Two Concepts of Corruption”, in Edmond J. Safra
Centre for Ethics Working Papers, no. 16, 1 August 2013.
have been able to provide the objectivity needed in this process and alerted
States Parties and the ASP to anomalies, violations and non-compliance at
an early enough stage of the process for corrective action to have been tak-
en. Whether States Parties would have acted upon this information is un-
known, but had it existed, it would have preserved some integrity for the
institution.
The project suffered from a lack of preparation in advance of the re-
structuring to ensure mechanisms were in place to provide checks and bal-
ances throughout the process. States Parties enabled a system in which
those responsible for ReVision could determine whether an internal audit of
the project could proceed or not, thereby exposing the Court to significant
risk and liability. The Presidency did not take steps to ensure the proper
administration of the Court with an appropriate level of oversight of the
Registrar during this process. When non-compliance with external Audit
recommendations regarding the (mis)use of funds was discovered, the CBF
was prepared to shroud it in justification and States Parties were unwilling
to critique this conduct as improper, let alone address it as a potential viola-
tion of Court rules.
It is evident that the restructuring process did not adhere to merit-
based decision-making processes and that there were serious violations of
the ICC’s legal framework leading to the unfair treatment of staff and the
Court’s failure to meet its duty of care. This was harmful for the staff and
created significant liabilities for the ICC. It is also apparent that the struc-
ture and operating methods of the Project Board did not embody the neces-
sary objectivity and credibility for the process and approved phases of the
project that were inherently flawed. The restructuring suffered from a sig-
nificant lack of transparency in almost all areas including within its deci-
sion-making procedures and in the communication with States Parties with
key aspects of the information provided to States proving to be unreliable
and lacking in veracity. Each one of these areas on their own, meets the
definition of institutional corruption. That corruption is ‘satisfied’ in all of
these aspects, is revealing of the widespread and deep-seated vulnerabili-
ties within the internal and external control systems of the Court. It is also
indicative of a lack of impartiality and critical evaluation in the exercise of
governance by the ASP.
During this period at the Court, institutional dishonesty flourished at
a rapid and voluminous pace. Most alarming was the ease with which this
was accepted by States Parties, the ICC leadership and most independent
had earlier raised a number of concerns about the restructuring including its
legality, efficacy and potential impact on the Court.
It is not yet clear that the ASP and its subsidiary bodies, the Audit
Committee and the CBF, are taking seriously enough the systemic vulnera-
bilities exposed by the restructuring process, the extent of the damage in-
flicted upon the reputation and credibility of the Court, and the urgency
with which it should be undertaking actions to restore trust and confidence
in this publicly funded and correspondingly, publicly accountable interna-
tional institution for justice. It is perhaps most important that the process
begins by restoring the ICC’s confidence and trust in itself.
The failure of ReVision to deliver on its objectives and the financial
costs of the project have perhaps done significantly less harm to the ICC
than the corruption that the management of the process injected into the
heart of the Court and the culture of unethical behaviour that the process
tapped into and accelerated across the ICC as a whole.
For the Court, ReVision was a painful example of the fragility of an
institution untethered from a clear set of ethical values and practices, oper-
ating without the institutional safeguards needed to ensure its integrity. For
States Parties, it was a devastating example of the impact of long-term in-
stitutional neglect, the result of not applying an ethics lens to their over-
sight functions, and emblematic of the limitations of budget-driven govern-
ance.
8.8. Conclusion
At this time in its history, the ICC is ethically discordant with the principles
of the Rome Statute and the global inspiration that gave rise to this revolu-
tionary treaty. Such contrast is the perfect invitation for new models of di-
plomacy and collective leadership to emerge.
The willingness of States Parties to hold themselves and each other
accountable is central to the integration of ethical practices within their
governance and decision-making activities. The continued readiness to
overlook impropriety of elected ICC officials, the sparing of political
blushes, the shielding of senior leaders from accountability processes by
their respective States Parties, and diminishing and denying the harm in-
flicted upon the Court’s institutional integrity, breeds more of the same.
This has led to a crisis of trust and ethical integrity within the institution.
The Independent Expert Review found that the ICC suffers internally from
distrust and a culture of fear. 337 According to their report, concerns about
ethics were identified as an important topic for all stakeholders during their
consultation process and it noted the erosive effect of allegations of poten-
tial ethics violations on the Court’s reputation, credibility and trust. 338 Pro-
fessor Gregory Gordon has described this period in the field of internation-
al justice as “an existential crisis that calls for an ethical catharsis” and pos-
tures that it is this very crisis which “might be what ultimately saves it”. 339
Fortunately, the Court is constantly in the process of becoming the
‘International Criminal Court’ of the Rome Statute, in service to humanity,
preserving the delicate mosaic of peoples united by common bonds, and
providing accountability for the most serious crimes in order to foster
peace and well-being. 340
People in every country of the world, including the 2.5 billion who
are currently citizens of States Parties to the ICC, are increasingly looking
for institutions where conduct matches mission, and where institutional
culture is aligned with the nobility of its mandate. Business, as usual, is no
longer enough.
There is a growing global consciousness emerging that is impressed
more by authenticity than status; seeks credibility, not perfection; and
chooses courage over cynicism. These are the qualities needed in a new era
of multilateral leadership to restore the integrity of the Court, expand pub-
lic trust, and renew pride in this magnificent endeavour.
337
Independent Expert Review, 2020, para. 62, see above note 85.
338
Ibid., para. 254
339
Gregory S. Gordon, “Closing Remarks at the Peace Palace Conference on Integrity in Inter-
national Justice”, CILRAP, 2 December, at 2.34-2.50 minutes (www.cilrap.org/cilrap-film/
181202-gordon-closing/).
340
ICC Rome Statute, Preamble, see above note 2.
9.1. Introduction
The offices of the prosecutor of the international courts and tribunals 1 es-
tablished since 1993 have shown wildly disparate results with respect to the
number of individuals brought to trial and convicted on some or all charges.
The formative institutions of the modern era – the International Criminal
Tribunals for the former Yugoslavia and for Rwanda (‘ICTY’ and
‘ICTR’) – sentenced 90 and 62 persons, respectively, for the perpetration of
core international crimes. 2 Other bodies have registered lesser numbers of
convictions. For instance, the Special Court for Sierra Leone (‘SCSL’) sen-
tenced nine persons to custodial sentences for international offences, 3 and
the Extraordinary Chambers in the Courts of Cambodia (‘ECCC’) have
registered three convictions. 4 The Special Tribunal for Lebanon (‘STL’) has
yet to issue a single judgement, although the investigative body which gave
rise to the Tribunal commenced its work in 2005. 5 In a similar vein, the
Kosovo Specialist Chambers (‘KSC’) and Specialist Prosecutor’s Office
has not at the time of writing brought its first charge, even though its inves-
*
Dr. William H. Wiley is the founder and Executive Director of the Commission for Interna-
tional Justice and Accountability (CIJA). He started his career in the field of international
criminal investigations with the Canadian war-crimes programme in 1997 and later served at
the International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia, International Criminal Tribu-
nal for Rwanda, International Criminal Court, and the Iraqi High Tribunal.
1
The use of the adjective ‘international’ in this context refers to bodies established under
United Nations and international-treaty auspices as well as so-called hybrid institutions
which bring together domestic and international laws and actors.
2
International Residual Mechanism for Criminal Tribunals (‘IRMCT’), “Infographic: ICTY
Facts & Figures” and “The ICTR in Brief” (available on its web site).
3
See the Residual Special Court for Sierra Leone’s web site.
4
Extraordinary Chambers in the Courts of Cambodia, “Who has been prosecuted” (available
on its web site).
5
The United Nations International Independent Investigation Commission (‘UNIIIC’) was
established in April 2005 pursuant to United Nations Security Council resolution 1595.
6
The Special Investigative Task Force, established in 2011, evolved into the Special Prosecu-
tor’s Office in 2016; see Kosovo Specialist Chambers and Specialist Prosecutor’s Office,
“Special Investigative Task Force” (available on its web site).
7
The four persons convicted at trial, at the time of writing, are Thomas Lubanga Dyilo, Ger-
main Katanga, Ahmad al-Faqi al-Mahdi, and Bosco Ntaganda. Al-Mahdi pleaded guilty; ap-
pellate proceedings remain underway in the case of Ntaganda. This tally does not include
Jean-Pierre Bemba, all of whose convictions for the perpetration of core international crimes
were vacated by an ICC appellate panel.
8
Morten Bergsmo, “Revisiting Integrity in International Justice”, FICHL Policy Brief Series
No. 93 (2018), Torkel Opsahl Academic EPublisher, Brussels, 2018 (https://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/e550f7).
the States funding these bodies, have increasingly had the effect of drawing
limited resources away from the core investigative and prosecutorial func-
tions. In turn, the resources have been spent upon relevant, albeit secondary
tasks such as strategic communications, the protection (defined broadly and
hopelessly imprecisely) of victims, who may or may not be witnesses, and
other presumed stakeholders in the judicial process (save suspects and the
accused). Under-explored to date by scholars and commentators, 9 the redi-
rection of resources in this manner from the core functions weighs particu-
larly heavily upon offices of the prosecutor. This phenomenon is particular-
ly in evidence at the ICC, which the uncharitable might assert displays, at
times, a tendency to place more focus upon the needs of victims than on the
evidentiary requirements for a successful prosecution.
Finally, in this context, it will be observed that the professional per-
formance of the managerial and, most importantly, the leadership cadres of
the international courts and tribunals have, since 1993, proved to be uneven.
The shortcomings witnessed over the last quarter-century are inseparable
from the recruitment policies of the institutions which have employed (or
otherwise promoted) men and women to leadership and management posi-
tions. More specifically, the assessment of individuals for senior leadership
and managerial positions have not factored the qualities of institutional
loyalty and moral courage into hiring processes, thereby exacerbating the
problems which arise from the continued employment of unproductive per-
sonnel at lesser ranks as well as the frequent failure of offices of the prose-
cutor to resist external pressures to shift finite resources away from the
core investigative and prosecutorial functions. Managerial and, most espe-
cially, leadership insufficiency encourages institutional rot, too often lead-
ing to the voluntary withdrawal of the most talented personnel to other
places of employment. High rates of staff turnover – which characterized
most especially the ICC-OTP during the suzerainty of chief Prosecutor
Luis Moreno-Ocampo – have a concomitantly negative effect upon institu-
tional memory. In turn, the degradation of the latter has a deleterious im-
pact upon the proper functioning of international offices of the prosecutor,
given the fact that the temporal parameters which frame the opening of a
given investigation and the conclusion of appellate proceedings in the
event of a conviction will span several years.
9
The exception to this rule is Kjersti Lohne, Advocates of Humanity: Human Rights NGOs in
International Criminal Justice, Ph.D. dissertation, Department of Criminology and Sociolo-
gy of Law, University of Oslo, 2015.
As was noted at the outset of this chapter, Morten Bergsmo has dis-
tinguished himself in recent years as the most forceful advocate for the cre-
ation of a culture of integrity within the system of international criminal
justice. Whilst it may be tempting for some to see his demands for upright-
ness and high moral character as nothing more than a rejoinder to the ethi-
cal lapses of Moreno-Ocampo, to do so would be to misconstrue the argu-
ments advanced by Bergsmo as well as the pressing need for new ap-
proaches to personnel matters within the existing institutions charged with
the application of international criminal and humanitarian law. It is the
view taken here that, notwithstanding improvements witnessed over the
last 10 years, there remains an urgent requirement for a root-and-branch
reform of the flawed approach to leadership and management, which has
been too often in evidence in the system of international criminal justice.
Until such reforms are made, the overall prosecutorial record of the interna-
tional courts and tribunals shall remain at levels incommensurate with their
financial expenditures, thereby serving to call the entire system of interna-
tional criminal justice into disrepute.
9.3. Leadership and Management in International Courts and
Tribunals
Many of the problems plaguing the system of international criminal justice
and the associated offices of the prosecutor can be traced to insufficient
institutional leadership and management. As has been noted already, this
state of affairs owes a great deal to the manner in which persons are ap-
pointed to positions of significant responsibility. Unsatisfactory leadership
and management also reflect the fact that the distinction between leadership
and management is poorly understood by those employed by international
courts and tribunals, not least the very persons holding leadership and
management appointments.
There exists a dizzying quantity of books, audio guides, seminars and
the like which are designed to create effective leaders as well as managers
in the world of business; these materials are mind-numbing, at least for
those disinterested in matters of commerce. Highly professional military
forces have their own approach to leadership and management, built re-
spectively around the distinction between the officer and non-
commissioned officer ranks, and the unique training regimens of each pro-
fessional stream. In contrast, treatises which concern themselves with the
practice of law are rarely, if ever, coupled with panegyrics on the im-
10
As far as this author is aware, the only non-practitioner of law (that is, neither a licensed
lawyer nor a judge) to have held a senior most leadership position in the international sys-
tem of criminal justice was Mr. Robin Vincent, a brilliant court administrator from England
who served as Registrar of the SCSL and, later, the STL.
cutions – set out by the leader and agreed to by his or her managers. Co-
ordination between leaders and managers to this end is of the utmost im-
portance; it is correspondingly crucial that the leader ensure that his or her
time not be absorbed disproportionately by dealings with external stake-
holders. The leader who has insufficient contact with his or her subordi-
nates will, invariably, exercise poor command and control over the institu-
tion which he or she leads. As such, the leader needs to communicate regu-
larly with subordinate leaders and managers, not least to ensure the execu-
tion of the vision in accordance with the goals which afford concrete shape
to that vision. Beyond such co-ordination efforts, competent managers
should be free to act with a certain autonomy, that is, to be free from micro-
management emanating from the leadership level. In large institutions,
where the leaders and managers know their jobs and are committed to the
successful execution of the agreed goals, it is incumbent upon managers to
report only that such-and-such goals have been accomplished within estab-
lished temporal parameters or, where the latter is proving difficult, to re-
quest further direction. In the execution of the goals assigned to them,
managers may resort to innovative methods which are consistent with the
vision of the leader and, in the case of an investigative body, consistent
with any relevant procedural law. In this respect, innovation is a hallmark
of creative leadership as well as capable management.
9.3.3. OTP Leaders, Managers and Followers
It might logically be asked at this juncture what positions in an internation-
al office of the prosecutor are held by leaders and which roles are assumed
by managers.
The chief prosecutor in any given office of the prosecutor is indis-
putably a leader, as is his or her deputy chief prosecutor. The functionaries
who surround these individuals in the immediate office of a chief prosecu-
tor are neither managers nor leaders, though persons so employed do on
occasion come to the erroneous conclusion that their proximity to the lead-
ership lends them their own measure of executive authority. 11 Where mis-
11
A long-ago spokesperson for chief Prosecutor Carla Del Ponte, who was situated in the im-
mediate Office of the Prosecutor, was perceived by some within the OTP of harbouring such
delusions. In 2003, the author of this chapter was told by his senior trial attorney to embark
on a mission to Montenegro to speak to a valuable (in the view of the spokesperson) source.
When this author protested that any such mission was likely to constitute a waste of time
and money, it was explained to him that the direction had come from the said spokesperson
conceptions of this nature appear in evidence, the failure is that of the lead-
er(s) rather than that of delusional subordinates, most especially where
leaders use relatively inexperienced staff in their immediate office to give
direction to senior managers. Office of the prosecutor leaders (that is, chief
and deputy prosecutors) need to interact directly with their senior managers,
that is, their chiefs of appeals, prosecutions 12 and investigations. Each of
these senior managers will have sub-managers, most notably the senior
prosecutors (in the case of a chief of prosecutions) and investigative team
leaders (in the case of a chief of investigations). 13 These sub-managers
have purely management functions. The same might be said of the senior
managers, although the latter may, at their discretion and in agreement with
the leadership cadre, take on certain of the characteristics of the leader, for
instance, where they share with the leader responsibility for the communi-
cation of the institutional vision to subordinate ranks. All other personnel
employed by an office of the prosecutor are effectively followers insofar as
their primary task is to conform to the institutional vision by contributing,
in accordance with their function, to the successful execution of the con-
crete goals communicated to them by their respective managers and sub-
managers.
9.4. Institutional Loyalty
Capable leadership and management alone will not ensure the success of an
international criminal court or tribunal and, most especially, its office of the
prosecutor; there is an additional requirement for institutional loyalty
which weighs upon every leader, manager and follower. Indeed, the effec-
tiveness of any given court or tribunal will run parallel to the degree of in-
stitutional loyalty which is in evidence throughout the ranks of those em-
ployed therein. The fostering of a culture of institutional loyalty, not least
and could not, therefore, easily be challenged. It was not; and, as expected, the mission
proved to be pointless.
12
At the ICC-OTP, what was known as the Chief of Prosecutions in the ad hoc Tribunals is
named the Prosecutions Coordinator.
13
The chief of investigations at the ICC-OTP has a deputy who carries the title Investigations
Coordinator. This arrangement would appear to work well, not least as the position has been
held, since its creation, by a series of capable incumbents. At the ICTY-OTP, the equivalent
position was known as Investigations Commander, there being four such posts when the au-
thor arrived at the OTP in 2000. Ms. Del Ponte ordered the posts to be abolished in 2001 on
the grounds that they were superfluous to requirements although the incumbents ultimately
retained their positions, albeit without substantial authority over investigative matters.
17
Staff Regulations and Rules of the United Nations, 1 January 2018, ST/SGB/2018/1, Regu-
lation 1.2.
18
Ibid., Regulation 1.1:
I solemnly declare and promise to exercise in all loyalty, discretion and conscience the
functions entrusted to me as an international civil servant of the United Nations, to dis-
charge these functions and regulate my conduct with the interests of the United Nations
only in view, and not to seek or accept instructions in regard to the performance of my
duties from any Government or other source external to the Organization. I also solemn-
ly declare and promise to respect the obligations incumbent upon me as set out in the
Staff Regulations and Rules.
their own homes in Kigali when they were supposed to be working in out-
lying areas whilst pocketing the daily subsistence allowance (‘DSA’) paid
by the United Nations for meals and accommodation. Although ultimately
petty in nature, conduct of this nature constituted fraud in the strict sense –
and in this context, it is worth recalling that the offenders of these and other
indiscretions were criminal investigators employed by a law-enforcement
body.
A further problem at the ICTR-OTP during its early years was that a
great many of the investigators had a better grasp of the various privileges
enjoyed by United Nations staff – in particular, the familial benefits to
which those with dependent spouses and children were entitled – than they
did of the case-files to which they had been assigned. Or such was the view
formed by this author, who was on occasion called upon by fellow team
members to interpret the relevant (to the latter) United Nations rules on the
grounds he had studied law. Protestations by de facto counsel that he had
studied international criminal and humanitarian law, not whatever law in-
formed the United Nations rules, with which in any event he had no fiduci-
ary interest as he had no dependents, fell upon deaf ears.
Far more serious offences against the integrity and proper function-
ing of the ICTR-OTP were perpetrated during the early life of that institu-
tion by the Deputy Prosecutor, Mr. Bernard Muna, who was likewise based
in Kigali. He would arrive daily at the Investigations Division headquarters,
seated in the back of a white Mercedes sedan which featured a small UN
flag affixed to the bonnet. Upon exiting his vehicle at the main door of the
building, whatever staff found themselves in the proximity of his arrival
would engage in great displays of bowing and scraping as Mr. Muna made
his way into the building and towards his office. The charitable might as-
cribe the waves of genuflection to social mores. A less generous interpreta-
tion of the grovelling would hold that Mr. Muna had created the impression
in the minds of a great many of the personnel in the Kigali office that they
served the United Nations only at his pleasure. Indeed, under the noses of
chief Prosecutors Louise Arbour and, in turn, Carla Del Ponte, Mr. Muna
had built an impressive patronage network which encompassed much of
the Investigations Division management as well as its rank-and-file. No
suggestion is made here that Mr. Muna realized fiduciary benefit from this
arrangement, which is to observe that the purpose of the structure was un-
clear. What is certain is that its effect was to control tightly the hiring of
the monies left over after one had met the actual cost of room and board
whilst on mission. Plainly, a number of investigators had grown accus-
tomed to supplementing their familial budgets by this means, which in
fairness was not formally contrary to the applicable rules. It will be recalled
nonetheless that these same rules afforded well-paid, lightly-taxed interna-
tional public servants with all manner of education and housing grants with
which to support dependent family members.
More troubling than needless mission travel was the practice, which
was occasionally in evidence until the aforementioned reorganization of the
Investigations Division, of exploiting the differential between the rates of
DSA and mission subsistence allowance (‘MSA’). DSA was paid for short-
er missions, that is, for periods of travel of up to 30 continuous days. MSA
was meant to cover lengthy deployments; it was paid at a lower rate on the
assumption that long deployments in a fixed location would reduce ac-
commodation costs markedly insofar as those so deployed could make
longer-term housing arrangements whilst at the same time facilitating the
preparation of one’s own meals. The trick within the ICTY Investigations
Division would see personnel deploying away from headquarters for tem-
poral periods close to, though not exceeding the point at which DSA would
become MSA. To avoid financial loss arising from the movement from
DSA to MSA rates, a brief sojourn to The Hague would then be taken be-
fore DSA became MSA with, in turn, redeployment to the same location.
Proceeding in this manner, DSA rates would be paid for lengthy, albeit not
strictly continuous absences from The Hague.
Until the reorganization of the ICTY Investigations Division effected
by Ms. Del Ponte, the more serious problem bedevilling the OTP was the
tendency of Investigations Division managers to facilitate the hiring of
their erstwhile colleagues in the domestic realm to rank-and-file investiga-
tor positions, without having undertaken a sufficient assessment of the suit-
ability of each individual for the investigation of core international crimes.
In this manner, the Investigations Division approach to recruitment to the
rangement was termed the daily subsistence allowance (or DSA, as indicated above). The
production of receipts, beyond proof of presence in the given location, was not required. The
DSA rates were very generous, particularly where the traveller was prepared to eschew tra-
ditional hotels for privately-hired accommodation; and, by the time this author arrived at the
ICTY in 2000, a vast network of private accommodation options had been identified in the
cities to which ICTY personnel travelled habitually (for instance, Sarajevo, Zagreb and later
Belgrade, after the fall from power of Slobodan Milošević).
21
It would be wholly false to assert that the Chief of Investigations oversaw patronage ar-
rangements of the sort facilitated by Mr. Muna. The former is an honourable man whose
professional capabilities were evidently deemed by Ms. Del Ponte to be incommensurate
with his appointment as Chief of Investigations.
9.5.3. ICC
When this author served with the Investigations Division at the ICC during
its formative period (2003–2005), rank-and-file self-discipline, as well as
the quality of the Investigations Division leadership and management, were
of a high order. During the said period, the ICC had two Deputy Prosecu-
tors, one of whom, Dr. Serge Brammertz, oversaw the Investigations Divi-
sion. In this role, Dr. Brammertz was assisted by a capable Chief of Inves-
tigations to whom the investigative team leaders reported. The latter over-
saw the Democratic Republic of the Congo (‘DRC’) and Uganda (that is,
Lord’s Resistance Army) investigations; later, a Darfur team was estab-
lished to deal with that situation. Presumably by design, given widespread
knowledge in the field of international criminal and humanitarian law of
the managerial deficiencies plaguing the investigations divisions of the ad
hoc Tribunals, neither Dr. Brammertz nor any of the ICC investigative
managers were recruited from or had any experience of the system of inter-
national criminal justice prior to joining the ICC-OTP. Perhaps for this rea-
son, the initial ICC Investigations Division arrangements worked well, ow-
ing to the quality of the leadership, management, and the rank-and-file per-
sonnel, many of the latter having been hand-picked from the ICTY-OTP. Or
rather, the leadership and management structure of the ICC Investigations
Division worked well until such time as Mr. Moreno-Ocampo – who had
no discernible grasp of either investigations or international criminal and
humanitarian law – began to meddle in the day-to-day investigative work,
roughly one year into his tenure.
The brazen manipulation of travel allowances and the like which
characterized the conduct of a minority of investigators at the ad hoc Tri-
bunals was not in evidence at the ICC Investigations Division. Aside from
the high levels of professional motivation and institutional loyalty which
were shown by the initial intake to the OTP as a whole (those overseeing
this initial intake deserve recognition), there were no additional monies to
be had insofar as investigative missions were undertaken, with rare excep-
tions, to locations with exceedingly spartan living arrangements and the
DSA rates had accordingly been set at negligible levels. Indeed, the situa-
tion was such that those whose jobs required deployment to the field had to
be equipped with sleeping bags, mosquito nets, medical kits and other bits
of field gear as the quality of the hotels in many of the mission areas –
where there were any hotels at all – invariably offered conditions only
marginally better than those of the local prisons.
Finally, it will be noted that at the ICTR and the ICTY, intelligence
organs with an interest in the course of particular investigations were be-
lieved, not without a good deal of prima facie evidence, to have developed
informants within the offices of the prosecutor of those institutions. One
refers, most especially, to Rwandan and Croatian security services. Quite
obviously, acting as an informant for a foreign intelligence service whilst
employed by the United Nations would constitute a grievous lapse of pro-
fessional ethics running manifestly contrary to the applicable regulations
and rules. Where the ICC-OTP was concerned, suggestions have been
made that intelligence agents loyal to the then-President of the DRC, Mr.
Joseph Kabila, developed a source within the ICC DRC Team as early as
2004. However, assertions of this nature must necessarily be characterized
as unproven. 22
9.6. Leadership at the OTPs of the ICTY, the ICTR and the ICC
From 2000 to 2005, as mentioned above, this author had the opportunity to
observe and otherwise witness the ramifications of a range of OTP leader-
ship styles across the ICTY, the ICTR and the ICC. The latter shall be con-
sidered here with an eye to illustrating the benefits which arise from effec-
tive leadership and the problems which invariably follow where it is insuf-
ficient.
9.6.1. ICTR
The deleterious effect upon the Investigations Division of the tenure of Mr.
Muna has already been touched upon. What is left to consider, briefly, is
the effect upon the Investigations Division of the ICTR-OTP of the leader-
ship of Ms. Arbour and Ms. Del Ponte; they served as chief Prosecutor dur-
ing the periods 1996–1999 and 1999–2003, respectively, with the terms of
both chief Prosecutors being marked by the production of sub-standard in-
vestigative case-files.
Ms. Arbour and Ms. Del Ponte were highly-capable as well as ethical
professionals who sought to execute their mandates in conformity with the
ideals set out in the Statute of the ICTR. Whereas both of these chief Pros-
ecutors were affable individuals, Ms. Arbour evidenced a clear ability to
tolerate fools gladly, in marked contrast to Ms. Del Ponte, rendering the
22
International offices of the prosecutor have been consistently loath to establish counter-
intelligence capabilities. This reticence has led to endless breaches of security and consti-
tutes the Achilles’ heel of all existing witness-protection arrangements.
former the more popular of the two in the eyes of the Investigations Divi-
sion management as well as the rank-and-file.
The leadership of Ms. Arbour over the Investigations Division of the
ICTR might be regarded as a failure. Admittedly, she was poorly served by
her Deputy Prosecutor, Mr. Muna, from his appointment in April 1997.
What is more, the fact that Ms. Arbour was based several-thousand kilome-
tres away in The Hague, as she was concomitantly chief Prosecutor of the
ICTR as well as the ICTY, lent Mr. Muna a freer hand to wreak havoc in
Kigali. The ICTR-OTP as a whole experienced immense growth in staffing
numbers under Ms. Arbour, and it was during this period that the ranks of
the Investigations Division came to be filled with investigators as well as
managers who were, in the main, unsuited to the investigation of breaches
of international criminal and humanitarian law.
In assessing the tenure of Ms. Arbour from the perspective of the
ICTR-OTP Investigations Division, there are a number of mitigating fac-
tors to be considered: first, the requirement that she was required to oversee
concomitantly the ICTY-OTP, which was likewise experiencing considera-
ble expansion in its staffing numbers; and second, the stellar work under-
taken by Ms. Arbour to ensure, through relations with external actors such
as the UN Security Council as well as myriad States, a future for both of
the ad hoc Tribunals. However, responsibility for a great many of the in-
vestigative shortcomings of the ICTR-OTP, most of which long outlived
Ms. Arbour’s tenure as chief Prosecutor, must be laid at her feet. If nothing
else, the term of Ms. Arbour illustrates the point that even the most inspira-
tional leader will fail where he or she does not remain in constant contact
with his or her leadership and management teams or otherwise fails to con-
trol them effectively.
The record of Ms. Del Ponte is altogether positive when seen from
the perspective of the necessity of carrying out effective investigations.
First, she sacked Mr. Muna, albeit well into her term. Second, when sack-
ing Mr. Muna, the chief Prosecutor placed trial lawyers in charge of inves-
tigations, thereby neutering, to an extent, the fact that the removal of Mr.
Muna was not coupled with changes to the ranks of the investigative man-
agement cadre. In the event, the requirement that trial counsel oversee the
investigative processes from the start served to improve the quality of the
investigative output somewhat less than it might have done were geogra-
phy not something of Ms. Del Ponte’s enemy. One refers to the fact that,
like Ms. Arbour, Ms. Del Ponte was (until 2003) concomitantly chief Pros-
ecutor of the ICTY and therefore limited in the amount of time that she
could spend in Arusha, never mind Kigali. A second problem was the bi-
furcation of the OTP between those cities, with the trial lawyers afforded
responsibility for the building of individual cases (after the sacking of Mr.
Muna) being based in Arusha, whilst the investigators were, logically
enough, situated in Kigali. A third problem was that the quality of the trial
lawyers available to Ms. Del Ponte remained uneven, despite the mass-
sacking of a number of senior counsel earlier in her tenure.
In summary, Ms. Del Ponte took several (re-)organizational decisions
which were badly needed, thereby laying the foundation for improvements
in the quality of the ICTR investigative output. Ultimately, it was her suc-
cessor, chief Prosecutor Hassan Jallow, who was left to capitalize upon the-
se improvements. The view taken here is that Ms. Del Ponte showed con-
siderable moral courage as well as institutional loyalty in reforming the
investigative management arrangements of the ICTR, through the sackings
of some and the neutering of the authority of others. For these and other
reasons, based on personal observations, the leadership of Ms. Del Ponte of
the ICTR-OTP can be assessed positively, not least given the highly unsuit-
able arrangements which had been bequeathed to her in 1999 by Ms. Ar-
bour.
9.6.2. ICTY
During her tenure as ICTY chief Prosecutor, Ms. Del Ponte made important
changes to the functioning of the Investigations Division, having inherited
from Ms. Arbour a poorly functioning operation. The removal of the Chief
of Investigations, with Mr. Lopez-Terres as his replacement, has already
been noted. Additionally, Ms. Del Ponte would later sack her Deputy Pros-
ecutor, Mr. Graham Blewitt, and Chief of Prosecutions, Mr. Michael John-
son, though the reason for their removal in 2004 was unrelated to the prop-
er functioning of the Investigations Division. 23 As at the ICTR-OTP, ICTY-
OTP trial counsel were placed in charge of the building of individual case-
files, thereby circumventing, for the most part, the collective insufficiency
of the management and rank-and-file membership of the Investigations Di-
vision.
23
Mr. Blewitt and Mr. Johnson were removed from their posts after Ms. Del Ponte received
evidence that they were advocating for the replacement of Ms. Del Ponte as ICTY chief
Prosecutor.
The changes initiated in The Hague worked well for two reasons.
First, the Investigations and Prosecutions Divisions were situated in the
same building, not one thousand kilometres apart, as was the case with the
ICTR. Second, the Investigations Division of the ICTY had at its disposal a
large number of highly specialized as well as capable linkage analysts, sit-
uated within the Leadership Research and Military Analysis Teams (‘LRT’,
‘MAT’). Analysts from these teams already worked closely and construc-
tively with OTP trial counsel when cases came to trial. These linkage ana-
lyst–trial counsel relationships were generally predicated on the fact that,
prior to the reform of the management of the investigative processes, more
often than not, trial counsel found themselves commencing litigation with
insufficient linkage evidence to secure a conviction on some or all of the
offences alleged in any given indictment. Under the circumstances, when
trial counsel assumed responsibility for case building during the investiga-
tive phase, rather than only at the start of trial – by which point investiga-
tions should, as a matter of professional ethics and procedural fairness have
been all but complete – the analyst–counsel relationships of this nature
served to inform positively the ICTY-OTP case-files developed from 2001.
9.6.3. ICC
The paucity of disciplinary breaches and like failures by rank-and-file per-
sonnel at the ICC-OTP witnessed by this author during 2003–2005 owed
much to a strong culture of institutional loyalty, effective management and,
where Dr. Brammertz was concerned, effective leadership.
The difficulties experienced by the ICC-OTP in bringing consistently
credible allegations against the accused and, in turn, securing convictions
where allegations have given rise to charges has been examined ad nause-
um elsewhere and need not be recounted here. What will be observed in
this chapter is the fact that the initial recruitment effort of the OTP – which
was in the enviable position of poaching top-drawer talent from elsewhere
in the system of international criminal justice during a period of OTP re-
form at the ad hoc Tribunals – led to the retention of a great many highly-
experienced investigators, analysts and lawyers with an inherent belief in
the mission of the Court as this was set out in the language of the Rome
Statute and in the carefully drafted vacancy announcements and job de-
scriptions by the Preparatory Team. Likewise, the selection of investigative
managers from outside of the field of international criminal justice was un-
dertaken with considerable care. The bulk of the credit for the positive hir-
24
For instance, in the Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court, 17 July 1998, Article
54(1)(a) (https://legal-tools.org/doc/9c9fd2), where the Prosecutor is required to “[i]n order
to establish the truth, extend the investigation to cover all facts and evidence relevant to an
assessment of whether there is criminal responsibility under this Statute, and, in doing so,
investigate incriminating and exonerating circumstances equally”.
25
Prior to joining the ICTY, the investigator in question was employed as an intelligence of-
ficer by a domestic security service.
agers and sub-managers until 2001. This was hardly surprising given that
very few of the police officers employed by the ICTY during its first dec-
ade arrived at the OTP after having witnessed the sort of analytical input
which informs the building of multifaceted criminal cases in which the in-
vestigative targets stand several organization layers above the physical per-
petrators of the underlying criminal acts. As far as the casual observer
could tell, the police officers retained by the OTP for most of its first dec-
ade hailed from the domains of routine domestic policing and (domestic)
murder squads. One has no reason to doubt that the ICTY-OTP investiga-
tors had been highly proficient in these domestic realms. However, the dif-
ficulty with recruitment from these specializations was that what was need-
ed were men and women with a grasp of complex fraud and transnational
crime, insofar as the investigative methodology used in these areas approx-
imates closely that of international criminal investigations.
The exclusion of trial counsel from investigative processes gave rise
to a situation prior to 2001 in which the litigators tended to see the case-
files assigned to them only on the metaphorical eve of trial, that is, after
suspects had been rendered accused persons and, more often than not, al-
ready spent periods of time in pre-trial custody which would be uncon-
scionable in the jurisdictions in which all concerned had worked domesti-
cally. Secondly, owing to the (mis-)recruitment and promotion practices
within the Investigations Division, the files were invariably a mess at the
outset of the trial. One erstwhile senior trial attorney likened what the trial
lawyers were seeing – when they finally did see the case-files – as akin to
“getting inundated with three filing cabinets full of statements and docu-
ments”, which had not been assembled in any coherent manner. 26 Far
worse than the poor organization of the case-files was the fact that a great
many trials commenced with the prosecutors possessing insufficient link-
age evidence to warrant a conviction – naturally enough raising questions
regarding whether the accused ought to have been indicted and detained.
The action taken by the ICTY-OTP in these situations would see the senior
trial attorneys responsible for a case which was in disarray initiate as well
as lead a proper linkage investigation, generally with one of the LRT or
MAT linkage analysts working closely to hand, whilst concurrently leading
the prosecution in court. Manifestly, an approach to investigations and
prosecutions of this nature would never have been tolerated in any of the
26
Quoted in John Hagan, Justice in the Balkans: Prosecuting War Crimes in the Hague Tribu-
nal, University of Chicago Press, 2003, p. 224.
27
There were very few French investigators at the ICTR. Rather, the OTP had a great many
investigators from former French colonies that had retained variants of French procedural
law following independence.
lyst serving within the case-specific team, generally (if the senior trial at-
torney had any sense) at his or her right hand.
9.7.6. The Effective Management of Case-Building Processes
It should not be inferred from the improved investigative practices of the
OTPs of the ICTY and the ICTR that an effective case-building effort
might be achieved only where a senior trial attorney serves in the lead role.
Such an arrangement is desirable, given that prosecution cases, to be effec-
tive, require a clear understanding of the substantive law. However, the in-
creasing number of legally trained, or otherwise legally aware investigators
and analysts working in the system of international criminal justice points
to the potential for an investigator or analyst to serve as a case-specific
team manager, prior to a given case proceeding to trial. Where an investiga-
tor or analyst is assigned to the lead role in such situations, it remains nec-
essary for trial counsel to remain close to hand to advise the case-specific
team manager on questions relating to the intersection of evidence and law.
By way of example, non-lawyers have served as investigative team leaders
at what remains, to date, the only non-public international criminal and
humanitarian law investigative body, that is, the Commission for Interna-
tional Justice and Accountability (‘CIJA’). In particular, CIJA has, on occa-
sion, appointed non-lawyers to the head of investigative teams, with a law-
yer acting as the de facto second in command, generally where the day-to-
day challenges of prima facie evidence collection in high-physical-risk en-
vironments exceed those posed in meeting the legal requirements of effec-
tive case building. 28 In a similar vein, the longstanding ICC-OTP Chief of
Investigations is a former police officer, though his deputy (that is, the In-
vestigations Coordinator) is a Portuguese prosecutor and the case-by-case
investigations at the ICC-OTP are overseen for all intents and purposes by
Prosecutions Division counsel.
9.8. Conclusion
It is the duty of States as well as the supranational institutions which sup-
port international criminal justice to ensure that qualified personnel are ap-
pointed to leadership positions within offices of the prosecutor and, equally,
to engineer their prompt removal where their professional competence or
28
For instance, the CIJA Da’esh Crimes Team has seen three team leaders since January 2014,
each of whom brought to the position significant field experience in a military and intelli-
gence capacity vis-à-vis non-State actors operating in areas of high-intensity armed conflict.
29
Bergsmo, 2018, see above note 8.
leadership identified in this chapter and, in turn, applied them to the offices
of the prosecutor for which they have been entrusted with responsibility.
The examples of Ms. Del Ponte and Dr. Brammertz have been cited in this
chapter, though one hastens to add that there have been others. What has
ultimately set apart the successful leaders from those who have come up
short is their willingness to sack non-performing managers as well as rank-
and-file personnel who ought never to have been retained – conduct which
reflects, amongst other considerations, their understanding of the im-
portance of ensuring excellence in the execution of the investigative and
prosecutorial functions (that is, the core tasks) of an office of the prosecutor.
However, until the principles of effective leadership and management in
(most especially) the area of international criminal investigations are more
widely discussed, the overall prosecutorial output of the system of interna-
tional criminal justice shall continue to fall short of what might be expected
as a reasonable return on the monies which are poured annually into this
endeavour.
Decency as a Prerequisite to
Integrity in International Proceedings
Andrew T. Cayley *
Hans Holbein’s portrait of Sir Thomas More graced the programme of the
conference that gave rise to the papers in this volume. I expect his face to
appear on the cover of the book. He was a man of principle and conscience
at a time, in England, when that took very great courage indeed. In Robert
Bolt’s play, A Man for all Seasons, which depicts the last year of More’s
life, More says:
I believe, when statesmen forsake their own private con-
science for the sake of their public duties, they lead their
country by a short route to chaos. 1
10.1. Introduction
Decency should be a natural part of the private conscience. But it is one of
those human qualities which is hard to define with absolute precision be-
cause all of us have such differing experiences and instincts shaped by the
challenges we have met and the decisions we have made in the face of
those challenges.
The American sociologist and civil rights activist, William E.B. Du
Bois, wrote:
How shall Integrity face Oppression? What shall Honesty do
in the face of Deception, Decency in the face of Insult, Self-
Defence before Blows? How shall Desert and Accomplish-
ment meet Despising, Detraction, and Lies? What shall Virtue
do to meet Brute Force? There are so many answers and so
contradictory; and such differences for those on the one hand
*
Andrew T. Cayley CMG QC is the United Kingdom’s Director of Service Prosecutions and
former Senior Prosecuting Counsel at the International Criminal Court and the International
Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia. Between 2009 and 2013, he was the Interna-
tional Co-Prosecutor of the Extraordinary Chambers in the Courts of Cambodia. The chapter
draws on judgments in cases on which he has worked or been closely associated with.
1
Robert Bolt, A Man for All Seasons, 1954.
2
William .E.B. Du Bois, The Ordeal of Mansart, Kraus-Thomson, 1976, p. 275.
proach, but I think my reflexes are now well-tuned to what decency re-
quires.
The English word ‘decency’ has its origins in the Ancient World. It is
from the Latin present participle ‘decere’, meaning fitting or suitable. De-
cency in the courts is about trust and being honest in court proceedings. I
approach this discussion as someone who has predominantly prosecuted
before the courts. Of the international defence work I have done, I would
readily accept that the duties affecting defence counsel are much more
challenging, in particular balancing the interests of fearlessly defending a
client against the overarching interests of the proper administration of jus-
tice. But in the end, whether prosecuting or defending, if the courts do not
trust us as counsel, they are not going to believe us.
Decency, I would submit, may often require you, particularly when
prosecuting, to act in a way that is not self-serving. It may require you to
lose a point or argument in the courtroom.
Decency, you will find, is at the heart of almost all sets of regulations
for the governance of counsel before domestic and international courts. To
take my own legal system, that of England and Wales, as a straightforward
example: counsel have ten core duties to comply with, and these duties ap-
ply to all counsel whatever the area of law in which they practice. 3 The du-
ties are laid down by an organization called the Bar Standards Board,
which is the independent regulator which governs the conduct of barristers
in England and Wales. 4
The ten core duties are:
1. You must observe your duty to the court in the administration of jus-
tice.
2. You must act in the best interests of each client.
3. You must act with honesty, and with integrity.
4. You must maintain your independence.
5. You must not behave in a way which is likely to diminish the trust and
confidence which the public places in you or in the profession.
6. You must keep the affairs of each client confidential.
3
“The Code of Conduct”, The Bar Standards Board Handbook, fourth edition, 2019, part 2,
sect. B, p. 22 (‘The Core Duties’).
4
Ibid., p. 9.
5
See above note 3 (emphasis added).
6
ICC Code of Professional Conduct for Counsel, 2 December 2005, ICC-ASP/4/Res.1
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/f9ed33) (emphasis added).
7
See, for example, Solicitors Regulatory Authority Overseas Rules, 2013.
8
International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia (‘ICTY’), Code of Professional
Conduct for Counsel Appearing before the International Tribunal, 1997, IT/125 REV. 3
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/rtgkbb).
9
ICTY and International Criminal Tribunal for Rwanda (‘ICTR’), Standards of Professional
Conduct for Prosecution Counsel, Prosecutor’s Regulation No 2 (1999), 14 September 1999
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/d74c40).
in dealing with the parties. Judicial codes for the ad hoc tribunals and the
ICC state broadly similar duties. 10
As I have already discussed, decency can be an abstract concept so,
for the purposes of this chapter, it is of value to give some concrete exam-
ples of how international courts have interpreted requirements of conduct
for both counsel and judges.
10.2. The Prosecutor v. Radislav Krstić
Between 1999 and 2001, I was junior counsel in the Krstić case. 11 It was
the first prosecution at the ICTY for the crime of genocide. It was a har-
rowing trial with evidence which garnered much public attention because
of the nature of the principal charge. Krstić was convicted, after trial, of
genocide, crimes against humanity and a war crime. 12 At first instance, he
was sentenced to forty-six years imprisonment. 13
During the trial, everyone felt the overwhelming weight and tragic
nature of what took place. It had a profound impact on us all. To this day,
nearly twenty years on, reading the first part of the trial judgment, I still
sense this great outpouring of grief and righteous anger in the face of in-
dustrial killing. You can see in those paragraphs how the judges felt. They
were deeply affected by what they had seen and heard, but they had to pub-
licly express that any private indignation they felt had to be put out of their
mind for the sake of a fair trial:
The events of the nine days from July 10-19 1995 in Srebreni-
ca defy description in their horror and their implications for
humankind’s capacity to revert to acts of brutality under the
stresses of conflict. In little over one week, thousands of lives
were extinguished, irreparably rent or simply wiped from the
pages of history.... The Trial Chamber cannot permit itself the
indulgence of expressing how it feels about what happened in
Srebrenica, or even how individuals as well as national and in-
ternational groups not the subject of this case contributed to
the tragedy. This defendant, like all others, deserves individu-
10
See, for example, ICTY, Code of professional conduct for the judges of the Tribunal, 6 July
2016, S/2016/976 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/55lsey); ICC, Code of Judicial Ethics, 2
January 2005, ICC-BD/02-01-05 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/383f8f).
11
ICTY, Prosecutor v. Krstić, Trial Judgement, 2 August 2001, IT-98-33-T (‘Krstić case’)
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/440d3a).
12
Ibid., paras. 687–689.
13
Ibid., para. 726.
14
Ibid., para. 2.
15
Krstić case, Appeals Judgment, 19 April 2004, IT-98-33-A, para. 152 (‘Krstić appeal’)
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/86a108).
16
Ibid., para. 154.
17
ICTY Rules of Procedure and Evidence, November 1999, IT/32/Rev. 17 (‘ICTY Rules’)
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/mo8alp).
18
Ibid.
19
Krstić appeal, para. 154, see above note 15.
20
Ibid.
21
Ibid., para. 155.
22
Ibid., para. 156.
23
ICTY Rules, rule 65 ter E(v), see above note 17.
24
Krstić appeal, para. 156, see above note 15.
25
Ibid., para. 157.
26
Ibid., paras. 157 and 159.
27
Ibid., para. 158.
essarily assist in the interpretation of it. 38 The new Rule 65ter(E) required
the Prosecution to provide the Defence with access to copies of the Prose-
cution’s exhibits prior to trial. 39 Before the amendment, however, the actual
scope of the Rule was open to interpretation, as shown by the contrasting
decisions of the Krstić pre-trial conference and of the Trial Chamber in
Krajišnik and Plavšić. 40 The text of the former Rule 65ter(E) did not ex-
pressly require exhibits themselves to be disclosed but referred only to
them being ‘listed’, suggesting that Rule 65ter(E) was not a means by
which the disclosure of exhibits could be secured. 41 The subsequent
amendment to the Rules suggested, however, that the judges of the Tribunal
recognized that this practice might lead both the Defence and the Prosecu-
tion into difficulties when it comes to contesting the authenticity of exhib-
its. 42 Where the parties contested exhibits, delays to the trial could occur
while adjournments are granted in order to permit the parties to investigate
those exhibits as they are tendered. 43 As such, the subsequent amendment
may have been a matter relevant to the efficient management of the trial
itself, and not the result of any perceived unfairness to the Defence. 44
Furthermore, in Krstić, the Prosecutor had reached an agreement
with Defence Counsel – at the suggestion of the Trial Chamber – and estab-
lished a regime for the disclosure of certain evidence. 45 In agreeing to the
disclosure regime with the Defence, the Prosecution was, in fact, exceeding
its obligations under the Rules in as much as those obligations had been
determined pre-trial. 46 At trial, the Defence did not object to this agreement
and made no complaint regarding the disclosure regime. 47 On appeal, the
Prosecution argued that the Defence’s acceptance of this regime meant that
the Defence could not now claim that the regime was unfair. 48 The Appeals
Chamber did not agree that initial compliance by the Defence with the dis-
38
Ibid.
39
Ibid.
40
Ibid.
41
Ibid., para. 163.
42
Ibid.
43
Ibid.
44
Ibid., para. 164.
45
Ibid.
46
Ibid.
47
Ibid.
48
Ibid.
closure regime could be a basis for refusing to allow the Defence to argue
on appeal that it was unfair. 49 However, to succeed on this ground of appeal,
the Defence would have to establish that it was prevented from properly
investigating the authenticity of the exhibits by the Trial Chamber’s inter-
pretation of the Rule, and that it suffered prejudice as a result. 50 The De-
fence did not establish any prejudice. On the contrary, the Trial Chamber
did permit adjournments which allowed the Defence the opportunity to
contest the authenticity of various exhibits tendered by the Prosecution.
The Appeals Chamber accordingly dismissed this ground of appeal.
During 1999 and 2000, there was an in-built tension in the ICTY
Rules of Procedure and Evidence concerning disclosure. If the Defence
invoked Rule 66(B), and sought inspection of exhibits and other real evi-
dence in the custody and control of the Prosecutor and on which the Prose-
cutor would seek to rely at trial, the Prosecution could then invoke the
same right against the Defence under Rule 67(C). The Defence often did
not want to have to disclose its own documentary evidence before trial. If
the truth were told, I think it was regularly the case that the Defence were
unable to make disclosure of their own documents before the beginning of
trial because they did not know what documents they would be seeking to
rely on. This decision by the Appeals Chamber in Krstić centred around
disclosure rights. It was technically absolutely correct in that you could not,
at that time, circumvent reciprocal discovery rights by relying on rules
around pre-trial preparation. That said, a fundamental internationally rec-
ognized right in any criminal trial, at the time of Krstić, was for an accused
person “to be informed promptly, in a language which he understands and
in detail, of the nature and cause of the accusation against him”. 51
The Appeals Chamber held that there was no impropriety by the
Prosecution, as they had simply applied the ICTY Rules as they then exist-
ed. But, arguably, for Krstić to know the case against him promptly and in
detail, all exhibits should have been disclosed prior to trial and not piece-
meal as the case went along. The potential loss of reciprocal discovery was
49
Ibid., para. 165.
50
Ibid.
51
European Convention on Human Rights, 3 September 1953, Article 6(3)(a) (emphasis added)
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/8267cb). See also International Covenant on Civil and Po-
litical Rights, 23 March 1976, Article 14(3) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/2838f3); Amer-
ican Convention on Human Rights, 18 July 1978, Article 8(2)(b) (https://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/1152cf).
tactically significant for the Prosecution, but the decision not to disclose
exhibits to the Defence led to this rather unfortunate result of prima facie
unfairness, even though the Defence could not show any prejudice.
During the presentation of the Defence’s case at trial, the Prosecution
introduced taped evidence that was played to Krstić during his cross-
examination. 52 The existence of the taped evidence had not been disclosed
to the Defence until after the closure of both the Prosecution’s case and the
evidence-in-chief of the accused, even though the Prosecution had been in
possession of it for some time. 53 The Defence had, however, been aware of
the contents of the tape prior to its introduction to the Trial Chamber, and
had not objected to it being played at the time. 54 On appeal, the Defence
submitted that a new trial should be ordered for two reasons: the alleged
impossibility of the Trial Chamber ignoring the contents of the tape; and
the Prosecution’s employment of so-called ‘sharp’ trial tactics. 55
The contents of the tape, if true, were devastating for Krstić:
Intercepted and recorded on August 2 1995, it appears to refer
to what action should be taken against Bosnian men who fled
the massacre and were caught in the hills around Srebrenica.
Krstić: Are you working down there?
Obrenovic: We are working, indeed.
K: Good.
O: There are still a few, [they] got snared ...
K: Yeah.
O: ... either by guns or mines.
K: Kill all in turn. Fuck their mothers!
O: Everything is going according to plan.
K: Don't leave a single one alive!
O: What?
K: Do not leave anyone alive!
O: Everything is going according to plan. Everything. 56
52
Krstić appeal, para. 167, see above note 15.
53
Ibid.
54
Ibid.
55
Ibid., para. 168.
56
The Guardian, “Serb major denies Bosnian genocide”, 19 April 2001.
The Defence argued that, once the tape had been played to the Trial
Chamber, it became impossible for the Trial Chamber to ignore its contents
when deciding on the guilt and sentence of the accused, even though the
Trial Chamber had excluded it from evidence. 57 The Appeals Chamber did
not accept this argument. The Appeals Chamber stated that the role of
Judges as arbiters of both fact and law was essential to the basic function-
ing of the Tribunal. 58 Judges were frequently required to disregard evi-
dence from their deliberations, not only as an incident to their role as Judg-
es but also as an acknowledged part of their judicial function in assessing
the admissibility of evidence at trial. 59 The Defence had shown neither the
existence of any prejudice resulting from the playing of the tape nor that
the contents of the tape were taken into account or relied upon by the Trial
Chamber in arriving at its conclusions. 60 There were no grounds to support
the Defence’s submission that the playing of the tape influenced the Judges,
and therefore no re-trial was warranted. 61
The Defence argued that the manner in which the tape was used con-
stituted a ‘sharp’ trial tactic by the Prosecution and that the Appeals Cham-
ber should deter future prosecutorial misconduct by granting the Defence a
re-trial. 62 The Prosecution defended its conduct by arguing that there was
no directly applicable Rule prohibiting parties from introducing evidence in
the manner described. 63 The Defence suggested that the Prosecution delib-
erately declined to disclose the tape as an exhibit, deciding instead for tac-
tical reasons to conceal it for use in cross-examination “so that the defence
would not have an opportunity to explain it”. 64 The Decision of the Trial
Chamber to exclude the evidence, together with the nature of the evidence
in question and the amount of time in which the Prosecution possessed it,
supported the Defence’s submission. 65 There appeared to be sufficient
grounds in the circumstances to question the propriety of the Prosecution as
57
Krstić appeal, para. 169, see above note 15.
58
Ibid., para. 170.
59
Ibid.
60
Ibid., para. 171.
61
Ibid.
62
Ibid., para. 172.
63
Ibid.
64
Ibid., para. 173.
65
Ibid., para. 174.
regards the disclosure of this evidence. 66 The Appeals Chamber did not ac-
cept that a re-trial was necessary but instead concluded that where counsel
had engaged in such misconduct, the appropriate sanctions were provided
by Rule 46 (Misconduct of Counsel). 67 So here the Appeals Chamber re-
garded this disclosure decision by the Prosecution as professional miscon-
duct – potentially a lack of integrity or dishonesty.
At the time, I did not understand the decision of the OTP not to rely
on this evidence in its case-in-chief because it was potentially powerful
evidence. Also, as a general rule in English law, all evidence on which the
Prosecution intends to rely on as probative of guilt should be called before
the close of their own case. 68 Subject to a number of limited exceptions, the
Prosecution cannot call new evidence after the start of the Defence case. 69
So for me, at the time, the decision by the OTP to introduce this evidence
for the first time in the accused’s cross-examination by the OTP was ill-
judged. I recall it went down badly with the Trial Chamber judges too and
there was a strong sense at the time that they were disappointed by the
conduct of the OTP. Since the evidence was excluded by the judges, it lost
any value it might have had. On appeal, Krstić was found not to have gen-
ocidal intent. To this day, I wonder had we adduced this evidence in the
normal fashion, in our own case, whether that outcome would have been
different. We will never know.
The last issue I will address from the Krstić appeal was an alleged
violation of Rule 68 of the ICTY Rules by the Prosecution. 70 I suspect Rule
68 was one of the most oft-quoted of the Rules of Procedure and Evidence.
This Rule required the Prosecution to disclose to the Defence any material
which, in the actual knowledge of the Prosecutor, suggested the innocence
or mitigated the guilt of the accused or affected the credibility of Prosecu-
tion’s evidence. So, the obligation to disclose exculpatory evidence to the
Defence. This obligation goes to the heart of what decency means to a
prosecutor because, of course, this obligation requires a prosecutor to be
like a minister of justice and to ensure that the process of prosecution is a
fair one, whereby the accused receives information known to the prosecu-
66
Ibid.
67
Ibid.
68
United Kingdom, Court of Appeal, R. v. Rice, Judgment, 29 January 1963, [1963] 1 QB 857.
69
David Ormerod and David Perry, Blackstone’s Criminal Practice, Oxford University Press,
2019, pp. 2580–2585.
70
Krstić appeal, para. 176, see above note 15.
tor which undermines the prosecutor’s case or assists the accused’s defence.
Undoubtedly, in large complex international cases, it was not always clear
what was exculpatory and what was not because it was not always apparent
what defence or defences the accused was running. Defences often devel-
oped throughout a case. And I do not in any way, infer criticism of defence
counsel for this uncertainty. Having done some international defence work
myself, it was often hard to simply encapsulate what the defence was going
to be and what constituted all the evidence which would be helpful to the
client and was in the prosecutor’s possession. So, the disclosure of exculpa-
tory material, pursuant to Rule 68, led to many sleepless nights for prose-
cutors. It often provided for dramatic court encounters where such material
was discovered late on in a trial and then disclosed to the defence, who
would understandably shout foul and ask for sanctions to be applied to the
prosecutor. Judges of the international courts, I think, became equally frus-
trated by the application of this Rule and the procedural mishaps that oc-
curred around it.
In the Krstić case, the Defence argued that the Prosecution violated
its disclosure obligations under Rule 68 by: failing to disclose a number of
witness statements containing exculpatory material; failing to disclose ex-
culpatory material amongst other evidence without identifying that material
as exculpatory; preventing the Defence from taking copies of exculpatory
materials, and instead requiring the Defence to view the materials at the
offices of the Prosecution; and failing to make two disclosures as soon as
practicable. 71
So, the Defence argued that a number of interviews with witnesses,
conducted by the Prosecution prior to the Trial Chamber delivering the
Judgement, contained exculpatory evidence and that the failure of the Pros-
ecution to disclose that material at that time constituted a breach of Rule
68. 72 The Prosecution conceded, at the time, that of the ten witness state-
ments filed by the Defence in its first Rule 115 Motion, six “fall within the
ambit of Rule 68”, but argued that the other four statements did not fall
within the Rule, and that, in any case, the Defence had been unable to es-
tablish prejudice resulting from the failure to disclose. 73
71
Ibid.
72
Ibid., para. 177.
73
Ibid.
74
Ibid., para. 178.
75
Ibid.
76
Ibid.
77
Ibid.
78
Ibid., para. 179.
79
Ibid.
80
Ibid.
81
Ibid., para. 180.
82
Ibid.
83
Ibid.
84
Ibid., para. 182.
85
Ibid., paras. 183–186.
86
Ibid.
87
Ibid., para. 189.
patory. 88 The Appeals Chamber agreed with the Prosecution that Rule 68
did not require the Prosecution to identify the material being disclosed to
the Defence as exculpatory. 89 The jurisprudence of the Tribunal showed
that, while some Trial Chambers had recognized that it would be fairer for
the Prosecution to do so, there was no prima facie requirement, absent an
order of the Trial Chamber to that effect, that it must do so. 90 However, the
fact that there was no prima facie obligation on the Prosecution to identify
the disclosed Rule 68 material as exculpatory did not prevent the accused
from arguing, as a ground of appeal, that he suffered prejudice as a result of
the Prosecution’s failure to do so. 91 Here the Appeals Chamber had not
been persuaded by the Defence that the failure of the Prosecution to identi-
fy exculpatory evidence it disclosed resulted in any prejudice to the De-
fence. 92 They found the Defence had both sufficient time in which to ana-
lyse the material, and the opportunity to challenge it during cross-
examination. 93 This ground of appeal was dismissed. I confess I disagreed
with this finding. My feeling was, while there was no obligation to identify
specific sentences or paragraphs in documents which were potentially ex-
culpatory, at least identifying single documents or groups of documents
which were potentially exculpatory seemed to me to be the minimum that
should be expected of the Prosecution. And I still believe that today.
Next, the Appeals Chamber had to consider whether Rule 68 required
the Prosecution to allow the Defence to take copies of exculpatory materi-
al. 94 The Defence submitted that, in only being permitted to view copies of
exculpatory evidence in the Prosecution’s office, and being refused copies
of the materials, the Prosecution breached Rule 68, as well as its obligation
to act as a ‘minister of justice’ – so in effect with fairness and decency. 95
On a plain reading of Rule 68, the Prosecution was found to be merely
obliged to disclose the existence of Rule 68 material, not to provide the
actual material itself. 96 The Appeals Chamber found if the Defence had
88
Ibid.
89
Ibid., para. 190.
90
Ibid.
91
Ibid., para. 191.
92
Ibid., para. 192.
93
Ibid.
94
Ibid., para. 194.
95
Ibid.
96
Ibid., para. 195.
demonstrated that the preparation of its case had been prejudiced by only
being able to view the Rule 68 material held by the Prosecutor, then it
should have brought this prejudice to the attention of the Trial Chamber. 97
The Prosecution did disclose the existence of this material, and the Defence
did not complain to the Trial Chamber, at the time, it was unable to make
copies. 98 The Defence did not persuade the Appeals Chamber that it did
indeed suffer any prejudice during the trial, and so this ground of appeal
was dismissed. 99 Whatever the strict reading of the rule, one might question
why the Prosecution would not provide copies of potentially exculpatory
documents to the Defence to avoid later dispute? What advantage did they
gain in this situation by not providing copies? I can see situations where the
provider of a document, such as a government or international organization,
might not wish copies of sensitive documents to be copied and distributed
beyond the Prosecution, but I cannot see any advantage for the Prosecution
here in not providing copies of Rule 68 material to the Defence.
Lastly, I want to consider the appellate finding in the Krstić appeal
on whether two disclosures were made ‘as soon as practicable’. Here the
Defence submitted that certain disclosures were not made ‘as soon as prac-
ticable’, as required by Rule 68. 100 For example, disclosures of 25 June
2000 occurred over two years after the Prosecution came into possession of
the evidence, and more than three months after the trial had begun. 101 Dis-
closures of 5 March 2001 occurred over three months after the Prosecution
came into possession of the evidence. 102 The Defence also alleged that the
Prosecution deliberately withheld evidence in order eventually to avail it-
self of the reciprocal discovery mechanism of Rules 67(B) and 67(C). 103
I was aware in the year 2000 of the amount of material that was col-
lectively in possession of the OTP, and the time it took to translate that ma-
terial from Bosnian and Serbian into English and French. And then to study
it and decide its importance, including whether it was exculpatory. The Ap-
peals Chamber was sympathetic to the argument of the Prosecution that, in
most instances, material requires processing, translation, analysis and iden-
97
Ibid.
98
Ibid.
99
Ibid.
100
Ibid., para. 196.
101
Ibid.
102
Ibid.
103
Ibid.
104
Ibid., para. 197.
105
Ibid.
106
Ibid.
107
Ibid.
108
Ibid., para.198.
109
Ibid.
110
Ibid., para.199.
111
Ibid.
112
ICTY, The Prosecutor v. Šainović et al., Trial Chamber, Judgement, 26 February 2009, IT-
05-87-T, vol. 3, para. 1138 (‘Šainović et al. case’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/d79e85).
113
Šainović et al. case, Judgement Summary, 26 February 2009, p. 4 (https://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/c75af2).
114
Ibid., p. 12.
115
Šainović et al. case, para. 1212, see above note 112.
116
Šainović et al. case, Appeals Chamber, Judgement, 23 January 2014, IT-05-87-A, para. 176
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/81ac8c).
117
Ibid.
Lukić’s view, showed “disparaging treatment” and argued that the pressure
of the Tribunal’s completion strategy coupled with Judge Bonomy’s prior
work in advocating the speeding-up of trials in Scotland, might have been
the reason for such “prejudgement [or] bias”. 118 Lukić alleged that as a re-
sult of this bias: (i) he received a significantly higher sentence compared to
that of Ojdanić and Lazarević, and was sentenced to 22 years of imprison-
ment along with other co-accused who, unlike him, did not have circum-
stances in mitigation; 119 (ii) his voluntary surrender, unlike that of Laz-
arević, was not regarded as a mitigating factor; 120 (iii) Milutinović, who
had attended the same meetings and had a similar level of knowledge of the
crimes, was acquitted; 121 (iv) motions filed by Lukić for admission of doc-
uments from the bar table were dismissed by the Trial Chamber; 122 and (v)
the evidence of defence witnesses was almost entirely disregarded in the
Trial Judgement, thus suggesting that Lukić’s Defence had not been con-
sidered. 123
In response, the Prosecution submitted that Lukić had failed to
demonstrate an appearance of bias and that the examples he alleged show,
instead, the efforts of the Presiding Judge to ensure the fair and expeditious
conduct of the proceedings. 124 The Prosecution argued that the Trial Cham-
ber correctly distinguished the criminal responsibility of the individual co-
accused, had valid reasons for denying the admission of certain evidence
tendered by Lukić and provided detailed conclusions on the credibility of
the defence witnesses. 125
Lukić replied that the combination of the Trial Judgement’s “openly
hostile disposition” towards him, the difference in treatment he received
compared to that received by Milutinović, Lazarević and Ojdanić, and the
impugned remarks of the Presiding Judge established bias that invalidated
the Trial Judgement. 126
118
Ibid.
119
Ibid.
120
Ibid.
121
Ibid.
122
Ibid.
123
Ibid.
124
Ibid., para. 177.
125
Ibid.
126
Ibid., para.178.
127
Ibid., para. 179.
128
Ibid.
129
Ibid., paras. 180–181.
might not bring an impartial and unprejudiced mind to the issues arising in
the case. 130 The Appeals Chamber emphasized that Judges enjoy a pre-
sumption of impartiality and that there is a high threshold to reach in order
to rebut that presumption. 131 In this respect, the Appeals Chamber had held
that:
in the absence of evidence to the contrary, it must be assumed
that the Judges of the Tribunal can disabuse their minds of any
irrelevant personal beliefs or predispositions. 132 It is for the
Appellant to adduce sufficient evidence to satisfy the Appeals
Chamber that [the] Judge […] was not impartial in his case.
There is a high threshold to reach in order to rebut the pre-
sumption of impartiality. 133 As has been stated, disqualifica-
tion is only made out by showing that there is a reasonable
apprehension of bias by reason of prejudgement, and this must
be firmly established. 134
The Appeals Chamber pointed out that Lukić did not raise the ques-
tion of Judge Bonomy’s impartiality before the Trial Chamber. 135 The Ap-
peals Chamber stated such an omission could constitute waiver of the right
to raise the matter on appeal, but it had been the practice of the Appeals
Chamber to treat the issue of bias as a special circumstance allowing it to
address the merits of the challenge despite the waiver. 136 So the Appeals
Chamber considered the merits of Lukić’s challenges first, addressing
Judge Bonomy’s previous involvement in the Milošević case.
The Appeals Chamber noted that, following the resignation of Judge
Richard May and pursuant to an order of the President of the Tribunal, on
10 June 2004 Judge Bonomy was assigned to Trial Chamber III, hearing
the case of Milošević. 137 He performed the functions of a trial judge in that
case until 14 March 2006 when, following the death of Milošević, the pro-
ceedings were terminated. 138 Lukić alleged that the Milošević case shared
130
Ibid., para. 181.
131
Ibid.
132
Ibid.
133
Ibid.
134
Ibid., citing ICTY, Prosecutor v. Anto Furundžija, Appeals Chamber, Judgement, 21 July
2000, IT-95-17/1-A (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/660d3f/).
135
Ibid., para. 182.
136
Ibid.
137
Ibid., para. 183.
138
Ibid.
many common witnesses with his case. 139 However, he had failed to pre-
sent any arguments explaining how Judge Bonomy’s involvement in the
Milošević proceedings would lead a reasonable and informed observer to
apprehend bias. 140 The Appeals Chamber pointed out that the Judges of the
Tribunal often become involved in several trials which, by their very nature,
concern issues that overlap and may be presented with witness testimony
that was already admitted in another case. 141 The Appeals Chamber as-
sumed, in the absence of evidence to the contrary that, by virtue of their
training and experience, Judges will rule fairly on the issues before them,
relying solely and exclusively on the evidence adduced in the particular
case. 142 Lukić’s generic contention falls short of rebutting this presumption
of impartiality. His submission was therefore dismissed. 143
Second, the Appeals Chamber addressed Judge Bonomy’s prior work
in advocating the speeding-up of trials in Scotland and the ICTY’s comple-
tion strategy. Lukić submitted that Judge Bonomy “was known in Scotland
for his work in advocating the speeding-up of the trial process”. 144 He re-
ferred in this respect to a 142-page document entitled “Improving Practice:
2002 Review of the Practices and Procedure of the High Court of Justici-
ary” authored by Judge Bonomy. 145 Again, however, Lukić did not substan-
tiate his contention nor provide any precise references to information in the
document that would support the allegation of apprehension of bias. 146 He
did not specify how the document was relevant to the work of the Tribunal
and, in particular, to his case. 147 So the Appeals Chamber dismissed this
argument on appeal too. 148
Regarding Lukić’s first appeal point on bias, candidly, I always had
concerns about the judges’ involvement in trials with overlapping factual
bases. Not because such involvement went to their decency or integrity.
Judges are credited with being able to do the mental gymnastics required to
139
Ibid., para. 184.
140
Ibid.
141
Ibid.
142
Ibid.
143
Ibid.
144
Ibid. para. 185.
145
Ibid.
146
Ibid.
147
Ibid.
148
Ibid.
149
Ibid. para. 186.
150
Ibid. para. 187.
151
Ibid. para. 188.
152
Ibid.
directed Lukić to proceed with another question. 153 The trial record indicat-
ed that, prior to the impugned remark, the Prosecution objected to the ques-
tion put to the witness by Lukić’s co-counsel and the Presiding Judge in-
tervened, inquiring into its relevance. A hypothetical fair-minded observer,
properly informed, would recognize that the Presiding Judge’s allegoric
remark was made in the context of an intervention, the purpose of which
was to ensure that the mode of the witness examination was effective. 154
Accordingly, the Appeals Chamber found that no appearance of bias had
been demonstrated in this case.
Lukić further claimed that on two occasions the Presiding Judge pre-
vented him “from attempting to make a record and be heard”. 155 Lukić re-
ferred to a statement of the Presiding Judge made on 14 February 2008:
JUDGE BONOMY: Mr. Lukic, sit down, please. Mr. Mija-
tovic can answer questions[.] 156
He also refers to the following exchange which took place on 4 March
2008:
JUDGE BONOMY: Sit down. You’re just interfering with the
cross-examination now. MR. IVETIC: I don’t believe so, Your
Honour. I think this is a very important point. JUDGE
BONOMY: Sit down. MR. IVETIC: And I want it on the rec-
ord. JUDGE BONOMY: Sit down and deal with it in re-
examination. 157
In response, the Prosecution argued that in both instances the inter-
vention of the Presiding Judge was appropriate as, first, he directed Lukić’s
lead counsel not to give evidence on behalf of the witness, and, second, he
overruled an unfounded objection by Lukić’s co-counsel. 158
As shown by the trial record, in the first instance, Lukić’s lead coun-
sel intervened when the Presiding Judge was seeking to elicit an answer
from Miroslav Mijatovic concerning the reporting obligations of the Koso-
vo Secretariats of the Interior. A reading of the relevant section of the tran-
script showed that not only was Lukić’s lead counsel not prevented from
153
Ibid.
154
Ibid., para. 189.
155
Ibid., para. 190.
156
Ibid.
157
Ibid.
158
Ibid., para. 191.
159
Ibid., para. 192.
160
Ibid.
161
Ibid.
162
Ibid., para. 193.
163
Ibid.
164
Ibid., para. 194.
165
Ibid., citing Ljubivoje Joksić, 8 February 2008, T. 21925.
166
Ibid., para. 195.
167
Ibid.
168
Ibid.
169
Ibid.
170
Ibid., para. 196.
171
Ibid., para. 197.
172
Ibid.
173
Ibid.
174
Ibid.
175
Ibid., para. 198.
176
Ibid.
177
Ibid., para. 199.
tion submitted that the Presiding Judge’s reaction to the allegation of dis-
honesty made by Lukić’s co-counsel against the Prosecution during his
Closing Arguments was appropriate, in that inaccuracies in the Prosecu-
tion’s Closing Brief were not a sufficient basis for an accusation that the
Prosecution purposefully sought to mislead the Trial Chamber. 178
The impugned statement reads:
Mr. Ivetic, I’m not prepared to sit back any longer and listen
to allegations of lack of candour when there have been many
instances in this trial when the Lukic briefs have been less
than accurate without the allegation being made against you of
lack of candour. Do you consider that what you’re doing is an
appropriate way to be addressing us in regard to matters which
do not simply on the face of your assertion justify that
claim? 179
It is evident from the transcript that Judge Bonomy’s remark was
made in response to the following statement of Lukić’s co-counsel:
You cannot believe a word of what is contained in the [Prose-
cution’s] brief because they make a mockery of candour and
honesty in their citations. 180
Lukić’s co-counsel later recognized that “perhaps candour is a strong
word”, but maintained that the Trial Chamber should carefully examine the
evidence cited by the Prosecution. 181 The Presiding Judge responded as
follows:
[Y]our actual remarks were that the Prosecution submissions
make a mockery of candour and honesty, and that's just one of
a series of remarks that bear the interpretation that there is a
deliberate attempt on the part of the Prosecution to mislead the
Bench. Now, we recognise the highly charged atmosphere
which surrounds this stage in the proceedings; nevertheless,
we regret that you have not had the courtesy to recognise that
the language you've just used is not appropriate language for
counsel appearing in any Tribunal. At this late stage in the
proceedings, we choose to simply record that we do not accept
178
Ibid.
179
Ibid., para. 200.
180
Ibid.
181
Ibid.
182
Ibid.
183
Ibid., para. 201.
right course. And that is very hard. In his book, Justice for All and How to
Achieve It, he wrote this about his time at the ICTY:
The way in which any country’s lawyers work can determine
the fairness of a trial quite as much as the law itself does. The
UK legal system historically depended for its integrity sub-
stantially on the independence of its barrister advocates – usu-
ally genuinely and completely independent practitioners –
who earned fees on a case-by case basis and whose only sale-
able asset were their reputations. They knew that one obvious
professional blunder or a breach of ethical standards could be
terminal for reputation and career. Whatever their internal in-
clinations they were normally pushed by powerful vectors to
behave honestly, honourably, openly and incompliance with
professional standards. They had too much to lose if they
didn’t. 184
Before coming to the ICTY in 1999, Geoffrey Nice had spent nearly
thirty years as an independent practitioner at the English bar. His reputation
came before him, and decency and fairness, for the reasons in the quoted
passage above, were in his bones. I know because, as a young lawyer, I
went to him for advice. The passage from his book succinctly demonstrates,
that in the end, whatever the law says, decency depends on the strength and
chosen direction of individuals. Most of us instinctively know what decen-
cy requires of us before the courts. There can be instances, certainly, where
it is not clear regarding the right thing to do, but I would submit that these
instances are rare indeed and that by and large, if there is uncertainty – say,
for example, in whether to disclose material to the defence or not – it is al-
ways preferable to disclose unless there are compelling reasons not to dis-
close that material. And, then, the court should be consulted.
I would add here, too, that it is a lot easier on yourself to be straight-
forward and honest in a case because then you do not have to constantly
keep reminding yourself of what you have most recently said or written.
Your relations with the other parties and the judges are based on the trust
and confidence that you are speaking candidly about the case, the evidence
and the law. You are under much less strain, and you live longer.
In international criminal trials, there has been an historic risk that the
nature of the cases and the terrible crimes required relentless and hard-
184
Geoffrey Nice, Justice for All and How to Achieve It, Scala Arts & Heritage, London, 2017,
p. 301.
185
Robert Bolt, A Man for All Seasons, 1954.
11.1. Introduction
When the explosion of nationalism destroyed Yugoslavia primarily because
Serbian chauvinists and their leader Slobodan Milošević wanted to make
Serbia Great again, a prominent colleague journalist in Belgrade said to me:
“these are hard times”. In the Serbo-Croatian language, the word is the
same for hard and heavy, so hard and heavy times. I think of this often be-
cause these are also hard and heavy times in, to quote one of the last presi-
dents of Yugoslavia, “a strange and dangerous world”. 2
The world has always been strange (and fascinating and beautiful, if
I may add), but it has never been more dangerous, or in greater peril, be-
*
Julija Bogoeva holds a law degree from the University of Belgrade. As a journalist she
reported from the ICTY the first four years. For thirteen years, she was a researcher at the
ICTY Office of the Prosecutor. She is the co-editor of the book Srebrenica – Ein Prozess,
and author of the analysis “The War in Yugoslavia in ICTY Judgements”.
1
Thomas Sankara, a man of integrity, President of Burkina Faso 1983-1987 (assassinated), in
a 1985 interview with Swiss journalist Jean-Philippe Rapp: “Interview de Jean Philippe
Rapp réalisé en 1985: ‘Oser inventer l’avenir’” (available on the Thomas Sankara’s web
site).
2
Janez Drnovšek, “Interview with the President of the Republic for radio Štajerski val”, Pres-
ident of the Republic of Slovenia, 17 January 2007 (available on the President’s archived
web site).
cause of the real threat of nuclear war, 3 the existence of nuclear and other
weapons of mass destruction, and because of the effects of human acceler-
ated global warming.
This chapter is a personal reflection on the significance of integrity,
with a focus on the International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugosla-
via (‘ICTY’) and the International Criminal Court (‘ICC’).
11.2. The Context: These Are Not Times of Integrity
At the outset, I would like to mention some elements more directly relevant
to the very important topic here in the contemporary context.
These are not times of integrity in any meaning of the term, nor times
of justice, equality, fraternity, and human dignity:
• The world population has never been more depressed, according to
the latest research; 4 and no wonder.
• Finance and competition are religion, and money is God; market-
based societies have led to repugnant forms of inequality being nor-
malized, 5 while “a fundamental truth – that peace rests on social jus-
3
UN Secretary-General António Guterres, “Remarks to the Conference on Disarmament”, 25
February 2019, stating that “I will be blunt. Key components of the international arms con-
trol architecture are collapsing.”; John Mecklin, “A new abnormal: It is still 2 minutes to
midnight – 2019 Doomsday Clock Statement”, Bulletin of the Atomic Scientists, 24 January
2019 (available on its web site); Scott Ritter, “One Minute to Midnight”, Truthdig, 12 Feb-
ruary 2019 (available on its web site), which states that “I disagree, however, with his use of
the word ‘slightly’ to describe the situation we face, and I dissent from the bulletin’s deci-
sion to stay the hands of the Doomsday Clock. Humanity is sleepwalking toward global an-
nihilation, furthered by a collective amnesia about the threat posed by nuclear weapons, es-
pecially in an environment void of meaningful arms control […] The world is on the edge of
the nuclear abyss. It’s one minute before midnight and we are acting as if we have time. We
don’t”.
4
Julie Ray, “World Took a Negative Turn in 2017”, Gallup, 12 September 2018 (available on
its web site); The Edelman Trust Barometer published global research in late 2017 showing
that on average 53% of people worldwide felt the system they lived in was failing. Respond-
ents expressed a “sense of injustice”, “lack of hope”, “lack of confidence” and “desire for
change”. In countries like France, Germany, Italy, US, Spain, the UK and the Netherlands,
between 56% and 72% of the population described a meltdown of their trust in democratic
society, see “2017 Edelman Trust Barometer”, Edelman, 21 January 2017 (available on its
web site).
5
See Boaventura de Sousa Santos, The End of the Cognitive Empire, Duke University Press,
Durham and London, 2018, Preface: Peter Phillips (author of Giants: The Global Power
Elite, Seven Stories Press, New York, 2018) examines the roles and networks of the world’s
richest and most powerful in interview with The Real News, see “The Global Power Elite: A
Transnational Class”, The Real News Network, 26 December 2018 (available on its web site).
In the interview, Phillips said:
In that sixty, seventy year period now, we’ve seen a globalization of power and wealth in
the world so that capital is concentrated in very, very few hands, the hands of what I call
the giants, these are the transnational investment companies. Seventeen of them have
over a trillion dollars in assets collectively, seventeen controlled forty-one trillion dollars
in 2017. They represent and are the investment, literally the investment banks and in-
vestment advisers, for the two thousand plus billionaires and the thirty-six million mil-
lionaires in the world who put their money into investment capital where they want to
get a return, annual return. And that’s been concentrated, the wealth has concentrated
even greater now, it’s like eight people have control over half the wealth in the world.
But what it boils down to is eighty percent of the people in the world live on less than
ten dollars a day, half of the people in the world live on less than three dollars a day, and
about a quarter live on less than two. So there’s massive inequality. 30,000 people a day
die from starvation and malnutrition, so there’s this ongoing massacre of people. When
there’s more than enough food in the world, a third of it’s thrown away because it’s just
not profitable to sell it. So this whole system is pretty much non-humanitarian, based
upon gaining profit and capital concentration, and of those seventeen giant investment
firms, there’s only 199 people that manage those firms. So they’re deciding how wealth
will be invested, fifty trillion dollars worth now, and making those kinds of decisions.
And their biggest problem is they’ve got more capital than they’ve got safe places to put
it in.
Henry Girouw, “Resisting the Weaponization of Ignorance in the Age of Trump”,
Truthout, 12 February 2019 (available on its web site), where he wrote:
A morbid inequality now shapes all aspects of life in the United States. Three men – Jeff
Bezos, Warren Buffett and Bill Gates – have among them as much wealth as the bottom
half of U.S. society. In a society of pervasive ignorance, such wealth is viewed as the
outcome of the actions and successes of the individual actors. But in a society in which
civic literacy and reason rule, such wealth would be considered characteristic of an
economy appropriately named casino capitalism. In a society in which 80 percent of U.S.
workers live paycheck to paycheck, and 20 percent of all children live below the poverty
line, such inequalities in wealth and power constitute forms of domestic terrorism – that
is, state-initiated violence or terrorism practiced in one’s own country against one’s own
people...We live in dangerous times and there is an urgent need for more individuals, in-
stitutions and social movements to come together in an effort to construct a new political
and social imaginary. We must support each other in coming to believe that the current
regimes of tyranny can be resisted, that alternative futures are possible and that acting on
these beliefs will make radical change happen.
Richard Wolff, “Economic Update: Is U.S. Capitalism In Decline?”, The Real News
Network, 9 July 2019 (available on its web site), where he stated that “[i]n 2018 the average
pay of an American CEO was – 238,000 dollars a week, the average pay of an American
worker was – 752 dollars a week”. Moreover, according to research of Jörg Wiegratz, Lec-
turer in Political Economy of Global Development at University of Leeds,
we are currently living in the age of fraud. Fraud has become mainstream; it is at high
levels, institutionalized, at the core of “the system” and part and parcel of the
(re)production of contemporary society. That applies to many societies, not just in the
often discussed Global South but also in the Global North.
tice has been ushered out of our sight and consciousness”, noted an
author on the digital publication platform Social Europe.
• The principle of legality, democratic institutions and the rule of law
are being undermined or openly abandoned.
• Trust between States, in national institutions and a rule-based order is
at a breaking point, as stated by the United Nations Secretary-
General (‘UNSG’). 6 Research tells us that trust in justice and the
courts is low and that, in many countries of the global south and
north, the military and the police are trusted more. 7 It also confirms
that “[d]istrust in domestic judiciaries tends to go together with dis-
trust in the international judiciary”. 8
Humanity seems to have lost moral compass:
• States are becoming more and more secretive, effectively ensuring
impunity for the ruling class, including for core international crimes,
while expanding their surveillance powers over everything and eve-
ryone. 9
• Whole countries are being destroyed on false pretences in criminal
wars with new levels of barbarity and violations of international hu-
The seven key characteristics of contemporary fraud in the global economy include: (i)
fraud is at an industrial scale; (ii) it has become significantly routine; (iii) it is ever more bla-
tant; (iv) it is spreading across the economy and society, that is, it is affecting new areas,
such as education; (v) it produces staggering levels of social harm; (vi) it is co-produced by
economic and state actors; and (vii) it implicates the most powerful members of society (the
ruling class, transnational companies, top managers, top state officials, the rich and famous,
celebrated role models, etc.). See Jörg Wiegratz, “The Age of Fraud: the Link Between
Capitalism and Profiteering by Deception”, Counter Punch, 26 September 2018 (available
on its web site).
6
UN Secretary-General António Guterres, “Address to the General Assembly”, 25 September
2018.
7
Courtney Johnson, “Trust in the Military Exceeds Trust in Other Institutions in Western
Europe and U.S.”, Pew Research Center, 4 September 2018 (available on its web site).
8
Erik Voeten, “Public Opinion and the Legitimacy of International Courts”, in Theoretical
Inquires in Law, 2013, vol. 14, no. 2, p. 425. It is notable that in Gallup’s 2005 “Voice of the
People” survey, the single broad comparative survey the author found that asked about the
ICC, those with negative sentiments outnumbered those who were positive only in Austria,
Croatia, Israel, Serbia and the United States.
9
William Binney, “Random Slaughter: ‘The NSA Tracks Them and the CIA Whacks Them’”,
Information Clearing House, 8 August 2018 (available on its web site)
12
Albie Sachs, The Strange Alchemy of Life and Law, Oxford University Press, 2009, pp. 148–
149.
13
Frank M. Johnson Jr., “Civilization Integrity, and Justice: Some Observations on the Func-
tion of the Judiciary in Honor of Judge Irving L. Goldberg”, in SMU Law Review, 1989, vol.
43, pp. 650–651, 655.
the truth, the restoration of individual dignity and the reparation of the in-
tegrity of community and society.
In international (criminal) justice, people of integrity, the very best,
are needed for attaining the highest standards of law, the best law, 14 the
highest standards of uncovering the truth and of justice. They are needed
because of the exceptional nature of the crimes, because of the extraordi-
nary complexity and hostilities of the international environment in which
they operate, and because it is only right that the best should judge the
worst excesses of humanity, demonstrating fairness and advantages of jus-
tice over revenge.
Integrity entails incorruptibility, a particularly important element,
which protects against instrumentalization; against the outside influence
and internal pressures. It means speaking up and speaking out whenever
that is called for without fear or calculation.
A 2018 Oxford University multi-disciplinary review of the definition
of integrity in academic literature, 15 40 journals across seven disciplines,
including law, as well as books, found that virtue and ethical framework
appears most productive for the grounding and understanding of the nor-
mative elements of integrity. It also stated that public integrity should be
seen as a rational basis for trust; that it is explicitly concerned with the co-
herence of purposes, and the consistency of action with those stated pur-
poses; that it is focused on the cultivation of ethical culture, not simply on
rule compliance, and that it is not merely the absence of corruption.
The study shows that individual-centred conceptions of integrity are
prevalent, but that there is also a growth in the academic literature on the
integrity of institutions. The linking of integrity directly to institutions is
considered a promising development, citing views that an institution will
have integrity if it adheres to its publicly declared values, and that integrity
14
Philip Allott opines that “lawyers have a duty to try to make the law as good as it can be.
Nowhere is this more necessary than in international society [...] We must give to interna-
tional law the true status and function of law in a society of all human beings and all human
societies – an international society in which other human societies, including state-societies,
play their part in serving the common human interest, that is to say, the survival and flour-
ishing of all human beings”. See Philip Allott, “How to Make a Better World: Human Power
and Human Weakness”, FICHL Policy Brief Series No. 75 (2016), Torkel Opsahl Academic
EPublisher, Brussels, 2016 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/a35654).
15
Thomas Robinson, Lucinda Cadzow and Nikolas Kirby, “Investigating Integrity: A Multi-
Disciplinary Literature Review”, in Working Paper, Blavatnik School of Government, Uni-
versity of Oxford, 2018.
we are safe”. I believed in her and trusted her judgment. I have equal re-
spect for Carla Del Ponte 17 who fended off all kinds of pressures, both ex-
ternal and internal, and was punished for attempting to pursue the so-called
special investigations in Rwanda and other reasons. 18 When Serge Bram-
mertz 19 became the Chief Prosecutor and was meeting the trial teams, the
first thing he said to us was: “How can I help you?”. The effect of such an
attitude on team spirit and confidence in the fulfilment of the Office of the
Prosecutor mission is immeasurable.
Thanks to the unmatched inspirational power of example, with peo-
ple of integrity, the example of international (criminal) justice can do more
for strengthening the rule of law and efforts at raising the quality of justice
nationally than is imagined and can be measured.
The standards projected by the ICTY were so high that the interna-
tional criminal trial was respected even by opponents not ideologically
blinded or otherwise prejudiced. Professionals and laypeople alike in the
former Yugoslavia, for example, were captivated by the solidity of the
criminal justice process in The Hague, regardless of criticism and dilem-
mas arising from the differences between the domestic civil law system and
the hybrid law and procedure of the ICTY. That, despite the incessant, ve-
hement anti-ICTY propaganda. The confidence the ICTY process inspired
was captured in anecdotes mentioned by Arbour at an event in Amsterdam
while she was Chief Prosecutor. A surviving victim in Bosnia had been
asked what she would do with the perpetrator. She replied that she would
kill him, or better yet, go to “that woman judge in The Hague”. The father
of a Serbian victim in Kosovo replied to a similar question that he would
want to see the perpetrator in the dock in The Hague. A number of the ac-
cused preferred the ICTY to domestic jurisdiction. A desire to attain high
17
Carla Del Ponte, Chief ICTY Prosecutor 1999–2007.
18
John Hooper, “I was sacked as Rwanda genocide prosecutor for challenging president, says
Del Ponte”, The Guardian, 13 September 2003 (available on its web site). Del Ponte’s fight
for the independence of the Prosecutor is reflected in WikiLeaks cables. Her mandate at the
ICTY was renewed on 4 September 2003, but her Office was split. A veteran ICTY journal-
ist Marliese Simons wrote in the New York Times on 28 July 2003: “With the quiet support
of the United States, the Rwandan government has been campaigning to have Carla Del
Ponte replaced as chief prosecutor for the tribunal dealing with the mass killing in Rwanda
in 1994, Western diplomats and tribunal officials have said in recent days”. See Marlise Si-
mons, “Rwanda Is Said to Seek New Prosecutor for War Crimes Court”, New York Times, 28
July 2003 (available on its web site).
19
Serge Brammertz, Chief ICTY Prosecutor 2008–2017.
22
See Muhamed Sacirbey, in “A Diplomatic “Hunting Party” – facts never published before by
Ms. Hartmann – part 1”, Croatian World Network, 16 September 2007, section “A Timeline
of Evidence” (available on its web site); Christopher B. Mahoney, “The Justice Pivot: US
International Law Influence Outside the Rome Statute”, in Georgetown Journal of Interna-
tional Law, 2015, vol. 46, no. 4.
23
Declaration of the high-level meeting of the General Assembly on the rule of law at the na-
tional and international levels, UN Doc. A/RES/67/1, 30 November 2012 (https://www.
legal-tools.org/doc/d0qwyx/).
24
Florence Hartman, Lanceurs d'alerte. Les mauvaises consciences de nos démocraties, Don
Quichotte, 2014, p. 12.
25
“Credibility of ICTY must be restored”, Norwegian Helsinki Committee, 7 April 2016
(available on its web site).
26
“UN expert says ‘collective persecution’ of Julian Assange must end now”, media release,
31 May 2019 (available on the UN Office of the High Commissioner for Human Rights’s
web site).
27
Nils Melzer, “Demasking the Torture of Julian Assange”, Medium, 26 June 2019 (available
on its web site).
a single mistake that may appear as a departure from the law and ‘high
moral character’, from both individual and institutional integrity. To ensure
the adherence to the highest standards of justice when relevant internal
procedures are not, or cannot be set in motion, or prove to be ineffective,
international courts need to provide full protection for whistle-blowers.
Common sense and experience teach that it is best, or least harmful, to ex-
pose wrongdoing and malfeasance sooner than later, so that problems are
solved instead of stored as family secrets which always have toxic effects
and ultimately never remain in the family.
11.5. Without Integrity, International Justice Is a House of Cards
There is a simple fact that may be overlooked: every person working in
international (criminal) justice forms an impression of the process and
shares it with numbers of people who then pass that on to others. Each per-
son working in international (criminal) justice is viewed with particular
attention by everyone because the mandate is atypical, with expectations
and suspicions attached. Hence, the words and deeds of everyone in inter-
national (criminal) justice determine the trust in its integrity.
Every lapse in integrity, however ‘trivial’ it may seem, has conse-
quences that are not always obvious or predictable. 28 Each one causes dis-
appointment and confusion: internally, it disrupts teamwork because it rup-
tures mutual trust, reliance and respect, and the compactness needed in the
substantial team effort that international (criminal) justice requires. Lack of
integrity at the highest levels leads to anxiety and a drop in mission confi-
dence that infects the working atmosphere; externally, it affects any enthu-
siasm and support for international justice that there may be. Actions that
compromise integrity hand control over the international justice project to
28
Take as an example investigators getting drunk while on mission, or, intoxictated or not,
boasting or denigrating the local officials and populace, or an investigator telling his col-
leagues that the international court they all work in is a ‘kangaroo court’ unlike his national
jurisdiction. Even small lapses not related to integrity, like an unacknowledged courtesy, af-
fect the way the courts, their officials and staff are viewed. I recall vividly the surprise and
disappointment, expressed more in body language than words, of two prominent Belgrade
defense attorneys of great integrity when they received not a word from the ICTY President
for sending him books on Yugoslav law that he needed. The attorneys, one of whom was a
former Supreme Military Court judge, had promptly answered my request to aid the ICTY
President. In memory of that former Supreme Military Court judge, I want to record that
early on in the Yugoslav crisis, he publicly proposed, with passionate argument, the for-
mation of a Yugoslav war crimes court comprising the best Yugoslav judges from all the re-
publics. Unfortunately, it was too late.
when they use a lecture to visiting national judges to insist that ‘their own’
particular judgement is superior being grounded more in civil law, which
they take the time to laud as superior to common law. Or when prosecutors
jeopardize a case by rivalries and personal ambitions and openly blame
each other. Or when a prosecutor insists on absolute personal loyalty and
creates an exclusive circle by surrounding himself with those who comply.
Or when a prosecutor not on a case suddenly, at the last moment, requests
the withdrawal of a signed indictment that is supported by rock-solid evi-
dence. Such dramatic events affect everyone involved. It is even more
damaging when a high profile international prosecutor repeatedly and pub-
licly falsely accuses the chief prosecutor of an alleged deal with a govern-
ment for concealing crucial evidence, or when judgments are manifestly
unjust, being contrary to established facts and the law, but favourable for
powerful States and interests. 29 Or when an unpersuasive decision fully
aligns with the interests of a threatening superpower. 30
It must not be forgotten that there is no greater injustice than injus-
tice done by a court of law or its officers. The resulting harm is profound,
and it cannot be undone. People will then tell you that they have lost all
respect for the judges, the court and the law.
In order to ensure that persons of integrity, the best, are in leading
positions in international (criminal) justice, it is essential to devise an op-
timal system for candidate selection. If all candidates satisfy merit and in-
tegrity criteria, and possess professional experience, the actual system of
appointment or election is of secondary importance. Until a time when in-
ternational judges and prosecutors are elected by an independent profes-
sional body, their election or appointment will remain politicized. Interests
other than the interests of justice may be determinative. It is well known
that international positions are used in domestic politics to reward loyalty,
return favours or repay debts, to remove those considered undesirable, or to
promote friends, family or partners, and, not least, to secure influence, in-
side information and control. It has become clear over the years that some
29
Julija Bogoeva, “International Judges and Government Interests: The Case of President
Meron”, FICHL Policy Brief Series No. 48 (2016), Torkel Opsahl Academic EPublisher,
Brussels, 2016 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/56a576).
30
ICC, Situation in the Islamic Republic of Afghanistan, Pre-Trial Chamber, Decision Pursu-
ant to Article 15 of the Rome Statute on the Authorisation of an Investigation into the Situa-
tion in the Islamic Republic of Afghanistan, 12 April 2019, ICC-02/17-33 (http://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/2fb1f4/).
powerful States do not want their nationals at the highest positions in inter-
national criminal courts in order to avoid the attendant responsibilities and
‘entanglements’, but instead try to make use of all other avenues of influ-
ence and control.
It seems most purposeful to focus on ensuring that only quality can-
didates are in the running. They should be put forward at the national level
by professional bodies, not governments and politicians. One way would
be to establish a pool of candidates for domestic and international war
crimes prosecutions at the State level. That would, as a matter of policy,
give prominence to accountability for core international crimes, and incen-
tivize and enable interested professionals to aim for qualifying for such a
pool. The criteria would be merit and integrity based, transparent, and set
by the legal profession. Maximum three members of a national pool at any
given time could be included in such a pool at the international level. They
would be chosen by a national professional body. Any candidates for the
most senior positions in international justice, however, selected from such
an international pool, and those finally elected or appointed, would have
the necessary qualities, as a minimum guarantee of integrity and effective-
ness of international (criminal) justice. But the aim should be higher, that
the best in the pool become candidates for the top positions. That would
require the will to have the best and to identify the best at every election or
appointment of the most senior officers in international justice. The stimu-
lating of this will, so that it takes root and can be fostered, is a primary task
in creating a new culture of international justice, peace, human dignity and
prosperity for all.
The simple slogan – “If you want peace, have justice” – of the global
movement World Beyond War, encapsulates this new culture that, in fact, is
being created by people of integrity around the globe. In cultivating the
will to have only the best prosecute and judge in international justice, legal
professionals of integrity will by no means be alone.
11.6. Conclusion
Due to lack of integrity and professional excellence of some of its (highest)
officers, and apparent attempts to please the mighty and powerful, or in
fear of their wrath, the still nascent international (criminal) justice project
has faltered and has been endangered. Instead, by displaying individual and
institutional integrity, organs of international (criminal) justice could pre-
vail on the still sceptical and reluctant (States and the general public) that
they are capable of impartially, fairly and independently fulfilling their task;
that there will be no subservience, double standards and hypocrisy in the
administration of international justice.
By earning respect based on integrity, international (criminal) justice
could secure its non-dependence on the big powers of the day, enjoy wide
confidence, and rest on genuine majority support. There is more than
enough evidence that ‘adjusting’ to the wishes and whims of the powerful
means serving the interests of the military-corporate-media complex, the
war machine, which is vitally interconnected with the political class it has
subordinated to its goals of profit and domination. 31 Serving such interests
is directly opposite to the principle of legality, to morality, the notion of
justice and the purpose of international (criminal) justice. It effectively
renders the practice of international (criminal) justice senseless. That hard
fact cannot be changed by any amount of theorizing, pragmatism, well-
wishing, white-washing or propagandizing.
Viewed from any angle, therefore, integrity is key for international
(criminal) justice. Integrity should be valued and acknowledged. Great im-
portance and attention should be given to ensuring that persons of integrity
are in the highest positions in international courts. Their qualities set the
standard and the tone and determine the ethical atmosphere – the more they
are respected and trusted for their integrity, the higher the morale, the work
ethic, and the results. And the willingness to stand up for justice. And not
least, it is very enriching and a pleasure to work with people of integrity.
There are many such professionals. We should always look for them, find
them, and stand by them.
The words of the great humanist Erich Fromm still hold true. The
contemporary contradiction between an abundance of technical means for
material satisfaction and the incapacity to use them exclusively for peace
and the welfare of the people is soluble; it is not a necessary contradiction
but one due to man’s lack of courage and wisdom.
31
William D. Hartung, “The Military-Industrial Complex on Steroids”, Information Clearing
House, 18 July 2019 (available on its web site), which states that “[a]s POGO’s research has
demonstrated, the infamous ‘revolving door’ that deposits defense executives like Esper in
top national security posts swings both ways. The group estimates that, in 2018 alone, 645
senior government officials – mostly from the Pentagon, the uniformed military, and Capitol
Hill – went to work as executives, consultants, or board members of one of the top 20 de-
fense contractors”.
*
Marina Aksenova is Professor of comparative and international criminal law at IE Univer-
sity, Madrid. She graduated with honours from the International University in Moscow. She
holds an LL.M. in Public International Law from the University of Amsterdam and an M.Sc.
in Criminal Justice and Criminology from the University of Oxford. Dr. Aksenova defended
her Ph.D. entitled “Complicity in International Criminal Law” in 2014 at the European Uni-
versity Institute, in Florence. Prior to joining the IE Law School, she was as a postdoctoral
research fellow at the Centre of Excellence for International Courts (iCourts), Faculty of
Law, University of Copenhagen.
1
Morten Bergsmo, “Revisiting Integrity in International Justice”, FICHL Policy Brief Series
No. 93 (2018), Torkel Opsahl Academic EPublisher (‘TOAEP’), Brussels, 2018 (https://
legal-tools.org/doc/e550f7). See, for more discussion of the legal meaning of integrity, the
lecture by Olympia Bekou, “Integrity Standards in the Statutes of International Criminal Ju-
risdictions”, Centre for International Law Research and Policy (‘CILRAP’) Films, 1 De-
cember 2018 (www.cilrap.org/cilrap-film/181201-bekou/).
ourselves through aesthetics. Art goes beyond language and even beyond
the representation of meaning by creating a direct experience. It facilitates
the channel of communication between the observer and the observed, dis-
pensing with the dimensions of time and space. 6 In other words, art creates
room in which the attention of the observer is manipulated so that he or she
perceives the world in an unfamiliar way. To further demonstrate what is
meant by the affective function of art, it is helpful to refer to the work of
the art theorist John Dewey, who points out that art traditionally accompa-
nied daily rituals, such as worship, hunting or law-making. 7 Originally, art
was inseparable from the conditions of its creation, thereby bringing its
affective function to the forefront: experience associated with the object of
art was of utmost importance. For instance, the Greek Parthenon, which is
regarded today as an art masterpiece, was originally designed and built as a
place of civic commemoration. 8 Dewey further observes that it is only
much later and through the process of industrialization that art became con-
textualized by being confined to specific places, such as museums or opera
houses. 9 Such contextualization strengthened the representational vision of
art.
The experiential aspect of art opens up the emotional channels for re-
ceiving the interpretative or representational message, while at the same
time avoiding intransigence. In this way, the message is internalized by an
individual, taking into account their subjective reality and experience of
life. It is the process-oriented feature of art that invites contemplation and
makes it possible to speak of the improved alignment of inner moral con-
victions and external action in individuals. Art and creative expression have
the capacity to go beyond firm analytical structures, and surpass cognitive
biases and other ‘mental defences’ to enhance clearer views of the specific
situation calling for attention. Dewey’s distinction between the ‘thinker’
and the ‘artist’ in the context of life cycles is helpful to explain this point.
Life, according to Dewey, goes in cycles reflective of an adaption to
the environment by any living creature. There is constant adjustment and
transformation of imbalance happening (for instance, satisfying hunger).
Dewey calls this process the rhythm of loss of integration with the envi-
6
Ibid.
7
John Dewey, Art as Experience, Capricorn, 1958 [1934].
8
Ibid., p. 4.
9
Ibid., p. 6.
ronment and recovery of union with it. 10 This rhythm produces both intel-
lectual and aesthetic work. The former is more concerned with the conflict
or the situation in which the discord arose, while the latter focuses on the
phase of experience where union is achieved. Hence both the ‘thinker’ and
the ‘artist’ are ultimately concerned with the interaction of any living crea-
ture with its surroundings, simply with the emphasis put in different places.
The intellectuals create solutions to the problem using language, symbols
and mathematical signs, whereas the artists do their thinking in the very
qualitative media they work in. 11
Going back to the question of integrity in the field of international
justice, this chapter argues that the time is ripe to rethink what we expect
from international law. The premise is that there needs to be a better de-
fined link between its ‘outward’ values and the ‘inner’ values of those
tasked with imparting the ‘outward’ values. As a first step in this process,
the chapter suggests reflecting on the vehicles to facilitate this reassess-
ment process. Relying, among other frames of reference, on natural law
theory, it insists on strengthening the persuasive authority of international
law by referring to the list of basic human goods, including that of aesthet-
ics. The contribution engages in particular with the work of John Finnis,
who discusses basic human goods pursued by humans, such as aesthetic
experience. 12 Justice is a way of distributing these goods in society, and
law is a coercive instrument for such distribution. The question is whether
law can also be a direct reflection of the basic goods and not just the ‘en-
forcer’ of them. This is particularly true for international (criminal) law,
which relies strongly on persuasion. International law has the capacity to
impose duties or to confer powers on State officials, thereby reducing arbi-
trariness in their decision-making; it creates causes of action. 13 How can
instrumentalization be prevented and the universality of international law
be preserved in these circumstances? The answer lies in strengthening its
link with the underlying values it represents, including that of aesthetics.
John Finnis in his work on natural law identifies an exhaustive list of
seven basic human goods pursued by humans: life, knowledge, play, aes-
10
Ibid., p. 14.
11
Ibid., p. 15.
12
John Finnis, Natural Law and Natural Rights, second edition, Oxford University Press, 2011,
p. 85.
13
Basak Çali, The Authority of International Law: Obedience, Respect, and Rebuttal, Oxford
University Press, 2015, p. 11.
19
Finnis, 2011, see above note 12.
20
Ibid., pp. 161–63.
21
Ibid., p. 164.
22
Hans Kelsen, The Pure Theory of Law, original German first edition 1934; second edition,
1960, translated to English by Max Knight (trans.), University of California Press, Los An-
geles, 1967, p. 34; Dennis Lloyd, The Idea of Law, Penguin Books, Middlesex, 1970 [1964],
p. 35 (in his index, the entry for coercion says, “See force, sanction”); Jacques Derrida,
“Force of Law: The Mystical Foundation of Authority”, in Drucilla Cornell, Michel Rosen-
feld and David Gray Carlson (eds.), Deconstruction and the Possibility of Justice, Routledge,
New York and London, 1992, chap. 1.
23
Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, Cambridge University Press, 1996, chap. 21, as cited by
Quentin Skinner, in Bo Stråth (eds.), States and Citizens: History, Theory, Prospects, Cam-
bridge University Press, 2003, pp. 15–16.
cause reasoned reflection produces the will to obey the law. 24 The same
will to obey may not necessarily arise with the same strength when it
comes to the norms of international law because the threat of sanctions is
not as pronounced as in domestic orders.
The authority of international law is, to a large extent, persuasive and
includes the capacity of law to impose duties or to confer powers on State
officials. 25 Basak Çali explains that, in practice, it means State officials en-
gage in a deliberative exercise comparing and contrasting the authority of
domestic law and international law when responding to authority claims
made by international law. 26 This is the manifestation of the persuasive
power of international law: it contributes to the decision-making process by
reducing arbitrariness. It thus protects common values, not so much
through coercion, but rather through bestowing additional causes of action
on those in power.
The enforcement deficit characteristic of general public international
law is acutely felt in the specific sub-field of international criminal law,
which is the focal point of this chapter. The problem of modern interna-
tional criminal justice is that it is torn between its focus on the universal
sense of morality and its high degree of dependence on political processes
at international, State and individual levels. For instance, at the internation-
al level, there is no consensus on whether to bring the situation in Syria to
the attention of the United Nations Security Council for its subsequent re-
ferral to the ICC. 27 At the State level, there is wariness by some States
about what is perceived as interference by the international community in
the domestic affairs of States through the activities of international courts
and human rights bodies. 28 And at an individual level, some high-ranking
State officials enjoy de facto impunity, even in the presence of an arrest
warrant issued by the ICC. 29 These inconsistencies have a direct bearing on
24
Ibid.
25
Çali, 2015, see above note 13.
26
Ibid., p. 64.
27
UN Security Council, “Referral of Syria to International Criminal Court Fails as Negative
Votes Prevent Security Council from Adopting Draft Resolution”, press release, 22 May
2014, UN Doc. SC/11407.
28
For example, Reuters, “Philippines informs U.N. of ICC withdrawal, court regrets move”,
16 March 2018.
29
For example, International Criminal Court (‘ICC’), Situation in Darfur, Sudan, The Prosecu-
tor v. Omar Hassan Ahmad Al Bashir, Pre-Trial Chamber I, Warrant of Arrest for Omar Has-
san Ahmad Al Bashir, 4 March 2009, ICC-02/05-01/09-1 (https://legal-tools.org/doc/814cca).
30
Kathryn Sikkink, The Justice Cascade: How Human Rights Prosecutions Are Changing
World Politics, W.W. Norton, 2011; Marina Aksenova, “Symbolism as a Constraint on Inter-
national Criminal Law”, in Leiden Journal of International Law, 2017, vol. 30, no. 2,
pp. 475–499.
31
Richard K. Sherwin, Visualizing Law in the Age of the Digital Baroque: Arabesques and
Entanglements, Routledge, 2011, pp. 187.
32
Ibid., p. 174.
33
Ibid., p. 113.
34
In this regard, TOAEP’s commitment to a wider use of the AV-recordings of conference
lectures to support academic arguments in its publications is highly commendable.
35
Sherwin, 2011, p. 177, see above note 31.
36
Ibid., p. 174.
37
Ibid., p. 187.
38
Ibid., p. 188.
39
Aksenova, 2017, see above note 30.
40
Immi Tallgren, “The Sensibility and Sense of International Criminal Law”, in European
Journal of International Law, 2002, vol. 3, pp. 571, 572.
41
Ibid., p. 593.
42
Ibid., p. 594.
43
ICC, Situation in Uganda, The Prosecutor v. Dominic Ongwen, Case Information Sheet,
October 2018, ICC-02/04-01/15.
44
Mark Drumbl, “The Ongwen Trial at the ICC: Tough Questions on Child Soldiers”, Open
Democracy, 14 April 2015 (available on its website).
45
Erin Baines, Buried in the Heart: Women, Complex Victimhood and the War in Northern
Uganda, Cambridge University Press, 2016, p. 3.
tion (of torture, for example) but also by creating a direct experience of
what it means to be human with all its complexities and ambiguities.
There is thus a clear need for mediating noble claims of international
criminal law as formulated in the Preamble of the Rome Statute of the ICC
and what this field is actually able to achieve. It is argued here that artistic
expression can assist with this exercise by adding an experiential dimen-
sion to the claims of international criminal justice. In addition to that, art
then becomes a suitable medium for communicating complex truth. It is
possible that re-orienting the rhetoric of international criminal justice to-
wards visual jurisprudence may provide an additional layer of context and
complexity, and thereby contribute to the integrity of the participants of an
international justice process.
12.2.3. The Connection Between Ethics and Aesthetics
Admittedly, the study of integrity initially brings to mind the role of ethics
and not that of aesthetics. 46 This is because ethics, as a branch of philoso-
phy – and religion – deals with human actions and the general principles
guiding these actions. Ethics is outcome-oriented – the goal is to apply
generalized principles to a specific matter in order to attain the result
aligned with a certain moral foundation. In contrast, aesthetics is process-
oriented. It is less concerned with outcomes, but places values on the pro-
cess through which certain action takes place. Aesthetics is, therefore, con-
cerned with thoughtful contemplation. It is not focused on the general prin-
ciples, but rather on the uniqueness of each experience. 47 Why study the
role of aesthetics, one may ask, if it is ethics that supplies us with a ‘code
of conduct’ that we may apply to the situations which require the alignment
of inner guidance with the demands of external rules and values?
The work of Wittgenstein may provide an answer to this question. He
argued that essentially ethics and aesthetics are two sides of the same coin.
Just as they focus on different aspects of the same action (generality versus
specificity; outcome versus process; acting versus experiencing), they do
46
See, for instance, lectures by Dieneke de Vos, “Recent Developments in Ethics Standard-
Setting and Mechanisms in the UN”, CILRAP Films, 1 December 2018 (www.cilrap.org/
cilrap-film/181202-vos/); Shannon E. Fyfe, “Integrity and Prosecutorial Ethics in Interna-
tional Criminal Justice”, CILRAP Films, 1 December 2018 (www.cilrap.org/cilrap-film/
181202-fyfe/).
47
Diané Collinson, “Ethics and Aesthetics are one”, in The British Journal of Aesthetics, 1985,
vol. 25, no. 3, p. 266.
not imply a different set of underlying values. Rather they discuss the very
same process from a different point of venture. 48
In line with this position, this chapter does not denounce the role of
ethics in promoting integrity, but rather suggests an alternative way of per-
ceiving it. To give a concrete example, one may contemplate judicial im-
partiality. One way to look at this principle is through the lens of ethics that
requires judges to apply the law without being influenced by personal con-
victions and biases. This is one of the fundamental elements of due process
and is codified in a variety of human rights instruments as well as the stat-
utes of international courts and tribunals. 49
However, one may also see the application of the same principle as a
process in each particular case. What are the elements inherent in an inter-
national criminal trial that promote judicial impartiality? One can suggest
that certain procedures characteristic of an international trial – such as the
swearing in of judges as they pledge to avoid representing a State or any
other vested interests, their professionally worn attire as well as formalized
conduct in the courtroom, including rising when the judges enter the
room – all emphasize respect to the nature of judicial activity and remind
judges of the need to uphold the principle of judicial independence. Is the
process a trivial matter? Far from it, this chapter argues. Misalignment of
inner guidance and the demands of justice can occur easily depending on
the factual circumstances of the case, ‘triggering’ certain biases in a judge,
which they may not even be conscious of. 50 There may also be situations of
personal fatigue or general policy considerations of expediency of an inter-
national trial. All these factors may compromise judicial impartiality if it is
only formulated as a general principle or a rule. The process whereby this
rule is enforced in practice exists as a constant reminder of the need to up-
hold this principle in each specific case.
12.2.4. The Role of Art in Evoking the Truth-Content
Theodor Adorno, in the famous Aesthetic Theory, acknowledges the diffi-
culty of defining art and chooses to describe it through dialectical exercises
48
Ibid.
49
For example, European Convention on Human Rights, 4 November 1950, Article 6 (https://
legal-tools.org/doc/8267cb); Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court, 17 July 1998,
Article 36(3)(a) (https://legal-tools.org/doc/7b9af9).
50
For a recent example, see Kevin Jon Heller, “Judge Ozaki Must Resign — Or Be Removed”,
Opinio Juris, 29 March 2019 (available on its web site).
ICC. This norm clearly protects life as a basic human value. The crime of
genocide sits at the apex of the group of offences with highly traumatic
connotations for future generations. It criminalizes the destruction of indi-
viduals as a collective entity, on the basis of their belonging to a group de-
fined by certain characteristics. This act is particularly heinous for it attacks
persons and denies them their right to exist as a group. Hannah Arendt re-
ferred to genocide as “an attack upon human diversity as such, that is, upon
a characteristic of the ‘human status’ without which the very words ‘man-
kind’ or ‘humanity’ would be devoid of meaning”. 60 The convoluted logic
underlying acts of genocide threatens the whole of humankind due to its
capacity to indoctrinate and turn humans against each other. The dangerous
potential of genocide, historically tested, elevates it to the status of the
most odious international crime.
Genocide is also an attack on sociability or the peaceful co-existence
of humans. The process whereby genocide occurs consists of several
steps. 61 It starts with the feelings of animosity, resentment and fear directed
against individuals based on their belonging to a certain group. These sen-
timents are not endogenous, however, and are usually linked to the ideas
planted ‘from above’ by the authority seeking control or power. One group
is made to believe that the other group is threatening the well-being of the
former. Sometimes, the feelings of mistrust and resentment are mutual be-
tween the groups. The ideology of hate is one of the ways to manipulate
people and make them ‘governable’. As a result of indoctrination, the cul-
ture of blaming others for personal grievances with the potential of escalat-
ing into violence is thus created.
Even if somebody, based on their flawed practical reasonableness,
decides to destroy a group as such for the sake of pursuing other goods, law
would stand in their way as a deterrent. In this case, law overtakes individ-
ual practical reasonableness and becomes a manifestation of the same value
at the community level. Finnis defines practical reasonableness as bringing
intelligence and order into one’s own actions and habits. 62 However, one’s
internal order and decision-making process may come into conflict with the
60
Hannah Arendt, Eichmann in Jerusalem: A Report on the Banality of Evil, Viking Press,
1965, pp. 268, 269.
61
For more discussion, see, for example, Bert Ingelaere, Stephan Parmentier, Jacques Haers
and Babara Segaert (eds.), Genocide, Risk and Resilience: An Interdisciplinary Approach,
Palgrave, 2013.
62
Finnis, 2011, p. 88, see above note 12.
63
Eric A. Posner, “Law and the Emotions”, University of Chicago, John M. Olin Law and
Economics Working Paper No. 103, September 2000, pp. 2–5.
64
Gregory M. Reichberg, Thomas Aquinas on War and Peace, Cambridge University Press,
2016, p. 92.
65
Émile Durkheim, The Division of Labour in Society, 1893, p. 52.
66
Ruti G. Teitel, Transitional Justice, Cambridge University Press, 2010, p. 72.
67
Marina Aksenova, “The Role of ICT in Historical Accounts of Genocide”, in Uladzislau
Belavusau and Aleksandra Gliszczyńska-Grabias (eds.), Law and Memory: Towards Legal
Governance of History, Cambridge University Press, 2017, p. 57.
68
Jeffrey C. Alexander, “Cultural Pragmatics: Social Performance between Ritual and Strate-
gy”, in Jeffrey C. Alexander, Bernhard Giesen and Jason L. Mast (eds.), Social Performance:
Symbolic Action, Cultural Pragmatics and Ritual, Cambridge University Press, 2006, p. 32.
69
For more on this topic, see Aksenova, 2017, see above note 67.
70
Alexander, 2006, p. 58, see above note 68.
71
Émile Durkheim, The Elementary Forms of the Religious Life, George Allen & Unwin,
London, 1912, p. 471.
72
ICC, “The ICC has moved to its permanent premises”, press release, 14 December 2015,
ICC-CPI-20151214-PR1180.
73
International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia (‘ICTY’), Prosecutor v. Radislav
Krstić, Appeals Chamber, Judgement, 19 April 2004, IT-98-33-A, para. 36 (https://legal-
tools.org/doc/86a108).
comprise the system and make it operational. This view serves as a re-
minder of why international criminal law exists in the first place and what
its overall objectives are.
Moreover, the strong aesthetic element embedded in the field of in-
ternational criminal justice complements the production of knowledge by
the courts through judgments and decisions. Aesthetics allows revealing an
additional layer of truth about suffering through artistic expression. As dis-
cussed in the previous section, truth-content is an inalienable part of the
art-object and the aesthetic experience of the art, according to Adorno.
12.3.2. Methodological Advantages of Using Art in the Field of
International Justice
From a methodological perspective, art may serve as a method of inquiry
with the purpose of illuminating aspects of the field of international justice
currently concealed from view.
The thought of exploring the instrumental dimension of art is not new,
as art has been used for educational purposes since as early as in the times
of the Renaissance. In the field of politics, art is frequently employed to
question dogmatic ideas and reach out to diverse segments of the popula-
tion. For instance, Chinese artist AI Wei Wei drew attention to the refugee
crisis by wrapping a Florentine Palazzo in orange lifeboats during his 2016
exhibition there. In addition to that, visual methods are used in discourse
analysis, which can be studied through documentary or historical images
with other forms of data. 74 More generally, sociology has started taking the
‘visual’ more seriously with the ongoing research on the promise of visual
methodology as an alternative way of scientific inquiry. 75
Such a turn has not yet occurred in the study and practice of law, a
discipline which remains focused entirely on texts and the written word.
One can imagine, however, how undertaking art projects aimed at promot-
ing international (criminal) law values, such as integrity, can contribute to
the study of the discipline as such. Creative expression can bring to light
the aspects of this field long ignored by traditional approaches. For in-
stance, an exhibition dedicated to the work of the ICC may evoke respons-
es in the general public indicative of the new solutions to practical prob-
74
Gillian Rose, Visual Methodologies: An Introduction to Researching with Visual Materials,
third edition, Sage, 2012.
75
Ibid.
lems faced by the Court. The ICC took its first steps in this direction in
2018 by partnering with the National Geographic photographer Marcus
Bleasdale in organizing an exhibition entitled “Healing, Trauma and Hope”.
The exhibition took place on the ICC premises in The Hague and at the
United Nations Headquarters in New York and is available online at the
time of writing. 76 It is important to note, however, that precise impact of
such creative outreach activities has not yet been fully studied. 77
12.3.3. Practical Example of Using Art in International Criminal Law
This sub-section explores the practical ways in which art and creative ex-
pression can be interjected in the process of administration of international
justice. International criminal law and its emerging system of reparations is
chosen to illustrate the point. In this example, the ultimate goal of engaging
with art is promoting reconciliation in the affected communities. 78 While
the purpose of strengthening integrity is not directly covered in the follow-
ing discussion, it is fair to assume that exploring the ways of enhancing
international justice through alternative means has direct impact on the in-
tegrity of its actors. As discussed in the introduction, lack of integrity often
stems from the lack of alignment of inner values and their outer expression.
Arguably, the more instruments international justice has at its disposal, the
more clarity its various stakeholders will benefit from. Seeing positive
change in the communities and focusing on the core values of the disci-
pline can facilitate better judgment in individuals.
The practice of reparations is one clear entry point where interna-
tional justice starts accepting the deployment of creative expression. While
the old generation of international criminal courts and tribunals placed little
emphasis on reparations and victim participation, the ICC together with
Extraordinary Chambers in the Courts of Cambodia (‘ECCC’) are pioneer-
ing the idea of inclusivity of victims’ concerns in international criminal
proceedings. Pursuant to Article 75(1) of the Rome Statute of the ICC, the
Court may order reparations to victims, in the form of restitution, compen-
sation and rehabilitation. This list is not exhaustive as the Court may select
76
ICC, “Trauma, healing and hope” (available on its web site).
77
Fiana Gantheret, “The Use of Artistic Productions as a Transitional Justice Mechanism in
the Context of International Criminal Justice and the Misuse of International Tribunals’
Mandates”, Art and International Justice Blog, 1 July 2019.
78
Rachel Kerr, “The ‘Art’ of Reconciliation’, FICHL Policy Brief Series No. 78 (2017),
TOAEP, Brussels, 2017 ( http://www.toaep.org/pbs-pdf/78-kerr/).
79
ICC, Situation in the Democratic Republic of Congo, The Prosecutor v. Germain Katanga,
Trial Chamber, Order for Reparations Pursuant to Article 75 of the Statute, ICC 01/04-01/07,
24 March 2017, para. 297 (https://legal-tools.org/doc/63d36d).
80
ICC, Situation in the Democratic Republic of Congo, The Prosecutor v. Thomas Lubanga
Dyilo, Appeals Chamber, Order for Reparations (amended), 3 March 2015, ICC-01/04-
01/06-3129-AnxA, para. 67 (https://legal-tools.org/doc/df2804).
81
Ibid., para. 46.
raising within this broader community about the harm inflicted on children
as a result of their inscription in the armed forces. 82
The use of symbolic rehabilitative measures can also be seen in the
Al Mahdi case, in which the ICC pronounced on the appropriate reparations
in cases of the destruction of cultural heritage. This case is unique because
artistic expression is not only a tool for reparations, but also the value pro-
tected by the principles of international criminal law. The reparations order,
issued in August 2017, found Mr. Al Mahdi, who orchestrated the demoli-
tion of ten shrines of historical and cultural significance in Timbuktu, Ma-
li, 83 liable for EUR 2.7 million for damage caused by the attack. 84 The
Court emphasized the emotional distress caused to the Timbuktu communi-
ty as a whole by the destruction of the shrines. 85 The ICC further stressed
the inherent, unique and sentimental value of most cultural property and
cultural heritage because of their purpose and symbolism. 86
Thus, the mental anguish caused by its obliteration is addressed on
an individual level by compensation and on a collective level by symbolic
rehabilitative measures, such as memorial, commemoration or forgiveness
ceremony. The aim is to grant public recognition to the harm suffered by
the Timbuktu community. 87 The Court also focused on Mr. Al Mahdi’s
apology, which it found to be “genuine, categorical and empathetic”. 88 As a
symbolic measure with potential reconciliatory impact, the judges ordered
the excerpt from the trial containing an apology be put on the Court’s web
82
ICC, Situation in the Democratic Republic of Congo, The Prosecutor v. Thomas Lubanga
Dyilo, Trial Chamber II, Public Redacted version of Filing regarding symbolic collective
reparations projects with Confidential Annex: Draft Request for Proposals, ICC-01/04-
01/06-3223-Conf, 19 September 2016, ICC-01/04-01/06 (https://legal-tools.org/doc/
401740).
83
Marina Aksenova, “The Al Mahdi Judgment and Sentence at the ICC: A Source of Cautious
Optimism for International Criminal Justice”, EJIL: Talk!, 13 October 2016 (available on its
web site).
84
ICC, Situation in the Republic of Mali, The Prosecutor v. Ahmed Al Faqi Al Mahdi, Trial
Chamber, Reparations Order, 17 August 2017, ICC-01/12-01/15, para. 134 (https://legal-
tools.org/doc/02d1bb).
85
Ibid., para. 90.
86
Ibid., para. 22.
87
Ibid., para. 90.
88
Ibid., para. 70 (citing Trial Judgment, paras. 103–05).
89
Ibid., paras. 70–71.
90
Extraordinary Chambers in the Courts of Cambodia, The Prosecutor v. Nuon Chea and
Khieu Samphan, Trial Chamber, Civil Party Lead Co-Lawyers’ Final Claim for Reparation
in Case 002/02 with Confidential Annexes, 30 May 2017, E457/6/2/1, para. 30 (https://legal-
tools.org/doc/876df7).
13.1. Introduction
Questions of ethics and integrity should be at the core of justice institutions,
whether at a national or international level, yet they are often either ne-
glected or, more likely, simply presumed to exist. Integrity is often seen as
something one simply ‘has’ (or ‘has not’). Yet, when asked what it means
to ‘have’ integrity, various definitions are likely to be offered, depending on
one’s viewpoint or the nature of the institution.
For example, during discussions in 1998 around revisions to the
United Nations Staff Regulations and Rules and the possible adoption of a
United Nations (‘UN’) Code of Conduct, one UN representative stated that
of the three staff requirements set out in Article 101 of the UN Charter (ef-
ficiency, competence and integrity), integrity “was the most difficult to
measure in relative terms” and as such needed further definition. 1 Con-
trastingly, other representatives stated that “Member States would not pro-
pose candidates lacking in integrity” and that as such, “there was no need”
for these regulations to expand upon this term. 2 In other words, integrity
*
Dieneke T. de Vos is currently Integrity Lead with Oxfam Novib, where she heads the or-
ganization’s integrity unit, which is responsible for the prevention of and response to allega-
tions of sexual harassment, sexual exploitation and abuse, child abuse, and corruption mis-
conduct. Dr. de Vos was previously an Ethics Officer with the United Nations and has
worked for various other international organizations in the field of international justice. Dr.
de Vos received her Ph.D. in international criminal law from the European University Insti-
tute. All views expressed in this chapter are the author’s own, and do not necessarily repre-
sent those of her current or past employers.
1
Comments of the International Civil Service Commission on the report of the Secretary-
General entitled “Proposed United Nations Code of conduct” (A/52/488), Addendum to Re-
port of the International Civil Service Commission for the year 1997, UN Doc.
A/52/30/Add.1, 20 May 1998, para. 28 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/7fp24a/).
2
Ibid., para. 34.
3
Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court, 17 July 1998, Articles 33(3)(a), 42(3),
43(3) and 44(2) (‘ICC Statute’) (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/3758e4/).
4
The interpretation of the ‘high moral character’-requirement has gained particular promi-
nence during the 2020 election of the third chief Prosecutor of the International Criminal
Court. See, for example, Eric Witte, “By Failing to Screen ICC Prosecutor Candidates for
Sexual Misconduct, States Put Court at Risk”, International Justice Monitor, 9 March 2020
(available on its web site).
5
The term ‘ethics (or ethical) infrastructure’ was first coined by Ted Schneyer in his work on
the legal profession in the United States. He focused primarily on understanding ‘law firm
discipline’, which was defined as a system of compliance with professional conduct rules: a
set of organizational systems, procedures, policies and incentives that promote desirable be-
haviour and discourage unethical conduct. See, for example, Ted Schneyer, “Professional
Discipline for Law Firms?”, in Cornell Law Review, 1991, vol. 77, no. 1, pp. 1–46; Ted
Schneyer, “A Tale of Four Systems: Reflections on How Law Influences the Ethical Infra-
structure of Law Firms”, in South Texas Law Review, 1998, vol. 39, pp. 245–277. This chap-
ter, however, follows Parker et al. (2008) in arguing for a broader understanding of the term
‘ethics infrastructure’ that “incorporates informal management policies and work cultures
(not just formal management policies) and the promotion of ethical dialogue and values (not
just compliance with professional conduct rules)”. Christine Parker, Adrian Evans, Linda
Haller, Suzanne Le Mire and Ried Mortensen, “The Ethical Infrastructure of Legal Practice
in Larger Law Firms: Values, Policy and Behaviour”, in UNSW Law Journal, 2008, vol. 13,
no. 1, p. 160 (fn. 6).
als within those institutions understand what it means to act with the re-
quired integrity in that particular institutional context.
This chapter thus focuses on this linkage between the institution and
the individual by examining the ethics infrastructure of the UN. The first
part will set out the UN’s regulatory framework around (individual) con-
duct and behaviour. This section thus focuses on what individual integrity
means in a UN institutional context, and how it is shaped by and given
meaning through established rules and regulations. It will try to answer the
question: what does it mean for international civil servants to ‘have’ integ-
rity under the UN’s ‘regulatory’ ethics infrastructure? The second part of
this chapter will then turn its focus to some of the institutional mechanisms
developed to help shape and ultimately enforce the UN’s standards around
individual integrity – the UN’s ‘institutional’ ethics infrastructure. In par-
ticular, this section will seek to understand the function of the UN Ethics
Office in safeguarding both the integrity of the institution itself and the in-
tegrity of its individual staff members and will illustrate a number of con-
crete institutional mechanisms established by and/or under the guardian-
ship of the UN Ethics Office.
However, as the third and final part of this chapter argues, examining
the UN’s regulatory and institutional ethics infrastructure presents an in-
complete picture. Sections 13.1. and 13.2. of this chapter illustrate that the
UN has a range of rules and regulations, and enforcement and compliance
mechanisms around expected standards of behaviour of international civil
servants vis-à-vis external parties linked to organizational and reputational
risks. Fewer structures, exist, however, to address interpersonal conduct
within the organization. The UN’s ethics infrastructure has prioritised rules,
systems and structures to address unethical behaviour that constitute mis-
conduct against the institution, that is, violations against the organization’s
(public or financial) interests such as fraud and corruption, over unethical
actions that firstly harm individuals and harm the institution secondarily
(such as sexual harassment, bullying and discrimination). The third and
final part of this chapter thus focuses on this gap in the UN’s ethics infra-
structure, which has gained increased attention in the past years: sexual
harassment as a serious breach of both individual and institutional integrity.
It argues that an organizational ethics infrastructure designed to give mean-
ing to, and shape, individual integrity must be inclusive of systems and
structures to address interpersonal (mis)conduct.
6
Parker et al., 2008, p. 172, see above note 5.
7
Charter of the United Nations, 26 June 1945, Article 101(3) (https://www.legal-tools.org/
doc/6b3cd5): “The paramount consideration in the employment of the staff […] shall be the
necessity of securing the highest standards of efficiency, competence, and integrity” (em-
phasis added).
8
Some argue that Dag Hammarskjöld best personified and personally helped define, or even
gave birth to, what it means to be an international civil servant today. See, for example, The
Ethics of Dag Hammarskjöld, Dag Hammarskjöld Foundation, Uppsala, 2010, p. 4
(available on its web site): “[He] shaped a lasting concept of the role and responsibilities of
the international civil servant, creating standards against which his successors continue to be
measured”.
9
Guy Fiti Sinclair, “The International Civil Servant in Theory and Practice: Law, Morality,
and Expertise”, in European Journal of International Law, 2015, vol. 26, no. 3, pp. 755–756.
10
Staff Regulations and Rules of the United Nations, Secretary General’s Bulletin
ST/SGB/2018/1, 1 January 2018, Staff Regulation 1.1(a) (‘ST/SGB/2018/1’) (https://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/zn5lba/).
11
Elia Armstrong, “Integrity, Transparency and Accountability in Public Administration: Re-
cent Trends, Regional and International Developments and Emerging Issues”, United Na-
tions Department of Economic and Social Affairs, August 2005, p. 1.
12
ST/SGB/2018/1, Staff Regulation 1.2(b), see above note 10. See also, para. 5 of the 2013
Standards of Conduct, which provide that the concept of integrity “embraces all aspects of
behaviour of an international civil servant, including such qualities as honesty, truthfulness,
impartiality and incorruptibility”. Standards of Conduct of the International Civil Service,
International Civil Service Commission, July 2013.
13
The Standards of Conduct for the International Civil Service were first drafted by the Inter-
national Civil Service Advisory Board in 1954. They have since been revised by the Interna-
tional Civil Service Commission in 2001, and most recently in 2013. The 2013 Standards of
Conduct, which remain in force today, were approved, with effect from 1 January 2013, by
the General Assembly through resolution 67/257 of 12 April 2013 (https://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/y77yzh/). The Standards of Conduct set out the principles that must define the
relationship between staff members and their organisations (for example, loyalty, mutual re-
spect, and an enabling environment), the relationship between international civil servants
and outside entities, in particular governments (for example, independence, neutrality and
incorruptibility), and the principles underpinning staff members’ personal conduct (for ex-
ample, respect for different cultures, avoiding conflicts of interest, and not abusing their
power).
14
See, in particular ST/SGB/2018/1, Chapter I of the Staff Regulations (Regulation 1.2) and
Chapter I of the Staff Rules (Rule 1.2), see above note 10. The UN Staff Regulations and
Staff Rules, like the UN Charter, are applicable to all UN staff members, including those of
the separately administered funds and programmes. For other categories of personnel who
do not fall within the scope of the Staff Regulations and Rules, such as experts on mission,
separate policies have been adopted setting out similar conduct requirements. See, for ex-
ample: “Regulations Governing the Status, Basic Rights and Duties of Officials other than
Secretariat Officials, and Experts on Mission”, Secretary-General’s Bulletin ST/SGB/2002/9,
17 June 2002, Regulation 2 (‘ST/SGB/2002/9’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/abt35z/);
“Consultants and individual contractors”, Administrative Instruction ST/AI/2013/4, 19 De-
cember 2013, Sections 5.5-5.6 (‘ST/AI/2013/4’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/k3vfax/);
“Gratis personnel”, Administrative Instruction ST/AI/1999/6, 28 May 1999, Section 11
(‘ST/AI/1999/6’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/lsqcgc/); “The UN internship pro-
gramme”, Administrative Instruction ST/AI/2014/1, 13 January 2014, Section 6.2
tegrity can generally be divided into two categories. Firstly, the rules and
regulations that define international civil servants’ impartiality and inde-
pendence from outside entities, in particular, governmental or other politi-
cal actors; and, secondly, the rules and regulations governing the private
affiliations and personal conduct of international civil servants. This regu-
latory ethics infrastructure thus delineates the behaviour expected of inter-
national civil servants because of their status, including the limitations that
attach thereto, in particular in their engagement with outside entities.
Most of the Staff Rules and Regulations prescribing staff members’
independence and impartiality revolve around the principle that interna-
tional civil servants are not, in any way, representatives of governments or
other outside entities, nor are they proponents of their policies. 15 As the
Standards of Conduct explain, their impartiality requires international civil
servants to act with the greatest tact and discretion. Moreover, it implies
tolerance and restraint in expressing opinions particularly on controversial,
political or religious matters as “international civil servants do not have the
freedom of private persons to take sides or to express their convictions
publicly on controversial matters, either individually or as members of a
group, irrespective of the medium used”. 16
As a result, there are certain things one must leave at the door when
entering the international civil service. Notably, while the UN respects the
inviolability of staff members’ personal opinions, including political or re-
ligious, as international civil servants, UN staff members must not act in a
manner that could reflect adversely upon the interests of the organization or
upon the independence, impartiality and integrity required by their status as
international civil servants. 17 Accordingly, while UN staff members may
exercise their right to vote, may be a member of a political party or make
normal financial contributions to political parties, they may not stand for
election and their participation in certain activities, such as making public
pronouncements on controversial issues in a personal capacity, or cam-
paigning or fundraising on behalf of a political party, individual or outside
18
Ibid., Staff Regulation 1.2(f), (h), Staff Rule 1.2(u); “Charter of the United Nations and the
Convention on the Privileges and Immunities of the United Nations: provisions relating to
the status, basic rights and duties of United Nations staff members, with commentary”, Sec-
retary-General’s Bulletin ST/SGB/2016/9, 21 July 2016 (‘Commentary to the Staff Rules
and Regulations’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/mjxin2/). See also Standards of Conduct
for the International Civil Service, paras. 48–49, see above note 12.
19
Ibid., para. 33.
20
The UN Declaration (or Oath) of Office is set out in ST/SGB/2018/1, Staff Regulation
1.1(b), see above note 10.
21
Ibid., Staff Regulation 1.2(o) and (p); Staff Rule 1.2(s), (t), and (v), see above note 10.
22
Commentary to the Staff Rules and Regulations, Staff Rule 1.2(t), see above note 18.
29
Ibid., Staff Rule 1.2(n). The Commentary to Staff Rule 1.2(n), explains: “the Secretary-
General would normally grant authorization to accept an honorary degree or certificate from
any university or related institution that is recognized as an academic institution by the Sec-
retary-General. For example, no approval would be granted for honours from so-called “di-
ploma mills” or institutions not recognized by a competent national authority”. Commentary
to the Staff Rules and Regulations, see above note 18.
30
Commentary to Staff Regulation 1.2(j): “Staff regulation 1.2 (j) stresses the importance of
the appearance of strict independence and impartiality of staff and thus reaffirms the abso-
lute prohibition on acceptance of benefits from Governments. No exception to this prohibi-
tion beyond staff regulation 1.2 (k) […] is foreseen, and there is no basis for the Secretary-
General to grant approval for acceptance” (emphasis added). Ibid.
31
ST/SGB/2018/1, Staff Regulation 1.2(k), and Staff Rule 1.2(l), see above note 10. See also
the Commentary to the Staff Regulations and Rules, see above note 18. The Secretary-
General may then decide to display such received items in any of the UN’s premises for ed-
ucational or symbolic purposes. “Preservation and Disposition of Gifts and Historical Items”,
Secretary-General’s Bulletin ST/SGB/136, 1 February 1971, provides that articles or items
(including archival or documentary materials) may be displayed or exhibited for educational,
informational and decorative purposes in UN premises or elsewhere. See also, ST/AI/2010/1,
above note 25, and “Honours, gifts or renumeration from outside sources”, Information Cir-
cular, 16 August 2006, ST/IC/2006/31 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/j19d4l/).
32
ST/SGB/2018/1, Staff Regulation 1.2(g), see above note 10.
33
Commentary to the Staff Rules and Regulations, Staff Regulation 1.2(g), see above note 18.
34
ST/SGB/2018/1, Staff Rule 1.2(k), see above note 10: “Staff members shall neither offer nor
promise any favour, gift, remuneration or any other personal benefit to another staff member
or to any third party with a view to causing him or her to perform, fail to perform or delay
the performance of any official act. Similarly, staff members shall neither seek nor accept
any favour, gift, remuneration or any other personal benefit from another staff member or
from any third party in exchange for performing, failing to perform or delaying the perfor-
mance of any official act”.
35
Ibid., Staff Regulation 1.2(m) and Staff Rule 1.2(q).
36
Activities of the Ethics Office, Report of the Secretary General, 8 June 2018, UN Doc.
A/73/89, para. 17 (‘UN Ethics Office Annual Report 2017’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/
doc/z8uoqo/).
37
ST/SGB/2018/1, Staff Regulation 1.2(m) and Staff Rule 1.2(q), see above note 10.
38
Standards of Conduct of the International Civil Service, para. 10, see above note 12.
39
The Oil for Food programme was established in 1995 under Security Council resolution 986
to alleviate “the serious nutritional and health situation of the Iraqi population”. The pro-
gramme sought to allow the purchase by Iraq of “medicine, health supplies, foodstuffs, and
materials and supplies for essential civilian needs” through the controlled sale of oil from
Iraq through an escrow system. Security Council resolution 986, “authorization to permit the
import of petroleum and petroleum products originating in Iraq, as a temporary measure to
provide for humanitarian needs of the Iraqi people”, 14 April 1995, UN Doc. S/RES/986
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/502a28/). However, following the programme’s official
closure in 2003, in January 2004, serious allegations were made that around 270 persons and
companies sympathetic to Saddam Hussein paid bribes and agreed to pay substantial kick-
backs to the Iraqi government in exchange for their participation in this scheme. A subse-
quent investigation found “a range of lapses, negligence and corrupt practices that allowed
Saddam [Hussein]’s regime to earn as much as $11 billion while under sanctions”: Robert
McMahon, “The Impact of the UN Oil-for-Food Scandal”, Council for Foreign Relations,
2006 (available on its web site). It also pointed to deep flaws in the UN’s oversight of the
administration of the programme.
40
“Ethics Office – establishment and terms of reference”, Secretary-General’s Bulletin
ST/SGB/2005/22, 30 December 2005 (‘ST/SGB/2005/22’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/
a8gm8e/). Several of the separately funded agencies and programmes, such as the UNFPA,
UNICEF, UNDP and the United Nations High Commissioner for Refugees (‘UNHCR’),
have since also established their own Ethics Offices. Rather than canvassing the entire spec-
trum of work of these different Ethics Offices in the UN system, this chapter will focus on
the UN Ethics Office established within the UN Secretariat. The Director of the UN Ethics
Office chairs the Ethics Panel of the United Nations (‘EPUN’), which is comprised of the
Directors of the various ethics offices of the UN system (UNDP, UNICEF, UNFPA, UN-
HCR, the United Nations Office for Project Services, the World Food Programme and the
United Nations Relief and Works Agency for Palestine Refugees in the Near East) and is
charged with ensuring coherence and harmonization in ethics standard setting across the UN
family. The UN Ethics Office continues to provide ethics services to entities which have not
appointed an ethics officer and/or established an ethics office, in accordance with: “United
Nations system-wide application of ethics: separately administered organs and programmes”,
Secretary-General’s Bulletin ST/SGB/2007/11, 30 November 2007 (‘ST/SGB/2007/11’)
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/te040l/). See also the web site of the UN Ethics Office for
more information about EPUN (formerly the UN Ethics Committee).
41
ST/SGB/2005/22, para. 3.1, see above note 40.
42
UN Ethics Office Annual Report 2017, para. 2, see above note 36.
Office serves the best interests of the organization, seeking to advance the
integrity of both the institution and that of its staff members. While the UN
Ethics Office provides five lines of service, requests for confidential ethics
advice, in particular on the management and mitigation of conflicts of in-
terest and other reputational risks, constitutes the majority of its work: in
2019, 44 per cent of the requests for service submitted to the UN Ethics
Office were requests for ethics advice. 43 Importantly, requests for ethics
advice are confidential, 44 which allows staff to seek advice and guidance in
confidence concerning ethical dilemmas they may face. By providing ad-
vice to staff members on concrete ethics questions, the Ethics Office helps
staff and the organization proactively and preventatively manage and miti-
gate conflict-of-interest risks and potential reputational harm, and thus
helps safeguard the integrity of both individual civil servants and of the
institution as a whole. In other words, through its advisory function, the
UN Ethics Office constitutes an important institutional mechanism that
gives meaning to and helps shape the interpretation of the UN’s regulatory
ethics infrastructure, including its individual integrity requirements.
In addition to the advice provided at the request of staff members
and/or to management on the mitigation of conflict-of-interest risks or re-
lated ethics concerns, the UN Ethics Office also administers the UN Finan-
cial Disclosure Programme (‘UNFDP’). The UNFDP requires the disclo-
sure of personal assets and affiliations by selected staff members on an an-
nual basis with a view towards assisting staff members and the organization
in identifying, mitigating and managing personal conflict-of-interest risks.
Participation in the UNFDP is determined based on a staff member’s sen-
iority or the substantive nature of their position. Initially, only staff mem-
bers at the Assistant Secretary-General level and above were required to
file financial disclosure statements. 45 However, the financial disclosure
programme was reviewed and expanded significantly in 2006, in part as a
43
Activities of the Ethics Office, Report of the Secretary General, 30 April 2020, UN Doc.
A/75/82, paras. 8, 13 (‘UN Ethics Office Annual Report 2019’).
44
The mandate of the Ethics Office specifically protects the confidentiality of its ethics advice:
“In respect of its advisory functions as set out in section 3.1(c) above, the Ethics Office shall
not be compelled by any United Nations official or body to testify about concerns brought to
its attention”. ST/SGB/2005/22, para. 3.4, see above note 40.
45
See “Financial Disclosure Programme”, Secretary-General’s Bulletin ST/SGB/1999/3, 28
April 1999 (‘ST/SGB/1999/3’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/wnk1hh/).
result of the oil-for-food scandal, 46 and now covers: all senior staff mem-
bers at Director (D-1) level and above; all staff members who are procure-
ment officers or whose principal duties relate to the procurement of goods
or services for the UN; all staff members whose principal duties relate to
the investment of the assets of the UN; other staff members with direct ac-
cess to confidential procurement or investment information; and, all staff
members of the UN Ethics Office. 47 Participation in the UNFDP is manda-
tory; failure to comply may constitute misconduct and will be referred to
the Office of Human Resources Management for possible disciplinary ac-
tion. 48
Staff members required to participate in the UNFDP must disclose in
relation to themselves and their spouse and/or dependent children (if any)
their assets, profits, non-UN income, stock options, gifts and liabilities
(above a certain threshold) in addition to their private affiliations such as
outside activities, leadership or policy-making positions with non-UN enti-
ties, relatives employed within the UN system, or any other activity that
may reflect upon their integrity. 49 In addition, staff members serving on a
“When Actually Employed” (WAE) basis, on a one-dollar-per-year (sym-
bolic) appointment, 50 or on appointments of a short duration must file a
46
The UN’s financial disclosure programme was first established in 1999 to implement the
requirements set out in Staff Regulations 1.2(m) and (n). It was subsequently expanded in
2005 following the conclusions of the Volcker Report about the Oil-for-Food scandal, and
again amended in 2006 following the establishment of the UN Ethics Office. For the rele-
vant administrative documents, see ibid., ST/SGB/1999/3; “Financial Disclosure and Decla-
ration of Interest Statements”, Secretary-General’s Bulletin ST/SGB/2005/19, 25 November
2005 (‘ST/SGB/2005/19’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/th9lb9/), and “Financial Disclo-
sure and Declaration of Interest Statements”, Secretary-General’s Bulletin ST/SGB/2006/6,
10 April 2006 (‘ST/SGB/2006/6’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/58es6q/). The latter re-
mains in force at the time of writing.
47
Ibid., para. 2.1.
48
In its 2017 Annual Report, the UN Ethics Office notes that during the 2017 filing cycle, two
filers failed to submit their statements and were referred to the Office of Human Resources
Management (‘OHRM’). See UN Ethics Office Annual Report 2017, para. 26, see above
note 36.
49
ST/SGB/2006/6, paras. 3.1 and 3.2, see above note 46.
50
WAE and One-Dollar-A-Year contracts are granted only in exceptional circumstances and
are limited to high-level appointments, such as at the level of Assistant-Secretary-General,
Under-Secretary-General, Special Representative, or Special Envoy. See UN General As-
sembly resolution 67/255 ‘Human Resources Management’, UN Doc. A/RES/67/255, 23
May 2013, para. 63 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/zq330a/); “Use of ‘When Actually Em-
ployed’ contracts for special representatives, envoys and other special high-level positions”,
57
Research has shown that employees who believe their manager behaves ethically are more
likely to behave ethically themselves, are happier in their work, are more committed to their
work, and are more likely to help others. See, for example, David M. Mayer, Karl Aquino,
Rebecca L. Greenbaum and Maribeth Kuenzi, “Who displays ethical leadership and why
does it matter? An examination of antecedents and consequences of ethical leadership”, in
Academy of Management Journal, 2012, vol. 55, no. 1, p. 167.
58
UN Ethics Office Annual Report 2017, paras. 15–16, see above note 36. It should be noted
that UNDP’s Ethics Office makes reference to the development and adoption of a Conflict
of Interest Declaration Form for newly recruited staff members already in its 2014 Annual
Report. Activities of the UNDP Ethics Office in 2013: Report of the Ethics Office,
DP/2014/17, 25 March 2014, para. 4 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/4t9ohx/).
59
UN Ethics Office Annual Report 2017, para. 15, see above note 36.
60
Ibid., para. 62.
61
Mayer et al., 2012, p. 167, see above note 57.
62
See the Policy on Voluntary Public Disclosure by UN staff members of Financial Disclosure
and Declaration of Interest Statements (available on UN’s web site).
63
See the web site of the Voluntary Public Disclosure.
64
UN Ethics Office Annual Report 2017, para. 39, see above note 36: “In 2016, of the 163
senior officials eligible to participate in the voluntary public disclosure initiative, 115 (or
70.6 per cent) did so. In 2017, 95 of the 142 eligible senior officials (or 66.9 per cent) partic-
ipated. Overall participation rates remained largely in line with those in previous years”. In
2019, a little more than 75 per cent of eligible officials participated. UN Ethics Office Annu-
al Report 2019, para. 29, see above note 43.
65
H.E. President María Fernanda Espinosa Garces (the seventy-third President of the UN
General Assembly) is the second President to do so (available on UN’s web site).
ethical leadership for the integrity of an institution. However, the ethics and
integrity requirements, of course, apply to all staff members, regardless of
their seniority within an organization. All UN staff members are required to
disclose possible, potential and actual conflicts of interest and are required
to proactively seek advice from the Ethics Office when they are in doubt. 66
This ensures a certain degree of consistency in the application and interpre-
tation of the UN’s regulatory ethics infrastructure. 67 It also seeks to ensure
conflicts of interest are increasingly identified before they occur, thus pro-
actively managing and mitigating any such reputational risks.
To facilitate a broader understanding of the ethics and integrity re-
quirements across the UN, since 2013, the Executive Office of the Secre-
tary-General jointly with the UN Ethics Office each year launches what are
called the ‘Leadership Dialogues’. The Leadership Dialogues provide a
structured framework around a specific theme for managers to discuss eth-
ics questions with their staff at a dedicated time. The theme, while different
every year, focuses on further developing staff member’s understanding of
their required integrity. For example, the 2017 Leadership Dialogue was
entitled: “Standards of Conduct: What’s expected of me?”. 68 It focused on
the UN standards of conduct and what they mean for being accountable for
one’s actions, making decisions in the best interests of the organization,
and adhering to the organizational regulations, rules and policies in this
regard. Topics covered included organizational priorities relating to the
prevention of sexual exploitation, abuse and harassment, conflicts of inter-
est, the rules around gifts, and staff members’ participation in political ac-
tivities. In 2019, the Leadership Dialogue was entitled “Conflicts of interest:
why do they matter?”. 69 All managers are required to undertake this struc-
tured 1.5-hour dialogue session on an annual basis with their direct reports.
Starting with the Secretary-General, who undertakes the session with his
Under-Secretary-Generals, the Leadership Dialogue thus cascades through
66
Whereas all UN Secretariat staff members are expected and encouraged to seek advice from
the UN Ethics Office when in doubt, in UNDP, staff members are required to first seek eth-
ics clearance from the UNDP Ethics Office before seeking approval from their management
to engage in outside activities. See, “Operating with Unwavering Integrity”, UNDP Code of
Ethics, October 2017, p. 12 (available on UNDP’s web site).
67
The consistency of ethics standards and policies is further strengthened through regular
EPUN meetings and consultations on particularly complex cases or issues having UN-wide
implications. See further note 40, above.
68
See the website of the Leadership Dialogues (available on UN’s web site).
69
Ibid.
the organization and across teams, departments and countries. The UN Eth-
ics Office monitors compliance and is available for further support and ad-
vice as teams embark on their annual Leadership Dialogue exercise. 70 Such
initiatives, which allow managers dedicated time to discuss ethics and in-
tegrity questions with their direct reports, provide an important impetus for
further developing and enhancing the organization’s collective understand-
ing of the ethical challenges that occur in the context of its work, and the
different viewpoints that may exist on how to resolve such challenges.
Such regular conversations form an important part of an organization’s eth-
ics learning, and a deeper “moral learning process”, 71 another important
component of establishing and reinforcing a culture of organizational ethics
and individual integrity.
In other words, a number of institutional mechanisms have been es-
tablished over the years to further enhance understanding of and ensure
compliance by its staff members with the UN’s regulatory ethics infrastruc-
ture, which in turn seek to enhance public trust and confidence in (the in-
tegrity of) the institution itself. More importantly, through its advisory, rep-
utational risk management, and outreach initiatives, the UN Ethics Office
aims to contribute to creating an organizational culture where every staff
member understands and fulfils the requirements of independence, impar-
tiality and integrity, treats everyone with respect and dignity, and fosters a
safe and inclusive working environment for all.
However, as important as regulatory and institutional ethics infra-
structures are, research has shown that the single best predictor of unethical
behaviour is organizational culture, 72 and in particular organizational toler-
ance. Where unethical behaviour is seen to be tolerated (such as where
there are no repercussions or where those repercussions are not publicly
communicated as accountability standards), the overall impact of regulato-
ry or institutional ethics infrastructure on strengthening the (perceived) in-
70
Ibid.
71
On the ‘moral learning process’, see, for example, Dr. Julien Topal, “Installing a Moral
Learning Process: Integrity Beyond Traditional Ethics Training”, Columbia Center for the
Advancement of Public Integrity, 2017 (available on its web site).
72
See, for example, Azish Filabi and Caterina Bulgarella, “Organizational Culture Drives Eth-
ical Behaviour: Evidence From Pilot Studies”, 2018 OECD Anti-Corruption and Integrity
Forum (available on OECD web site); Paula A. Johnson, Sheila E. Widnall and Frazier F.
Benya (eds.), Sexual Harassment of Women: Climate, Culture, and Consequences in Aca-
demic Sciences, Engineering, and Medicine, The National Academies Press, Washington,
D.C., 2018.
73
Although allegations of sexual exploitation by aid workers first surfaced in 1992 in the con-
text of the UN Mission in Cambodia, the issue was not formally recognised until a 2002 re-
port by Save the Children and UNHCR highlighted widespread sexual abuse of populations
by UN peacekeepers and NGO personnel in West Africa. Accusations included: sexual as-
sault, rape, sex trafficking, organized prostitution rings, abduction, child pornography, and
sex in exchange for food, medicine, employment, and protection. See, Save the Children and
UNHCR, “Sexual Violence and Exploitation: The Experience of Refugee Children in Guin-
ea, Liberia and Sierra Leone”, 1 February 2002. See also, Melanie O’Brien, Criminalising
Peacekeepers: Modernising National Approaches to Sexual Exploitation and Abuse, Pal-
grave MacMillan, 2017; Rosa Freedman, “UNaccountable: A New Approach to Peacekeep-
ers and Sexual Abuse”, in European Journal of International Law, 2018, vol. 29, no. 3,
pp. 961–985; Jasmine-Kim Westendorf, Violating Peace: Sex, Aid and Peacekeeping, Cor-
nell University Press, 2020.
74
For instance, in 2018, of the 55 allegations of sexual exploitation and abuse reported to the
UN peacekeeping operations and special political missions, 38 were against military person-
nel, 4 against police, and 13 against civilian personnel. Additionally, a further 94 allegations
were reported involving UN staff and related personnel of UN entities other than peacekeep-
ing operations and special political missions. See, “Special measures for protection from
sexual exploitation and abuse”, Report of the Secretary-General, UN Doc. A/73/744, 14
February 2019 (and annexes) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/e5i9ma/). The United Nations
publishes quarterly updates on allegations of sexual exploitation and abuse and maintains an
up-to-date online database of allegations (available on its web site).
75
“Safe Space Survey on Sexual Harassment in the Workplace Report”, Deloitte (for the Unit-
ed Nations), January 2019 (available on Code Blue Campaign’s web site) (‘Safe Space Sur-
vey Report’). See also, “One in three UN workers say they have been sexually harassed in
past two years”, The Guardian, 16 January 2019 (available on its web site).
76
In February 2018, allegations surfaced in the media about the abuse of vulnerable women by
senior Oxfam officials in Haiti in 2011. Oxfam announced a Ten Point Action Plan to ad-
dress sexual misconduct and accountability, which included the establishment of an Inde-
pendent Commission. The Commission’s Interim Report was published in January 2019 and
its final report in June 2019 (available on its web site).
77
Amnesty International commissioned an external, independent investigation into the circum-
stances following the deaths of two staff members who had taken their own lives while in
the service of the organization. The external investigation report was published in January
2019. “Staff Wellbeing Review”, Amnesty International, January 2019 (available on its web
site) (‘Amnesty International Report’).
78
Kieran Pender, “Us Too? Bullying and Harassment in the Legal Profession”, International
Bar Association, May 2019 (available on its web site) (‘IBA Report’).
79
Ibid., pp. 55–56.
chief Prosecutor of the ICC. 80 This emerging data shows very clearly that
much more work needs to be done not only to improve existing policy
frameworks around sexual harassment to recognise the full spectrum of
behaviours that occur, but also to invest in stronger compliance, regulatory
and institutional ethics infrastructure to address sexual harassment. 81 This
section will thus focus on recent developments at the UN in relation to this
under-researched and emerging area in ethics research and scholarship.
I deliberately call this an ‘emerging area’ because most scholarship
and other ethics research has focused on conflicts of interest, reputational
risk management and other anti-corruption measures as encompassing ‘eth-
ics’ or ‘ethics infrastructure’. For instance, the Organisation for Economic
Co-operation and Development has conducted a number of research pro-
jects and developed various concept papers on governance in public institu-
tions, which define integrity as anti-corruption. 82 Likewise, scholarship on
ethics in the legal profession thus far has focused mostly on inappropriate
and corrupt conduct by lawyers vis-à-vis their clients or the law and courts
more generally. 83 Arguably, even the UN’s ethics infrastructure discussed
above is similarly focused (more) on anti-corruption; notably, the UN Eth-
ics Office’s mandate defines ‘ethical issues’ as “conflicts of interest”. 84
This is perhaps not surprising as the UN Ethics Office, was created in di-
rect response to a corruption scandal. This has, however, meant that the
80
Danya Chaikel, “ICC Prosecutor Symposium: The Next ICC Prosecutor Must Embody In-
tegrity in the #MeToo Era”, in Opinio Juris, 16 April 2020 (available on its web site). See
also, the April 2020 ATLAS Statement to the Committee on the Election of the Prosecutor
and States Parties to the Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court calling for a fair,
transparent and safe procedure for receiving and assessing complaints of misconduct against
candidates for ICC Prosecutor (available on its web site).
81
This section largely focuses on frameworks to address sexual harassment as opposed to oth-
er sexual misconduct such as sexual exploitation and abuse (SEA) by aid workers of the
populations they are working for/with, which has been extensively covered elsewhere. The
author recognizes that this is distinction is arbitrary as sexual harassment, exploitation and
abuse are part of a continuum of sexual violence. For more on SEA, see sources above in
note 73.
82
See, for example, the 2005 OECD policy document, “Public Sector Integrity – A Framework
for Assessment” or its 2018 research paper by Azish Filabi and Caterina Bulgarella, “Organ-
izational Culture Drives Ethical Behaviour: Evidence from Pilot Studies”, 2018 OECD
Global Anti-Corruption and Integrity Forum, 27 March 2018.
83
For an overview, see, for example, Parker et al., 2008, pp. 161–163, see above note 5.
84
ST/SGB/2005/22, Section 3.1, see above note 40: “(c) Providing confidential advice and
guidance to staff on ethical issues (e.g., conflict of interest), including administering an eth-
ics helpline” (emphasis added).
85
See, for example, Carole Pateman, “Feminist Critiques of the Public/Private Dichotomy”, in
Stanely I. Benn and Gerald F. Gaus (eds.), Public and Private in Social Life, St. Martin's
Press, New York, 1983; Hilary Charlesworth, “The Public/Private Distinction and the Right
to Development in International Law”, Australian Year Book of International Law, 1988, vol.
12, pp. 1902–04; Hilary Charlesworth, “Feminist Methods in International Law”, in The
American Journal of International Law, 1999, vol. 93, no. 2, pp. 3793–94; Christine Chin-
kin, “A Critique of the Public/Private Dimension”, in European Journal of International
Law, 1999, vol. 10, no. 2, pp. 3873–95.
86
Standards of Conduct for the International Civil Service, paras. 21 and 22, see above note 12.
87
“Special measures for protection from sexual exploitation and sexual abuse”, Secretary-
General’s Bulletin ST/SGB/2003/13, 9 October 2003 (‘ST/SGB/2003/13’) (https://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/ftozsr/); “Prohibition of discrimination, harassment, including sex-
ual harassment, and abuse of authority”, Secretary-General’s Bulletin ST/SGB/2008/5, 11
February 2008 (‘ST/SGB/2008/5’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/ibc9oq/). Since the writ-
ing of this chapter, the UN Secretariat has adopted an updated policy on discrimination, har-
assment, including sexual harassment, and abuse of authority: Secretary-General’s Bulletin
ST/SGB/2019/8, 10 September 2019.
88
Until 2019, under the UN’s policy on (sexual) harassment, senior managers were responsible
for addressing complaints of sexual harassment by establishing a fact-finding panel “of at
least two individuals from the department, office or mission concerned who have been
trained in investigating allegations of prohibited conduct or, if necessary, from the Office of
Human Resources Management roster”. See ST/SGB/2008/5, section 5. Although a full cri-
tique of the UN’s policy framework around sexual harassment is beyond the scope of this
chapter, it should be noted that best practice in addressing integrity violations is for such al-
legations to be investigated by independent investigators. Individuals who work closely with
the alleged offender of sexual harassment, or with the person targeted, are not generally
deemed to be sufficiently impartial and independent to allow for the fair and transparent de-
cision-making on such matters. As such, the appointment of a fact-finding panel of individu-
als from within a department, office or mission, depending on the size of that department,
office or mission, can be problematic.
89
“Charity boss Justin Forsyth resigns from Unicef”, BBC News, 22 February 2018.
90
“Top UN official accused of sexual harassment stands down”, The Guardian, 23 February
2018.
98
See Annex 4 to “CEB Taskforce on Addressing Sexual Harassment within the Organizations
of the UN system – Progress Report”, UN Doc. CEB/2018/HLCM/14, 3 October 2018
(‘CEB/2018/HLCM/14’). See also, the UN Secretariat’s updated policy ST/SGB/2019/8,
above note 87. Additionally, in July 2019, jointly with member states, the UN launched a
Model Code of Conduct to Prevent Harassment, Including Sexual Harassment, at UN Sys-
tem Events. The International Bar Association in May 2019 announced that it would also
develop a harassment policy specifically applicable to the events and conferences it organiz-
es around the world each year. IBA Report, May 2019, p. 101, see above note 78.
99
CEB/2018/HLCM/14, paras. 22–30, see above note 98. Efforts are also ongoing in the
broader humanitarian and development sector to set up similar misconduct disclosure sys-
tems at an inter-agency level. For more information on this Inter-Agency Misconduct Dis-
closure Scheme, see the website of the Steering Committee for Humanitarian Response.
100
CEB/2018/HLCM/14/Add.1, Annex 4, p. 13, see above note 98.
lege based on unequal gender relations and other power dynamics”. 101 It
also acknowledges the intersectional nature of identities, noting that “pow-
er imbalances based on gender, workplace or educational status, racial or
ethnic backgrounds, age, disability, sexual orientation or economic class
could impact on sexual harassment”. 102 This recognition of sexual harass-
ment as an expression of power inequality is important as it is still too of-
ten underrecognized: sexual harassment (most often) has very little to do
with sex and everything to do with power. Although sexual harassment
does not always constitute an abuse of authority in the professional mis-
conduct understanding of the word (such as a senior manager abusing their
position of authority to gain sexual favours from junior staff, as the behav-
iour can also occur between individuals of similar ‘rank’ in an organiza-
tional hierarchy), sexual harassment always constitutes an abuse of relative
or social power, as it expresses and reinforces existing (gendered and other)
power imbalances and inequalities. 103
The UN’s Model Policy on sexual harassment also acknowledges
that sexual harassment can be verbal, non-verbal and physical, and can oc-
cur between people of the same and of different genders. Importantly, the
policy emphasises the need for support to victims and a victim-centred ap-
proach as well as work on prevention. Involving victims or survivors in the
response to sexual harassment in a meaningful way is one way to equalize
the unequal power dynamic that harmed them in the first place. This in-
cludes allowing victims/survivors to remain meaningfully engaged and in-
volved in decisions about a process that influences and affects them, in-
cluding the power to decide the extent to which they wish to remain in-
volved (if at all) in any disciplinary investigation. 104 Although the meaning
of such a survivor or victim-centred approach to sexual harassment is not
specifically spelled out in the Model Policy, and thus requires further defi-
nition in the UN’s practices, the recognition that a process must be survivor
101
Ibid.
102
Ibid., p. 14
103
“Towards an End to Sexual Harassment: The Urgency and Nature of Change in the Era of
#MeToo”, in UN Women, November 2018, p. 10: “Sexual harassment expresses and rein-
forces inequalities of power” (‘UN Women Report’). See also, Catharine A. MacKinnon,
Sexual Harassment of Working Women, Yale University Press, New Haven, 1979.
104
Lyndsey Jones-Renaud, “What does a Survivor-Centered Approach to Workplace Harass-
ment Look Like?”, in Medium, 29 November 2018.
105
UN Women Report, November 2018, p. 8, see above note 103: “Define sexual harassment
as what it is: a human rights violation of gender-based discrimination, regardless of sex, in a
context of unequal power relations such as a workplace and/or gender hierarchy. It can take
the form of various acts including rape, other aggressive touching, forced viewing of por-
nography, taking and circulation of sexual photographs, as well as verbal sexual conduct.
Definitions should define, not trivialize (for example, refer to ‘annoyance’), make moral
judgments (‘offensiveness’), or engage in demeaning psychologizing (‘humiliation’)”.
106
On the wins and losses of the new policy, see also: Priyanka Chirimar, “UN’s New Harass-
ment Policy: You win some, you lose some”, Action against Prohibited Conduct (AAPC), 25
September 2020 (available on its web site).
107
For instance, Oxfam has adopted UN definitions of sexual harassment, sexual exploitation,
and sexual abuse. See Oxfam, “One Oxfam Policy on Protection from Sexual Exploitation
and Abuse”, December 2018 (available on its web site). See also, the definitions adopted in
the CHS Alliance’s PSEAH Quick Reference Handbook, revised version 2020 (available on
its web site).
contractors and consultants. 112 The policy defines retaliation as “any direct
or indirect detrimental action that adversely affects the employment or
working conditions of an individual, where such action has been recom-
mended, threatened or taken for the purpose of punishing, intimidating or
injuring an individual because that individual engaged in” a protected ac-
tivity. 113 Such a ‘protected activity’, however, is narrowly defined to cover
reporting misconduct through established reporting channels 114 and/or co-
operating with a duly authorised audit or investigation. While protection
against retaliation for reporting misconduct is an important part of a func-
tioning ethics infrastructure to encourage staff members and others to speak
up about concerns of misconduct, through the adoption of such a formal
definition, it fails to address more informal ways in which retaliation mani-
fests, in particular in cases of sexual harassment. For example, women
have reported that they were denied promotions, have been excluded from
meetings or duty travel, and were denied training opportunities, projects,
assignments or other work to advance their career merely for rebuffing
sexual advances from senior officials. 115 Such retaliatory behaviour often
already occurs before a complainant submits a report of misconduct
through the appropriate reporting channel (if they do at all), and as such,
would likely fall outside the formal scope of the UN’s protection against
retaliation policy. In other words, these other forms of retaliatory behaviour,
112
“Protection against retaliation for reporting misconduct and for cooperating with duly au-
thorized audits or investigations”, Secretary-General’s Bulletin ST/SGB/2017/2/Rev.1, 28
November 2017 (‘ST/SGB/2017/2/Rev.1’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/opkf43/). Sec-
tion 2.1. now provides that protection against retaliation applies to any staff member (re-
gardless of the type of appointment or its duration), intern, United Nations volunteer, indi-
vidual contractor or consultant who engages in a protected activity. A protected activity is
defined as reporting misconduct through established reporting channels and/or cooperating
with a duly authorised audit or investigation. Previously, the policy only covered UN staff
members, interns and UN volunteers. Note, the UNDP protection against retaliation policy
already covered non-staff personnel such as contractors, interns and UNVs serving in UNDP
or another UNDP administered fund, programme or agency since July 2012. The revised
policy also introduced protection of individuals who choose to report wrongdoing to an ex-
ternal entity in limited circumstances, allows for recommending transfer of the alleged retal-
iator, and explicitly prohibits retaliation against outside parties.
113
Ibid., Section 1.4.
114
The established reporting channels are set out in: “Unsatisfactory conduct, investigations
and the disciplinary process”, Administrative Instruction ST/AI/2017/1, 26 October 2017
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/vzfumy/).
115
PassBlue, January 2019, see above note 94.
much more common than retaliation as defined in the policy, still remain
subject only to other, more informal resolution mechanisms.
The various measures taken by the UN since 2018 are important first
steps towards addressing sexual harassment. But they are simply that: first
steps. Their true test will lie in their implementation and, in particular, in
their impact upon changing structural dimensions of inequality that have
manifested in an organizational culture that has long silenced and ignored
sexual harassment (in the UN and beyond, as illustrated by the #MeToo
movement). The UN and NGO surveys on (sexual) harassment that have
followed each other in relatively quick succession in the first six months of
2019, confirm the importance of workplace culture, and in particular une-
qual power dimensions and structures of privilege that protect those in po-
sitions of power, as a predictor for incidents of (sexual) harassment and
other forms of gender-based violence in the workplace. 116 What these re-
ports ultimately illustrate is that having regulatory and institutional ethics
infrastructure is simply not enough when the values underpinning that eth-
ics framework are not lived as a reality by staff and reflected in the man-
agement practices of institutions.
Ultimately, to address systemic integrity breaches such as sexual
harassment, whether in the UN or elsewhere, requires addressing the per-
vasive male-dominated power structures that exist, and challenging the dis-
tributions of power within the workforce and therefore the nature of the
workforce. Research has shown that sexual harassment is much more likely
to occur in workplace contexts “where men outnumber women, where
leadership is male-dominated, […] where the power structure is hierar-
chical, where lower-level employees are largely dependent on superiors for
advancement, and where power is highly concentrated in a single per-
son”. 117 Another key determining factor is organizational climate, and, in
particular, “organizational tolerance”. 118 In other words, organizations with
116
UNAIDS Report, December 2018, see above note 91; Safe Space Survey Report, January
2019, see above note 75; Amnesty International Report, January 2019, see above note 77;
IBA Report, May 2019, see above note 78; Oxfam interim and final report of Independent
Commission, June 2019, see above note 76.
117
Nancy Gertner, “Sexual Harassment and the Bench”, in Stanford Law Review Online, 2018,
vol. 71, p. 91.
118
UN Women Report, November 2018, p. 16, see above note 103; Chloe Hart, Alison Dahl
Crossley and Shelley Correll, “Study: When Leaders Take Sexual Harassment Seriously, So
Do Employees”, in Harvard Business Review, 14 December 2018 (available on its web site);
Paula A. Johnson, 2018, see above note 72.
119
See, for example, Nancy Gertner, 2018, p. 91, see above note 117; IBA Report, May 2019,
p. 14, see above note 78.
120
UN System-Wide Strategy on Gender Parity, October 2017 (available on UN web site).
121
See, for an example of Feminist Leadership Principles, Shawna Wakefield, “Transformative
and Feminist Leadership for Women’s Rights”, Oxfam America Research Backgrounder Se-
ries, 23 January 2017 (available on its web site).
there is always a risk that organizational culture and practices reflect those
same injustices and inequalities these organisations were designed to
fight. 122 For this reason, many organisations, like the UN, have adopted
Codes of Conduct and other regulatory ethics infrastructure to provide their
staff members with a framework or moral compass to guide decisions they
are making on a daily basis. Such ethics and integrity frameworks thus of-
ten focus on delineating both desirable and undesirable behaviour in line
with an organization’s core values.
However, as Parker et al. (2008) have demonstrated,
ethical infrastructures will only be useful if everyone […] is
explicitly encouraged to raise ethical issues so that ethical
problems can be identified, discussed and resolved – and peo-
ple are not punished for raising them in the first place. 123
In other words, successful ethics infrastructures require not only the
existence of rules and regulations, and mechanisms to enforce compliance
and mete out sanctions for transgressions, but a deeper engagement with
ethics and integrity by an institution and its staff on a day-to-day basis,
both externally and internally. Integrity and its associated ethics infrastruc-
ture must become part and parcel of an organization’s informal workplace
practices, cultures and expectations. Otherwise, “there is a danger that ethi-
cal infrastructure will simply amount to formal ethical structures that do
not connect with informal work team cultures and individual [staff mem-
bers’] values in practice”. 124 A workplace culture that privileges and is per-
122
In 2010, David La Piana described what he called the ‘Non-Profit Paradox’: “Nonprofits
tend to recreate within their own organizational cultures the problems they are trying to
solve in society”. He explains that organizations that are highly value-driven, such as non-
profits, employ individuals who are also highly value and mission-driven. Yet this mission-
drive and their commitment to progressive social values, he explains, “can drive dysfunc-
tional organizational behaviour by blinding workers to their own faults”. Additionally, he al-
so observed that “values-driven people sometimes feel that their ethical activities entitle
them to act less morally”. The irony, then, is that such value-driven individuals who often
observe or interact with human rights abusers may (unintentionally) start exhibiting those
same abusive behaviours in their interaction with others, most notably with their peers and
colleagues. At the same time, value-driven individuals in less powerful positions tend to be-
come particularly sensitive to possible abuses of power, and thus to feel oppressed by those
in positions of power. See David La Piana, “The Nonprofit Paradox: Why organizations are
so often plagued by the very ills they aim to cure”, in Stanford Social Innovation Review,
2010.
123
Parker et al., 2008, p. 183, see above note 5.
124
Ibid., p. 161.
Sexual Harassment
Matthias Neuner *
This chapter discusses the United Nations’ (‘UN’) decades-long and ongo-
ing effort to preserve and defend the integrity of its staff by defining sexual
harassment 1 and investigating as well as judicially pursuing those who are
alleged to have engaged in such illegal behaviour. Personal conduct in this
area is at the very centre of the notion of ‘integrity’ of those who serve in-
ternational organisations. It is a topic that has only become more important
in recent years, especially after the global #metoo movement.
Twenty-six years after the enactment of the first administrative defi-
nition of sexual harassment, the Chief Executive Board for Coordination
(‘CEB’) of the UN observed in 2018 that “sexual harassment results from a
culture of discrimination and privilege, based on unequal gender relations
and power dynamics. It creates hostile workplaces, which limit the tar-
get/victim/affected individual’s ability to thrive”. 2
*
Matthias Neuner is Trial Counsel, Office of the Prosecutor, Special Tribunal for Lebanon.
The views expressed in this chapter are those of the author and do not necessarily reflect the
views of the Tribunal.
1
This chapter exclusively focuses on sexual harassment and covers neither sexual exploita-
tion nor sexual abuse. Sexual exploitation means “any actual or attempted abuse of a posi-
tion of vulnerability, differential power, or trust, for sexual purposes, including, but not lim-
ited to, profiting monetarily, socially or politically from the sexual exploitation of another”,
similarly, the term ‘sexual abuse’ means the “actual or threatened physical intrusion of a
sexual nature, whether by force or under unequal or coercive conditions”. Secretary-
General’s Bulletin, Special measures for protection from sexual exploitation and sexual
abuse, UN Doc. ST/SGB/2003/13, 9 October 2003, section 1 (https://www.legal-tools.org/
doc/ftozsr/). For the UN Organization Mission in the Democratic Republic of Congo, a
‘Code of Conduct on Sexual exploitation and sexual abuse’ has been published, which refers
to ST/SGB/2003/13 and ST/SGB/1999/13. Section 7.2 of the latter instrument prohibits that
UN forces commit against civilians and persons hors de combat “rape, enforced prostitution,
any form of sexual assault and humiliation and degrading treatment”. Secretary-General’s
Bulletin, Observance by United Nations forces of international humanitarian law, UN Doc.
ST/SGB/1999/13, 6 August 1999 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/kbgmi6/). This chapter
does not discuss any of the criminal offences mentioned in section 7.2 of ST/SGB/1999/13.
2
UN Chief Executives Board, System Model Policy on Sexual Harassment, London, 3-4 May
2018 (‘UN model policy on sexual harassment’), section II (policy statement), para. 1.
3
UN Secretary-General’s (‘S-G’) bulletin, Prohibition of discrimination, harassment, includ-
ing sexual harassment, and abuse of authority, 11 February 2008, ST/SGB/2008/5, Article
1.3 (‘2008-UN-AI’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/ibc9oq/).
4
Michael Rubenstein, Dignity of women at work – A Report on the Problem of Sexual Har-
assment in the Member States of the European Communities, Office for Official Publications
of the European Communities, 1988, paras. 1.5, 1.7, 12.1 (‘Rubenstein report’).
I was not myself. I did not know what to do. […] I felt very
embarrassed. […] It was difficult to go to work every day […]
[E]veryone was looking at me. I stayed indoors the whole
time. I did not speak to anyone. 5
14.2. History
Sexual harassment was first discussed and defined domestically, namely in
the United States of America (‘US’) in the late seventies and early eighties.
With regards to international organisations, sexual harassment was men-
tioned in a UN document in 1979, discussed by the European Communities
(‘EC’) in the eighties and, in the early nineties, first defined by the EC and,
shortly thereafter, by the United Nations. In this section, these develop-
ments will be traced chronologically.
14.2.1. International and Domestic Efforts to Define Sexual
Harassment
Article 8 of the UN Charter (‘Charter’) directs the UN to “place no re-
strictions on the eligibility of men and women to participate in any capacity
and under conditions of equality in its […] organs”. In addition, Article
101(3) of the Charter refers to the “highest standards of efficiency, compe-
tence, and integrity” of UN staff. 6 Integrity was initially not understood to
encompass sexual harassment, as this concept was developed only later, in
the seventies. In 1954, when the International Civil Advisory Board pre-
pared standards, which gave meaning to equality in Article 8 and “integri-
ty” in Article 101 of the Charter, these mentioned that UN staff should cul-
tivate “social relations with colleagues of different races, religions and cul-
tural backgrounds” and the “conduct of superiors must be free of intimida-
tion”. 7 However, harassment and in particular sexual harassment were
omitted.
In the seventies, discussions in the US resulted in the adoption of
domestic administrative regulations and judicial recognition that sexual
harassment is unlawful sex discrimination. 8
5
United Nations Dispute Tribunal (‘UNDT’), Cateaux v. S-G, UNDT/NBI/2010/066, Judg-
ment, 21 February 2013, UNDT/2013/027, paras. 40, 41 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/
exsyrw/).
6
Charter of the United Nations, 26 June 1945 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/6b3cd5/).
7
International Civil Advisory Board, Report on Standards of Conduct in the International
Civil Service, 1954, paras. 11, 13 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/d94c61/).
8
Rubenstein report, 1988, p. 1, paras. 1.1, 1.2, see above note 4.
9
Administrative Tribunal of the United Nations (‘UN-AdminT’), Ho v. S-G, Judgment no.
189, 7 October 1974 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/3m78i2/).
10
UN Secretariat, Information circular from the Under-S-G for Administration and Manage-
ment, Guidelines for promoting equal treatment of men and women in the Secretariat, 8
March 1979, ST/IC/79/17, para. 9.
11
Ellen Frankel Paul, “Sexual Harassment as Sex Discrimination: A Defective Paradigm”, in
Yale Law and Policy Review, 1990, p. 344.
12
Catharine A. MacKinnon, Sexual Harassment of Working Women – A Case of Sex Discrimi-
nation, Yale University Press, 1979.
13
Ibid., p. 1.
14
Ibid., pp. 32–42.
15
Equal Employment Opportunity Commission (‘EEOC’), Interim Guidelines on Sexual Har-
assment, 11 April 1980, p. 25024 (‘EEOC interim guidelines 1980’).
16
Ibid.
17
Ibid, p. 25025, § 1604.11.
18
Often referred to as quid pro quo (compare UN-AdminT, Applicant v. S-G, Judgment, 30
January 2009, No. 1423, pp. 3, 6 (section II), 10 (section XVIII) (https://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/uhsmw3/)); Paul, 1990, p. 333, see above note 11.
19
Equal Employment Opportunity Commission (‘EEOC’), Guidelines on Discrimination Be-
cause of Sex, 10 November 1980, § 1604.11.
Regarding the third variant, this amended definition dropped the re-
quirement for ‘substantial’ interference with an individual’s work perfor-
mance, substituting it with ‘unreasonable’ interference.
14.2.1.2.2. US Supreme Court
In 1986, the Supreme Court of the US decided the case Meritor Savings
Bank v. Vinson. The judges accepted the definition advanced by the
EEOC 20 and further held that a ‘hostile environment’ sexual harassment is
a form of sex discrimination. 21 The judges found that sexual harassment
occurs when it is “sufficiently severe or pervasive ‘to alter the conditions of
[the affected individual’s] employment and create an abusive working envi-
ronment […]’”. 22
14.2.1.2.3. The EC’s Efforts to Define Sexual Harassment until 1991
In the mid-eighties, the European Parliament and the Council of Ministers,
in a series of resolutions, recognised sexual harassment as a problem affect-
ing the dignity and rights of women at work. 23 Still, by 1988 the Ru-
benstein report observed that no Member States of the EC “has any express
legal prohibition of sexual harassment”. 24 European legislation had been
dormant. Rubenstein’s report sent a wakeup call to the EC in Brussels and
to other capitals of European States, resulting in a delayed effort to catch
up with the legislative developments in the US on defining and prohibiting
sexual harassment at work.
On 20 June 1988, the EC’s Advisory Committee on Equal Opportu-
nities for Women and Men suggested adopting a recommendation and a
20
US Supreme Court, Meritor Savings Bank v. Vinson, Judgment, 19 June 1986, No. 84-
1979, p. 57 (65).
21
Ibid., p. 57, section 1, pp. 66, 67.
22
Ibid., p. 67, quoting US Court of Appeals, 11th Circuit, Henson v. City of Dundee¸ Judgment,
9 August 1982, No. 80-5827, 682 F.2d 897 (1982).
23
Rubenstein report, para. 1.2, see above note 4, referring, among others, to a “series of reso-
lutions” of the European Parliament and the European Council resolution of 13 December
1984 on the promotion of positive action for women (Council Recommendation of 13 De-
cember 1984 on the promotion of positive action for women, 84/635/EEC, in Official Jour-
nal of the European Communities, 19 December 1984, no. L 331/34, op. para. 4, second
point; also compare European Parliament, Recommendation to member states on 25 October
1984, in Official Journal of the European Communities, 26 November 1984, no C 315/77.
24
Rubenstein report, paras. 1.6, 12.3, and chapter IV, see above note 4.
25
European Communities, Commission Recommendation of 27 November 1991 on the pro-
tection of the dignity of women and men at work, 27 November 1991, 92/131/EEC, in Offi-
cial Journal of the European Communities, 4 February 1992, no. L 49/1 (‘EC Commission
Recommendation 1991’).
26
Ibid., annex, “Protecting the dignity of women and men at work: code of practice on
measures to combat sexual harassment”, section 2, para. 1.
27
UN, Promotion of equal treatment of men and women in the secretariat and prevention of
sexual harassment, 29 October 1992, ST/SGB/253, para. 1 (‘ST/SGB/253’) (https://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/l1e3wb/).
28
UN, Administrative Instruction: Procedures for dealing with sexual harassment, 29 October
1992, ST/AI/379, para. 2 (‘1992-UN-AI’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/juboyq/).
29
The EC definition interchangeably uses ‘unwelcome’ and ‘unwanted’.
30
Compare the first variant of the definition of US law on the prohibition of sexual harassment
(EEOC interim guidelines 1980, page 25025, § 1604.11 under (1)).
31
1992-UN-AI, para. 9, see above note 28; ST/SGB/253, para. 1, ST/SGB/253, see above note
27.
With sexual harassment being defined, the first cases were reported
and formal procedures were initiated to determine whether allegations of
sexual harassment could be substantiated. Some disciplinary proceedings
involving sexual harassment resulted in the imposition of sanctions on cer-
tain offenders. Some of these cases were then litigated in front of the UN
administrative tribunals. In the following, a cursory overview of some of
the 43 judgements issued by the UNAdminT, the UN Dispute Tribunal
(‘UNDT’) and the UN Appeals Tribunal (‘UNAT’) is provided. The follow-
ing graphs distilling key facts of the 43 cases provide some important in-
formation and context.
The gender breakdown of the alleged offenders was:
Unclear
5%
Female
11%
aale
84%
Absolute numbers:
Male: 36
Female: 5
Unclear:2
The term ‘unclear’ in the above signals that due to the gender-neutral
language used throughout the judgment it was not possible to determine the
gender of the alleged perpetrator.
aale
14%
Female
81%
Absolute numbers:
Male: 6
Female: 35
Unclear:2
Unclear
8%
aale
9%
Female
83%
Female
33%
Male
67%
Also, the growing sexual liberation of society has led to more indi-
viduals identifying themselves as lesbian, gay, bisexual or queer. Thus, the
aforementioned male–female dichotomy has become a little bit simplistic
and therefore outdated. Indirectly acknowledging these developments, the
nuances in the CEB’s statement become obvious: “sexual harassment is the
manifestation of a culture of discrimination and privilege based on unequal
gender relations and other power dynamics”. 33
This statement replaces the outdated male/female dichotomy and
highlights instead discrimination and privilege, which are exercised against
a background of gender relations and other power dynamics.
For example, 11 of the cases reviewed were related to ‘power dy-
namics’ involving a person in superior capacity. 34 Furthermore, at least
32
Rubenstein report, para. 1.5, see above note 4.
33
UN model policy on sexual harassment, section II, para. 1, see above note 2.
34
UN-AdminT, Claxton v. S-G, Judgement, 30 June 1992, No. 560 (https://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/iujb1v/); UN-AdminT, van der Graaf v. S-G, Judgement, 23 July 2001, AT/
DEC/997 (‘van der Graaf v. S-G’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/fyqtk7/); UN-AdminT,
Al-Fahoum v. S-G, Judgement, 20 November 2001, AT/DEC/1018 (https://www.legal-
38
2008-UN-AI, para. 1.3, see above note 3.
39
World Food Programme (‘WFP’), Policy on the Prevention of Harassment, 19 February
1999, HR 99/002, para. 6.
40
UNHCR, Policy on Harassment, Sexual Harassment, and Abuse of Authority, para. 2
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/y9vlxr/).
41
2008-UN-AI, para. 1.3, see above note 3.
42
Ibid., para. 1.2.
43
UNDT, Belkhabaz v. S-G, Judgment, 5 February 2018, UNDT/2018/016/Corr.1, para. 141
(‘UNDT – judgment Belkhabaz’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/jnftsy/); United Nations
Appeals Tribunal (‘UNAT’), Belkhabaz v. S-G, Judgment, 26 October 2018, 2018-UNAT-
873, para. 31 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/lra752/).
44
UNDT – judgment Belkhabaz, para. 141, see above note 3.
45
UN model policy on sexual harassment, section I, see above note 2.
46
UNAT judgment Michaud, para. 61, see above note 34.
women in the organisation and responded that it was not just their brains
that got them to where they were, but that they all had to do a bit of some-
thing else to get there. She had to be prepared to do something and that her
future lay in his hands. 47 The subordinate felt uneasy about these “com-
ments and that it seemed that he inferred she had to sell her body to pro-
gress”. 48
Though the UNDT finally denied the contested behaviour had
amounted to sexual harassment, it extensively considered the expectations
and perceptions of the individual affected by these words:
a. Did Female 1 ask the [alleged offender] what he meant
when he allegedly told her that she had “to be prepared to
do something and your future lies in my hands”? The evi-
dence is that she did not and merely assumed that by this
vague remark, he was referring to sexual favours and con-
sequently felt degraded.
b. Granted that her version of the facts are to be believed ra-
ther than that of the [alleged offender], was it not possible
that in saying that her future lay in his hands, the [alleged
offender] had other ideas of what he expected of her rather
than a sexual relationship? There is no evidence that the
words allegedly spoken by the [alleged offender] were ac-
companied by any suggestive actions or gestures as to lead
to the singular conclusion that he wanted sexual favours
from Female 1.
c. Was the fact of Female 1’s assumption as to what the [al-
leged offender] meant and her feelings of being upset and
degraded as a result thereof sufficient to establish that sex-
ual harassment had occurred in this alleged singular en-
counter with the [alleged offender]? My answer to this is
No.
d. Assuming yet again that the account of Female 1 is to be
preferred over the explanations of the [alleged offender],
was the remark such that it would reasonably be expected
or perceived to cause offence or humiliation? The alleged
remark is so vague and unclear that any ordinary person
may wonder at what the [alleged offender] meant but
47
UNDT, Cooke v. S-G, Judgment, 19 October 2012, UNDT/2012/154, para. 83 (https://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/94bml2/).
48
Ibid., para. 84.
49
Ibid., para. 102.
50
UNAT, Applicant v. S-G, Judgment, 16 March 2012, 2012-UNAT-209, para. 54 (https://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/9cztvz/).
51
English Court of Appeal, McQuire v Western Morning News, Judgment, 11 May 1903,
2 K.B. 100 at 109 per Collins M.R.
52
UNAT judgment Michaud, para. 61, see above note 34 (emphasis added).
53
ST/SGB/253, see above note 27; United Nations Children's Fund (‘UNICEF’), Sexual Har-
assment in the UNICEF Workplace, 11 March 1994, CF/AI/1994-005 (https://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/unou0n/); International Criminal Court, Administrative Instruction
ICC/AI/2005/005, 14 July 2005, section 2.2 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/hyvqzp/);
World Food Programme, Policy on Harassment, Sexual Harassment and Abuse of Authority,
14 February 2007, ED2007/003, para. 7 (‘WFP policy on sexual harassment’) (https://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/x3j9ng/).
54
Food and Agriculture Organisation, Policy on the prevention of harassment, sexual harass-
ment and abuse of authority, 15 January 2015, no. 2015/03, para. 12(f) (https://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/bflryf/); UNICEF, Prohibition of harassment, sexual harassment and abuse of
authority, 10 October 2008, CF/EXD/2008- 004, section 1.1(b) (https://www.legal-tools.org/
doc/1g2arj/); UNICEF, Prohibition of discrimination, harassment, sexual harassment and
abuse of authority, 30 November 2012, CF/EXD/2012-007, section 1.1(b) or (c); UN Devel-
opment Program, “Duties and Responsibilities”, in HR User Guide, January 2010, section I
para. 5; United Nations Relief and Works Agency (‘UNRWA’), Prohibition of Discrimina-
tion, Harassment – including Sexual Harassment – and Abuse of Power, General Staff Circu-
lar No. 06/2010, para. 6(c).
55
US Supreme Court, Harris v. Forklift Systems, Inc., Judgment, 9 November 1993, No. 92-
1168, pp. 17, 21 (emphasis added).
56
Christopher Uggen and Amy Blackstone, “Sexual Harassment as a Gendered Expression of
Power”, in American Sociological Review, 2004, vol. 69, no. 1, p. 64 (65).
57
UNAT Bagot judgment, para. 62, see above note 34.
58
UNDT, Applicant v. S-G, Judgment, 23 June 2011, UNDT/2011/106, para. 43 (‘UNDT –
judgment on friendship gone cold’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/2rkaem/).
59
UNAT Bagot judgment, see above note 34; UNAT Perelli judgment, see above note 34.
because the judges disagreed with the assessment of the first instance
courts whether certain conduct was ‘unwelcome’ or not.
14.3.2.1. Welcome or Unwelcome Conduct
At the core of many sexual harassment cases lies the disagreement of the
alleged offender and target about whether certain conduct was unwelcome
or not. While the target will claim that behaviour was certainly ‘unwel-
come’, the alleged offender will claim the exact opposite. Thus, as both
sides find themselves involved in disciplinary proceedings, one as the al-
leged offender and the other as the target, they are bound to disagree on this
key element.
The UN jurisprudence adopts a conservative stance on which per-
spective, the one of the alleged offender or the affected individual, is ulti-
mately decisive for determining whether a conduct was welcome or not.
The UNAT, by requiring that “the alleged offender should reasonably be
able to understand that his advances are not welcome”, 60 appears to empha-
size the perspective of the alleged offender. Only if the alleged offender
was reasonably able to understand or should reasonably have known 61 that
the conduct was unwelcome, then this conduct may amount to sexual har-
assment.
In conclusion, the judges do not rely on the perspective of the target,
but rather on one of the alleged offender to determine whether conduct is
‘unwelcome’. One can interpret this phrase to point out that the burden of
proof that the alleged offender was “reasonably able to understand” lies
squarely with the administration or the alleged target. 62 The administration,
which usually intends to implement the zero-tolerance 63 approach on sexu-
al harassment by pursuing the alleged offender, has to prove that the person
who engaged in the contested conduct disregarded certain ‘sign-posts’ or
‘signals’ which would have enabled a reasonable person to conclude that
60
UNAT Bagot judgment, para. 52, see above note 34.
61
UNAT Perelli judgment, para. 105, see above note 34.
62
UNAdminT, Belas-Gianou v. S-G, Judgment, 28 July 1995, Judgement No. 707, p. 30
(‘UNAdminT judgment Belas-Gianou’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/cbcpj7/). “It is, of
course the responsibility of the person alleging sexual harassment […] to produce convinc-
ing evidence in support of the allegations”.
63
UN Chief Executives Board for Coordination (‘CEB’), Summary of deliberations, 24 July
2018, CEB/2018/1, Annex I, pp. 17, 18 (‘CEB First deliberations 2018’) (https://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/g4iqls/); CEB, Summary of deliberations, 18 January 2019, CEB/2018/2, pa-
ra. 53(a) (‘CEB Second deliberations 2018’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/hfwl5d/).
tions, that make it difficult to decide whether certain conduct was unwel-
come.
If the affected individual claims boundaries and that these were
transgressed, then the alleged offender can raise the defence that a reasona-
ble person was unable to note these boundaries. The alleged offender then
claims a subjective deficit: to be unaware of the existence of boundaries
because a reasonable person in the same shoes would have been unaware
too.
14.3.2.3. Constructive Knowledge
In response to a defence that the alleged offender could have reasonably
been unaware and was thus unable to notice the boundaries, the jurispru-
dence analyses whether the specific circumstances of each situation create
constructive knowledge of the alleged offender that conduct was unwel-
come. 69 Constructive knowledge “ensures accountability for sexual har-
assment that is conducted out of thoughtlessness or irresponsibility but
nevertheless creates problems for affected staff members”. 70
The UNAT required in Bagot v. S-G that it should be established in a
“clear and unambiguous way that [the alleged offender] had constructive
knowledge of the unwelcome nature of his actions”. 71
Constructive knowledge can flow from a variety of sources. For ex-
ample, after a former male colleague expressed to a female co-worker in an
email that he could “help her getting pregnant” the target of this sexual ad-
vance responded “if I will be ever in a position to share a room one of us
must sleep on the floor”. 72 The same target of this advance also sent anoth-
er email clarifying “I do not want to give you any false hope because I do
not want to have sex with you. I never wanted that”. 73 Both emails set a
boundary, regardless of an otherwise longstanding close friendship with
sexual overtones, constituting at least constructive knowledge that further
sexual advances are ‘unwelcome’ in case the colleague chooses to engage
in further innuendos.
69
UNDT Perelli judgment, para. 104, see above note 34.
70
Ibid.
71
UNAT Bagot judgment, para. 60, see above note 34.
72
UNAT, Applicant v. S-G, Judgment, 28 March 2013, 2013-UNAT-280, para. 45 (‘UNAT –
judgment on friendship gone cold’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/6ivbku/).
73
Ibid., para. 46.
74
UNAdminT judgment Belas-Gianou, para. 63, see above note 62.
75
Ibid., p. 31, section VI.
76
Ibid., p. 31, section VI(e) and p. 33, section VIII.
77
Ibid., p. 34, section IX.
78
Ibid., p. 35, section X.
79
Ibid., p. 34, section X. Compare also p. 40, section XIX: “In essence, the Applicant’s claims
of sexual harassment […] find support only in her own statements to the Tribunal and to
others to whom she says she conveyed them”.
80
UNDT – judgment on friendship gone cold, paras. 42, 44, 47, 134, 135, see above note 58;
UNAT – judgment on friendship gone cold, para. 39, see above note 72.
81
Ibid., para. 41.
82
Ibid., para. 45.
But I do not wont [sic] to give you any false hope becouse [sic]
I do not wont [sic] to have sex with you. I never wonted [sic]
that and morre [sic] correct I do not wont [sic] to have sex
with anybody at all. I do not joke now. 83
Four weeks after the target had resumed duties at the duty station, the
alleged offender sent via email a photo of his genitalia to the subordinate
who responded
I simply cannot belive [sic] that you have sent me this photo. I
have not seen your intimate part before definetly [sic] and I
truly hope you are joking only. What on earth made you to
take this kind picture of your exposed body and send it to me
[…] I can forgive you only if you were drunk completely [sic]
when done so. 84
However, the next morning, the affected individual joked with the superior
that “it was well shaved”. 85 About two weeks later, the targeted person
moved out of the hotel in which the alleged offender was also staying, in a
separate room. 86
The first instance court and the UNAT disagreed whether the conduct
of the superior who had sent a photo of his genitalia was ‘unwelcome’ pur-
suant to 1992 UN Administrative Instruction.
14.4.2.1. UNDT
The UNDT focused on the overall behaviour displayed between the superi-
or and the subordinate by claiming:
The charge of sexual harassment against the Applicant cannot
be sustained in the circumstances. To the extent that [the af-
fected individual] was willing and happy to engage in sex talk
via emails, telephone, text messages and in-person with the
[alleged offender], the [affected individual] cannot blow hot
and cold deciding after the fact and several months later after
other disagreements that [the affected individual] was sexually
harassed based on incidents [the affected individual] had at
the time they occurred joked about. 87
83
Ibid., para. 46.
84
Ibid., para. 50.
85
UNDT – judgment on friendship gone cold, para. 67, see above note 58.
86
Ibid., paras. 44, 65; UNAT – judgment on friendship gone cold, para. 51, see above note 72.
87
UNDT – judgment on friendship gone cold, para. 187, see above note 58 (compare also
paras. 64, 65).
In essence, the UNDT argued that the alleged conduct was not unwel-
come. 88 The UNDT found that what happened between the affected indi-
vidual and the alleged offender was “a personal and intimate feud between
two consenting adult staff members”. 89
14.4.2.2. UNAT
The UNAT disagreed, finding the conduct was ‘unwelcome’: From the out-
set the affected individual “did not share the [alleged offender’s] desire to
pursue a sexual relationship”. 90 The judges held that the target had set
boundaries while being recruited by the alleged offender for a post under
his supervision:
The transmission by the [offender] of a photograph of his gen-
italia to a female colleague, much less a female colleague un-
der his direct supervision, irrespective of whether the photo-
graph was sent within or outside work hours, can at its best
[…] 'be characterised as outrageous, and most probably un-
wanted’. In the present case, there was no “probability” sur-
rounding the issue as to whether this action was unwanted or
unwelcome, given the boundaries which the [target] had set in
her correspondence of January 2005. […] The fundamental
basis of the [alleged offender’s] and [target’s] relationship,
from 15 February 2005 onwards, was that of supervisor and
supervisee. Given the unequal nature of this relationship and
the boundaries which the [target] had attempted to establish,
together with the [alleged offender’s] breach of those bounda-
ries, […] the [offender’s] very graphic conduct on 15 March
2005 and its unwelcome nature rendered the [target’s] work
environment “offensive” within the meaning of ST/AI/379. 91
The judges continued that the offender’s
approaches to the [target] remained sexual in nature, notwith-
standing the absence of overt sexual comments or entreaties
88
Compare ibid., para. 67: “It can be deduced also from later communication between [the
affected individual and alleged offender] that their friendship continued nevertheless and
that [the affected individual] did not find the photograph [of the penis] unwelcome or offen-
sive”. Further, the judge observed in this same case, with regards to workplace harassment:
“Such conduct must be unwelcome in the sense that the alleged victim did not solicit, incite
or court the conduct and regarded it as undesirable and offensive” (compare also para. 59).
89
Ibid., para. 181.
90
Ibid., para. 59.
91
UNAT – judgment on friendship gone cold, para. 60, see above note 72.
come and, at the very least, would have made the subordinates uncomfort-
able in his presence, and impacted on staff members’ relationship to the
superior. 95 The superior was not denying that he had spoken about massag-
es, had sent numerous messages, had touched his staff and talked with one
subordinate about marriage, but emphasised that he was also asked a lot of
questions by the staff concerned about his own mixed cultural upbringing
and therefore neither the conversations nor actions would have had a sexual
connotation. 96
Having listened to the superior, the UNDT observed that at least one
witness also reported about email interactions which were not unwelcome,
and that the superior acknowledged discussions about massages and other
topics which one could interpret “in more than one way”. 97 Overall, the
UNDT emphasised that the investigation leading to the summary dismissal
of the superior was not conducted properly, and was “one-sided”. 98 This
left the judge with two possibilities: either the subordinated staff, having
learned from each other, brought their genuine and serious concerns jointly
about the alleged offender to the attention of senior management, or the
subordinates did not like his management style and elevated some concerns
to engineer his removal. 99 As the investigation and disciplinary proceedings
failed to clarify which of both options applied, the UNDT set aside the
summary dismissal of the superior. 100
This case demonstrates how crucial a proper investigation is. The in-
vestigation should not only touch upon the facts constituting sexual har-
assment, but also cover the perceptions of both sides of the contested con-
duct, and the overall dynamic the conduct has at the workplace. Due to the
UN’s zero-tolerance policy, allegations of sexual harassment, if proven at
the end of a proper investigation, are likely to result in the removal of the
alleged offender. Thus, the facts must be proven to the ‘clear and convinc-
ing’ evidence standard required for dismissal. 101
95
Ibid., para. 125.
96
Ibid., paras. 131–133, 135.
97
Ibid., paras. 128–132.
98
Ibid., para. 141.
99
Ibid., paras. 140, 139.
100
Ibid., paras. 143, 144.
101
UNAT, Molari v. S-G, Judgment, 21 October 2011, 2011-UNAT-164, para. 2 (‘UNAT
judgment Molari’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/6r0pmm/).
102
UNAT Bagot judgment, paras. 2, 3, see above note 34.
103
Ibid., paras. 3, 54, 55.
104
Ibid., paras. 3, 55.
105
Ibid., para. 55.
106
Ibid., para. 3.
107
Ibid.
subsequent biting. 108 The Dispute Tribunal pointed out that until the target
objected (following the biting), the alleged offender who then stopped
could reasonably consider that the behaviour until then was not unwel-
come. 109 However, following the target abruptly leaving the apartment and
having declined the offer to be driven home, the first instance judge found
that “no reasonable person could have doubted that the emergency situation
was only an excuse to leave his apartment and that any other action on his
part would be unwelcome”. 110 Thus, in these circumstances, all subsequent
calls and text messages constituted sexual harassment:
In view of the manner in which the meeting at the apartment
had ended,[…] [I]t was obvious that [the affected individual]
did not want to talk to the [alleged offender] any further.
Therefore, the [alleged offender’s] actions in calling [the tar-
get] six times between 6:06 p.m. and 6:29 p.m. and sending
[…] three text messages between 6:26 p.m. and 9:20 p.m. cer-
tainly constituted unwelcome conduct. Furthermore, the con-
tent of the 17-minute conversation […] does constitute sexual
harassment. The sexual harassment continued [the next day]
when the Applicant sent a text message to [the target] at 5:47
a.m. and attempted to call […] at 3:26 p.m. 111
14.4.4.2. UNAT
The UNAT disagreed with this assessment and doubted that the conduct of
the alleged offender following the biting was unwelcome, at least the al-
leged offender had no constructive knowledge of it.
The Appeals judges pointed out that the reasoning of the UNRWA’s
judges “does not reveal in a clear and unambiguous way that [the alleged
offender] had constructive knowledge of the unwelcome nature of his ac-
tions”. 112 For the contested conduct to amount to sexual harassment,
it is not enough to be found ‘inappropriate.’ No conduct auto-
matically rises to the level of sexual harassment merely on the
108
UNRWA Bagot judgment, paras. 104–110, see above note 34; compare UNAT Bagot judg-
ment, paras. 49, 51, 52, see above note 34.
109
Ibid., para. 110.
110
Ibid., para. 112.
111
Ibid., para. 114.
112
UNAT Bagot judgment, para. 60, see above note 34.
113
Ibid., para. 62.
114
Ibid., paras. 63, 64.
115
UNAT Perelli judgment, paras. 2, 3, 6, see above note 59.
116
Ibid., paras. 6, 8b.
cal contact with a male subordinate; 117 overall some staff members be-
lieved in good faith that the offensive, hostile or intimidating environment
in the unit was created or further aggravated by Perelli. 118
The alleged offender argued that in seven years at the UN, no staff
member ever complained to management about sexual harassment by
Perelli. 119
14.4.5.1. UNDT
The UNDT argued that Perelli was
a senior manager and head of [a] division in a multicultural
organisation. The workplace of the UN is governed by stand-
ards of conduct set by the Charter, staff regulations, rules and
policies. Staff members have at least presumptive knowledge
of these exacting standards, and, particularly given the posi-
tion of seniority, the alleged offender should have been aware
that such conduct breached them. It was the alleged offender’s
responsibility to ensure that the workplace Perelli managed
was free of sexually explicit behaviour and that Perelli did not
contribute to or encourage it. 120
14.4.5.2. UNAT
The UNAT was aware that Perelli was not on actual notice about the un-
welcome nature of the conduct. The court therefore focused on the issue,
whether the UNDT’s conclusion that Perelli had no constructive knowledge
of the unwelcome nature of one’s own actions, is factually and legally sus-
tainable.
The UNAT referred to a report of the Joint Disciplinary Committee
that found: 1) Perelli did not introduce coarse language and profanity in the
unit as such conduct existed there before, 2) subordinates issued no warn-
ing or request about Perelli’s behaviour during the six years tenure as Di-
rector, 3) body language was insufficient to demonstrate that Perelli was
put on notice; and 4) if oral complaints reached Perelli and other senior of-
ficials, then these related to management issues and not sexual harassment
117
UNDT Perelli judgment, para. 95, see above note 34; compare UNAT Perelli judgment,
para. 55, see above note 59.
118
Ibid.
119
Ibid.¸ para. 106.
120
Ibid.¸ para. 107.
issues. 121 The panel found that Perelli’s contention was credible: having
received no clear warning signals from staff that her conduct was seen as
offensive and/or inappropriate, Perelli was unaware that her own conduct
was considered by some as inappropriate and unwelcome; in such circum-
stances, a reasonable person would not necessarily have been aware, given
the existing differences in cultural backgrounds and professional work ex-
periences. 122 The appeals judges concurred with the panel’s assessment and
found that Perelli had no constructive knowledge that her own conduct was
unwelcome by staff.
14.5. Superiors
By virtue of their position, perceived and real power, superiors can greatly
influence the careers and well-being of staff. Thus, they are expected to set
the example of the highest standards of behaviour. As they are expected to
perform a role model function, their entails not only to refrain from engag-
ing in any conduct potentially amounting to sexual harassment, but also to
inform staff about their rights, including the possibility to report miscon-
duct, and, if reports are then made, to react to allegations in a prompt, im-
partial and fair manner.
The evolution of these functions of superiors should be briefly
sketched out. The UN Administrative Instructions moved from vague to
specific in this regard. The 1992 UN Administrative Instruction simply re-
ferred to “senior member of the department or office” 123 without clarifying
whether this person is the direct supervisor, a mid-level manager or top
manager in the office. By contrast, the 2008 UN Administrative Instruction
introduces a distinction between managers and supervisors 124 on the one
hand and “heads of department/office/mission” on the other hand. 125
14.5.1. Acting Twofold upon Receiving Information
Both UN Administrative Instructions from 1992 and 2008 provide that su-
periors exercise a twofold function in relation to informal and formal set-
tlement of situations arising out of allegations of sexual harassment. The
1992 UN Administrative Instruction leaves it to the discretion of the ag-
121
Ibid., para. 64.
122
Ibid.
123
1992-UN-AI, section 6, see above note 28.
124
2008-UN-AI, section 3.2, see above note 3.
125
Ibid., section 3.3.
126
1992-UN-AI, section 6, see above note 28.
127
Ibid., section 7.
128
Ibid., section 9.
129
2008-UN-AI, sections 5.3., 5.6(j), 5.7, 5.9, 5.11, see above note 3, namely the second sen-
tence referring indirectly to the superior as the “third party who has direct knowledge of the
situation”.
130
Ibid., section 5.6(j). Compare also 1992-UN-AI, see above note 28, which mentions, in sec-
tion 5, several persons able to conduct informal settlements before mentioning, in section 6,
first the Personnel Officer and, finally, the “senior member of the department”.
131
UN model policy on sexual harassment, section IV, sub-paras. 2–4, see above note 2.
132
Ibid., p. 6, explanatory notes.
133
Ibid., sections 4.2, 4.3.
134
CEB First deliberations 2018, para. 49, see above note 63; CEB Second deliberations 2018,
para. 52(d), see above note 63.
135
Ibid., section 3.2.
another staff member. 136 On other occasions, Portillo Moya had used the
swear words puta (‘fuck’), hijueputa (a shorter form of ‘son of a bitch’)
claiming not to have meant her colleagues, but to address one’s frustra-
tion. 137
The administration informed Portillo Moya to have displayed a
standard of conduct, which was below that required in international civil
service. 138 Particularly, section 13 of the applicable WFP’s Directive states
“[e]mployees with supervisory and/or management responsibilities are re-
sponsible for: maintaining a high standard of personal conduct in dealing
with all employees, and leading by example in maintaining the personal
dignity of employees […]”. 139 The administration imposed the sanction
‘separation from service’ on Portillo Moya. 140
14.5.3. Senior Position Demands a Higher Level of Sensitivity
The UNAT held in Michaud v. S-G that a senior position demands and jus-
tifies a higher level of sensitivity. Among investigators in the UN’s Office
of International Oversight, a dispute arose out of an email exchange occur-
ring between a superior and subordinate about ten days after the latter had
joined an investigative mission in Afghanistan. 141 The UNAT observed “the
e-mails speak for themselves and invite admonition, if not censure, without
further ado” 142 because they are inappropriately suggestive and contain
comments of the superior intended to suggest sexual interest. 143 Both the
UNDT and the UNAT agreed that the sanction of written reprimand im-
posed by the administration was appropriate. 144 The UNAT admitted that
the words contained in the emails would be
136
UNDT judgment Portillo Moya, paras. 7, 31(d), 38, see above note 34. Translations supplied
in the source.
137
Ibid., paras. 7, 38.
138
Ibid., para. 8.
139
WFP policy on sexual harassment, p. 3, para. 13, see above note 53.
140
UNDT judgment Portillo Moya, paras. 74, 75, 8, 10, 25, see above note 34.
141
For the content of the email exchange see UNDT judgment Michaud, paras. 4–7, see above
note 34.
142
UNAT judgment Michaud, para. 60, see above note 34.
143
Ibid., para. 61.
144
UNDT judgment Michaud, para. 70, see above note 34; UNAT judgment Michaud, paras. 63,
61, see above note 34.
145
UNAT judgment Michaud, para. 61, see above note 34.
146
2008-UN-AI, section 3.2, see above note 3.
147
Ibid., section 3.3.
148
Ibid., section 3.2.
149
Ibid., section 4.4 in connection with section 4.2.
questing for sex, and kissing the aggrieved individual on the face. 150 An-
other staff member whose contract was expiring understood Khan’s actions
as requesting sexual favours. 151 The WFP’s policy clarifies, “When this
[sexual] harassment is committed by a person in a position to influence the
career or employment conditions of the victim, the sexual harassment is
more offensive as it may also constitute abuse of authority”. 152
The UNDT found Khan’s conduct constituted sexual harassment 153
and that the
Head of the Sub-Office […] was required to respect high pro-
fessional and moral standards, […]had direct responsibility to
both prevent and ensure that the workplace [the head] man-
aged was free of offensive and harmful behaviour. Contrary to
his obligations, [the head] not only disregarded the interest of
the staff members in his office but […] was actually directly
responsible for creating a hostile working environment. 154
These acts were aggravated because the position of head of a sub-office
means the superior can influence the employment conditions of the staff. 155
14.5.4.2. Perelli v. S-G
The case Perelli v. S-G has been already discussed. 156 It related to a director
of a division who had found a persistently sexually charged atmosphere
when taking up office 157 and who did little, if anything, to change this. In-
deed, insufficient proof existed that this head of the division had construc-
tive knowledge satisfying the “clear and convincing” 158 evidence standard
required for dismissal that subordinates felt sexually harassed. It is under-
150
UNDT – judgment Khan, paras. 59, 69, see above note 34.
151
Ibid., para. 65.
152
WFP policy on sexual harassment, p. 13, see above note 53.
153
UNDT – judgment Khan, para. 76, see above note 34.
154
Ibid., para. 110.
155
Ibid., para. 111.
156
See Section 14.4.5. above.
157
UNAT Perelli judgment, paras. 6, 34, 64, see above note 59: “Perelli did not introduce
coarse language and profanity in [this office]; such conduct existed before [the alleged of-
fender] joined the Division”; UNDT Perelli judgment, para. 26, see above note 34.
158
UNAT Perelli judgment, paras. 66, 55, see above note 59, in footnote 10 referring to UNAT
judgment Molari, para. 2, see above note 101; UNAT, Aqel v. Commissioner-General of the
UNRWA, Judgment, 1 July 2010, 2010-UNAT-040, para. 27 (https://www.legal-tools.org/
doc/57k511/).
standable that the UNAT set aside the UNDT’s judgment supporting sum-
mary dismissal of Perelli. On the other hand, this director was neither fully
ignorant nor just indifferent to the sexually charged atmosphere in the
workplace directed. Rather, the director appeared to have at least ‘played
along’, possibly even actively contributed to the sexually charged atmos-
phere: the investigation panel’s report revealed that
[m]any referred to [Perelli’s] use of crude language, sexual
jokes, references and innuendo about [the director’s] sex life,
as well as inquiries and references to staff’s sexual habits, of-
ten in front of others. None of the staff had directly com-
plained about these matters to [Perelli], although some had in-
dicated to [Perelli] that they felt uncomfortable in these situa-
tions. 159
So the staff at least mentioned to Perelli that they felt ‘uncomforta-
ble’ about the atmosphere. There was no higher person to whom complaints
could have been addressed within this division, as Perelli assumed the
highest post.
This raises two questions: how did Perelli use her own position as
head of department to ‘act as role model by upholding the highest stand-
ards of conduct’? And, did Perelli indeed discharge the superior’s ‘duty to
take all appropriate measures to promote a harmonious work environment,
free of intimidation, hostility, offence and any form of prohibited conduct’
pursuant to section 3.2 of 2008 UN Administrative Instruction? The UNDT
suggests that Perelli did not, because the outcome of the investigation into
the allegations revealed
[…] it was more likely than not that there was at least one in-
stance of physical contact with Mr A, a […] staff member. The
contact was non-consensual. […]. [I]t was supported by ‘cred-
ible corroborating testimony [by two staff members] and less
than categorical denial by [Perelli].’ This inappropriate physi-
cal contact was described as [Perelli] leaning over Mr A while
he was sitting at his computer and touching his body with her
breasts. 160
The balance of probability standard (‘more likely than not’) is too
low to form a basis for summary dismissal of Perelli. Dismissals can be
based only on the standard of ‘clear and convincing’ evidence. However,
159
UNDT Perelli judgment, para. 26, see above note 34 (emphasis added).
160
UNDT Perelli judgment, para. 54, see above note 34.
the Perelli case is not only about the question of the legality of her sum-
mary dismissal, but also about how the UN regulations for superiors func-
tion in practice regarding the prohibition of sexual harassment. To assess
whether Perelli satisfied the obligations the 2008 UN Administrative In-
struction created for heads of divisions, the balance of probability standard
is enough. Two corroborating statements existed about this incidence which,
together, suggest that Perelli neither acted as a role model nor ensured “the
highest standards of conduct” as section 3.2 of the 2008 UN Administrative
Instruction required of managers and superiors. Furthermore, Perelli was
no ordinary manager or superior, but was, as the head of division, above
this level and thus expected to “hold all managers and other supervisory
staff accountable for compliance” with the 2008 UN Administrative In-
struction. 161 The alleged and corroborated incident renders it nearly impos-
sible that Perelli could have performed the role of head of office as envis-
aged by section 3.3 of the 2008 UN Administrative Instruction.
Nevertheless, the UNAT was correct in pointing out that Perelli’s
constructive knowledge of other allegations of sexual harassment by sub-
ordinates in her department had not been proven to the ‘clear and convinc-
ing’ standard required. However, the signal sent to the affected individuals
in Perelli’s unit was at least irritating, because the UNAT not only reversed
the UNDT’s judgment which had upheld the UN Administration’s dismis-
sal, but also “order[ed] Ms Perelli’s reinstatement or, if the Administration
so chooses, the award to her of two years’ net base salary”. 162
14.6. Conclusion
The efforts within the UN to ban, investigate, and adjudicate cases of sexu-
al harassment are decades-long and ongoing. In comparison to the US, the
UN commenced these belated efforts in 1992; but since then, it persistently
pursues its approach of ‘zero-tolerance’ 163 regarding such conduct.
Since 2018, the UN created a system-wide database in which it regis-
ters offenders who have engaged in sexual harassment to avoid rehiring
them. 164 A mechanism for UN system-wide collection and analysis of data
161
2008-UN-AI, section 3.3, see above note 3.
162
UNAT Perelli judgment, para. 70, see above note 59.
163
CEB Second deliberations 2018, para. 53 (a), see above note 63.
164
Ibid., para. 52(b), see above note 63; CEB First deliberations 2018, para. 48 and Annex I,
p. 18, see above note 63.
has been set up. 165 The most senior heads of the organisation have pledged
to strengthen the UN’s capacity to investigate 166 sexual harassment to im-
prove the quality of investigations of sexual harassment including, but not
limited to, through specific training and selection suitable staff. Apart from
boosting psychological and other support for the direct targets of sexual
harassment, the UN also makes efforts to address the witnesses of sexual
harassment and enhance the protection of whistle-blowers. 167
165
CEB Second deliberations 2018, para. 52(c), see above note 63.
166
Ibid., para. 52(e).
167
CEB First deliberations 2018, Annex 1, p. 17, see above note 63; Eileen A. Cronin and
Aicha Afifi, Review of whistle-blower policies and practices in United Nations system or-
ganizations, 2018, JIU/Rep/2018/4, paras. 112, 156; UN News, “Secretary-General Guterres
approves updated UN whistleblower protection policy”, 23 January 2017 (available on its
web site).
15.1. Introduction
The principle of integrity has a twofold importance for Ombudsman insti-
tutions. It is, at once, a precondition for their functioning and the goal that
many of their inquiries are aimed at achieving. The scope of this chapter is
to describe the role that the principle of integrity plays in the work and the
functioning of the European Ombudsman.
The chapter will describe how the principle of integrity is an integral
part of the right to good administration established in Article 41 of the Eu-
ropean Charter of Fundamental Rights 1 and how the European Ombuds-
man has addressed it in practice, from which lessons for other international
justice institutions may be drawn. The work of the European Ombudsman
that will be presented in this chapter shows how a direct relationship exists
between integrity and transparency and how improving the transparency of
public institutions directly improves their integrity.
15.2. Ombudsmen Institutions and the Principle of Integrity
The first Ombudsman institution originated in Sweden in 1809 following
the deposition of King Gustav IV Adolf. The legislator set up a body
(Riksdagens Ombudsmän) to allow the Parliament (the ‘Riksdag’) to exer-
cise a certain degree of control over the executive power. However, it is
*
Marta Hirsch-Ziembinska is the Principal Adviser of the European Ombudsman, formerly
Head of Complaints and Inquiries Unit and ICT. Vieri Biondi works as case handler at the
European Ombudsman. The views and opinions expressed in this chapter are those of the
authors and do not necessarily reflect the official policy or position of the European Om-
budsman.
1
Charter of Fundamental Rights of the European Union, 7 June 2016, 2016/C 202/02 (https://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/j00z87/).
only in the second half of the twentieth century that Ombudsman institu-
tions spread in most European countries. 2
The role and structure of Ombudsman institutions may vary from
country to country. However, certain goals are common to all of them, par-
ticularly ensuring and promoting the principle of integrity in the public sec-
tor. The importance that Ombudsmen have in ensuring integrity in public
administrations is also recognized in a working paper of the Organisation
for Economic Co-operation and Development (‘OECD’). 3
However, Ombudsman institutions have to deal with the principle of
integrity not only in the framework of their inquiries; it is of the utmost
importance for Ombudsmen to ensure the integrity of their own institutions
before engaging in their core activities. This is due to the nature of Om-
budsman institutions, which do not have the power to issue binding deci-
sions. Ombudsmen rely on their moral authority to have their recommenda-
tions accepted and their suggestions followed by the institutions that are the
object of their investigations. The authority of Ombudsmen is not inherent
to these institutions; it is directly linked to the moral authority of the office-
holders. For this reason, Ombudsmen need to maintain their impartiality
and independence, and to conform their actions to the highest ethical
standards to be able to ensure the effective functioning of their institution
and their credibility when addressing the shortcomings of other bodies.
This is why Ombudsmen, although usually appointed by a political body,
tend to be very cautious in trying not to politicize their institutions. An
Ombudsman perceived as politicized would lose moral authority over other
institutions and would simply become one of the many actors on the politi-
cal level.
15.3. The European Ombudsman
The European Ombudsman was established in 1992, at the same time as
European citizenship, with the Maastricht Treaty 4 to act as a bridge be-
tween the European Union (‘EU’) and its citizens. The first European Om-
2
Nicholas Copeland, “National Ombudsmen in the EU”, EPRS Library Briefing, 23 Septem-
ber 2010 (available on its web site).
3
Organisation for Economic Co-operation and Development (‘OECD’), “The Role of Om-
budsman Institutions in Open Government”, in OECD Working Paper on Public Govern-
ance, 2018, p. 12.
4
Treaty on European Union, 7 February 1992, 92/C 191/01, Article 138e (https://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/806147/).
5
European Ombudsman, Annual Report for 1997, 20 April 1998 (https://www.legal-tools.org/
doc/zu9e1m/).
6
Consolidated version of the Treaty on the Functioning of the European Union, 7 June 2016,
2016/C 202/01 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/15b8be/).
7
Decision of the European Parliament amending Decision 94/262/ECSC, EC, Euratom on the
regulations and general conditions governing the performance of the Ombudsman's duties,
18 June 2008, 2008/587/EC, Euratom (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/rkj24h/).
ies addressed the principle of integrity from the point of view of a conflict
of interest, as defined by the OECD, 14 and keeping in mind the distinction
between an apparent, potential and actual conflict of interest. 15
15.4.1. The So-Called Revolving Doors Phenomenon
The expression ‘revolving doors’ refers to the situation of EU civil servants
who leave the Union for a job in the private sector and of people joining
the Union from the private sector. While it is clearly legitimate for profes-
sionals working in the private or in the public sector to change their jobs,
the above situations present certain risks that the institutions have to keep
in mind when dealing with them.
In the case of former EU civil servants who move to the private sec-
tor, the risk is that they may use confidential information obtained while
working for the EU in their new positions. In addition, there is a concrete
risk that these individuals might take advantage of their contacts within EU
institutions to lobby, directly or indirectly, their former colleagues. When
workers join the Union from the private sector, the risk is that a conflict of
interest may arise in case they have to work on files which relate to their
previous employment.
In addition to the risks described above, the public might perceive
this movement of high-level civil servants from the Union to the private
sector as unethical, regardless of the behaviour of the individuals con-
cerned. Thus, in order to safeguard the public trust in the Union, it is of the
utmost importance to ensure that the procedures in place are effective and
that they are strictly followed.
The European Ombudsman, while always being conscious of the
fundamental right to work, 16 follows revolving doors situations very close-
ly, especially when they concern senior high-level staff of the EU.
In September 2016, the European Ombudsman took a decision on
two complaints submitted by a number of non-governmental organizations
concerning the European Commission’s handling of the revolving doors
phenomenon. 17 In the context of her inquiry, the Ombudsman issued rec-
14
OECD, Bribery in Public Procurement: Methods, Actors and Counter-Measures, OECD
Publishing, 2007, p. 33.
15
Code of Conduct for the European Ombudsman, see above note 13.
16
Charter of Fundamental Rights of the European Union, Article 15, see above note 1.
17
European Ombudsman, Decision of the European Ombudsman closing the inquiry based on
complaints 2077/2012/TN and 1853/2013/TN concerning the European Commission’s han-
20
Recommendations of the European Ombudsman in the joint inquiry into complaint
194/2017/EA, 334/2017/EA, and 543/2017/EA on the European Commission’s handling of
post-mandate employment of former Commissioners, a former Commission President and
the role of its ‘Ethics Committee’, 20 July 2018 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/eu1t29/).
21
European Union, Commission Decision of 31 January 2018 on a Code of Conduct for the
Members of the European Commission, 31 January 2018, Article 11 (https://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/dwjlw0/).
22
European Commission, Decision of 30 May 2016 establishing horizontal rules on the crea-
tion and operation of Commission expert groups, 30 May 2016, C (2016) 3301 final (https://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/fhziyq/); European Commission, Communication to the Commis-
sion Framework for Commission Expert Groups: Horizontal Rules and Public Register, 30
May 2016, C (2016) 3300 final (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/01v7ek/).
23
Emily O’Reilly, Introductory Address for a dialogue with the Civil Society Europe Annual
General Assembly, Brussels, 26 April 2018.
24
An overview of the Ombudsman’s solution proposal can be found in the Decision of the
European Ombudsman closing her inquiry into complaint 1682/2010/(ANA)BEH against
the European Commission, 19 December 2013, para. 144 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/
gx5bbj/).
25
Ibid.
26
European Ombudsman, “European Ombudsman launches public consultation concerning the
composition of European Commission expert groups”, 14 May 2014 (available on European
Ombudsman’s web site).
27
European Ombudsman, Recommendation of the European Ombudsman in her strategic
inquiry OI/6/2014/NF concerning the composition of Commission expert groups, 29 January
2016 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/uxi25m/).
the Commission had reformed the expert groups system and closed the in-
quiry considering that its purpose had been achieved. 28
15.4.3. Lobbying
Lobbying is an extremely delicate topic as the public might perceive the
fact that civil servants meet with interest representatives as inappropriate.
Citizens might thus question the integrity of the civil servants involved in
these meetings and consequently that of the institution that they represent.
At the same time, lobbying is an essential tool of our democracies, as seek-
ing the views of interest representatives allows policy-makers to receive
precious input, allowing them to better understand the practical conse-
quences of their decisions.
Lobbying activities are common and widespread in the Brussels’ re-
ality. The European Ombudsman has consistently maintained that transpar-
ent and well-regulated lobbying is an activity carried out in the public in-
terest, as it allows the EU administration to be informed of the global im-
pact of its proposed policies. 29 On the contrary, non-transparent lobbying is
a dangerous activity which might jeopardize the public trust in the Europe-
an Union’s institutions and should thus be avoided. Hence, it is evident that
it is of the utmost importance that civil servants behave in accordance with
the highest ethical standards when meeting with interest representatives.
In 2011, the European Commission and the Parliament set up the
Transparency Register to ensure public oversight on the activities of inter-
est representatives who meet with EU civil servants. While the Registry is
already a very advanced model, certain of its aspects would need further
improvement. In the framework of a public consultation launched by the
European Commission in 2016, the Ombudsman opened a ‘strategic initia-
tive’ to contribute to the debate. As a result, the Ombudsman made nine
suggestions to the Commission on how to further improve the Transparen-
cy Registry. 30 These suggestions concerned different issues such as making
the Registry common to all institutions and agencies, including information
28
European Ombudsman, Decision of the European Ombudsman in her strategic inquiry
OI/6/2014/NF concerning the composition and transparency of European Commission ex-
pert groups, 14 November 2017 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/6wn5vz/).
29
Emily O’Reilly, Address to Transparency International/EPACA conference, Brussels, 13
November 2019 (‘Introductory Speech’).
30
Emily O'Reilly, “Efforts to improve the EU Transparency Register”, 25 May 2016 (available
on European Ombudsman’s web site).
On Whistle-Blowing and
Inquiry in Public Institutions
Jan Fougner *
16.1. Introduction
Given that ensuring integrity in international justice is the desired end, the
predominant questions are which means are suitable to achieve such an end
and how must these institutions apply such means.
International justice institutions are ultimately defined by persons –
judges, prosecutors, administrative employees, bureaucrats, management et
al. – and the institutions must, therefore, establish a framework within
which these persons can avoid misconduct and pursue integrity. Further, in
the event of non-compliance within such a framework, impartial inquiries
should be considered a means through which one may hold the perpetrator
of misconduct responsible and thus re-establish integrity.
Whereas whistle-blowing may be conducive to eradicating miscon-
duct by introducing a culture of transparency, and freedom of expression
and from oppression, impartial inquiries may impede concealment, place
responsibility, and suggest effective measures to prevent future misconduct.
These two mechanisms, namely whistle-blowing and inquiries, represent
proactive and reactive approaches, symbiotically, inculcating the virtue of
integrity in an institution.
Both nationally and internationally, great efforts have been made to
ensure transparency and disclosure in order to drive us towards integrity.
Several countries have introduced new legislation on whistle-blowing, 1 and
*
Jan Fougner is Partner in the leading Norwegian law firm Wiersholm (whose employment
practice he leads), and Professor at BI Norwegian Business School. He has led a number of
high-profile inquiries involving problems of integrity (including in the police) and is an ex-
pert on whistle-blowing. He holds the Cand. jur. from the University of Oslo and a doctoral
degree from the University of Aarhus.
1
France, Loi relative à la transparence, à la lutte contre la corruption et à la modernisation de
la vie économique, 9 December 2016 (‘Sapin II’); Norway, Lov om arbeidsmiljø, arbeidstid
og stillingsvern m.v. (arbeidsmiljøloven) (Act relating to working environment, working
hours and employment protection, etc. (Working Environment Act)), 17 June 2005, Chapter
2A; UK Financial Conduct Authority, Accountability and Whistleblowing Instrument 2015,
surely, the EU Directive on this matter is a sign of progress. 2 For the same
reason, inquiries have been undertaken, for instance concerning the gov-
ernments’ implication in Iraq and Libya, 3 the Mueller investigation in the
United States (‘US’), the Sarkozy affair in France, 4 and the inquiries into
the Khashoggi affair and the North-Korean missile programme and facili-
ties. 5
It is conspicuous that the legislation on whistle-blowing and inquiries
do not pinpoint the judiciary as such. Even though some inquiries, such as
‘kids for cash’ in the US, suggest a certain interest in questions regarding
justice and corruption, one might wonder whether we perceive the judicial
system as being less flawed by corruption than other institutions. One
might ask whether the judiciary is per se transparent and righteous without
the same need to implement measures to safeguard integrity.
There are those challenging such a viewpoint. As an example, the In-
ternational Criminal Court (‘ICC’) has been confronted with stark criticism
regarding immoral behaviour (from both the Helsinki Committee, Bolton
and representatives of Burundi and the Philippines). An Independent Ex-
pert Review submitted a comprehensive, critical report on 30 September
24 September 2015; and EU, Protection of persons reporting on breaches of Union law, 16
April 2019.
2
See Directive (EU) 2019/1937 of the European Parliament and of the Council of 23 October
2019 on the protection of persons who report breaches of Union law, PE/78/2019/REV/1.
3
The UK and Norway, respectively.
4
For instance, the Libya investigation in Norway is an example of this purpose of an investi-
gation. A few years ago, the Norwegian Parliament asked the executive branch to initiate an
investigation of the Norwegian military as well as civilian participation in operations in Lib-
ya in 2011. More specifically, the purpose was to draw lessons from the participation in Lib-
ya as to how to improve future participation in international operations.
As for the Chilcot report concerning the United Kingdom’s participation in an opposed
invasion and full‑scale occupation of the sovereign State of Iraq, it was also aimed at en-
lightening the public and elucidating an event rather than causing prosecutions. The Chilcot
report concluded that the there was no “imminent threat from Saddam Hussein” and that by
supporting the war, the UK was in fact “undermining the Security Council’s authority”.
There is yet another example of such investigations, which is even more prominent: the
Mueller investigation in the US, assessing potential Russian meddling during the 2016 pres-
idential election race between Donald Trump and Hillary Clinton.
5
Deirdre Shesgreen, “North Korea running at least 13 secret operating bases for ballistic mis-
sile program, new study shows”, in USA Today, 12 November 2018.
6
See Independent Expert Review, Independent Expert Review of the International Criminal
Court and the Rome Statute System: Final Report, 30 September 2020 (https://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/cv19d5/).
7
RFI, “Burkina Faso: 37 magistrats épinglés pour des cas de corruption”, 9 July 2017.
8
The ‘Kids for cash’ scandal in Philadelphia and Brett Kavanaugh, who is now judge of the
Supreme Court.
9
Jacques Commaille, À quoi nous sert le droit ?, Gallimard, Paris, 2015, Introduction.
10
Edwin H. Sutherland, “White-Collar Criminality”, in American Sociological Review, 1940,
vol. 5, no. 1, pp. 1–12.
11
Donald J. Newman, “White-Collar Crime”, in Law and Contemporary Problems, 1958, vol.
23, no. 4, p. 738.
12
Sutherland, 1940, see above note 10.
13
“The History Of Whistleblowing in America”, in Whistleblowers International (available on
its web site).
14
United Nation Convention against Corruption, 31 October 2003, Preamble (‘UNCAC’)
(http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/7640fb/).
15
OECD, Study on Whistleblower Protection Frameworks, Compendium of Best Practices and
Guiding Principles for Legislation, 2011 (available on its web site).
16
UNCAC, see above note 14.
17
Natalie Christelis et al., in Petter Langseth (ed.), United Nations Handbook on Practical
Anti-Corruption Measures for Prosecutors and Investigators, UN Office on Drugs and
Crime, Vienna, September 2004, p. 75 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/zw3xvs/):
public inquiries into major disasters and scandals have shown that a workplace culture
of silence in the face of malpractices can cost hundreds of lives, damage thousands of
livelihoods, cause tens of thousands of jobs to be lost and undermine public confidence
in major institutions. In some cases, victims may be compensated but no one held ac-
countable for what has happened.
18
European Commission, “Whistleblower protection”, 23 April 2018.
19
Chapter 2A, see above note 1 (which is being revisited now).
20
Which established a robust regime of whistle-blower protections from unfair treatment that
went into effect in 2016, see above note 1.
21
Protection of persons reporting on breaches of Union law, see above note 1.
22
Janet P. Near and Marcia P. Miceli, “Organizational Dissidence: The Case of Whistle-
blowing”, in Journal of Business Ethics, 1985, vol. 4, no. 1, p. 4: “the disclosure by organi-
zation members of illegal, immoral or illegitimate practices under the control of their em-
ployers, to persons or organizations that may be able to effect action”; cited in Varslingsut-
valget, in Departementenes sikkerhets- og serviceorganisasjon (ed.), Varsling – verdier og
vern: Varslingsutvalgets utredning om varsling i arbeidslivet, Oslo, 2018, NOU 2018:6.
23
The concept was described by the term qui tam, which became “synonymous with whistle-
blowers who sue corrupt companies on behalf of their government”, see “The History Of
Whistleblowing in America”, see above note 13.
24
Marion A. Hersh, “Whistleblowers – heroes or traitors?: Individual and collective responsi-
bility for ethical behaviour”, in Annual Reviews in Control, 2002, vol. 26, no. 2, p. 243; ref-
erence to Kent D. Strader, “Counterclaims against Whistleblowers: Should Counterclaims
against Qui Tam Plaintiffs Be Allowed in False Claims Act Cases”, in University of Cincin-
nati Law Review, 1993, vol. 62, p. 713 (1 Hersh (2002), p. 243 with further reference to
Strader (1993)).
25
Erling Grimstad, Granskning: ved mistanke om korrupsjon og andre former for økonomisk
kriminalitet i arbeidsforhold, Gyldendal juridisk, 2015, p. 21.
16.3. How May Such Means Effectively Achieve the End of Inculcating
the Virtue of Integrity in Justice Institutions?
The implementation of whistle-blowing procedures depends on the will-
ingness of the institution to ensure these. In Norway, different governmen-
tal departments apply such procedures, including internal and external re-
porting channels and procedures for successive investigations. 26 These may
be employed in international justice systems as well.
It may be more challenging to institute inquiries because the revela-
tion of the course of events, the finding of a causal link between a phenom-
enon and an action, as well as the provision of an analysis of a problem in
the institution might generate a feeling of being under attack. Generally,
one should not throw caution to the wind and initiate external inquiries for
all misconduct. An employee’s minor misconduct should principally be
investigated internally. Inquiries by external parties are expensive and bur-
densome for those implied, but indeed a more powerful tool when used
correctly.
If the misconduct is serious and committed by a superior, inquiries
by external experts will usually be more fitting. The superior will be dis-
qualified as partial and any direct subordinate in the same administration
must, based on the general notion on impartiality, 27 usually be considered
partial as well. Hence, if a superior has engaged in misconduct, all of the
subordinates are, in a legal context, partial and inquiries by external parties
seem like the most suitable approach.
Additionally, the psychological factor of feeling under attack must be
taken seriously. Gross misconduct committed by a superior will usually be
26
The Ministry of Foreign Affairs, Norway, and now the Ministries of Justice and of Customs
follow.
27
This notion derives from, among others, the International Covenant on Civil and Political
Rights, 16 December 1966, which in its Article 14(1) states that “all persons shall be equal
before the courts and tribunals”, and that “in the determination of any criminal charge
against him, or of his rights and obligations in a suit of law, everyone shall be entitled to a
fair and public hearing by a competent, independent and impartial tribunal established by
law” (emphasis added) (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/2838f3/). The UN Human Rights
Committee has unambiguously held the same, as well as the African Charter on Human and
Peoples’ Rights, 21 October 1986, Article 7(1) (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/f0db44/), and
the American Convention on Human Rights, 22 November 1969, Article 8(1) (http://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/1152cf/). Lastly, this is specified in Article 6(1) of the European
Convention on Human Rights, 4 November 1950 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/8267cb/),
as well as in the Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court, 17 July 1998, Article
36(3)(a) (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/7b9af9/).
28
European Convention on Human Rights, Article 5, see above note 27.
29
Ibid., Article 6.
30
Ibid.
31
Ibid., Article 8. See also the International Covenant on Civil and Political rights.
32
Norway, Advokatforeningens retningslinjer for private granskninger, 4 March 2011, part 2,
sections 3.2, 5.1, 5.2, 6 and 6.3 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/kn9t3j/).
Court has a duty to fight abuse of power, corruption and misconduct be-
cause it is a guardian of freedom from harm against fundamental common
values. Remembering the Machiavellian maxim, whistle-blowing mecha-
nisms, as well as impartial and independent inquiries, may impede absolute
power and therefore hinder corruption, ultimately establishing, or re-
establishing, the virtue of integrity.
17.1. Introduction
Private investigators have always created a certain admiration and fascina-
tion. In fact, informed by famous writers such a Sir Arthur Conan Doyle, in
the eyes of their readers – and the public in general – private investigators
are the real heroes of crime novels, usually solving a case that eventually
brings fame not to themselves but to the police detective they are working
with. Thus, Inspector Lestrade has Sherlock Holmes and Leland Stot-
telmeyer has Adrian Monk. Not to forget all those private investigators who
generally assist the local police, such as Jane Marple and Hercule Poirot.
And then there are those who conduct ‘investigations’ in a broad sense,
even though it seems counter-intuitive to classify them as private investiga-
tors: Bruce Wayne aka Batman; John Shaft; the A-Team; Christian Wolff
aka “The Accountant”; Tintin, the young Belgian reporter; Mikael
Blomkvist, journalist and the main character in Stieg Larsson’s Millennium
series; and April O’Neil, anchor-woman for Channel 6 News in the 1987-
1996 animated Teenage Mutant Ninja Turtles series.
The appeal of private investigations has now reached the field of in-
ternational criminal justice. For instance, the work of the Commission for
International Justice and Accountability (‘CIJA’) has attracted some atten-
tion, also in connection with recent universal jurisdiction cases concerning
Syria. Of course, investigatory work done by private non-State agencies is
*
Alexander Heinze is an Assistant Professor of Law at the University of Göttingen, Germany.
He holds a Ph.D. in International Criminal Law (with honours), received his Master’s in In-
ternational and Comparative Law from Trinity College Dublin, Ireland, with distinction and
published various papers on topics such as international criminal law and procedure, media
law, comparative criminal law, human rights law and jurisprudence. His book International
Criminal Procedure and Disclosure (Duncker & Humblot, 2014) won three awards. He is a
member of the ILA’s Committee on Complementarity in ICL, co-editor of the German Law
Journal, book review editor of the Criminal Law Forum, and worked for the Appeals
Chamber of the ICC as a visiting professional. The author would like to thank the editors for
their valuable comments.
behaviour by their most important aids. At most, they refer to their supervi-
sion and the fact that all witness statements have to be repeated in front of
them anyway, let alone that evidence collected by private investigators is
merely used as lead evidence. Yet, once the cooperation between an ICT
and private individuals 4 in the collection of evidence becomes public,
which is usually the case when something went wrong, reality speaks a dif-
ferent language. In the Lubanga case before the ICC, the suspicion arose
that certain so-called intermediaries had bribed various persons to prepare
false evidence for alleged former child soldiers. In another instance, in the
same case, the Office of the Prosecutor (‘OTP’) was supposed to use cer-
tain material as lead evidence only, but did the opposite.
This chapter is about these instances; it is about illegal conduct of
private investigators; and it is eventually about the proposal of a compass
for private investigators.
The chapter is structured into four main sections. It starts with a
stocktaking endeavour, describing the occurrence of private investigations
in the former Yugoslavia and Rwanda, in Kosovo, Sierra Leone, Cambodia
and, especially, Syria (17.2.). Following a brief delineation of the ad-
vantages of private investigations (17.3.) and some terminological remarks
(17.4.), the focus turns to the main section on private investigations as a
matter of ethics and integrity (17.5.).
The chapter will demonstrate that the idea of the ‘integrity’ or ‘legit-
imacy’ of the trial as a distinctive kind of legal process can serve as an im-
portant, if not the only compass for private conduct in the collection of evi-
dence. Concretely, let us suppose a private investigator offers money to a
witness in return for information about a suspect and his or her criminal
activities. 5 After all, it has become public that the OTP of the Special Court
for Sierra Leone had an extensive practice of paying both informants and
4
I prefer the term ‘individual’ over ‘actor’, since the focus of this chapter is on private con-
duct. I use the term ‘actors’ to describe agents acting for or on behalf of certain institutions
and organisations. Individual actors – or individuals – have the ability to act reflexively but
in doing so “they are significantly constrained by the structures in which they operate” (Ne-
rida Chazal, The International Criminal Court and Global Social Control, Routledge Taylor
& Francis, Abingdon, 2016, p. 4).
5
Other examples, convened by Robertson for the context of interviews: leading questions,
“brainwashing” the witness, persuasion, the private investigator is a national of the State un-
der investigation, see Geoffrey Robertson, “Human Rights Fact-Finding: Some Legal and
Ethical Dilemmas”, in Morten Bergsmo and Carsten Stahn (eds.), Quality Control in Fact-
Finding, second edition, TOAEP, Brussels, 2020, pp. 491–507.
6
In detail the eye-opening account of Wayne Jordash, “Insiders: The Special Court for Sierra
Leone’s Dirty Laundry”, Justiceinfo.net, 30 April 2020.
7
About the semantic difference between those two in more detail, albeit misleadingly de-
scribed as “linguistics”, Dimitrios Giannoulopoulos, Improperly Obtained Evidence in An-
glo-American and Continental Law, Hart, Oxford, 2019, pp. 6–7.
8
Sabine Gless and Laura Macula, “Exclusionary Rules – Is It Time For Change?”, in IUS
Gentium, 2019, vol. 74, p. 349 (350).
9
Bergsmo and Wiley, 2008, p. 9, see above note 1.
10
Mark S. Ellis, “The contribution of non-governmental organizations to the creation of inter-
national criminal tribunals”, in Bartram S. Brown (ed.), Research Handbook on Internation-
al Criminal Law, Edward Elgar, Cheltenham, 2011, p. 143 (156).
11
De Vries, 2019, p. 602, see above note 1.
12
Ellis, 2011, p. 143, see above note 10. See also William Korey, NGOs and the Universal
Declaration of Human Rights, Palgrave, New York, 1998, p. 320: “[HRW] had at least one
or more staffers present in Bosnia and other parts of Former Yugoslavia throughout all of
1992 and 1993. These virtually full-time representatives of the New York-based NGO had
maintained contacts with local human rights activists and a variety of sources within the var-
ious levels of governments and media in the area”.
13
Emma Daly, “Beyond Justice: How the Yugoslav Tribunal Made History”, in Human Rights
Watch, 19 December 2017 (available on its web site). See also Ellis, 2011, p. 143, see above
note 10.
14
Human Rights Watch, “War Crimes in Bosnia-Hercegovina”, 1 August 1992 (available on
its web site).
15
Daly, 2017, see above note 13.
16
Ellis, 2011, p. 143, see above note 10; Korey, 1998, p. 322, see above note 12.
17
Helsinki Watch, Prosecute Now!, 1 August 1993.
18
Ellis, 2011, p. 144, see above note 10.
19
Korey, 1998, p. 325, see above note 12.
20
Physicians for Human Rights (‘PHR’), “Bosnian Serb Commander Ratko Mladic Convicted
of Genocide, War Crimes, Crimes Against Humanity”, 22 November 2017 (available on its
web site).
21
PHR, “Mass Grave Investigations | Mass Crimes in Srebrenica”, undated (available on its
web site).
17.2.1.2. Kosovo
In Kosovo, too, evidence about the forced expulsion, arbitrary killings, tor-
ture and sexual assault of the Albanians was gathered by NGOs. 26 Journal-
ists and human rights researchers have investigated, documented and re-
ported many individual accounts of human rights violations taking place in
Kosovo. 27
PHR and the Program on Forced Migration and Health of Columbia
University’s Joseph L. Mailman School of Public Health designed a study
to “establish patterns of human rights violations among Kosovar refugees
by Serb forces using a population-based approach”. 28 The study “randomly
22
Ellis, 2011, p. 156, see above note 10.
23
PHR, “Forensic science is applied in nearly every area of our work and is crucial to docu-
ment mass crimes”, undated (available on its web site).
24
In the same vein, see Hassan B. Jallow, “Challenges of Investigating and Prosecuting Inter-
national Crimes”, in Emmanuel Decaux, Adama Dieng and Malick Sow (eds.), From Hu-
man Rights to International Criminal Law, Martinus Nijhoff, Leiden, Boston, 2007, p. 437
(438).
25
Ibid., p. 438.
26
Ellis, 2011, p. 156, see above note 10.
27
PHR, “War Crimes in Kosovo – A Population-Based Assessment of Human Rights Violation
Against Kosovar Albanians”, 1 August 1999, p. 1 (available on its web site).
28
Ibid.
29
Ibid.
30
Ellis, 2011, p. 156, see above note 10.
31
See, for instance, American Bar Association and Central and East European Law Initiative
(‘ABA-CEELI’), An Introduction to the Human Trafficking Assessment Tool, December
2005 (available on its web site). See also Ellis, 2011, p. 156, see above note 10.
32
ABA-CEELI, American Association for the Advancement of Science (‘AAAS’), Political
Killings in Kosova/Kosovo, March-June 1999, 2000, p. xi (available on its web site).
33
Ellis, 2011, p. 157, see above note 10; ABA-CEELI, AAAS, 2000, p. xi, see above note 32.
34
Ibid.
35
See Human Rights Data Analysis Group (‘HRDAG’), “Kosovo” (available on its web
sitehttps://hrdag.org/kosovo/).
36
Ellis, 2011, p. 157, see above note 10.
13,627”. 37 This analysis was used by the ICTY-OTP in the trial of Slo-
bodan Milošević to refute the argument that the killings were simply a con-
sequence of battles between the Kosovo Liberation Army and Serbian forc-
es. 38
17.2.1.3. Sierra Leone, Cambodia, Liberia, MH17
In Sierra Leone, No Peace Without Justice (‘NPWJ’) initiated a Conflict
Mapping Program, namely
the reconstruction of the chain of events during the ten-year
war through the scrupulous selection and debriefing of key in-
dividuals throughout the country whose profession, role in
their community or in the forces involved in the conflict,
placed them in a position to follow events as they unfolded. 39
NPWJ’s analysis was “based on testimonial and other data overlaid with
order of battle and command structures of the various forces as they
evolved over time and space”. 40 The mapping aimed at establishing the
“chain of command within the armed forces operating in Sierra Leone and
assembling these disparate pieces of information to create the bigger pic-
ture of the decade-long conflict in Sierra Leone” to demonstrate “direct and
command responsibility for crimes committed during the conflict”. 41
As in Kosovo, in 1999, the ABA established a Sierra Leone War
Crimes Documentation Project aimed at contributing to the documentation
of the war crimes committed in Sierra Leone between 1991 and 2002, and,
37
ABA-CEELI, AAAS, 2000, p. xi, see above note 32.
38
The International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia (‘ICTY’), Prosecutor v. Slo-
bodan Milosevic, Transcript, IT-02-54, 14 March 2002, p. 2256:
During the break, I checked some assertions that you denied, and I would like to ask you
a few questions about this. Namely, I asked about your cooperation and adjustment of
data to the data of the International Crisis Group, and you said that was not true. How-
ever, on the website of your AAA association, and that is website
hrdataaas.org/kosovo/index/html [as interpreted], titled “Political Killings in Kosovo
from March to June 1999,” in the column called “Statistical Analysis of Data,” it says:
The method of killing people in Kosovo coincides with migrations, and this claim corre-
sponds to the data obtained from the International Crisis Group; and then others are
enumerated as well.
39
No Peace Without Justice (‘NPWJ’), “Conflict Mapping in Sierra Leone: Violations of In-
ternational Humanitarian Law 1991 to 2002”, Preface, p. III (available on its web site).
40
Ibid., p. VII.
41
Ibid., p. VIII.
42
AAAS, “Partnership 8: Surveying Human Rights Abuses in Sierra Leone” (available on its
web site).
43
See International Crisis Group, Reality Demands: Documenting Violations of International
Humanitarian Law in Kosovo 1999, 27 June 2000 (available on its web site); Ellis, 2011,
p. 157, see above note 10.
44
See Documentation Centre of Cambodia, “Documentation” (available on its web site).
45
See Civitas Maxima, “Our Work” (available on its web site).
46
See Bellingcat, “Key MH17 Figure Identified As Senior FSB Official: Colonel General An-
drey Burlaka”, 28 April 2020 (available on its web site).
47
See Organisation for the Prohibition of Chemical Weapons, “Fact-Finding Mission” (availa-
ble on its web site). In more detail Rebecca Barber, “Uniting for Peace Not Aggression: Re-
sponding to Chemical Weapons in Syria Without Breaking the Law”, in Journal of Conflict
and Security Law, 2018, vol. 24, no. 1, p. 74.
48
Organisation for the Prohibition of Chemical Weapons, Addressing the threat from Chemical
Weapons Use, 27 June 2018, C-SS-4/DEC.3, para. 10 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/
lmqyd4/).
49
Ingrid Elliott, “‘A Meaningful Step towards Accountability’? A View from the Field on the
United Nations International, Impartial and Independent Mechanism for Syria”, in Journal
of International Criminal Justice, 2017, vol. 15, no. 2, p. 240; Michael P. Scharf, Milena
Sterio, and Paul R. Williams, The Syrian Conflict’s Impact on International Law, Cambridge
University Press, Cambridge, 2020, pp. 4 ff.
50
United Nations General Assembly, International, Impartial and Independent Mechanism to
Assist in the Investigation and Prosecution of Those Responsible for the Most Serious
Crimes under International Law Committed in the Syrian Arab Republic since March 2011,
UN Doc. A/RES/71/248, 11 January 2017 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/fecaf0/). See al-
so Christian Wenaweser and James Cockayne, “Justice for Syria? The International, Impar-
tial and Independent Mechanism and the Emergence of the UN General Assembly in the
Realm of International Criminal Justice”, in Journal of International Criminal Justice, 2017,
vol. 15, no. 2, pp. 211–230; Elliott, 2017, pp. 239–256, see above note 49; Alex Whiting,
“An Investigation Mechanism for Syria. The General Assembly Steps into the Breach”, in
Journal of International Criminal Justice, 2017, vol. 15, no. 2, pp. 231–237.
51
United Nations General Assembly, Implementation of the resolution establishing the Inter-
national, Impartial and Independent Mechanism to Assist in the Investigation and Prosecu-
tion of Persons Responsible for the Most Serious Crimes under International Law Commit-
ted in the Syrian Arab Republic since March 2011, UN Doc. A/71/755, 19 January 2017
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/a0cd85/). See also Elliott, 2017, pp. 239–256, see above
note 49.
52
United Nations, “Secretary-General appoints Catherine Marchi-Uhel of France to head In-
ternational Impartial Independent Mechanism Investigating Serious Crimes in Syria”, 3 July
2017, SG/A/1744-BIO/4979-DC/3720 (available on the UN’s web site); Nick Cumming-
Bruce, “Ex-judge chosen by U.N. to Gather Evidence of Syria War Crimes”, The New York
Times, 4 July 2017.
53
An instructive overview can be found on the UN Human Rights Council’s website: https://
www.ohchr.org/EN/HRBodies/HRC/Pages/COIs.aspx.
54
Sareta Ashraph and Federica D’Alessandra, “Structural Challenges Confronted by UN Ac-
countability Mandates: Perspectives from Current and Former Staff (Part II)”, OpinioJuris,
14 October 2020.
55
Michelle Burgis-Kasthala, “Entrepreneurial Justice: Syria, the Commission for International
Justice and Accountability and the Renewal of International Criminal Justice”, in European
Journal of International Law, 2020, vol. 30, no. 4, pp. 1174 ff. with a very detailed and in-
structive account of CIJA, its protagonists and work on pp. 1176 ff.
56
Melinda Rankin, “Investigating Crimes against Humanity in Syria and Iraq: The Commis-
sion for International Justice and Accountability”, in Global Responsibility to Protect, 2017,
vol. 9, no. 4, pp. 400–401.
57
Elliott, 2017, p. 245, see above note 49.
58
Ibid.
59
Bergsmo and Wiley, 2008, p. 4, see above note 1.
60
ICC Office of the Prosecutor (‘OTP’), Strategic Plan 2016-2018, 16 November 2015, p. 20
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/2dbc2d/).
61
Stressing its importance: Nikita Mehandru and Alexa Koenig, “ICTs, Social Media & the
Future of Human Rights”, in Duke Law & Technology Review, 2019, vol. 17, no. 1, pp. 129–
145; for a nuanced and differentiated account, weighing advantages and risks of open source
information in international fact finding, see Yvonne McDermott, Daragh Murray and Alexa
Koenig, “Digital Accountability Symposium: Whose Stories Get Told, and by Whom? Rep-
resentativeness in Open Source Human Rights Investigations”, OpinioJuris, 19 December
2019. The authors are part of a larger team that initiated the project “Using open source re-
search to transform the discovery and documentation of Human Rights Violations”, see
OSR4Rights, “Using open source research to transform the discovery and documentation of
Human Rights Violations” (available on its web site).
62
ICC OTP, Strategic Plan 2019-2021, 17 July 2019 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/7ncqt3/).
63
ICC OTP, 2015, p. 21, see above note 60.
64
ICC OTP, 2019, p. 21, see above note 62.
65
Bergsmo and Wiley, 2008, pp. 12–13, see above note 1.
66
Ibid., p. 8.
67
Seema Kassab, “Justice in Syria: Individual Criminal Liability for Highest Officials in the
Assad Regime”, in Michigan Journal of International Law, 2018, vol. 39, no. 2, p. 283
(287); Elliott, 2017, p. 239, see above note 49.
68
Kassab, 2018, p. 287, see above note 67.
69
See Chris Engels, Written Testimony before the Commission on Security and Cooperation in
Europe, 22 September 2016; Elliott, 2017, p. 245, see above note 49.
70
See Jörg Diehl, Christoph Reuter, and Fidelius Schmid, “Die Jagd”, in Der Spiegel, 8 June
2018, pp. 40–42; Boris Burghardt, “Endlich! – Erster Haftbefehl gegen einen ranghohen
Vertreter des syrischen Assad-Regimes”, in Völkerrechtsblog, 11 June 2018.
71
Generalbundesanwalt, “Anklage gegen zwei mutmaßliche Mitarbeiter des syrischen Ge-
heimdienstes wegen der Begehung von Verbrechen gegen die Menschlichkeit u.a. erhoben”,
29 October 2019 (available on its web site). See also Philip Oltermann and Emma Graham-
Harrison, “Germany charges two Syrians with crimes against humanity”, The Guardian, 29
October 2019 (available on its web site).
72
See European Center for Constitutional and Human Rights (‘ECCHR’), “Who we are”
(available on its web site).
73
ECCHR, “With the Frist Criminal Trial Worldwide on Torture in Syria, German Courts to
Set International Precedent”, 29 October 2019 (available on its web site).
74
Oberlandesgericht Koblenz, Beschluss v. 6.3.2020, 1 StE 9/19.
75
See, for instance, Amnesty International, “Syria: Torture trial in Germany a ‘historic step’
towards justice”, 22 April 2020. See the instructive comment of Elisabeth Baier, “A puzzle
coming together – The henchmen of Assad’s torture regime on trial in Germany”, in Völker-
rechtsblog, 23 April 2020.
76
See the recent account of Christian Ritscher, “Aktuelle Entwicklung in der Strafverfolgung
des Generalbundesanwalts auf dem Gebiet des Völkerstrafrechts”, in Zeitschrift für Interna-
tionale Strafrechtsdogmatik, 2019, pp. 599 ff.
77
ECCHR, Universal Jurisdiction in Germany? – The Congo War Crimes Trial: First Case
under the Code of Crimes against International Law, 8 June 2016, p. 7 (available on its web
site).
78
Cf. Christian Ritscher, “‘Foreign Fighters’ und Kriegsvölkerstrafrecht”, in Zeitschrift für
Internationale Strafrechtsdogmatik, 2016, vol. 11, pp. 807 (807 f.); Ritscher, 2019, p. 600,
see above note 76; Kai Ambos, Internationales Strafrecht, fifth edition, C.H. Beck, Mün-
chen, 2018, § 6 mn. 40.
79
See Sara Afshar, “Assad’s Syria recorded its own atrocities. The world can’t ignore them”,
The Guardian, 27 August 2018; Ritscher, 2019, p. 600, see above note 76.
80
See Nick Cumming-Bruce, “Germany Arrests Syrian Intelligence Officers Accused of
Crimes Against Humanity”, The New York Times, 13 February 2019.
81
See Diehl, Reuter and Schmid, 2018, p. 41, see above note 70.
82
Nerma Jelačić, “Tweet”, Twitter, 13 February 2019.
83
Reported in Kristin Helberg, “Der Kriegsverbrecher Assad gehört vor Gericht”, Zeit Online,
28 November 2016.
84
Ibid.
85
Ibid.
86
Ben Taub, “The Assad Files”, The New Yorker, 18 April 2016 (available on its web site). See
also Kassab, 2018, p. 289, see above note 67.
87
Alexander Heinze, “Private International Criminal Investigations”, in Zeitschrift für interna-
tionale Strafrechtsdogmatik, 2019, pp. 173–174.
88
Ibid., p. 174.
89
Martin Gill and Jerry Hart, “Exploring Investigative Policing: A Study of Private Detectives
in Britain”, in The British Journal of Criminology, 1997, vol. 37, no. 4, p. 550 with fn. 1.
90
Ibid.
snail mail and email communication, and of phone conversations; and the
audio-visual observation of the work place. 98 Internal investigators regular-
ly even conduct ‘interviews’ with employees of the company. 99 The list of
those resembling activities – store detectives, solicitors and even psychics –
is long. 100 George and Button, therefore, use a more complex definition,
reproduced by Johnston: private investigators are
[i]ndividuals (whether in house or contract) and firms (other
than public enforcement bodies) who offer services related to
the obtaining, selling or supplying of any information relating
to the identity, conduct, movements, whereabouts, associa-
tions, transactions or character of any person, groups of per-
sons or association, or of any other type of organization. 101
The narrowest definition would reduce private investigators to “work either
for the victim or for the defendant or his attorney in criminal proceed-
ings”. 102 Dörmann provides a slightly broader definition:
Usually, private investigators working in the criminal justice
field do so on behalf of the defence, checking the accuracy of
police evidence and looking for witnesses who might under-
mine the case for the prosecution. By contrast, criminal inves-
tigations for private companies usually aim to establish the
causes of loss and of any guilt associated with such loss. 103
The difficulty to define the term ‘private investigator’ or ‘private in-
vestigations’ is increased on the international level. Here, too, many actors
carry out the work of investigators, such as journalists or the media in gen-
eral, as the above-mentioned ‘Caesar’ photos illustrate. 104 But even when
the term ‘private investigator’ is narrowed down to IGOs or NGOs, the na-
ture of these organisations is often unclear. Thus, any definition would be
arbitrary. 105 The only suggestion I would make is to dispense of the term
‘private’, since it is too broad and seems to be rather occupied by a domes-
tic understanding. I also recommend avoiding the term ‘human rights’,
since agencies such as CIJA do investigative work without human rights
monitoring. Therefore, the best term to use would therefore be ‘third party
investigations’, which goes back to Bergsmo and Wiley’s description of
personnel “not serving with a belligerent party”. 106
17.5. Private Investigations: A Matter of Ethics and Integrity
17.5.1. The Ethical Problem with Private Investigations
Lawyers are expected to abide by laws, professional rules, and informal
professional norms, and in many jurisdictions, they are also required to
abide by a professional code of conduct. 107 Professional legal ethics in-
volve recognising that lawyers are often confronted with ethical dilemmas.
Criminal lawyers, in particular, face “conflicting values, aims and inter-
ests”. 108 They are expected, however, to separate the “morality of the[ir]
representation” from the “morality of the client’s cause”. 109 A criminal
lawyer is expected to vigorously argue for her side of the case, whether as a
defence lawyer or a prosecution lawyer, and whether or not she thinks that
she in fact has the most compelling argument. But this vigour remains lim-
ited by ethical constraints, such as the moral requirement to respect the
dignity of all persons involved in a criminal trial, and the moral prohibition
of lying to advance a client’s interests. While a defence lawyer may have
less control over criminal justice proceedings other than determining how
best to advocate for his client, a prosecutor has additional ethical obliga-
105
In the same vein for the national level, see Johnston, 2007, p. 278, see above note 93.
106
Bergsmo and Wiley, 2008, p. 12, see above note 1.
107
See Donald Nicolson, “Making Lawyers Moral? Ethical Codes and Moral Character”, in
Legal Studies, 2005, vol. 25, no. 4, pp. 601–26; Liz Campbell, Andrew Ashworth and Mike
Redmayne, The Criminal Process, fifth edition, Oxford University Press, 2019, pp. 60 ff.
108
Richard Young and Andrew Sanders, “The Ethics of Prosecution Lawyers”, in Legal Ethics,
2004, vol. 7, no. 2, pp. 190–209.
109
David Luban, Legal Ethics and Human Dignity, Cambridge University Press, 2007, p. 20.
tions due to her ability to select defendants for trial and determine the
scope of the criminal justice process. 110
The normative foundations of prosecutorial ethics consist of two
main concepts: a prosecutor’s general duty to seek justice, 111 and the moral
theories that inform the corresponding, specific ethical obligations of the
prosecutor. In both adversarial and inquisitorial systems of law, 112 regard-
less of other specific duties, the prosecutor is expected to seek justice. 113
While the particular features of what constitutes justice vary between, and
sometimes within, criminal legal systems, it is always tied to the concept of
fairness. 114
110
This of course applies more to the criminal justice process in the legal tradition of the com-
mon law than to a civil law criminal process, cf. Alexander Heinze, International Criminal
Procedure and Disclosure, Duncker & Humblot, Berlin, 2014, pp. 107 ff. See also Alexan-
der Heinze and Shannon Fyfe, “Prosecutorial Ethics and Preliminary Examinations at the
ICC”, in Morten Bergsmo and Carsten Stahn (eds.), Quality Control in Preliminary Exami-
nation: Volume 2, Torkel Opsahl Academic EPublisher (‘TOAEP’), Brussels, 2018, pp. 5–6
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/dff594/).
111
See Fred C. Zacharias, “Structuring the Ethics of Prosecutorial Trial Practice: Can Prosecu-
tors Do Justice?”, in Vanderbilt Law Review, 1991, vol. 44, no. 1, pp. 45 ff.
112
About the meaning of terms ‘inquisitorial’ and ‘adversarial’ in more detail, see Heinze, 2014,
pp. 117 ff., see above note 110; Kai Ambos and Alexander Heinze, “Abbreviated Procedures
in Comparative Criminal Procedure: A Structural Approach with a View to International
Criminal Procedure”, in Morten Bergsmo (ed.), Abbreviated Criminal Procedures for Core
International Crimes, TOAEP, Brussels, 2017, pp. 27, 28 ff. (https://www.toaep.org/ps-pdf/
9-bergsmo).
113
Shawn Marie Boyne, The German Prosecution Service: Guardians of the Law, Springer,
Berlin, Heidelberg, 2014, p. 5 (“[P]rosecutors possess an ethical obligation to pursue jus-
tice”). The fact that the search for truth in inquisitorial systems is a constitutive feature
(Heinze, 2014, p. 107, see above note 110) does not render justice as an ethical obligation of
the prosecutor less relevant. In inquisitorial systems too truth is a means to the end of justice,
as Karl Peters famously pointed out in his seminal work about the German criminal process
(Karl Peters, Strafprozeß, C.F. Müller, Heidelberg, 1985, p. 82 (“Das Strafverfahren kann
das Ziel der Gerechtigkeit nur erreichen, wenn es die Wahrheit findet”).) In the same vein,
see Theodore L. Kubicek, Adversarial Justice: America’s Court System on Trial, Algora,
New York, 2006, p. 37 with further references. See also Barton L. Ingraham, The Structure
of Criminal Procedure, Greenwood Press, New York et al., 1987, p. 13.
114
See, for example, ICC, Situation in the Democratic Republic of the Congo, The Prosecutor v.
Thomas Lubanga Dyilo, Appeals Chamber, Judgment on the Appeal of Mr. Thomas Luban-
ga Dyilo against the Decision on the Defence Challenge to the Jurisdiction of the Court pur-
suant to article 19 (2) (a) of the Statute of 3 October 2006, 14 December 2006, ICC-01/04-
01/06-772, para. 37 (‘Lubanga, 2006’) (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/1505f7/): “Where
fair trial becomes impossible because of breaches of the fundamental rights of the suspect or
the accused by his/her accusers, it would be a contradiction in terms to put the person on tri-
al. Justice could not be done. A fair trial is the only means to do justice. If no fair trial can be
held, the object of the judicial process is frustrated and the process must be stopped”. See al-
so Catherine S. Namakula, “The Human Rights Mandate of a Prosecutor of an International
Criminal Trial”, in International Criminal Law Review, 2017, vol. 17, no. 5, pp. 935, 936.
About the meaning of fairness in that context Heinze and Fyfe, 2018, pp. 6–8, see above
note 110.
115
Allison M. Danner, “Enhancing the Legitimacy and Accountability of Prosecutorial Discre-
tion at the International Criminal Court”, in The American Journal of International Law,
2003, vol. 97, no. 3, pp. 536–37.
116
Nicolson, 2005, p. 606, see above note 107.
117
Daniel Markovits, A Modern Legal Ethics: Adversary Advocacy in a Democratic Age,
Princeton University Press, New York, 2010, p. 7.
118
Heinze and Fyfe, “The Role of the Prosecutor”, in Kai Ambos et al. (eds.), Core Concepts in
Criminal Law and Justice, vol. 1, Cambridge University Press, 2020, pp. 344 ff.; Heinze and
Fyfe, 2018, pp. 3 ff., see above note 110.
119
Bergsmo and Wiley, 2008, p. 2, see above note 1.
120
A definition of human rights monitoring is provided in Anette Faye Jacobsen (ed.), Human
Rights Monitoring, Martinus Nijhoff, Leiden, Boston, 2008, p. 1:
advocacy. 121 The problem lies in entities, such as CIJA, which do mainly
investigatory work and have donors at the same time. 122 Here, concerns
about the substantive outcomes of investigations and criminal trials, the
overall performance or record of an investigator or prosecutor, or the social
and political impacts of criminal trials, will likely involve more consequen-
tialist considerations. 123 From a psychological perspective, competition in
that sense regularly leads to role-induced bias or what Simon et al. labelled
the “myside bias”. 124
This is most visible at the national level. In meeting the needs of
their clients, private investigators pursue instrumental ends. 125 As Johnston
describes:
Unlike police detectives, who collect evidence for construct-
ing cases within a system of public justice, private investiga-
tors aim only to minimize the economic, social or personal
losses of their clients. Instrumentalism is driven by a proactive,
risk-based mentality, the object of which is to anticipate, rec-
Human rights monitoring can be defined as the systematic collection, verification, and
use of information to address human rights problems or compliances. The compiled data
will have to be analyzed against agreed standards. These standards primarily entail the
human rights obligations and commitments that the State is a party to, and thus has
committed itself to live up to; as well as additional human rights provisions which have
come to be recognized as customary law applicable to all authorities regardless of the
State’s formal acknowledgement […].
121
Bergsmo and Wiley, 2008, p. 2, see above note 1.
122
See also Burgis-Kasthala, 2020, p. 1173, see above note 55.
123
Frédéric Mégret, “International Prosecutors: Accountability and Ethics”, in Leuven Centre
for Global Governance Studies, Working Paper No. 18, 2008, p. 8. Surely, consequentialist
considerations also play an important role in prosecutorial decision making, especially at the
ICC, as I have argued – together with Kai Ambos – in amicus curiae observation, see ICC,
Situation in the Islamic Republic of Afghanistan, Written Submissions in the Proceedings
Relating to the Appeals Filed Against the “Decision Pursuant to Article 15 of the Rome
Statute on the Authorisation of an Investigation into the Situation in the Islamic Republic of
Afghanistan” Issued on 12 April 2019 (ICC-02/17-33) and Pursuant to “Decision on the par-
ticipation of amici curiae, the Office of Public Counsel for the Defence and the cross-border
victims” Issued on 14 October 2019 (ICC-02/17-97), 14 November 2019, Ambos and Heinze,
ICC-02/17-108 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/5v8d2b/) and Annex (https://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/7m3bj2/).
124
Dan Simon et al., “The Adversarial Mindset”, in Psychology, Public Policy, and Law, 2020,
vol. 26, pp. 354 ff.
125
Johnston, 2007, p. 280, see above note 93.
ognize and appraise risks and, having done so, to initiate ac-
tions that will help to minimize their impact on clients. 126
Prenzler, in his previously mentioned study, found that “the large majority
[of interviewees] also felt that anecdotal reports of misconduct were of suf-
ficient gravity to justify greater control and scrutiny of the industry by gov-
ernment”. 127 The investigators he interviewed particularly nominated “pri-
vacy as the area where their profession posed the greatest danger to the
public”. 128 Privacy is especially problematic in the case of social media
evidence. Take, for instance, the investigations in Myanmar, where the
Human Rights Council recently created another investigative mecha-
nism. 129 Human Rights Council resolution 34/22 mandated the Mission
to establish the facts and circumstances of the alleged recent
human rights violations by military and security forces, and
abuses, in Myanmar, in particular in Rakhine State, including
but not limited to arbitrary detention, torture and inhuman
treatment, rape and other forms of sexual violence, extrajudi-
cial, summary or arbitrary killings, enforced disappearances,
forced displacement and unlawful destruction of property,
with a view to ensuring full accountability for perpetrators and
justice for victims. 130
126
Ibid.
127
Prenzler, 2001, p. 6, see above note 92.
128
Ibid., p. 36.
129
Global Justice Center, “Statement on the Creation of the IIIM for Myanmar”, press release,
27 September 2018 (available on its web site); International Commission of Jurists, “My-
anmar: creation of UN mechanism a step toward accountability”, 27 September 2018
(available on its web site). See generally Neriah Yue, “The ‘Weaponization’ of Facebook in
Myanmar: A Case for Corporate Criminal Liability’, in Hastings Law Journal, 2020, vol. 71,
pp. 816 ff.; Emma Palmer, Adapting International Criminal Justice in Southeast Asia: Be-
yond the International Criminal Court, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2020,
pp. 159 ff.; Derek Tonkin, “Mission Creep Untrammelled: The UN Fact-Finding Mission on
Myanmar”, FICHL Policy Brief Series No. 102 (2020), Torkel Opsahl Academic EPublisher,
Brussels, 2020 (http://www.toaep.org/pbs-pdf/102-tonkin).
130
Human Rights Council, Report of the detailed findings of the Independent International
Fact-Finding Mission on Myanmar, UN Doc. A/HRC/39/CRP.2, 17 September 2018, para. 4
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/0c0c69/). See also https://iimm.un.org/mandate-and-
establishment/. In more detail Heinze, 2019, pp. 171–172, see above note 87; Aksenova,
Bergsmo and Stahn, 2020, pp. 10 ff., see above note 1, with a list of “International Fact-
Finding Mandates 1992-2020” at pp. 32–44. Generally about fact-finding by the Special
Procedures of the Human Rights Council Martin Scheinin, “Improving Fact-Finding in Trea-
ty-Based Human Rights Mechanisms and the Special Procedures of the United Nations Hu-
man Rights Council”, in Morten Bergsmo and Carsten Stahn (eds.), Quality Control in Fact-
Apart from 875 in-depth interviews the mission conducted, 131 it also em-
phasised the important role of social media information. 132 It reported,
among other things:
The Mission has seen a vast amount of hate speech across all
types of platforms, including the print media, broadcasts,
pamphlets, CD/DVDs, songs, webpages and social media ac-
counts. For example, the Mission encountered over 150 online
public social media accounts, pages and groups that have reg-
ularly spread messages amounting to hate speech against Mus-
lims in general or Rohingya in particular. 133
In another study, Prenzler and King reported that according to “one-
third of the respondents, non-compliance [with ethical boundaries] was
fairly widespread”, while others felt that instances of non-compliance were
rather isolated. 134 Button describes that “there are many examples of illegal
and unethical behaviour. There have been many alleged and reported inci-
dents of private investigators bugging premises, breaking and entering,
kidnapping or gaining confidential information from the police”. 135
As previously remarked, investigators are expected to separate the
“morality in their representation” from the “morality of the client’s
cause”. 136 This may lead to a moral dilemma when investigators who com-
ply with ethical standards are asked by their clients to ignore these. Gill
and Hart describe that “there is a demand for services that can only be con-
sidered to be of dubious legitimacy”. 137 All investigators interviewed
Finding, second edition, Brussels, TOAEP, 2020, pp. 75 ff. About the question whether in-
formation collected by human rights bodies and “human rights investigators” can generally
be admitted as direct evidence at ICTs, see Lyal S. Sunga, “Can International Criminal In-
vestigators and Prosecutors Afford to Ignore Information from United Nations Human
Rights Sources?”, ibid., pp. 409 ff.
131
Ibid., para. 19.
132
Ibid., paras. 515, 744. See also Emma Irving, “The Role of Social Media is Significant:
Facebook and the Fact Finding Mission on Myanmar”, Opinio Juris, 7 September 2018.
133
Human Rights Council, 2018, para. 1310, see above note 130.
134
Timothy Prenzler and Michael King, The Role of Private Investigators and Commercial
Agents in Law Enforcement, Australian Institute of Criminology, August 2002, p. 5 (availa-
ble on the repository of Griffith University).
135
Button, 1998, p. 10, see above note 94. See also Johnston, 2007, see above note 93.
136
Luban, 2007, p. 20, see above note 109.
137
Martin Gill and Jerry Hart, “Private Security: Enforcing Corporate Security Policy Using
Private Investigators”, in European Journal on Criminal Policy and Research, 1999, vol. 7,
p. 255.
138
Gill and Hart, 1999, p. 255, see above note 137.
139
Michael J. Struett, “The Politics of Discursive Legitimacy: Understanding the Dynamics and
Implications of Prosecutorial Discretion at the International Criminal Court”, in Steven C.
Roach (ed.), Governance, Order, and the International Criminal Court, Oxford University
Press, 2009, p. 115.
140
Rankin, 2017, p. 414, see above note 56.
141
Cheryl Hardcastle for instance, Windsor-Tecumseh Minister for Canadian Parliament, high-
lighted: “We do know in the international community that some people have criticized the
privatizing of international criminal investigations”, cited in ibid., p. 405, fn. 39.
142
See Danner, 2003, p. 532, see above note 115; Ellis, 2011, p. 156, see above note 10.
143
Rankin, 2017, p. 414, see above note 56.
144
Ibid.
145
Antony Duff et al., The Trial on Trial: Volume 3, Towards a Normative Theory of the Crimi-
nal Trial, Hart, Oxford and Portland, Oregon, 2007, p. 108.
146
Paul Roberts et al., “Introduction: Re-examining Criminal Process Through the Lens of
Integrity”, in Paul Roberts et al. (eds.), The Integrity of Criminal Process, Hart, Oxford and
Portland, 2016, p. 4 with further references.
147
About the pragmatical turn in textual interpretation, see Umberto Eco, Die Grenzen der
Interpretation, Hanser, München, 1992, pp. 350 ff.
148
About the usage of words see already Wittgenstein, Philosophische Untersuchungen,
posthum second edition, Blackwell, Malden, 1958, reprint 1999, p. 20.
149
John A. Simpson and Edmund S.C. Weiner, The Compact Oxford English Dictionary, Clar-
endon Press, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1989 and 2002, p. 860 [1066].
150
Ibid., p. 860 [1066].
151
Ibid.
152
Ibid.
153
Adrian A.S. Zuckerman, “Coercion and the Judicial Ascertainment of Truth”, in Israel Law
Review, 1989, vol. 23, no. 2-3, p. 357.
154
Ibid.
pect must not be violated. 155 Here, the notion of integrity is closely con-
nected to human dignity, 156 as enshrined in various human rights instru-
ments. 157 Understood this way, integrity is often equated with autonomy,
individuality, independence, responsibility, and self-knowledge. 158 As Ger-
ald Dworkin puts it: “Individuals have the right to be treated as persons, as
masters of their own body, as responsible for their decisions, as makers of
choices”. 159 The Kantian footprint (namely: Kant’s Categorical Impera-
tive) 160 is obvious here. This supreme principle of ethics aims at the moti-
vation (or reasons) for acting; any consideration of external behaviour is
absent. 161 Kant’s Categorical Imperative illustrates that dignity is “intrinsic,
deontological and non-negotiable (replaceable), it is the basis of the indi-
viduality and the mutual recognition (inter-personal relationship) of the
members of a society”. 162 By contrast, the principle of Kant’s legal philos-
155
Israel, Supreme Court, Abu Midjam v. State of Israel, 1980, P.D. 34(4) 533, p. 539 – about
the case, see Rinat Kitai Sangero and Yuval Merin, “Israel: The Supreme Court’s New, Cau-
tious Exclusionary Rule”, in Stephen C. Thaman (ed.), Exclusionary Rules in Comparative
Law, Springer, Dordrecht, 2013, p. 105. See also Eliahu Harnon, “Criminal Procedure and
Evidence”, in Israel Law Review, 1990, vol. 24, no. 3-4, p. 592 (603).
156
Directive 2013/32/EU of the European Parliament and of the Council of 26 June 2013 on
common procedures for granting and withdrawing international protection (recast), 29 June
2013, OJ L. 180/60, Article 13 (‘Procedures Directive’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/
7ijsc2/).
157
See, for instance, Charter of Fundamental Rights of the European Union, 14 December 2007,
2007/C 303/01, Article 1 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/715d2e/). See also Galina Cornel-
isse, “Protecting human dignity across and within borders: the legal regulation of interna-
tional migration in Europe”, in Logi Gunnarsson, Ulrike Mürbe, and Norman Weiß (eds.),
The Human Right to a Dignified Existence in an International Context: Legal and Philo-
sophical Perspectives, Nomos, Baden-Baden, 2019, pp. 97–98.
158
Gerald Dworkin, The Theory and Practice of Autonomy, Cambridge University Press, 1988
and 1997, p. 6.
159
Ibid., p. 103.
160
“I ought never to act except in such a way that I could also will that my maxim should be-
come a universal law”, Immanuel Kant, Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, Mary J.
Gregor (ed., trans.), Cambridge University Press, 1997, p. 15 [402].
161
Luke J. Davies, “A Kantian Defense of the Right to Health Care”, in Reidar Maliks and
Andreas Føllesdal (eds.), Kantian Theory and Human Rights, Routledge, London, 2014,
p. 82; Wilfried Küper, “Das Strafgesetz ist ein kategorischer Imperativ: Zum ‘Strafgesetz’ in
Kants Rechtslehre”, in Michael Hettinger and Jan Zopfs (eds.), Wilfried Küper – Strafrecht-
liche Beiträge zu Rechtsgeschichte und Rechtsphilosophie, Mohr Siebeck, Tübingen, 2017,
pp. 397 ff.
162
Marie E. Newhouse, “Two Types of Legal Wrongdoing”, in Legal Theory, 2017, vol. 22, no.
1, pp. 59 ff.; Ulfried Neumann, “Das Rechtsprinzip der Menschenwürde als Schutz elemen-
tarer menschlicher Bedürfnisse: Versuch einer Eingrenzung”, in Archiv für Rechts- und
ophy, the Universal Principle of Right, 163 “transposes the categorical im-
perative to the sphere of external action”. 164 Freedom referred to by the
Universal Principle of Right is “external freedom”, it “bars considerations
of internal motivation”. 165 The distinction between external and internal
freedom is Kant’s
most profound statement on the relationship between an au-
tonomous morality and political practice. By reconstructing
Kant’s arguments in favor of their distinction, we see the dy-
namics behind his theory of justice: The pure practical reason
of morality (inner freedom) informs – and thereby subordi-
nates – the structure of outer freedom and the political reality
with which it is associated. 166
Taking Kant’s Categorical Imperative and the Universal Principle of Right
as a basis, the ‘object perspective’ is not only a semantic description but at
the same time an evaluation, since the infringement of the suspect’s rights
turns this suspect into an object, 167 up to a dehumanisation. 168
Sozialphilosophie, 2017, vol. 103, no. 3, p. 293; Julian A. Sempill, “Law, Dignity and the
Elusive Promise of a Third Way”, in Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, 2018, vol. 38, no. 2,
p. 228.
163
Any action is right if it can coexist with everyone’s freedom in accordance with a universal
law, or if on its maxim the freedom of choice of each can coexist with everyone’s freedom in
accordance with a universal law. See Immanuel Kant, The Metaphysics of Morals, Mary J.
Gregor (trans.), Cambridge University Press, 1991, p. 57 [231] (http://www.legal-tools.org/
doc/cb8e1e/). See also Kai Ambos, “Punishment without a Sovereign? The Ius Puniendi Is-
sue of International Criminal Law”, in Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, 2013, vol. 33, no. 2,
pp. 293, 305.
164
Benedict Vischer, “Systematicity to Excess – Kant’s Conception of the International Legal
Order”, in Stefan Kadelbach, Thomas Kleinlein and David Roth-Isigkeit (eds.), System, Or-
der, and International Law, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2017, p. 306: “[W]hile the
categorical imperative requires the universalizability of the voluntary maxim, the principle
of right merely demands that the action – irrespectively of the agents’ motive – conforms to
a universal law”. About the different interpretations of Kant’s external action, see Dietmar
von der Pfordten, “On Kant’s Concept of Law”, in Archiv für Rechts- und Sozialphilosophie,
2015, vol. 101, no. 2, pp. 193 ff.
165
Davies, 2014, p. 82, see above note 161.
166
Antonio Franceschet, Kant and Liberal Internationalism, Palgrave Macmillan, New York,
2002, pp. 23–24.
167
Cf. Jacob Bronsther, “Torture and Respect”, in Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology,
2019, vol. 109, no. 3, p. 423 (431, albeit with regard to “penal rape”).
168
Peters, 1985, p. 82, see above note 113.
169
Simpson and Weiner, 1989 and 2002, p. 860 [1066], see above note 149.
170
Roberts et al., 2016, p. 10, see above note 146.
171
Ibid.
172
Ibid.
173
In the same vein, see Patrick Lenta, “Freedom of Conscience and the Value of Personal In-
tegrity”, in Ratio Juris, 2016, vol. 29, no. 2, pp. 247–248.
174
Ibid.
175
Lynne McFall, “Integrity”, in Ethics, 1987, vol. 98, no. 1, p. 5 (9).
176
Ibid., p. 14.
that someone had personal integrity, even if we were to find his ideal mor-
ally abhorrent”. 177 In reaction to this, it is questioned whether personal in-
tegrity has value whatsoever. In Lenta’s words: “One might think that per-
sonal integrity is valueless since an individual’s possessing personal integ-
rity is compatible with his being wicked. In the case of the genocidal Nazi
who possesses personal integrity it may well be better if he lacked personal
integrity”. 178
The integrity of those who collect evidence has long been recognised
as a central value and qualification. Take, for instance, the Oath of Honor
of the International Association of Chiefs of Police: “On my honor, I will
never betray my badge, my integrity, my character, or the public trust. I
will always have the courage to hold myself and others accountable for our
actions. I will always uphold the Constitution, my community, and the
agency I serve”. 179 Similarly, prosecutors “are meant to hold their profes-
sional integrity” and expected to have an “ethical compass”. 180 Corrigan
goes even further: “The first, best, and most effective shield against injus-
tice for an individual accused [person], or society in general, must be found
not in the persons of defense counsel, trial judge, or appellate jurist, but in
the integrity of the prosecutor”. 181 The ICC, per its Statute, requires the
staff of the OTP and Registry to have “the highest standards of efficiency,
competency and integrity”. 182
17.5.2.1.3. Integrity from the Perspective of the Process:
The Context Perspective
As previously mentioned, according to a lexical definition, ‘integrity’ also
means “undivided or unbroken state”; “material wholeness, completeness,
entirety”. Integrity, thus, also implies normative coherence juxtaposed to
fragmentation. For the current purpose, this refers to the “material whole-
177
Ibid. (emphasis in the original).
178
Lenta, 2016, p. 248, see above note 173.
179
The International Association of Chiefs of Police (‘IACP’), “The Oath of Honor” (available
on its web site). See also Joycelyn M. Pollock, Ethical Dilemmas and Decisions in Criminal
Justice, tenth edition, Cangage, Boston, 2019, p. 129.
180
Brent E. Turvey and Craig M. Cooley, Miscarriages of Justice, Elsevier, Amsterdam et al.,
2014, p. 286.
181
Carol A. Corrigan, “On Prosecutorial Ethics”, in Hastings Constitutional Law Quarterly,
1986, vol. 13, no. 3, p. 537.
182
Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court, 17 July 1998, Article 44(2) (‘ICC Statute’)
(http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/7b9af9/).
183
David Dixon, “Integrity, Interrogation and Criminal Justice”, in Paul Roberts et al. (eds.),
The Integrity of Criminal Process, Hart, Oxford and Portland, 2016, p. 79.
184
Andrew Ashworth, “Testing Fidelity to Legal Values: Official Involvement and Criminal
Justice”, in Stephen Shute and Andrew P. Simester, Criminal Law Theory: Doctrines of the
General Part, Oxford University Press, 2002, p. 308.
185
Ibid., p. 309.
186
Ibid.
187
A. Duff et al., 2007, p. 226 see above note 145. See also See Andrew Ashworth, “Exploring
the Integrity Principle in Evidence and Procedure”, in Peter Mirfield and Roger Smith (eds.),
Essays for Colin Tapper, LexisNexis, London, 2003, pp. 113–115.
188
See below Section 17.5.2.3.2.3.
189
HO Hock Lai, “Exclusion of Wrongfully Obtained Evidence: A Comparative Analysis”, in
Darryl K. Brown et al. (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Criminal Process, Oxford University
Press, 2019, p. 834.
190
See above Section 17.1.
191
Kai Ambos, “The Transnational Use of Torture Evidence”, in Israel Law Review, 2009, vol.
42, no. 2, p. 366 (emphasis in the original, fn. omitted).
192
Kelly Pitcher, Judicial Responses to Pre-Trial Procedural Violations in International Crimi-
nal Proceedings, Asser Press, Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg, 2018, p. 185; John Jackson,
“Human Rights, Constitutional Law and Exclusionary Safeguards in Ireland”, in Paul Rob-
erts and Jill Hunter (eds.), Criminal Evidence and Human Rights, Hart, Oxford and Portland,
Oregon, 2012, p. 119 (121). For reviews of the various rationales, see Peter Mirfield, Silence,
Confessions and Improperly Obtained Evidence, Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1997, chaps. 2
and 6; Ian H. Dennis, The Law of Evidence, seventh edition, Sweet & Maxwell, Thomson
Reuters, London, 2020, mn. 3-041–3.046; Paul Roberts and Adrian Zuckerman, Criminal
Evidence, second edition, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2010, pp. 179 ff.
193
Peter Duff views the deterrence rationale (calling it “disciplinary rationale”) as part of the
“integrity of the process”, see Peter Duff, “Admissibility of Improperly Obtained Physical
Evidence in the Scottish Criminal Trial: The Search for Principle”, in Edinburgh Law Re-
view, 2004, vol. 8, no. 2, p. 152 (160).
194
Roberts and Hunter, 2012, p. 121, see above note 192 (“Another argument often advanced is
that the prohibition on the use of evidence serves as a deterrent to investigators and prosecu-
tors from repeating their improper conduct in the future”); Adrian A.S. Zuckerman, “Illegal-
ly-Obtained Evidence—Discretion as a Guardian of Legitimacy”, in Current Legal Prob-
lems, 1987, vol. 40, no. 1, pp. 56–57.
195
HO, 2019, p. 824, see above note 189; Roberts and Zuckerman, 2010, p. 185, see above note
192.
196
Stephen C. Thaman and Dominik Brodowski, “Exclusion or Non-Use of Illegally Gathered
Evidence in the Criminal Process: Focus on Common Law and German Approaches”, in Kai
Ambos et al. (eds.), Core Concepts in Criminal Law and Justice, vol. 1, Cambridge Univer-
sity Press, 2020, p. 458.
197
United States, Supreme Court (‘US SC’), Terry v. Ohio, 1968, 392 US 1, p. 12. See also US
SC, Mapp v. Ohio, 1961, 367 US 643, p. 655.
198
LIU Jingkun, The Exclusionary Rule of Illegal Evidence in China, Springer, Law Press Chi-
na, Beijing, 2019, p. 44.
199
Ibid.
200
HO, 2019, p. 824, see above note 189.
201
A. Duff et al., 2007, p. 228, see above note 145.
202
Zuckerman, 1987, p. 59, see above note 194; Roberts and Zuckerman, 2010, p. 27, see
above note 192; P. Duff, 2004, p. 161, see above note 193: “are we really justified in letting
the guilty go free in order that we can protect the public from the police?”.
203
See, for example, Luis Greco, “Warum gerade Beweisverbot? Ketzerische Bemerkungen zur
Figur des Beweisverbots”, in Ulrich Stein et al. (eds.), Systematik in Strafrechtswissenschaft
und Gesetzgebung, Festschrift für Klaus Rogall zum 70. Geburtstag am 10. August 2018,
Duncker & Humblot, 2018, pp. 485–515 (507 ff.).
204
HO, 2019, p. 825, see above note 189; Gless and Macula, 2019, p. 355, see above note 8.
205
Gless and Macula, 2019, p. 355, see above note 8.
206
As it the case in Germany, Thaman and Brodowski, 2020, p. 458, see above note 196.
207
Zuckerman, 1987, p. 59, see above note 194.
208
Ibid.
tion. 209 Third, in many criminal justice systems, officials who violate an
exclusionary rule never learn whether or not the evidence they obtained is
excluded. 210 A fourth point is made by HO:
To deter the police from breaking rules on evidence gathering,
they must know what the rules are. It is questionable whether
they do possess adequate knowledge. Exclusion will have lit-
tle signaling and disincentivization impact if there is no com-
munication channel that keeps the police in the loop every
time the court rejects the evidence that they have collected. 211
Ambos would not go so far to reject the deterrence rationale altogether but
downgrade it to a “positive side-effect”. 212
17.5.2.2.2. Integrity from Object Perspective:
The Theory of Remedies
The theory of remedies (also known as the “rights thesis”, 213 ‘vindication’,
‘remedial’ or ‘protective’ theory 214 ) focuses on the person interrogated
and – more specifically – on his or her rights. Evidence ought to be exclud-
ed because legal (subjective) rights have been infringed. 215 The idea behind
this rationale is that trials can and should protect citizens against the arbi-
trary exercise of State power. 216 If rights have been violated, the victim of
the violation is entitled to a remedy (hence the name). 217 Human rights in
the structure of criminal procedure vest the accused with legal rights which
he or she can use to oppose State repression in the investigation and prose-
cution of a crime. 218 This defensive role is denoted in legal theory as the
shield function of human rights law. 219 A criminal trial has a particularly
209
Thaman and Brodowski, 2020, p. 458, see above note 196; Gless and Macula, 2019, p. 355,
see above note 8; Zuckerman, 1987, p. 59, see above note 194.
210
Gless and Macula, 2019, p. 355, see above note 8.
211
HO, 2019, p. 825, see above note 189 (fn. omitted). In the same vein, albeit with regard to
search and seizure, see Zuckerman, 1987, p. 59, see above note 194.
212
Ambos, 2009, p. 366, see above note 191.
213
A. Duff et al., 2007, p. 230, see above note 145.
214
Zuckerman, 1987, pp. 56–57, see above note 194; P. Duff, 2004, p. 164, see above note 193.
215
About the “rights perspective” in general Campbell, Ashworth, and Redmayne, 2019, p. 46,
see above note 107; see also P. Duff, 2004, p. 155, see above note 193.
216
A. Duff et al., 2007, p. 227, see above note 145.
217
Ibid., p. 230.
218
Krešimir Kamber, Prosecuting Human Rights Offences, Brill, Leiden, 2017, p. 7.
219
Ibid.
negative effect for the (alleged) offender’s rights such as his or her reputa-
tion, financial position, personal liberty, and even life. 220 Thus, human
rights protection ensures that the individual is shielded from the State’s
abuse of the ius puniendi. 221 Of course, human rights law also mandates the
State to criminalise, investigate, prosecute and, if appropriate, punish crim-
inal attacks on human rights. 222 This role can be descriptively denoted as
the sword function of human rights law. 223 If failing to convict the defend-
ant “where there is a powerful epistemic case against him is a serious abro-
gation of responsibility by the state, it will need powerful justification in
terms of deterrence, a justification which we suspect will not be forthcom-
ing”. 224
Duff et al. integrate this shield function of human rights in a trial into
a more general communicative theory of the criminal trial. 225 In the spirit
of this communicative theory of the trial, “state power must be justified to
the defendant through the appropriate kind of communicative process,
treating him as a responsible agent”. 226 The combination of the remedy ra-
tionale and communicative theory is particularly appealing for international
investigations, as I will demonstrate below. 227
The remedial theory “is rights-based, and backward-looking, and de-
fends exclusion as a direct response to the specific wrong committed by the
police in getting the evidence”. 228 Yet, unlike the deterrence theory, which
220
Stefan Trechsel, Human Rights in Criminal Proceedings, Oxford University Press, 2005)
pp. 6 ff. (“An individual’s reputation, financial position, personal liberty, even life […] is at
stake”); Julia Geneuss, “Obstacles to Cross-fertilisation: The International Criminal Tribu-
nals’ ‘Unique Context’ and the Flexibility of the European Court of Human Rights’ Case
Law”, in Nordic Journal of International Law, 2015, vol. 84, no. 3, pp. 410–411.
221
Geneuss, 2015, pp. 410–411, see above note 220.
222
Inter–American Court of Human Rights, Case of Velásquez Rodríguez v. Honduras, Merits,
Judgment, 29 July 1988, Series C, No. 4, para. 176:
The State is obligated to investigate every situation involving a violation of the rights
protected by the Convention. If the State apparatus acts in such a way that the violation
goes unpunished and the victim's full enjoyment of such rights is not restored as soon as
possible, the State has failed to comply with its duty to ensure the free and full exercise
of those rights to the persons within its jurisdiction.
223
Kamber, 2017, p. 7, see above note 218.
224
A. Duff et al., 2007, p. 229, see above note 145.
225
Ibid., p. 227.
226
Ibid.
227
See below Section 17.5.2.3.2.3.1.
228
HO, 2019, p. 824, see above note 189.
229
Roberts and Hunter, 2012, p. 121, see above note 192. See especially Andrew Ashworth,
“Excluding Evidence as Protecting Rights”, in Criminal Law Review, 1977, p. 723.
230
LIU, 2019, p. 50, see above note 198.
231
Zuckerman, 1987, p. 58, see above note 194:
In a criminal trial exclusion of evidence of guilt amounts to a contribution towards the
acquittal of a person who may be guilty. It is by no means self-evident that acquittal of
the guilty is an appropriate response to earlier police transgressions. Nor is a blanket ex-
clusion capable of achieving a balance between the seriousness of the infringement and
the benefit to the accused.
232
“There are far stronger grounds for punishing an officer who deliberately broke the rules or
tricked the accused than where there has been mere inadvertence”, P. Duff, 2004, p. 161, see
above note 193.
233
See also ibid., p. 164.
234
Ibid., p. 171.
235
Ibid., p. 159.
236
Roberts and Hunter, 2012, p. 121, see above note 192.
237
Zuckerman, 1987, p. 56, see above note 194.
238
In detail, see Dennis, 2020, mn. 2-022, see above note 192.
239
LIU, 2019, p. 46, see above note 198.
240
Dennis, 2020, mn. 2-022, see above note 192.
241
Zuckerman, 1987, p. 56, see above note 194; Roberts and Zuckerman, 2010, p. 16, see
above note 192; LIU, 2019, p. 45, see above note 198; P. Duff, 2004, p. 155, see above note
193: “[M]ost people would agree that it would not reflect well upon a criminal justice sys-
tem if it were prepared to admit incriminating statements which had been tortured out of the
accused by the police”.
242
HO, 2019, p. 830, see above note 189.
ry. 243 As HO puts it: “To preserve judicial legitimacy, and to avoid being
tainted by the executive’s dirty hands, the court has to renounce and disas-
sociate itself from the police illegality by refusing to accept and act on the
product of the illegality”. 244 In the Rothman case before the Supreme Court
of Canada, 245 Judges Laskin and Estey stated in their dissent:
The basic reason for the exclusionary confession rule is a con-
cern for the integrity of the criminal justice system. The sup-
port and respect of the community for that system can only be
maintained if persons in authority conduct themselves in a
way that does not bring the administration of justice into dis-
repute. 246
The consideration of the public attitude is a double-edged sword: it
appears doubtful that the public, especially the victims, would accept the
decision of excluding key evidence only due to a relatively minor violation
of legal procedure. Thus, the argument of legitimacy allows for a consider-
able exercise of balancing. The theory of fair trial is an important basis of
the exclusionary rule in England. Section 78 (1) of the Police and Criminal
Evidence Act 1984 stipulates that
In any proceedings the court may refuse to allow evidence on
which the prosecution proposes to rely to be given if it ap-
pears to the court that, having regard to all the circumstances,
including the circumstances in which the evidence was ob-
tained, the admission of the evidence would have such an ad-
verse effect on the fairness of the proceedings that the court
ought not to admit it.
Amongst the rationales of exclusionary rules, the moral legitimacy ra-
tionale receives increasing popularity, 247 while it carries some inherent
dangers: “public opinion in these matters is likely to mirror the ‘populist
243
Ibid.
244
Ibid., with further references.
245
Canada, Supreme Court, Rothman v. The Queen, [1981] 1 SCR 640 (available on its web
site).
246
Ibid., p. 642.
247
P. Duff, 2004, p. 173, see above note 193: “A further response might be that the moral legit-
imacy rationale provides a better explanation of what it is that the courts actually do, even if
they do not always fully recognise or articulate their reasoning”.
punitiveness’ expressed in the tabloid press and by ‘law and order’ politi-
cians”. 248
17.5.2.2.3.2. Integrity as Reliability
The rational that provides most flexibility is the reliability theory: evidence
may be unreliable because of how it was obtained. 249 See, for instance,
Section 76(2)(b) of the Police and Criminal Evidence Act of 1984 reads:
If, in any proceedings where the prosecution proposes to give
in evidence a confession made by an accused person, it is rep-
resented to the court that the confession was or may have been
obtained […] in consequence of anything said or done which
was likely, in the circumstances existing at the time, to render
unreliable any confession which might be made by him in
consequence thereof, the court shall not allow the confession
to be given in evidence against him except in so far as the
prosecution proves to the court beyond reasonable doubt that
the confession (notwithstanding that it may be true) was not
obtained as aforesaid. 250
Two aspects render the reliability rationale an integrity concept: First, ex-
cluding evidence that has been wrongfully obtained would advance the
search for truth, since the use of unreliable evidence “increases the risk of
error in fact-finding”. 251 As previously argued, the search for truth is a
means to the end of justice and thus a vital part of the integrity of a trial.
Second, a guilty verdict that is based on unreliable evidence is an unfair
verdict. 252 An unfair verdict lacks – as already mentioned – legitimacy. Ac-
cordingly, the reliability and legitimacy theory are intertwined. The con-
nection between reliability and fairness is also underlined by the European
248
Ibid., p. 175, citing Ashworth, 2003, p. 111, see above note 187. P. Duff borrows the term
“public punitiveness” from Anthony Bottoms, “The philosophy and politics of punishment
and sentencing”, in Chris Clarkson and Rod Morgan (eds.), The Politics of Sentencing Re-
form, Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1995, pp. 39–41.
249
Roberts and Hunter, 2012, p. 121, see above note 192.
250
UK, Police and Criminal Evidence Act 1984, 31 October 1984, s. 78 (https://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/b52ec0/). Emphasis added.
251
HO, 2019, p. 828, see above note 189; P. Duff, 2004, p. 154, see above note 193: “The first
reason for excluding evidence is the fear that it may adversely affect the accuracy of the out-
come of the trial. This may be because the evidence is, quite simply, inherently unreliable or
because the evidence, even if factually accurate, is likely for other reasons to distort the de-
cision-making process, thus affecting the reliability of the outcome”.
252
HO, 2019, p. 832, see above note 189.
Court of Human Rights in the Gäfgen case, where evidence was obtained
by way of torture: 253
[T]he quality of the evidence must be taken into consideration,
as must the circumstances in which it was obtained and
whether these circumstances cast doubts on its reliability or
accuracy. While no problem of fairness necessarily arises
where the evidence obtained was unsupported by other mate-
rial, it may be noted that where the evidence is very strong
and there is no risk of its being unreliable, the need for sup-
porting evidence is correspondingly weaker. 254
253
European Court of Human Rights, Gäfgen v. Germany, Judgment, 1 June 2010, 22978/05;
John D. Jackson and Sarah J. Summers, The Internationalisation of Criminal Evidence,
Cambridge University Press, Cambridge et al., 2012, p. 158; Jamil Ddamulira Mujuzi, “The
Admissibility of Confessions and Real Evidence Obtained in Violation of Human Rights in
Criminal Trials in European Countries: Analysing the Jurisprudence of the European Court
of Human Rights”, in European Criminal Law Review, 2019, vol. 9, no. 3, pp. 340–345.
254
Gäfgen v. Germany, 2010, para. 164, see above note 253.
255
It should be stressed, though, that the concept of a Rule of Law goes back to Plato and Aris-
totle, see in more detail the account of Erhard Denninger, “Rechtsstaat”, in id. and Klaus
Lüderssen (eds.), Polizei und Strafprozeß im demokratischen Rechtsstaat, Suhrkamp, Frank-
furt a.M., 1978, pp. 67–72.
256
Albert Venn Dicey, Introduction to the Study of the Law of the Constitution, tenth edition,
MacMillan, London, 1886 (reproduced in 1979), pp. 188 ff.
257
Dicey, 1886 and 1979, p. 188, see above note 256.
258
Ibid., p. 193.
259
Erhard Denninger, “’Rechtsstaat’ oder ‘Rule of Law’ – was ist das heute?”, in Cornelius
Prittwitz et al. (eds.), Festschrift für Klaus Lüderssen, Nomos, Baden-Baden, 2002, p. 43.
260
Dicey, 1886 and 1979, p. 193, see above note 256.
261
See also Matthias Klatt, “Der Begriff des Rechtsstaats”, in Eric Hilgendorf and Jan C. Joer-
den (eds.), Handbuch Rechtsphilosophie, J.B. Metzler, Stuttgart, 2017, pp. 390 ff.; Eberhard
Schmidt-Aßmann, “§ 26 – Der Rechtsstaat”, in Josef Isensee and Paul Kirchhof (ed.),
Handbuch des Staatsrechts der Bundesrepublik Deutschland, Bd. II: Verfassungsstaat, C.F.
Müller, Heidelberg 2004, mn. 1.
262
Neil MacCormick, Questioning Sovereignty, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1999-2002,
p. 43. About the difference between rule of law and Rechtsstaatsprinzip Oliver Lepsius,
Verwaltungsrecht unter dem Common Law. Amerikanische Entwicklungen bis zum New Deal,
Mohr Siebeck, Tübingen, 1997, pp. 207 ff. Denninger stresses that Rule of Law and
Rechtsstaatsprinzip have conceptually different roots: While the Rule of Law is political, the
Rechtsstaatsprinzip is apolitical. In England, for instance, subjective rights have always
been closely connected to a functioning process of democratic political participation. The
roots of the Rechtsstaatsprinzip, by contrast, are a reaction to the failed attempt at democra-
cy in 1848 and 1849 and are thus apolitical and individualistic, Denninger, 1978, p. 68, see
above note 255.
ple. 263 The rule of law could thus well be categorised as what Popper fa-
mously labelled as one of the “mere puzzles arising out of the misuse of
language”. 264
A central idea of the rule of law is that the government should be
subject to and accountable under the law. 265 A core value for achieving this
is the separation of powers. 266 In Germany, for instance, any State activity
infringing the rights of citizens requires a clear statutory legal basis. 267 The
criminal trial is an important platform in this system. The court’s role is to
scrutinise unlawfulness on the part of the executive – eventually to pre-
serve the integrity of the criminal process. 268 Courts make sure that the
truth in a criminal trial is not sought at any price but that there are legal
limitations on ascertaining it with the constitutional rights being protected.
Truth has an integrity component. 269 Thus, the executive must be prevented
263
Neil MacCormick, “Der Rechtsstaat und die rule of law”, in Juristenzeitung, 1984, p. 65 (67)
(author’s translation). As a result, Denninger expressly emphasizes that he attempts to
“describe” the essential, i.e. functional-necessary elements of the “invention” rule of law,
which is supposed to be ahistorical, see Denninger, 2002, p. 43, see above note 259 (“Der
folgende Versuch einer Beschreibung der ‘wesentlichen’, das heißt funktionsnatwendigen
Elemente der ,Erfindung‘ rule of law ist also auf die Bewältigung gegen— wärtiger und ab-
sehbarer zukünftiger Probleme gerichtet. Er ist damit bewusst „unhistorisch“ […].”). Klatt
recognises three phases of the development of a Rechtsstaat-definition, see in more detail
Klatt, 2017, pp. 390 ff., see above note 261.
264
Karl Popper, Unended Quest, Routledge, London and New York, 2005, p. 11.
265
Friedrich August von Hayek, The Road to Serfdom, Dymock’s Book Arcade, Sydney, 1944,
p. 54; Roberts and Zuckerman, 2010, p. 17, see above note 192.
266
Ralf Dreier, “Der Rechtsstaat im Spannungsverhältnis zwischen Gesetz und Recht”, in Ju-
ristenzeitung, 1985, vol. 40, no. 8, p. 353.
267
See German Federal Constitutional Court, Judgment of 12 Apr. 2005 – 2 BvR 581/01 =
BVerfGE 112, 304, 315 for the area of criminal procedure, and generally German Federal
Constitutional Court, Judgment of 21 Dec. 1977 – 1 BvL 1/75, 1 BvR 147/75 = BVerfGE 47,
46, 78–9; Thaman and Brodowski, 2020, p. 429, see above note 196.
268
See Pitcher, 2018, p. 117, see above note 192.
269
Richard L. Lippke, “Fundamental Values of Criminal Procedure”, in Darryl K. Brown et al.
(eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Criminal Process, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2019,
p. 31:
I believe that it is useful to identify two subsidiary values in the service of truth. The
first is integrity, according to which the various state agents tasked with arresting, inves-
tigating, and charging individuals with crimes, and seeing to the adjudication of charges,
must respect and consistently abide by procedures that are reliable and evidence-driven.
270
See, for example, HO Hock Lai, “The Criminal Trial, the Rule of Law and the Exclusion of
Unlawfully Obtained Evidence”, in Criminal Law and Philosophy, 2016, vol. 10, no. 1,
p. 109; HO, 2019, p. 833, see above note 189.
271
John Finnis, Natural Law and Natural Rights, second edition, Oxford University Press, 2011,
p. 273.
272
United Kingdom, House of Lords (‘UK HL’), R v. Looseley, [2001] UKHL 53, [2001] WLR
2060.
273
See also Klatt, 2017, pp. 391–392, see above note 261, with further references.
274
See already MacCormick, 1984, p. 69, see above note 263.
275
Ibid. (author’s translation).
276
Ibid.: “Zum einen sind sie [die Prinzipien der Rechtsstaatlichkeit] formale Leitlinien einer
vernünftigen Rechtspraxis auf Gesetzes- und Rechtsanwendungsebene; sie gebe der Forde-
rung Ausdruck, daß Rechtsnormen unabhängig von der Akteptabilität ihrer Inhalte in Über-
einstimmung mit den Erfordernissen von formal verstandener ‘reasonableness’ erlassen und
angewandt werden müssen” (author’s translation).
277
In fact, MacCormick uses the term “überpositives Vernunftrecht”. About the difference
between Naturrecht and überposititivem Recht, Frank Dietrich, “Rechtsbegriffe”, in Eric
Hilgendorf and Jan C. Joerden (eds.), Handbuch Rechtsphilosophie, J.B. Metzler, Stuttgart,
2017, p. 2 (6).
278
MacCormick, 1984, p. 69, see above note 263: “Zum anderen sind diese Prinzipien eher
dem überpositiven Vernunftrecht als dem geschriebenen Recht zugehörig – einem Vernunft-
recht, wie es die Rechtsphilosophie und Staatslehre im Laufe der Jahrhunderte in kritischer
Auseinandersetzung mit bestehenden Rechtsordnungen entwickelt haben. Insofern sind sie
gewohnheitsrechtlich verankert” (author’s translation).
279
For references see ibid.
280
In this vein, see Denninger, 2002, pp. 44–45, see above note 259: “‘Recht’, und das heißt in
einer entwickelten industriellen und postindustriellen Gesellschaft fast ausschließlich: ge-
setztes, ‘positiviertes’, damit auch änderbares Recht, also ‘Gesetz’”.
281
Ibid., p. 46.
282
Lon L. Fuller, The Morality of Law, revised edition, Yale University Press, New Haven,
1969, p. 81.
283
Ibid.
284
Ibid.
285
MacCormick, 1999 and 2002, p. 45, see above note 262.
286
HO, 2016, pp. 119–120, see above note 270.
287
Joseph Raz, The Authority of Law – Essays on Law and Morality, Oxford University Press,
1979, pp. 208 ff.; Finnis, 2011, pp. 270 ff., see above note 271; Klatt, 2017, pp. 391–392,
see above note 261; Schmidt-Aßmann, 2004, mn. 4, see above note 261.
288
Cf. Hasso Hofmann, “Geschichtlichkeit und Universalitätsanspruch des Rechtsstaats”, in
Der Staat, 1995, vol. 34, no. 1, p. 1 (12); Schmidt-Aßmann, 2004, mn. 19, see above note
261; Klatt, 2017, p. 391, see above note 261.
289
MacCormick, 1999 and 2002, p. 43, see above note 262.
In other words, the rule of law incorporates basic civil and political
rights. 290 It protects the dignity, integrity and moral equality of persons and
groups. 291 Dworkin’s theory of law as ‘integrity’ goes into the same direc-
tion, reflecting a broad and substantive conception of the rule of law, 292 so
does Habermas’ Diskurstheorie. 293 Thus, the substantive element of the
rule of law combines the two dimensions of integrity: the systemic dimen-
sion and the deontological. It also includes the remedy rationale of exclu-
sionary rules. 294
17.5.2.2.4. Intermediate Conclusion
In this section, I have displayed the rationales for the exclusion of evidence
illegally obtained by State officials to answer the question whether integrity
should be the value that provides guidance for a private individual conduct-
ing an investigation. Within these rationales, I have identified the role of
integrity and connected it to the three perspectives of integrity introduced
at the outset of the section. The ‘remedy rationale’ corresponds with the
‘object perspective’, the ‘deterrence rationale’ with the ‘subject perspec-
tive’ and the ‘integrity of the process rationale’ with the ‘context perspec-
tive’. The latter has three variants: integrity as moral authority of the ver-
dict and integrity as legitimacy; integrity as reliability; and integrity as the
rule of law. Integrity as the rule of law may incorporate all other elements
290
Ibid., p. 46. Critically Raz, 1979, pp. 208 ff., see above note 287; Ernst-Wolfgang Böcken-
förde, “Grundrechte als Grundsatznormen – Zur gegenwärtigen Lage der Grundrechtsdog-
matik”, in Ernst-Wolfgang Böckenförde (ed.), Staat, Verfassung, Demokratie. Studien zur
Verfassungstheorie und zum Verfassungsrecht, Suhrkamp, Frankfurt a. M., 1991, pp. 190,
197 ff.
291
Martin Krygier, “Rule of Law (and Rechtsstaat)”, in James R. Silkenat, James E. Hickey, Jr.,
and Peter D. Barenboim (eds.), The Legal Doctrines of the Rule of Law and the Legal State
(Rechtsstaat), Springer, Cham, 2014, p. 52.
292
Ronald Dworkin, Law’s Empire, The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, Cambridge,
Massachusetts, 1986, 176 ff. See also T.R.S. Allan, “Freedom, Equality, Legality”, in James
R. Silkenat, James E. Hickey, Jr., and Peter D. Barenboim (eds.), The Legal Doctrines of the
Rule of Law and the Legal State (Rechtsstaat), Springer, Cham, 2014, p. 155 (169). In the
same vein, see Jürgen Habermas, Faktizität und Geltung, fourth edition, Suhrkamp, Frank-
furt am Main, 1994, p. 272: “Denn der Gesichtspunkt der Integrität, unter dem der Richter
das geltende Recht rational rekonstruiert, ist Ausdruck einer rechtsstaatlichen Idee, die die
Rechtsprechung zusammen mit dem politischen Gesetzgeber dem Gründungsakt der Verfas-
sung und der Praxis der am Verfassungsprozeß beteiligten Staatsbürger bloß entlehnt” (em-
phasis in the original).
293
Ibid., p. 250.
294
See above Section 17.5.2.2.2.
of the ‘context perspective’, namely, the moral authority of the verdict, le-
gitimacy (fair trial) and reliability. The natural law dimension of the rule of
law is crucial for this umbrella function.
17.5.2.3. The Role of Integrity in Illegally Obtaining Evidence in a
Private Investigation
The distinction between the various perspectives mentioned above – put
differently: the individual-collective approach 295 – can be upheld on the
international level, albeit not without a determination of preceding issues.
Those issues are the nature of investigations under consideration in this
chapter and the different notions of fairness.
17.5.2.3.1. Investigatory Contexts
It lies within the nature of international criminal proceedings that the roots
of certain pieces of information can be traced back to other investigatory
contexts. This investigatory context can be non-existent – this is the situa-
tion this chapter is about: a private individual collects evidence that is then
offered to an ICT. The evaluation of the context as ‘non-existent’ stems
from the (albeit semantic, not necessarily conceptual) premise that an in-
vestigation is always conducted by State authorities, while a private person
could only conduct an ‘examination’ 296 or make an ‘inquiry’. 297 What
seems to be a tempting way to separate already, through semantics and tax-
onomy, the collection of evidence by a State actor on the one hand, and by
a private person on the other hand, is problematic in two ways. First, the
solution of conceptual puzzles through semantics and taxonomy has always
an arbitrary after taste. In other words, the problem is merely shifted to an-
other level. Second, as I will demonstrate, a systemic understanding of ‘in-
295
Ambos, 2009, p. 366, see above note 191.
296
In this vein, see Nienaber, 2019, pp. 47–48, see above note 97.
297
In this vein, see Ulrich Eisenberg, Beweisrecht der StPO – Spezialkommentar, tenth edition,
C.H. Beck, München, 2017, mn. 395 (“Nachforschungen”). De Vries provides a rather broad
interpretation of term ‘investigation’ that seems to be based on the functional reading of de-
cisions of regional human rights courts, albeit ignoring the procedural context of the deci-
sions, see De Vries, 2019, p. 605, see above note 1 (“capable of leading to the identification
and punishment of those responsible”). For a definition of the term “fact-finding” – albeit
from an epistemological perspective and not from an institutional one – Simon De Smet,
“Justified Belief in the Unbelievable”, in Morten Bergsmo and Carsten Stahn (eds.), Quality
Control in Fact-Finding, second edition, TOAEP, Brussels, 2020, pp. 83 ff. Several forms of
fact-finding exercises are listed by Robertson, 2020, pp. 480–482, see above note 5.
vestigation’ can and even must include the conduct of everyone acting
within that system, namely, both State and private actors.
Moreover, the context can also be a domestic investigation, for ex-
ample, evidence obtained legally under domestic law would be obtained
illegally under the law of the ICT; entrapment by a law enforcement offi-
cial of another jurisdiction 298 – or even an international investigation,
where a third party working for an organ of the respective ICT (UN peace-
keeping forces, for instance) obtains evidence through illegal means. I will
call these contexts the inter-investigatory context (international investiga-
tion – domestic investigation); the intra-investigatory context (internal in-
vestigation by a private individual or another third actor); and the extra-
investigatory context (collection of evidence by a private individual outside
any ICT-investigation). Spatial restrictions dictate a dietary approach to
those contexts.
17.5.2.3.1.1. The Inter-Investigatory Context
The inter-investigatory context has indeed been dealt with by ICTs in the
past when national authorities obtained evidence in violation of the sus-
pect’s rights applicable before the Tribunals. In one instance, at the trial
against Mucić, the Defence contended that Austrian authorities denied then
suspect Mucić the right to counsel, the right to remain silent, and induced
him to make a confession. 299 At that time, Austrian law did not provide for
a right to counsel during questioning, which the ICTY evaluated as “not
strange and not in violation of fundamental human rights or the European
Convention on human rights”. 300 I will go into the relevant provisions on a
possible exclusion or admission of the evidence in a moment. Right now,
for the description of the inter-investigatory context it suffices to say that
the ICTY felt – unsurprisingly – that it was not bound by the law of a dif-
ferent investigatory context. 301 It is in the discretion of the Chamber,
though, whether it “may apply such rules”. 302 As a result, the Trial Cham-
298
A. Duff et al., 2007, p. 242, see above note 145.
299
ICTY, Prosecutor v. Delalić et al., Trial Chamber, Decision on Zdravko Mucic's Motion for
the Exclusion of Evidence, 2 September 1997, IT-96-21-T, para. 8 (‘Delalić et al.’) (https://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/afbced/). See also the analysis in Pitcher, 2018, p. 289, see above
note 192.
300
Delalić et al., 1997, para. 46, see above note 299.
301
Ibid., para. 49: “The Trial Chamber is not bound by national rules of evidence – Sub-rule
89(A)”.
302
Ibid.
ber held that the Austrian procedure was in breach of the right to counsel
according to Article 18(3) ICTY Statute and therefore the statement before
the police was inadmissible at trial. 303 A similar situation occurred before
the ICTR. On 15 April 1996, the authorities of Cameroon arrested and de-
tained Barayagwiza and several other suspects on suspicion of having
committed genocide and crimes against humanity in Rwanda in 1994. 304
Barayagwiza later argued that his pre-trial detention in Cameroon was ex-
cessive and that he was not promptly informed of the charges brought
against him. This rendered his otherwise lawful arrest unlawful and consti-
tuted an obstacle to the Tribunal's personal jurisdiction on the basis of the
“abuse of process doctrine”. 305
In the ICC Statute, the inter-investigatory context was taken into ac-
count via Article 69(8): “When deciding on the relevance or admissibility
of evidence collected by a State, the Court shall not rule on the application
of the State’s national law”. The provision clarifies a rather simple insight:
that the ICC is supposed to apply its own law when deciding upon the ad-
missibility of evidence. 306 Article 69(8) is thus a concretisation of Article
10: “Nothing in this Part shall be interpreted as limiting or prejudicing in
any way existing or developing rules of international law for purposes oth-
er than this Statute”. On its face, the provision applies to Part 2 of the Stat-
ute, namely, Articles 5–21. 307 Nevertheless, the drafting process of the pro-
vision indicates that it may also apply to Articles outside Part 2. 308 And
since it includes Article 21, it certainly applies when internationally recog-
nised human rights are concerned. Even though Article 10 exists to clarify
that the Statute does not bar outside development, it cuts both ways and
also stresses the differences between the text in the Statute and other in-
struments, including national law. 309 The purpose of Article 10 appears as a
kind of reservation clause and clarifies that all articles in Part 2 are limited
303
Ibid., para. 52.
304
International Criminal Tribunal for Rwanda (‘ICTR’), Prosecutor v. Barayagwiza, Decision,
3 November 1999, ICTR-97-19-AR72, Introduction, para. 5 (‘Barayagwiza decision’)
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/ee7411/).
305
Ibid., Introduction, paras. 13 et seq.
306
Pitcher, 2018, p. 325, see above note 192.
307
Alexander Heinze, “Article 10”, in Kai Ambos (ed.), Rome Statute of the International
Criminal Court – A Commentary, fourth edition, C.H. Beck, Hart, Nomos, München et al.,
2021, p. 775, mn. 16.
308
Ibid., mn. 12.
309
Ibid., p. 655, mn. 16.
310
Ibid., p. 648, mn. 6.
311
ICC, Prosecutor v. Katanga and Ngudjolo, Decision on the Prosecutor’s Bar Table Motions,
17 December 2010, ICC-01/04-01/07-2635, para. 55 (fn. omitted) (‘Katanga and Ngudjolo,
2010’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/7710b6/).
312
Ibid., para. 56 (fn. omitted, emphasis in the original).
313
Ibid., para. 58 (fn. omitted).
interest of the organ. 314 In the latter, the person acts independently of a tri-
bunal organ and outside an investigation. As described at the outset of this
chapter, the extra-investigatory context is of relevance for the purpose of
the chapter. 315
17.5.2.3.1.2.1. Procedural Rules and the Extra-Investigatory Context
The particularity here lies in the lack of an investigatory context and the
ensuing lack of rules that regulate the collection of evidence in such a con-
text. But let us pause for a moment here: the lack of investigatory rules in
an extra-investigatory context is not as clear as it seems at first sight. First,
as already mentioned, 316 legislators may decide to regulate private conduct
in an extra-investigatory context. Second, the inapplicability of procedural
rules to private conduct requires an explanation. It goes to nothing less than
the question of whom procedural rules are addressed to. The source of ex-
clusionary rules can be constitutions, codes or case law, and, in the words
of Thaman and Brodowski, “can be formulated in absolute terms, strictly
requiring the exclusion of any evidence gathered in violation of ‘the law’ or
of certain constitutional or fundamental rights, or can be formulated so as
to allow judges discretion in deciding whether to admit or exclude illegally
gathered evidence”. 317 Take, for instance, § 136a(3) cl. 2 of the German
Code of Criminal Procedure (Strafprozessordnung, ‘StPO’), barring the use
of evidence obtained through prohibited methods of examination (such as
“physical interference, administration of drugs, torment, deception or hyp-
nosis”).
Already in 1952 the German Higher Regional Court (Oberland-
esgericht, ‘OLG’) of Oldenburg decided that § 136a StPO only addressed
State organs. 318 This is also the prevailing view in German legal litera-
314
German scholars want to apply exclusionary rules when the private investigation was initiat-
ed by a state organ, see Martina Matula, Private Ermittlungen, Kovac, Hamburg, 2012,
p. 101 with further references.
315
About the intra-investigatory context: P. Duff, 2004, pp. 163–164, see above note 193, with
case examples from Scotland.
316
See above Section 17.5.1.
317
Thaman and Brodowski, 2020, p. 437, see above note 196 (fn. omitted).
318
Higher Regional Court (Oberlandesgericht, ‘OLG’) Oldenburg, in Neue Juristische Wo-
chenschrift, 1953, p. 1237; Matula, 2012, p. 97, see above note 314. The German Code of
Criminal Procedure is available in the ICC Legal Tools Database (https://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/wc2l2a/).
dressees) 326 to those who potentially ‘use’ the law, that is, the decision
makers (Baden), 327 the arguments are manifold. Therefore, it seems more
like a claim than a justified argument that an exclusionary rule – such as §
136a StPO – is directed at State organs. The larger issue that looms behind
the question whom exclusionary rules are addressed to is the question of
what procedural rules are (compared to rules of substantive criminal law).
Space restrictions again pose limits to an in-depth-elaboration.
17.5.2.3.1.2.2.1. The Relationship Between Procedural and Substantive
Law
Compared to substantive law, procedural law has famously been classified
as “imperative law” vis-à-vis “punitory law”, 328 “secondary rules” vis-à-vis
“primary rules” 329 or as “decision rules” vis-à-vis “conduct rules”. 330 Even
today, some reduce the function of criminal procedure to merely execute
substantive criminal law, 331 on the basis that substance was logically ante-
rior to procedure. 332 However, a clear (hierarchical) division between sub-
stantive criminal law and procedure is neither possible nor desirable in a
legal system. 333 It may even be viewed as a mere semantic distinction – not
326
Peter Noll, Gesetzgebungslehre, Rowohlt, Reinbek bei Hamburg, 1973, pp. 172 ff.
327
Eberhard Baden, Gesetzgebung und Gesetzesanwendung im Kommunikationsprozeß, Nomos,
Baden-Baden, 1977, p. 69.
328
Jeremy Bentham, An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation, Batoche
Books, Kitchener, 2000 [1781], p. 241.
329
Herbert L.A. Hart, The Concept of Law, second edition, Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1994,
pp. 79–99.
330
Meir Dan-Cohen, “Decision Rules and Conduct Rules: On Acoustic Separation in Criminal
Law”, in Harvard Law Review, 1984, vol. 97, no. 3, pp. 625–677.
331
Karel De Meester, The Investigation Phase in International Criminal Procedure (Intersentia,
Cambridge, Antwerp, Portland, 2015, p. 100; Gunther Arzt, “Der Internationale Straf-
gerichtshof und die formelle Wahrheit”, in Jörg Arnold et al. (eds.), Festschrift für Albin
Eser, C.H. Beck, München, 2005, pp. 691–692 with further references.
332
Herbert L. Packer, “Two Models of the Criminal Process”, in University of Pennsylvania
Law Review, 1964, vol. 113, no. 1, pp. 1–69 (1, 3); Joshua Dressler, Alan C. Michaels, and
Ric Simmons, Understanding Criminal Procedure, Volume One: Investigation, third edition,
Carolina Academic Press, Durham, 2017, § 1.01.
333
In a similar vein Heike Jung, “Anmerkungen zum Verhältnis des materiellen Strafrechts
zum Strafverfahrensrecht”, in Goltdammer’s Archiv für Strafrecht, 2019, pp. 259 ff. In fact,
most legal systems “are more concerned about procedural rights than about rights to a sub-
stantive law”, George P. Fletcher, Basic Concepts of Criminal Law, Oxford University Press,
1998, p. 9.
more and not less. 334 This is especially true at the international level, where
the concept of international criminal justice is still controversial, especially
amongst the Realist school. 335 Moreover, there is not even a coherent defi-
nition of “international criminal law”, 336 which “has not evolved in a linear,
cohesive, consistent, or logical fashion” 337 and inevitably leads to an amal-
gamation of international criminal law and international criminal justice.
The retributive or deterrent effect of punishment in international criminal
law has always been dependent on the perception of international criminal
trials. 338 Another telling example of the maceration of the substance-
procedure divide at the international level is the application of the principle
of non-retroactivity (nullum crimen, nulla poena sine lege praevia) 339 to
procedural rules. While at the domestic level, this rule is usually only ap-
plied to matters of substance rather than procedure, 340 the ICC Statute ex-
334
Klaus Volk, Prozeßvoraussetzungen im Strafrecht, Verlag Rolf Gremer, Ebelsbach, 1978,
p. 4.
335
Paul Roberts, “Comparative Law for International Criminal Justice”, in David Nelken and
Esin Örücü (eds.), Comparative Law – A Handbook, Hart Publishing, Oxford and Portland,
Oregon, 2007, p. 341; Andreas Werkmeister, Straftheorien im Völkerstrafrecht, Nomos, Ba-
den-Baden, 2015, p. 31; M. Cherif Bassiouni, “The Discipline of International Criminal
Law”, in M. Cherif Bassiouni (ed.), International Criminal Law, vol. 1, third edition, Marti-
nus Nijhoff, Leiden, 2008, p. 26, all with further references.
336
Roberts, 2007, p. 342, see above note 335; Jackson and Summers, 2012, p. 112, see above
note 253.
337
Bassiouni, 2008, pp. 17–18, see above note 335.
338
Francis Biddle, In Brief Authority, Greenwood Press, Westport, 1962/1972, p. 372; Patricia
M. Wald, “Running the Trial of the Century”, Cardozo Law Review, 2005–6, vol. 27,
pp. 1559, 1574; Geoffrey Lawrence, “Nuremberg Trial”, in Guénaël Mettraux (ed.), Per-
spectives on the Nuremberg Trial, Oxford University Press, 2008, pp. 290, 292; Margaret M.
de Guzman and Timothy Kelly, “The International Criminal Court is Legitimate Enough to
Deserve Support”, in Temple International and Comparative Law Journal, 2019, vol. 33,
p. 402.
339
Claus Roxin and Luis Greco, Strafrecht Allgemeiner Teil, vol. 1, fifth edition, C.H. Beck,
München, 2020, § 5 mn. 10.
340
Bruce Broomhall, “Article 51”, in Kai Ambos (ed.), Rome Statute of the ICC – A Commen-
tary, fourth edition, C.H. Beck, Hart, Nomos, München et al., 2021, pp. 1592–1613, mn. 33;
Alexander Heinze, “Tor zu einer anderen Welt”, in Bock et al. (eds), Strafrecht als interdis-
ziplinäre Wissenschaft (Nomos, Baden-Baden, 2015, p. 199 with further references. A retro-
active application of procedural rules is usually nevertheless prohibited through the rule of
law, see ibid. pp. 199–200.
341
ICC Statute, Article 51(4), see above note 182. In the same vein, but less explicit, see ICTY,
Rules of Procedure and Evidence, 8 July 2015, IT/32/Rev.50, Rule 6(D) (‘ICTY RPE’)
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/30df50/); ICTR, Rules of Procedure and Evidence, 13 May
2015, Rule 6(c) (‘ICTR RPE’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/c6a7c6/) and Special Tribu-
nal for Lebanon (‘STL’), Rules of Procedure and Evidence, 20 March 2009, Rule 5(H)
(‘STL RPE’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/3773bf/). See, generally, Philipp Ambach,
“The ‘Lessons Learnt’ process at the ICC – a suitable vehicle for procedural improve-
ments?”, in Zeitschrift für Internationale Strafrechtsdogmatik, 2016, vol. 11, p. 855.
342
Albeit with the qualification “to the detriment of the person who is being investigated or
prosecuted or who has been convicted” (ICC Statute, Article 51(4), see above note 182),
which allows the retroactive application of amendments to the RPE in exceptional cases, as
it has been passionately discussed in the context of the application of the amended Rule 68,
ICC RPE (“Prior recorded testimony”) in the case against Ruto and Sang before the ICC, see
in more detail Kai Ambos, Treatise on International Criminal Law: Volume III: Internation-
al Criminal Procedure, Oxford University Press, 2016, pp. 497–499.
343
Ofer Malcai and Ronit Levine-Schnur, “When Procedure Takes Priority: A Theoretical
Evaluation of the Contemporary Trends in Criminal Procedure and Evidence Law”, in Ca-
nadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence, 2017, vol. 30, no. 1, p. 194.
344
Hans-Ludwig Schreiber, “Die Zulässigkeit der rückwirkenden Verlängerung von Verjäh-
rungsfristen früher begangener Delikte”, in Zeitschrift für die gesamte Strafrechtswissen-
schaft, 1968, vol. 80, p. 366; see also Volk, 1978, p. 56, see above note 334.
345
Malcai and Levine-Schnur, 2017, p. 201, see above note 343.
346
Campbell, Ashworth, and Redmayne, 2019, pp. 42 ff., see above note 107.
347
See above Section 17.5.2.2.3.1.
the remedy theory. 348 Malcai and Levine-Schnur call this the “ex-post and
ex-ante perspectives” of “substance-procedure dilemmas”, which is in the
case of exclusionary rules: “creating significant incentives to avoid the vio-
lation of rights without making the substantive outcome of trial strictly
conditional on the legality or constitutionality of the (probative) evidence”.
German courts have addressed this dilemma by embracing it and
drawing (or, at least, attempting to draw) a clear line between procedure
and substance. In that line, the main reason for a rejection of any exclu-
sionary rule in the case of private acts is a plain reference to the fact that
private individuals who act illegally against other persons commit
crimes. 349 Thus, there would be no need for other means of sanctions. This
argument, however, cannot be transferred to the situation at hand, namely
private individuals, non-official investigations, and the international con-
text. First, because the international or transnational context makes the
identification of the respective criminal offense considerably difficult. Se-
cond, and more importantly, what this view lays bare is the premise – prob-
ably influenced by German dogmatic – of a clear distinction between sub-
stantive and procedural law. 350 In reality, the argument goes like this: we
have a sanction from substantive law, why apply a procedural one? This
distinction, however, is not only domestically controversial, but even more
at the international level, as I have shown.
17.5.2.3.1.2.2.2. Exclusionary Rules: Conduct Rules, Decision Rules or
Both?
A conceptual visualisation of these dilemmas is provided by Meir Dan-
Cohen’s (albeit controversial) 351 distinction between “decision rules” vis-à-
vis “conduct rules”. Drawing on previous dichotomies (or, less strictly, dis-
tinctions), for Dan-Cohen there are laws addressed to the general public –
the citizens – that are designed to shape people’s behaviour (conduct con-
trol) and laws that are addressed to officials that provide guidelines for
348
See above Section 17.5.2.2.2.
349
Matula, 2012, p. 150, see above note 314, with further references.
350
In that vein, see Theodor Kleinknecht, “Die Beweisverbote im Strafprozeß”, in Neue Juristi-
sche Wochenschrift, 1966, p. 1542.
351
See the critical comments of Kyron Huigens, Samuel W. Buell, Anne M. Coughlin, Luís
Duarte d’Almeida, Adil Ahmad Hague, Eric J. Miller and Malcolm Thorburn, in Paul H.
Robinson, Stephen P. Garvey and Kimberly Kessler Ferzan (eds.), Criminal Law Conversa-
tions, Oxford University Press, 2009, pp. 12 ff.
their decisions. The former, imply instructing the public about the required
conduct and by issuing threats to secure compliance. The latter are made
‘with respect’ to members of the general public. They are designed to au-
thorise, constrain, or otherwise guide officials in the wielding of the State’s
power (“power control”). Dan-Cohen emphasises that “communicating to
legally trained officials suggests a different style than communicating to
the legally untutored general public”. Thus, the guidelines “may be en-
hanced by the use of a technical, esoteric terminology that is incomprehen-
sible to the public at large”.
Taking these characteristics of decision rules together, on its face,
rules of procedure and evidence fall into the category of decision rules, “on
the grounds that they concern the basis for the legal conduct of trials as in-
terpreted by judges and lawyers”. 352 If this were the case, procedural rules
would not be addressed to private individuals. Yet, this general observation
might be ill-suited for exclusionary rules, since those do regulate conduct.
The question is whether exclusionary rules are addressed to public officials,
regardless of their conduct regulation – in that case, they are decision rules,
or whether they regulate a conduct, regardless of their nature as procedural
rules that generally address public officials – in that case, they are conduct
rules. To be fair, upon application of Dan-Cohen’s theoretical model, the
characteristics of exclusionary rules overwhelmingly seem to point in the
direction of decision rules. Yet, Dan-Cohen himself admits that his dichot-
omy is theoretical, and unfolds in a more nuanced fashion in the ‘real
world’. Thus, the question of whether exclusionary rules are conduct rules
or decision rules might not have a clear answer after all. As Dan-Cohen
puts it: “Any given rule may be a conduct rule, a decision rule, or both. The
mere linguistic form in which a legal rule is cast does not determine the
category to which it belongs”. 353
A central element for the differing appearance of both conduct rules
and decision rules is what Dan-Cohen calls “acoustic separation”, which –
at least theoretically – “ensures that conduct rules cannot, as such, affect
decisions; similarly, decision rules cannot, as such, influence conduct”. 354
This is different in the real world:
352
A. Duff et al., 2007, p. 276, see above note 145.
353
Meir Dan-Cohen, “Decision Rules and Conduct Rules – On Acoustic Separation in Criminal
Law”, in Paul H. Robinson, Stephen P. Garvey, Kimberly Kessler Ferzan (eds.), Criminal
Law Conversations, Oxford University Press, 2009, p. 4.
354
Ibid., p. 4.
355
Ibid.
356
Malcai and Levine-Schnur, 2017, p. 201 with fn. 55, see above note 343.
357
Dan-Cohen, 1984, pp. 634–635, see above note 330.
358
Heinze, 2014, pp. 34 ff., see above note 110.
359
Christoph Safferling, International Criminal Procedure, Oxford University Press, 2012,
p. 112.
360
Ibid.
361
In the same vein, see Swoboda, Verfahrens- und Beweisstrategien, Nomos, Baden-Baden,
2013, p. 203, seeing no alternative to a case-by-case approach.
362
Safferling, 2012, p. 110, see above note 359.
363
ICC OTP, Policy Paper on the Interests of Justice, 1 September 2007, p. 7, fn. 9 (https://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/bb02e5/).
364
Safferling, 2012, p. 111, see above note 359.
365
Kristina D. Rutledge, “Spoiling Everything – But for Whom? Rules of Evidence and Inter-
national Criminal Proceedings”, in Regent University Law Review, 2003-2004, vol. 16, no. 1,
pp. 151–189 (162–163).
366
Robert Christensen, “Getting to Peace by Reconciling Notions of Justice: The Importance of
Considering Discrepancies Between Civil and Common Legal Systems in the Formation of
the International Criminal Court”, in UCLA Journal of International Law and Foreign Af-
fairs, 2001-2002, vol. 6, p. 414.
367
Daniel Terris, Cesare P.R. Romano, Leigh Swigart, The International Judge, Oxford Univer-
sity Press, Oxford, 2007, pp. 104–105. See, for instance, the “Judge-Legislator” model
known from the ad hoc Tribunals, see Fabricio Guariglia, “The Rules of Procedure and Evi-
dence for the International Criminal Court: A New Development in International Adjudica-
tion of Individual Criminal Responsibility”, in Antonio Cassese, Paola Gaeta and John
R.W.D. Jones (eds.), The Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court; A Commentary,
vol. II, Oxford University Press, 2002, p. 1116.
does not imply, however, that such rules need not be compre-
hensible to citizens; indeed, the comprehensibility of the pro-
ceedings is still a precondition of a just public trial. If the trial
is to address citizens in legal and moral terms which they can
understand, the rules for courts must also be rules for citizens,
in that they must be articulated in a way that connects appro-
priately with the ethical language of participants in the trial. 368
Methodically, Duff et al. evade a by-effect of the application of Dan-
Cohen’s models: to miss the forest for the trees. It is so tempting to dive
into the theoretical characteristics of decision rules and conduct rules that it
is very easy to lose sight of what procedural law is really about: to regulate
conduct during the proceedings and a trial respectively. The question of
whom procedural rules are addressed to cannot therefore be answered with-
out the question of what procedural rules are concerned with. It is uncon-
vincing to rely on a principle according to which “the legal process should
signify its insistence that those who enforce the law should also obey the
law”. 369 The argumentum a contrario that those who do not enforce the law
are not obliged to obey the law demonstrates the fallacy of the principle,
and calls for a holistic view on the addressee-issue.
17.5.2.3.1.2.2.3. The Holistic View: The Criminal Process as a System
This holistic view on the addressee-issue has roots in Luhmann’s systems
theory, which has a threefold effect. First, procedural law does not just de-
lineate a bipolar relationship between the law and its addressees, but is a
system. Especially the late Luhmann promoted the idea of sociological sys-
tems, where communication is a central feature. 370 Luhmann relied on the-
ories of systems, as they had developed within biology and cybernetics.
Law, within this theory, is one of society’s sub-systems. 371 Teubner has tak-
en this further, drawing on Luhmann’s version of systems theory, to the
368
A. Duff et al., 2007, p. 276, see above note 145.
369
Per Lord Griffiths in UK HL, R v. Horseferry Road Magistrates’ Court, ex parte Bennett,
[1994] 1 AC 42; Ashworth, 2002, p. 318, see above note 184.
370
Niklas Luhmann, Einführung in die Systemtheorie, Dirk Baecker (ed.), fourth edition, Carl-
Auer, Heidelberg, 2008, pp. 100 ff.; Richard Nobles, and David Schiff, “Taking the Com-
plexity of Complex Systems Seriously”, in The Modern Law Review, 2019, Advance Article,
p. 2.
371
Ibid.; Dietmar Braun, “Rationalisierungskonzepte in der Systemtheorie Niklas Luhmanns
und in der Handlungstheorie Hartmut Essers: Ein Theorienvergleich”, in Rainer Greshoff
and Uwe Schimank (eds.), Integrative Sozialtheorie? Esser – Luhmann – Weber, VS Verlag,
Wiesbaden, 2006, p. 377 with fn. 13.
372
See, for example, Gunther Teubner, “Altera pars audiatur: Law in the Collision of Discours-
es”, in Richard Rawlings (ed.), Law, Society and Economy, Oxford University Press (Clar-
endon Press), Oxford, 1997, chap. 7.
373
Niklas Luhmann, Das Recht der Gesellschaft, Suhrkamp, Frankfurt am Main, 1993-1997,
p. 43; Theresa F. Schweiger, Prozedurales Strafrecht: Zur Bedeutung von Verfahren und
Form im Strafrecht, Studien zum Strafrecht, vol. 91, Nomos, Baden-Baden, 2018, p. 113.
374
Gunther Teubner, “Evolution of Autopoietic Law”, in Gunther Teubner (ed.), Autopoietic
Law: A New Approach to Law and Society, Walter de Gruyter, Berlin and New York, 1988,
p. 17.
375
Ibid., p. 18; Mark van Hoecke, Law as Communication, Hart, Oxford and Portland, 2012,
p. 117.
376
Campbell, Ashworth, and Redmayne, 2019, pp. 2, 11-12, see above note 107; Heinze, 2014,
pp. 114 ff., see above note 110; Alexander Heinze, “Bridge over Troubled Water – A Seman-
tic Approach to Purposes and Goals in International Criminal Justice”, in International
Criminal Law Review, 2018, vol. 18, no. 6, p. 937.
377
Luhmann, 1993-1997, p. 34, see above note 373.
378
Roman Hamel, Strafen als Sprechakt, Duncker & Humblot, Berlin, 2009, pp. 81–82.
expressive function of punishment. I will get back to this a little later, since
this connection becomes vital in international criminal law.
When taking the procedural system and the investigatory process as a
closed system, 379 where everyone is addressed by the relevant rules, the
next step would be to determine the parameters of such a system. I have
done this elsewhere, not only with regard to national systems of criminal
procedure 380 but, especially, with a view to international criminal procedure.
Thus, I will limit myself to some brief remarks. The relevant attempts to
model a procedural system can generally be divided into descriptive and
normative models, although not all of them fit into this distinction and
many of them seem to have an overlap between a rather descriptive or
normative take. 381 The most prominent example of the descriptive model
are Packer’s Crime Control and Due Process Models. Packer’s bifurcated
approach focuses, on the one hand, on the efficient suppression of crime
and, on the other, on fair trial rights and the concept of limited governmen-
tal power. 382 While under “crime control” speed, efficiency and finality are
the overriding values, and any rule or measure compromising such values
is deemed inappropriate, 383 “due process” aims at the protection of the
“most disadvantaged” and thus demands equal treatment regardless of
wealth or social status. 384 Under Packer’s crime control model, the authori-
ty of the criminal justice system is derived from the laws passed by legisla-
tures, whereas under his due process model authority is derived from the
Supreme Court.
379
About procedural law (more concretely, evidence law) as a system, see Roberts and Zuck-
erman, 2010, chap. 1 and p. 188, see above note 192.
380
Heinze, 2014, pp. 92 ff., see above note 110.
381
In more detail, see ibid., pp. 133 ff.
382
Herbert L. Packer, The Limits of the Criminal Sanction, Stanford University Press/Oxford
University Press, Stanford, California and Oxford, 1969, pp. 149–53; see also the accounts
of Yvonne McDermott, Fairness in International Criminal Trials, Oxford University Press,
Oxford, 2016, pp. 9–10; Katja Šugman Stubbs, “An Increasingly Blurred Division between
Criminal and Administrative Law”, in Bruce Ackerman, Kai Ambos, and Hrvoje Sikirić
(eds.), Visions of Justice – Liber Amicorum Mirjan Damaška, Duncker & Humblot, Berlin,
2016, pp. 351–370, 353; Campbell, Ashworth, and Redmayne, 2019, pp. 39 ff., see above
note 107.
383
Cf. Heinze, 2014, p. 134, see above note 110.
384
See Packer, 1969, p. 168, see above note 382.
385
Ibid., pp. 167–168.
386
Ibid., p. 199.
387
Ibid., p. 173.
388
Ibid., p. 158.
389
As opposed to “legal guilt” that could be established beyond a reasonable doubt through
admissible evidence and after considering all the rights and defences of the accused.
390
But see Peter L. Arenella, “Rethinking the Functions of Criminal Procedure: The Warren
and Burger Courts’ Competing Ideologies”, in Georgetown Law Journal, 1983, vol. 72, no.
2, pp. 185–248.
391
Packer, 1969, p. 159, see above note 382.
sible, the conviction of the rest, with a minimum of occasions for challenge,
let alone post-audit”. 392
It is important to clarify that Packer’s Crime Control Model in no
sense authorises broad police abuse, as some authors assert. 393 It is quite
the opposite: Packer’s Crime Control model even imposes ordinary law for
State officials in line with Dicey’s idea of the rule of law. 394 However, it is
fair to say that what the model most fears is a criminal going free just be-
cause of (procedural) mistakes done by the police. 395
17.5.2.3.1.2.2.3.2. Parameters of the System Criminal Process:
Due Process
The Due Process Model, by contrast, is not concerned with “factual guilt”
but with “legal guilt”. 396 This seems to touch upon different understandings
of fairness, on which I will elaborate in the next section. The Due Process
Model aims at the protection of the “most disadvantaged” and thus de-
mands equal treatment regardless of wealth or social status. 397 It places
much less emphasis on efficiency and guilty pleas than the Crime Control
Model and strives to avoid police abuses. 398 Procedural rights like the right
to remain silent and the right to contact counsel are seen as most im-
portant. 399 Unlike the Crime Control Model, the Due Process Model does
not allow separate civil, disciplinary, or criminal actions in cases of prose-
cutorial or police abuses. 400 Therefore, the model provides for “prophylac-
tic and deterrent” 401 exclusionary rules because much police abuse will
392
Ibid., p. 160.
393
Kent Roach, “Four Models of the Criminal Process”, in Journal of Criminal Law & Crimi-
nology, 1999, vol. 89, no. 2, pp. 671–716.
394
Cf. Dicey, 1886 and 1979, pp. 188 ff., see above note 256.
395
United States, New York Court of Appeals, People v. Defore, 12 January 1926, 150 N.E. 585,
587.
396
Packer, 1969, p. 167, see above note 382.
397
Ibid., p. 168.
398
Ibid., p. 180.
399
Ibid., p. 191: “The rationale of exclusion is not that the confession is untrustworthy, but that
it is at odds with the postulates of an accusatory system of criminal justice in which it is up
to the state to make its case against a defendant without forcing him to co-operate in the
process, and without capitalizing on his ignorance of his legal rights”.
400
Ibid., p. 180. About disciplinary sanctions with respect to disclosure failures, see Heinze,
2014, pp. 421 ff., above note 110.
401
Ibid., p. 168.
never reach the stage of a criminal trial. 402 Under the Crime Control Model,
anything that exhausts resources must be avoided, that is, a criminal trial.
This can be done through guilty pleas and plea-bargaining arrangements.
The opposite is the case in the Due Process Model. A criminal trial “should
be viewed not as an undesirable burden but rather as the logical and proper
culmination of the process”. 403 Thus, guilty pleas are not encouraged; 404 the
criminal trial – conceivably based on Luhmann 405 – has an intrinsic value
and is detached from substantive law. 406 The Luhmannesque notion of a
trial (and of proceedings) renders it possible that within the confines of the
Due Process Model, exclusionary rules also apply when evidence was ille-
gally obtained by private individuals.
Packer’s categorisation served as a basis for further elaborations, for
example, taking into account rehabilitation and societal stability, 407 focus-
ing on cases that never reach the courtroom, 408 emphasising more strongly
the protection of innocents, 409 and the interests of victims. 410 Damaška, in
402
Ibid., p. 180.
403
Ibid., p. 224.
404
Ibid.
405
Niklas Luhmann, Legitimation durch Verfahren, Suhrkamp, Frankfurt a. M., 1983 [first edi-
tion published by Hermann Luchterhand Verlag in 1969], pp. 30–31 (“Verfahren finden eine
Art generelle Anerkennung, die unabhängig ist vom Befriedigungswert der einzelnen Ent-
scheidung, und diese Anerkennung zieht die Hinnahme und Beachtung verbindlicher Ent-
scheidungen nach sich”); see also Gerson Trüg, “Die Position des Opfers im Völkerstrafver-
fahren vor dem IStGH – Ein Beitrag zu einer opferbezogenen verfahrenstheoretischen Be-
standsaufnahme”, in Zeitschrift für die gesamte Strafrechtswissenschaft, 2013, vol. 125, no.
1, p. 78.
406
See Packer, 1969, p. 217, sees above note 382 (“Many of the limitations on substantive
criminal enactments safeguard us against being punished for a mere propensity to commit
crime”).
407
John Griffiths, “Ideology in Criminal Procedure or A Third ‘Model’ of the Criminal Process”,
in Yale Law Journal, 1969-1970, vol. 79, no. 3, pp. 359–417.
408
Satnam Choongh, “Policing the Dross – A Social Disciplinary Model of Policing”, in British
Journal of Criminology, 1998, vol. 38, no. 4, p. 625.
409
Keith A. Findley, “Toward a New Paradigm of Criminal Justice: How the Innocence Move-
ment Merges Crime Control and Due Process”, in Texas Tech Law Review, 2008-2009, vol.
41, pp. 141 ff.
410
Kent Roach, 1999, p. 672, see above note 393; Hadar Aviram, “Packer in Context: Formal-
ism and Fairness in the Due Process Model”, in Law and Social Inquiry, 2011, vol. 36, no. 1,
p. 241. See also Trüg, 2013, p. 79, see above note 405, who however neglects existing pro-
cedural models which take the role of the victim into consideration. See, generally, Ambos,
2016, p. 7, see above note 342.
his seminal The Faces of Justice, 411 developed a set of models based on
attitudes towards State authority and on concepts of government. 412 It goes
beyond the scope of this chapter to also apply those to the question of ex-
clusionary rules.
17.5.2.3.1.3. Intermediate Conclusion
There are different investigatory contexts when private individuals collect
evidence that eventually may be used before an ICT. The inter-
investigatory context (international investigation – domestic investigation);
the intra-investigatory context (internal investigation by a private individu-
al); and the extra-investigatory context (collection of evidence by a private
individual outside any investigation). I raised the question whether the pro-
cedural regime, especially exclusionary rules, maybe applicable in the in-
ter-investigatory, intra-investigatory and extra-investigatory contexts. The
inter-investigatory context turned out to be the least problematic. In the in-
tra-investigatory context, there is an attribution of the private individual to
an organ of the ICT (usually, the OTP) that may occur rather openly
through a utilisation of the individual in the collection process, that is, ab
initio; or through an ex post attribution, when the individual acted in the
interest of the organ. In the latter, a person acts independently of an ICT-
organ and outside an investigation. It is the extra-investigatory context that
is the neuralgic point of exclusionary rules applied before ICTs. This sec-
tion was merely concerned with the admittedly rather simple question of
whether exclusionary rules apply in this setting. As I have demonstrated,
the allegedly simple question unfolded into an analysis that entered the
depth of procedural law theory. Through norm theory (Dan-Cohen) and
systems theory (Luhmann and Teubner), combined with procedural theory
(Packer), I have laid bare a wide-ranging controversy about the addressees
of procedural rules. I conclude that a bipolar legislator-addressee relation-
ship is fruitless. Instead, the addressee of procedural law is the process as a
411
“[A] key work in the field of comparative procedure”, Steven G. Calabresi, “The Compara-
tive Constitutional Law Scholarship of Professor Mirjan Damaška: A Tribute”, in Bruce
Ackerman, Kai Ambos, and Hrvoje Sikirić (eds.), Visions of Justice – Liber Amicorum Mir-
jan Damaška, Duncker & Humblot, Berlin, 2016, p. 107.
412
Mirjan Damaška, The Faces of Justice and State Authority, Yale University Press, New Ha-
ven and London, 1986, pp. 8–12. For a comprehensive overview of the reviews of this book
see Izhak Englard, “The Faces of Justice and State Authority: A Review of the Reviews”, in
Bruce Ackerman, Kai Ambos, and Hrvoje Sikirić (eds.), Visions of Justice – Liber Amicorum
Mirjan Damaška, Duncker & Humblot, Berlin, 2016, pp. 199–211.
system. Rules apply to everyone within that system – and might even apply
beyond that system through transgressive communication (just as the
judgment communicates not only with the accused and victim but with so-
ciety as a whole). Even when we divide the procedural law into a Crime
Control and Due Process function, with the former addressing the police
and prosecution, the latter applies to everyone that is involved in the inves-
tigatory process when this involvement eventually has an impact on due
process. Understood this way, the exclusionary rules also apply to private
conduct.
17.5.2.3.2. Rationales for the Exclusion of Illegally Obtained Evidence
Before International Criminal Tribunals in the Face of
Private Conduct
Due to the controversy around the application of exclusionary rules to the
extra-investigatory context, the rationales for exclusionary rules again be-
come the focus of attention – on its face because of the theoretical gap left
by the controversy concerning the application of exclusionary rules. It is
worth mentioning that this gap is larger in the civil law tradition than in the
common law tradition. In the former, the application of legal principles is
normally derived from or based on written law. 413 Thus, the exclusion of
evidence must be based on written exclusionary rules. The generality of
legal rules is high—codes in the civil law tradition are said to be rather a
collection of abstract principles than specific rules for particular situations
or even concrete cases. 414 Unsurprisingly, in Germany, most recent works
about the exclusion of illegally obtained evidence by private individuals
413
Brianne McGonigle Leyh, Procedural Justice? Victim Participation in International Crimi-
nal Proceedings, Intersentia, Cambridge et al., 2011, p. 70; Michael Bohlander, “Language,
Culture, Legal Traditions, and International Criminal Justice”, in Journal of International
Criminal Justice, 2014, vol. 12, no. 3, pp. 494 ff.; on the importance of truth-seeking, see,
for example, Michèle-Laure Rassat, Traité de procedure pénale, Presses Univ. de France,
Paris, 2001, p. 297; Frédéric Desportes and Laurence Lazerges-Cousquer, Traité de
procédure pénale, fourth edition, Economica, Paris, 2016, mn. 550; Hans-Heiner Kühne,
Strafprozessrecht, ninth edition, C.F. Müller, Heidelberg, 2015, mn. 1, 628, 751; Peters,
1985, pp. 16, 82–83, see above note 113.
414
Joseph Sanders, “Law and Legal Systems”, in Edgar F. Borgatta and Rhonda J.V. Montgom-
ery (eds.), Encyclopedia of Sociology, vol. III, second edition, Macmillan, New York et al.,
2000, pp. 1544, 1546; Heinze, 2014, p. 109, see above note 110. For a German perspective,
see Michael Bohlander, “Radbruch Redux: The Need for Revisiting the Conversation be-
tween Common and Civil Law at Root Level at the Example of International Criminal Jus-
tice”, in Leiden Journal of International Law, 2011, vol. 24, no. 2, pp. 393–410, 402.
revolve around the question whether § 136a StPO, as written law, is appli-
cable 415 – and not so much about what could be the rationale for excluding
or admitting such evidence. While the civil law tradition emphasises codi-
fication, the chief source 416 of law in common law legal systems is the case
law of the courts. 417 Procedural rules are especially set forth in the case law
in a direct (or indirect) application of the constitution (if there is one). 418 As
a result, the rationales for exclusionary rules have a much more prominent
position in common law than in civil law. Yet, here too, the temptation is
high to deny those rationales practical relevance, since they do not allow
for a mechanical application of exclusionary rules. Roberts and Zuckerman
made a similar observation and expressed it more eloquently:
the impact of foundational principles on the day-to-day prac-
tice of the courts has been blunted by common lawyers’ ex-
cessive preoccupation with technical legal definitions. The
traditional textbook treatment of the Law of Evidence may al-
lude to the rationale underpinning particular rules, but discus-
sion then tends to proceed as though it can be assumed that
the rules are either self-actuating, internally coherent, and ex-
415
See, for example, Sebastian Eckhardt, Private Ermittlungsbeiträge im Rahmen der staatli-
chen Strafverfolgung, Peter Lang, Frankfurt a.M. et al., 2009, pp. 14 ff.; Anja Bienert, Pri-
vate Ermittlungen und ihre Bedeutung auf dem Gebiet der Beweisverwertungsverbote, Sha-
ker, Aachen, 1997, pp. 11 ff.
416
Many observers from the civil law system still ignore that the common law in the respective
legal system has often been replaced by statutory law, see, in the same vein, Massimo
Donini, “An impossible exchange? Versuche zu einem Dialog zwischen civil lawyers und
common lawyers über Gesetzlichkeit, Moral und Straftheorie”, in Jahrbuch der Juristischen
Zeitgeschichte, 2017, vol. 18, no. 1, p. 342. See also Geoffrey Samuel, A Short Introduction
to Judging and to Legal Reasoning, Edward Elgar, Celtenham, Northampton, MA, 2016,
p. 31: “The common law has of course traditionally been regarded as being based upon cas-
es and precedents. Before the 19th century this was largely true, but today the position is
dramatically different. By far the most important source of law in England is legislation and
the great majority of cases decided by the courts involve the interpretation and application of
a legislative text”; Carissa Byrne Hessick, “The Myth of Common Law Crimes”, in Virginia
Law Review, 2019, vol. 105, no. 5, pp. 965–1024.
417
Michael Zander, “Forms and Functions of the Sources of the Law from a Common Law
Perspective”, in Albin Eser and Christiane Rabenstein (eds.), Neighbours in Law – Are
Common Law and Civil Law Moving Closer Together?, Papers in Honour of Barbara Hu-
ber on her 65th Birthday, Edition iuscrim, Freiburg i. Br., 2001, pp. 32, 43; Heinze, 2014,
p. 111, see above note 110.
418
David Alan Sklansky, “Quasi-Affirmative Rights in Constitutional Criminal Procedure”, in
Virginia Law Review, 2002, vol. 88, no. 6, pp. 1229–1300; Jerold H. Israel and Wayne R.
LaFave, Criminal Procedure, seventh edition, Thomson West, St. Paul, Minnesota, 2006,
pp. 3 ff.; Matthew Lippman, Criminal Procedure, second edition, Sage, London, 2014, p. 5.
uals act, the criminal prosecution option becomes even more relevant, as is
one of the prevailing objections against exclusionary rules in an extra-
investigatory context in Germany. However, the criminal prosecution ar-
gument needs to be treated with caution at the international level – as ar-
gued earlier. 425
Second, it is doubtful whether the exclusion of evidence is really the
best vindication for police wrongdoing, especially when the individual of-
ficer is more concerned with making an arrest and/or has no personal inter-
est in a conviction. 426 This counter-argument is even stronger at the interna-
tional level, considering the individual motivations of private investigators,
often acting in the interests of their donors. Third, in many criminal justice
systems, officials who violate an exclusionary rule never learn whether or
not the evidence they obtained is excluded. 427 This argument is especially
true at the international level – for instance, when CIJA collects evidence
and it is unclear before which national or international court this evidence
might be used. 428 This leads to the fourth counter-argument: if it is doubtful
whether public officials know in fact the exclusionary rule that might apply.
This is all the more true in a context where it is unclear where the evidence
might be admitted.
ICTs have reacted to the weakness of the deterrence theory, albeit in
the inter-investigatory context. In Brđanin, the Trial Chamber admitted
transcripts of illegally intercepted telephone conversations by the security
forces of Bosnia and Herzegovina with the argument that the “function of
this Tribunal is not to deter and punish illegal conduct by domestic law en-
forcement authorities by excluding illegally obtained evidence”. 429
425
See above Section 17.5.2.3.1.2.2.1.
426
Thaman and Brodowski, 2020, p. 458, see above note 196; Gless and Macula, 2019, p. 355,
see above note 8.
427
Ibid.
428
In more detail Heinze, 2019, pp. 171 ff., see above note 87; William H. Wiley, “Internation-
al(ised) Criminal Justice at a Crossroads: The Role of Civil Society in the Investigation of
Core International Crimes and the ‘CIJA Model’”, in Morten Bergsmo and Carsten Stahn
(eds.), Quality Control in Fact-Finding, second edition, TOAEP, Brussels, 2020, pp. 547 ff.
429
See ICTY, Prosecutor v. Radoslav Brđanin, Decision on the Defence “Objection to Intercept
Evidence”, 3 October 2003, IT-99-36-T, para. 63 (https://legal-tools.org/doc/7efabf/); see al-
so ICTY, Prosecutor v. Kordić & Čerkez, Transcript, 2 February 2000, IT-95-14/2-T, 13671
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/298d4d/): “It’s not the duty of this Tribunal to discipline
armies or anything of that sort”. Pitcher, 2018, p. 291, see above note 192, with further ref-
erences.
430
George C. Christie, Philosopher Kings? The Adjudication of Conflicting Human Rights and
Social Values, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2011, p. 15.
431
Kant, 1991, p. 57 [231], see above note 163.
432
Alan W. Norrie, Law, Ideology and Punishment, Kluwer, London, 1991, p. 51 (emphasis in
the original).
433
Brian Orend, “Kant on International Law and Armed Conflict”, in Canadian Journal of Law
and Jurisprudence, 1998, vol. 11, no. 2, p. 335.
434
Fernando R. Teson, “Kantianism and Legislation”, in Annual Review of Law and Ethics,
2008, vol. 16, p. 283.
435
Klaus Rogall, “§ 136a StPO”, in Hans-Joachim Rudolphi et al. (eds.), Systematischer Kom-
mentar zur Strafprozessordnung, vol. II, §§ 94–136a StPO, fifth edition, Wolters Kluwer
(Carl Heymanns), Köln, 2016, mn. 13.
436
See above Section 17.5.2.2.2.
437
Rogall, 2016, mn. 13, see above note 435.
438
Ibid., mn. 14.
439
Jürgen Habermas, “Kant’s Idea of Perpetual Peace with the Benefit of 200 Years’ Hindsight”,
in James Bohman and Matthias Lutz-Bachmann (eds.), Perpetual Peace – Essays on Kant’s
Cosmopolitan Ideal, MIT Press, Cambridge, 1997, p. 137 (“as constitutional norms they en-
joy a positive validity (of instituted law), but as rights they are attributed to each person as a
human being they acquire a above positive value”).
440
Ibid.
441
Ibid.
442
As defined in the ICC Statute, Article 7(3), see above note 182, the term ‘gender’ “refers to
the two sexes, male and female, within the context of society” (fn. added).
443
Ibid., Article 21(3).
444
See also Adriaan Bos, “1948–1998: The Universal Declaration of Human Rights and the
Statute of the International Criminal Court”, in Fordham International Law Journal, 1998–
99, vol. 22, no. 2, pp. 229, 234.
445
Rebecca Young, “‘Internationally Recognized Human Rights’ Before the International Crim-
inal Court”, in International and Comparative Law Quarterly, 2011, vol. 60, no. 1, pp. 189–
90; Michael Reisman, “Sovereignty and Human Rights in Contemporary International Law”,
in American Journal International Law, 1990, vol. 84, no. 4, pp. 866, 872: “The internation-
al human rights program is more than a piecemeal addition to the traditional corpus of inter-
national law, more than another chapter sandwiched into traditional textbooks of interna-
tional law. By shifting the fulcrum of the system from the protection of sovereigns to the
protection of people, it works qualitative changes in virtually every component.”; James D.
Fry, “International Human Rights Law in Investment Arbitration: Evidence of International
Law’s Unity”, in Duke Journal of Comparative & International Law, 2007–08, vol. 18, no.
1, p. 123: “The possibility exists that the field of human rights is an extra-special type of
specialized regime that impacts all aspects of international law, and should not be seen as
just another specialized body of law that other specialized bodies might use to reinterpret
their own rules in its light, but is one that requires other specialized bodies to be reinterpret-
ed in its light”; Dinah Shelton, “Normative Hierarchy in International Law”, in American
Journal International Law, 2006, vol. 100, no. 2, pp. 291, 294; Stefanie Schmahl, “Human
Dignity in International Human Rights, Humanitarian and International Criminal Law: A
Comparative Approach”, in Eric Hilgendorf and Mordechai Kremnitzer (eds.), Human Dig-
nity and Criminal Law, Duncker & Humblot, Berlin, 2018, p. 101; Yvonne McDermott,
“The Influence of International Human Rights Law on International Criminal Procedure”, in
Within the context of the ICC Statute, human rights reached the sta-
tus of basic rights. In this context, human rights violations “are no longer
condemned and fought from the moral point of view in an unmediated way,
but are rather prosecuted as criminal actions within the framework of state-
organised legal order according to the institutionalised legal procedures”. 446
The Statute translates general human rights norms “into the language of
criminal law”, not only by defining the core international crimes, but also
by providing procedural guarantees and a canonical formulation of the role
of internationally recognised human rights. 447 The Appeals Chamber of the
ICC has ruled, concerning the role of human rights in the interpretation of
the Statute, that
[h]uman rights underpin the Statute; every aspect of it […]. Its
provisions must be interpreted, and more importantly applied
in accordance with internationally recognized human rights;
first and foremost, in the context of the Statute, the right to a
fair trial, a concept broadly perceived and applied, embracing
the judicial process in its entirety. 448
In other words, human rights can certainly be seen as the mainstay of
the ICC Statute. 449 The mere existence and work of the Court help to pro-
mote human rights by: creating a historical record for past wrongs; 450 offer-
ing a forum for victims to voice their opinions and receive satisfaction and
compensation for past violations; 451 creating judicial precedent; and deter-
Philipp Kastner (ed.), International Criminal Law in Context, Routledge, London, New York,
2018, p. 288.
446
Habermas, 1997, p. 140, see above note 439.
447
ICC Statute, Article 21(3), see above note 182: “The application and interpretation of law
pursuant to this article must be consistent with internationally recognized human rights”.
448
Lubanga, 2006, para. 37, see above note 114. The ICC Pre-Trial Chamber I referred to that
Judgment in Prosecutor v. Laurent Gbagbo, Pre-Trial Chamber I, Decision on the fitness of
Laurent Gbagbo to take part in the proceedings before this Court, 2 November 2012, ICC-
02/11-01/11-286-Red, para. 45 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/4729b8/).
449
Benjamin Perrin, “Searching for Law While Seeking Justice: The Difficulties of Enforcing
International Humanitarian Law in International Criminal Trials”, in Ottawa Law Review,
2007–08, vol. 39, no. 2, p. 398.
450
United Nations Security Council, Statement of Judge Claude Jorda, UN Doc. S/PV.4161, 20
June 2000, p. 3 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/365c3f/); Jens David Ohlin, “A Meta-
Theory of International Criminal Procedure: Vindicating the Rule of Law”, in UCLA Jour-
nal of International Law & Foreign Affairs, 2009, vol. 77, no. 1, pp. 86 ff. For more detail,
see Heinze, 2014, pp. 218 ff., see above note 110.
451
Ben Swart, “Foreword”, in Journal of International Criminal Justice, 2008, vol. 6, no. 1,
pp. 87, 100; Minna Schrag, “Lessons Learned from ICTY Experience”, in Journal of Inter-
ring potential violators of the gravest crimes 452 while punishing past of-
fenders. 453 Thus, human rights norms in the Statute “provide a blueprint for
the common good of a community” in the Aristotelian sense 454 – which is,
at the same time, the link to Habermas’s interpretation of Republicanism. 455
Kant laid the foundations for all current conceptions of human dignity and
world peace. For Kant, a permanent peace is predicated on the recognition
and respect for human rights, and gross human rights violations rights must
be stigmatised as serious wrongs and punished. 456 Kant’s language in this
regard resonates in the following statement by the ICTY Appeals Chamber:
A State-sovereignty-oriented approach has been gradually
supplanted by a human-being oriented approach. Gradually
the maxim of Roman law hominum causa omne jus constitu-
tum est (all law is created for the benefit of human beings) has
gained a firm foothold in the international community as well.
It follows that in the area of armed conflict the distinction be-
tween interstate wars and civil wars is losing its value as far as
human beings are concerned. Why protect civilians from bel-
ligerent violence, or ban rape, torture or the wanton destruc-
tion of hospitals, churches, museums or private property, as
well as proscribe weapons causing unnecessary suffering
when two sovereign States are engaged in war, and yet refrain
from enacting the same bans or providing the same protection
when armed violence has erupted “only” within the territory
national Criminal Justice, 2004, vol. 2, no. 2, pp. 427–28. For Ralph, this helps to constitute
a world society: see Jason Ralph, “International Society, the International Criminal Court
and American Foreign Policy”, in Review of International Studies, 2005, vol. 31, no. 1,
pp. 27 (39).
452
Kai Ambos, Treatise on International Criminal Law, vol. I, Oxford University Press, Oxford,
2013, p. 71.
453
ICTR, The Prosecutor v. Omar Serushago, Trial Chamber, Sentence, 5 February 1999,
ICTR-98-39-S, para. 20 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/e2dddb/); ICTR, The Prosecutor v.
Georges Anderson Nderubumwe Rutaganda, Trial Chamber, Judgement and Sentence, 6 De-
cember 1999, ICTR-96-3-T, para. 455 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/f0dbbb/); ICTR, The
Prosecutor v. Emmanuel Ndindabahizi, Trial Chamber, Judgement and Sentence, 15 July
2004, ICTR-2001-71-I, para. 498 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/272b55/); ICTR, The
Prosecutor v. François Karera, Trial Chamber, Judgement and Sentence, 7 December 2007,
ICTR-01-74-T, para. 571 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/7bc57f/).
454
John M. Czarnetzky and Ronald J. Rychlak, “An Empire of Law: Legalism and the Interna-
tional Criminal Court”, in Notre Dame Law Review, 2003, vol. 79, no. 1, pp. 55, 110.
455
Fernando H. Llano, “European Constitutional Patriotism and Postnational Citizenship in
Jürgen Habermas”, in Archiv für Rechts- und Sozialphilosophie, 2017, vol. 103, no. 4, p. 506.
456
Ambos, 2013, pp. 293, 306, see above note 452.
sis of the integrity of the process is fairness. I have elaborated on this else-
where with Shannon Fyfe. 461
The interrelationship between criminal justice and fairness is obvious.
A judicial or administrative body is tasked with serving the public, and in
serving the public, a government body’s most important higher-order goal
is to treat every member of the public fairly. Especially the juxtaposition of
procedural and substantive fairness is vital for private investigations. Pro-
cedural fairness can be assessed based on a system’s rules 462 and will be
translated into integrity from the perspective of the process. Rights that are
guaranteed by procedures “allow for a system of law to emerge out of a set
of substantive rules and […] minimize arbitrariness”. 463 If the same estab-
lished rules and procedures are applied to all defendants and suspects (or
potential suspects) without bias, then a system can be said to be procedural-
ly fair, regardless of outcomes. To provide an extreme example: the ac-
cused is acquitted due to illegally obtained evidence, even though this evi-
dence proofs his guilt beyond reasonable doubt – a popular counter-
argument against the remedy rationale. 464 However, “equal treatment in-
volves at one extreme the impartial application of existing rules and proce-
dures, regardless of the outcome (procedural justice), and at the other, the
idea that any policies or procedures that have the effect of punishing or
controlling a higher proportion of one social group than another are un-
just”. 465 One might argue, then, “that law and social policy should be ad-
justed so as to achieve equal outcomes”. 466 This is distributive fairness,
which shall be neglected in this chapter. Substantive fairness involves the
protection of substantive rights, such as the right to bodily autonomy, liber-
461
Heinze and Fyfe, 2020, pp. 345 ff., see above note 118; Heinze and Fyfe, 2018, pp. 3 ff., see
above note 110.
462
See, for example, Fuller, 1969, see above note 282; McDermott, 2016, see above note 382.
463
Larry May, Global Justice and Due Process, Cambridge University Press, 2011, p. 52.
464
Zuckerman, 1987, p. 58, see above note 194 (“It is by no means self-evident that acquittal of
the guilty is an appropriate response to earlier police transgressions. Nor is a blanket exclu-
sion capable of achieving a balance between the seriousness of the infringement and the
benefit to the accused”).
465
Loraine Gelsthorpe and Nicola Padfield, “Introduction”, in Loraine Gelsthorpe and Nicola
Padfield (eds.), Exercising Discretion: Decision-making in the criminal justice system and
beyond, Willian Publishing, New York, 2003, p. 12. See also Rebecca E. Hollander-Blumoff,
“Fairness Beyond the Adversary System”, in Fordham Law Review, 2017, vol. 85, no. 5,
pp. 2081–2095.
466
Gelsthorpe and Padfield, 2003, p. 12, see above note 465.
the criminal process (and status afforded to the concept of ‘truth’ altogether)
is outside the scope of this chapter. In Germany, a distinction is made be-
tween procedural truth and substantive truth, which largely corresponds
with the distinction between procedural fairness and substantive fairness. 474
As Weigend notes, “[i]f truth-finding connotes the revelation (or discovery)
of an objective reality, it is the result that legitimizes the process. The judi-
cial process is only the means to discover the hidden, ‘objective’ reality and
should be organized to optimize the chances of finding the ‘piece of
gold’”. 475 He goes on to distinguish this substantive view of truth from
procedural truth, which is “whatever emerges from a fair and rational dis-
course among the parties’, and ‘the content of the rules that determine the
process [are] more important than the outcome itself, and adherence to the-
se rules acquires paramount importance for truth-finding”. 476 Interestingly,
the BGH has explicitly underlined the role of procedural truth in criminal
procedure:
[a]cceptance and legitimacy of criminal judgments are not
based on the trust in a ‘correctness’, understood as a material
truth that is discovered in the course of a criminal trial. Instead,
trust in the ‘procedural truth’ it is both necessary and suffi-
cient. The ‘procedural truth’ is created through a trial that
p. 393. However, it should be stressed that the goals of criminal procedure in Germany and
their relationship are highly disputed, see Dieter Dölling, “Über das Ziel des Strafver-
fahrens”, in Christian Fahl et al. (eds.), Festschrift für Werner Beulke zum 70 Geburtstag,
C.F. Müller, Heidelberg, 2015, pp. 679–87. About the divergent meanings of ‘truth’ in cri-
minal procedure Edda Weslau, “Wahrheit und Legenden: die Debatte über den adversatori-
schen Strafprozess”, in Roland Hefendehl, Tatjana Hörnle and Luis Greco (eds.), Festschrift
für Bernd Schünemann zum 70 Geburtstag, De Gruyter, Berlin, 2014, pp. 1002–1005.
474
In that vein Edda Weßlau, Das Konsensprinzip im Strafverfahren – Leitidee für eine Gesam-
treform?, Nomos, Baden-Baden, 2002, p. 20.
475
See Thomas Weigend, “Should We Search for the Truth, and Who Should Do it?”, in North
Carolina Journal of International Law and Commercial Regulation, 2011, vol. 36, no. 2,
p. 389 (fn. omitted).
476
See ibid., p. 389 (fn. omitted). Weigend cites Jacqueline Hodgson, “Conceptions of the Trial
in Inquisitorial and Adversarial Procedure”, in Antony Duff et al. (eds), The Trial on Trial –
Volume 2: Judgment and calling to account, Hart, Oxford, 2006, p. 225–226. For a general
analysis, see A. Duff et al., 2007, pp. 61 ff., see above note 145. See also Safferling, 2012,
p. 55, see above note 359. From the perspective of communication- and discourse-theory,
see Klaus Rolinski, “Der Grundsatz der Unmittelbarkeit: Garant der Wahrheitsfindung?”, in
Robert Esser et al. (eds.), Festschrift für Hans-Heiner Kühne, C.F. Müller, Heidelberg, 2013,
p. 311; Mariana Sacher, “Diskurstheorie als Legitimation für die Absprachen im Strafverfah-
ren?”, in Roland Hefendehl, Tatjana Hörnle, and Luis Greco, Festschrift für Bernd Schüne-
mann zum 70. Geburtstag, De Gruyter, Berlin, 2014, pp. 959–960.
477
See BGH, Judgment from 10 June 2015 – 2 StR 97/14, in Neue Zeitschrift für Strafrecht
(NStZ) 2016, 52, 58 (author’s translation). The original quote reads:
Akzeptanz und Legitimation strafrichterlicher Urteile werden nicht durch das Vertrauen
auf ‘Richtigkeit’ im Sinne einer im Verfahren gefundenen materiellen Wahrheit be-
gründet. Ausreichend aber auch erforderlich ist das Vertrauen in die ‘prozessuale Wahr-
heit’, die vermittelt wird durch ein rechtsrichtiges, prozessordnungsgemäßes und daher
unter anderem faires Verfahren.
478
Claus Roxin and Bernd Schünemann, Strafverfahrensrecht, twenty-ninth edition, C.H. Beck,
München, 2017, § 11 mn. 4; Bertram Schmitt, “Introduction”, in Lutz Meyer-Goßner and
Bertram Schmitt (eds.), Kommentar zur Strafprozessordnung, sixty-third edition, C.H. Beck,
München, 2020, mn. 19; Klaus Geppert, “Zum ‚fair-trial-Prinzip’ nach Art. 6 Abs. 1 Satz 1
der Europäischen Menschenrechtskonvention”, in Juristische Ausbildung, 1992, pp. 597–
604 (597); Robert Esser, Auf dem Weg zu einem europäischen Strafverfahrensrecht, de Gruy-
ter, Berlin, 2002, p. 401.
479
United States, Constitution of the United States of America, 1787, amendment XIV (https://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/bc3d56/).
480
Ibid., amends. IX, X, XI, XIII.
481
Gary Slapper and David Kelly, The English Legal System, eighth edition, Routledge, Lon-
don, New York, 2017, p. 394 (emphasis in the original). Cicchini argues that the truth as
proof-model is now also applied by prosecutors in the US, see Michael D. Cicchini, “Spin
Doctors: Prosecutor Sophistry and the Burden of Proof”, in University of Cincinnati Law
Review, 2018, vol. 87, no. 2, p. 491.
482
See in more detail Heinze and Fyfe, 2020, p. 348, see above note 118.
483
Pitcher, 2018, p. 281, see above note 192 (“is concerned with the need to ensure a fair trial;
specifically, it appears to be linked to a chamber’s truth-finding task, i.e. the ability of a
chamber to determine the guilt or innocence of accused accurately, or otherwise to ‘trial
fairness’”) with further references.
484
ICTY RPE, Rule 89(D), see above note 341.
485
See above Section 17.5.2.2.3.1.
486
A. Duff et al., 2007, p. 236, see above note 145.
487
The following part is, albeit in modified form, taken from Alexander Heinze, “The Statute of
the International Criminal Court as a Kantian Constitution”, in Morten Bergsmo and Emili-
ano J. Buis (eds.), Philosophical Foundations of International Criminal Law: Correlating
Thinkers, TOAEP, Brussels, 2018, pp. 351–428.
488
See for a definition and in more detail Heinze, 2018, pp. 417 ff., see above note 487. On the
different forms of expressivism in ICL Sander, LJIL, 32 (2019), 851 ff.; Carsten Stahn, A
Critical Introduction to International Criminal Law, Cambridge University Press, Cam-
bridge, 2019, pp. 181–182; on the limits of expressivism Barrie Sander, “The Expressive
Limits of International Criminal Justice: Victim Trauma and Local Culture in the Iron Cage
of the Law”, in International Criminal Law Review, 2019, vol. 19, pp. 1014 ff.; Daniela
Demko, “An Expressive Theory of International Punishment for International Crimes”, in
Florian Jeßberger and Julia Geneuss (eds.), Why punish perpetrators of mass atrocities?
Purposes of punishment in international criminal law, Cambridge University Press, 2020,
pp. 176 ff.
489
Heinze, 2018, pp. 417 ff., see above note 487; Klaus Günther, “Positive General Prevention
and the Idea of Civic Courage in International Criminal Law”, in Florian Jeßberger and Julia
Geneuss (eds.), Why punish perpetrators of mass atrocities? Purposes of punishment in in-
ternational criminal law, Cambridge University Press, 2020, pp. 213 ff.
490
Mark A. Drumbl, Atrocity, Punishment, and International Law, Cambridge University Press,
Cambridge, 2007, pp. 173 ff.; Mark A. Drumbl, “International Punishment from ‘Other’ Per-
spectives”, in Róisín Mulgrew and Denis Abels (eds.), Research Handbook on the Interna-
tional Penal System, Edward Elgar Publishing, Northampton, 2016, p. 386; Jonathan H.
Choi, “Early Release in International Criminal Law”, in Yale Law Journal¸ 2014, vol. 123,
no. 6, p. 1810; Robert D. Sloane, “The Expressive Capacity of International Punishment”, in
Stanford Journal of International Law, 2007, vol. 43, no. 1, p. 44; Kirsten J. Fisher, Moral
Accountability and International Criminal Law, Routledge, London, 2012, pp. 51, 56–63, 65;
Carsten Stahn, “Between ‘Faith’ and ‘Facts’”, in Leiden Journal of International Law, 2012,
vol. 25, no. 2, pp. 251, 279–80; Larry May, Aggression and Crimes Against Peace, Cam-
bridge University Press, Cambridge, 2008, pp. 329 ff. From a German perspective, see also
Klaus Günther, “Criminal Law, Crime and Punishment as Communication”, in Andrew
P. Simester et al. (eds.), Liberal Criminal Theory, Hart, Oxford, 2014, pp. 123 ff. About the
communicative function within the (new) retributivist theories, see Michael Pawlik, “Kritik
der präventionstheoretischen Strafbegründungen”, in Klaus Rogall et al. (eds.), Festschrift
für Rudolphi, Luchterhand, Neuwied, 2004, p. 229.
491
Kai Ambos, “Review Essay: Liberal Criminal Theory”, in Criminal Law Forum, 2017, vol.
28, no. 3, pp. 589, 601.
cape it. 492 That is why international criminal law seeks to achieve retribu-
tive and deterrent effects of punishment through creating a certain percep-
tion of international criminal trials. It is also why the protection of due pro-
cess rights is perceived as crucial in order to restore international peace,
and strengthen the trust of the international society in legal norms (proce-
dure “as an end in itself” 493), and is the reason why Nazi perpetrators were
not executed without trial. Instead, the former President of the US, Harry S.
Truman, remarked at the start of the trials before the International Military
Tribunal at Nuremberg in 1945: “The world should be impressed by the
fairness of the trial. These German murderers must be punished, but only
upon proof of individual guilt at a trial”. 494
It would be detrimental to the expressivist and communicative func-
tion of a public trial, if a conviction rendered by an ICT was based on ille-
gally obtained evidence – irrespective of the status of the person who ob-
tained the evidence. Rogall makes a similar general-preventive, or expres-
sivist argument: trials and judgments respectively have a general-
preventive effect. This effect would be circumvented, if evidence that is
illegally obtained by private individuals could generally be admitted. 495
Rogall combines this argument with an empirical premise: private investi-
492
International criminal law is also “educating society about its past” through the truth-telling
function of international criminal trials, see Mina Rauschenbach, “Individuals Accused of
International Crimes as Delegitimized Agents of Truth”, in International Criminal Justice
Review, 2018, Advance Article, p. 3 with further references.
493
Jonathan Hafetz, Punishing Atrocities Through a Fair Trial, Cambridge University Press,
2018, p. 109.
494
Cited in Francis Biddle, In Brief Authority, Greenwood Press, Westport, 1962/1972, p. 372;
Patricia M. Wald, “Running the Trial of the Century”, in Cardozo Law Review, 2005–6, vol.
27, no. 4, pp. 1559, 1574. US Chief prosecutor Jackson famously argued: “Unless we write
the record of this movement with clarity and precision, we cannot blame the future if in days
of peace it finds incredible the accusatory generalities uttered during war. We must establish
incredible events by credible evidence.”, see Telford Taylor, The Anatomy of the Nuremberg
Trials, Back Bay Books, Boston, 1992, p. 54; Henry T. King, “The Spirit of Nurem-
berg―Idealism”, in Beth A. Griech-Polelle (ed.), The Nuremberg War Crimes Trial and its
Policy Consequences Today, 2nd edn., Nomos, Baden-Baden 2020, p. 5. Or, in the words of
British International Military Tribunal Judge Geoffrey Lawrence, one wanted to punish
“those who were guilty”, to establish “the supremacy of international law over national law”
and to prove “actual facts, in order to bring home to the German people and to the peoples
of the world, the depths of infamy to which the pursuit of total warfare had brought Germa-
ny”, see Geoffrey Lawrence, “Nuremberg Trial”, in Guénaël Mettraux (ed.), Perspectives on
the Nuremberg Trial, Oxford University Press, 2008, pp. 290, 292.
495
Rogall, 2016, mn. 13, see above note 435.
496
Ibid.
497
See above Section 17.5.2.2.2.
498
Henning Radtke, “Beweisverwertungsverbote in Verfahrensstadien vor der Hauptverhand-
lung und die sog. Widerspruchslösung”, in Stephan Barton et al. (eds.), Festschrift für Rein-
hold Schlothauer zum 70. Geburtstag, C.H. Beck, München, 2018, pp. 461 ff.; Hilde Kauf-
mann, Strafanspruch Strafklagerecht, Otto Schwartz, Göttingen, 1968), pp. 9 ff.; Klaus Gün-
ther, “Falscher Friede durch repressives Völkerstrafrecht?”, in Werner Beulke et al. (eds.),
Das Dilemma des rechtsstaatlichen Strafrechts. Berliner Wissenschafts-Verlag, Berlin, 2009,
p. 89 (“Parallel zum öffentlichen Strafanspruch beim nationalstaatlichen Strafrecht wird
auch der völkerrechtliche Strafanspruch nicht im Namen der Verletzten erhoben, sondern im
Namen der Völkergemeinschaft oder im Namen eines Staates, der auf der Grundlage des
Universalitätsprinzips ein Völkerrechtsverbrechen verfolgt”). In detail Kai Ambos, “Straf-
recht und Verfassung: Gibt es einen Anspruch auf Strafgesetze, Strafverfolgung, Strafver-
hängung?”, in Jan Christoph Bublitz et al. (eds.), Recht – Philosophie – Literatur. Festschrift
für Reinhard Merkel zum 70. Geburtstag, Berlin, Duncker & Humblot, 2020, pp. 565 ff.
About a critique of the term ‘Strafanspruch’ Jung, 2019, pp. 265–266, see above note 333.
499
See above notes 488 and 489 with main text.
500
Günther Jakobs, “Strafrechtliche Zurechnung und die Bedingungen der Normgeltung”, in
Ulfried Neumann and Lorenz Schulz (eds.), Verantwortung in Recht und Moral. ARSP-
Beiheft, vol. 74, Franz Steiner Verlag, Stuttgart, 2000, pp. 58–59; Günther Jakobs, “Das
Strafrecht zwischen Funktionalismus und ,,alteuropäischem’’ Prinzipiendenken”, in Zeit-
schrift für die gesamte Strafrechtswissenschaft, 1995, vol. 107, no. 4, pp. 843 ff. In detail
Ambos, 2013, p. 300, see above note 163.
501
Günther Jakobs, Strafrecht, Allgemeiner Teil, second edition, Walter de Gruyter, Berlin, New
York, 1991, pp. 34 ff. See also Andrew P. Simester, Antje Du Bois-Pedain, and Ulfried
Neumann, Liberal Criminal Theory: Essays for Andreas von Hirsch, Hart Publishing,
Oxford, 2014, p. 25.
502
Dennis, 2020, mn. 2-022, see above note 192.
503
The definitions are taken from Andreas Føllesdal, “The Legitimacy of International Courts”,
in Journal of Political Philosophy, 2020, Advance Article, p. 5. See generally with an in-
structive overview Cesare P.R. Romano, “Legitimacy, Authority, and Performance: Contem-
porary Anxieties of International Courts and Tribunals”, in American Journal of Interna-
tional Law, 2020, vol. 114, pp. 149–163. About the legitimacy of International Criminal Jus-
tice, combined with expressivism, Tom Dannenbaum, “Legitimacy in War and Punishment”,
in Kevin Jon Heller, et al. (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of International Criminal Law, Ox-
ford University Press, Oxford, 2020), pp. 136 ff.
504
In detail, see Heinze, 2018, pp. 929–957, see above note 376.
505
In a similar vein, see Volk, 1978, p. 173, see above note 334.
506
As clarified throughout the chapter, its research object is illegally obtained evidence. It goes
without saying that the sentence to this footnote in the main text applies mutatis mutandis
also to the rationale of disclosing exculpatory evidence and other procedural safeguards. Af-
ter all, the goal of punishing perpetrators of international crimes also strives to punish only
those perpetrators who are perceived to be guilty beyond reasonable doubt.
507
Jens David Ohlin, “Goals of International Criminal Justice and International Criminal Pro-
cedure”, in Göran Sluiter et al. (eds.), International Criminal Procedure, Oxford University
Press, 2013, p. 61.
512
Ibid., mn. 15.
513
Thaman and Brodowski, 2020, p. 437, see above note 196.
514
Bernhard Haffke, “Schweigepflicht, Verfahrensrevision und Beweisverbot”, in Goltdam-
mer’s Archiv für Strafrecht, 1973, p. 83.
515
ICC Statute, Article 69(7)(a), see above note 182; also ICTY RPE, Rule 95(1), see above
note 341; ICTR RPE, Rule 95(1), see above note 341 and Mechanism for International
Criminal Tribunals (‘MICT’), Rules of Procedure and Evidence, 8 June 2012, MICT/1, Rule
117(1) (‘MICT RPE’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/cef176/).
516
ICTY RPE, Rule 89(D), see above note 341 and MICT RPE, Rule 105(D), see above note
515 (emphasis added).
517
ICTY RPE, Rule 95, see above note 341; ICTR RPE, Rule 95, see above note 341 and
MICT RPE, Rule 117, see above note 515; also Special Court for Sierra Leone (‘SCSL’),
Rules of Procedure and Evidence, 31 May 2012, Rule 95 (‘SCSL RPE’) (https://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/4c2a6b/) (exclusion if “admission would bring the administration of justice in-
to serious disrepute”).
518
Dennis, 2020, mn. 2-022, see above note 192. In a similar vein Allen Buchanan, “The Com-
plex Epistemology of Institutional Legitimacy Assessments, As Illustrated by the Case of the
International Criminal Court”, in Temple International and Comparative Law Journal, 2019,
vol. 33, p. 332-333.
519
Turvey and Cooley, 2014, p. 164, see above note 180 (emphasis added).
520
Roberts et al., 2016, p. 5, see above note 146.
521
Matula, 2012, p. 101, see above note 314.
522
Rogall, 2016, mn. 11 with further references in fn. 63, see above note 435.
523
Ibid., mn. 13: “Nach unserer verfassungsmäßigen Ordnung hat der Staat die Rechtsordnung
so zu gestalten (vgl. Art. 1 Abs. 1 Satz 2, Abs. 3, 20 Abs. 3 GG), dass eine Verletzung der
Grundrechte, namentlich der Menschenwürde, verhindert wird. Diese staatliche Schutz-
verpflichtung besteht dabei auch gegenüber Angriffen Privater”.
524
Gerald J. Postema, “Law’s Rule: Reflexivity, Mutual Accountability, and the Rule of Law”,
in ZHAI Xiaobo and Michael Quinn (eds.), Bentham’s Theory of Law and Public Opinion,
Cambridge University Press, 2014, p. 56.
525
Heinze, 2014, pp. 264 ff., see above note 110.
tire trial and eventually putting into question the substantive fairness of an
acquittal (when it is almost certain, for instance, that the accused is guilty).
What sounds like a viable but almost artificial compromise is a reali-
ty in German criminal procedure. German courts differentiate between
rules prohibiting the obtaining or taking of evidence (Beweiserhebungsver-
bote), and rules prohibiting the use of evidence by the court in its assess-
ment of the defendant’s guilt (Beweisverwertungsverbote). 526 How radical-
ly separated the two stages, or put differently: how closed the two sub-
systems are, is a matter of controversy, with the strictest separation-theory
probably brought forward by Jäger (“Separation- and Abstraction Princi-
ple”). 527 Distinguishing between the obtaining of evidence and its actual
use at trial is Janus-faced. This works in both ways: not every illegally ob-
tained piece of evidence necessarily leads to its exclusion. 528 And not all
evidence obtained legally may later be used as evidence. 529 The separation
of the two stages and the focus on the short- and long-term effects of a pro-
cedural violation creates a chain reaction of exclusionary rules: those rules
may address a) the “re-use” 530 of the (same) evidence as evidence in further
proceedings against the same or other defendants; b) a possible effect of
illegally obtained evidence on a fresh investigation; and c) whether further
evidence taken on the basis of excluded evidence needs to be excluded as
well (“fruit of the poisonous tree”; “Fernwirkung”). 531
Separating the two stages in the scenario that this chapter is about (il-
legally obtained evidence in the extra-investigatory context at the interna-
tional level), ICTs could declare that illegally obtained evidence must be
526
In detail, see Thaman and Brodowski, 2020, pp. 434–435, see above note 196.
527
Christian Jäger, Beweisverwertung und Beweisverwertungsverbote im Straprozess, C.H.
Beck, München, 2003, pp. 137–138 (author’s translation, original terminology: “Trennungs-
und Abstraktionsprinzip”).
528
See German Federal Constitutional Court, Decision of 20 09 2018 – 2 BvR 708/18 –, pa-
ra. 40; idem, Decision of 16.02.2006 – 2 BvR 2085/05 = BVerfG NStZ 2006, 46, 47; idem,
Decision of 02.07.2009 – 2 BvR 2225/08 = NJW 2009, 3225; German Federal Court of Jus-
tice, Judgment of 13.01.2011 – 3 StR 332/10 = BGHSt 56, 127, para. 13; Kai Ambos, Be-
weisverwertungsverbote, Duncker & Humblot, Berlin, 2010, p. 22; Jäger, 2003, p. 135, see
above note 527; Matthias Jahn, Beweiserhebung und Beweisverwertungsverbote im Span-
nungsfeld zwischen den Garantien des Rechtsstaates und der effektiven Bekämpfung von
Kriminalität und Terrorismus, Gutachten C, 67. Deutscher Juristentag, C.H. Beck, München,
2008, p. 36.
529
Thaman and Brodowski, 2020, p. 436, see above note 196.
530
Translation by ibid., p. 458.
531
Generally, see ibid., p. 436.
536
Second Annual Report of the International Tribunal for the Prosecution of Persons Respon-
sible for Serious Violations of International Humanitarian Law Committed in the Territory
of the Former Yugoslavia since 1991, reprinted in ICTY Yearbook, p. 287, U.N. Doc.
S/1995/728, 23 August 1995 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/9a66a1/). For the amendment
see ICTY, Rules of Procedure and Evidence, 6 October 1995, IT/32/REV.6 (https://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/rkps3b/).
537
Calvo-Goller, 2006, p. 97, see above note 535; Ambos, 2009, p. 370, see above note 191.
538
ICC, Prosecutor v. Lubanga, Decision on the admission of material from the “bar table”, 24
June 2009, ICC-01/04-01/06-1981, para. 41 (fn. omitted, emphasis added) (https://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/c692ec/).
539
Ambos, 2013, p. 24, see above note 452.
prong, allowing for the exclusion ab initio (the dual test was provided in
brackets, though):
Evidence obtained by means of violation of this Statute or of
other rules of international law [or by means which cast sub-
stantial doubt on its reliability] [or whose admission is anti-
thetical to, and would seriously damage, the integrity of the
proceedings] [or by means which constitute a serious violation
of internationally protected human rights] [or which have been
collected in violation of the rights of the defence] shall not be
admissible. 540
In other instances, an ICT might find a violation grave enough to find
that the illegally obtained evidence can neither be admitted in court nor
lead to other evidence. Thus, the separation hypothesis provides a tool to
disentangle the Gordian knot of procedural vs. substantive fairness.
17.5.2.3.2.3.3.2.2. Disclosure System
The separation hypothesis is a familiar basis for another evidentiary prob-
lem that provides useful guidance for the matter at hand: disclosure viola-
tions. An appellate court in England, for instance, referred to the “integrity
of the discovery process”, albeit in a civil case. 541 I have pointed this out
elsewhere: the position of a human rights non-governmental organisation
with respect to the confidentiality of witnesses and the information collect-
ed from them is troubling. 542 This created a problem that became visible at
the ICC: in the Lubanga case, the Prosecution obtained evidence from the
UN and certain NGOs pursuant to confidentiality agreements made under
Article 54(3)(e) of the ICC Statute. 543 Basically, there was nothing wrong
540
Article 62(5) Zutphen Draft, in M. Cherif Bassiouni and William A. Schabas (eds.), The
Legislative History of the International Criminal Court, vol. 2, second edition, Brill Nijhoff,
Leiden, Boston, 2016, pp. 620–621.
541
UK HL, Taylor & Anor. v. Director of the Serious Fraud Office & Ors., 29 October 1998,
[1998] 3 W.L.R. 1040, [1999] 2 A.C. 177, p. 191.
542
Bergsmo and Wiley, 2008, p. 18, see above note 1.
543
Article 18(3) of the ICC–UN Relationship Agreement provides that “the United Nations and
the Prosecutor may agree that the United Nations provide documents or information to the
Prosecutor on condition of confidentiality and solely for the purpose of generating new evi-
dence and that such documents shall not be disclosed to other organs of the Court or third
parties, at any stage of the proceedings or thereafter, without the consent of the United Na-
tions”, cited in Prosecutor v Lubanga, Decision on the consequences of non-disclosure of
exculpatory materials covered by Article 54(3)(e) agreements, 15 June 2008, ICC-01/04–
01/06-1401, para. 93 (‘Lubanga, 2008’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/e6a054/). The
same rule applies to the UN peacekeeping mission, MONUC, in the Democratic Republic of
with that. As long as the amount of evidence obtained this way is relatively
minor, and the documents or information were received on a confidential
basis “solely for the purpose of generating new evidence” (lead evidence),
the Prosecution was allowed to do this. 544 It had no effect on the trial phas-
es, and thus paid tribute to the separation hypothesis. In other words, a few
documents and pieces of information can be obtained, coupled with an
agreement for non-disclosure, as long as the only purpose of receiving this
material is that it leads to other evidence. However, this was far from what
the Prosecution did. First, the Prosecution obtained more than fifty per cent
of its evidence on the basis of confidentiality agreements with NGOs. 545
The Prosecution itself admitted that its use of Article 54(3)(e) of the ICC
Statute to obtain evidence “may be viewed as excessive” and that “an ex-
cessive use of Art. 54(3)(e) would be problematic”. 546 Second, a great
amount of these documents were exculpatory material relevant to defence
preparation. 547 These documents usually have to be turned over to the de-
fence. 548 Third, and most importantly, the Prosecution did not use the Arti-
cle 54(3)(e)-agreements only for the purpose to obtain other evidence, for
example, as “springboard or lead potential”. 549 In fact, the Prosecution did
quite the opposite, as the Trial Chamber described:
Congo by way of Article 10(6) of the MONUC Memorandum of Understanding with the
ICC, which reads: “Unless otherwise specified in writing […], documents held by MONUC
that are provided by the United Nations to the Prosecutor shall be understood to be provided
in accordance with and subject to arrangements envisaged in Article 18, paragraph 3, of the
Relationship Agreement”, cited in Kai Ambos, “Confidential Investigations (Article 54(3)(e)
ICC Statute) vs. Disclosure Obligations: The Lubanga Case and National Law”, in New
Criminal Law Review, 2009, vol. 12, no. 4, p. 550. Generally, see Heinze, 2014, p. 454, see
above note 110.
544
Lubanga, 2008, para. 93, see above note 543.
545
ICC, Prosecutor v. Lubanga, Hearing Transcript, 13 March 2008, ICC-01/04-01/06-T-79,
pp. 5–6 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/bdf4aa/).
546
Cf. Lubanga, 2008, para. 32, see above note 543.
547
Ibid., para. 63 (“In this case over 200 documents, which the prosecution accepts have poten-
tial exculpatory effect or which are material to defence preparation, are the subject of
agreements of this kind. On 10 June 2008, the Chamber was told that there are ‘approxi-
mately’ 95 items of potentially exculpatory material and 112 items which are ‘material to de-
fence preparation’, pursuant to Rule 77, making a total of 207 items of evidence. Of these
207 items, 156 were provided by the UN”, fn. omitted). See also Heinze, 2014, p. 455, see
above note 110.
548
See ibid., pp. 344 ff.
549
Cf. Lubanga, 2008, para. 72, see above note 543.
550
Ibid., para. 73.
551
Jenia Iontcheva Turner, “Policing International Prosecutors”, in New York University Jour-
nal of International Law & Policy, 2012, vol. 45, pp. 194 ff.: “The balancing approach rec-
ognizes that remedies such as dismissal, stay, retrial, and exclusion may impose significant
burdens on third parties and on the justice system, and it takes these burdens into considera-
tion when determining the optimal remedy”.
552
UK, Police and Criminal Evidence Act 1984, s. 78, see above note 250.
553
ICC, Prosecutor v. Lubanga, Appeals Chamber, Judgment on the appeal of the Prosecutor
against the decision of Trial Chamber I of 8 July 2010 entitled “Decision on the Prosecu-
tion’s Urgent Request for Variation of the Time-Limit to Disclose the Identity of Intermedi-
ary 143 or Alternatively to Stay Proceedings Pending Further Consultations with the VWU”,
8 October 2010, ICC-01/04-01/06-2582, para. 55 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/8f3b61/);
in more detail Heinze, 2014, pp. 443 ff., see above note 110.
dural stages that can easily be viewed as a unified system; and b) the false
premise that these stages are in fact closed.
Employing Damaška’s models of criminal procedure, the criminal
process needs to be viewed first and foremost holistically, independent of
its stages. Just because a procedural stage might appear in a certain setting
does not change the characterisation of the process as a whole, but quite the
contrary: procedural stages are usually “assigned methodological subtasks”
that differ from each other: “One stage can be devoted to the gathering and
organization of relevant material, another to the initial decision, still anoth-
er to hierarchical review, and so on, depending on the number of levels in
the pyramid of authority”. 554 At first sight, this argument appears to resem-
ble the familiar argument that different procedural stages may have differ-
ent “objectives and procedural influences”. 555 However, a procedural stage
does not present some sort of autonomous, closed, Luhmannesque 556 sys-
tem. 557 Damaška too doubted the autonomy of procedural stages by ac-
knowledging that a) in the hierarchical ideal procedural stages are just part
of a multi-layered hierarchy 558 (and are therefore – as already mentioned –
assigned to “methodological subtasks”); 559 and b) the existence of proce-
dural stages per se and the extent of their integration into the proceedings
are already characteristics of a certain procedural model. 560 Thus, to treat
procedural stages separately with regard to their objectives and characteris-
tics is already constitutive of a certain procedural model. To do so would
554
Damaška, 1986, pp. 47–48, see above note 412.
555
See, for example, Mark Klamberg, Evidence in International Criminal Trials, Martinus
Nijhoff, Leiden, Boston, 2013, p. 499.
556
See Niklas Luhmann, Soziologische Aufklärung 1: Aufsätze zur Theorie sozialer Systeme,
eighth edition, Springer, Cham, 2009, p. 226; Gunther Teubner, Recht als autopoietisches
System, Suhrkamp, Frankfurt am Main, 1989; Niklas Luhmann, “Introduction to Autopoietic
Law”, in Niklas Luhmann (ed.), Autopoietic Law: A New Approach to Law and Society, De
Gruyter, Berlin, 1988, pp. 1, 3; Luhmann, 2008, pp. 50 ff. (sixth edition, 2011, p. 111), see
above note 370; Brian H. Bix, Legal Theory, Oxford University Press, 2004, p. 18; Roger
Cotterrell, “Law in Social Theory and Social Theory in the Study of Law”, in Austin Sarat
(ed.), The Blackwell Companion to Law and Society, Blackwell, Malden, 2007, pp. 16, 22;
Clemens Mattheis, “The System Theory of Niklas Luhmann and the Constitutionalization of
the World Society”, in Goettingen Journal of International Law, 2012, vol. 4, no. 2, pp. 626
ff.
557
In a similar vein, see Campbell, Ashworth, and Redmayne, 2019, p. 10, see above note 107.
558
Damaška, 1986, pp. 47–48, see above note 412.
559
Emphasis added.
560
See Damaška, 1986, p. 57, see above note 412.
somehow beg the question. Think of the perception of the criminal process
in civil law vis-á-vis common law systems: it is certainly fair to say that all
domestic legal systems within the common law or civil law tradition con-
tain concentrated and ‘continuous’ proceedings, but they reach this concen-
tration differently. In proceedings of the civil law tradition, the trial is the
cumulation of a continuing criminal process, whereas many common law
legal systems conceive the trial as “a discrete and continuous event” and
differentiate more sharply between the trial and pre-trial phases of criminal
proceedings. 561 A good illustration for this difference is the fact, that Franz
Kafka’s “Der Prozess” is still translated as “The Trial” in English, instead
of “The Proceedings”, which would certainly be more accurate. 562
Furthermore, the ICC provides a reality check to the separation hy-
pothesis, since the investigation phase (read as formal investigations) 563
and the trial phase can hardly be separated. As I have commented on else-
where, 564 the ICC Appeals Chamber held that “the Prosecutor must be al-
lowed to continue his investigation beyond the confirmation hearing, if this
is necessary in order to establish the truth”. 565 The Appeals Chamber based
this decision on Article 54(1)(a) of the ICC Statute, which lays down that
the Prosecutor shall, “[i]n order to establish the truth, extend the investiga-
tion to cover all facts and evidence relevant to an assessment of whether
there is criminal responsibility under this Statute, and, in doing so, investi-
gate incriminating and exonerating circumstances equally”. 566 The Appeals
Chamber further recognised that “ideally, it would be desirable for the in-
vestigation to be complete by the time of the confirmation hearing” but this
561
Roberts and Zuckerman, 2010, p. 55, see above note 192.
562
Mirjan Damaška, “Models of Criminal Procedure”, in Zbornik Pravnog Fakulteta u Zagrebu,
2001, vol. 51, p. 490.
563
Ambos, 2016, pp. 342 ff., see above note 342.
564
Heinze, 2014, pp. 524 ff., see above note 110.
565
ICC, Prosecutor v. Thomas Lubanga Dyilo, Appeals Chamber, Judgement on the Prosecu-
tor’s Appeal Against the Decision of Pre-Trial Chamber I entitled Decision Establishing
General Principles Governing Applications to Restrict Disclosure Pursuant to Rule 81(2)
and (4) of the Rules of Procedure and Evidence, 13 October 2006, ICC-01/04-01/06-568,
para. 52 (‘Lubanga, 2006’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/7813d4/). This view has been
adopted by Trial Chamber IV in the case against Nourain and Jerbo Jamus, see ICC, Prose-
cutor v. Abdallah Banda Abakaer Nourain and Saleh Mohammed Jerbo Jamus, Trial Cham-
ber, Prosecution’s Response to the Defence’s Oral Application of 19 April 2011, 4 May 2011,
ICC-02/05-03/09-140, para. 7 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/e5a6ea/).
566
Lubanga, 2006, para. 52, see above note 565.
was “not a requirement of the Statute”. 567 It, therefore, accepted the argu-
ment of the Prosecutor
that in certain circumstances to rule out further investigation
after the confirmation hearing may deprive the Court of sig-
nificant and relevant evidence, including potentially exonerat-
ing evidence – particularly in situations where the ongoing na-
ture of the conflict results in more compelling evidence be-
coming available for the first time after the confirmation hear-
ing.
As a consequence, the Prosecution may investigate as long as the trial has
not been concluded. I have expanded on this argument elsewhere. 568 The
rights of the defence to have adequate time and facilities for the preparation
of the trial could be safeguarded even if the investigation continues beyond
the confirmation of the charges. 569
This does not mean that viewing procedural stages separately to de-
cide about the admission or exclusion of evidence could not be a practical
compromise. Yet, this compromise comes at the price of dissolving the
criminal process as a system. As I have demonstrated, it is also questiona-
ble whether the separation hypothesis may work at the international level in
the face of the growing popularity of private investigations. Even the OTP
in the Lubanga case deliberately violated procedural rules to ensure the
success of its investigation. It can only be speculated that the Office was
probably rather certain that the ICC could not afford excluding the evi-
dence and eventually acquit Lubanga – for reasons of substantive fairness.
Argumentum a majore ad minus, a similar motivation might drive private
investigators. Duff et al. take this argument conceptually even further. They
distinguish two types of integrity (both types have been elaborated on ear-
lier in a different context): 570
First, a defendant might claim that it would be inconsistent to
continue the prosecution given the State’s conduct at the pre-
trial stage. Secondly, a defendant might claim that the moral
standing of the trial would be undermined by the prosecution
567
Ibid., para. 54.
568
In more detail Heinze, 2014, pp. 524 ff., see above note 110.
569
Cf. Lubanga, 2006, para. 55, see above note 565.
570
See above Section 17.5.2.2.
571
A. Duff et al., 2007, p. 234, see above note 145.
572
Ibid. (“It rests on the identification between the state and the actions of its officials such that
actions by officials in the course of investigation are to be treated as actions by the state,
which then have implications for the justification of future state actions”).
573
Ibid.
574
Ibid., p. 236.
575
Ibid.
576
See above Section 17.5.2.3.1.2.2.3.
577
In a similar vein, see A. Duff et al., 2007, p. 239, see above note 145: “What distinguishes
the cases of private torture, private entrapment, private phone-tapping and the like from this
case is that those cases are investigatory”.
578
Ibid.
579
See above Sections 17.5.2.2.3.1. and 17.5.2.3.2.3.1. In the same vein, see ibid.
580
Ibid. (“[E]ven as far as private citizens are concerned, use of evidence wrongfully obtained
involves treating the actions of those private citizens as part of the investigation. The argu-
ment on this view is that the integrity principle, the principle that the trial cannot be de-
tached from the investigation in normative terms, applies to private actions as well as ac-
tions of public officials”).
581
Ibid., p. 243.
582
About practicability as an important value in evidence law, see Volk, 1978, p. 3, above note
334.
583
See above Section 17.5.1.
584
See above Section 17.2.2.
585
Heinze, 2018, pp. 356 ff., see above note 487.
586
Seyla Benhabib, Another Cosmopolitanism, Oxford University Press, 2006, p. 21.
587
In more detail Denninger, 1978, p. 69, see above note 255.
588
Ambos, 2013, pp. 293, 305–6, see above note 163.
589
Immanuel Kant, Toward Perpetual Peace and Other Writings on Politics, Peace, and Histo-
ry, Yale University Press, New Haven, 2006, p. 105; Benhabib, 2006, pp. 21–22, see above
note 586. For a detailed analysis see Jasmine K. Gani, “The Erasure of Race: Cosmopolitan-
ism and the Illusion of Kantian Hospitality”, in Millennium, 2017, vol. 45, no. 3, pp. 425 ff.;
Pauline Kleingeld, “Kant’s Cosmopolitan Law: World Citizenship for a Global Order”, in
Kantian Review, 1998, vol. 2, p. 75.
590
Kant, 1991, p. 158, see above note 163 (emphasis in the original); Wade L. Huntley, “Kant’s
Third Image”, in International Studies Quarterly, 1996, vol. 40, no. 1, p. 51.
and each has a right to make this attempt without the other”, 591 and a free
“public use of man’s reason”. 592 For Benhabib, therefore, human rights
covenants can be qualified as cosmopolitan norms. 593 Günther follows
from Kant’s Third Definitive Article, that the application of public human
rights is a necessary precondition for a permanent peace. 594 In sum, with
this conception, Kant laid the foundations for all current conceptions of
human dignity and world peace, an “international rule of law”. 595 Even
though according to the Second Definitive Article, international law is cre-
ated through treaty obligations between States, cosmopolitan norms move
the individual as a moral and legal person in a worldwide civil society into
the centre of attention. 596
17.5.2.3.2.4. Intermediate Conclusion
In this section, the rationales for exclusionary rules were applied to the ex-
tra-investigatory context. After questioning the usefulness of the deterrence
theory, both remedy theory and the integrity of the process provide an im-
591
Kant, 1991, p. 158, see above note 163 (fn. omitted).
592
Immanuel Kant, “An Answer to the Question: What is ‘Enlightenment?’”, in Hans Reiss
(ed.), Immanuel Kant, Political Writings, H.B. Nisbet (trans.), Cambridge University Press,
1991, p. 55; Garrett Wallace Brown, “Kantian Cosmopolitan Law and the Idea of a Cosmo-
politan Constitution”, in History of Political Thought, 2006, vol. 27, no. 4, pp. 661, 664;
Gani, 2017, p. 431, see above note 589; Jürgen Habermas, Politische Theorie, Philoso-
phische Texte, vol. 4, Suhrkamp, Frankfurt am Main, 2009, p. 321: “Die Gefahr des Despot-
ismus, die in allen von der Obrigkeit bloß auferlegten Gesetzen brütet, kann einzig durch das
republikanische Verfahren einer fairen Meinungs- und Willensbildung aller potentiellen
Betroffenen vorgebeugt werden”.
593
Seyla Benhabib, “Claiming Rights across Borders”, in American Political Science Review,
2009, vol. 103, no. 4, pp. 691, 696. Against this view with a narrow reading of hospitality,
Vischer, 2017, p. 325, see above note 164: “Kant’s cosmopolitan law is far from proclaiming
a firm catalogue of human rights or even a world constitution. It only asserts in a rather
moral than legal tone a minimal guarantee of peaceful intercourse, and explicitly presumes
the ongoing asymmetry of host and visitor”.
594
See also Günther, 2009, p. 84, see above note 498. About Kant’s two-step-justification see
Heinze, 2018, p. 371, see above note 487.
595
Huntley, 1996, pp. 45, 49, see above note 590; Alec Stone Sweet, “A Cosmopolitan Legal
Order: Constitutional Pluralism and Rights Adjudication in Europe”, in Global Constitu-
tionalism, 2012, vol. 1, no. 1, pp. 53 (58); Jorrik Fulda, “Eine legitime Globalverfassung?
Die US-Hegemonie und die weltgesellschaftlich gerechte Vollendung des Kantischen Pro-
jektes”, in Archiv des Völkerrechts, 2016, vol. 54, no. 3, pp. 334, 345. About the role of hu-
man dignity in international human rights law and international criminal law, see Schmahl,
2018, pp. 79 ff., above note 445.
596
Benhabib, 2009, pp. 691, 695, see above note 593.
597
Emphasis supplied.
598
Roberts et al., 2016, p. 5, see above note 146.
evidence had been illegally obtained, declare that, even if this evidence
must be excluded from trial, it could still be obtained and eventually be
used in the pre-trial stage as lead evidence. An exclusionary rule would
thus only address the non-use of evidence in court and requires balancing
that allows for obtainment of the evidence (even though it was illegally ob-
tained).
Yet, the separation hypothesis must be rejected on the international
level. It artificially separates procedural stages that can easily be viewed as
a unified and is based on the false premise that procedural stages are in fact
closed. The rejection of the separation-hypothesis and the ensuing holistic
view on the process (Duff et al.’s integrity as integration) is the continua-
tion of the holistic view on the addressee-issue. Integrity as integration,
combined with the presumption that procedural rules are not merely ad-
dressed to actors but to systems and sub-systems respectively, allow for the
application of exclusionary rules to private conduct. Whether exclusionary
rules apply does not depend on the investigator but on the existence of an
investigation. 599
Last but not least, the Lubanga disclosure scenario casts doubt on the
practicability of the condition to only use illegally obtained evidence as
lead evidence: this condition is very much dependant on the bona fide con-
duct of both prosecutors and investigators. It might not be taken seriously
when a court is reluctant to follow through with an effective remedy, that is,
a stay of proceedings, as the ICC declared. These remedies and conse-
quences and their effectiveness to ensure the integrity of the process shall
be briefly analysed in the following section.
17.5.2.4. Consequences and Remedies: Exclusion vs. Other Remedies
As mentioned at the outset, integrity as an element and value in the deci-
sion about illegally obtained evidence by private individuals may lead to
several consequences. For the sake of better following the arguments, I
have decided to single out – by way of example – the exclusion of evidence
as the consequence for a violation of the integrity element (in whatever
form). It goes without saying that there are other consequences. Their mere
existence has a considerable influence on the decision about whether to
599
In a similar vein, see A. Duff et al., 2007, p. 239, above note 145: “What distinguishes the
cases of private torture, private entrapment, private phone-tapping and the like from this
case is that those cases are investigatory”.
exclude evidence from a trial or not. Rogall 600 and others 601 have made this
point concerning the balancing exercise within the exclusion decision: the
exclusion or non-use of evidence is one, but not necessarily the most apt
reaction to an illegal gathering of evidence. According to them, whether
this response is the appropriate remedy depends more on systemic aspects
than on the individual situation of the accused. Thus, integrity can also be
used to rationalise a stay of proceedings. It is the broader question of how
to address procedural violations committed in the pre-trial phase of the
proceedings. I will provide a brief sketch of those judicial responses, since
there are others who have provided profound studies of the matter, espe-
cially recently Pitcher. 602 Other remedies involve financial compensa-
tion, 603 sentence reductions, 604 integrity testing and integrity units. Finan-
cial compensation and sentence reductions provide enough material for an-
other chapter and will thus be neglected altogether. Integrity testing and
integrity units need to be illuminated briefly since their existence is indeed
an important check for both prosecutors and persons working in law en-
forcement.
Some prosecutors have set prosecution integrity units within their of-
fices, to provide an internal review when they believe it is warranted. 605
The units usually work closely together with innocence projects. Some
states in the US have created so-called ‘integrity testing’, where a police
officer “is placed in a position where he or she might be tempted to break a
rule or a law and monitored to see what he or she will do”. 606 As Pollock
explains: “Integrity testing is like undercover work in that unsuspecting
600
Klaus Rogall, “Gegenwärtiger Stand und Entwicklungstendenzen der Lehre von den straf-
prozessualen Beweisverboten”, in Zeitschrift für die gesamte Strafrechtswissenschaft, 1979,
pp. 31–35; see also Klaus Rogall, “Über die Folgen der rechtswidrigen Beschaffung des
Zeugenbeweises im Strafprozeß”, in Juristenzeitung, 1996, 947–948; for a further summary
see Thaman and Brodowski, 2020, p. 451, see above note 196.
601
See Jürgen Wolter, “Beweisverbote und Umgehungsverbote zwischen Wahrheitserforschung
und Ausforschung”, in Claus Wilhelm Canaris et al. (eds.), 50 Jahre Bundesgerichtshof,
Festgabe aus der Wissenschaft, Band IV, C.H. Beck, München, 2000, pp. 963, 985–986;
Greco, 2018, pp. 512 ff., see above note 203; see, generally, Thaman and Brodowski, 2020,
p. 451, see above note 196.
602
Pitcher, 2018, see above note 192.
603
Ibid., pp. 298 ff.
604
Ibid., pp. 302 ff.
605
Turvey and Cooley, 2014, p. 368, see above note 180.
606
Pollock, 2019, p. 204, see above note 179.
607
Ibid.
608
Dennis, 2020, mn. 2-009, see above note 192.
609
Roberts and Hunter, 2012, p. 49, see above note 192.
610
Lüderssen made this argument, albeit on a more conceptual level, see Klaus Lüderssen,
“Was ist das – ein ‘Rechtsstaat’?”, in Erhard Denninger and Klaus Lüderssen (eds.), Polizei
und Strafprozeß im demokratischen Rechtsstaat, Suhrkamp, Frankfurt a. M., 1978, p. 95.
611
Cf. ICC Statute, Article 69(7), see above note 182: “shall not be admissible”.
612
Cf., for example, ICTY RPE, Rule 95, see above note 341; MICT RPE, Rule 117, see above
note 515 and ICC Statute, Article 69(7), see above note 182.
613
Cf., for example, ICTY RPE, Rule 89(D), see above note 341 and MICT RPE, Rule 105(D),
see above note 515 and ICC Statute, Article 69(4), see above note 182.
614
The value of a dogma is that it applies to a wide range of cases and instance. Those cases
and instance thus do not have to be rationalized de novo, every time they occur, see Volk,
1978, p. 54, see above note 334.
615
Canaris perceives the use of a ‘theory’ as a rather classifying and semantic exercise, see
Claus-Wilhelm Canaris, “Funktion, Struktur und Falsifikation juristischer Theorien”, in Ju-
ristenzeitung, 1993, p. 379: “[Theorie] ermöglicht die begriffliche und/oder dogmatische
Einordnung der einschlägigen Problemlösung(en)”).
616
P. Duff, 2004, p. 165, see above note 193.
617
Thaman and Brodowski, 2020, pp. 451–452, see above note 196 (fn. omitted, emphasis in
the original). See also Jahn, 2008, pp. 46–47, see above note 528.
618
Pitcher, 2018, p. 327, see above note 192.
619
A. Duff et al., 2007, p. 239, see above note 145.
620
Ibid.
621
About the difference between a permanent and a conditional stay of proceedings Pitcher,
2018, pp. 305 ff., see above note 192.
622
Roberts et al., 2016, p. 6, see above note 146.
623
Barayagwiza decision, 1999, Introduction, para. 77, see above note 304.
624
ICTY, Prosecutor v. Stanišić and Župljanin, Decision on Mićo Stanišić’s Motion Requesting
a Declaration of Mistrial and Stojan Župljanin’s Motion to Vacate Trial Judgement, 2 April
2014, IT-08-91-A, para. 35 (fn. omitted) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/494e31/).
625
ICC, Prosecutor v. Callixte Mbarushimana, Pre-Trial Chamber, Decision on the “Defence
request for a permanent stay of proceedings”, 1 July 2011, ICC-01/04-01/10-264, p. 4, with
further references (‘Mbarushimana, 2011’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/27c6ab/); ICC,
Prosecutor v. Abdallah Banda Abakaer Nourain and Saleh Mohammed Jerbo Jamus, Trial
Chamber, Decision on the defence request for a temporary stay of proceedings, 26 October
2012, ICC-02/05-03/09-410 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/414cc4/). Recently ICC, Pros-
ecutor v. Ali Muhammad Ali Abd-Al-Rahman (“Ali Kushayb”), Decision on Defence Re-
quest for a Stay of Proceedings, 16 October 2020, ICC-02/05-01/20-186, paras. 7 ff.
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/1nq46m/).
626
Lubanga, 2006, para. 35, see above note 114; Mbarushimana, 2011, p. 4, see above note 625.
627
Lubanga, 2006, paras. 36–37, see above note 114; Mbarushimana, 2011, p. 4, see above note
625.
628
Lubanga, 2006, para. 37, see above note 114.
ings. 629 Only gross violations, which make it impossible for the accused “to
make his/her defence within the framework of his rights” justify the pro-
ceedings being stayed. 630 Thus, as has been stated in the case law of the
Court, 631 behaviours which may trigger a stay of proceedings are those that
entail unfairness of such a nature that it cannot be resolved, rectified or cor-
rected in the subsequent course of the proceedings. 632
One form of this ‘behaviour’ has included disclosure violations by
the Prosecution. The Trial Chamber imposed a stay of proceedings because
of an abuse of process relating to disclosure violations in connection with
Article 54(3)(e) of the ICC Statute. 633 The Chamber imposed the stay of
proceedings because of an abuse of process, also labelled as the “balancing
approach”. 634 It stated that “[t]he prosecution’s approach constitutes a
wholesale and serious abuse, and a violation of an important provision
which was intended to allow the prosecution to receive evidence confiden-
tially, in very restrictive circumstances”. 635 Thus, the Trial Chamber issued
a stay of the proceedings, because “the trial process has been ruptured to
such a degree that it is now impossible to piece together the constituent el-
ements of a fair trial” 636 and this “right to a fair trial – which is without
doubt a fundamental right – includes an entitlement to disclosure of excul-
patory material”. 637 The Appeals Chamber later confirmed the stay, 638 but
629
Mbarushimana, 2011, p. 4, see above note 625.
630
Lubanga, 2006, para. 39, see above note 114; Mbarushimana, 2011, pp. 4–5, see above note
625.
631
See, for example, Lubanga, 2008, para. 89, see above note 543.
632
Mbarushimana, 2011, p. 5, see above note 625.
633
See above Section 17.5.2.3.2.3.3.2.2. See, generally, Heinze, 2014, pp. 458 ff., see above
note 110.
634
Turner, 2012, see above note 551.
635
Lubanga, 2008, para. 73, see above note 543; see, generally, Turner, 2012, pp. 179 ff., above
note 551.
636
Lubanga, 2008, para. 93, see above note 543.
637
Ibid., para. 77. With ponderous words, the Chamber continued (para. 91):
This is an international criminal court, with the sole purpose of trying those charged
with the ‘most serious crimes of concern to the international community as a whole’ and
the judges are enjoined, in discharging this important role, to ensure that the accused re-
ceives a fair trial. If, at the outset, it is clear that the essential preconditions of a fair trial
are missing and there is no sufficient indication that this will be resolved during the trial
process, it is necessary – indeed, inevitable – that the proceedings should be stayed.
638
ICC, Prosecutor v. Lubanga, Appeals Chamber, Judgment on the appeal of the Prosecutor
against the decision of Trial Chamber I entitled “Decision on the consequences of non-
made clear that the Trial Chamber “intended to impose a stay that was con-
ditional and therefore potentially only temporary”. 639
17.5.2.4.2.1. The Intra-Investigatory Context: Lubanga and
Intermediaries
Even more relevant for the purpose of this chapter is an instance where an-
other stay was imposed: when during the proceedings against Lubanga the
suspicion arose that certain so-called intermediaries had bribed various per-
sons to prepare false evidence for alleged former child soldiers. 640 Interme-
diaries are “local organisations and/or private persons supporting the OTP
by assisting in the collection of evidence and communication with potential
witnesses, given their familiarity with the cultural, geographic and other
characteristics of the region where alleged crimes took place”. 641 In the
case against Lubanga about twenty-three intermediaries assisted the OTP,
seven of whom were used to contact approximately half of the witnesses
the OTP called to give evidence against Lubanga. 642 Usually, both the co-
operation with intermediaries and their use to create incriminating evidence
are common and perfectly legal. Moreover, the Chamber deemed it appro-
priate that the identities of the intermediaries would not have to be dis-
disclosure of exculpatory materials covered by Article 54(3)(e) agreements and the applica-
tion to stay the prosecution of the accused, together with certain other issues raised at the
Status Conference on 10 June 2008”, 21 October 2008, ICC-01/04-01/06-1486 (https://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/485c2d/).
639
Ibid., para. 75, continuing: “The Trial Chamber acknowledged, however, that circumstances
might change, in particular should the information providers alter their position and give
their consent to the disclosure of the documents in question.”
640
ICC, Prosecutor v. Thomas Lubanga Dyilo, Trial Chamber, Transcript of hearing, 13 March
2009, ICC-01/04-01/06-T-146-Red-ENG, p. 3, lines 11-18 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/
b0e64b/) (“[…] the Defence explained that they wished to explore the possibility that certain
people have participated in preparing false evidence for alleged former child soldiers, and in
this case that [143] helped the witness to invent a false story or a false identity, or both.”),
cited in Prosecutor v. Thomas Lubanga Dyilo, Redacted Decision on Intermediaries, 31 May
2010, ICC-01/04-01/06-2434-Red2, para. 16 (‘Lubanga, 2010’) (https://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/8b5694/).
641
See ICC Monitor, no. 41, November 2010 – April 2011, p. 9; Ambos, 2016, p. 122, see
above note 342; Ambos, 2013, p. 31, see above note 452. The ASP broadly defines an inter-
mediary “as an individual or entity that facilitates contact between the Court and a witness,
victim or other source of information.”, see ASP, Resolution ICC-ASP/9/Res.5, Adopted at
the 5th plenary meeting, 10 December 2010, Annex, para. 2 with fn. 3 (https://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/a399fa/).
642
Lubanga, 2010, para. 3, see above note 640.
643
Cf. ibid., para. 6.
644
ICC, Prosecutor v. Thomas Lubanga Dyilo, Transcript of hearing, 15 March 2010, ICC-
01/04-01/06-T-261-Red3-ENG, p. 6, line 18 to p. 7, line 8 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/
d5ee58/) cited in ibid., para. 41.
645
About ICC, Rules of Procedure and Evidence, 9 September 2002, Rule 77 (‘ICC RPE’)
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/8bcf6f/); see Heinze, 2014, pp. 355 ff., above note 110.
646
Lubanga, 2010, para. 139, see above note 640. The entire approach is:
a. Given the markedly different considerations that apply to each intermediary (or oth-
ers who assisted in a similar or linked manner), disclosure of their identities to the
defence is to be decided on an individual-by-individual basis, rather than by way of
a more general, undifferentiated approach.
b. The threshold for disclosure is whether prima facie grounds have been identified for
suspecting that the intermediary in question had been in contact with one or more
witnesses whose incriminating evidence has been materially called into question, for
instance by internal contradictions or by other evidence. In these circumstances, the
intermediary’s identity is disclosable under Rule 77 of the Rules. [...]
c. The identities of intermediaries (or others who assisted in a similar or linked manner)
who do not meet the test in b. are not to be disclosed.
d. Disclosure of the identity of an intermediary (or others who assisted in a similar or
linked manner) is not to be effected until there has been an assessment by the VWU,
and any protective measures that are necessary have been put in place.
e. The identities of intermediaries who did not deal with trial witnesses who gave in-
criminating evidence are not to be revealed, unless there are specific reasons for
suspecting that the individual in question attempted to persuade one or more indi-
viduals to give false evidence or otherwise misused his or her position. Applications
in this regard will be dealt with by the Chamber on an individual basis.
f. The threshold for calling intermediaries prior to the defence abuse submissions is
that there is evidence, as opposed to prima facie grounds to suspect, that the individ-
ual in question attempted to persuade one or more individuals to give false evidence.
647
Lubanga, 2010, para. 150, see above note 640.
648
ICC, Prosecutor v. Thomas Lubanga Dyilo, Trial Chamber, Redacted Decision on the Prose-
cution’s Urgent Request for Variation of the Time-Limit to Disclose the Identity of Interme-
diary 143 or Alternatively to Stay Proceedings Pending Further Consultations with the VWU,
8 July 2010, ICC-01/04-01/06-2517-RED, paras. 12, 13 (‘Decision on the Prosecution’s Ur-
gent Request’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/cd4f10/).
649
ICC, Prosecutor v. Thomas Lubanga Dyilo, Trial Chamber, Prosecution’s Urgent Request
for Variation of the Time-Limit to Disclose the Identity of Intermediary 143 or Alternatively
to Stay Proceedings Pending Further Consultations with VWU, 7 July 2010, ICC-01/04-
01/06-2515, paras. 1, 3 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/5e2ba5/), cited in ibid., para. 13.
658
Ibid., para. 114 (emphasis added).
659
Ibid. (emphasis added).
660
Ibid. (emphasis added). See, in detail, the analysis in Pitcher, 2018, p. 273, see above note
192.
661
ICTY, Prosecutor v. Tolimir, Trial Chamber, Decision on Preliminary Motions on the In-
dictment pursuant to Rule 72 of the Rules, 14 December 2007, IT-05-88/2-PT, para. 8
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/014693/).
662
McMahon, 2001, p. 16, see above note 102.
663
Ibid.
664
Ibid., p. 138.
665
Ibid., p. 144.
666
Ibid.
667
Ibid., p. 16.
668
About term “evidence” vis-à-vis “material” and “information”, see Ambos, 2016, pp. 446–
447, see above note 342.
669
In a similar vein, see Rankin, 2017, p. 402, see above note 56.
670
Ibid., p. 403.
671
Ambos, 2016, p. 447, see above note 342. Cf. ICC RPE, Rule 63(2), see above note 645
(“assess freely all evidence”); for the case law, for example, see ICC, Prosecutor v. Bemba
et al., Appeals Chamber, Public Redacted Judgment on the appeals of Mr Jean-Pierre Bemba
Gombo, Mr Aimé Kilolo Musamba, Mr Jean-Jacques Mangenda Kabongo, Mr Fidèle Baba-
la Wandu and Mr Narcisse Arido against the decision of Trial Chamber VII entitled “Judg-
ment pursuant to Article 74 of the Statute”, 8 March 2018, ICC-01/05-01/13-2275-Red, pa-
ras. 93, 554 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/56cfc0/) (“‘[d]eferring these assessments is al-
so more consonant with’ the right and duty to assess freely, according to Rule 63(2) of the
Rules, all evidence submitted”), 585, 591; previously ICC, Prosecutor v. Lubanga, Trial
Chamber I, Decision on the admissibility of four documents, 13 June 2008, ICC-01/04-
01/06-1399, paras. 24, 32 (‘Lubanga Decision on admissibility’) (https://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/2855e0/); ICC, Prosecutor v. Ruto and Sang, Trial Chamber V(A), Public re-
dacted version of Decision on the Prosecution’s Application for Addition of Documents to
Its List of Evidence, 3 September 2014, ICC-01/09-01/11-1485-Red2, para. 28 (https://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/342ede/) (“The Prosecution notes that there is a principle that the
Chamber should have the ability to freely assess the evidence before it rather than seek to
limit the use of evidence at the outset”); ICC, Prosecutor v. Ongwen, Pre-Trial Chamber II,
Decision on Prosecution Request in Relation to its Mental Health Experts Examining the
Accused, 28 June 2017, ICC-02/04-01/15-902, para. 6 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/
80f3dc/).
mum flexibility” 672 and “broad discretion” when deciding on the admissi-
bility. 673 The admissibility decision of the ICC, for instance, depends on the
“relevance” 674 and “probative value” 675 of the evidence 676 and the absence
of any serious rights violation. 677 Thus, as long as CIJA investigators do
not commit a (serious) rights violation, it could be speculated that their in-
formation will at least not be ruled inadmissible prior to a judgment. 678 Es-
672
Gideon Boas et al., International Criminal Procedure, International Criminal Law Practi-
tioner Library Series, vol. III, Cambridge University Press, 2011, p. 336; Ambos, 2016,
p. 447, see above note 342.
673
Cf. Lubanga Decision on admissibility, para. 23, see above note 671; Prosecutor v. Bemba,
Trial Chamber III, Judgment pursuant to Article 74 of the Statute, 21 March 2016, ICC-
01/05-01/08-3343, para. 222 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/edb0cf/) (“In deciding on the
admission of the various items, […] the Chamber is afforded a measure of discretion”.); for
the same position at the ad hoc Tribunals and other ICTs, see ICTY, Prosecutor v. Aleksovski,
Appeals Chamber, Decision on Prosecutor’s Appeal on Admissibility of Evidence, 16 Feb-
ruary 1999, IT-95-14/1-AR73, para. 15 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/168b25/); ICTY,
Prosecutor v. Kordić and Čerkez, Appeals Chamber, Decision on Appeal Regarding State-
ment of a Deceased Witness, 21 July 2000, IT-95-14/2-AR73.5, para. 20 (https://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/da3903/); ICTY, Prosecutor v. Aleksovski, Appeals Chamber, Judgment, 24
March 2000, IT-95-14/1-A, para. 63 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/176f05/); ICTR, Pros-
ecutor v. Musema, Appeals Chamber, Judgment, 16 November 2001, ICTR-96-13-A, pa-
ras. 37–8 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/fba4cc/); SCSL, Prosecutor v. Norman et al., Tri-
al Chamber I, Appeal against Decision Refusing Bail, 11 March 2005, SCSL-04-14-AR65,
para. 26 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/5f388e/) (purpose of Rule 89(C) “to avoid sterile
legal debate over admissibility”). For the literature see, for example, Ambos, 2016, pp. 447
ff., see above note 342 with further references.
674
ICC Statute, Articles 64(9)(a) and 69(4), see above note 182 (authorising the Trial Chamber
to “rule” on the “relevance” of evidence), ICC RPE, Rule 63(2), see above note 645; see al-
so ICTY RPE, Rule 89(C), see above note 341; ICTR RPE, Rule 89(C), see above note 341;
SCSL RPE, Rule 89(C), see above note 517 and MICT RPE, Rule 105(C), see above note
515 (referring to “relevant” evidence); Ambos, 2016, p. 448, see above note 342.
675
ICC Statute, Article 69(4), see above note 182, ICC RPE, Rule 72(2), see above note 645;
see also ICTY RPE, Rule 89(C), see above note 341; ICTR RPE, Rule 89(C), see above note
341 and MICT RPE, Rule 105(C), see above note 515. Cf. SCSL, Prosecutor v. Taylor, Ap-
peals Chamber, Decision on “Prosecution Notice of Appeal and Submissions Concerning the
Decision Regarding the Tender of Documents”, 6 February 2009, SCSL-03-01-T-721, pa-
ra. 37 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/453718/); also Boas et al., 2011, p. 340, see above
note 672, with further references in fn. 18.
676
In more detail Ambos, 2016, pp. 449–450, see above note 342.
677
ICC Statute, Article 69(4), see above note 182, ICC RPE, Rule 72(2), see above note 645;
see also ICTY RPE, Rule 89(D), see above note 341 and MICT RPE, Rule 105(D), see
above note 515. Cf. Katanga and Ngudjolo, 2010, paras. 13 et seq., see above note 311.
678
In a similar vein Donald K. Piragoff and Paula Clarke, “Article 69”, in Kai Ambos (ed.),
Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court – A Commentary, fourth edition, C.H.
Beck, Hart, Nomos, München et al., 2021, p. 2093, mn. 95.
pecially considering the ICC’s practice, and, more concretely, the Ongwen
Trial Chamber 679 – which rejected the Chambers’ previous practice 680 of
deciding on admissibility issues at the moment of submission (the ‘admis-
sion approach’) and promoted an alternative approach (authorised by the
Bemba Appeals Chamber) 681 to defer the admissibility decision “until the
end of the proceedings” (the ‘submission approach’). 682 The submission
approach was recently adopted by Trial Chamber X in the Al Hassan
case, 683 and by Trial Chamber V in the Yekatom and Ngaissona case. 684
However, if private investigators commit a rights violation while collecting
evidence, exclusionary rules apply – irrespective of whether the investiga-
tors worked on behalf of an ICT-organ or proprio motu.
Second, on the international level, the importance of documentary
evidence cannot be overstated. 685 Especially photography and visual media
679
ICC, Prosecutor v. Ongwen, Initial Directions on the Conduct of the Proceedings, 13 July
2016, ICC-02/04-01/15-497, paras. 24 et seq. (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/60d63f/);
Decision on Request to Admit Evidence Preserved Under Article 56 of the Statute, 11 Au-
gust 2016, ICC-02/04-01/15-520, para. 7 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/c47593/). In the
same vein, see Fabricio Guariglia, “‘Admission’ v. ‘Submission’ of Evidence at the Interna-
tional Criminal Court”, in Journal of International Criminal Justice, 2018, vol. 16, no. 2,
p. 321 (who, however, cites the wrong decision in fn. 20).
680
See, for example, Katanga and Ngudjolo, 2010, para. 15, see above note 311. For a similar
approach at the ICTY, see Christine Schuon, International Criminal Procedure, A Clash of
Legal Cultures, T.M.C. Asser Press, The Hague, 2010, pp. 137–8 (shift from admissibility to
weight/reliability). See, generally, Ambos, 2016, p. 449, see above note 342.
681
ICC, Prosecutor v. Bemba, Appeals Chamber, Judgment on the Appeals of Mr. Jean-Pierre
Bemba Gombo and the Prosecutor against the Decision of TC III entitled “Decision on the
admission into evidence of materials contained in the prosecution’s list of evidence”, 3 May
2011, ICC-01/05-01/08-1386, paras. 37, 41-2, 52-7 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/7b62af/).
682
Ibid., para. 37; in the same vein, see Prosecutor v. Bemba et al., Decision on Prosecution
Requests for Admission of Documentary Evidence, 24 September 2015, ICC-01/05-01/13-
1285, para. 9 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/5a06b3/). See, generally, Guariglia, 2018,
p. 315, see above note 679.
683
ICC, Prosecutor v. Al Hassan, Annex A to the Decision on the conduct of proceedings, 6
May 2020, ICC-01/12-01/18-789-AnxA, paras. 29 et seq. (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/
jk54h9/).
684
ICC, Prosecutor v. Alfred Yekatom and Patrice-Edouard Ngaïssona, Initial Directions on the
Conduct of the Proceedings, 26 August 2020, ICC-01/14-01/18-631, paras. 52–59
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/ubfjw1/).
685
Ambos, 2016, p. 487, see above note 342. Cf. Gaynor et al., 2013, pp. 1045–1046, see
above note 533. But see also Nancy Amoury Combs, Fact-Finding Without Facts, Cam-
bridge University Press, 2010, pp. 6, 12–14, finding that the ICTR, the SCSL, and the SPSC
basically relied on witness testimony with only the latter also receiving significant forensic
evidence.
is gaining increasing importance and relevance before both ICTs and na-
tional courts trying international crimes. 686 Unsurprisingly, Wiley, CIJA’s
Director, maintained: “The queen and king of evidence in any criminal in-
vestigation is a document. It isn’t cross-examined because it is factual”. 687
As to the admissibility of documentary evidence the same general princi-
ples apply, that is, it depends on its relevance and probative value (reliabil-
ity). 688 A document can only be reliable if it is authentic since “the fact that
the document is what it purports to be enhances the likely truth of the con-
tents thereof”. 689 Thus, authenticity speaks to the probative value of a doc-
ument, be it in the form of reliability or its evidentiary weight. 690 Further-
more, the ‘chain of custody’, that is, the document’s production process
from its creation to the submission to a Chamber, is to be considered. 691
The demonstration of that chain of custody is certainly one of the main
challenges for the work of CIJA-investigators. 692
686
See Section 17.3 for the impact the Group Caesar had on German proceedings. See also
Aoife Duffy, “Bearing Witness to Atrocity Crimes: Photography and International Law”, in
Human Rights Quarterly, 2018, vol. 40, no. 4, pp. 798 ff.
687
Rankin, 2017, p. 409, see above note 56.
688
See also ICTY, Prosecutor v. Brđanin and Talić, Standards Order, 15 February 2002, IT-99-
36-T, para. 18 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/005043/); ICTR, Prosecutor v. Musema, Ap-
peals Chamber, Judgement, 16 November 2001, ICTR-96-13-A, para. 56 (https://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/6a3fce/); Katanga and Ngudjolo, 2010, paras. 13 et seq., see above
note 311; ICC, Prosecutor v. Ruto and Sang, Decision on the Prosecution's Request for Ad-
mission of Documentary Evidence, 10 June 2014, ICC-01/09-01/11-1353, paras. 13 et seq.,
37 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/e1a55f/). See, generally, Ambos, 2016, p. 487, see
above note 342.
689
ICC, Prosecutor v. Bemba, Public Redacted Version of Decision on the Prosecution’s Appli-
cation for Admission of Materials into Evidence Pursuant to Article 64 (9) of the Rome
Statute of 6 September 2012, 8 October 2012, ICC-01/05-01/08-2299-Red, para. 9 (https://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/13ca4b/); see also Ambos, 2016, p. 501, see above note 342.
690
ICTY, Prosecutor v. Blaškić, Trial Chamber, Decision on the Defence Motion for Reconsid-
eration of the Ruling to Exclude from Evidence Authentic and Exculpatory Documentary
Evidence, 30 January 1998, IT-95-14-T (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/vdkn6i/) (“the
weight to be ascribed to it will depend on the additional elements which will have, if neces-
sary, been provided and which permit attesting to its authenticity”). See also Boas et al.,
2011, p. 341, see above note 672.
691
ICC, Prosecutor v. Lubanga, Judgment pursuant to Article 74 of the Statute, 5 April 2012,
ICC-01/04-01/06-2842, para. 109 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/677866/); Prosecutor v.
Katanga, Judgment pursuant to article 74 of the Statute, 7 March 2014, ICC-01/04-01/07-
3436-tENG, para. 91 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/f74b4f/).
692
Rankin, 2017, p. 401, see above note 56.
17.6. Conclusion
Considering the current political landscape of anti-multilateralism and the
politically impotent UN Security Council, it was long overdue that the in-
ternational community became more creative in its fight against impunity.
The IIIMs in both Syria and Myanmar are the first step, CIJA is another. In
an instructive short article about private investigations in Austria and Ger-
many, Maier listed three reasons for the initiation of private investiga-
tions. 693 First, when public authorities are unwilling or unable to investi-
gate; second, when the investigations of public authorities are ineffective
and badly done; and third, when the victim does not want public authorities
to investigate. The first and second requirements are met in the situation of
Syria: the ICC (or any other ICT) cannot investigate, and investigations on
the ground are fruitless. Private investigations are without an alternative, so
to say, and there is nothing wrong with that. Despite the rich history and
impressive success of private investigations in domestic contexts, private
investigators still feel that “their role within society, the value of their ser-
vices and the problems they faced, have been overlooked and undervalued
for too long”. 694 In fact, the perception of private investigators does not
mirror the admiration readers identify with Sherlock Holmes and Miss
Marple. Many private investigators are still viewed as “cowboys” and
“dodgy characters”. 695 This does not do justice to their work – at the inter-
national level, it is likely that they will be the future, and the next ICC
Prosecutor is certainly aware of that. After all, human rights organisations
and entities such as CIJA on the one hand, and the investigative arms of
ICTs on the other, share one goal: the desire to end impunity. 696 This goal,
however, is a double-edged sword: it makes the use of evidence collected
by private individuals both necessary and dangerous; without it, perpetra-
tors of international crimes can hardly be convicted – when illegally ob-
tained, a conviction becomes less likely. It is thus past time for a frame-
work for private conduct in investigatory contexts at the international level.
One way to establish such a framework is regulation. Countries such as the
US, Canada, Australia, New Zealand, Belgium, the Netherlands, Germany,
Finland or Spain, have a statutory framework for regulating private investi-
693
Bernhard Maier, “Verbrechensaufklärung durch Privatdetektive”, Kriminalistik, 2001,
pp. 670–672 (670).
694
Gill and Hart, 1999, p. 246, see above note 137.
695
Ibid.
696
Bergsmo and Wiley, 2008, p. 2, see above note 1.
697
Johnston, 2007, p. 288, see above note 93.
698
Gill and Hart, 1999, p. 248, see above note 137; Johnston, 2007, p. 288, see above note 93.
699
ICC ASP, Review Conference of the Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court, Dec-
laration RC/Decl.1, 1 June 2010 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/146df9-1/), emphasis add-
ed.
18.1. Introduction
Establishing a culture of accountability for every actor participating in ju-
dicial proceedings is a crucial element in strengthening the integrity of such
proceedings, and ultimately of a judicial institution. In the same vein, the
foundational documents of each international or internationalised court and
tribunal profess that the qualifications of the judges, key actors in judicial
proceedings, must include integrity. However, it is only of late that judges
are themselves subjected to some form of accountability, with recent years
seeing the adoption of numerous codes of judicial ethics (‘CoJEs’) before
international and internationalised courts and tribunals (‘ICTs’), some of
which include disciplinary procedures. Prior to such developments, judges
could only be subject to case-specific motions for disqualification with lim-
ited effect, and the result of which could never lead to their overall removal
from their positions. The adoption of these various CoJEs may thus be seen
*
Bettina Julia Spilker is Legal Officer, International, Impartial and Independent Mechanism
(Syria). The views expressed in this article are those of the author alone and do not neces-
sarily reflect the views of the International, Impartial and Independent Mechanism (Syria) or
of the United Nations. The author is grateful to Guénaël Mettraux, Kinga Tibori-Szabó and
Simon Meisenberg for their invaluable comments on earlier drafts.
1
Judges: Independence, Efficiency and Responsibilities, Recommendation and Explanatory
Memorandum, adopted by the Committee of Ministers of the Council of Europe on 17 No-
vember 2010, CM/Rec(2010)12, para. 69 (‘Recommendation of Committee of Ministers’)
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/8r16ac/).
2
See Morten Bergsmo, “Revisiting Integrity in International Justice”, FICHL Policy Brief
Series No. 93 (2018), Torkel Opsahl Academic EPublisher, Brussels, 2018, pp. 2–3 (“4. In-
stitutional ‘Integrity’ Measures Available to International Courts”) (https://www.toaep.org/
pbs-pdf/93-bergsmo/).
Appointment of Adoption of
Establishment
First Judges CoJE
ICTY 1993 1994 2016 3
ICTR 1994 1995 n/a
ICC 1998 2003 2005 4
SCSL 2002 2002 n/a
ECCC 2003 2006 2008 5
STL 2007 2009 2016 6
IRMCT 2010 2012 2015; 7
revised 2018; 8
KSC 2015 2017 2017 9
3
ICTY, Code of professional conduct for the judges of the Tribunal, adopted on 6 July 2016
(‘ICTY CoJE’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/55lsey/).
4
ICC, Code of Judicial Ethics, adopted on 9 March 2005 (‘ICC CoJE’) (https://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/383f8f).
5
ECCC, Code of Judicial Ethics, adopted on 31 January 2008 (‘ECCC CoJE’) (https://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/5dys4p/).
6
STL, Code of Professional Conduct for the Judges of the Special Tribunal for Lebanon,
adopted on 27 September 2016 (‘STL CoJE’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/oird6k/).
7
IRMCT, Code of Professional Conduct for the Judges of the Mechanism, adopted on 11 May
2015 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/23cc92).
8
IRMCT, Code of Professional Conduct for the Judges of the Mechanism, adopted on 9 April
2018 (‘IRMCT CoJE’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/5deknw/).
9
KSC, Code of Judicial Ethics for Judges Appointed to the Roster of International Judges of
the Kosovo Specialist Chambers, adopted on 14 March 2017 (‘KSC CoJE’) (https://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/wl7m65/).
10
Updated Statute of the International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia, 25 May,
1993, Article 13 (‘ICTY Statute’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/b4f63b); Statute of the
International Criminal Tribunal for Rwanda, 8 November 1994, Article 12 (‘ICTR Statute’)
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/8732d6); Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court,
17 July 1998, Article 36(3)(a) (‘ICC Statute’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/7b9af9);
Statute of the Special Court for Sierra Leone, 14 August 2000, Article 13 (‘SCSL Statute’)
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/aa0e20); Statute of the Special Tribunal for Lebanon, 30
May 2007, Article 9(1) (‘STL Statute’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/da0bbb); Statute of
the International Residual Mechanism for Criminal Tribunals, 22 December 2010, Article
9(1) (‘IRMCT Statute’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/30782d).
11
For example, ICTY staff members were subject to the UN Staff Rules and Regulations,
which detailed provisions on disciplinary misconduct and any proceedings attached thereto
(see Rules 10.1-10.4). However, they are only applicable to staff members. Staff Regulations
and Rules of the United Nations, UN Doc. ST/SGB/2018/1, 1 January 2018 (https://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/zn5lba/).
12
See, for example, ICTY Statute, Article 13; ICTR Statute, Article 12; SCSL Statute, Article
13(1), see above note 10.
13
See, for example, ICTR, Rules of Procedure and Evidence, 29 June 1995, Rule 15 (‘ICTR
RPE’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/0b0d43/); ICTY, Rules of Procedure and Evidence,
11 February 1994, Rule 15 (‘ICTY RPE’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/30df50/); SCSL,
Rules of Procedure and Evidence, 16 January 2002, Rule 15 (‘SCSL RPE’) (https://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/b36b82/); STL, Rules of Procedure and Evidence, 20 March 2009,
Rule 25 (‘STL RPE’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/3773bf/); IRMCT, Rules of Proce-
dure and Evidence, 8 June 2012, Rule 18 (‘IRMCT RPE’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/
cef176/).
ble to all judges, as per the respective Statutes of ICTs 14 – a principle in-
trinsically linked to each judge’s integrity. The jurisprudence developed in
respect of disqualification requests is instructive – it primarily focusses on
issues of impartiality, rather than integrity, although it is clear that there is
some overlap between these concepts.
Early ICTY Appeals Chamber jurisprudence in Furundžija deter-
mined that “there is a general rule that a Judge should not only be subjec-
tively free from bias, but also that there should be nothing in the surround-
ing circumstances which objectively gives rise to an appearance of bias”. 15
It was thus determined that the requirement of impartiality is violated not
only where a judge is actually biased, but also where there is an appearance
of bias. 16
On that basis, the following principles were developed:
1. A judge is not impartial if it is shown that actual bias exists.
2. There is an unacceptable appearance of bias if:
a. a judge is a party to the case, or has a financial or proprietary in-
terest in the outcome of a case, or if the judge’s decision will lead
to the promotion of a cause in which he or she is involved, togeth-
er with one of the parties. Under these circumstances, a judge’s
disqualification from the case is automatic; or
b. the circumstances would lead a reasonable observer, properly in-
formed, to reasonably apprehend bias. 17
14
See, for example, ICTY Statute, Article 13; ICTR Statute, Article 12; ICC Statute, Article
36(3)(a); SCSL Statute, Article 13; STL Statute, Article 9(1); IRMCT Statute, Article 9(1),
see above note 10.
15
ICTY, Prosecutor v. Furundžija, Appeals Chamber, Judgement, 21 July 2000, IT-95-17/1-A,
para. 189 (emphasis added) (‘Furundžija Appeal Judgement’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/
doc/660d3f).
16
ICTR, The Prosecutor v. Karemera et al., Trial Chamber, Decision on Joseph Nzirorera’s
Motion for Disqualification of Judges Byron, Kam, and Joensen, 7 March 2008, ICTR-98-
44-T, para. 4 (‘Karemera et al. Decision of 7 March 2008’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/
6003e9/), referring to Furundžija Appeal Judgment, paras. 181–188; ICTY, Prosecutor v.
Brđanin and Talić, Trial Chamber, Decision on Application by Momir Talić for the Disquali-
fication and Withdrawal of a Judge, 18 May 2000, IT-99-36-T, paras. 9–14 (‘Brđanin and
Talić Decision of 18 May 2000’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/44e03e).
17
Furundžija Appeal Judgement, para. 189, footnote 257, see above note 15, recalling that in
Talić, it was found that the test on this prong is “whether the reaction of the hypothetical
fair-minded observer (with sufficient knowledge of the actual circumstances to make a rea-
sonable judgement) would be that [the judge] … might not bring an impartial and unpreju-
diced mind”; Brđanin and Talić Decision of 18 May 2000, para. 15, see above note 16.
18
Ibid., para. 190, referring to Supreme Court of Canada, R.D.S. v. The Queen, 27 September
1997; see also ICTR, The Prosecutor v. Nahimana et al., Appeals Chamber, Judgement, 28
November 2007, ICTR-99-52-A, para. 50 (‘Nahimana et al. Appeal Judgment’) (https://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/04e4f9/); ICTY, Prosecutor v. Galić, Appeals Chamber, Judgement,
30 November 2006, IT-98-29-A, para. 40 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/c81a32/); ICTR,
The Prosecutor v. Rutaganda, Appeals Chamber, Judgement, 26 May 2003, ICTR-96-3-A,
para. 40 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/40bf4a/); Prosecutor v. Delalić et al., Appeals
Chamber, Judgement, 20 February 2001, IT-96-21-A, para. 682 (‘Delalić et al. Appeal
Judgment’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/051554/).
19
Karemera et al. Decision of 7 March 2008, para. 5, see above note 16, referring to Furundži-
ja Appeal Judgment, para. 195; Brđanin and Talić Decision of 18 May 2000, para. 9, see
above note 16; SCSL, Prosecutor v. Sesay, Decision on Defence Motion Seeking the Dis-
qualification of Justice Robertson from the Appeals Chamber, 13 March 2004, SCSL-04-15-
A, para. 16 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/d83edd/); ICTR, The Prosecutor v. Ntahobali,
The Bureau, Decision on Motion for Disqualification of Judges, 7 March 2006, ICTR-97-
21-T, para. 9 (‘Ntahobali Decision of 7 March 2006’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/
69f139/).
20
ICTY, Prosecutor v. Stanišić and Župljanin, Appeals Chamber, Judgement, 30 June 2016,
IT-08-91-A, para. 43 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/e414f6/), referring to Delalić et al.
Appeal Judgment, para. 707, see above note 18; ICTR, The Prosecutor v. Karemera et al.,
Decision on Joseph Nzirorera’s Motion for Disqualification of Judge Byron and Stay of Pro-
ceedings, 20 February 2009, ICTR-98-44-T, para. 6 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/
f27eb3/).
21
Karemera et al. Decision of 7 March 2008, para. 5, see above note 16, referring to Ntahobali
Decision of 7 March 2006, para. 9, see above note 19; Furundžija Appeal Judgement, pa-
ra. 185, see above note 15.
22
Karemera et al. Decision of 7 March 2008, para. 5, ibid.
23
ICTR, The Prosecutor v. Kayishema and Ruzindana, Appeals Chamber, Judgment (Reasons),
1 June 2001, ICTR-95-1-A, para. 55 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/9ea5f4/), referring to
Furundžija Appeal Judgement, paras. 196–197, see above note 15; ICTR, The Prosecutor v.
Akayesu, Appeals Chamber, Judgment, 1 June 2001, ICTR-96-4-A, paras. 90 et seq.
(‘Akayesu Appeal’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/c62d06/); Delalić et al. Appeal Judg-
ment, paras. 682 et seq. and 698 et seq., see above note 18.
24
Karemera et al. Decision of 7 March 2008, para. 6, see above note 16.
25
ICTR, The Prosecutor v. Nyiramasuhuko et al., Appeals Chamber, Judgement, vol. II, 14
December 2015, ICTR-98-42-A, para. 2843 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/93cee1/), re-
ferring to ICTR, The Prosecutor v. Karemera et al., Appeals Chamber, Judgement, 29 Sep-
tember 2014, ICTR-98-44-A, para. 24 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/372a64/); ICTR, The
Prosecutor v. Hategekimana, Appeals Chamber, Judgement, 8 May 2012, ICTR-00-55B-A,
para. 16 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/885b2c/); Nahimana et al. Appeal Judgment, pa-
ra. 48, see above note 18; Akayesu Appeal, para. 91, see above note 23; Furundžija Appeal
Judgement, para. 197, see above note 15.
26
Nahimana et al. Appeal Judgment, para. 48, see above note 18, referring to Furundžija Ap-
peal Judgement, para. 197, see above note 15.
27
Karemera et al. Decision of 7 March 2008, para. 6, see above note 16, referring to Ntahobali
Decision of 7 March 2006, para. 9, see above note 19; Delalić et al. Appeal Judgment, pa-
ra. 707, see above note 18.
28
ICTR, The Prosecutor v. Karemera et al., Reasons for Decision on Interlocutory Appeals
Regarding the Continuation of Proceedings with a Substitute Judge and on Nzirorera’s Mo-
tion for Leave to Consider New Material, 22 October 2004, ICTR-98-44-AR15bis.2, pa-
ra. 67 (‘Karemera et al. Decision of 22 October 2004’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/
7e9d02/).
29
Ibid., para. 67.
30
Ibid., para. 69.
31
ICTY, Prosecutor v. Šešelj, Decision on Defence Motion for Disqualification of Judge Fred-
erik Harhoff and Report to the Vice-President, 28 August 2013, IT-03-67-T, para. 12 (‘Šešelj
Decision of 28 August 2013’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/5b4aa1/).
32
Ibid., para. 13.
33
Ibid., Dissenting Opinion of Judge Liu, para. 2.
34
Ibid., para. 8.
35
Ibid., para. 9.
36
See, for example, ICTY Statute, Article 15, see above note 10; STL Statute, Article 28, see
above note 10; IRMCT Statute, Article 13, see above note 10.
37
See, for example, ICTY RPE, Rule 19(B), see above note 13; STL RPE, Rule 32(E), see
above note 13; IRMCT RPE, Rule 23(B), see above note 13.
38
In a similar fashion, an ICC Code of Conduct for the Office of the Prosecutor was drafted as
an institutional priority at an early stage, as an important means of cultivating coherence be-
tween the being of prosecutors and doing of investigations. See Salim A. Nakhjavani, “The
Origins and Development of the Code of Conduct”, in Morten Bergsmo, Klaus Rackwitz
The preamble of the ICC CoJE is brief and notably refers to the sol-
emn undertaking, as provided for in Article 45 of the ICC Statute and
fleshed out in Rule 5(1)(a) of the ICC RPE. 39 The judges further recall
principles of judicial independence, impartiality and proper conduct, as
well as the “need for guidelines of general application to contribute to judi-
cial independence and impartiality and with a view to ensuring the legiti-
macy and effectiveness of the international judicial process”. Regard is no-
tably had to the UN Basic Principles on the Independence of the Judici-
ary (1985). 40
According to Article 1 of the ICC CoJE, the Code is adopted by the
judges pursuant to Regulation 126 of the Regulations of the Court. Indeed,
the latter provision incorporates an explicit legal basis for the adoption of
the CoJE, which is to be drawn up by the ICC President upon consultation
with the judges – and to be adopted by the majority of the judges. The
Regulations of the Court being adopted by the judges themselves, 41 it does
appear somewhat circular to note that a legal basis for the adoption of the
CoJE was adopted by the same actors who eventually adopted the CoJE
itself. However, as will be seen below, this was not the case with other Co-
JEs, and may also be seen as demonstrative of the ICC judges’ awareness
of the necessity for such a Code, and consequently, for a clear legal basis
for that purpose – it may, of course, be asked whether this was so because
the judges were conscious of the general importance of such a Code for the
purpose of ensuring the integrity of the judicial process, or whether the Co-
JE was adopted in order to provide a more detailed framework to flank the
disciplinary procedure the judges are subjected to by virtue of Articles 46-
47 of the ICC Statute and Rules 23-32 of the ICC RPE, both imposed upon
them by the States Parties. Article 11(1) of the ICC CoJE would point to
the latter interpretation, as it is stipulated that its principles shall “serve as
guidelines on the essential ethical standards required of judges in the per-
and SONG Tianying (eds.), Historical Origins of International Criminal Law: Volume 5,
2017, p. 954 (https://www.toaep.org/ps-pdf/24-bergsmo-rackwitz-song).
39
The solemn undertaking of Prosecutors also served as source for one of the central concepts
of the draft ICC Code of Conduct for the Office of the Prosecutor. See ibid., p. 959.
40
Basic Principles on the Independence of the Judiciary, adopted by the Seventh United Na-
tions Congress on the Prevention of Crime and the Treatment of Offenders held at Milan
from 26 August to 6 September 1985 and endorsed by General Assembly resolutions 40/32
of 29 November 1985 and 40/146 of 13 December 1985 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/
rnabsy/).
41
ICC Statute, Article 52(1), see above note 10.
formance of their duties. They are advisory in nature and have the object of
assisting judges with respect to ethical and professional issues with which
they are confronted”. 42 Academic commentators point to the same interpre-
tation, as it has been noted that the ICC CoJE
was adopted in response to the need for general guidelines to
contribute to judicial independence and impartiality and with
the aim of ensuring the legitimacy and effectiveness of the in-
ternational judicial process. […] The [ICC CoJE] provides the
guidelines on the essential ethical standards required of judges
according to the principles of independence, impartiality, in-
tegrity, confidentiality and diligence. As such, it will assist in
assessing any complaint of misconduct alleged against a judge
of the [ICC]. 43
42
Emphasis added.
43
“Article 46”, in Otto Triffterer and Kai Ambos (eds.), Commentary on the Rome Statute of
the International Criminal Court, third edition, C.H. Beck, Hart, Nomos, 2016, para. 5.
Rule 14 of the ICTY RPE. Further, the judges recall the UN Basic Princi-
ples on the Independence of the Judiciary (1985).
According to its Article 1, the ICTY CoJE is adopted by the judges
pursuant to Rule 24 of the ICTY RPE. The latter provision is entitled “Ple-
nary Meetings of the Tribunal” and incorporates in its sub-rules a range of
competences of judges. Article 1 of the ICTY CoJE, however, does not
specify which sub-rule is being applied in this respect – thought may have
been had to Rule 24(iv) or (vi) 44 of the ICTY RPE. However, neither of
these sub-rules are a perfect fit: a “decision upon matters relating to the
internal function of the Chambers and the Tribunals” would have to be in-
terpreted very broadly to cover the adoption of a legislative document. The
same consideration applies to the “exercise of other functions provided for
in the Statute or in the Rules” – given that, aside from the RPE, the adop-
tion of legislative instruments by the judges (as opposed to the President) is
not provided for in the ICTY Statute or its RPE.
This is symptomatic of a regulatory void, which could be explained
by the fact that a CoJE was simply not envisaged for an ICT established in
1993. Having nevertheless adopted this CoJE, the judges demonstrated cre-
ativity as far as a legal basis is concerned. It is questionable whether this
would have withstood a serious challenge – however, this remains a strictly
hypothetical question, given that the CoJE did not contain any disciplinary
mechanism, thus providing no forum for such a challenge; and, most im-
portantly, given that such a challenge never took place, whilst the ICTY
shut its doors in 2017.
18.3.1.4. STL (2016)
The preamble of the STL CoJE – in a similar fashion as the ICTY CoJE –
refers back to Article 9(1) of the STL Statute, which provides for the quali-
fications of judges, as well as for the solemn declaration to be undertaken
by each judge under Rule 24 of the STL RPE. In a unique fashion, the STL
judges take note of the “process for excusal or disqualification of judges
provided in Rule 25 of the [STL] Rules”. Whilst the relationship between
the latter proceedings and the CoJE is not further fleshed out, its mention-
ing does point to an obvious connection between processes of excusal and
44
ICTY RPE, Rule 24(iv) and (vi), see above note 13: “Judges shall meet in plenary to […] (iv)
decide upon matters relating to the internal functioning of the Chambers and the Tribunal;
[…] (vi) exercise any other functions provided for in the Statute or in the Rules”.
45
STL RPE, Rule 40(ii) and (iv), see above note 13: “Judges shall meet in plenary to […] (iv)
decide upon matters relating to the internal functioning of the Chambers and the Tribunal;
[…] (vi) exercise any other functions provided for in the Statute or in the Rules”.
46
The Republic of Kosovo, Law on Specialist Chambers and Specialist Prosecutor’s Office,
adopted on 3 August 2015 (‘KSC Law’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/8b71c3/).
47
See Exchange of Letters between the Kosovo President and the EU High Representative,
pp. 8–9.
50
See Sections 18.4.1.3. and 18.4.2. below.
51
IRMCT RPE, Rule 26(A)(iii) and (v), see above note 13: “Judges may decide in Plenary to:
[…] (iii) decide upon matters relating to the internal functioning of the Chambers and the
Tribunal; […] (v) exercise any other functions provided for in the Statute or in the Rules”.
always when it comes to the adoption and content of RPE of ICTs, given
the lack of travaux préparatoires, the ratio for this remains unclear.
The most encouraging example of a legal basis may be found in the
ICC Regulations of the Court, providing for an explicit legal basis – even
though arguably out of necessity in light of the disciplinary system im-
posed by States Parties. It is further encouraging that the States Parties
chose to impose a system of disciplinary proceedings – a measure not taken
in respect of neither the ECCC, the ICTY, the IRMCT or the STL.
The KSC regulations are further encouraging, as they demonstrate
that the foundational documents of such institutions may also incorporate
the indication of a necessity to put into place disciplinary mechanisms, as
demonstrated in Article 31(4) of the KSC Law.
18.3.2. Applicable Standards
The CoJEs analysed in this chapter set out a number of principles, the re-
spective wording of which has evolved over the years. In this section, each
of these principles and their evolution will be briefly presented – starting
from the first adopted CoJE, the ICC CoJE, and analysing how the wording
of each provision developed.
18.3.2.1. Judicial Independence
A cornerstone of judicial ethics, judicial independence is incorporated as
the first article of every CoJE. The initial wording of the ICC CoJE, incor-
porated verbatim by the ECCC CoJE, read as follows:
1. Judges shall uphold the independence of their office and
the authority of the [Court/ECCC] and shall conduct them-
selves accordingly in carrying out their judicial functions.
2. Judges shall not engage in any activity which is likely to
interfere with their judicial functions or to affect confi-
dence in their independence. 52
Subsequent CoJEs of the ICTY, the STL and the IRMCT replaced
Paragraph 1 of this Article with the following wording:
1. In the exercise of their judicial functions, Judges shall be
independent of all external authority or influence. 53
52
ICC CoJE, Article 3, see above note 4; ECCC CoJE, Article 1, see above note 5.
53
ICTY CoJE, Article 2, see above note 3; STL CoJE, Article 2, see above note 6; IRMCT
CoJE, Article 2, see above note 8.
The KSC CoJE provides the most comprehensive version of this Ar-
ticle, having kept all three paragraphs mentioned above. Importantly, the
KSC CoJE replaced the reference to the independence of “all external au-
thority and influence” by independence of “any authority and influence”. 54
This reflects a broad understanding of the concept of judicial independence,
incorporating both internal and external independence, as reflected in other
similar instruments. 55
In addition, in respect of the last paragraph, the KSC CoJE adds that
judges shall not engage in any activity which is likely to affect “respect for
their judicial office”.
In respect of the ICC, it is noteworthy that the principle of judicial
independence is also incorporated at Article 40 of ICC Statute itself. Whilst
Article 40(1) and (2) largely reflect the above provisions of the CoJE, Arti-
cle 40(3) provides that “Judges required to serve on a full-time basis at the
seat of the Court shall not engage in any other occupation of a professional
nature”. Article 40(4) goes further in providing for a procedure in case of
disagreement on the interpretation of Article 40(2) and (3): Any question
regarding their application shall be decided by a majority of judges, where-
by the judge concerned shall not take part in such a decision.
A question recently arose in respect of the interpretation of Arti-
cle 40(2) of the ICC Statute. The Judge in question had initially asked to
resign as a full-time judge, whilst indicating her readiness to continue sit-
ting on a non-full-time judge on a case to which she had been assigned
since the beginning of the trial and which was in the deliberation stage at
the relevant time. Her request was granted accordingly. 56 Shortly thereafter,
the Judge put forward a second request, notifying the ICC Presidency that
she had been appointed as ambassador for her country to a third country
and seeking the approval of her continued participation in the relevant ICC
case, whilst having taken up her position as ambassador. Regarding Arti-
cle 40(2) of the ICC Statute, the Judge submitted that her new responsibil-
ity would “not in any way interfere with [her] judicial function […] [n]or
would it affect confidence in her independence”. In particular, she noted
that her new responsibilities would be confined to the bilateral relationship
54
KSC CoJE, Article 3(1), see above note 9.
55
See, for example, Recommendation of Committee of Ministers, Recommendations 11-21
and 22-25, see above note 1.
56
ICC, Internal Memorandum, 19 March 2019, 2019/PRES/00003-21, paras. 3–4 (https://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/5a27d1/).
between her country and the third country and that she would refrain from
exercising her responsibilities in this respect if and when it may have any
implications for the relevant ICC case. Finally, the Judge stated that –
should her request not be granted – she would submit her resignation as an
ICC judge. 57
In accordance with the procedure provided in Article 40(4) of the
ICC Statute, the ICC Judges deliberated and, by absolute majority, came to
the conclusion that the Judge’s request was “not incompatible with the re-
quirements of judicial independence established in [Article 40]”. 58 In doing
so, the Judges applied Article 40 in a concrete – rather than abstract – man-
ner, noting that the language of the provision suggested that it is concerned
with “the concrete question of whether functions actually being performed
by a specific judge could affect judicial independence”. 59 The majority fur-
ther noted the language of Article 40(2), namely reference to any activity
“likely to” affect confidence in a judge’s independence, and concluded that
“likelihood denotes a level of certainty beyond more speculation or possi-
bility”. 60 Having established the latter, the majority focussed on the second
limb of Article 40(2) and, in this respect, took into account that the Judge’s
professional activities as ambassador would be entirely confined to the bi-
lateral relationship between the Judge’s country and the third country, nei-
ther of which are connected to any case before the ICC. It further noted the
Judge’s commitment to refraining from exercising her responsibilities
where this may impact on the relevant ICC case. The majority thus con-
cluded that it was “not likely that performing her functions as Ambassador
to [the third country] would affect confidence in [the Judge’s] independ-
ence as Judge of the Court”. 61
The minority took a different position. Equally concerned with the
second limb of Article 40(2) of the ICC Statute, it noted that the question of
the “likelihood of affecting confidence in judicial independence” is “inevi-
tably concerned with the appearance of judicial independence, in the eyes
of reasonable outsider observers”. 62 It is noteworthy that this standard is
57
Ibid., para. 5.
58
Ibid., para. 8.
59
Ibid., para. 10.
60
Ibid., para. 11.
61
Ibid., para. 13.
62
Ibid., para. 15.
63
See Section 18.2. above.
64
Ibid., para. 15.
65
Ibid., para. 15, referring to ICTY, Prosecutor v. Delalić et al., Decision of the Bureau on
Motion on Judicial Independence, 4 September 1998, IT-96-21-T (https://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/c2f2bf/).
66
See, for example, Kevin John Heller, “Judge Ozaki Must Resign — Or Be Removed”, Opin-
io Juris, 29 March 2019 (available on its web site).
18.3.2.2. Impartiality
The initial wording of the principle of impartiality adopted by the ICC Co-
JE is reflected verbatim in the ECCC CoJE:
1. Judges shall be impartial and ensure the appearance of im-
partiality in the discharge of their judicial functions.
2. Judges shall avoid any conflict of interest, or being placed
in a situation which might reasonably be perceived as giv-
ing rise to a conflict of interest. 67
This largely reflects the jurisprudence discussed above in respect of the
disqualification of judges. 68
In respect of paragraph (1), the KSC CoJE implemented a slight
amendment, reflecting that judges “shall exercise their functions impartial-
ly” rather than simply “be impartial”. 69 This may be interpreted as the at-
tempt to narrow the concept of impartiality further and tie it to the actual
exercise of their judicial functions.
Regarding paragraph (2), one minor, yet noteworthy, amendment to
the above wording was implemented into the ICTY, STL, KSC and IRMCT
CoJEs: Instead of avoiding “being placed” in situations which might rea-
sonably be perceived as giving rise to a conflict of interest, judges shall
simply avoid such situations altogether:
1. Judges shall avoid any conflict of interest, as well as situa-
tions which might reasonably be perceived as giving rise to
a conflict of interest. 70
This may be read as reflecting the understanding that judges may not
only be passively placed in such situations but that there may be situations
where they actively contributed thereto – which shall be avoided altogether.
67
ICC CoJE, Article 4, see above note 4; ECCC CoJE, Article 2, see above note 5; ICTY CoJE,
Article 3, see above note 3; STL CoJE, Article 3, see above note 6; KSC CoJE, Article 4, see
above note 9; IRMCT CoJE, Article 3, see above note 8.
68
See Section 18.2. above.
69
KSC CoJE, Article 4(1), see above note 9.
70
ICTY CoJE, Article 3, see above note 3; STL CoJE, Article 3, see above note 6; KSC CoJE,
Article 4, see above note 9; IRMCT CoJE, Article 3, see above note 8. Note that KSC CoJE,
Article 4 further specifies “any situation”.
18.3.2.3. Integrity
The principle of integrity, as reflected in the wording of the various CoJEs,
has undergone significant changes since the adoption of the initial version
of the ICC CoJE:
1. Judges shall conduct themselves with probity and integrity
in accordance with their office, thereby enhancing public
confidence in the judiciary.
2. Judges shall not directly or indirectly accept any gift, ad-
vantage, privilege or reward that can reasonably be per-
ceived as being intended to influence the performance of
their judicial functions. 71
Aside from minor amendment to paragraphs (1) 72 and (2), 73 the most
important change came with the addition of a new paragraph (3) in the IC-
TY, STL and IRMCT CoJEs:
3. Judges shall treat other judges and staff members with dig-
nity and respect, and shall not engage in any form of dis-
crimination, harassment, including sexual harassment, and
abuse of authority. 74
The addition of this paragraph marks a major step forward, even for
CoJEs not attaching disciplinary measures – the inclusion of this prohibi-
tion is emblematic of an awareness that judges may commit such offences
and that they should thus be subject to the same prohibitions in this respect
as any staff member of international organisations. 75 This stands in stark
contrast with the fact that similar prohibitions are missing from seminal
documents on the principles attaching to the judiciary, a number of which
71
ICC CoJE, Article 5, see above note 4.
72
“[…] in accordance with their judicial office […]”: ICTY CoJE, Article 3(1), see above note
3; STL CoJE, Article 4(1), see above note 6; IRMCT CoJE, Article 4(1), see above note 8.
73
“[…] the performance of their judicial functions or the independence of their office”. ECCC
CoJE, Article 3(2), see above note 5; ICTY CoJE, Article 4(2), see above note 3; STL CoJE,
Article 4(2), see above note 6; IRMCT CoJE, Article 4(2), see above note 8.
74
ICTY CoJE, Article 4(3), see above note 3; STL CoJE, Article 4(3), see above note 6;
IRMCT CoJE, Article 4(3), see above note 8.
75
For example, Prohibition of discrimination, harassment, including sexual harassment, and
abuse of authority, 11 February 2008, ST/SGB/2008/5 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/
ibc9oq/).
76
See United Nations Basic Principles on the Independence of the Judiciary, 1985, see above
note 40; Bangalore Principles, see above note 48; Recommendation of Committee of Minis-
ters, see above note 1.
77
Emphasis added.
78
See Section 18.2. above.
79
In a similar fashion, the ICC Code of Conduct for the Office of the Prosecutor was drafted in
order to serve as a “catalyst to unify the vision and harmonise the activities of the inherently
diverse membership of a unitary and permanent Office [of the Prosecutor] – one charged
with unique responsibilities to uphold international justice in a world shaped by increasingly
complex political, economic, social and moral crises and evolving collective patterns of re-
sponse”. See Nakhjavani, 2017, pp. 955–60, see above note 38.
80
See, for example, ‘ICC Judges hold retreat focusing on collegiality and various aspects of
judicial proceedings’, 28 September 2018, ICC-CPI-20180928-PR1412 (https://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/6ba117/).
81
See, for example, IRMCT, Code of Professional Conduct for Defence Counsel Appearing
Before the Mechanism, 14 November 2012, Article 3(v) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/
eeb133/); ICC Code of Professional Conduct for counsel, Article 24(1), ICC-ASP/4/Res.1
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/f9ed33/); ICC Regulations of the Court, 26 May 2004,
Regulation 69(3) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/2988d1/).
82
ICC CoJE, Article 6, see above note 4.
83
ICTY CoJE, Article 5, see above note 3; STL CoJE, Article 5, see above note 6; KSC CoJE,
Article 6, see above note 9; IRMCT CoJE, Article 5, see above note 8; ECCC CoJE, Article
4, see above note 5.
84
This was not part of ECCC CoJE, Article 5(4), see above note 5.
85
ICC CoJE, Article 7, see above note 4; ECCC CoJE, Article 5, see above note 5.
86
ICTY CoJE, Article 6(1), see above note 3; STL CoJE, Article 6(1), see above note 6;
IRMCT CoJE, Article 6(1), see above note 8.
87
KSC CoJE, Article 7(1), see above note 9.
88
KSC Law, Article 26(2) see above note 46.
89
ICTY CoJE, Article 6(3), see above note 3; STL CoJE, Article 6(3), see above note 6;
IRMCT CoJE, see above note 8.
90
KSC CoJE, Article 7(3)-(5), see above note 9.
91
ICC CoJE, Article 8, see above note 4; ECCC CoJE, Article 6, see above note 5.
92
The issue of a judge’s lack of attentiveness during proceeding was indeed subject of appel-
late proceedings before the ICTY, Delalić et al. Appeal Judgment, paras. 628–629, see above
note 18.
93
STL CoJE, Article 7(1), see above note 6; IRMCT CoJE, Article 7(1), see above note 8.
whilst the KSC CoJE added to that the requirement that judges be “respect-
ful”. 94
In addition, both the STL and IRMCT CoJEs specified at Para-
graph (2) that judges shall exercise vigilance in controlling the manner of
questioning of witnesses, “particularly when they are victims”. 95 In this
respect, the KSC CoJE went even further and, stressing that special atten-
tion should be given to the right “and interest” of participants in the pro-
ceedings. In addition, a second sentence was added to Paragraph (2):
“Judges shall exercise particular vigilance in respect of vulnerable witness-
es, including victims of sexual and gender based violence and children”. 96
Overall, this may be seen as reflecting the evolution of the role and posi-
tion of victims within international criminal justice – from mere witnesses,
at the ad hoc tribunals to actual participants in proceedings, at the ICC, the
STL and the KSC. In addition, it stresses the awareness amongst judges of
the particularly vulnerable nature of certain victims – there are indications
that in the past, this may not always have been the case. 97
Finally, the KSC CoJE adopted a shortened version of Paragraph (3)
above, removing the first part of the sentence and reformulating it as fol-
lows: “Judges shall, to the extent possible, ensure that any person partici-
pating in the proceedings refrains from comments or conduct which are
degrading”. 98 This shortening may simply reflect the fact that the first part
of Paragraph (3) may be seen as covered by Paragraph (1) in any case –
and that it would be duplicative to keep both provisions in this respect.
18.3.2.7. Public Expression and Association
The following provision is included in the ICC and ECCC CoJEs as far as
Public Expression and Association is concerned:
1. Judges shall exercise their freedom of expression and as-
sociation in a manner that is compatible with their office
and that does not affect or appear to affect judicial inde-
pendence or impartiality.
94
KSC CoJE, Article 8(1), see above note 9.
95
STL CoJE, Article 7(2), see above note 6; IRMCT CoJE, see above note 8.
96
KSC CoJE, Article 8(2), see above note 9.
97
See Binaifer Nowrojee, “‘Your Justice is Too Slow’ – Will the ICTR Fail Rwanda’s Rape
Victims?”, in United Nations Research Institute for Social Development, Occasional Paper
10, November 2005, pp. 23–24.
98
KSC CoJE, Article 8(3), see above note 9.
99
ICC CoJE, Article 9, see above note 4; ECCC CoJE, Article 7, see above note 5.
100
STL CoJE, Article 8(2), see above note 6; KSC CoJE, Article 9(2), see above note 9;
IRMCT CoJE, Article 8(2), see above note 8.
101
KSC CoJE, Article 9(2), see above note 9.
102
Ibid., Article 9(3)-(4).
The ICTY CoJE did not include an equivalent provision, whilst the
STL, KSC and IRMCT CoJEs did not include Paragraph (2) above in their
equivalent provision. 104 It may be questioned whether this was because the
judges determined that it was covering a scenario obviously falling under
Paragraph (1) and that thus did not need to be further specified, or because
they considered that a political function was not per se incompatible with a
judicial function.
The case discussed above 105 demonstrates that this is not an abstract
question, but that it has concrete implications for ICTs, wherebyjudges may
be called upon to take up a position within a country’s executive. It is sug-
gested that it would perhaps have been wise to retain this provision in order
to provide clarity in this respect. On the other hand, it is recalled that Euro-
pean Court of Human Rights jurisprudence does not regard judicial and
executive functions as per se mutually exclusive, where matters to be de-
cided upon in their judicial functions fall outside of the ambit of powers
exercised as part of their executive functions. 106 It is perhaps in light of
such jurisprudence that the categorical exclusion clause contained in Para-
graph (2) above was removed by the STL, KSC and IRMCT CoJEs.
Finally, it is noted that the KSC CoJE, in fact, adopted its very own
version of this provision, reflecting once more its structure as tribunal func-
tioning with a roster of judges, who will exercise judicial functions only if
and when assigned to do so by the President:
In accordance with Article 26(4) of the Law, any activity un-
dertaken by Judges other than that before the Specialist
Chambers shall be compatible with their judicial functions
and the efficient and timely functioning of the Specialist
Chambers. 107
Indeed, judges of the KSC must be able to continue their regular pro-
fessional activities pending any assignment to exercise judicial functions
with the KSC – as long as it is compatible with these judicial functions, and
with the efficient and timely function of the institution.
103
ICC CoJE, Article 10, see above note 4; ECCC CoJE, Article 8, see above note 5.
104
STL CoJE, Article 9, see above note 6; IRMCT CoJE, Article 9, see above note 8.
105
See Section 18.3.2.1. above.
106
European Court of Human Rights (‘ECHR’), Sramek v. Austria, Judgment, 22 October 1984,
App. No. 8790/79, para. 40 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/de30a4/).
107
KSC CoJE, Article 10, see above note 9.
108
Ibid., Article 11.
109
See Bergsmo, 2018, p. 3, see above note 2.
110
Ibid.
CoJEs. The following section will thus focus on the procedures in place at
the ICC, the KSC and the IRMCT.
The disciplinary procedure at the ICC is not included in the CoJE it-
self – rather, the latter is found scattered throughout various regulatory
documents: Articles 46 and 47 of the ICC Statute; Rules 23-32 of the ICC
RPE; Regulations 119-125 of the Regulations of the Court. Both the KSC
and IRMCT CoJEs include a disciplinary procedure.
These procedures will be analysed in the following, focusing on the
definition of disciplinary offences, the procedure to be followed and the
sanctions to be imposed.
18.4.1. Disciplinary Offences
18.4.1.1. ICC
The ICC regime differentiates between “serious misconduct and serious
breach of duty”, defined in Rule 24 of the ICC RPE, and “misconduct of a
less serious nature”, defined in Rule 25 of the ICC RPE. The former is
linked to Article 46(1)(a) of the ICC Statute and may lead to removal from
office, whilst the latter is tied to Article 47 of the ICC Statute and may trig-
ger the imposition of disciplinary measures.
Rule 24(1) of the ICC RPE further differentiates between serious
misconduct in, and outside the course of official duties. Pursuant to
Rule 24(1)(a), the former constitutes conduct which is “incompatible with
official functions, and causes or is likely to cause serious harm to the prop-
er administration of justice before the Court or the proper internal function-
ing of the Court”. A non-exhaustive list of three examples is included. Pur-
suant to Rule 24(1)(b), serious misconduct outside the course of official
duties takes place where it is of grave nature that causes or is likely to
cause serious harm to the standing of the Court. “Serious misconduct” has
thus been interpreted to cover “not only professional conduct in relation to
the duties of the office but also personal behaviour in general and is there-
fore broader than ‘breach of duty’ which relates only to the duties of the
office”. 111
Pursuant to Rule 24(2), a “serious breach of duty” takes place where
a judge has been “grossly negligent in the performance of his or her duties
or has knowingly acted in contravention of those duties”. Here also, a non-
111
Triffterer and Ambos, 2016, para. 8, see above note 43.
112
Ibid., para. 8.
113
Emphasis added.
114
Ibid., para. 9.
115
Ibid., Article 47, para. 3.
116
Very limited variations in language are found in Article 13(1)(a)(i) (“[…] where such disclo-
sure seriously prejudicial to […]”), 13(1)(a)(ii) (“concealing or withholding information or
wording of Rule 24(1)(a) and (b) of the ICC RPE. In addition, Arti-
cle 13(1)(b) of the KSC CoJE provides two examples, reflecting situations
which could readily fall outside the course of official duties, namely:
(i) the commission of a criminal act which reflects adversely on the
Judge’s honesty and trustworthiness as a Judge; and
(ii) the engagement in conduct involving harassment, abuse of authority,
dishonesty, fraud, deceit or misrepresentation.
In the light of the above, Article 13(1)(a) could be interpreted as re-
flecting conduct occurring in the course of official duties, whilst Arti-
cle 13(1)(b) reflects conduct occurring outside such duties.
Article 14 of the CoJE provides a definition of “misconduct of a less
serious nature”. Here again, two alternatives are provided. Under Arti-
cle 14(1)(a), “misconduct of a less serious nature” is conduct that “causes
or is likely to cause harm to the proper administration of justice before the
Specialist Chambers or the proper internal functioning of the Specialist
Chambers”. A non-exhaustive list of examples is provided in this respect.
Pursuant to Article 14(1)(b), “misconduct of a less serious nature” is con-
duct that “causes or is likely to cause harm to the standing of the Specialist
Chambers”. No examples are provided in this respect. As in respect of Ar-
ticle 13 KSC CoJE, in light of the above examples, it may be suggested
that Article 14(1)(a) is concerned with misconduct committed in the course
of judicial duties, whilst Article 14(1)(b) captures a more broader category
of misconduct which may also include instances occurring outside such
duties, but which may nevertheless have an impact on the standing of the
Specialist Chambers.
18.4.1.3. IRMCT
Whilst the ICC and KSC have implemented very similar definitions of
misconduct, the IRMCT chose a different path. Indeed, pursuant to Arti-
cle 11(2)(a) of the IRMCT CoJE, “misconduct refers to conduct that consti-
tutes a violation of the standards set forth in this Code”. The brevity of this
provision is striking, and appears to have been inspired by Article 35(i) of
117
IRMCT Code of Professional Conduct for Defence Counsel Appearing Before the Mecha-
nism, see above note 81.
118
Where the President proprio motu initiates proceedings, the IRMCT CoJE, see above note 8,
specifies that the complaint would be addressed to the Judge who assumes the President’s
functions in accordance with Rule 24 of the IRMCT RPE, see above note 13. For the pur-
pose of the present description, references to the ‘President of the IRMCT’ shall be read as
including references to the Judge who assumes the President’s functions.
and voting. In particular, the responding judge may be heard, answer any
questions put to him or her, and provide further clarifications.
As far as the imposition of sanctions is concerned, and where the
judges conclude that an allegation of serious misconduct has been estab-
lished, they must decide by an absolute majority on the dismissal of the
responding judge from the roster, pursuant to Article 21(1) of the KSC Co-
JE. In this respect, Article 21 of the KSC CoJE is reflective of Article 31(4)
of the KSC Law. Where an absolute majority of judges favours a dismissal,
Article 21(2) of the KSC CoJE provides that it shall have “immediate ef-
fect” and that the responding judge “cease[s] to be part of the Specialist
Chambers”. Pursuant to this provision, there is no necessity for a recom-
mendation to the Appointing Authority to dismiss the judge and it is the
Plenary which takes the actual decision of dismissal. Considering that, pur-
suant to Article 28(4) of the KSC Law, it is the Appointing Authority which
appoints the KSC judges and places them on the roster for the duration of
the existence of the KSC, it is debatable whether the KSC judges them-
selves have the authority to dismiss one of their peers from the roster. Arti-
cle 31(4) of the KSC Law merely provides that no KSC judge may be dis-
missed – without specifying by whom – unless the absolute majority of
judges finds that “he or she has ceased to fulfil the requirements of Arti-
cles 27 and 31”. This would merely appear to provide the authority to the
Plenary to determine whether a judge has ceased to fulfil these require-
ments. Whether, in addition thereto, this amounts to a delegation of au-
thority to the Plenary for the actual dismissal of a judge may readily be
questioned. Article 31(4) of the KSC Law is less than clear in this respect
and the basic principle in cases of actus contrarius, applicable in European
Union (‘EU’) administrative law, 119 would dictate that a decision such as
the appointment of a judge to a roster may only be reversed by the authori-
ty who made the initial appointment, that is, the Appointing Authority.
However, as there is no jurisprudence as of yet in this respect, this question
must remain open for the time being.
Further, in case any allegations of misconduct of a less serious nature
are established, Article 22(2) of the KSC CoJE provides for a catalogue of
119
“[I]n accordance with a general principle of law that, in principle, a body which has power
to adopt a particular legal measure also has power to abrogate or amend it by adopting an
actus contarius, unless such power is expressly conferred upon another body.” The Court of
First Instance of European Communities, Lagardière and Canal+ v. Commission, Judgment,
20 November 2002, T-251/00, para. 130 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/510mj2/).
authority to remove an IRMCT judge from the roster. The only authority
provided by the IRMCT CoJE is that of reporting the matter to the authori-
ty who (re-)appoints IRMCT judges in accordance with Article 10(2), (3)
and (4) of the IRMCT Statute, that is, the UN Secretary-General, and to
request the removal of the judge concerned. It is interesting to note that the
authority which elects IRMCT judges, that is, the UN General Assembly in
accordance with Article 10(1) of the IRMCT Statute, is not involved in the
process. However, this would indicate at least to a certain extent that the
administrative act of appointment may only be reversed by the authority
who made an appointment –if and when the question arises at the KSC, the
IRMCT CoJE will thus be an interesting source to look into in order to fur-
ther interpret Articles 21 of the KSC CoJE and 31(4) of the KSC Law.
18.4.3. Procedure before the ICC
As spelled out above, the procedure before the ICC is set out in various
regulatory documents, namely the ICC Statute, its RPE and the Regulations
of the Court. 123 It is worth having a detailed look in this respect, particular-
ly because the initial regulatory framework was recently amended in the
ICC RPE. The following section will therefore outline the initial procedure,
followed by an analysis of the amendment thereto.
18.4.3.1. Initial Procedure 124
In its initial version, Rule 26(2) provided for any complaint to be transmit-
ted to the Presidency, which also had the competence to proprio motu initi-
ate proceedings. In accordance with this provision as well as with Regula-
tion 119(1), the Presidency then set aside anonymous or manifestly un-
founded complaints, with the assistance of three judges assigned on the
basis of automatic rotation. With the possibility of seeking submissions
from the persons being complained against or from the complainant, in ac-
123
For the purpose of the following section, any reference to ‘Article’ shall be a reference to the
ICC Statute; to ‘Rule’ shall be a reference to the ICC RPE; to ‘Regulation’ shall be a refer-
ence to the ICC Regulations of the Court.
124
See ICC Rules of Procedure and Evidence, 9 September 2002, Rule 26(2) (‘ICC RPE’)
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/8bcf6f/). It is noted that the initial version of Rule 26 of the
ICC RPE gave the Presidency the competence to receive complaints not only against Judges,
but also against the Prosecutor, the Registrar and the Deputy Registrar, as reflected not only
in the initial version of Rule 26(1) of the ICC RPE but also in Regulation 119(1) of the Reg-
ulations of the Court. For the purpose of the present paper, the focus will be on complaints
against Judges. As per the amended version of Rule 26(2), as set out below, the overall com-
petence of the Presidency has now been moved to the IOM.
125
Resolution on amendments to rule 26 of the Rules of Procedure and Evidence, 11 December
2018, ICC-ASP/17/Res.2 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/mhkgg7/).
126
“Draft resolution on amendments to rule 26 of the Rules of Procedure and Evidence”, an-
nexed to Report of the Working Group on Amendments, 29 November 2018, ICC-
ASP/17/35 (emphasis added).
127
See ICC Regulations of the Court, Regulations 119-122, see above note 81.
128
“Report of the Study Group on Governance Cluster I in relation to the amendment to rule 26
of the Rules of Procedure and Evidence”, annexed to Report of the Bureau on the Study
Group on Governance, 27 November 2018, ICC-ASP/17/30, para. 22 (‘Report ICC-
ASP/17/30’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/faoyip/).
the amendment to Rule 26 (December 2018) was adopted after the most
recent amendment to the Regulations of the Court (November 2018), is
thus open for speculation.
Relevant resolutions indicate that this fundamental amendment of
Rule 26 derives from the necessity to make it compatible with the opera-
tional mandate of the IOM, 129 created in 2009 130 with its operational man-
date defined in 2013. 131 The ASP requested that such an amendment be
considered, 132 and the amendment itself was then recommended by the
Study Group on Governance 133 and the Working Group on Amendments. 134
During consultations in respect of this amendment, the ICC Presi-
dency noted that – since the establishment of the IOM – a practice had de-
veloped whereby the Presidency would send any complaints received to the
IOM, which reported the result of its investigation to the Presidency,
which – in turn – would send the report to the panel of three judges. A for-
mer head of the IOM had accordingly suggested that an amendment be
adopted to reflect this practice. 135 However, during consultations, a range
of States Parties noted the need to avoid “any potential conflict of interest
between the role of those who judge and those who are to be judged and
the necessity for an independent and impartial investigation”. 136 A drafting
option retaining a role for the Presidency and the judges in the investiga-
tion whilst reflecting the IOM’s mandate was eventually rejected in favour
of the current version, which clearly removes any role of the Presidency
and judges in the investigation and thus provides for the IOM alone to con-
duct the investigation and make recommendations to the ASP and the Pres-
129
Ibid., para. 3.
130
ICC, Establishment of an independent oversight mechanism, adopted on 26 November 2009,
Resolution ICC-ASP/8/Res. 1 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/bf0e8c/).
131
ICC, Independent Oversight Mechanism Resolution, adopted on 27 November 2013, ICC-
ASP/12/Res.6 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/64ebeb/).
132
ICC, “Mandate of the Assembly of State Parties for the intersessional period”, annexed to
Strengthening the International Criminal Court and the Assembly of States Parties, adopted
on 14 December 2017, Resolution ICC-ASP/16/Res.6, para. 9(c) (https://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/36d60d/).
133
Report ICC-ASP/17/30, paras. 26–27, see above note 128.
134
ICC, Report of the Working Group on Amendments, 29 November 2018, Report ICC-ASP/
17/35, paras. 17–20, 28 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/ceidsz/).
135
Report ICC-ASP/17/30, para. 11, see above note 128.
136
Ibid., para. 12.
idency accordingly. In favouring this option, the necessity for clarity on the
leadership of investigation was stressed by a range of States Parties. 137
In so doing, the ICC aligned its procedure with that applied at the
KSC and the IRMCT, namely allowing for an investigation to be conducted
by an independent body. Although the IOM is established as subsidiary
body of the ASP in accordance with Article 112(4) and thus would not
strictly qualify as ‘external’, this amendment remains a significant step
forward from the initial procedure, which provided for three ICC judges
respectively the Presidency to investigate and make recommendations on
allegations in respect of their own colleagues. As noted by a range of States
Parties, it thus constitutes a momentous step forward vis-à-vis the initial
version of the procedure and towards guaranteeing its fairness and trans-
parency. 138
Ultimately, the decision on whether or not to remove a judge still re-
mains subject to a vote by the Plenary, in accordance with Rule 29(1), and
to a decision by the ASP, pursuant to Article 46(2)(a). This is similar to the
procedure applied at the IRMCT and is a further confirmation of the prac-
tice of actus contrarius – namely that a decision of removal of a judge may
ultimately only be taken by the ASP, as the body which elected the judge in
the first place pursuant to Article 36(6). Further, a decision to impose disci-
plinary measures remains within the competence of the Presidency, in ac-
cordance with Rule 30(1). Again, this follows the procedure applied at the
IRMCT, and – to a certain extent – at the KSC, where the latter decision is
left with the Plenary rather than the President.
The second crucial matter regulated in the recent amendment to
Rule 26 is the possibility of submitting anonymous complaints: indeed, the
first sentence of the new Rule 26(1) in fine provides that a complaint
“may” include the identity of the complainant. This is a fundamental
amendment vis-à-vis the initial version, which provided for the Presidency
to set aside anonymous complaints. In so doing, the ICC disciplinary pro-
cedure moves away from the procedure applied at the IRMCT and the KSC,
where the identity of the complainant has to be included, and anonymous
complaints must accordingly be summarily dismissed. 139
137
Ibid., paras. 13–14.
138
Ibid., para. 12.
139
See KSC CoJE, Articles 15(5)(a) and 17(1), see above note 9 and IRMCT CoJE, Article
11(6)(a), see above note 8; It is noted that, unlike the KSC CoJE, the IRMCT CoJE does not
provide for the obligation to dismiss an anonymous complaint. However, given the obliga-
tion to include the identity of the complainant provided in Article 11(6)(a) IRMCT CoJE, it
is submitted that an anonymous complaint would have to be dismissed as unreceivable in
accordance with Article 12(1), Sentence 4 IRMCT CoJE, see above note 8.
140
Report ICC-ASP/17/30, para. 15, see above note 128.
141
Ibid.
142
Ibid., para. 24(c).
143
See ICC Whistle-blowing and Whistle-blower Protection Policy, 8 October 2014,
ICC/PRESD/G/2014/003 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/0c36ff/); Bergsmo, 2018, pp. 3–4,
see above note 2.
Also, on the downside, one central issue when reviewing the disci-
plinary proceedings is the lack of accessible jurisprudence to analyse
whether and how the latter function in practice. It is noted that both the
KSC and IRMCT CoJEs include regulations to keep any proceedings in
relation thereto confidential as a matter of principle. Whilst public redacted
versions of some records are envisaged, 144 it is unclear which records are
concerned, how this will be handled in practice and it can thus far only be
noted that there are no such records available. As far as the ICC regime is
concerned, it does not provide for clear provisions regarding confidentiality.
Amended Rule 26(1) of the ICC RPE merely regulates that any complaint
shall remain confidential. How any other record will be handled is not fur-
ther specified – and here also, the lack of any accessible jurisprudence is
striking. 145
18.5. Final Remarks
The above analysis paints a mixed picture – whereby some clear conclu-
sions may be drawn, particularly on whether or not a culture of accounta-
bility is emerging for the judiciary in ICTs.
A review of the regulations and jurisprudence applied to motions for
disqualification determined that it is less than satisfactory in holding ac-
countable central participants in proceedings, namely the judges them-
selves. There was therefore a real necessity in putting systems of accounta-
bility into place– the first step of which was to further define the principles
applicable to judges, and to eventually attach disciplinary procedures and
sanctions to any violation thereof.
An analysis of the preambles and legal bases of various CoJEs re-
vealed that, in doing so, judges were notably mindful of their own solemn
undertakings as well as of UN or EU principles of judicial ethics. In a
unique manner, the STL CoJE expressly made the link with the process of
excusal and disqualification of judges, which demonstrates the close link
between this process and the principles of judicial ethics adopted in the Co-
JEs. It is striking that the ICC is the only institution which provides an ex-
plicit legal basis for the adoption of the CoJE. For all other ICTs, the actual
legal basis thereof remains unclear at best and would perhaps not withstand
144
IRMCT CoJE, Articles 14(6) and 15, see above note 8 and KSC CoJE, Article 23, see above
note 9.
145
Triffterer and Ambos, 2016, para. 10, see above note 43.
146
Paris Declaration on the Effectiveness of International Criminal Justice, 16 October 2017,
p. 4 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/ow1amx/).
147
Oslo Recommendations for Enhancing the Legitimacy of International Courts, 26 July 2018,
p. 2 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/4g0kcc/).
Reflections on Integrity in
International Criminal Justice and
Regional Human Rights Courts
Erik Møse *
19.1. Introduction
For this volume I would like to provide some reflections on integrity chal-
lenges facing international criminal courts and regional human rights courts.
This may seem surprising at first sight, as the two groups of courts seem-
ingly perform different tasks: criminal courts decide whether to convict or
acquit individuals after trials, whereas human rights institutions establish
State responsibility based on complaint procedures and examination of re-
ports from States. Moreover, each group includes courts with different
characteristics. In the criminal sphere, the two ad hoc tribunals set up in the
1990s to address the atrocities in the former Yugoslavia and Rwanda (‘IC-
TY’ and ‘ICTR’, respectively) in many ways differed from the hybrid
courts set up from 2002 with respect to Sierra Leone, Cambodia and Leba-
non (‘SCSL’, ‘ECCC’ and ‘STL’, respectively). The International Criminal
Court (‘ICC’), established by the Rome Statute in 1998, 1 is unique, as it is
the only permanent international criminal court. Turning to the three re-
gional courts in the human rights field – the European Court of Human
Rights, the Inter-American Court of Human Rights, and the African Court
of Human and Peoples’ Rights – they have different structures and their
powers are not identical.
This said, these courts certainly have common features. They are in-
ternational; they intervene because of alleged deficiencies at the national
level; their aim is to reduce the occurrence of human rights abuses; and
they frequently find themselves in the public spotlight, facing more or less
*
Erik Møse is Judge of the Supreme Court of Norway. He was previously Judge of the Euro-
pean Court of Human Rights, and President of the International Criminal Tribunal for
Rwanda.
1
Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court, 17 July 1998 (http://www.legal-tools.org/
doc/7b9af9/).
2
These principles are reflected in the Preamble of the ECHR, 4 November 1950
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/8267cb) and in Articles 1–3 of the Statute of the Council of
Europe, 5 May 1949, and have frequently been confirmed in the case-law of the European
Court of Human Rights.
3
See, for instance, the preamble of Security Council Resolution 955 (1994) on the Establish-
ment of an International Tribunal and adoption of the Statute of the Tribunal, UN Doc.
S/RES/955 (1994), 8 November 1994 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/f5ef47/).
4
Security Council Resolution 827 (1993) on Establishment of the International Tribunal for
Prosecution of Persons Responsible for Serious Violations of International Humanitarian
Law Committed in the Territory of the Former Yugoslavia since 1991, UN Doc. S/RES/827
(1993), 25 May 1993 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/b4f63b).
5
Security Council Resolution 977 (1995) on the Decision to Designate Arusha as the Seat of
the ICTR, UN Doc. S/RES/977 (1995), 22 February 1995 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/
396c27). See also: Report of the Secretary-General Pursuant to Paragraph 5 of Security
Council Resolution 955 (1994), UN doc. S/1995/134, 13 February 1994 (https://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/b38d44d).
trators will normally be high, the international criminal courts cannot pos-
sibly deal with all of them, but have to focus on the leaders. This may lead
some observers to believe that the process is selective. In addition, the vol-
ume and complexity of cases dealing with international crimes slow down
the trials, again creating disappointment. Similarly, the Strasbourg Court is
considered by many applicants in Europe their only beacon of hope; they
have – rightly or wrongly – no confidence that their national authorities,
including the judiciaries, will redress human rights violations. Nonetheless,
because of the Court’s large workload, the process usually takes years,
which may lead to impatience and disappointment.
These four general characteristics are among the reasons why inter-
national courts are under scrutiny by several groups. In addition, States
Parties contributing to the institutions’ big budgets want value for their
money. Meanwhile, the slow progress of international criminal courts leads
to what has often been referred to as ‘tribunal fatigue’. 6 Some countries
may have a specific interest in the outcome, for instance, Rwanda with re-
spect to the ICTR, and the respondent State in Strasbourg. In the courtroom,
not only will the parties in criminal cases (the prosecution and the defence)
and in human rights proceedings (the applicant and the respondent State)
follow the bench closely, but witnesses or victims will also notice mistakes
or weaknesses. More generally, the media, non-governmental organizations,
academic observers, and the world community at large attach importance to
the international courts’ performance.
It is therefore essential that there be no doubt about the legitimacy of
an international court. Its credibility depends on the performance of the
many individuals working inside each institution – judges as well as staff.
Institutional legitimacy requires individual integrity.
19.3. Inefficiency
In conformity with the overall focus of this anthology, this contribution fo-
cuses on personal integrity. This said, there is no watertight division be-
tween the institutional legitimacy of an institution and the performance of
its employees. Their daily activities should be in conformity with the aims
6
This term has even found its way into the literature: see, for instance, Roger P. Alford, “The
Proliferation of International Courts and Tribunals: International Adjudication in Ascend-
ance”, in Proceedings of the Annual Meeting (American Society of International Law), 2000,
vol. 94, pp. 160–165.
10
European Court of Human Rights, “Interlaken Declaration”, 19 February 2010; European
Court of Human Rights, “Izmir Declaration”, 27 April 2011; as well as several follow-up
proposals within the Council of Europe.
11
Council of Europe, Protocol No. 14 to the European Convention on Human Rights, 13 May
2004 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/dd5017).
12
For an overview over up-to-date statistics regarding current pending cases by the European
Court of Human Rights, see “Statistics” (available on its web site).
quently, the plans for an overall reform of the ECHR’s supervisory system
were not followed up. Recent ministerial conferences have instead focused
on the need to strengthen the existing court system and on the principle of
subsidiarity. 13 Last but not least, the Court has constantly tried to stream-
line its internal working methods in order to increase its judicial output.
19.4. Personal Integrity – Some Illustrations
Criticism relating to the personal integrity of individuals working in inter-
national courts may cover quite different situations. It is my impression that
allegations of mismanagement, or even corruption or other illegal acts, are
rare. Should such criticism occur, it is important that the institution carry
out thorough investigations, even if the person accused of such behaviour
has left, in order to clarify whether the allegation has any factual basis and,
if so, to take necessary measures and demonstrate a rupture with the past.
I cannot recall any relevant illustrations from Strasbourg. In Arusha,
there was, in the early years, serious operational deficiencies, in particular
in the Registry. This resulted in administrative improvements from 1997.
Subsequently, there were occasionally other allegations, for instance, about
unsatisfactory witness protection if a witness had been assaulted after re-
turning to Rwanda subsequent to his testimony. Such assertions were al-
ways subject to thorough investigations, leading to the finding that there
was no basis for criticism against the Tribunal.
A more common form of criticism relates to what could generally be
called questionable behaviour in connection with the judicial proceedings.
This may take different forms. Below follow a few examples.
Starting with the behaviour in the courtroom, criticism against the
Strasbourg proceedings are extremely rare. The hearings normally last only
two to three hours and consist of oral pleadings (about 45 minutes from
each party), brief questions from the judges, and responses.
The situation is more complicated in international criminal courts
with trials lasting for up to hundreds of days, covering a variety of situa-
tions. For instance, the cross-examination of witnesses who are also vic-
tims of grave crimes presents challenges to lawyers testing their credibility
13
See, to some extent, European Court of Human Rights, “Brighton Declaration”, 20 April
2020, and more clearly “Brussels Declaration”, 27 March 2015, and “Copenhagen Declara-
tion”, 13 April 2018.
even if they will normally take into account that such witnesses are vulner-
able.
In all court settings, it is essential that judges’ questions not be per-
ceived as biased, as this may easily lead to doubts about the legitimacy of
the institution. Needless to say, this does not in any way limit a judge’s in-
dependence or freedom of expression. There are many ways to formulate a
question.
A point of particular relevance to international criminal trials is that
the judges must avoid unnecessary use of time in the courtroom; otherwise
their court will be perceived as inefficient (see Section 19.2 above). It is
necessary to find the right balance between efficient and fair proceedings,
for instance, when the parties ask for more time. There are examples of
what some observers would characterize as an unnecessary consumption of
time, both with respect to the taking of evidence and during discussions of
procedural issues.
Another illustration, which is relevant to both groups of international
courts, relates to the use of separate opinions (concurring or dissenting).
While national systems differ on the acceptance of such opinions, most in-
ternational courts allow them, either explicitly or by implication. There is
no doubt that such opinions may be necessary and useful, and it goes with-
out saying that their use does not in itself raise any risk to the legitimacy of
a court. However, if some judges resort to this possibility too frequently, or
if a separate opinion is quite lengthy (perhaps even longer than the majority
judgment), there is a risk that the message of the court’s judgments become
less clear and leave observers with the impression that the court is more
divided than it really is. Lengthy opinions also require considerable re-
sources (for example, translation and checking of footnotes) and may even
slow down the delivery of the judgment. Finally, it may be worth recalling
that separate opinions should be drafted in a way that is respectful to the
view of the majority. 14
Integrity issues may also arise in connection with the daily manage-
ment outside the context of the judicial proceedings. A recurring theme has
been to what extent a judge may be absent from the court in order to carry
out extra-judicial activities. Over the years, the general policy has general-
ly become stricter. The question now arises with respect to teaching or at-
tending conferences. As will be seen below (fourth and fifth remarks under
14
See also Section 19.5. below, text accompanying notes 21 et seq.
15
Guidelines for “Judges’ teaching activities”, adopted by the European Court of Human
Rights’ Bureau on 5 October 2011.
16
Morten Bergsmo, “Revisiting Integrity in International Justice”, FICHL Policy Brief Series
No. 93 (2018), Torkel Opsahl Academic EPublisher, Brussels, 2018 (https://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/e550f7/).
17
ICC, Code of Judicial Ethics, 2 January 2005, ICC-BD/02-01-05 (https://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/383f8f).
18
ICC, Code of Conduct for the Office of the Prosecutor, entry into force 5 September 2013
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/3e11eb). It includes, inter alia, provisions on general
standards, independence, honourable conduct, faithful conduct, conscientious conduct, im-
partiality, confidentiality, public expression and association, conflict of interest, and non-
acceptance of gifts.
19
International Residual Mechanism for Criminal Tribunals, Code of Professional Conduct of
the Judges of the Mechanism, MICT/14/Rev.1, 9 April 2018, (https://www.legal-tools.org/
doc/23cc92 (MICT/14)).
20
European Court of Human Rights, Resolution on Judicial Ethics, adopted by the Plenary
Court on 23 June 2008.
21
The Study Group of the International Law Association on the Practice and Procedure of
International Courts and Tribunals in association with the Project on International Courts
and Tribunals, “The Burgh House Principles on the Independence of the International Judi-
ciary”, 2004 (available on International Law Association’s web site).
22
The 17 principles deal with independence and freedom from interference; nomination, elec-
tion and appointment; security of tenure; service and remuneration; privileges and immuni-
ties; budget; freedom of expression and association; extra-judicial activity; past links to a
case or to a party; interest in the outcome of a case; contacts with a party; post-service limi-
tation; disclosure; waiver, withdrawal or disqualification; and misconduct.
23
Institut de Droit international, Sixth Commission, “The Position of the International Judge”,
adopted on 9 September 2011.
24
The seven articles give guidance concerning selection of judges; term of judicial functions;
status of judges; remuneration and conditions of service; organization of international courts
and tribunals (with emphasis on independence); immunities and privileges; and international
part-time judges.
25
The “Oslo Recommendation for Enhancing the Legitimacy of International Courts”, 26
September 2018 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/4g0kcc/), was drafted collectively on 2
June and finalised on 26 July 2018 by the participants of the Brandeis Institute for Interna-
tional Judges. The conference (30 May to 2 June 2018) was organized by the International
Center for Ethics, Justice and Public Life (Brandeis University) and the PluriCourts Centre
for the Study of the Legitimate Roles of the Judiciary in the Global Order (Faculty of Law,
University of Oslo).
26
The five sections (A to E) cover the following topics: nomination and selection of interna-
tional judges; ethics and judicial integrity; efficiency of proceedings; transparency of pro-
ceedings and access to judicial output; and role of judges in outreach and interactions with
the public.
27
Bergsmo, 2018, see above note 16.
This facilitates the appointment procedure and reduces the risk of surprises.
In international elections, however, the candidates are usually unknown to
those electing them. It is therefore advisable to ensure transparency of elec-
tions of international judges and other high officials.
One interesting example is the European Court of Human Rights’
election process. Each State Party nominates three candidates, and the Par-
liamentary Assembly of the Council of Europe elects one of them in re-
spect of the State concerned. The Assembly has adopted several recom-
mendations to improve the election process, the underlying approach being
that the national selection should be “rigorous, fair and transparent in order
to enhance the quality, efficacy and authority of the Court”. 28 In particular,
the national application procedure, both the announcement and the final
recommendation, should be as transparent as possible. Moreover, the As-
sembly’s election process, which includes interviews with the candidates,
has been improved in many ways.
The Committee of Ministers also established a committee with the
task to scrutinize the curricula vitae of the nominated candidates and give
advice before the three names are transmitted to the Assembly. 29 The com-
mittee has seven members with judicial experience. It has influenced the
nomination process in some countries.
19.6. Final Remarks
Criticism against institutions is common both at the national and interna-
tional levels. It concerns various entities: legislative, judicial and adminis-
trative. This is not surprising but rather reflects that the institutions are rel-
evant, exercise power, and hence should be scrutinized. Criticism is a sign
of interest in their work and may lead to improvements. An institution that
adopts a defensive attitude and does not react to well-founded criticism
risks losing its legitimacy.
Gradually, the international judiciary has become subject to debate.
Even though criminal courts and human rights courts differ in many ways,
28
For the many resolutions by the Parliamentary Assembly about the election of the judges to
the Strasbourg Court, see generally: Parliamentary Assembly of the Council of Europe, Pro-
cedure for the election of judges to the European Court of Human rights as of 15th of April
2019, SG-AS (2020) 03 rev 3, 30 September 2020.
29
Council of Europe, CM/Res/(2010)26 on the establishment of an Advisory Panel of Experts
on Candidates for Election as Judge to the European Court of Human Rights, 10 November
2010.
20.1. Introduction
‘Integrity’ is perhaps as often cited as it is too seldom considered in legal
discourse. It is for this reason that this anthology edited by Morten
Bergsmo and Viviane Dittrich is so welcome – and so sorely needed. The
word ‘integrity’, the concept and values that are embraced by it, are neither
throw-away lines, or redundant surplusage. Rather, without the integrity of
a criminal investigation, a legal process, or a lawyer, an investigator or oth-
er official engaged within it, due process is rendered a remote possibility.
*
Karim A.A. Khan QC, Assistant Secretary-General, is Special Adviser and Head of the UN
Investigative Team to promote Accountability for crimes committed by Da’esh/ISIL
(‘UNITAD’). As a barrister, he has been engaged as counsel for prosecution, victims or the
defence in cases before the ICC, the International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugosla-
via (‘ICTY’), International Criminal Tribunal for Rwanda (‘ICTR’), Special Court for Sierra
Leone (‘SCSL’), Extraordinary Chambers in the Courts of Cambodia (‘ECCC’), the Special
Tribunal for Lebanon (‘STL’), and the European Union Rule of Law Mission in Kosovo
(‘EULEX’) court in Kosovo and the Special Panel for Serious Crimes in East Timor. He has
also worked as a legal adviser in the Office of the Prosecutor (‘OTP’) of both the ICTY &
ICTR and in the Crown Prosecution Service and the Law Commission of England and
Wales. Jonathan Agar is a Legal Officer in the Office of the Special Adviser, UNITAD.
Previously, he has held positions with the United Nations Office of Legal Affairs, the United
Nations Office on Drugs and Crime, and the United Kingdom Government Legal Service.
This article is written by the authors in their personal capacity and does not represent the
views of the United Nations.
1
John Webster, The Duchess of Malfi, Act 1, Scene 1.
Without integrity in all its various forms, the law and its processes are lia-
ble to be brought into disrepute. The consequence will be an erosion of
trust in the vital pillar of justice and her various institutions.
The quote from John Webster’s play that frames this chapter articu-
lates a reality that integrity and leadership must commence from those ‘at
the top’ and percolate down. It warns of the danger and consequences that
will arise when the leadership is tainted or seen as polluted. But, as this
chapter will also seek to demonstrate, it is also the case that integrity in the
investigation of crimes, in accountability mechanisms and in the adjudica-
tion of crimes, requires a self-sustaining ecosystem in which – simultane-
ously – all parts are imbued with the quality of ‘integrity’ and in which all
parts scrutinize and, thereby, reinforce or help ensure the integrity of each
other.
As the work and activities of international courts, mechanisms and
investigative teams come under increasing scrutiny, our adherence to these
principles is rendered even more essential. As the voices of those States
and other actors questioning the value and legitimacy of international ac-
tion with respect to criminal accountability grow louder, advocates of glob-
al action must not be impeded by concerns and criticisms regarding the
transparency and effectiveness of the existing international criminal justice
architecture.
The responsibility for placing these principles of independence, im-
partiality and integrity at the centre of the cause of international criminal
justice ultimately resides with those charged with leading relevant entities.
As intimated, a culture of integrity must start with the heads of mechanisms
both leading by example and empowering senior and mid-level manage-
ment to implement an effective normative and institutional integrity
framework. A culture of integrity should be developed that cascades down
from mission leadership in a manner that ensures coherence of delivery and
a common and sincere commitment by all team members, international and
national, to its adherence.
While the central importance of the principles of integrity and impar-
tiality to the delivery of justice remains constant, the mechanisms and poli-
cies introduced to implement these concepts must respond to the context in
which they seek to operate. The application of integrity frameworks within
international criminal justice mechanisms established in recent times will
necessarily address challenges sometimes similar and at other times differ-
ent to those encountered 20 years ago at the time of the adoption of the
2
See Morten Bergsmo, “Revisiting Integrity in International Justice”, FICHL Policy Brief
Series No. 93 (2018), Torkel Opsahl Academic EPublisher, Brussels, 2018 (https://www.
legal-tools.org/doc/e550f7/).
3
United Nations Security Council (‘UNSC’), Resolution 2379 (2017), Threats to Internation-
al Peace and Security, UN Doc. S/RES/2379, 21 September 2017 (‘S/RES/2379’) (https://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/1510b4/).
justice entities can continue to adapt their integrity systems to their evolv-
ing mandates and operational imperatives.
With respect to the core normative framework, we will consider in
particular the interconnection and interaction between the broader frame-
work provided by the UN Charter, 4 the UN Staff Rules and Regulations, 5
and other system-level instruments, and the increasingly specialized integ-
rity architecture specific to the mandate and operational particularities of
UNITAD. Attention will be paid in this regard to how the concept of integ-
rity is addressed in the provisions of Security Council resolution 2379
(2017), the Terms of Reference regarding the activities of UNITAD in Iraq,
as approved by the Security Council on 13 February 2018, 6 as well as the
tailored integrity policies and practices implemented since the establish-
ment of the Team. Some of these are bespoke to UNITAD and some are
simply functions of established good practice that is essential to ensuring
the integrity of evidence. Chain of custody, a preference for the best evi-
dence, where available, proper interview protocols and interaction with
witnesses, and a degree of circumspection regarding hearsay without sup-
porting evidence, are all factors that are tried and tested – and recognizable
elements, in one form or another, in most legal systems.
Drawing on the experience gained since the commencement of the
activities of UNITAD in Baghdad in October 2018, consideration will be
given to three key aspects of its work which have engaged the concepts of
integrity, impartiality and independence. First, we will consider the indi-
vidual and personal level of integrity. We will reflect on how common con-
cepts of impartiality and independence can be instilled in all staff members
within an organization that draws not only on the talents of over 150 staff
4
Charter of the United Nations, 1 UNTS XVI, 24 October 1945, Articles 100 and 101 in par-
ticular (‘UN Charter’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/6b3cd5/).
5
Most recently, see amendments introduced through UN General Assembly resolution, Hu-
man Resources Management, UN Doc. A/RES/72/254, 24 December 2017 (‘A/RES/72/254’)
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/cc7il5/), as promulgated by the Secretary-General through
Secretary-General’s Bulletin, UN Doc. ST/SGB/2018/1, effective from 1 January 2018
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/zn5lba/).
6
Terms of reference of the Investigative Team to support domestic efforts to hold Islamic
State in Iraq and the Levant (Da’esh) accountable for acts that may amount to war crimes,
crimes against humanity and genocide committed in Iraq, established pursuant to Security
Council resolution 2379 (2017), attached as Annex to Letter dated 9 February 2018 from the
Secretary-General addressed to the President of the Security Council, UN Doc. S/2018/118,
14 February 2018 (‘Terms of reference’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/niw4cw/).
7
See Alexander Heinze and Shannon Fyfe, “Prosecutorial Ethics and Preliminary Examina-
tions at the ICC”, in Morten Bergsmo and Carsten Stahn (eds.), Quality Control in Prelimi-
nary Examination: Volume 2, Torkel Opsahl Academic EPublisher, Brussels, 2018 (https://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/dff594/).
8
See Report of the Office of the United Nations High Commission for Human Rights on the
human rights situation in Iraq in the light of abuses committed by the so-called Islamic State
in Iraq and the Levant and associated groups, UN Doc. A/HRC/28/18, 13 March 2015
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/8a4f0d/), and “They came to destroy”: ISIL Crimes Against
the Yazidis, Report of the Independent International Commission of Inquiry on the Syrian
Arab Republic, UN Doc. A/HRC/32/CRP.2, 15 June 2016 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/
24962f/).
of their movement, thereby reducing the ability of its form of violent ex-
tremism to spread further.
In the initial conceptual discussions amongst States on the establish-
ment of a potential international mechanism addressing ISIL crimes, em-
phasis was placed on the need for any international action to be based on
the principle of respect for national jurisdiction, as well as effective co-
operation and co-ordination with relevant national authorities. At the same
time, many States and other actors emphasized the need for the future
mechanism to be able to act independently and impartially so as to ensure
the integrity of its work as well as strengthen the admissibility of eviden-
tiary material collected before national courts, both in Iraq and other States.
From the outset, the Team’s work has been bound to these dual imperatives
of respect for national sovereignty and the principle of independence,
which were viewed as central to its ability to conduct its work effectively
and in a manner ensuring that evidence collected could serve as an effec-
tive basis for domestic prosecutions.
It is in this context that the Government of Iraq, on 9 August 2017,
formally requested the assistance of the international community in making
sure that members of ISIL are held accountable for their crimes in Iraq, in-
cluding where those may amount to crimes against humanity, war crimes,
or genocide. Following extensive negotiations led by the United Kingdom
as penholder, the Security Council responded with one voice, unanimously
adopting resolution 2379 (2017). 9 It requested the Secretary-General to es-
tablish an Investigative Team, headed by a Special Adviser, “to support
domestic efforts to hold ISIL accountable by collecting, preserving, and
storing evidence in Iraq of acts that may amount to war crimes, crimes
against humanity, and genocide committed by the terrorist group ISIL in
Iraq”. 10 In addition to this core investigative mandate, paragraph 3 of this
resolution provides that the Special Adviser, while avoiding duplication of
effort with other relevant UN bodies, will also promote throughout the
world, accountability for acts that may amount to war crimes, crimes
against humanity, or genocide committed by ISIL, and work with survivors,
in a manner consistent with relevant national laws, to ensure their interests
in achieving accountability for ISIL are fully recognized.
9
S/RES/2379, see above note 3. The mandate was unanimously extended through UN Securi-
ty Council resolution 2490 (2019), Threats to international peace and security, UN Doc.
S/RES/2490, on 20 September 2019 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/l2hnjy/).
10
S/RES/2379, para. 3, see above note 3.
13
Ibid., para. 6.
14
Ibid.
15
Ibid., para. 2.
16
UN Guidelines on the Role of Prosecutors, Adopted by the Eighth United Nations Congress
on the Prevention of Crime and the Treatment of Offenders, Havana, Cuba, 27 August to 7
September 1990 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/15b063/).
17
Sara Ferro Ribeiro and Danae van der Straten Ponthiz, International Protocol on the Docu-
mentation and Investigation of Sexual Violence in Conflict, on behalf of the Foreign and
Commonwealth Office, second edition, London, 2017.
18
First report of the Special Adviser and Head of the United Nations Investigative Team to
Promote Accountability for Crimes Committed by Da’esh/Islamic State in Iraq and the Le-
vant, UN Doc. S/2018/1031, 15 November 2018, paras. 19–27 (https://www.legal-tools.org/
doc/7bq4w0/).
19
Second report of the Special Adviser and Head of the United Nations Investigative Team to
Promote Accountability for Crimes Committed by Da’esh/Islamic State in Iraq and the Le-
vant, UN Doc. S/2019/407, 17 May 2019, para. 13 (‘Second report of the Special Adviser’)
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/siofyo/). These three initial investigative priorities are: (a)
Attacks committed by ISIL against the Yazidi community in the Sinjar district in August
2014; (b) Crimes committed by ISIL in Mosul between 2014 and 2016, including the execu-
tion of religious minorities, crimes involving sexual and gender-based violence, and crimes
against children; (c) The mass killing of unarmed Iraqi air force cadets from Tikrit Air Acad-
emy in June 2014.
20
Third report of the Special Adviser and Head of the United Nations Investigative Team to
Promote Accountability for Crimes Committed by Da’esh/Islamic State in Iraq and the Le-
vant, UN Doc. S/2019/878, 13 November 2019, para. 10 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/
b5y1rx/).
21
Ibid., para. 6.
22
See https://www.unitad.un.org/
23
See “UNITAD IRAQ”, Facebook (available on its web site).
24
See “UNITAD”, Twitter (available on its web site).
25
See Terms of reference, para. 11, see above note 6.
26
Ibid., para. 18.
27
Ibid.
28
Ibid., para. 6.
29
Ibid., paras. 7, 19.
30
Ibid., para. 21.
31
Ibid., para. 22.
32
Ibid., para. 20.
33
UN Charter, see above note 4.
34
Ibid.
35
Ibid.
36
Ibid.
37
A/RES/72/254, see above note 5.
38
See UN General Assembly, Resolution adopted by the General Assembly on 24 December
2012, UN Doc. A/RES/67/246, 24 December 2012 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/l0arge/)
and Secretary General’s bulletin 2013/4, Financial Rules and Regulations of the United Na-
tions, UN Doc. ST/SGB/2013/4, 1 July 2013 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/zos34u/).
39
See also the Secretary-General’s Bulletin, Status, basic rights and duties of United Nations
Staff Members, UN Doc. ST/SGB/2016/9, 21 July 2016 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/
mjxin2/). This contains a commentary by the Secretary-General to assist staff members in
better understanding the obligations applicable to staff conduct.
40
Secretary General’s Bulletin, Protection against retaliation for reporting misconduct and for
co-operating with duly authorized audits or investigations, UN Doc. ST/SGB/2017/2, 20
January 2017 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/bhpac4/).
41
“United Nations Leadership Dialogue”, UN Ethics Office web site (available on UN’s web
site).
42
Similar considerations will apply for recently-established entities such as the International,
Impartial and Independent Mechanism (‘IIIM’) to assist in the Investigation and Prosecution
of Persons for the Most Serious Crimes Under International Law committed in the Syrian
Arab Republic since March 2011 and the Independent Investigative Mechanism for Myan-
mar (‘IIMM’).
43
Robert F. Kennedy, University of San Francisco School of Law, 29 September 1962.
yond reasonable doubt, and when the duties and responsibilities of various
actors are so frequently challenged. 44
In constructing its own specialized integrity framework, the Investi-
gative Team has sought to accommodate the legitimate demands of States,
non-governmental organizations, but most importantly those of survivors
and impacted communities, by placing emphasis on operationalizing its
mandate while also dedicating resources to ensuring an adequate integrity
framework is developed to guide initial activities. UNITAD, as all recently-
established international criminal justice entities, has been required to
demonstrate its ability to deliver on its mandate and satisfy the needs of
stakeholders from the outset of its work. The commencement of investiga-
tive activities and the establishment of core integrity policy frameworks are,
therefore, processes that must be carried out in parallel.
It should be recognized that this simultaneous demand for the estab-
lishment of specialized deontological structures and the delivery of core
functions is not a challenge particular to UNITAD or even specific to the
current political climate. 45 These simultaneous challenges have been faced
by other international mechanisms including the ICTY, the ICTR, and in-
deed the ICC where the Office of the Prosecutor was required to develop
the regulations and code of conduct governing its work while at the same
time taking forward its first investigations and prosecutions. The degree to
which this was achieved is a matter that may be debated. There have cer-
tainly been challenges. This is starkly reflected by the fact that whilst the
Rome Statute came into force in 2002, no such regulations or code were in
place by the time the Prosecutor submitted the Lubanga Case to the Trial
Chamber in June 2008. With respect to the code of conduct, this remained
the case for a further five years until the Defence sought an order in
Muthaura that the ICC Code of Conduct apply to the Prosecution given the
absence of a dedicated code being promulgated by the Prosecutor in the
preceding 11 years. 46
44
For example, evidence may be excluded if obtained in a manner contrary to that provided
for international human rights law, and cases may be unnecessarily ‘politicised’ because of
the use of intermediaries or witnesses from only one side of the political divide.
45
Although it is perhaps worth recalling that unlike IIIM and IIMM, UNITAD was not preced-
ed with a commission of Experts or Inquiry, the materials of which would be turned over to
the mechanism when established.
46
See ICC, The Prosecutor v. Francis Kirimi Muthaura and Uhuru Muigai Kenyatta, Trial
Chamber, Joint Defence Application for an Order to the Prosecutor for the provision of a list
containing the bar memberships and good standing status of Prosecution trial lawyers ex-
pected to make submissions at trial and Request that the Trial Chamber promulgate a proto-
col of professional ethics applicable to Prosecution lawyers, 17 January 2013, ICC-01/09-
02/11 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/c9e14f/); and Decision on the Defence application
concerning professional ethics applicable to prosecution lawyers, which confirmed the code
would apply to the OTP in the interim prior to the promulgation of a code by the OTP, 31
May 2013, ICC-01/09-02/11 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/d27ea0/).
Special Adviser of high moral character and integrity and possessing the
highest level of professional competence.
Since the first author’s appointment in August 2018, he has sought to
ensure that these principles and qualities are reflected in his leadership but,
most importantly, also transmitted down through all teams and units. In
developing our staffing structure, which now totals around 150 staff mem-
bers based in Iraq, our objective has been to create a symbiotic relationship
of mutual learning between national and international elements, thereby
establishing a common identity and commitment to delivery of accounta-
bility with respect to ISIL crimes. By forging a common sense of purpose
across all components of the Team, we provide a stable basis upon which
the principles of integrity, impartiality and independence can be integrated
into all aspects of our work.
20.3.1.1. Empowering National Expertise Ensuring Gender Balance
Within the Team
This commitment to the development of a cohesive and balanced approach
to our work is reflected in the staffing structure adopted at the outset of the
development of the Team in 2018, with national experts integrated into all
key substantive sections, including the Field Investigation Units and Anal-
ysis and Evidence Unit, as well as specialist entities, such as the Sexual and
Gender-Based Violence and Children’s Unit, Forensic Sciences Unit and
Witness Protection and Support Unit. This priority given to ensuring an
effective national component across all key parts of the Team has further
been reflected in our development of specialized, supplementary projects
funded through extrabudgetary funds provided by Member States. Specifi-
cally, through these supplementary operational projects, additional special-
ized units are being established in areas including digitization of eviden-
tiary material, financial crimes and protection of cultural heritage, all of
which incorporate at least one-third of national expert staffing.
In addition to ensuring the national component of the Team is suffi-
ciently prioritized and resourced, attention has been paid to providing a
specialized function within the Team allowing national experts to effective-
ly guide and support the engagement of the Team with national authorities.
To this end, a dedicated National Engagement and Support Unit has been
established, headed by the most senior Iraqi national expert within the
Team. The creation of a dedicated entity to ensure appropriate and in-
formed strategic advice is provided to the Special Adviser, and to facilitate
47
Second report of the Special Adviser, para. 16, see above note 19
48
UN Charter, see above note 4.
49
Secretary-General’s Bulletin, Information sensitivity, classification and handling, UN Doc.
ST/SGB/2007/6, 12 February 2007 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/3bfra2/).
be borne in mind that these impacted communities have very often sur-
vived devastating events. Indeed, they may still be reliving these experi-
ences due to psychological or physical injuries, or the reality of the predic-
ament in refugee camps or as displaced communities. Very often, some ac-
tors, either NGOs, national authorities or agencies, may present justice to
them as transformational. Whilst it can be in some ways, it is trite that it
does not bring the dead back to life or restore a family that has endured
horrors that should never have been imagined, never mind carried out. In
these circumstances, a candid discussion about the limitations of ‘justice’,
and the difficulties in achieving it, can be kinder and more credible. In fact,
when this is combined with an explanation of the importance of preserving
a record, collecting evidence, and endeavouring to hold criminals to ac-
count in fair trials, impacted communities can be galvanized in a way that
is indispensable to an investigation. Even if momentarily disappointed, or
sobered by certain realities, they will see the investigative team as honest
and sincere. This form of personal and collective integrity may have a sig-
nificant impact on how a team is perceived and received by an affected
community given the importance of managing expectations.
20.3.2.2. Institutional Responses to the Implementation of Witness
Protection Policies Aligned with Principles of Integrity
In developing an integrity-based framework concerning the engagement
with survivors and witnesses, it may be assumed that the core policies and
practices of the relevant mechanism or entity would represent the starting-
point. However, in no other area of our work are the human resources, the
institutional expertise of an entity more important. Priority must, therefore,
above all, be given to securing and effectively structuring the institutional
architecture of the Team focused on ensuring the effective delivery of an
approach prioritizing the dignity of survivors and witnesses and the provi-
sion of support and protection to reduce to an absolute minimum the risk of
re-traumatization.
In developing this institutional framework, UNITAD has prioritized
the establishment of two key pillars: (i) a dedicated Witness Protection and
Support Unit (‘WPSU’), with responsibility for ensuring that the Team en-
gages with all survivors and victims in a manner aligned with international
standards; and (ii) a specialized Gender Crimes and Crimes against Chil-
dren Unit (‘GCCU’) charged with ensuring that the work of the Investiga-
tive Team with respect to such crimes is conducted in a manner that deliv-
nal entities such as with the Human Rights in Trauma Mental Health Pro-
gram at Stanford University who have provided support with respect to the
development of standard operating procedures and practices for engage-
ment with vulnerable witnesses and a forthcoming field guide on trauma-
informed approaches to investigative activities. Such collaboration reflects
a broader commitment by the Team to leverage the work and expertise of
entities both within the UN system and externally, so as to develop the
strongest possible standards of investigative practices.
Drawing on the expertise of their specialized staffing structure, as
well as its external partnerships, the leadership of the WPSU and the
GCCU have, in turn, led the development of the tailored integrity frame-
work of the Team as relevant to the interaction of its members with wit-
nesses, victims and survivors. The rapid development and operationaliza-
tion of this framework have been crucial in engendering the trust of im-
pacted communities in Iraq which has also allowed those most vulnerable
individuals to come forward with their accounts and enhance their effective
participation in the accountability process.
20.3.2.3. Specialized Integrity Policies and Practices with Respect to
Survivors and Witnesses
Drawing on the specialized institutional and staffing architecture of the
Team regarding witness and survivor engagement, the Team has put in
place a tailored policy framework that seeks to ensure all investigative
work is adapted to address the specific needs of ISIL victims and witnesses.
The central policy in this regard is the Witness Protection Strategy, devel-
oped by the WPSU and the GCCU at the outset of the Team’s work, which
builds upon previous models adopted at the ICTY, the ICTR, Special Court
for Sierra Leone, the ICC and the Special Tribunal for Lebanon, in particu-
lar concerning the conduct of threat assessments and the consequent im-
plementation of specialized protection procedures with respect to individu-
al witnesses.
The guiding operating principle of the Team under this strategic ap-
proach is to limit the potential exposure of witnesses to identified threats,
by ensuring that interviews are conducted according to a systematic and
deliberate planning process and on the basis of an identified investigative
need. However, the strategy does not aim to ensure only physical safety
and confidentiality but takes into account the needs of witnesses in a holis-
tic manner including psychological wellbeing, dignity, privacy, respect,
50
Samuel Johnson, “Rasselas”, 1759, Ch. 41.
Member States to hold those responsible for the crimes of ISIL to account,
in line with the rule of law and due process.
As the Investigative Team has moved into the fully operational phase
of its work, and as it begins to provide direct support for domestic account-
ability processes, its ability to address new challenges will depend on its
capacity to continue to simultaneously leverage its unique position as an
impartial and independent entity, and maintain the continued support of the
people of Iraq. Our experience shows that adherence to the principles of
integrity and impartiality will be central to our ability to effectively support
the Government of Iraq in addition to effectively delivering on the promis-
es made to victims and survivors that those responsible for inflicting crimes
on their communities will be held accountable for their crimes.
The lessons learned from the initial stages of the work of UNITAD
can be extrapolated and applied to the activities and approach of interna-
tional criminal justice mechanisms more broadly. If we are to ensure the
continued trust of Member States, impacted communities and the broader
public in international criminal justice institutions as effective mechanisms
for the delivery of criminal accountability, we must renew our commitment
to placing the principle of integrity at the centre of our work and ensure a
comprehensive approach is adopted with respect to its implementation. As
confidence in the administration of justice wanes, and as the utility of the
international rules-based system comes under pressure, a concerted focus
on upholding the highest possible standards of integrity, efficiency and im-
partiality has never been more needed.
At a time when common standards and the idea of justice itself can
often seem in peril, in an environment where it is sometimes fallaciously
alleged that there is no truth – only competing facts – justice must be
guarded like never before. Integrity must remain the sentry on guard.
21.1. Introduction
In this chapter, I will offer several observations on the relationship between
the legal and policy frameworks of international institutions and integrity.
Before that, however, I would like to compliment the International Nurem-
berg Principles Academy and the Centre for International Law Research
and Policy (‘CILRAP’) for organizing the international conference ‘Integri-
ty in International Justice’ in the Peace Palace in The Hague in December
2018, and for initiating the Integrity Project which has resulted in this
comprehensive anthology. It actually takes courage to address such issues,
which are usually taken for ‘granted without saying’. It requires looking at
integrity in international justice without fear or bias, comparing the way
things are with the way they should be. This is indeed the actual support
international justice needs: the frankness of true friends, instead of the flat-
tery of courtesans. It requires going beyond the complacent fascination and
deference for international justice institutions and their officials, remem-
bering that these institutions are ultimately made up of women and men,
with their own limits, needs and dilemmas, whatever the qualities of such
individuals. It also requires looking deeper into the governance and policy
framework of these organisations to find what, if anything, is going wrong,
instead of entering superfluous judgments as to the alleged poor quality of
their personnel and officials as the sole explanation for their failure to fulfil
their mandate. The best civil servants and officials can do barely better than
the worst ones if a proper policy framework governing their action is miss-
*
Dr. Cyril Laucci was Legal Advisor in the Registry of the International Criminal Court
from 2009 to 2015. He is currently Lead Counsel for Mr. Ali Muhammad Ali Abd-Al-
Rahman before the ICC, Director at The Legal Carpentry, and Project Manager on Strength-
ening Internal Justice Systems at European Molecular Biology Laboratory.
ing. The main difference is that the first priority for good civil servants and
officials in such a case is addressing policy gaps, and promulgating a prop-
er legal framework for their sound action.
Rules alone cannot guarantee integrity. Norms are useful in setting a
standard framework of reference on which individuals can rely to assess
the integrity of a given behaviour. In most cases, rules and policies – when
they exist – provide ready-made answers and guidance for international
civil servants to learn about the integrity that is expected from them. By
itself, compliance with policies will not always be sufficient to lead one
towards integrity and ethical behaviour. Nevertheless, clear guidelines will,
at least, provide a framework within which individual dilemmas can find
ready-made solutions for ethical action. In case of policy gaps, individual
civil servants are left with no such guidance. Hence, the identification of
ethical behaviour essentially relies on individual value judgments. In such a
scenario, those who care about integrity, and are sufficiently enlightened to
identify the right behaviour succeed, while those who lack integrity, or the
capacity to uphold it consistently, fail.
Furthermore, for those who fail, disciplinary action is made more dif-
ficult – if at all possible – in the absence of clearly defined disciplinary
breaches. Nullum crimen sine lege does apply to disciplinary action. 1 Poli-
cy gaps and failures to prevent unethical behaviour are thus impediments to
disciplinary liability and a cause of impunity. In turn, the consequential
perception of impunity plays as a strong deterrent to integrity. Where integ-
rity breaches are protected from disciplinary action, they may facilitate the
career development and promotion of offenders; at the same time, those
who restrain their actions and try to advise adherence to ethical behaviour
in all circumstances are perceived as trouble-makers. Unethical behaviour
generates its own dynamics of solidarity between offenders, and retaliation
against those who refuse to depart from integrity. Naming and shaming
those who err is made difficult by the absence of rule that define and re-
press the phenomenon. It also exposes non-like-minded staff members and
whistle-blowers who care for integrity to retaliation, as easy scapegoats
immolated on the ground of the alleged lack of efficiency resulting from
their willingness to play by rules which, to all effects, do not exist.
1
International Labour Organization Administrative Tribunal (‘ILOAT’), In re Berte and
Beslier, Judgment, 20 December 1983, No. 566, p. 5 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/
395956/).
zation, perhaps even more so when such organization is the central body in
international criminal justice: the International Criminal Court (‘ICC’) (see
Section 21.2. below). I am expressing this concern as a true friend of the
ICC, with the genuine wish that the management of the Court may eventu-
ally heed my advice and take the necessary measures to correct the course.
I am sharing this advice with the intent of making sure that, should the
management persist in refusing to react, the concerned individuals risk fac-
ing the criticism arising from not addressing the policy gaps that undermine
the daily action of this important institution, preventing the satisfactory ful-
filment of its mandate of prosecuting the most serious crimes of interna-
tional concern. Two years after making this advice public at the Peace Pal-
ace Conference of December 2018, I can see, with sadness, that it has re-
mained unsuccessful so far: the final report of the Independent Expert Re-
view (‘IER’) delivered on 30 September 2020 still flags “potentially out-
dated administrative issuances or those that are contradictory to principles
set out in decisions of the International Labour Organisation – Administra-
tive Tribunal (ILOAT) against the Court”, and suggests, in its Recommen-
dation R12, that “a systemic process should further be put in place to ena-
ble the Court’s internal legal framework’s compliance with ILOAT deci-
sions, as soon as practicable after such a decision involving the Court is
delivered, to identify and implement any necessary amendments”. 2 This
chapter is written with the genuine hope of saving the ICC from a future
where it may decline by itself, by failing to uphold the highest standards of
integrity, without need for a decisive action of its usual, numerous and
powerful foes.
21.2. Overview of the Structure of the Internal Legal and Policy
Framework of the International Criminal Court
The legal framework of relevance for the topic at hand is not composed by
the usual sources of ICC law: although some articles of the Rome Statute
referred to below are relevant, the other provisions governing the mandate
and judicial proceedings of the Court in the Statute, the Rules of Procedure
and Evidence, and other regulations have no direct relevance.
The combined provisions of Articles 38(3)(a), 42(2) and 43(2) of the
Rome Statute entrust the Registrar, as “principal administrative officer of
2
Independent Expert Review of the International Criminal Court and the Rome Statute Sys-
tem: Final Report, 30 September 2020, para. 59 and Recommendation R12, pp. 22–23 (‘IER
Report’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/cv19d5).
the Court” exercising his or her functions under the authority of the Presi-
dent of the Court and the Presidency, in charge of its “proper administra-
tion, with the exception of the Office of the Prosecutor”, with the main re-
sponsibility of establishing the machinery governing the daily administra-
tion of the Court.
On the basis of these combined provisions, the ICC Presidency is-
sued, on 9 December 2003, the first ever Presidential Directive of the Court
setting up the “Procedures for the Promulgation of Administrative Issuanc-
es”. 3 Section 1.1 of this Presidential Directive defines the various types of
administrative issuances that can be issued by the Court: (a) Presidential
Directives; (b) Administrative Instructions; and (c) Information Circulars.
The list is limitative. Sections 2−4 define the scope of each type of issu-
ances, their hierarchy, and the authority entrusted with their promulgation.
Sections 5 and 6 set up the procedure for the consultation, promulgation,
publication and review of administrative issuances. Section 7 provides
general guidelines for their interpretation. The Presidential Directive of 9
December 2003 thus plays a preeminent, quasi-constitutional role of organ-
ic law (in French, loi organique), immediately under the Rome Statute,
next to the Staff Regulations adopted under Article 44(3) of the Statute, and
at the very top of the administrative and policy framework of the Court. All
subsequent administrative issuances, more than one hundred, 4 were prom-
ulgated in accordance with this Presidential Directive.
21.2.1. Instances of Non-Observance of the Terms of the Presidential
Directive of 2003
A quick review of the corpus of ICC administrative issuances reveals that,
though promulgated pursuant to Presidential Directive of 9 December 2003,
they were not necessarily compliant with its provisions. Since the delivery
of the author’s speech at the Peace Palace Conference of December 2018,
the Court has fortunately taken action and redressed some of these issues,
as mentioned in the relevant footnotes below.
3
International Criminal Court (‘ICC’), Procedures for the Promulgation of Administrative
Issuances, 9 December 2003, ICC/PRESD/G/2003/001 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/
6a92e0/).
4
ICC, “Administrative Issuances” (available on its web site). The full list – unfortunately not
up to date – of ICC administrative issuances.
5
ICC, Recruitment guidelines for Established Posts, Professional and higher General Service
categories, 2 November 2009 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/50ed6b/) (not fixed).
6
ICC, Guidelines on Special Post Allowances (SPA), 1 August 2007, ICC/HRS/2007/7385
(http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/018904/) (not fixed).
7
ICC, Official Working Hours of the Court and Official Holidays, 1 June 2007,
ICC/HRS/2007/7229 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/471713/) (partially fixed by
ICC/AI/2019/004, 28 October 2019 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/asnyvr/)).
8
ICC, Rules of Procedure of the Appeals Board, 21 March 2006, ICC/INF/2006/003 (http://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/fb03b5/) (fixed by ICC/AI/2019/005, 28 October 2019 (https://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/2ekgxu/)).
9
ICC, Staff Training and Development – Guidelines, 27 March 2006, ICC/INF/2006/009
(‘Staff Training and Development – Guidelines’) (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/317ad3/)
(not fixed).
10
ICC, Rules of Procedure of the Disciplinary Advisory Board, 7 May 2007,
ICC/INF/2007/003 (‘Rules of Procedure of the Disciplinary Advisory Board’) (http://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/c7e8f0/) (fixed by ICC/AI/2019/006, 28 October 2019 (https://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/43ztuk/)).
11
ICC, An executive statement by the Registrar on the ICC Security and Safety Section (SSS),
Joint Threat and Assessment Group (JTAG), Joint Crisis Management Team (JCMT) and In-
formation Security Management Forum (ISMF), 22 January 2008, ICC/INF/2008/003 (‘Ex-
ecutive Statement’) (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/278a95/) (not fixed).
12
ICC, Mandatory Security Arrangements, 23 August 2011, ICC/lNF/2011/006 (‘Mandatory
Security Arrangements’) (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/676299/) (not fixed).
13
ICC, United Nations Laissez-Passer, 19 March 2015, ICC/INF/2015/008 (‘United Nations
Laissez-Passer’) (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/9a62af/) (not fixed).
14
ICC, Guidelines on Language Proficiency and Language Incentives, 30 December 2016,
ICC/INF/2016/011 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/ee42ad/) (fixed by ICC/AI/2019/007, 28
October 2019 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/sxt7ql/)).
15
ICC, ICC Informational Protection Policy, 19 June 2007, ICC/AI/2007/001 (http://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/04b126/) (not fixed).
16
ICC, ICC Anti-Fraud Policy, 13 May 2014, ICC/PRESD/G/2014/002 (‘ICC Anti-Fraud Pol-
icy’) (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/a5168a/) (not fixed).
17
ICC, ICC Whistleblowing and Whistleblower Protection Policy, 8 October 2014,
ICC/PRESD/G/2014/003 (‘ICC Whistleblowing and Whistleblower Protection Policy’)
(http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/0c36ff/) (not fixed).
18
ICC, Staff Regulations, 30 September 2016, ICC/PRESD/G/2016/002 (‘ICC Staff Regula-
tions’) (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/bc0ddb/).
19
ICC, Disciplinary Procedure, 5 February 2008, ICC/AI/2008/001 (‘Disciplinary Procedure’)
(http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/094a22/).
20
ILOAT, F v. ICC, Judgment, 24 January 2018, No. 3907 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/
c1fdba/).
21
Ibid., p. 26; ILOAT, A v. ICC¸ Judgment, 24 January 2018, No. 3903, p. 20 (http://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/b3ed30/); ILOAT, G v. ICC, Judgment, 24 January 2018, No. 3904,
p. 20 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/06301a/); ILOAT, L. (No. 3) v. ICC, Judgment, 24 Jan-
uary 2018, No. 3908, p. 9 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/619e5a/); ILOAT, B. v. ICC¸
Judgment, 26 June 2018, No. 4004, p. 6 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/dca542/); ILOAT,
T.P. and M. v. ICC, Judgment, 26 June 2018, No. 4007, p. 5 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/
bcf9cb/).
22
ICC, ICC Recruitment guidelines for Established Posts, Professional and higher General
Service categories, 2 November 2009, ICC/INF/2012/020 (https://legal-tools.org/doc/
50ed6b).
However, this risk is limited by the fact that the right to challenge re-
cruitment decisions, like any other administrative decisions, is limited to
staff members who are already working for the Court under Article II.1 of
the ILOAT Statute and is not open to external applicants. Only internal ap-
plicants can challenge a recruitment process and, except in rare situations,
internal applicants will refrain from challenging such a decision by fear of
retaliation or other adverse consequences for their career within the Court.
The non-implementation of the principles governing the protection of whis-
tle-blowers (see Section 21.3.4. below) thus plays as a powerful deterrent
against the lodging of appeals against appointment decisions. Finally, the
absence of reaction from the management of the Court and of review of the
Recruitment Guidelines after the issuance of Judgment No. 3907 feeds the
perception that, notwithstanding the clear and unambiguous ruling of the
ILOAT, the Recruitment Guidelines may nonetheless be valid, for whatever
reason, in the mind of the majority of staff members, who are not suffi-
ciently acquainted with administrative subtleties. All these mitigating fac-
tors concur in limiting the risk of challenges against recruitment decisions
and containing it, below the advantages of keeping things as they are. As
long as a binding and properly promulgated selection and recruitment pro-
cedure is not in force, the hiring manager has the possibility of disregarding
the existing Recruitment Guidelines every time they do not serve his or her
purposes or those of the Human Resources Section.
Paradoxically, the procedure governing the selection and recruitment
of the most precarious category of staff members, employed under short-
term appointments, was properly promulgated by way of Administrative
Instruction ICC/AI/2016/001 of 28 January 2016. 23 Section 4 of that Ad-
ministrative Instruction governs the advertisement of vacancy announce-
ments and provides relaxed selection and appointment processes, ensuring
full discretion to the hiring manager in the selection of staff on short-term
appointments. This Administrative Instruction shows a contrario that the
ICC management is aware of the proper way of promulgating recruitment
procedures, and that nonetheless, when it does so, it only promulgates
loose provisions, ultimately preserving the capacity of hiring managers to
select and appoint the persons of their choosing.
23
ICC, Short-Term Appointments, 28 January 2016, ICC/AI/2016/001 (http://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/286b48/).
24
IER Report, paras. 218–227 and Recommendations R91 to R96, pp. 70–74, see above note 2.
25
Executive Statement, see above note 11.
26
Mandatory Security Arrangements, see above note 12.
27
United Nations Laissez-Passer, see above note 13.
28
ICC, Guidelines for the use of the United Nations Laissez Passer, 22 August 2005,
ICC/INF/2005/005 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/5ac2df/).
29
ILOAT, A v. ICC, Judgment, 26 June 2018, No. 4003, pp. 2–3 (‘Judgment 4003’) (http://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/81bbe3/).
30
Ibid., para. 4.
31
Ibid., para. 5.
32
Ibid., para. 16.
33
ICC, Comprehensive Report on the Reorganisation of the Registry of the International
Criminal Court, August 2016, para. 325 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/cbc6cc/).
34
Ibid., paras. 428, 447-448, 552.
have contributed to address and fix the policy concerns raised in the two
subsequent post-incidents reports on the Zintan crisis.
As already mentioned, the Information Circular of 19 March 2015 on
UN Laissez-Passer is unlawful and unenforceable as a result of its promul-
gation, in breach of the Presidential Directive of 9 December 2003. In addi-
tion, it provides that UN Laissez-Passer delivered to ICC staff and officials
shall contain an insert affirming that its bearer “is entitled to be accorded
the privileges and immunities provided for in the Agreement on the Privi-
leges and Immunities of the International Criminal Court of 9 September
2002 or in other agreements or arrangements defining the privileges and
immunities of the Court”. The Information Circular of 19 March 2015 fails
to inform potential bearers of the Laissez-Passer on the implications and
limits of these privileges and immunities, in particular the need for an ex-
change of Notes Verbales with the local authorities and the fact that the
ICC privileges and immunities only apply in States Parties to the Agree-
ment on the Privileges and Immunities of the Court. Many current Situa-
tion countries are not Parties to the Agreement, like Côte d’Ivoire, Kenya,
Sudan, Libya and Burundi, and ICC bearers of Laissez-Passer may also
travel to other non-situation countries which also are not Parties to the
Agreement on the Privileges and Immunities of the Court, such as the fol-
lowing countries under preliminary examination: Afghanistan, Bangladesh,
Myanmar, Guinea (which signed the Agreement on 1 April 2004 but did
not ratify it), Iraq, Nigeria, Palestine, Philippines or Venezuela (which
signed on 16 July 2003 but did not ratify). By providing an insert that af-
firms that ICC bearers of Laissez-Passer enjoy privileges and immunities
without the necessary information and caveats, the Information Circular of
19 March 2015 fails to discharge the Court’s duty of care 35 vis-à-vis its
staff and officials who may believe, on the face of the insert in their UN
Laissez-Passer, that they enjoy privileges and immunities when they do not.
The failure to secure the privileges and immunities of the four ICC staff
members played a central role in the materialization of the Zintan crisis of
2012, and resulted in the adverse Judgment No. 4003 issued by the ILOAT;
nevertheless, it has not led the Court to learn from its past mistakes and
address this issue properly. The fact that the Information Circular of 19
March 2015 was issued after the Zintan crisis and the issuance of the two
post-incident reports highlighting this policy gap certainly plays as a factor
35
Judgment 4003, p. 12, see above note 29.
aggravating the liability of the ICC management for its failure to discharge
the duty of care.
The ICC policy on mission preparation, diplomatic clearance, privi-
leges and immunities and mandatory security arrangements remains loose,
largely obsolete and noncompliant with the structure of the internal legal
framework of the Court. At any moment in time, an event similar to the
Zintan crisis of 2012 can re-occur, perhaps leading to a much worse result.
The management of the Court is taking a huge responsibility vis-à-vis the
life and security of its own staff and all other persons sent on ICC field
missions, such as counsel, by persisting in not addressing this problem in
spite of the res judicata rulings of the ILOAT in its Judgments Nos. 3907
and 4003. The IER report does not suggest otherwise in its above-
mentioned Recommendation R12, but it strangely addresses the specific
issue of field activities with respect to the Office of the Prosecutor only and
succinctly, 36 without considering the wider picture of the ICC-wide policy
framework governing field presence and the preparation of field missions.
Like for recruitment, the IER report thus missed the main problem here.
In light of the huge risk that follows the failure to review the ICC
field operations policies, one can legitimately wonder the reasons of the
ICC management for not addressing this serious issue, whereas its attention
was repeatedly drawn thereon. Their inaction feeds a perception that the
field operations policy framework is deliberately left as it is in order to
keep the greater flexibility in the conduct of field operations that a loose
legal environment provides. As long as a more stringent policy framework
is not in place, ICC staff members can be sent on missions without the need
for ensuring in advance that they are covered by privileges and immunities,
or to disclose in advance a detailed mission plan defining the exact purpose
of the mission, the foreseen activities and the locations to be visited. This
gives room to maximum flexibility in the conduct of missions, with last-
minute changes always possible. It echoes the concerns voiced in a recent
CILRAP conference on 22-23 February 2019 by a Senior Legal Officer of
the ICC Chambers about the serious challenges encountered by the Office
of the Prosecutor in planning investigations in advance. 37 It also opens the
36
IER Report, paras. 779–784 and Recommendations R293 to R298, pp. 251–253, see above
note 2.
37
Gilbert Bitti, “Quality control in Case Preparation and the Role of the Judiciary of the Inter-
national Criminal Court”, CILRAP Film, New Delhi, 23 February 2019 (https://
www.cilrap.org/cilrap-film/190223-bitti/).
38
ICC Staff Regulations, see above note 18.
39
ICC, Staff Rules of the International Criminal Court, 27 July 2015, ICC/AI/2015/004/Corr.1
Anx (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/2a5274/).
40
Disciplinary Procedure, see above note 19.
41
Rules of Procedure of the Appeals Board, see above note 9; replaced by ICC/AI/2019/005,
28 October 2019.
42
Rules of Procedure of the Disciplinary Advisory Board, see above note 10; replaced by
ICC/AI/2019/006, 28 October 2019.
43
ICC, Sexual and Other Forms of Harassment, 14 July 2005, ICC/AI/2005/005 (http://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/619941/).
44
ICC, Equal Employment Opportunity and Treatment, 14 July 2005, ICC/AI/2005/006
(http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/9c4023/).
45
ICC Assembly of State Parties (‘ICC ASP’), “Independent Oversight Mechanism”, 27 No-
vember 2013, ICC-ASP/12/Res.6 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/64ebeb/).
IOM provides, inter alia, that it plays a role in the investigation of discipli-
nary cases against staff members and elected officials.
Though apparently complete, the procedural framework applicable to
staff appeals and disciplinary cases actually maintains significant gaps,
which are likely to impact on the integrity of internal proceedings, should
litigants elect to rely on them in support of their claims, thus making the
Court highly vulnerable in case of appeal before the ILOAT.
Chapter XI of the ICC Staff Rules makes the submission of appeal
cases to the internal Appeals Board a mandatory step in the internal phase
of the proceedings on any staff appeal against an administrative decision.
Rule 111.3 provides general principles governing the procedure before the
Appeals Board. However, the Rules of Procedure of the Appeals Board
govern the more detailed aspects of the procedure before the Appeals
Board, such as the composition of Appeals Board panels, the recusal of its
members, the filing, format and content of submissions, the disclosure of
relevant documents, the drafting and content of the Panel’s recommenda-
tion and other aspects. Yet, the Rules of Procedure were initially promul-
gated as an annex to Information Circular ICC/INF/2006/003 of 27 March
2006, whereas Sections 2 and 3 of the Presidential Directive of 9 December
2003 required the promulgation of general procedures by way of Presiden-
tial Directive or Administrative Instruction. This was fixed by the promul-
gation of Administrative Issuance ICC/AI/2019/005 on 28 October 2019.
Until that date, pursuant to the ruling of the ILOAT at paragraph 25 of its
Judgment No. 3907, the Rules of Procedure of the Appeals Board were un-
lawful, as were all decisions taken pursuant to them, that is, all final deci-
sions on staff appeal cases. The invalid promulgation of the Rules of Pro-
cedure of the Appeals Board thus formed a solid basis for the quashing of
any final decision on a staff appeal case before the ILOAT. This made the
ICC highly vulnerable to any challenge made by its staff members against
its administrative decisions, whatever their merits. In the case of the major-
ity of staff members who were not aware of this gap, or who did not feel
confident enough to challenge the validity of the Rules of Procedure of the
Appeals Board, this risk remained limited. On the contrary, those staff
members who had this knowledge, and had enough confidence in their le-
gal skills to measure the consequences of the unlawfulness of the Rules of
the Appeals Board, could be confident that they would succeed in their ap-
peal against any decision they may have elected to challenge.
the full confidence and trust of all staff”, 49 which is, by far, an understate-
ment of the symptom, without identifying the cause.
In disciplinary cases where the IOM fulfils its investigative function
under Sections 27 to 41 of its Operational Mandate, the parties – the person
whose conduct is alleged to be unsatisfactory and, where applicable, the
complainant – can challenge its intervention on the basis of the absence of
a Presidential Directive implementing the Operational Mandate within the
internal policy framework of the Court in accordance with Section 2.1 of
the Presidential Directive of 9 December 2003. The ILOAT Judgment No.
3907 would support such a claim. This can be used to demonstrate a breach
of procedure, and claim the quashing of the disciplinary decision: discipli-
nary measures may be cancelled, with financial compensation for prejudice
or, in case of acquittals, complainants may get financial compensation for
the Court’s failure to protect their rights. Either party may also claim that
the transmission of confidential information about the disciplinary charges
and, where applicable, grievance complaints to the IOM amounts, in the
absence of a proper legal basis for its intervention, to unauthorized disclo-
sure, a compromise of classified information and unsatisfactory conduct
pursuant to Sections 1.7, 16.1(b) and 40.3 of the ICC Information Protec-
tion Policy (see Section 21.3.5. below). This could be the basis for further
disciplinary action against the officials who transmitted the classified in-
formation to the IOM and against the IOM staff members themselves, if
they disclosed it to further recipient(s) in the course of the performance of
their functions.
On the other hand, in disciplinary cases that do not involve the IOM,
the parties can both claim, in case of an adverse decision, that the IOM
should have been involved pursuant to Section 33 of the IOM Operational
Mandate, which provides: “All reports of misconduct or serious miscon-
duct, including possible unlawful acts, made against an elected official,
staff member or contractor shall, if received by the Court, be submitted to
the IOM”. 50 The Court could claim that, in the absence of proper imple-
mentation pursuant to Section 2.1 of the Presidential Directive of 9 De-
cember 2003, the requirement of referral to the IOM under Section 33 of its
Operational Mandate did not apply, but the challenging party could rely on
the fact that the ASP is the legitimate authority of the Court, in charge of
49
IER Report, para. 285, p. 93, see above note 2.
50
See above note 45.
establishing the IOM pursuant to Article 112(4) of the Rome Statute and on
the tu patere legem quam ipse fecisti principle in support of her or his chal-
lenge. Additionally, the ICC failure to comply with its Presidential Di-
rective of 9 December 2003 with respect to the implementation of the Op-
erational Mandate of the IOM cannot be used by the Court against a litigant
pursuant to the nemo auditur suam propriam turpitudinem allegans princi-
ple. 51
The abovementioned policy gaps impacting on staff appeal and dis-
ciplinary cases are highly prejudicial to the overall perception of the
Court’s adherence to the highest integrity standards. It is also a factor of the
major vulnerability of the Court in staff litigation cases. Most disturbingly,
it also feeds a perception of a double standard between those staff members
who are well acquainted with the policy gaps impacting on the integrity of
internal proceedings – or well-advised – and the others. The members of
the first category, which necessarily includes the vast majority of the high
management of the Court, can, if they like, enjoy quasi-total impunity for
any misconduct, as they know that they can rely on the existing irregulari-
ties to quash any adverse decision, and can negotiate amicable settlements
in a position of force. For the second category, which necessarily includes
the vast majority of the lower level, non-managerial staff of the Court, it
feeds a perception of helplessness against the potential abuses they may
endure from the higher management, falling in the first category, in full
impunity. All in all, the impossibility of safeguarding the integrity of staff
appeal and disciplinary cases questions the very existence of the rule of law
in the institution mandated to be the central body of international criminal
justice. This is a situation that no responsible manager of the Court should
normally leave unaddressed, once aware of it.
21.3.4. Anti-Fraud and Whistleblowing Policies
In 2014, the ICC promulgated the general principles of its anti-fraud and
whistleblowing policies by way of Presidential Directive ICC/PRESD/G/
2014/002 of 13 May 2014 52 and Presidential Directive ICC/PRESD/G/
2014/003 of 8 October 2014 53 respectively. Both Directives provide, at
Sections 6.1 and 5.1 respectively, that they shall be translated into relevant
51
ILOAT, Judgment, 4 February 2004, No. 2318, p. 6 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/35b9a6/).
52
ICC Anti-Fraud Policy, see above note 16.
53
ICC Whistleblowing and Whistleblower Protection Policy, see above note 17.
54
Legal Analysis of ICC Internal Accountability Mechanisms and Policies, see above note 47.
55
ICC, Disclosure Requirements – Financial Disclosure Programme of the Court (‘ICC-
FDP’) and IPSAS related party disclosures, 6 October 2015, ICC/AI/2015/005 (http://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/bbdb4c/).
56
IER Report, para. 287, p. 94, see above note 2.
ings before the ICC (see Section 21.3.3. above), this lack of compliance
provides more substance to the perception of impunity for misconduct, it
plays as a further deterrent to the fulfilment of staff members’ reporting
obligations, and further questions the existence of the rule of law within the
Court.
21.3.5. Protection of Information
The framework principles governing the protection of information within
the ICC are provided in a three-page Presidential Directive of 8 March
2005 entitled “Information Security Policy”. 57 This Presidential Directive
basically requires that all ‘users’ of information produced, transmitted and
stored for and by the Court “must comply with the security provisions and
restrictions placed on them by the Court” and further underlines that the
policy is binding both on the Court and “all those who seek access to its
information”. The ICC Information Protection Policy promulgated by Ad-
ministrative Instruction ICC/AI/2007/001 of 19 June 2007 58 governs most
aspects of the classification of ICC records, in any medium or form, judi-
cial and non-judicial alike. It defines the protection levels applicable to in-
formation within the ICC, the criteria applicable to the classification of in-
formation. It also provides rules governing its classification and handling,
dissemination on a ‘need-to-know’ basis and disclosure of classified infor-
mation, and the actions to be taken in cases of suspected compromise of
information security, including potential disciplinary action.
On 4 December 2013, the ICC amended Regulation 14 of the Regu-
lations of the Registry (‘RoR’) and redefined the levels of confidentiality
applicable to its judicial records. The four levels of classification under
Regulation 14 of the RoR are now: (a) ‘Public’, which is similar to ‘UN-
CLASSIFIED’ under Section 5.4 of the ICC Information Protection Policy;
(b) ‘Confidential’, which is similar to ‘[ICC] CONFIDENTIAL’ under Sec-
tion 5.10 of the ICC Information Protection Policy; (c) ‘Under Seal’, which
is similar to ‘[ICC] SECRET’ under Section 5.13 of the ICC Information
Protection Policy; and (d) ‘Secret’, which has no equivalent under the ICC
Information Protection Policy. The classification ‘[ICC] RESTRICTED’
provided under Sections 3.3(b) and 5.5-5.7 of the ICC Information Protec-
57
ICC, Information Security Policy, 8 March 2005, ICC/PRESD/G/2005/001 (http://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/3ae5ed/).
58
ICC, ICC Information Protection Policy, 19 June 2007, ICC/AI/2007/001 (https://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/04b126/).
tion Policy also has no equivalent under Regulation 14 of the RoR; in con-
trast, it is defined as the default classification for unmarked documents un-
der Section 5.14 of the ICC Information Protection Policy.
As a result of the amendment of Regulation 14 of the RoR, the ICC
Information Protection Policy of 2007 has become largely obsolete. The
numerous inconsistencies between this policy and the other instruments of
the Court is a factor of high insecurity for the daily operations of the Court,
in particular its judicial activities. Some of these risks were flagged in Feb-
ruary 2018 by the International Criminal Court Bar Association. 59 As a
consequence of the largely perceived obsolescence of the ICC Information
Protection Policy, there is now a wide consensus within the Court as to its
inapplicability, which has led to a Court-wide tacit agreement to disregard
it, instead of amending it. As a matter of general practice, the Office of the
Prosecutor does not mark judicial documents – in particular witness state-
ments – which are not (yet) filed in the records of a case or situation pro-
ceedings as to their level of classification, or marks them as [ICC] RE-
STRICTED only. Accordingly, these witness statements shall be deemed
[ICC] RESTRICTED only under the ICC Information Protection Policy
and are not confidential – and thus public – under Regulation 14 of the
RoR. This situation creates a high risk of incidental or malevolent dissemi-
nation of highly sensitive information compromising the protection of vic-
tims, witnesses and other persons at risk on account of such information.
Bona fide recipients of such sensitive information may not know that this
information is classified, because it is not marked so, and may disseminate
it further, thus increasing the risk. The sensitivity of this information should
normally require, by nature, its classification as Confidential. This issue
was raised before the Court in the Gbagbo and Blé Goudé case. 60 Trial
Chamber I confirmed that witness statements – though not marked – were
59
Legal Analysis of ICC Internal Accountability Mechanisms and Policies, see above note 47.
60
In French only: ICC, Le Procureur c. Laurent Gbagbo et Charles Blé Goudé, Version Pu-
blique Expurgée du Rapport du Conseiller Juridique désigné en vertu de la règle 74 du Rè-
glement de procédure et de preuve pour assister le témoin P-0046, 21 Février 2017, ICC-
02/11-01/15-810-Red, paras. 18–19 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/e61f0c/); ICC, Le
Procureur c. Laurent Gbagbo et Charles Blé Goudé, Observations Additionnelles relatives à
l’immunité du témoin P-0046 et à la confidentialité de sa déposition auprès des enquêteurs
du Bureau du Procureur, 20 Février 2017, ICC-02/11-01/15-815, paras. 7–14 (https://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/621750/).
61
ICC, Le Procureur c. Laurent Gbagbo et Charles Blé Goudé, Transcript of 15 February
2017, ICC-02/11-01/15, p. 3, lines 6-11 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/9f8359/).
62
ICC, Le Procureur c. Laurent Gbagbo et Charles Blé Goudé, ICC-02/11-01/15, Transcript
of 22 February 2017, p. 48 lines 23-25 to p. 49 lines 1-5 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/
4dc909/).
those involved with the trial”. 63 As is the case for field operations, the dis-
crepancy of the current practices of the Office of the Prosecutor with the
existing information protection policies provides the only rational explana-
tion – still, not a justification – for the Court’s failure to address the widely
known and acknowledged issues impacting the security of classified infor-
mation within the Court.
Once again, one can only hope that the IER Recommendation R12
mentioned above with respect to the undertaking of a full review of the
ICC policy framework will have, despite its lack of specificity, the power
to lead the Court to amend and update its Information Protection Policy,
inasmuch as there is internal willingness to do so. An offer made, on 30
January 2020, by the author of the present chapter to provide a ready-made
amended version of the ICC Information Protection Policy addressing its
current flaws was declined the same day, on the sole ground that it came
from the author (thus seemingly giving higher priority to the responding
staff member’s personal bias against the author, than the superior interest of
the Court to protect its information, displaying what integrity normally ad-
vises against). Recommendation R12 has thus been ready for implementa-
tion with respect to the ICC Information Protection Policy even before it
was made, but it is still fiercely resisted.
21.4. Conclusion
This chapter highlighted five examples of gaps in the ICC legal and policy
framework. These gaps are serious, and lead to the conclusion that the min-
imum basic requirements are not met in terms of policy and legal frame-
work, and that the ICC is failing, so far, to provide its staff and officials
with the minimal guidance they should receive in order to uphold the high-
est integrity standards.
In the absence of such guidance, the onus of upholding the highest
standard of integrity bears on ICC staff members and officials only. We
shall trust in their capacity to do so. The requirements of Articles 36(3)(a),
42(3), 43(3) and 44(2) of the Rome Statute that the ICC Judges, Prosecutor
and Registrar shall be persons of high moral character and that the staff
members be selected according to the highest standards of efficiency, com-
63
ICC, The Prosecutor v. Thomas Lubanga Dyilo, Decision on various issues related to wit-
nesses’ testimony during trial, 29 January 2008, ICC-01/04-01/06-1140, para. 36 (https://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/8367f1/).
petency and integrity are there to give trust in their capacity to lead their
way towards integrity without the need for such guidance.
The worst, however, is always possible. Like in Victor Hugo’s Ruy
Blas, even allegedly honest ministers and virtuous advisors do sometimes
loot their organization. 64 At paragraphs 15 and 17 of its Judgment No. 4003
issued on 26 June 2018, the ILOAT rules that the behaviour of the former
Registrar of the Court, Mr. Herman von Hebel – who was deemed a person
of high moral character pursuant to Article 43(3) of the Rome Statute –
amounted to “abuse of power, bad faith and retaliation” against one of the
four ICC staff members arrested and illegally detained in Zintan in 2012.
Though isolated, this instance reminds us that the guarantees provided in
the Rome Statute alone, though important, are not all, and fall short from
guaranteeing integrity and ethical behaviour in all circumstances.
By persisting in its failure to address the important policy and legal
issues detailed in the present contribution and provide the ICC with the ro-
bust policy framework called for in the IOM’s post-incident report on the
Zintan crisis of 21 February 2013, and many times since, up until the more
recent IER report of 30 September 2020, the management of the Court and
of the ASP as a whole accepted a great risk. Having tried several times to
persuade those concerned to take necessary measures, I hope that the pre-
sent contribution may strengthen the awareness of the importance of the
applicable standards of integrity at the ICC.
64
Victor Hugo, Ruy Blas, III:2 : “Bon appétit, Messieurs ! Ô Ministres intègres ! Conseillers
vertueux ! Voilà votre façon de servir, serviteurs qui pillez la maison !”.
22.1. Introduction
In December 2018, the Assembly of States Parties (‘ASP’) received the
report of its external auditor on Human Resources Management. 1 The re-
port – which draws on 25 interviews with officials and staff, and the results
of a staff questionnaire – includes the following puzzling observations:
The Court does not have an ethics charter. This situation may
be surprising given its mission. However, the first chapter of
the Staff Regulations, in article 1.2 on “fundamental values”,
addresses various points that may be covered by such a charter:
general rights and obligations, confidentiality, honorary dis-
tinctions, gifts or remuneration, conflicts of interest, employ-
ment and activities outside the Court, and the use of the
Court’s property. Although it has real legal significance, it
does not have the moral impact of an ethics charter binding
on staff. 2
Having made these observations, the external auditor reaches his
finding:
In its regulations, the International Criminal Court has a series
of legal rules regarding ethics but without requiring its staff to
adhere to a more complete “ethics charter”, which would add
*
Suhail Mohammed is a Candidate Legal Practitioner at Bowmans, South Africa. He has
completed B. Pharm., LL.B. with distinction from the University of the Witwatersrand, Jo-
hannesburg, South Africa. Salim A. Nakhjavani is an Adjunct Professor of Law, University
of the Witwatersrand, South Africa, an Advocate of the High Court, South Africa and a
Member of the Johannesburg Bar. He was awarded the B.C.L., LL.B. with a magna cum
laude from McGill University, and an LL.M. first class from the University of Cambridge,
United Kingdom.
1
ICC, Final audit report on Human Resources management, 24 July 2018, ICC-ASP/17/7
(‘Audit report’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/5qtwby/).
2
Ibid., para. 238 (emphasis added).
been disclosed to the external auditor or were omitted from the external
auditor’s report. Second, the (mis)management of misconduct has become
a serious institutional risk to the mandate of the ICC, and a costly one. 9 290F
3
Ibid., p. 38, “Finding”, under paras. 238–240 (emphasis added).
4
Ibid., “Recommendation 9”.
5
ICC, Report of the Court on Human Resources Management, 25 July 2019, ICC-ASP/18/4
(‘Report of the Court on Human Resources Management’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/
doc/pys2zp/).
6
See, for instance, Philip Allott’s satirical critique, Curing the Madness of the Intergovern-
mental World, 8 July 2014, p. 4 (originally given as “The Idea of International Society”, Al-
ec Roche Lecture, 2006, Oxford, available on the web site of the Squire Law Library, Uni-
versity of Cambridge).
7
Report of the Court on Human Resources Management, para. 13, p. 2, see above note 5.
8
See ICC, Annual Report of the head of the Independent Oversight Mechanism (‘IOM’), 11
November 2019, ICC-ASP/18/22, para. 14, p. 4 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/2u1ipr/),
noting that complaints of harassment, sexual harassment and abuse of authority made up just
over 40 per cent of the 32 complaints to the IOM between 1 October 2018 and 30 October
2019.
9
See, for example, ICC, Report of the Committee on Budget and Finance on the work of its
thirty-second session, 3 June 2019, paras. 140–152 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/
q91xoa/); noting specifically “with concern the increased number of litigation cases and
their significant financial impact” (para. 149), and provision of almost EUR 1 million for
some 27 cases pending before the International Labour Organization Administrative Tribu-
nal.
10
ICC, Independent Expert Review of the International Criminal Court and Rome Statute Sys-
tem, Final Report, 30 September 2020 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/cv19d5/).
11
Ibid.
12
ICC, Code of Judicial Ethics, 2 January 2005, ICC-BD/02-01/05 (https://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/383f8f/).
13
ICC, Code of Professional Conduct for counsel, 2 December 2005, ICC-ASP/4/Res.1
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/f9ed33).
14
ICC, Code of conduct for investigators, 10 September 2008, ICC/AI/2008/005 (‘ICC Code
of conduct for investigators’) (https://legal-tools.org/doc/c86582).
by the Registrar (2011); 15 the Code of Conduct for the Office of the Prose-
cutor, promulgated by the Prosecutor (2013); 16 and the Code of Conduct
for Intermediaries (2014). 17 A notable exclusion from this panoply of pro-
fession-specific standards appears to be the interpreters’ and translators’
profession, which was subject to specific ethical standards at the Interna-
tional Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia 18 and the Special Court
for Sierra Leone. 19
So, the ICC’s “moral message” to its staff is not missing. Far from
it – at least on paper. But transmission does not imply reception. The real
question is how the message is translated into action, both individually and
collectively. And the real challenge is that there may be little appetite for
the promulgation of yet more ethical standards in a social space already
inundated by expressions of moral righteousness, and in a world weary of
empty speech.
Moreover, any proposal for additional normative standards must be
assessed against the compliance burden of near-inevitable double deontol-
ogy. We use this term to refer to a situation of being “subject simultaneous-
ly to two [or more] professional codes of conduct”. 20 Indeed, it may be
more accurate, in the context of the ICC, to refer to multiple deontology,
and to distinguish two forms: horizontal and vertical. They encompass sit-
uations where a lawyer is bound by multiple codes of ethical conduct with-
in the ICC normative framework (horizontal multiple deontology); and also
between the ICC framework and their home State(s) of registration, admis-
sion or enrolment for purposes of legal practice (vertical multiple deontol-
ogy).
15
ICC, Code of Conduct for Staff Members, 4 April 2011, ICC/AI/2011/002 (https://legal-
tools.org/doc/75f9db).
16
ICC, Code of Conduct for the Office of the Prosecutor, 5 September 2013 (‘OTP Code’)
(https://legal-tools.org/doc/3e11eb).
17
ICC, Code of Conduct for Intermediaries, 1 March 2014 (https://legal-tools.org/doc/eac2f0).
18
International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia, the Code of Ethics for Interpret-
ers and Translators Employed by the International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugo-
slavia, 8 March 1999, IT/144 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/xix9r7/).
19
Special Court for Sierra Leone, Code of Ethics for Interpreters and Translators Employed by
the Special Court for Sierra Leone, 25 May 2004 (https://legal-tools.org/doc/c56846).
20
Council of Bars and Law Societies of Europe, Guidelines for Bars and Law Societies on
Free Movement of Lawyers within the European Union, p. 9. The English term comes from
the original French (“double déontologie”).
21
Ash-shifâ, al-Burhân, A. Badawi (eds.), Cairo: Association of Authorship, Translation and
Publication Press, 1966.
22
Jon McGinnis, “Scientific Methodologies in Medieval Islam”, in Journal of the History of
Philosophy, July 2003, vol. 41, no. 3, p. 307.
23
Ibid., p. 317.
24
Maurice H. Mendelson, “The Formation of Customary International Law”, in Recueil des
cours, 1998, vol. 272, p. 174, citing D.J. Enright, The Alluring Problem: An Essay on Irony,
1986, p. 5.
25
Audit report, p. 38, “Finding”, under paras. 238–240, see above note 1.
26
Ibid., para. 239.
27
ICC Code of conduct for investigators, see above note 14.
28
Ibid.
the Staff Regulations which forms the basis for the external auditor’s rec-
ommendation. This is the first demonstration of the congruency between
the OTP’s Code of Conduct and the proposed ethics charter.
The next point of analysis is Section 3 of the OTP’s Code of Conduct,
the “Purpose of the Code”. This section explains that the Code seeks to “es-
tablish a set of minimum standards of conduct […] as a supplement to the
general standards of conduct as promulgated in the Code of Conduct for
Staff Members, the Staff Regulations, the Staff Rules, the Code of Conduct
for Investigators and any other document that may be relevant to the per-
formance of their duties”. In addition to this, the General Principles of the
OTP’s Code of Conduct (found in Section 4) explicitly indicates that the
OTP is to be primarily guided by, inter alia, the principle of “professional
ethics and integrity”. The external auditor’s report explains that the existing
standards contained in Article 1.2 of the Staff Regulations “has a series of
legal rules regarding ethics but without requiring its staff to adhere to a
more complete ethics charter”. 29 The OTP’s Code of Conduct, it seems, has
the potential to function as the “complete ethics charter” that has been con-
templated by the external auditor, in respect of a subset of staff – those
serving in the OTP. This is premised on the fact that the OTP’s Code of
Conduct not only expands upon the “legal rules regarding ethics” (which
are located in Article 1.2 of the Staff Regulations), but also requires the
staff of the OTP to adhere to these clearly defined standards of conduct.
Both of these points, at least on their face, seem to achieve the objectives
laid out by the external auditor. Additionally, the manner in which the
OTP’s Code of Conduct functions seems to align with the objectives of the
external auditor in that it supplements the “fundamental values” in Article
1.2 of the Staff Regulations, instead of subsuming that Article.
The external auditor’s recommendation, however, was not solely
aimed at the OTP. Indeed, it was envisioned that the proposed ethics char-
ter would be applicable to all ICC staff. This, presumably, intended to not
only include the ICC’s four constituent organs, but also the counsel who
practise before the Court. It is worth noting, then, that the same commit-
ment to the “fundamental values” contained in Article 1.2 of the Staff Reg-
ulations has been made binding on members of each of these offices (in-
cluding counsel who practise before the Court) through their own separate-
ly applicable codes of conduct. These codes of conduct rightly vary in rela-
29
Audit report, p. 38, “Finding”, under paras. 238–240, see above note 1.
tion to the specific duties that flow from fundamental values, and differ
accordingly in terms of the management of conflicts of interests, confiden-
tiality, general obligations, remuneration and employment outside of the
Court. However, the essence of these codes remains the same: that they are
a set of ethical and professional guidelines which regulate standards of
conduct in relation to the fundamental values in Article 1.2 of the Staff
Regulations. This fact is mostly uncontroversial, and is easily ascertainable
from the explicit language of each of these individual codes. The content of
each of these codes, which have entered into force over a period between
2005 and 2011, would seem to satisfy the external auditor’s objectives in
the same manner as we described in relation to the OTP’s Code of Conduct.
However, an ethics charter that broadly commits itself to upholding
the “fundamental values” contained in Article 1.2 of the Staff Regulations
but fails to provide more definitive guidelines on how that can be achieved
will only ring hollow.
The next point that must be addressed, then, is whether the existing
of codes are – at least formally – capable of practicably fulfilling that
commitment. It is helpful to address this point through the lens of the actu-
al language of the existing guidelines, but perhaps more effective to do so
through an analysis of how these guidelines would (and could have been)
applied in publicly disclosed ethical lapses or failures which have affected
the Court in the past. We turn to consider three specific incidents arising
during the Lubanga trial; in respect of the Prosecutor’s editorial in the Dar-
fur situation; 30 and during the Ruto and Sang and Gbagbo trials.
22.2.1. The Lubanga Trial
The ethical turbulence associated with the Lubanga trial has been well
documented. 31 The issue was the disclosure of confidential documents by
the OTP during the course of the trial. During the trial, the Prosecutor had
failed to disclose a cache of documents which contained potentially excul-
patory evidence, citing “confidentiality” as the rationale for such conduct. 32
This failure was characterised as a “wholesale and serious abuse” by the
Trial Chamber. 33 The question that must be answered here is, firstly,
30
See Section 22.2.2. and note 36 below. See also Milan Markovic, “The ICC Prosecutor’s
Missing Code of Conduct”, in Texas International Law Journal, 2011, vol. 47, no. 1.
31
For a deeper discussion surrounding this particular case, see ibid.
32
ICC, The Prosecutor v. Thomas Lubanga Dyilo, Trial Chamber, ICC-01/04-01/06, para. 17.
33
Ibid., para. 76.
whether the existing OTP Code of Conduct – which would have been di-
rectly applicable, had it been in force at the material time – would have
been capable of providing adequate guidance in relation to this issue; and
secondly, if that is not the case, whether the proposed ethics charter would
be capable of providing suitable guidance in this same instance.
The OTP’s Code of Conduct appears to address the issue of disclo-
sure of documents in Section 3. This section, however, is broadly stated,
and simply places an emphasis on the OTP’s obligation to
comply with the applicable rules on disclosure of evidence
and inspection of material in the possession or control of the
Office in a manner that facilitates the fair and expeditious
conduct of the proceedings and fully respects the rights of the
person under investigation or the accused, with due regard for
the protection of victims and witnesses.
The breadth of this rule has been critiqued by commentators, 34 as it
does not provide “any useful clarity or guidance to members of the OTP to
aid their interpretation of the Statute”. 35 It certainly does not go as far as
the draft rule on disclosure that has been proposed by Markovic, 36 which
would provide strict guidelines as to the legal steps that the OTP ought to
follow in respect of the disclosure of confidential documents during the
trial process.
In our view, the broad terms of the duty of confidentiality in the
OTP’s Code do not limit the effectiveness of its ethical standards concern-
ing the issue of confidentiality. This is because, in our view, the Code of
Conduct ought not to constitute a crystallised guideline on trial procedure
or strategy. Its primary function is to provide an ethical and professional
underpinning which must be borne in mind when devising strategies which,
really, are a matter of procedural and evidentiary law, not ethics, and
should always be guided by the ICC Statute, the Rules of Procedure and
Evidence, and previous decisions made by the Court (where appropriate). 37
In this regard, the current Code of Conduct fulfils its purpose. That is be-
cause it places an imperative on the OTP to interpret these sources of law
34
Lawrence Pacewicz, “International Criminal Court Code of Conduct for the Office of the
Prosecutor”, in International Legal Materials, 2014, vol. 53, no. 2, p. 398.
35
Ibid.
36
Markovic, 2011, pp. 221–222, see above note 30.
37
Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court, 17 July 1998, Article 21 (‘ICC Statute’)
(http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/7b9af9/).
in such a manner that fulfils its obligation in terms of Section 3, while also
affording the OTP the flexibility required to properly pursue prosecutions,
as required by the mandate of that Office. What staff are guided to weigh is
this interface between the Code of Conduct and the law governing trials at
the ICC.
For the sake of argument, let us assume that the OTP’s current Code
of Conduct fails to provide adequate guidance with respect to the issue of
disclosure. The question that then arises is whether the external auditor’s
proposed ethics charter would be capable of filling the gap. We do not
think it would, for straightforward reasons: the external auditor’s proposal
is not specifically aimed at the OTP. Instead, it is aimed at ICC staff in
general. Such a charter could only be couched as generally – if not more
so – as the OTP’s existing Code of Conduct, which is tailored to idiosyn-
cratic issues such as prosecutorial obligations of disclosure. To the extent
the OTP’s Code of Conduct were deficient in the depth of guidance on dis-
closure, the more effective solution would likely be to amend or supple-
ment the existing Code of Conduct, not to promulgate an ethics charter.
22.2.2. The Darfur Situation and the Prosecutor’s Editorial
In 2010, the Appeals Chamber reversed the Pre-Trial Chamber’s decision
to grant an arrest warrant for Omar Al-Bashir for crimes committed in Dar-
fur during the period of March 2003 to July 2008. 38 The ratio that under-
pinned this decision was that the Pre-Trial Chamber applied the incorrect
standard of proof in determining whether an arrest warrant ought to have
been granted. 39 Almost immediately thereafter, the Prosecutor, Luis More-
no-Ocampo, authored a piece which was published in The Guardian, titled
“Now end this Darfur denial”. 40
In the piece, the Prosecutor claimed that the original decision by the
Pre-Trial Chamber had found that “Bashir’s forces have raped on a mass
scale in Darfur” and had “deliberately inflict[ed] on the Fur, Masalit and
Zaghawa ethnic groups living conditions calculated to bring about their
38
ICC, The Prosecutor v. Omar Hassan Ahmad Al Bashir, Appeals Chamber, Judgment on
Appeal Against the “Decision on the Prosecution's Application for a Warrant of Arrest
against Omar Hassan Ahmad Al Bashir”, 3 February 2010, ICC-02/05-01/09-73, para. 2
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/9ada8e/).
39
Ibid., paras. 41–42.
40
Luis Moreno-Ocampo, “Now end this Darfur denial”, The Guardian, 15 July 2010.
46
Ibid.
47
Pacewicz, 2014, p. 398, see above note 34.
48
Ibid., fn. 259.
49
ICC, The Prosecutor v. William Samoei Ruto and Joshua Arap Sang, Trial Chamber, ICC-
01/09-01/11.
50
Constance Rachel Turnbull, “Understanding and Improving the 2013 Code of Conduct for
the Office of the Prosecutor for the International Criminal Court”, in Georgetown Journal of
Legal Ethics, 2018, vol. 31, p. 891.
51
Ibid.
52
The Prosecutor v. William Samoei Ruto and Joshua Arap Sang, Trial Chamber, ICC-01/09-
01/11, para 59.
that tainted the Gbagbo trial 53 was of a similar nature. In that case, the is-
sue in question revolved around the (dis)use of evidence which “might
have cut against the investigative angle”. 54
As stated previously, the heart of our enquiry is whether the existing
ethical framework provides (or would have provided) adequate guidelines
that, if applied in these cases, would have provided greater clarity in re-
spect of the intersection between disclosure of evidence, confidentiality
and objective truth-seeking. The second step of the enquiry also reflects our
previous undertakings and, therefore, addresses whether the external audi-
tor’s proposed ethics charter would provide better guidance in respect of
this same intersection.
Sections 1 and 3 of the OTP’s Code of Conduct are particularly help-
ful in this respect. Section 1 provides clear guidance as to how a Prosecutor
ought to deal with the objective truth-seeking component of this enquiry. In
addressing this issue, Rule 49 explains that:
In compliance with the duty to establish the truth under article
54(1)(a) of the Statute, the Office shall investigate incriminat-
ing and exonerating circumstances equally in all steps in-
volved in the planning and conduct of investigative and prose-
cutorial activities. In particular, Members of the Office shall:
[…] b) consider all relevant circumstances when assessing ev-
idence, irrespective of whether they are to the advantage or
the disadvantage of the prosecution.
This is particularly helpful as it frames the ethical duties of the OTP
through a statutory lens, namely Article 54(1)(a) of the Rome Statute, as
well as a professional and ethical responsibility to not discriminate between
incriminating and exonerating evidence. This is particularly helpful in cas-
es such as Ruto and Sang and Gbagbo, as it crystallises a specific instance
when the Prosecutor must actively consider Article 54(1)(a), which places
an obligation on him or her to “investigate incriminating and exonerating
circumstances equally” – namely when assessing evidence during the case-
preparative phase. The helpfulness of Rule 49 is buttressed by the language
of Rule 49(b), which is far more comprehensive than the statutory duty
contained in Article 54(1)(a) in that it places particular emphasis on the
manner in which the OTP should assess evidence which may disadvantage
53
ICC, The Prosecutor v. Laurent Gbagbo, Trial Chamber, ICC-02/11-01/11-49.
54
Turnbull, 2018, p. 892, see above note 50.
55
Ibid.
erate the general legal obligation to assess evidence impartially. This obli-
gation, then, would likely resemble the normative content of Article
54(1)(a), but be made applicable to a broader range of ICC staff than that
article, which concerns only the OTP. This general proposition, then, will
provide a certain degree of guidance in the sense that it places an ethical
duty on members of the Court, which will function in tandem with the stat-
utory duty that exists in the Rome Statute. This guidance, however, will not
be any more comprehensive – nor any more helpful – than the existing
codes of conduct, which not only confer the same ‘dual duty’ onto the
Court’s staff, but also goes on to further explain the specific importance of
assessing and disclosing evidence which would be prejudicial to one’s own
case. The external auditor’s proposed ethics charter, then, will provide no
further guidance than what is contained within the existing ethical frame-
work.
22.2.4. Reflection
Each of the above-mentioned incidents falls into various constituents of the
“fundamental value” composite that the external auditor’s proposal seeks to
construct. As has been demonstrated, the existing statutory framework at
the ICC is sufficiently robust to achieve such construction on its own. Put
otherwise, the “moral message” which the external auditor wishes to com-
municate through the publication of an ethics charter is capable of being
delivered by the existing constellation of ethical codes in force at the ICC.
22.3. Entrenching the ICC’s “Moral Message” in Practice
Having established that the necessary “moral message” has, at least formal-
ly, been promulgated to the staff serving at every constituent office of the
ICC, we must now consider how this “moral message” might permeate at
the level of culture. 56 We will then consider whether an additional ethics
charter would be helpful in further entrenching the “moral message”.
The literature in management science makes plain that the mere ex-
istence of ethics charters and codes of conduct, does not in itself guarantee
56
The distinction that we have drawn between “formal” and “informal” communication refers
to the difference between having an ethical framework in place and ensuring the implemen-
tation of that ethical framework in a manner that results in the adoption of the ethical values
contained within that framework.
57
Simon Webley and Andrea Werner, “Corporate Codes of Ethics: Necessary But Not
Sufficient”, in Business Ethics: A European Review, 2008, vol. 17, no. 4, p. 405; Pablo Ruiz,
Ricardo Martinez, Cristina Diaz and Job Rodrigo, “Level of Coherence Among Ethics Pro-
gram Components and Its Impact on Ethical Intent”, in Journal of Business Ethics, 2015, vol.
128, no. 4, pp. 725–742.
58
Jennifer J. Kish-Gephart, David A. Harrison and Linda Klebe Treviño, “Bad Apples, Bad
Cases, and Bad Barrels: Meta-Analytic Evidence About Sources of Unethical Decisions at
Work”, in Journal of Applied Psychology, 2010, vol. 95, no. 1, pp. 1–31.
59
Webley and Werner, 2008, p. 406, see above note 57.
60
Ibid.
61
Ibid.
62
Ibid.
63
Ibid.
64
Ibid, citing Brian J. Farrell and Deirdre M. Cobbin, “A Content Analysis of Codes of Ethics
in Australian Enterprises”, in Journal of Managerial Psychology, 1996, vol. 11, no. 1,
pp. 37–55.
65
Ibid.
66
Ibid.
67
Rebecca Goodell, Ethics in American Business: Policies, Programs and Perceptions Report
of a Landmark Survey of U.S. Employees, Ethics Resource Center, Washington, DC, 1994.
68
Ibid.
69
Ibid., p. 37.
This finding was repeated in a 2004 Canadian study. 70 This study re-
volved around 57 interviews of employees and managers of four Canadian
companies in respect of the effectiveness of codes of ethics within their
organisations. On the back of this conclusion, the author of this study went
on to suggest that “the mere existence of a code will be unlikely to influ-
ence employee behaviour” and that companies which “merely possess a
code might legitimately be subject to allegations of window dressing”. 71
The outcomes of these studies suggest that to bolster the probability of eth-
ical compliance within an organisation, that organisation must supplement
its ethical code – or in the case of the ICC, the existing constellation of
codes of conduct – with an immersive, formal programme that ingrains its
ethical commitments into the consciousness of the Court’s staff. On this
point, structure and function are clearly interlinked. As suggested else-
where, an expressly virtues- or values-based code may hold more promise
than duty-based rules as ‘conversation-starters’, and not ‘conversation-
enders’ at the ICC, where staff are drawn from different ‘home’ legal sys-
tems and legal cultures. 72
Another issue that does seem to arise, however, is in relation to what
may be limited disciplinary action associated with breaches of the ICC’s
existing codes of conduct. This is particularly true in relation to the OTP’s
Code of Conduct. 73
On 21 July 1998, the late Chief Justice of South Africa – the first of
the democratic era – Ismail Mahomed, gave a speech to the International
Commission of Jurists in Cape Town. He explained how, absent the exer-
cise of the apparatus of the State in enforcing the orders of courts, they
“could easily be reduced to paper tigers with the ferocious capacity to snarl
and to roar but no teeth to bite and no sinews to execute their judgments
which may then be mockingly reduced to pieces of sterile scholarship,
toothless wisdom or pious poetry”. 74
70
Mark S. Schwartz, “Effective Corporate Codes of Ethics: Perception of Code Users”, in
Journal of Business Ethics, 2004, vol. 55, no. 4, pp. 323–343.
71
Ibid.
72
See Salim A. Nakhjavani, “ICC Statute Article 45”, Lexsitus Lecture, CILRAP Film, 28
September 2017, Johannesburg (www.cilrap.org/cilrap-film/45-nakhjavani/).
73
Turnbull, 2018, p. 900, see above note 50.
74
Ismail Mahomed, “The Independence of the Judiciary”, in South African Law Journal, 1998,
vol. 115, no. 4, pp. 658-667.
75
Timothy L. Fort, “Steps for Building Ethics Programs”, in Hastings Business Law Journal,
2005, vol. 1, no. 1, p. 201.
76
OTP Code, para. 75, see above note 16.
77
Turnbull, 2018, p. 900, see above note 50.
78
Webley and Werner, 2008, p. 408, see above note 57.
79
Ethics Resource Center, National Business Ethics Survey – How Employees View Ethics in
Their Organizations 1994–2005, 2005, Washington, DC.
80
Webley and Werner, 2008, p. 408, see above note 57.
81
Ibid.
82
Linda Klebe Trevino, Gary R. Weaver, David G. Gibson and Barbara Ley Toffler, “Manag-
ing Ethics and Legal Compliance: What Works And What Hurts”, in California Manage-
ment Review, 1999, vol. 41, no. 2, pp. 131–151.
83
Ibid.
84
Webley and Werner, 2008, p. 408, see above note 57.
85
See OTP Code, para. 15, see above note 16; see also Salim A. Nakhjavani, “The Origins and
Development of the Code of Conduct” in Bergsmo, Klaus Rackwitz and SONG Tianying
(eds.), Historical Origins of International Criminal Law: Volume 5, Torkel Opsahl Academ-
ic EPublisher, Brussels, 2017, p. 961 (https://www.toaep.org/ps-pdf/24-bergsmo-rackwitz-
song).
86
The Ethical Enterprise – Doing the Right Things in the Right Ways, Today and Tomorrow (A
Global Study of Business Ethics 2005-2015), American Management Association, New York,
2006; Raymond Baumhart, An Honest Profit – What Businessmen Say About Ethics in Busi-
ness, Holt, Rinehart and Winston, New York, 1968.
87
Webley and Werner, 2008, p. 408, see above note 57.
88
Ibid.
89
ICC Statute, Article 5, see above note 37.
90
ICC Statute, Preamble, 2nd recital, see above note 37.
91
Webley and Werner, 2008, p. 412, see above note 57.
tice, but also ensuring that their progress towards that goal is unimpeacha-
ble.
This last suggestion aligns closely with the findings of the 2004 Eth-
ics at Work survey of the UK-based Institute of Business Ethics. 92 About a
third of respondents who admitted to witnessing unethical conduct at their
workplaces revealed they had chosen not to disclose their observations.
This was predicated on the fact that they felt that “speaking up” would
jeopardise their job security or place them at odds with their colleagues. 93
Indeed, having to work under a climate of fear or retaliation naturally
serves a chilling factor against the disclosure of ethical breaches by persons
operating within that workspace. The ICC, like all workplaces, is likely to
have cultivated a culture whereby its staff are somewhat hesitant to make
such disclosures, whether it be out of fear of castigation or otherwise.
One potential solution that had been advanced during the drafting
process of the OTP Code of Conduct, but now finds no expression in the
final version of that Code, 94 or of the Code of Professional Conduct for
counsel – nor, indeed, in other codes – is the explicit recognition of a fea-
ture of a legal culture familiar in all major legal systems. In the practice of
law as a liberal profession, or as an independent practitioner (such as bar-
risters, advocates and the like), a great deal of ethical decision-making is
premised on seeking informal – but well-informed – advice from more ex-
perienced practitioners, on a collegial basis of confidentiality. The informal
conversation and advice, once rendered, are consigned to the oubliette.
Among independent legal practitioners, this culture only ‘works’ where the
more senior practitioner is committed to the independence and integrity of
the profession above personal interest.
There is no substantial reason, in our view, why such a channel can-
not be brought ‘in-house’ at the ICC, and for it to exist outside a staff
member’s management line. It is an advisory role that demands a certain
calibre of person, to be sure; but the same check on possible abuse that has
embedded this aspect of ethical practice among independent bars and law
societies across legal cultures – that is, a longstanding, unwavering com-
mitment to the institution and to the rule of law – must be expected of the
92
S. Webley and P. Dryden, Ethics at Work: A National Survey, London: Institute of Business
Ethics, 2005.
93
Ibid.
94
Nakhjavani, 2017, p. 957, see above note 85.
international civil service. It bears noting that the calibre of person with the
demonstrated capacity to consistently subordinate individual to institutional
interest – the likes of Noblemaire and Flemming – is not some kind of in-
accessible hero of virtue. That person should be nothing other than an ordi-
nary staff member of the Court.
Moreover, there is a profound, but often unarticulated ethical dimen-
sion to the first principles set out in the ICC Staff Rules: First, “[s]taff taff
members of the Court are international civil servants. Their responsibilities
as staff members of the Court are not national, but exclusively internation-
al”; 95 and second, “[t]he interest of the Court and the obligations that staff
members have towards it shall always take precedence over their other in-
terests or ties”. 96
22.4. Double Deontology: Desperately Seeking Coherence
The problem of vertical double deontology, as between ethical standards
binding on legal practitioners at the ICC and in their home States, is not
particularly vexing, at first glance. The Code of Professional Conduct for
Counsel sidesteps the problem by framing it only in terms of enforcement –
the proverbial ‘pain point’. That is, the disciplinary regime applicable un-
der the Code operates “without prejudice” to the “disciplinary powers” of
any other “disciplinary authority”. 97 There is a rule of complementarity sui
generis that suspends proceedings before the ICC’s disciplinary authority
in cases where a national authority is acting with respect to the same mis-
conduct, unless the national authority is “unwilling or unable to conclude
the disciplinary procedure”. 98
The unstated assumption is that a breach of standards matters less
than when one has not yet been caught, and absent the prospect of conflict-
ing disciplinary measures. The approach has a practical basis, nevertheless,
because the rule of thumb, across various national jurisdictions, is that
counsel appearing in a foreign or international court must uphold all the
ethical rules by which they are bound. It is only when their conduct is for-
mally called into question that the Code applicable at the ICC needs to pro-
vide a deadlock-breaking mechanism.
95
ICC, Staff Rules of the International Criminal Court, 27 July 2015, Rule 101.1 (‘Staff Rules’)
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/2a5274/).
96
Ibid., Rule 101.3.
97
Ibid., Rule 101.3.
98
Ibid., Article 38(4).
99
Stefano Bertea, “The Arguments from Coherence: Analysis and Evaluation”, in Oxford
Journal of Legal Studies, 2005, vol. 25, no. 3, pp. 371–72 (footnotes omitted).
100
Audit report, para. 239, see above note 1.
Reflections on Integrity in
the Prosecution of International Cases
Teresa McHenry and Ann Marie Ursini *
23.1. Introduction
Integrity in international justice – what is it, and how do we get it? And
why is the issue so vexing, particularly if everyone agrees that it is im-
portant? People would likely agree on the key means to achieve integrity:
leadership; culture; training; resources; and accountability. But integrity in
international justice is impossible to define and ultimately achieve without
a clear sense of what these ideals should look like in practice, especially
when practitioners and judges from different domestic legal systems must
operate together, often in newly-created international and hybrid legal sys-
tems.
As a prosecutor with over 30 years of experience with international
crimes, I 1 bring a pragmatic, rather than an academic or theoretical, ap-
proach to the subject of integrity in international criminal cases. For most
of my career, I have dealt with international crime and justice, mostly at the
United States (‘US’) Department of Justice (‘DOJ’) but also for five years
*
Teresa McHenry is the head of the Human Rights and Special Prosecutions Section
(‘HRSP’) within the Criminal Division of the US Department of Justice. She previously
served as the head of the Domestic Security Section, the head of the Alien Smuggling Task
Force, a trial attorney in the Organized Crime and Racketeering Section, and an Assistant
US Attorney for the District of Columbia, all within the US Department of Justice. From
1994 until 1998, she served with the Office of the Prosecutor, International Criminal Tribu-
nal for the former Yugoslavia. She serves as a member of the Commission for the Control of
Interpol’s Files, filling the position of a lawyer with human rights expertise. She has a B.A.
magna cum laude, from Rice University and a J.D., magna cum laude, from Harvard Law
School. Ann Marie Ursini is a Senior Trial Attorney at HRSP, where she has worked since
2013. She previously practiced in the US Attorney’s Office for the Northern District of Cali-
fornia and in the Office of the Prosecutor at the International Criminal Court. She earned a
B.A., magna cum laude, from California State University, Stanislaus, a J.D. from Santa
Clara University School of Law, where she served as Editor-in-Chief of the Santa Clara
Journal of International Law, and an LL.M. with distinction in National Security Law from
Georgetown University School of Law.
1
First person pronouns hereinafter reference Teresa McHenry.
2
Morten Bergsmo, “Revisiting Integrity in International Justice”, FICHL Policy Brief Series
No. 93 (2018), Torkel Opsahl Academic EPublisher, Brussels, 2016 (http://www.toaep.org/
pbs-pdf/93-bergsmo/).
knew at the Tribunal already agreed with their premise. I am not aware of
any prosecutor at the Tribunal who disagreed that rape could be a war
crime, a crime against humanity, or a method of genocide; in fact, we
charged rape as a war crime early in the Tribunal’s work. 3
My fellow prosecutors and I at the ICTY were not struggling with
whether rape could be a war crime. But we were struggling with numerous
practical, procedural and legal issues that arose in the course of prosecuting
this and other international crimes. We could have used help from academ-
ics and others as we struggled to go beyond what we knew from our do-
mestic legal systems. For instance, an overview of how different countries
balance a defendant’s right to information about a rape victim’s medical
history with a victim’s right to privacy about intimate medical issues would
have been useful. I worked on the first multi-defendant case at the ICTY, in
which the defendants sought separate trials, and it would have been valua-
ble to have an analysis of how different domestic systems, particularly non-
jury systems, determined when severance of co-defendants’ trials did or did
not contribute to the integrity of a case and fairness to the defence.
Since my time at the ICTY, there have been significant efforts to ad-
dress these and other challenges faced by the courts. I hope to further this
effort by sharing, from a practitioner’s perspective, some of the practical
challenges we face in bringing integrity to the work of international justice.
23.3. Investigations and Resources
In international justice, even the initial questions of who and what to inves-
tigate are tremendously complicated. At the ICTY, there was much discus-
sion and internal debate about who should be investigated and charged, and,
crucially, how resources should be allocated to various investigations. Eve-
ryone wanted to be fair and lead a process with integrity. But the facts were
not fully known, the conflict was ongoing, and the Tribunal was working to
survive such that it needed to demonstrate tangible results in the short term.
There were hard questions to grapple with: what does fairness mean in the
context of international investigations and charging? How do we stay true
to the ICTY’s mission of providing accountability for high-level perpetra-
tors? How could we deter and prevent future crimes? Further, how did our
goals interact with political realities?
3
International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia (‘ICTY’), Prosecutor v. Delalić et
al. (‘Čelebići case’), Indictment, 19 March 1996, IT-96-21-T (https://www.legal-tools.org/
doc/a40836/).
4
The question of how senior the perpetrator must be to merit attention and resources from an
international court is a recurring one. Interesting, the International Criminal Court OTP Stra-
tegic Plan issued after the CILRAP project conference in The Hague in December 2018,
contains language embracing, in some circumstances, “a strategy of building upwards by fo-
cusing on mid-level or notorious perpetrators first, with the aim of reaching the level of the
most responsible persons at a later stage”. International Criminal Court, Office of the Prose-
cutor, Strategic Plan 2019-2021, 17 July 2019, pp. 19–25 (‘ICC-OTP Strategic Plan 2019-
2021’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/7ncqt3).
Initially, for example, the Bosnian Serbs were not co-operating with
the ICTY, even for investigations involving Bosnian Serb victims. Later,
when the OTP sought evidence from the Bosnian government – a party os-
tensibly co-operating with the OTP – regarding responsibility for certain
crimes committed on the Bosnian side, we found the co-operation less than
robust. (Ultimately, much later, we got the information from the Bosnian
government and determined it would have been very helpful to the prose-
cution’s case, but we were already well into trial and the judges found it
untimely and refused to allow it into evidence.)
Co-operation by States is still a major challenge in international jus-
tice. These dynamics raise hard questions – how strongly, and using what
means, should prosecutors push for assistance? How long do you wait for a
State’s co-operation before deciding to bring charges based on what evi-
dence you have in hand? Is it ‘fair’ that persons who are nationals of a co-
operative State will be punished, but those from an uncooperative State
may not be because the State will not provide important evidence?
23.4. Witnesses
During investigations at the ICTY, the OTP faced a number of challenges
regarding witnesses during the investigation.
23.4.1. Witness Preparation
One of the most obvious and frustrating examples of how definitions of
integrity varied and conflicted among attorneys from different legal sys-
tems was in the preparation of witnesses prior to testimony. I remember
numerous discussions about this with ICTY colleagues from different
countries. Prosecutors from the United States offered that, in our domestic
cases, we would be derelict if we failed to meet with witnesses before they
testified to tell them what kinds of questions to expect, answer questions
they had about the proceeding, and, depending on the anticipated nature
and length of the witness testimony, conduct mock examinations. 5 One of
5
Some practitioners from systems where witness preparation is not routine mistakenly be-
lieve this preparation is akin to coaching or scripting a witness. I would never instruct a wit-
ness what to say (other than to listen to the questions closely and tell the truth) or provide a
script of how they should respond to my questions. The goals of preparing a witness before
their testimony are to ensure the witness had an opportunity to hear and understand the types
of questions I planned to ask in a low-pressure environment, where we could work out dif-
ferences in understanding or, in some cases, language barriers, before the witness was faced
with the intimidating challenge of speaking in court. Additionally, in an adversarial jury sys-
my Australian colleagues said that if they did the same thing in their do-
mestic system, their actions would be frowned upon; another colleague,
from Europe, said preparing a witness in this way, which in the US would
be considered standard practice, would be a criminal offence!
Like so many things at the ICTY, we had to figure out workable solu-
tions that met our respective definitions of integrity in the proceedings
along the way. For instance, I remember the first evidentiary hearing held
at the ICTY for judges to hear witnesses and confirm an indictment, in the
Nikolić case. 6 The judges informed the prosecutors that we should not
‘prepare’ the witnesses by talking to them about their testimony in any way.
For this type of hearing, there is no defendant or defence counsel present,
and there is no cross-examination, so we decided not to object to the judg-
es’ instructions, and we called witnesses to testify without preparing them
beforehand. The first day of witness testimony was a total mess. Witnesses
did not understand what was being asked, they wanted to talk about things
other than what we asked, and the judges were extremely frustrated by the
amount of irrelevant testimony and wasted time. After one day of testimony,
we got word that the judges had changed their minds and now wanted us to
prepare our witnesses before they testified. This was only one hearing in
one case, and I am certain that other judges and other courts have and will
handle these issues differently; I wonder to what extent international courts
have tried to standardize expectations in terms of witness preparation or
offered guidance to attorneys, and whether they have been able to achieve a
practical, workable balance.
23.4.2. Witness Statements
Another complexity that frequently arises in international cases is the issue
of multiple witness interviews and statements, taken by NGOs, journalists,
activists, domestic and international investigators, intermediaries and oth-
ers. An NGO active in Liberia recently told me that they are aware that
some witnesses have been interviewed by persons from as many as eight
tem, preparation helps prosecutors ensure they do not inadvertently ask questions that would
elicit testimony precluded by our rules of evidence and allows prosecutors to assess the
strength of their case. There is a saying among American attorneys: never ask a question in
court to which you do not know the answer. Working with witnesses ahead of a court ap-
pearance is, in our system, an essential part of an attorney’s preparation, and we do a disser-
vice to our client and the witness if we do not adequately prepare.
6
ICTY, Prosecutor v. Nikolić, IT-94-2.
information disclosed in open court. I know that later ICTY cases and other
tribunals have struggled with and continue to struggle with these issues,
particularly given the limitations of sanctions for attorneys who do not
comply with court rules and orders in the international context.
23.5. Discovery and Disclosure
In my experience, prosecutors take their disclosure obligations very seri-
ously and, next to witness security issues, this is one of the biggest chal-
lenges for prosecutors. Disclosure is particularly difficult in large fact- and
document-intensive cases like those prosecuted at the international level.
On large cases, prosecutors need strong case management support person-
nel and appropriate technology up to the task of organizing and redacting
an incredible volume of documents. In some cases, a prosecutor may not
even be able to review every piece of paper (or PDF page) in their case, but
must rely on processing information by type and source.
One consequence of the substantial resources needed to handle dis-
closure obligations is that prosecutors must exercise discretion in limiting
the information they themselves obtain. Prosecutors used to seek more
medical records than we do now, but because of disclosure obligations and
privacy concerns of victims, we now are more discerning. In the case of
electronic evidence, the prevalence of technology has exponentially in-
creased the volume of information available. For instance, in my office, a
recent search warrant for one social media account for a period of only a
few months returned over 10,000 pages of content, most of which required
costly and time-consuming translation. The volume of available infor-
mation combined with resource constraints force prosecutors and investiga-
tors to narrowly tailor their requests in order to return a manageable
amount of information, particularly if the records must be translated or re-
dacted to remove sensitive information, such as witness addresses. As we
work to be discerning, however, we have to be careful to make sure that we
are not failing to obtain or failing to disclose information important to the
case.
23.6. Institutional Ethics Advice and Support
In order to perform a difficult job with integrity, lawyers, staff and others
working in international criminal justice must have resources available to
help them ensure they understand and maintain high standards of ethical
conduct, and that there are mechanisms to report or deal with unethical be-
7
Bergsmo, 2018, see above note 2.
8
Ibid.
9
Ibid.
10
Ibid.
11
Čelebići case, Appeals Chamber, Judgement, 20 February 2001, IT-96-21-A, paras. 625–49
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/051554).
cided we should look up his background online. As it turns out, his creden-
tials were incredibly impressive. We all looked at his resume, stunned into
silence, until one prosecutor spoke up: “I want fingerprints, because there
is no way that the judge here at the Tribunal is the same judge whose re-
sume we are reading”. Choosing appropriate judges, then, involves more
than finding a sterling resume.
Judges are not the only problem. International systems struggle to
consistently hire qualified, competent personnel at all levels. In my career
at the US DOJ, I have been on several hiring committees, and I know a
person’s resume is not always an indicator of how strong an employee they
will be, which is why we use in-depth reference checks, writing samples,
interviews and other means to evaluate candidates. Like so much else, hir-
ing is more complicated internationally. At some point during my time at
the ICTY, maybe because I had been vocal about the need to improve hir-
ing practices, I was drafted to serve on a few hiring committees. I learned
how incredibly hard it is, maybe even impossible, to conduct meaningful
reference checks for practitioners from other countries where you do not
know anyone, you do not know the system, and you do not know the cul-
ture. It is possible that some people are great at working in their own do-
mestic system, but that does not necessarily mean they will be a great fit
for an international justice system.
Because of how difficult it is to evaluate the strength of a candidate
from a different legal system, I have observed that it can be hard to get
hired by international bodies if you do not know someone already in the
system. I think this hurts the practice of international law and may lead to a
host of issues, including the lack of diversity and fundamental fairness. I
suspect this is not necessarily because people in hiring positions only want
to hire their friends, but that, in the absence of a hiring system that reliably
identifies good candidates, some believe the safest way to hire someone
you have some confidence in is to hire someone you already know, or at
least someone who knows someone you know.
I wonder whether a useful exercise would be to conduct further ex-
amination of practical steps to improve the hiring or appointments in all
parts of international justice. For example, should there be some sort of
international bar association group that could conduct more in-depth, edu-
cated and impartial vetting of candidates?
A final challenge that I think is worth mentioning, both because I saw
it at the Tribunal and I have seen it in my own system, has to do with how
from the practical, topical analysis of outside observers. Several of the is-
sues I have addressed have already been the subject of much thought and
attention by those inside and outside the courts. 12 But with each new case,
each new judge, and each new practitioner, these issues arise in new and
different forms. The quest for integrity is perennial. I welcome the oppor-
tunity to share my thoughts and experience, and hopefully to encourage
practical efforts to improve things in the future.
12
For example, the recent ICC-OTP Strategic Plan identifies staff well-being as a key compo-
nent of the strategy. “Staff well-being” under the strategy includes, among other topics, gen-
der equality in recruitment, development, and leadership; ethics and standards of conduct,
including with regard to harassment; and reducing stress among the workforce, who may be
subject to secondary trauma. The prominent placement of staff well-being in the Strategic
Plan appears to indicate an acknowledgement that, for an institution to function with integri-
ty, its personnel must be treated with – and expected to demonstrate – integrity as well. ICC-
OTP Strategic Plan 2019-2021, pp. 27–28, see above note 4.
24.1. Introduction
Judge Aydin Sefa Akay, the (former) Turkish judge on the Ngirabatware
bench at the International Residual Mechanism for Criminal Tribunals
(‘MICT’ or ‘Mechanism’), was arrested in the aftermath of the attempted
coup d’état against the Erdoğan Government. Accused of terrorism-related
offences, Akay was convicted by a criminal court of first instance on the
charge of being a member of the Fetullahist Terrorist Organization. He was
sentenced to seven years and six months of imprisonment and, consequent-
ly, lost his seat on the MICT roster. This chapter will present reflections on
the integrity of some individuals in one way or another involved in the non-
reappointment of Judge Akay. The Akay saga will, in other words, serve as
a practical case-in-point, providing a concrete integrity test.
The chapter will start by outlining the facts of the Akay situation,
collating relevant information disclosed to the public. Then, the behaviour
of selected individuals will be reflected upon on the basis of applicable
codes of conduct and other integrity-grounded considerations. These indi-
viduals include the United Nations (‘UN’) Secretary-General (‘UNSG’),
UN Legal Counsel, MICT Counsel for the Office of the Prosecutor along
with the Prosecutor himself (‘OTP’ or ‘Prosecution’), Defence Counsel for
Ngirabatware, Peter Robinson, at the relevant point in time, and MICT
President and Pre-Review Judge Theodor Meron. By applying the integrity
*
Antonio Angotti is a licensed attorney in Florence, Italy and a Fellow at the Centre for In-
ternational Law Research and Policy (CILRAP). He holds a law degree from the University
of Florence and an LL.M. from the Pennsylvania State University. Basil Saen is an attorney
at the Brussels Bar, where he focuses on white-collar crime, criminal procedure and investi-
gations and a teaching assistant at the Institute for International Law of the University of
Leuven (KU Leuven). He holds a Master of Law from the University of Leuven (KU Leu-
ven). Shan Patel is Research Assistant at the Department of International Law and Dispute
Resolution, Max Planck Institute Luxembourg for Procedural Law and read, inter alia, in-
ternational criminal law and human rights at the London School of Economics and Political
Science.
1
See Morten Bergsmo, “Revisiting Integrity in International Justice”, FICHL Policy Brief
Series No. 93 (2018), Torkel Opsahl Academic EPublisher, Brussels, 2018 (http://
www.toaep.org/pbs-pdf/93-bergsmo).
2
Dag Hammarskjöld, “The International Civil Servant in Law and in Fact”, in Wilder Foote
(ed.), Servant of Peace: A Selection of Speeches and Statements of Dag Hammarskjöld, Sec-
retary-General of the United Nations 1953-1961, Harper & Row, New York, 1962, p. 348
(emphasis added) (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/64bcae/).
3
Bergsmo, 2018, see above note 1.
4
Ibid. See also Morten Bergsmo, “Integrity as Safeguard Against the Vicissitudes of Com-
mon Justice Institutions”, CILRAP Film, The Hague, 1 December 2018 (www.cilrap.org/
cilrap-film/181201-bergsmo/).
5
Ibid., p. 2.
6
See International Civil Service Advisory Board, “Report on Standards of Conduct in the
International Civil Service”, 8 October 1954 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/d94c61/).
7
Bergsmo, 2018, p. 2, see above note 1.
withstanding, aside from freedom from corruptibility, the Policy Brief sets
forth a variety of interesting traits included in a broad understanding of in-
tegrity equally valuable to recall, including truthfulness and fidelity. 8 These
traits resonate strongly with both the facts presented below and our reflec-
tions on integrity in relation thereto.
Lastly, the ethics of international civil servants are indeed fundamen-
tal to understand how desirable conduct can be inspired and obtained. Insti-
tutional integrity must be matched by the integrity of the individuals in-
volved, who can act as a buffer against external influences. Given the plu-
rality of actors and motives surrounding international justice, the Akay saga
reveals how examples of individual integrity may provide the bricks for a
wider reflection on its role and the risks of its absence.
24.2. Reflections on Questions of Integrity of the Concerned
Individuals
Before expanding on the integrity of a number of concerned individuals, a
brief overview will be presented of the circumstances surrounding Aydin
Sefa Akay’s criminal conviction in the Republic of Turkey and his subse-
quent non-reappointment as a judge of the Mechanism.
24.2.1. The Akay Saga
On or around 21 September 2016, Akay, who served as a judge on the
Mechanism’s Ngirabatware bench, was arrested in Turkey, his country of
origin. 9 His arrest was linked to “the events of July 2016 directed against
the constitutional order of Turkey”. 10 Elements of the Turkish military at-
tempted a coup d’état against the Government of Turkey on 15 July 2016.
In response, a state of emergency was declared and routinely extended,
leading to human rights concerns. 11 According to Human Rights Watch, the
Government “embarked on a wholesale purge of public officials, police,
8
Ibid.
9
International Residual Mechanism for Criminal Tribunals, Prosecutor v. Augustin Ngira-
batware, Appeals Chamber, Transcript of Hearing, 17 January 2017, MICT-12-29, p. 2
(‘MICT, Ngirabatware’) (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/d35912/).
10
Ibid.
11
Kareem Shaheen, “Suffocating Climate of Fear in Turkey Despite End of State of Emergen-
cy”, in The Guardian, 19 July 2018. Shaheen notes that the state of emergency ended in July
2018, but that a “suffocating climate of fear” continued to engulf the country.
teachers, judges and prosecutors”. 12 Critics aver that the state of emergency
has been used to detain, intimidate, and prosecute Government opponents
for lengthy periods and without trial. 13 Specifically, with regard to govern-
ment interference with the independence of the judiciary, the Office of the
United Nations High Commissioner for Human Rights documented “in-
creased executive control over, and interference with the judiciary and
prosecution service; the arrest, dismissal and arbitrary transfer of judges
and prosecutors to other courts; and recurring instances of threats against
lawyers”. 14 These internal politics and circumstances surrounding the arrest
and criminal conviction of Akay, though worrisome by rule of law stand-
ards, will not be further discussed in this chapter. Notwithstanding, such
context is important to understand and assess the actions taken vis-à-vis
Akay.
After his arrest, Akay sought release by domestic petition and filed
an application before the European Court of Human Rights. 15 Nevertheless,
he remained in detention, affecting the Mechanism’s ability to function and
ultimately leading to a standstill in the Ngirabatware proceedings, 16 with
corresponding implications to the accused’s right to a fair trial. Several mo-
tions were filed by the parties to the Ngirabatware case, followed by deci-
sions issued by Judge Meron, explicitly dealing with the Akay matter. At
the same time, correspondence was exchanged between the MICT, through
its President, the Defence Counsel for Ngirabatware, other UN officials and
institutions and the Government of Turkey.
On 5 October 2016, President Meron issued a letter to the UN Secu-
rity Council (‘UNSC’), describing the Akay situation, alerting the UNSC of
the matter, and asking to have his letter circulated as an official UNSC
12
Human Rights Watch, “World Report 2017: Turkey”, para. 1 (available on the Human
Rights Watch’s web site).
13
Shaheen, 2018, see above note 11.
14
Office of the UN High Commissioner for Human Rights (‘OHCHR’), “Report on the Impact
of the State of Emergency on Human Rights in Turkey, Including an Update on the South-
East”, March 2018, para. 48 (available on the OHCHR’s web site).
15
MICT, Ngirabatware, Order to the Government of the Republic of Turkey for the Release of
Judge Aydin Sefa Akay, 31 January 2017, para. 13, see above note 9(‘Order for Release’)
(http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/a4975e/) (citing European Court of Human Rights, Akay v.
Turkey, Referral No. 59/17).
16
Letter from the President of the International Residual Mechanism for Criminal Tribunals,
T. Meron, Regarding the Detention of Turkish Judge Aydin Sefa Akay to the UN Security
Council, UN Doc. S/2016/841, 5 October 2016.
document. 17 From that moment on, Meron continued to bring the issue up
in his communications with the UNSC, up to and including his last address
to the UNSC as President of the Mechanism. 18
Meron met with then-UNSG Ban Ki-moon on 8 November 2016.
The MICT President drew the UNSG’s attention to the situation and ex-
pressed his grave concern. He stated that absent a speedy release of Akay,
“a dangerous precedent for the rule of law, for the principle of judicial in-
dependence, and for international justice” would be established. 19
The following day, he brought the issue to the attention of the UN
General Assembly (‘UNGA’). In his address to the UNGA, Meron stressed
the importance of diplomatic immunity granted to MICT judges, which
allows them to “work remotely as much as possible and away from the
seats of the Mechanism”. 20 Akay himself was working from his country of
origin, Turkey, at the moment of his arrest. Meron informed the UNGA that
the UN Office of Legal Affairs (‘UNOLA’) had formally asserted Akay’s
immunity on behalf of the UNSG. 21 Meron expressed his regret that Turkey
did not issue any formal communication on the matter to the Mechanism or
the UN, and explicitly called upon Turkey to comply with its international
obligations under Chapter VII of the UN Charter and immediately release
Akay from detention. 22
Notably, Ngirabatware’s Counsel, Robinson, filed a motion the next
day asking, inter alia, to order Turkey to cease prosecution of Akay so that
the latter could continue his judicial functions on the MICT bench. 23 On 28
November 2016, Meron, as Pre-Review Judge, invited Turkey to file a re-
sponse to the motion. 24 No such response was however issued. 25 During the
17
Ibid.
18
MICT, President Theodor Meron, “Address to the UN Security Council”, 11 December
2018 (available on the MICT’s web site).
19
MICT, “President Meron Meets with UN Secretary-General Ban Ki-moon”, 9 November
2016, para. 4 (available on the MICT’s web site).
20
MICT, President Theodor Meron, “Address to the UN Security Council”, 9 November 2016,
p. 3 (available on the MICT’s web site).
21
Ibid.
22
Ibid.
23
MICT, Ngirabatware, Motion for Order to Government of Turkey or for Temporary Provi-
sional Release, 10 November 2016, see above note 9 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/
a2f168/).
24
MICT, Ngirabatware, Invitation to the Government of the Republic of Turkey, 28 Novem-
ber 2016, see above note 9 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/069a4c/).
25
MICT, Ngirabatware, Order for Release, para. 7, see above note 15.
26
MICT, Ngirabatware, Transcript of Hearing, p. 2, see above note 9.
27
Ibid., p. 3; MICT, Ngirabatware, Order for Release, para. 8, see above note 15.
28
MICT, Ngirabatware, Transcript of Hearing, p. 6, see above note 9.
29
Ibid.
30
MICT, Ngirabatware, Order for Release, para. 16, see above note 15.
31
Ibid., para. 18.
32
Resolution 1966 (2010), UN Doc. S/RES/1966, 22 December 2010, para. 16 (‘MICT Stat-
ute’) (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/e79460/).
33
MICT, Ngirabatware, Decision on Republic of Turkey’s Non-Compliance with Its Obliga-
tions to Cooperate with the Mechanism, 6 March 2017 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/
47e335/).
34
Ibid., p. 2.
35
MICT, “Mechanism Notifies United Nations Security Council of Turkey’s Non-
Compliance”, 16 March 2017 (available on the MICT’s web site).
36
Letter dated 10 March 2017 from the Permanent Representative of Turkey to the United
Nations addressed to the President of the Security Council, UN Doc. S/2017/210, 10 March
2017.
an offence punishable under the Turkish Penal Code. The Permanent Rep-
resentative further claimed that the Mechanism was not entitled to issue the
31 January 2017 order, that it clearly overstepped its mandate, and that the
order was a “flagrant and worrying attempt to interfere with the independ-
ent judicial process” of Turkey. 37 As a result, Turkey consistently consid-
ered the order to be null and void. 38
In June 2017, Akay was convicted by a Turkish criminal court of first
instance in Ankara for being a member of the Fetullahist Terrorist Organi-
zation. He was sentenced to seven years and six months of imprisonment.
Following his provisional release pending appeal, Akay resumed his judi-
cial functions for the Mechanism. President Meron expressed his regret for
Turkey’s actions and called on the Government to “take urgent steps to re-
spect the protected status of Judge Akay and to resolve the situation con-
sistent with international law”. 39
Consequently, in his 22 June 2018 letter to the President of the
UNSC, the UNSG noted that, under Article 9 of the MICT Statute, judges
are to be “persons of high moral character, impartiality and integrity who
possess the qualifications required in their respective countries for ap-
pointment to the highest judicial offices”. 40 The UNSG stated that the
Turkish Government had informed the Secretariat that Akay’s eligibility
was tarnished and that he “does not possess the qualifications for appoint-
ment to the highest judicial office in Turkey under the applicable law”. 41
The UNSG concluded that, in light of the information which the Govern-
ment of Turkey apparently had furnished, Judge Akay “does not currently
meet the qualification requirements for judges of the Mechanism under Ar-
ticle 9, paragraph 1, of the Statute and, consequently, cannot be considered
for reappointment”. 42
That being the case, on 29 June 2018, the UNSG did not reappoint
Judge Akay as a judge of the MICT. 43 In reaction, President Meron again
37
Ibid., p. 2.
38
Ibid.
39
MICT, “Statement of the Mechanism on Conviction of Judge Aydin Sefa Akay by Turkish
Criminal Court of First Instance”, 15 June 2017, para. 3 (available on the MICT’s web site).
40
Letter dated 22 June 2018 from the Secretary-General addressed to the President of the Se-
curity Council, UN Doc. S/2018/626, 26 June 2018, p. 1.
41
Ibid.
42
Ibid., p. 2.
43
MICT, “Statement of the President on the Non-Reappointment of Judge Akay”, 3 July 2018
(available on the MICT’s web site).
expressed his regret and disagreement. 44 Meron furthered that “the decision
not to reappoint Judge Akay is profoundly troubling on multiple levels”. 45
With regard to the fact that the decision not to reappoint Akay was based
on information provided by the Turkish Government, Meron averred that
the acquiescence to the position advanced by the Government
of Turkey represents a de facto acceptance of a State’s actions
undertaken in contravention of the diplomatic immunity as-
serted by the United Nations, a dangerous precedent to set. 46
He concluded by stressing the importance of judicial independence,
which he deems “a cornerstone principle of the rule of law”, and the danger
this precedent holds for the integrity of the Mechanism, as well as for the
overall project of international criminal justice. 47
On 23 July 2018, President Meron assigned Judge Lee G. Muthoga to
replace Judge Akay on the Ngirabatware bench. 48 Several months later, in
December 2018, the Turkish Judge Yusuf Aksar was elected to the judicial
roster of the Mechanism. 49
Most notably, in early 2019, Judge Christoph Flügge resigned from
the MICT citing, among other concerns, political interference by Turkey
and the United States. He claimed Turkey's allegations against Akay to be
“baseless” and stated that Akay's non-reappointment had been enabled by
the connivance of the UN. 50 According to Flügge, other judges of the
Mechanism protested to the course of events, but without success. Finally,
Flügge, much like Meron, underlined the importance of judicial independ-
ence, stating that:
[e]very incident in which judicial independence is breached is
one too many. Now there is this case, and everyone can in-
voke it in the future. Everyone can say: ‘But you let Turkey
get its way.’ This is an original sin. It can’t be fixed. 51
44
Ibid.
45
Ibid., para. 1.
46
Ibid., para. 5.
47
Ibid., para. 6.
48
MICT, Ngirabatware, Order Replacing a Judge in a Case before the Appeals Chamber, 23
July 2018, see above note 9 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/96d930/).
49
MICT, “General Assembly Elects Judge Yusuf Aksar of Turkey to Serve as Mechanism
Judge”, 7 January 2019 (available on the MICT’s web site).
50
Daniel Boffey, “UN Court Judge Quits The Hague Citing Political Interference”, in The
Guardian, 28 January 2019. See also Stefan Willeke, “Ich bin zutiefst beunruhigt”, in Die
Zeit, 25 January 2019.
51
Ibid.
52
MICT, “Address to the UN Security Council”, p. 2, see supra note 17.
53
Ban Ki-moon and António Guterres have both been confronted with the Akay saga during
their respective terms as UNSG. Whenever temporal references are made in relation to con-
duct, the SG to which this pertains has been specified.
54
Charter of the United Nations, 24 October 1945, ch. XV (‘UN Charter’) (outlining the object
and purpose of the Secretariat and, in particular, its leadership).
55
Ibid., Article7.
56
Kjell Skjelsbæk and Gunnar Fermann, “The UN Secretary-General and the Mediation of
International Disputes”, in Jacob Bercovitch (ed.), Resolving International Conflicts, Lynne
Rienner Publishers, London, 1996, p. 78.
57
UN Charter, Articles 98, 100, 101, see above note 54.
58
Ibid., Article 97.
59
Carsten Stahn and Henning Melber, “Human Security and Ethics in the Spirit of Dag Ham-
marskjöld: An Introduction”, in Carsten Stahn and Henning Melber (eds.), Peace Diploma-
cy, Global Justice and International Agency, Cambridge University Press, 2014, pp. 20–21.
60
See International Civil Service Commission (‘ICSC’), Standards of Conduct for the Interna-
tional Civil Service, 2013, para. 29 (‘ICSC Standards of Conduct’), approved by United Na-
tions Common System: Report of the International Civil Service Commission, UN Doc.
A/RES/67/257, 3 June 2013. The 2013 ICSC Standards of Conduct replaced the 2001 revi-
sion of the ethical standards adopted in 1954.
61
Indeed, Haack and Kille point to the duality in the UNSG mandate, encompassing both the
political and administrative dimension. See Kirsten Haack and Kent J Kille, “The UN Secre-
tary-General and Self-Directed Leadership: Development of the Democracy Agenda”, in Jo-
el E Oestreich (ed.), International Organizations as Self-Directed Actors: A Framework for
Analysis, Routledge, Oxford, 2012, pp. 29–59. See also Skjelsbæk and Fermann, 1996,
p. 79, see above note 56; Simon Chesterman (ed.), Secretary or General? The UN Secre-
tary-General in World Politics, Cambridge University Press, 2007.
62
Staff Rules and Regulations of the United Nations, UN Doc. ST/SGB/2017/1, 1 January
2017, Regulation 1.2 (d)-(e) (these references can likewise be found in the 2014 version);
ICSC Standards of Conduct, 2013, para. 29, see above note 60.
merate how public support is crucial for any UN organization – and, indeed,
the UN system in general. Civil servants, in that regard, have an ongoing
“responsibility to promote a better understanding of the [system]”. 63 The
independence codified in the UN Charter, thus, must continuously be bal-
anced with the duty to furnish the most optimal relations with States while
acting to the benefit of the organization.
Although the UN Charter indeed makes a direct mention of integrity
and does so in the context of the Secretariat, the reference pertains to
sought after traits that underpin employment considerations. 64 Notwith-
standing the fact that the concept accrued prominence over time, it is not
mentioned in the preamble neither is it found verbatim elsewhere nor con-
ceptually delineated in the UN Charter. However, Article 101 of the UN
Charter allows inferring that holding the requisite integrity is pertinent to
UN employees which, in turn, implies that all staff must act with integrity
when discharging official functions. In that sense, when read in conjunction
with the UN Staff Regulations and ICSC Standards of Conduct, it becomes
clear that integrity is considered one of the “great traditions of public ad-
ministration” entrenched in all aspects of civil service. 65
24.2.2.1.2. Actions
Intent on steering clear of an in-depth discussion on the immunities of in-
ternational judges, this aspect cannot be ignored in assessing the manner in
which the UNSG, as the representative of the international community,
handled the Akay situation. 66 It must be acknowledged that, in November
2016, the UNOLA did, in fact, call upon the Turkish government to halt
legal proceedings against Judge Akay on behalf of then-UNSG Ban Ki-
moon, drawing attention to the diplomatic immunity granted to members of,
inter alia, the MICT bench. 67 Prior to that, on 25 October 2016, the UNO-
63
ICSC Standards of Conduct, 2013, para. 35, see above note 60.
64
UN Charter, Article 101(3), see above note 54.
65
ICSC Standards of Conduct, 2013, paras. 2, 5, 22, see above note 60; Staff Rules and Regu-
lations of the United Nations, 2017, Regulation 1.2 (b), see above note 62.
66
For a discussion of both the functional and personal immunity of judges in relation to the
situation of Akay, see Ady Niv, “The Immunity of Judge Akay in Turkey: A Test Case for
International Judges’ Immunity and Independence”, in ASIL Insights, 2018, vol. 22, no. 14.
67
See United Nations, “Briefing by Spokesperson for Secretary-General, Stéphane Dujarric”,
10 November 2016 (available on the UN Audiovisual Library’s web site). For a factual
overview of the Akay situation, see above Section 24.2.1.
68
MICT, Ngirabatware, Motion to Initiate Contempt Proceedings, 3 April 2017, annex E, see
above note 9 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/a1a511/).
69
Ibid., paras. 1–2.
70
Ibid., para. 3.
71
Letter dated 22 June 2018 from the Secretary-General addressed to the President of the Se-
curity Council, 2018, see above note 40.
72
Ibid., para. 7.
73
See, for example, Kent J. Kille (ed.), The UN Secretary-General and Moral Authority: Eth-
ics and Religion in International Leadership, Georgetown University Press, Washington,
D.C., 2007.
74
Kent J. Kille, “The Secular Pope: Insights on the UN Secretary-General and Moral Authori-
ty”, in Kille (ed.), 2007, p. 352, see ibid.
75
See above notes 63 and 65.
76
Kille, 2007, pp. 352–353, see above note 74.
77
Simon Chesterman, “The Secretary-General We Deserve?”, in Global Governance, 2015,
vol. 21, no. 4, pp. 505–506. See also Jodok Troy, “Two “Popes” to Speak for the World:
The Pope and the United Nations Secretary General in World Politics”, in The Review of
Faith & International Affairs, 2017, vol. 15, no. 4, p. 71.
78
See, for example, Dina F. Haynes, “Ethics of International Civil Service: A Reflection on
How the Care of United Nations Staff Impacts the Ability to Fulfill Their Role in Harmoniz-
ing the World”, in Hamline Journal of Public Law & Policy, 2008, vol. 30, no. 1, pp. 208–
209. See also David M. Malone, “Eyes on the Prize: The Quest for Nonpermanent Seats on
the UN Security Council”, in Global Governance, 2000, vol. 6, no. 1, pp. 3–23; Elia Arm-
82
UN Secretary-General, Organization of the Secretariat of the United Nations, UN Doc.
ST/SGB/2015/3, 22 July 2015, sec. 3. See also UN Secretary-General, Organization of the
Office of Legal Affairs, UN Doc. ST/SGB/2008/13, 1 August 2008, sec. 3.1.
83
See above Section 24.2.2.1.1. On the accountability chain, see also Organization of the Of-
fice of Legal Affairs, 2008, sec. 3, 4, see above note 82.
84
Ibid.
85
Ibid., sec. 3.2.
86
Ibid., sec. 3.5.
87
See, for example, the core functions outlined on its website: UN Office of Legal Affairs,
“Office of the Legal Counsel” (available on the UNOLA’s web site).
88
International Law Commission, Provisional Summary Record of the 3371st Meeting, UN
Doc. A/CN.4/SR.3371, 6 July 2017, pp. 4–5.
89
Ibid.
90
Ibid., p. 5. Remarkably, when the MICT Statute was approved by the Security Council, Tur-
key held one of its rotating seats and voted in favour of its adoption, see 6463rd Meeting
Records, UN Doc. S/PV.6463, 22 December 2010, p. 3.
91
Provisional Summary Record of the 3371st Meeting, 2017, see above note 88.
92
MICT, Ngirabatware, Motion to Initiate Contempt Proceedings, annexes C, E, see above
note 68. See also above note 67.
93
MICT, Ngirabatware, Motion to Initiate Contempt Proceedings, annex C, see above note
68. For our reflections on the integrity of Defence Counsel, see below Section 1.1.1.3.
94
Ibid., annex E. Confirming the meeting between the UNSG and President Erdoğan, see also
“In Turkey, UN Chief Guterres Discusses Syria, Iraq, Cyprus with President”, in UN News,
11 February 2017 (available on the UN News’ web site); Shebab Khan, “UN Secretary-
General Says Fight Against Extremists in Syria Needs Political Solution”, in The Independ-
ent, 11 February 2017; “Erdoğan, BM Genel Sekreteri Guterres ile bir araya geldi”, in Sput-
nikNews Türkiye, 11 February 2017.
those between UNOLA and Member States, inaccessible due to their confi-
dential nature, any opinion will necessarily carry qualified weight. The
UNSC meeting records nevertheless provide some valuable insight insofar
that the efforts of the UN Legal Counsel and his office have been lauded by
some Member State Representatives. For example, Senegal “commend[ed]
the work being carried out by the Office of Legal Affairs of the Secretariat”
surrounding the Judge Akay and “welcome[d] the efforts […] to seek a
happy conclusion to this matter”. 95 Although final conclusions cannot be
drawn from this praise, it seems that the behaviour of the relevant UNOLA
officials fell in line with expectations. Such conduct is to be expected, tak-
ing into account the fact that independence and integrity are core values at
the organization, essential for civil servants such as the UN Legal Counsel,
as a member of the Secretariat. On top of that, the UNSG bulletin specifi-
cally notes that the Secretariat must “promote the principles of the Charter”
in its functioning, adding validity to such a supposition. 96
The duties of the UN Legal Counsel include, in addition, ensuring
the transparency of his office. 97 Despite the absence of any indication in the
UNSG bulletin as to whom this transparency of conduct is owed, read to-
gether with the Standards of Conduct and Staff Regulations, one can as-
sume that the Office services the general public and should allow the latter
to scrutinize UNOLA conduct. Unsurprisingly, the transparency-related
duties link to the requirement obliging the international civil servant to
promote the public’s understanding of the UN system. 98 Notwithstanding
any responsibilities that indeed might be owed to the public at large by vir-
tue of his status as a civil servant, as counsel to the UNSG and the UN bod-
ies, de Serpa Soares has a foremost – and overriding – duty to his client.
This could explain the relative lack of information furnished by the UN
Legal Counsel, as well as the UNOLA, and would categorize the conduct
portrayed as evidencing sufficient levels of integrity, within the confines of
the available professional latitude. In addition, the fact that President Mer-
on, a central voice in the Akay saga, consistently expressed his gratitude to
“Mr. Miguel de Serpa Soares […] for […] ongoing and critically important
95
7829th Meeting Records, UN Doc. S/PV.7829, 8 December 2016, p. 13; 7960th Meeting
Records, UN Doc. S/PV.7960, 7 June 2017, p. 15.
96
Organization of the Secretariat of the United Nations, 2015, sec. 2, see above note 82.
97
Organization of the Office of Legal Affairs, 2008, sec. 3.2, see above note 82.
98
ICSC Standards of Conduct, 2013, para. 35, see above note 60.
assistance”, one can assume that requisite levels of integrity were dis-
played. 99
1.1.1.2. The Office of the Prosecutor of the International Residual
Mechanism for Criminal Tribunals 100
24.2.2.1.7. Normative Framework
The MICT Prosecution is bound by the Standards of Professional Conduct
of Prosecution Counsel (‘Standards’). 101 Adopted by the then-Prosecutor,
Hassan Bubacar Jallow, these Standards are guided by a number of consid-
erations listed in the first article. One of these considerations affirms that
“Prosecutors, who in the MICT represent the international community, play
a crucial role in the administration of justice”. 102 The Prosecution is ex-
pected “to assist the Tribunal to arrive at the truth and to do justice for the
international community, victims and accused”, 103 and to respect the rights
of the accused, including the right to a fair trial by an impartial and inde-
pendent judiciary. 104 The MICT Standards likewise outline a cooperative
approach to the fulfilment of a part of the duties of the OTP: the Prosecu-
tion must see that the legitimate interests of the international community
are duly reflected in the administration of justice, and must do so in coop-
eration with the Mechanism.
In addition, the Guidelines on the Roles of Prosecutors (‘Guidelines’),
adopted by the Eighth UN Congress on the Prevention of Crime and the
Treatment of Offenders, 105 hold particular value due to the Mechanism hav-
ing received its mandate from the UNSC. Article 12 of the Guidelines is,
99
7829th Meeting Records, 2016, p. 5, see above note 95; 7960th Meeting Records, 2017,
p. 6, see above note 958278th Meeting Records, UN Doc. S/PV.8278, 6 June 2018, p. 2. It
should be acknowledged that Meron never explicitly linked his expression of gratitude to as-
sistance in the Akay matter.
100
At the time of writing, Mr. Serge Brammertz is the MICT Chief Prosecutor.
101
MICT, Prosecutor’s Regulation No. 1 (2013) on Standards of Professional Conduct of Pros-
ecution Counsel, MICT/12, 29 November 2013 (‘MICT Standards for Prosecution’) (http://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/d71ab0/).
102
Ibid., Article 1.
103
Ibid., Article 2(h).
104
Ibid., Article 2(a).
105
Guidelines on the Roles of Prosecutors, Eight UN Congress on the Prevention of Crime and
the Treatment of Offenders, UN Doc. A/CONF.144/28/Rev.1, 27 August 1990, p. 188 (‘UN
Guidelines on the Roles of Prosecutors’) (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/658aba/), wel-
comed by Resolution 45/166 (18 December 1990), UN Doc. A/RES/45/166, 18 December
1990.
however, careful in its reference to the duty to cooperate with the court in
protecting the accused person’s right to a fair trial. Indeed, it states that
“Prosecutors shall […] perform their duties fairly […] contributing to en-
suring due process”. 106
The Standards of Professional Responsibility and Statement of Es-
sential Duties and Rights of Prosecutors of the International Association of
Prosecutors 107 (‘IAP Standards’) should be considered a document with
significant persuasive power: more so, as it is mentioned in Article 1 of the
MICT Standards. 108 Article 4.3 of the IAP Standards explicitly demands
that “Prosecutors […] safeguard the rights of the accused in co-operation
with the court”, 109 which should be read alongside the duty enshrined in
Article 1 of the IAP Standards to “always protect an accused person’s right
to a fair trial”. 110
The obligation to cooperate with the court to ensure the accused’s
right to a fair trial by an independent judiciary is crucial for the case at
hand. This specific duty defines the role of the MICT Prosecution beyond
the successful prosecution of cases. When fair trial rights are in peril, the
OTP must work with the MICT adjudicatory arm to avert such threats. In
the Ngirabatware case, complying with the aforementioned obligation
would have meant acting in defence of Judge Akay’s independence in order
to preserve Ngirabatware’s right to a fair trial.
24.2.2.1.8. Actions
There were two potential avenues for the Prosecution through which to
protect the independence of the Ngirabatware bench. First, pursuant to
UNSC Resolution 1966 (2010), 111 the Prosecutor of the Mechanism, along
with the President, submit biannual progress reports to the UNSC. In the
reports of November 2016 112 and May 2017, 113 as described below, the
106
Ibid., Article 12, p. 192.
107
International Association of Prosecutors, Standards of Professional Responsibility and
Statement of Essential Duties and Rights of Prosecutors, 23 April 1999 (‘IAP Standards’)
(available on the IAP’s web site).
108
MICT Standards for Prosecution, Article 1, see above note 101.
109
IAP Standards, Article 4.3, see above note 107.
110
Ibid., Article 1.
111
MICT Statute, see above note 32.
112
Assessment and Progress Report of the President of the International Residual Mechanism
for Criminal Tribunals, Judge Theodor Meron, for the Period from 16 May to 15 November
2016, UN Doc. S/2016/975, 17 November 2016, Annex I, paras. 13, 38, 90.
President brought to the attention of the UNSC the issue of Judge Akay’s
independence. The Prosecutor, on the contrary, did not mention Akay or the
Ngirabatware proceedings at all.
A second avenue to protect the independence of the MICT judge be-
came available during the proceedings of the Ngirabatware case itself
when significant discussion on judicial independence took place. In the
hearing of 17 January 2017, 114 the Prosecution 115 emphasized how “a way
forward has to be found so that the fair trial issues that have arisen in this
case can be resolved without any further delay”, holding that “an order to
Turkey is not a guaranteed solution” while expressing “concern about the
prospect of [Turkey’s] timely compliance with any order issued”. 116 The
Prosecution suggested to replace Judge Akay on the bench and, to that end,
provided legal grounds for the different possibilities granted by the Statute
as well as the MICT Rules of Procedure and Evidence. 117 While it is fair to
note that the ‘remedies’ suggested during the course of the hearing would
have, for the most part, preserved Akay’s immunity, the Prosecution seem-
ingly did not weigh the far-reaching consequences in terms of judicial in-
dependence. The OTP has been shown to pursue one main interest: moving
the case forward, arguably willing to waive judicial independence in order
to minimize delays. This aim has been clearly articulated during the hear-
ing when the Prosecution affirmed that “ensuring an immediately available
review bench that can move forwards with deliberations in this case is the
priority”. 118
Other case documents contribute to outline the overall attitude of the
OTP. In its Response to Ngirabatware’s Motion for Order to Government
of Turkey or for Temporary Provisional Release, the Prosecution contended
that “a period of two months does not, in the particular circumstances of
this case, amount to undue delay given the complexity of the matter before
the Appeals Chamber” and requested the dismissal of both the motion and
113
Assessment and Progress Report of the President of the International Residual Mechanism
for Criminal Tribunals, Judge Theodor Meron, for the Period from 6 November 2016 to 15
May 2017, UN Doc. S/2017/434, 17 May 2017, Annex I, paras. 12–14, 38, 89.
114
MICT, Ngirabatware, Transcript of Hearing, see above note 9.
115
Ms. Michelle Jarvis appeared for the Prosecution, with Mr. Mathias Marcussen as Co-
Counsel and Mr. Iain Reid as Case Manager.
116
MICT, Ngirabatware, Transcript of Hearing, p. 14, see above note 9.
117
Ibid.
118
Ibid.
the request for an oral hearing. 119 The Prosecution did not mention the de-
tention of Judge Akay. Regardless, the implications of the matter were not
lost on the OTP. During the proceedings, the Prosecution acknowledged in
several instances how, ultimately, fair trial rights were severely impact-
ed. 120
24.2.2.1.9. Reflections on Integrity
The normative framework for the OTP outlines an obligation to protect the
accused person’s right to a fair trial in cooperation with the court in order
to properly contribute to the administration of justice. The Ngirabatware
proceedings show how the Prosecution prioritized the swift ending of the
case while disregarding, to some extent, Ngirabatware’s right to be judged
by an independent judiciary. The OTP also refrained from condemning or
pressuring the Government of Turkey, both in the proceedings itself and in
its reporting to the UNSC, even though the MICT Prosecutor is bound to
represent the international community. 121 As the international community
holds a legitimate interest in the independence of international judges and
in the preservation of diplomatic immunity, it can be argued that the Prose-
cution did not properly fulfil its mandate in this regard. The actions of the
OTP narrowly focused on furthering the case, perhaps in order to remain
non-aligned on the matter of Judge Akay’s conviction and imprisonment.
However, we conclude that even if the observed actions may not be directly
construed as a violation of the relevant norms, the MICT Prosecutor was
certainly not neutral in terms of integrity. Acting with integrity would have
demanded to fully embrace the duty to protect the right of the accused to an
impartial judge, contributing to the efforts of the Mechanism, and to safe-
guard judicial independence in the name and for the sake of the interna-
tional community.
119
MICT, Ngirabatware, Prosecution Response to Motion for Order to Government of Turkey
or for Temporary Provisional Release, 18 November 2016, (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/
762b6c/).
120
See MICT, Ngirabatware, Transcript of Hearing, p. 14, see above note 9.
121
MICT Standards for Prosecution, Article 1, see above note 101.
122
Mr. Ngirabatware was, at the time of the events we refer to, assisted by Mr. Peter Robinson.
123
MICT, Code of Professional Conduct for Defence Counsel Appearing Before the Mecha-
nism, 14 November 2012, MICT/6, Article 14 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/eeb133/).
124
Ibid.
125
Ibid., Article 20.
126
MICT, Ngirabatware, Transcript of Hearing, see above note 9.
127
Ibid., pp. 28–29.
128
Ibid., p. 29.
129
Ibid., p. 2.
130
Ibid., p. 6.
131
MICT, Ngirabatware, Motion to Initiate Contempt Proceedings, para. 5, see above note 68.
132
Ibid., pp. 12–13, 15-16, 18, 20-21, 25-26. See also Section 1.1.1.1.
133
Frederik Harhoff, “Mystery Lane: A Note on Independence and Impartiality in International
Criminal Trials”, FICHL Policy Brief Series No. 47 (2016), Torkel Opsahl Academic EPub-
lisher, Brussels, 2016 (http://www.toaep.org/pbs-pdf/47-harhoff/).
134
See Gunnar M. Ekeløve-Slydal, “ICTY Shifts Have Made Its Credibility Quake”, FICHL
Policy Brief Series No. 49 (2016), Torkel Opsahl Academic EPublisher, Brussels, 2016
(http://www.toaep.org/pbs-pdf/49-slydal); Julija Bogoeva, “International Judges and Gov-
ernment Interests: The Case of President Meron”, FICHL Policy Brief Series No. 48 (2016),
Torkel Opsahl Academic EPublisher, Brussels, 2016 (http://www.toaep.org/pbs-pdf/48-
bogoeva).
135
Gregory S. Gordon, “Measuring Integrity in Post-Conviction Proceedings” CILRAP Film,
The Hague, 2 December 2018 (https://www.cilrap.org/cilrap-film/181202-gordon/).
136
MICT, “Address to the UN Security Council”, p. 3, see above note 18.
137
MICT, Code of Professional Conduct for the Judges of the Mechanism, 9 April 2018,
MICT/14/Rev. 1 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/23cc92/).
138
Ibid., Article 10(2).
139
Basic Principles on the Independence of the Judiciary, Seventh UN Congress on the Preven-
tion of Crime and the Treatment of Offenders, UN Doc. A/CONF.121/22/Rev.1, 26 August
1985.
140
Ibid., Article 4.
ducted fairly and that the rights of the parties are respected”. 141 The use of
the term ‘ensure’ arguably construes an active duty to remove impediments
to the fair conduct of judicial proceedings. The MICT Statute, in addition,
affirms the aforementioned principle in its Article 18. 142
Considering how judicial independence is paramount for the respect
of the accused’s right to a fair trial, judges have the duty to ensure its re-
spect at all times. It could be argued that no value should surpass the pro-
tection of judicial independence, as the fair trial rights of the accused lie at
the very core of the rule of law. The explicit mention of the obligation to
ensure an expeditious trial should not be construed as being hierarchically
superior to the rights of the accused, as the Statute equally mandates “full
respect” for the latter too.
In the case at hand, complying with Article 18 of the MICT Statute in
a manner consistent with the Principles would have meant according priori-
ty to the right of the accused to be judged by an independent judiciary. The
provision of Article 10(2) of the Code should be construed as according
priority to the protection of judicial independence over any other obligation
the Code confers upon MICT judges.
24.2.2.1.14. Actions
The actions of Judge Meron in defence of Judge Akay’s independence have
shown consistency with his views on judicial independence and its uncon-
ditionality. In a 2005 article, 143 Meron made two statements that are rele-
vant to the topic at hand. First, he affirmed that a President of an interna-
tional criminal tribunal has a duty to “protect the Tribunal as a whole from
inappropriate encroachment”, even if said encroachment originates from
the Security Council itself. 144 Second, he wrote that “the President’s role as
spokesperson for the Tribunal involves him in diplomatic and political
141
Ibid., Article 6.
142
MICT Statute, p. 13, see above note 32. Article 18 reads: “[t]he Single Judge or Trial
Chambers conducting a trial shall ensure that the trial is fair and expeditious and that pro-
ceedings are conducted in accordance with the Rules of Procedure and Evidence, with full
respect for the rights of the accused and due regard for the protection of victims and wit-
nesses”.
143
Theodor Meron, “Judicial Independence and Impartiality in International Criminal Tribu-
nals”, in The American Journal of International Law, 2005, vol. 99, no. 2, pp. 359–369.
144
Ibid., p. 365.
functions”. 145 Judicial proceedings are not, therefore, the only avenue that a
President should use in order to fulfil his duties towards the Tribunal.
Judge Meron, consistent with the views he expressed in the past, be-
gan his defence of Judge Akay with a letter to the President of the UNSC,
exercising his political functions as the MICT President. 146 The letter, dated
5 October 2016, is the first of a series of initiatives taken by Judge Meron
to draw attention to the ongoing detention of Judge Akay, and its far-
reaching consequences on judicial independence, the rule of law and the
effective functioning of the Mechanism. Indeed, Meron conveyed to the
UNSC that he did not
consider it possible, under the circumstances, to reconcile full
respect for the fundamental principle of judicial independence,
on the one hand, with, on the other hand, the removal of Judge
Akay from the bench to which he has been assigned. 147
In his official capacity as President of the Mechanism, Judge Meron
filed two progress reports to the UNSC, on 17 November 2016 and 17 May
2017, in which he raised the issue of Akay’s detention, noting the broader
implications on the ability of the Mechanism to fulfil its mandate. 148 The
President’s annual report of August 2017 likewise mentioned the assertion
of diplomatic independence of Judge Akay, and the Government of Tur-
key’s non-compliance with the Mechanism’s order to cease all legal pro-
ceedings against Akay and to release him from detention. 149 In his personal
capacity, Meron has stressed the impact of Akay’s detention on the princi-
ple of the rule of law, affirming that “all of us who care about justice and
145
Ibid.
146
Letter from the President of the International Residual Mechanism for Criminal Tribunals,
T. Meron, Regarding the Detention of Turkish Judge Aydin Sefa Akay to the UN Security
Council, 2016, see above note 16.
147
MICT, “Address to the UN Security Council”, 8 December 2016 (available on the MICT’s
web site).
148
Assessment and Progress Report of the President of the International Residual Mechanism
for Criminal Tribunals, Judge Theodor Meron, for the Period from 16 May to 15 November
2016, 2016, see above note 112; Assessment and Progress Report of the President of the In-
ternational Residual Mechanism for Criminal Tribunals, Judge Theodor Meron, for the Peri-
od from 6 November 2016 to 15 May 2017, 2017, see above note 113.
149
UN General Assembly, UN Security Council, Fifth Annual Report of the International Re-
sidual Mechanism for Criminal Tribunals, UN Doc. A/72/621, UN Doc. S/2017/661, 1 Au-
gust 2017, para. 26.
are committed to the rule of law must do our utmost to defend this funda-
mental principle [judicial independence]”. 150
During the course of the 17 January 2017 Ngirabatware hearing, as
already mentioned above, the solutions suggested by the Prosecution cen-
tred around replacing Judge Akay on the bench while preserving his as-
signment as a judge of the Mechanism in order to maintain his diplomatic
immunity. Judge Meron, however, intervened to keep the focus on the im-
plications on due process and judicial independence. He pointed out that a
judge of the Mechanism should always be consulted before assigning him
to a panel, and that the consent of a judge must be sought when the Presi-
dent makes such administrative deliberations. Ultimately, Judge Meron
conveyed that the replacement of Judge Akay would have weighed heavily
on judicial independence, and recalled that he had deemed such replace-
ment inappropriate in his communications to the UNSC and the UNGA. 151
Following the hearing, Meron ordered the Government of Turkey to
release Judge Akay. 152 The Order was adopted after the President’s invita-
tions to Turkey to spontaneously release Akay were ignored. At the same
time, Judge Meron denied the Motion to initiate contempt proceedings on
the grounds that it fell outside of the mandate and the powers of the Mech-
anism, which had already taken appropriate steps reporting the issue to the
UNSC. 153
It has already been mentioned that, notwithstanding the efforts of
Judge Meron, Judge Akay was not reappointed to the Mechanism. In his
final appearance before the UNSC as the MICT President, Meron ex-
pressed “profound regret that a different and better resolution for the situa-
tion of my former colleague, Judge Aydin Sefa Akay, was not found”. 154 In
his last speech as President of the Mechanism, he furthermore argued that
at a time when the world is facing deeply troubling trends re-
lated to the undermining of independent judiciaries and the
weakening of the rule of law, we at the United Nations simply
cannot afford to be anything less than exemplary when it
150
Theodor Meron, “The Future of International Criminal Justice”, Remarks at the Embassy of
the Republic of Poland in The Hague on the Occasion of the Awarding of the Officer’s
Cross of the Order of Merit, 16 May 2017, p. 4 (available on the MICT’s web site).
151
MICT, Ngirabatware, Transcript of Hearing, p. 29, see above note 9.
152
MICT, Ngirabatware, Order for Release, see above note 15.
153
MICT, Ngirabatware, Decision on a Motion to Initiate Contempt Proceedings, 26 April
2017, see above note 9 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/838408/).
154
MICT, “Statement, Address to the UN Security Council”, p. 3, see above note 18.
was Meron’s duty to refuse any such replacement; had he replaced Judge
Akay, the resulting bench would have been indirectly determined by the
illegitimate influence of the Government of Turkey on the MICT’s inner
workings. Consequently, Ngirabatware’s right to a fair trial by an inde-
pendent judiciary would have been compressed for the sake of convenience
and, perhaps, expeditiousness. Conflictingly, Judge Meron’s duties man-
dated him to care most about the rights of the accused, while President
Meron had a duty to act in a manner which would ensure the proper func-
tioning of the Mechanism.
As described above, the initiatives of Judge Meron were met by si-
lence on the part of the UN institutions. Meron was joined in his effort by
the Defence Counsel, while the MICT Prosecutor elected to prioritize the
expeditiousness of the Ngirabatware proceedings over judicial independ-
ence. Notwithstanding the adversities, Meron consistently upheld the obli-
gations pertinent to his roles as President and Judge, without letting other
considerations – such as political convenience – influence his actions. His
behaviour is exemplary of individual integrity; displaying adherence to the
values protected by the applicable norms of conduct while remaining with-
in the boundaries set by his roles.
24.3. Institutional, Professional and Personal Integrity:
One and the Same?
Provisions such as Article 9 MICT Statute, titled “Qualification of Judg-
es”, 161 can be found in several instruments establishing internationalized
criminal courts or tribunals. 162 Article 9 MICT Statute requires judges,
among others, to be of “high moral character” and to “possess the qualifi-
cations required in their respective countries for appointment to the highest
judicial offices”. As noted by Bergsmo, the term integrity is – in interna-
tional criminal law – a legal requirement laid down in provisions such as
Article 9 MICT Statute. 163
161
MICT Statute, Article 9, see above note 32.
162
See, for example, Statute of the International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia,
25 May 1993, Article 13 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/b4f63b/); Statute of the Interna-
tional Criminal Tribunal for Rwanda, 8 November 1994, Article 12 (http://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/8732d6/); Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court, 17 July 1998, Ar-
ticle 36 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/7b9af9/).
163
Bergsmo, 2018, p. 3, see above note 1.
Dag Hammarskjöld equates integrity with “respect for law and re-
spect for truth” and with “conscience”. 164 Jacques Lemoine brings “the
moral qualities of dedication, fairness and impartiality” under the concept
of integrity. 165 These notions subsume something wider than what is de-
manded by a narrow interpretation of Article 9 MICT Statute. Some of the
actors in the Akay saga, such as the UNSG and the UN Legal Counsel,
clearly operated within the borders of the law. They followed Article 9
MICT Statute to the letter: Akay indeed forewent the “qualifications re-
quired in [his] respective countr[y] for appointment to the highest judicial
offices”; indeed, he was charged with and convicted for a grave crime.
Logically, following the Statute, he could not be reappointed as a
judge on the roster of the Mechanism. It appears, however, that Akay’s
conviction amounted to undue influence on judicial independence. It also
seems that the response of certain individuals to this issue did not ade-
quately defend this fundamental principle of international justice, resulting
in the non-reappointment of the judge, which can be deemed problematic
from a rule of law perspective.
Those who followed only the letter of Article 9 MICT Statute per-
haps lost sight of other, underlying yet fundamental values of the integrity
standard. They showed neither loyalty nor dedication to a principal actor of
international justice or to the fundamental virtues of truth and transparency.
Others, namely Defence Counsel Peter Robinson and Judge Theodor Mer-
on, can serve as examples acting in line with the integrity standard. It has
to be noted that they were allowed to do so in the roles they were accorded.
Meron, as President of the Mechanism, had to ensure that his chamber
functioned, which is not possible when one of its judges is detained. Rob-
inson had his own interests, as counsel, in fighting for Akay, in whose ab-
sence the procedure pertaining to his client could not proceed.
Nevertheless, both Robinson and Meron seem to have gone beyond
their professional obligations. Robinson explored all possible avenues to
bring the Akay matter to the surface and to the attention of those who could
have made a difference. Similarly to Meron, he attempted to affect Akay’s
situation, or at least make it known to the public. In the end, it is rather dis-
appointing that both were blocked by institutionalism, confidentiality and
an extensive reach of State sovereignty. Nevertheless, although of not much
164
Hammarskjöld, 1962, p. 348, see above note 2 (emphasis added).
165
Jacques Lemoine, The International Civil Servant: An Endangered Species, Martinus
Nijhoff Publishers, The Hague, 1995, p. 257 (emphasis added).
use to Akay, who remains behind bars, their conduct shows that it is possi-
ble to intertwine integrity – understood broadly – and professional obliga-
tions resulting from their specific roles.
The Akay saga has put the integrity of concerned individuals to the
test. While the Government of Turkey was pursuing its national interests,
the UN institutions and international civil servants involved did not pose
the needed resistance. The efforts of the parties which upheld the integrity
standard could not steer the outcome: nevertheless, they represent a mean-
ingful expression of the behaviour to be expected from individuals in such
roles and, as the authors of this chapter hope, provide a lasting example for
the future.
Finally, it must be noted that achieving or acting with integrity is not
a one-time test, and it demands much more than meeting the normative re-
quirements at the moment of appointment to a judicial institution. It is an
ongoing struggle for all international civil servants and high officials in
international justice. This is eloquently described by the concept of self-
oblivion, as expressed by Dag Hammarskjöld – the constant exercise of
force of will, and the careful balancing of one’s personal interests and val-
ues, on the one hand, with the values one has chosen to embrace, profes-
sionally, on the other hand: with a readiness to ‘surrender’ to the latter. The
resulting actions would likely protect the spirit of the law and its founding
principles, in addition to its letter and the obligations that are spelt out:
“[y]ou will find that the freedom of the continual farewell, the hourly self-
surrender, gives to your experience of reality the purity and clarity which
signify–self-realization”. 166
166
Dag Hammarskjöld, Markings, Faber and Faber, London, 1964, p. 77.
*
Professor Mohamed Badar holds the Chair in Comparative and International Criminal Law
at Northumbria Law School, Northumbria University, Newcastle. He has published exten-
sively on issues related to comparative and international criminal law, and his work has been
cited by international and national criminal courts. He previously served as Senior Prosecu-
tor and Judge in Egypt (1997-2006). Dr. Polona Florijančič is an independent researcher
who has taught and published in the fields of international criminal law and human rights
law among other fields. She has also conducted field research for the EUROMED justice
project on criminal co-operation and counter-terrorism in the MENA region (2017-2019).
She obtained her Ph.D. in International Trade Law and Development and an LL.M. in Inter-
national Human Rights from Brunel University (London), and an LL.B. from the European
Faculty of Law, Slovenia.
1
The International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia (‘ICTY’) Judge Frederik
Harhoff’s email, 6 June 2013 annexed to ICTY, Prosecutor v. Stanišić and Župljanin, Ap-
peals Chamber, Prosecution Response to Rule 115 Motion on behalf of Mićo Stanišić seek-
ing admission of additional evidence, 9 July 2013, IT-08-91-A (https://www.legal-tools.org/
doc/956cc2/).
2
Ibid.
3
Statute of the ICTY, 25 May 1993, Article 20 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/b4f63b).
4
ICTY, Rules of Procedure and Evidence, UN Doc. IT/32/Rev.50, 8 July 2015, adopted pur-
suant to Article 15 of the Statute of the Tribunal, incorporates amendments from 1994 to
November 2015, Rule 15(A) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/30df50/).
5
ICTY, Prosecutor v. Furundžija, Appeals Chamber, Judgement, 21 July 2000, IT-95-17/1-A,
paras. 189–190 (‘Furundžija Appeal Judgment’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/660d3f/).
6
ICTY, Prosecutor v. Šešelj, Trial Chamber, Professor Vojislav Šešelj’s Motion for Disquali-
fication of Judge Frederik Harhoff, 9 July 2013, IT-03-67-T (https://www.legal-tools.org/
doc/a7ccdc).
7
It should be mentioned that Judges Moloto and Hall had sat on other cases with Judge Har-
hoff.
8
ICTY, Prosecutor v. Šešelj, Chamber Convened by Order of the Vice-President, Decision on
Defence Motion for Disqualification of Judge Frederik Harhoff and Report to the Vice-
President, 28 August 2013, IT-03-67-T (‘Disqualification Decision’) (https://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/5b4aa1).
provide for a case where a motion for disqualification can be made during
deliberations”. 9
With regards to the Letter, in paragraph 13 of the Decision, the Ma-
jority stated:
By referring to a ‘set practice’ of convicting accused persons
without reference to an evaluation of the evidence in each in-
dividual case […] there are grounds for concluding that a rea-
sonable observer, properly informed, would reasonably appre-
hend bias on the part of Judge Harhoff in favour of conviction
[…]. This appearance of bias is further compounded by Judge
Harhoff’s statement that he is confronted by a professional
and moral dilemma which […] is a clear reference to his diffi-
culty in applying the current jurisprudence of the Tribunal.
In this statement, as well as in the whole Decision, the Majority’s
reasoning disregarded entirely a memorandum sent by Judge Harhoff to
Judge Antonetti, the Presiding Judge in the Šešelj case, as well as the lat-
ter’s report. 10 In the memorandum, Judge Harhoff explicitly clarified the
context and meaning of various parts of the Letter. He explained that it
should have been read in conjunction with the two news articles that he had
previously shared with the same recipients and which gave the necessary
background for understanding the concerns expressed in the Letter. 11 For
example, an article in The Economist noted that the judgments in Perišić
9
ICTY, Prosecutor v. Šešelj, President of the Chamber, Decision to Unseal the Report of the
Presiding Judge to the President of the Tribunal or Alternatively the Judge Designated by
him Regarding the Motion for Disqualification of Judge Harhoff, 4 September 2013, IT-03-
67-T, p. 3 (‘Decision to Unseal the Report’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/e91251).
10
According to Rule 15(B), the Presiding Judge of the Chamber has to confer with the judge
against whom bias is alleged before sending a report to the President of the Tribunal. After
the panel issued the decision to disqualify Judge Harhoff, Judges Antonetti and Lattanzi sent
a joint request for clarification to the panel and the Vice-President drawing their attention to
the fact that neither the report of the Presiding Judge nor the written comments of the Judge
in question had been mentioned in the decision. On the same day, Judge Harhoff also sent a
request that the panel of judges consider the two documents. The ICTY Prosecutor, Serge
Brammertz, sent a motion for review of the decision. Ibid., p. 1.
11
ICTY, Internal Memorandum from Judge Frederik Harhoff to Judge Jean-Claude Antonetti,
Motion for Disqualification of Judge Frederik Harhoff filed by the Accused Vojislav
Šešelj/Report, 8 July 2013, annexed to Prosecutor v. Šešelj, President of the Chamber, Deci-
sion to unseal the report of the Presiding Judge to the President of the Tribunal or alterna-
tively the Judge designated by him regarding the motion for disqualification of Judge Har-
hoff, 4 September 2013, IT-03-67-T (‘Harhoff, Memorandum’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/
doc/e91251/).
and Stanišić and Simatović meant it was now more difficult to convict sen-
ior officials, 12 while an article in the New York Times noted that Stanišić
and Simatović had raised the standard of proof for joint criminal enterprise
(‘JCE’) convictions, and that this was part of a trend in recent jurispru-
dence at the Tribunal that could be viewed as protecting the interests of
more powerful countries. 13 It was these sentiments that Judge Harhoff
sought to echo in his Letter, by noting that this change of practice would
henceforth probably make it very hard to convict any of the superior mili-
tary commanders; he considered the new requirements introduced would be
very difficult to prove, for example, the specific direction requirement for
aiding and abetting (see Section 25.2.1.). 14
Furthermore, Judge Harhoff asserted that the Letter was never in-
tended as a legal intervention, 15 but rather as an informal private communi-
cation and was for that reason “not very clear on the distinction between
JCE, aiding and abetting and command responsibility”. 16 He considered
that it went “without saying that no one can be convicted of a crime unless
the evidence convincingly supports a finding of guilt”, but he did not high-
light this because it was not the gist of the Letter. 17 Rather his concern was
with the Appeals Chamber’s acquittals, which, in his understanding, pre-
sented a departure from the Tribunal’s practice and made it impossible to
convict generals in the future. 18
In his own words, in terms of JCE, he considered the new practice to
require “more than just the degree of intent associated with knowledge, i.e.
that the supreme commanders could only be convicted in the future if a
stronger degree of intent could be proven at trial”. 19
Finally, Judge Harhoff also clarified that the ‘moral and professional
dilemma’ he referred to at the end of the Letter was directed at the potential
12
“Two puzzling judgments in the Hague: The International Criminal Tribunal for the Former
Yugoslavia Lost Credibility”, The Economist, 1 June 2013 (available on its web site).
13
Eric Gordy, “What Happened to the Hague Tribunal?”, The New York Times, 2 June 2013
(available on its web site).
14
See, for example, the specific direction by the accomplice, Harhoff, Memorandum, p. 3, see
above note 11.
15
Ibid., p. 2.
16
Ibid.
17
Ibid., pp. 2–3.
18
Ibid., p. 1.
19
Ibid., p. 3.
20
Ibid.
21
Ibid.
22
Ibid., p. 1.
23
Ibid.
24
“Antonetti: Don’t let Harhoff be ‘doubly victimized’’, Sense Agency, 4 September 2013
(available on its web site).
25
Disqualification Decision, para. 12, see above note 8, referring to ICTY, Prosecutor v. Šešelj,
Third Amended Indictment, 7 December 2007, IT-03-67-T, paras. 8, 10 (https://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/f427f1/).
26
ICTY, Prosecutor v. Šešelj, Transcript, 19 February 2009, IT-03-67-T, T. 3815 (Testimony of
prosecution expert witness Theunens); ICTY, Prosecutor v. Šešelj, Trial Chamber, Prosecu-
tion’s Closing Brief, 5 February 2012, IT-03-67-T, para. 593 (https://www.legal-tools.org/
doc/61hng5/).
27
ICTY, Prosecutor v. Šešelj, Transcript, 4 May 2011, IT-03-67-T, T. 16827 (Rule 98bis pro-
ceedings).
28
Decision to Unseal the Report, p. 2, see above note 9.
29
Disqualification Decision, para. 3, see above note 8; ICTY, Prosecutor v. Šešelj, Prosecu-
tion’s Response to Motion for Disqualification of Judge Frederick Harhoff, 17 July 2013, IT-
03-67-T, para. 5 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/afc254/).
30
Disqualification Decision, para. 12, see above note 8.
31
Ibid., para. 13.
32
Ibid., para. 9.
33
Martin Burcharth, “The email that went around the world”, Information, 7 December 2013
(available on its web site).
gal Officer at the ICTY where he was later appointed judge. Furthermore,
he has worked as an Associate Professor at the University of Copenhagen
and Professor of International Law at the University of Southern Den-
mark. 34 He sat as a judge in four Trial Chambers at the ICTY, and an evalu-
ation of this work by the Special Chamber would have further been im-
portant in terms of countering Šešelj’s submission that there was a specific
anti-Serb bias present on the part of Judge Harhoff. He, in fact, took part in
convicting the Bosnian Serb general Dragomir Milošević and the Bosnian
Serb interior minister and the security chief in Banja Luka, but he also took
part in convicting the Bosnian Muslim general Rasim Delić for war crimes
committed by mujahideen warriors. Furthermore, the two Appeals Cham-
ber judgments which Judge Harhoff criticized in the Letter concern both
Croats and Serbs. 35 He does refer as an example only to the “ethnic cleans-
ing of non-Serbs as part of the common purpose” of the JCE as alleged in
many indictments, but as he explains in his memorandum, this does not
imply that he holds JCE-expulsions of other ethnicities only as a matter for
the Serbs. 36
Writing his dissenting opinion to the Decision on the disqualification,
Judge LIU, expressed his concern with what he called “the cursory ap-
proach taken by the Majority” and its failure to properly contextualize the
statements or take into account the highly informal nature of the Letter. 37
Most importantly, LIU stated that he was not convinced that Judge Har-
hoff’s failure to refer to “an evaluation of the evidence in each individual
case” 38 creates the appearance that he is reluctant to apply the Tribunal’s
law and rules of procedure and evidence or that he is in favour of convic-
tion of accused before the Tribunal. 39 He also disagreed with the Majority’s
conclusion that the reference to ‘a professional and moral dilemma’ reflect-
ed a difficulty on Judge Harhoff’s part to apply the current jurisprudence of
the Tribunal. 40
The defence of the former Bosnia and Herzegovina (‘BiH’) Army
Main Staff commander, Rasim Delić, also called for a review of his judge-
34
Ibid.
35
Harhoff, Memorandum, p. 1, see above note 11.
36
Ibid.
37
Disqualification Decision, Dissenting Opinion of Judge Liu, paras. 6–7, see above note 8.
38
Ibid., para. 13.
39
Ibid., para. 7.
40
Ibid.
ment on the basis of Judge Harhoff’s alleged ‘bias’. However, the Appeals
Chamber dismissed the motion for review since Delić had already passed
away at the time and neither his next-of-kin nor Counsel had locus standi
in judicio. 41 The saga, nonetheless, received a more interesting update in
2016 with the appeal in the Stanišić and Župljanin case. 42 Perhaps unsur-
prisingly, the appellants seized the opportunity and claimed that the dis-
qualification of Judge Harhoff from the Šešelj proceedings, although not
legally binding, must lead to the same result in the proceedings against
them. 43 They submitted that they were specifically included in the category
of persons likely to be convicted as a result of Judge Harhoff’s predisposi-
tion, 44 and repeated the finding of the Majority in the Special Chamber that
his views demonstrated a belief in convicting accused persons under JCE
liability without proving the requisite legal elements. 45
One could hardly argue with their logic that if there had been a bias
in terms of sitting as a judge on the Šešelj trial, it would equally have exist-
41
ICTY, Prosecutor v. Delić, Appeals Chamber, Decision on Defence Motion for Review, 17
December 2013, IT-04-83-R.1, p. 2 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/d61bd1/).
42
ICTY, Prosecutor v. Stanišić and Župljanin, Appeals Chamber, Judgement, 30 June 2016,
IT-08-91-A (‘Stanišić and Župljanin Appeal Judgement’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/
e414f6/).
43
ICTY, Prosecutor v. Stanišić and Župljanin, Appeals Chamber, Additional Appellant’s brief
on behalf of Mićo Stanišić, 26 June 2014, IT-08-91-A, paras. 33–52 (‘Stanišić Additional
Appeal Brief’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/509154/); ICTY, Prosecutor v. Stanišić and
Župljanin, Stojan Župljanin Supplement to Appeal Brief (Ground Six), 26 June 2014, IT-08-
91-A, paras. 4–13, 28-29 (‘Župljanin Additional Appeal Brief’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/
doc/e6a556/); ICTY, Prosecutor v. Stanišić and Župljanin, Additional brief in reply on be-
half of Mićo Stanišić, 25 July 2014, IT-08-91-A, paras. 28–30 (‘Stanišić Additional Reply
Brief’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/48470a/). The Prosecution argued, amongst other
things, that the unanimous Trial Judgment in Stanišić and Župljanin shows that the Special
Chamber’s majority interpretation of the Letter was incorrect and that Harhoff’s Memoran-
dum was erroneously considered to be immaterial. See ICTY, Prosecutor v. Stanišić and
Župljanin, Appeal Hearing, 16 December 2015, AT. 133-134 (‘Appeal Hearing’); The Prose-
cution also argued that a conclusion contrary to the Disqualification Decision in Prosecutor
v. Šešelj would be consistent with prior instances where different chambers reached different
conclusions based on different arguments and evidence. ICTY, Prosecutor v. Stanišić and
Župljanin, Prosecution Consolidated Supplemental Response Brief, 18 July 2014, IT-08-91-
A, para. 31 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/6301a0/).
44
Appeal Hearing, AT. 79, 84, 152, see above note 43.
45
Stanišić Additional Appeal Brief, paras. 65–71, 73, 78-9 (referring to Letter pp. 3–4), see
above note 43; Župljanin Additional Appeal Brief, paras. 4, 10-13, see above note 43. See
Appeal Hearing, 16 December 2015, AT. 149-154, see above note 43; Stanišić Additional
Reply Brief, paras. 12, 34-35, see above note 43.
ed in their case, yet the Appeals Chamber found the opposite. Regarding
both the ‘deep professional and moral dilemma’ expressed in the Letter as
well as the ‘set practice’ 46 described therein, the Appeals Chamber accept-
ed the explanations from Judge Harhoff’s memorandum 47 and, taking into
account the whole Letter, it was not convinced that it would lead a reason-
able observer properly informed to conclude that Judge Harhoff was pre-
disposed to convicting the accused persons. 48 Thus, the Appeals Chamber
reached drastically different conclusions from the Special Chamber, yet it
seems that the only difference between the Šešelj and the Stanišić and
Župljanin cases was that the former was still ongoing at the time, while the
Trial Judgment in the latter had already been issued at the date of the publi-
cation of the Letter. 49 A rather superficial difference and hardly one which
could explain why the same judge, holding the same convictions, would be
biased in one and not the other, particularly since bias was alleged on the
basis of a predisposition against the faithful application of the law. 50
While strongly criticizing Judge Harhoff’s views on the law as ex-
pressed in the Letter and stating that they do not align with the jurispru-
dence of the Tribunal, 51 the Appeals Chamber recalled that personal con-
victions and opinions of ICC Judges are not in themselves a basis for infer-
ring a lack of impartiality. 52 Furthermore, it stated that the Trial Chamber
had applied the correct legal standard for JCE liability 53 to the circum-
stances of the case in question and not the views expressed in the Letter. 54
46
Letter, p. 1, see above note 1.
47
Stanišić and Župljanin Appeal Judgement, para. 56, see above note 42; Harhoff, Memoran-
dum, p. 3, see above note 11.
48
Ibid., para. 56.
49
Ibid., para. 54.
50
Ibid., para. 37, fns. 148, 149.
51
Ibid., para. 52.
52
ICTY, Prosecutor v. Delalić et al., Appeals Chamber, Judgement, 20 February 2001, IT-96-
21-A, para. 699 (‘Čelebići Appeal Judgement’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/051554/),
referring to Prosecutor v. Anto Furundžija, Appeals Chamber, Judgement, para. 203 (‘Fu-
rundžija Appeal Judgement’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/660d3f/). See also Scottish
High Court of Justiciary, Hoekstra v. HM Advocate, Judgment, 2000; New South Wales
Court of Appeal, Newcastle City Council v. Lindsay, Judgment, 2004, paras. 35–36.
53
ICTY, Prosecutor v. Stanišić and Župljanin, Trial Chamber, Judgement, vol. 1, 27 March
2013, IT-08-91-T, paras. 99–106 (‘Stanišić and Župljanin, Trial Judgement’) (https://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/2ed57f/).
54
The following paragraphs from Stanišić and Župljanin Appeal Judgement are significant in
this regard, paras. 51–53, see above note 42:
The Appeals Chamber particularly notes that a reasonable observer properly informed
would be aware that: (i) Judge Harhoff’s comments only generally concern the mode of
liability of joint criminal enterprise; (ii) none of the cases referred to by Judge Harhoff
altered the scope of joint criminal enterprise liability, contrary to his assertions; and (iii)
it has never been the law or practice, contrary to Judge Harhoff’s statement, to “convict
leaders for the crimes committed with their knowledge within a framework of a common
goal”. Further, it is the Appeals Chamber’s view that a reasonable observer properly in-
formed of all relevant circumstances would be aware of the relevant jurisprudence of the
Tribunal. A reasonable observer would therefore be aware that knowledge on the part of
an accused that crimes were committed is insufficient to find an accused responsible un-
der either the first or the third category of joint criminal enterprise.
The Appeals Chamber notes that a reasonable observer would also consider the fact
that Judge Harhoff neither distinguished the facts nor the respective modes of liability
relevant to the Gotovina and Markač Appeal Judgement, the Perišić Appeal Judgement,
and the Stanišić and Simatović Trial Judgement. Based on his views on the law and prac-
tice, which do not align with the Tribunal’s jurisprudence, coupled with his sweeping
generalisations of the judgements in question, Judge Harhoff expressed deep dissatisfac-
tion with what he considered a change in “set practice” at the Tribunal. However, the
Appeals Chamber recalls that personal convictions and opinions of Judges are not in
themselves a basis for inferring a lack of impartiality. Additionally, a reasonable observ-
er, properly informed, would take into account that at no time did Judge Harhoff direct
his comments to Stanišić and Župljanin. Thus, the Appeals Chamber is not convinced by
Stanišić’s submission that Judge Harhoff was predisposed to convicting Stanišić and
Župljanin.
Regarding Župljanin’s argument that sections of the Trial Judgement indicate that
the wrong mens rea standard was applied, the Appeals Chamber is not convinced that a
reasonable observer would consider that these cited sections reflect, or were influenced,
by the same opinions that Judge Harhoff expressed in the Letter. In this regard, the Ap-
peals Chamber notes that the Trial Chamber applied the correct legal standard for JCE
liability to the circumstances of the case and not the views expressed in the Letter. Fur-
ther, a reasonable observer would also take into account Judge Harhoff’s statement that
he did not set out in the Letter all of the applicable principles necessary to assess crimi-
nal liability, including proof beyond a reasonable doubt.
55
Ibid., para. 55, referring to ICTY, Prosecutor v. Šainović et al., Appeals Chamber, Judge-
ment, 23 January 2014, IT-05-87-A, para. 181 (‘Šainović et al., Appeal Judgement’) (https://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/81ac8c/); Furundžija Appeal Judgement, paras. 196–197, see
above note 52.
ing war, not a criminal organization – and its general war effort, not specif-
ic crimes, the specific direction requirement was not considered to have
been met. 59
Similarly, the Stanišić and Simatović Trial Judgment affirmed that
crimes had been committed and detailed the connections between the ac-
cused parties and the physical perpetrators. It further affirmed the existence
of a JCE to create ethnically homogeneous populations and concrete con-
tributions to the realization of this enterprise. Despite this, it held that in
order to establish guilt, evidence would have to prove that the support pro-
vided to the physical perpetrators was ‘specifically directed towards the
commission of the crimes’ that is “specifically directed to assist, encourage,
or lend moral support to the perpetration of [the] crime”. 60
Judge Harhoff saw the specific direction requirement as a dangerous
departure from previous jurisprudence, whereas both panels considering his
bias claimed that there was no such departure. Other commentators at the
time also considered the specific direction as established jurisprudence
based on the fact that in Vasiljević, as well as in Jokić, the Tribunal deter-
mined liability for aiding and abetting on a finding that there was a specific
direction to assist the perpetration of the crimes. Thus, it has been argued
that the Tribunal in Perišić, as well as in Stanišić and Simatović, did not
depart from previous standards but that, instead, the peculiar circumstances
of these cases directed a different outcome (that is, the fact that the accused
were officials in one country while the armed conflict was unfolding and
crimes were committed in another). However, to say this is to mask the fact
that the jurisprudence on specific direction was far from ‘established’ up
until that point and, if anything, there were more reasons to find, as Judge
Harhoff did, a departure from previous jurisprudence than its application.
The ‘specific direction’ requirement in aiding and abetting was, in
fact, part of the jurisprudence at the Tribunal since Tadić, that is, since the
introduction of the concept of JCE. 61 However, Tadić did not cite any prior
59
Ibid., para. 53.
60
ICTY, Prosecutor v. Stanišić and Simatović, Trial Chamber, Judgement, vol. 2, 30 May 2013,
IT-03-69-T, para. 1264 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/698c43/).
61
ICTY, Prosecutor v Tadić, Appeals Chamber, Judgement, 15 July 1999, IT-94-1-A, pa-
ra. 229(iii) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/8efc3a/):
(iii) The aider and abettor carries out acts specifically directed to assist encourage or
lend moral support to the perpetration of a certain specific crime (murder, extermination,
rape, torture, wanton destruction of civilian property, etc.) and this support has a sub-
stantial effect upon the perpetration of the crime. By contrast, in the case of acting in
pursuance of a common purpose or design, it is sufficient for the participant to perform
acts that in some way are directed to the furthering of the common plan or purpose.
62
Perišić, Appeal Judgement, Opinion Séparée du Juge Ramaroson sur la Question de la Visée
Spécifique dans la Complicité par Aide et Encouragement, paras. 2–4, see above note 57. In
the same vein, the Šainović et al., Appeal Judgement ultimately concluded that the Tadić
discussion was not aimed at systematically defining aiding and abetting liability (as was
done in Furundžija), but was instead included in order to better defining joint criminal en-
terprise, see para. 1623, see above note 55. See also ICTY, Prosecutor v. Aleksovski, Appeals
Chamber, Judgement, 24 March 2000, IT-95-14/1-A, para. 163 (https://www.legal-tools.org/
doc/176f05/), see also ICTY, Prosecutor v. Blagojević and Jokić, Appeals Chamber, Judge-
ment, 9 May 2007, IT-02-60-A (‘Blagojević and Jokić, Appeal Judgement’)
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/c32768/), which similarly noted that Tadić Appeal only
sought to contrast JCE with aiding and abetting and was not a complete statement on the law
of aiding and abetting.
63
Perišić, Appeal Judgement, Joint Separate Opinion of Judges Theodor Meron and Carmel
Agius, para. 3, see above note 57; Norman Farrell, “Attributing Criminal Liability to Corpo-
rate Actors: Some Lessons from the International Tribunals”, in Journal of International
Criminal Justice, 2010, vol. 8, no. 3, p. 890: “such a requirement is not part of either the ac-
tus reus or mens rea of aiding and abetting”.
64
Perišić, Appeal Judgement, Opinion Séparée du Juge Ramaroson, paras. 7–8, see above note
57; Perišić, Appeal Judgement, para. 39:
not all cases of aiding and abetting will involve proximity of an accused individual’s rel-
evant acts to crimes committed by principal perpetrators. Where an accused aider and
abettor is remote from relevant crimes, evidence proving other elements of aiding and
abetting may not be sufficient to prove specific direction. In such circumstances, the
Appeals Chamber, Judge Liu dissenting, holds that explicit consideration of specific di-
rection is required.
65
Ibid., Partially Dissenting Opinion of Judge Liu, para. 3.
66
Dhruv Sharma, “Specific Direction: An Unspecific Threshold”, in Groningen Journal of
International Law, 2019, vol. 6, no. 2, p. 320; Antonio Coco and Tom Gal, “Losing Direc-
tion: The ICTY Appeals Chamber’s Controversial Approach to Aiding and Abetting in
Perišić”, in Journal of International Criminal Justice 12, 2014, vol. 12, no. 2, p. 358.
67
ICTY, Prosecutor v. Furundžija, Trial Chamber, Judgement, 10 December 1998, IT-95-17/1-
T, paras.193-226 (actus reus) and 236-241 (mens rea) (‘Furundžija Trial Judgement’)
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/e6081b/) endorsed, inter alia, by ICTY, Prosecutor v.
Blaškić, Appeals Chamber, Judgement, 29 July 2004, IT-95-14-A, para. 46 (https://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/88d8e6/).
68
Furundžija Trial Judgement, para. 235, see above note 67; see also Special Court for Sierra
Leone, Prosecutor v Taylor, Appeals Chamber, Judgment, 26 September 2013, SCSL-03-01-
A, para. 368 (‘Taylor Appeal Judgement’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/3e7be5/). For an
sistance which increased the likelihood that the crime would be perpetrated
or that it could be perpetrated in a certain manner. 69 As for the mens rea,
the aider and abettor must have knowledge that the assistance will substan-
tially contribute to the commission of the crime. 70 This standard does not
imply certainty but rather the knowing acceptance of a risk that, in the or-
dinary course of events, the behaviour will substantially contribute to the
crime. 71 Unlike a member of a JCE, an aider and abettor does not need to
share the principal perpetrator’s criminal intent.
Blagojević and Jokić Appeal Judgment was the first appellate judg-
ment to deal directly with this matter. It noted that the Blaškić Appeals
Judgment’s confusing approach cited both the Vasiljević Appeal Judgment
as well as the Furundžija Trial Judgment, which had conflicting positions
on the matter. 72 The Judgment held that, while the Tadić Appeal Judgment
had never been explicitly departed from, other appeals judgments had not
included a specific direction requirement. This could be explained by “the
fact that such a finding will often be implicit in the finding that the accused
has provided practical assistance to the principal perpetrator which had a
substantial effect on the commission of the crime”. 73 The Chamber thus
considered it as part of the actus reus. In so finding, the Blagojević and
overview, see Antonio Cassese, Paola Gaeta et al., Cassese’s International Criminal Law,
3rd edn., Oxford University Press, 2013, at pp. 193 et seq.
69
ICTY, Prosecutor v. Tadić, Trial Chamber, Opinion and Judgement, 7 May 1997, IT-94-1-T,
para. 688 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/0a90ae/). This standard is usually deemed to be
higher than the ‘significant’ contribution demanded for a JCE. See Judgment, ICTY, Prose-
cutor v. Kvočka et al., Appeals Chamber, Judgement 28 February 2005, IT-98-30/1, para. 97
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/006011/), and ICTY, Prosecutor v. Gotovina et al., Appeals
Chamber, Judgement, 16 November 2012, IT-06-90, para. 149 (‘Gotovina Appeal Judge-
ment’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/03b685/).
70
ICTY, Prosecutor v. Mrkšić et al., Appeals Chamber, Judgement, 5 May 2009, IT-95-13-1-A,
para. 49 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/40bc41/). See also ICTY, Prosecutor v. Orić, Ap-
peals Chamber, Judgement, 3 July 2008, IT-03-68-A, para. 43 (https://www.legal-tools.org/
doc/e053a4/).
71
SCSL, Prosecutor against Brima, Trial Chamber, Judgement, 20 June 2007, SCSL-04-16-T,
para. 776 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/87ef08/); Furundžija Trial Judgment, para. 246,
see above note 67; ICTY, Prosecutor v Blaškić, Trial Chamber, Judgement, 3 March 2000,
IT-95-14-T, para. 287 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/e1ae55/); ICTY, Prosecutor v. Orić,
Trial Chamber, Judgement, 30 June 2006, OT-03-68-T, para. 288 (https://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/37564c/). See also The Hague Court of Appeal, Judgment, Prosecutor v. van
Anraat, 9 May 2007, 2200050906-2, para. 11.16 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/1e1b4b/).
72
Blagojević and Jokić, Appeal Judgement, paras. 185–188, see above note 62.
73
Ibid., para. 189.
74
ICTY, Prosecutor v. Mrkšić and Šljivančanin, Appeals Chamber, Judgement, 5 May 2009,
IT-95-13-1-A, para. 159 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/40bc41/).
75
ICTY, Prosecutor v. Lukić and Lukić, Appeals Chamber, Judgement, 4 December 2912, IT-
98-32/1-A, paras. 159, 424 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/da785e/).
76
Ibid., Separate and Partially Dissenting Opinion of Judge Güney, paras. 10–11.
77
Ibid., Separate Opinion of Judge Agius, paras. 1–6.
78
Perišić, Appeal Judgement, paras. 32–36, see above note 57.
79
Ibid., para. 15.
evant. 80 However, neither Brđanin nor Krstić, for example, were present at
the place where crimes were being committed, for which they were found
responsible as aiders and abettors. 81 Coco and Gal thus find Brđanin’s con-
duct in many ways similar to Perišić’s. 82
In the context of the ICC, one commentator called the ‘specific direc-
tion’ requirement “counter-intuitive to the objectives of the ICC as it unrea-
sonably increases evidentiary requirements at the Court and consequently
makes the fight against impunity, an already challenging task, even more
difficult”. 83 The ICTY Office of the Prosecutor claimed that it had no foun-
dation in customary international law, was contrary to prior Appeals
Chamber jurisprudence, lacked coherence as a legal doctrine and most im-
portantly, undermined respect for international humanitarian law. 84
Finally, in the Šainović Appeal Judgement, delivered on 23 January
2014, the Perišić Appeal Judgement’s reasoning was unequivocally over-
turned and the ‘specific direction’ requirement was found to be in “direct
and material conflict with the prevailing jurisprudence […] and with cus-
tomary international law”. 85 The same conclusion was reached by the Ap-
peals Chamber of the SCSL in the Taylor Appeal Judgement. 86
The majority in the Šainović Appeal Judgment (Judge Tuzmukha-
medov dissenting 87) found the Perišić Appeals Chamber’s interpretation of
Mrkšić and Šljivančanin Appeal Judgement and the Lukić and Lukić Ap-
peal Judgement to be in effect at odds with the plain reading of the judg-
ments and to have disregarded positions expressly taken and clearly set out
80
Ibid., para. 38 and fn. 100.
81
Coco and Gal, 2014, pp. 356–357, see above note 66.
82
Ibid., p. 356.
83
Sharma, 2019, p. 320, see above note 66 .
84
ICTY, Office of the Prosecutor Statement of the ICTY Prosecutor, “Statement of the ICTY
Prosecutor Serge Brammertz”, 24 June 2013 (‘Statement of Serge Brammertz’).
85
Šainović et al., Appeal Judgement, para. 1650, see above note 55.
86
Taylor Appeal Judgement, paras. 471–486, see above note 68.
87
Šainović et al., Appeal Judgement, Dissenting opinion of Judge Tuzmukhamedov, paras. 40–
47, see above note 55, Judge Tuzmukhamedov declined to take a position on specific direc-
tion, arguing instead that it was not necessary to determine the issue on the facts of the case
because Lazarević, commander of the VJ’s Priština corps stationed in Kosovo, was not geo-
graphically remote from the crime scene. The Majority, in footnote 5320, explained that the
issue of specific direction was explicitly raised by the Parties and that it was a legal issue of
“general significance to the Tribunal’s jurisprudence”.
88
Šainović et al., Appeal Judgement, paras. 1621–1622, see above note 55.
89
Ibid., para. 1625.
90
Ibid., paras. 1627, 1648 (analysis of the cases) and paras. 1649–1650 (conclusion).
91
This is unsurprising, since the three votes in the majority were all judges who formed the
Šainović Appeals Chamber majority (Pocar, LIU, Ramaroson), while one of the judges was
in the Perišić Appeals Chamber majority (Agius).
92
ICTY, Statement of Prosecutor Serge Brammertz in relation to the motion for reconsidera-
tion submitted by the Prosecution in the Perišić case, 3 February 2014 (‘Statement of Prose-
cutor 2014’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/195e1f/).
93
Stanišić and Župljanin, Trial Judgement, para. 786, see above note 53.
94
Burcharth, 2013, see above note 33.
95
ICTY, Prosecutor v Gotovina et al., Trial Chamber, Judgement, 15 April 2011, IT-06-90-T,
paras. 2314–15 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/d0d665/).
96
Ibid., paras. 1756–58, 1843-46, 1970-2098, 2304-12.
97
Gotovina Appeal Judgment, paras. 91–96, see above note 69.
98
Ibid., para. 93, footnotes omitted.
99
Ibid., Dissenting Opinion of Judge Pocar, para. 26.
100
Ibid., para. 39.
101
Ibid., para. 30.
102
Steven Freeland, “Judicial Decision-Making in International Criminal Courts: “Effective”
Justice?”, in Griffith Journal of Law and Human Dignity, 2015, vol. 3, no. 1, p. 71.
103
Ibid.
104
Ibid.
105
John R.W.D. Jones et al., Milestones in International Criminal Justice: Recent Legal Con-
troversies at the UN Yugoslav Tribunal, Chatham House, London, 2013.
106
Ibid.
107
Marie Dhumieres, “Judge Thrown off Yugoslavia War Crimes Tribunal for Criticising
Change of Direction in Verdicts”, The Independent, 24 September 2013 (available on its web
site).
108
Harhoff, Memorandum, see above note 11.
109
Colleen Rohan and Gregor Guy-Smith, “Comment on Judge Harhoff’s Letter”, 19 June
2013, International Criminal Law Bureau.
110
Burcharth, 2013, see above note 33.
111
Ibid.
112
It has also been claimed elsewhere that several fellow judges endorsed Harhoff’s objections,
but preferred to remain anonymous, see Martin Burcharth, “Fellow Judges support ousted
colleague’s criticism of Hague Tribunal”, Information, 6 December 2013 (available on its
web site).
113
Ibid.
114
Stanišić and Župljanin, Trial Judgement, para. 786, see above note 53.
115
Simons, 2013, see above note 56.
116
Ibid.:
After the only session to deliberate the acquittal that Judge Meron had drafted in the
case of the two Croatian generals, one official said, the judge abruptly declined a request
by two dissenting judges for further debate […] In his letter, Judge Harhoff also said
Judge Michele Picard of France was recently given only four days to write her dissent
against the majority decision to acquit two Serbian police chiefs, Jovica Stanišić and
Franko Simatović. ‘She was very taken aback by the acquittal and deeply upset about
the fast way it had to be handled,’ said an official close to the case.
117
Theodor Meron, “Judicial Independence and Impartiality in International Criminal Tribu-
nals”, in The American Journal of International Law, 2005, vol. 99, no. 2, p. 361.
118
WikiLeaks, “ICTY: Ambassador Prosper’s Meetings with ICTY President and Registrar”, 7
November 2003.
119
Marko Milanović, “Danish Judge Blasts ICTY President”, EJIL: Talk!, 13 June 2013, com-
ments section (available on its web site).
120
Ibid.
121
ICTY, Prosecutor v. Perišić, Public Redacted Version of the Appeal Brief of Momčilo
Perišić, 10 April 2012, IT-04-81-A, paras. 20–21 (‘Perišić Appeal Brief’) (https://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/b20df0/).
122
Ibid., para. 25.
123
Ibid., paras. 27–28.
124
James G. Stewart, “The ICTY Loses its Way on Complicity – Part 2”, Opinio Juris, 3 April
2013 (available on its web site).
128
Jacques Lemoine, The International Civil Servant: An Endangered Species, Kluwer Law
International, 1995, p. 45, citing Dag Hammarskjöld, The International Civil Servant in Law
and in Fact, Oxford University Press, 1961.
129
Dhumieres, 2013, see above note 107.
130
Lemoine, 1995, p. 46, see above note 128.
ratives in Croatia and Serbia, of which the ‘victorious’ brand is even more
poisonous and harder to cure. 131 Similarly, Nakarada observed that with
this judgment, the Croatian government was proclaimed innocent, and the
victims were humiliated. 132 This and the subsequent dropping of the charg-
es against the Albanian leader of the Kosovo Liberation Army, Ramush Ha-
radinaj, made even those Serbs who were previously supportive of the IC-
TY as an institution of justice now believe that it was highly biased, that is
treating victims unequally depending on their ethnic origin. 133 In terms of
Perišić, who was the top figure within the Yugoslav Army, his conviction in
2011 was immensely significant for Bosniaks, 134 while Stanišić was the
first intelligence chief of a country to be judged by an international crimi-
nal tribunal. As Orentlicher noted, even if Judge Harhoff’s speculations
about external influence were just that – speculations – in the eyes of many
Bosnians “it was the proverbial smoking gun”. 135
Keil and Perry describe how the expectations from the Tribunal have
been exceptionally high in terms of fighting impunity:
However after the acquittals in the cases of Gotovina et al.,
Haradinaj et al. and Perišić as well as the Stanišić and Sima-
tović first instance verdicts, the standing of the Tribunal
among victims in BiH is likely to be less favourable, judging
by the reactions of victim associations and discussions in the
media. 136
Fifteen victims’ associations from BiH called for the resignation of
Meron, yet their call was simply ignored. According to media reports, after
five weeks of silence, the President of the Association of Mothers of the
131
Marko Milanović, “The Gotovina Omnishambles”, EJIL: Talk!, 18 November 2012 (availa-
ble on its web site).
132
Radmila Nakarada, “Acquittal of Gotovina and Markač: A Blow to the Serbian and Croatian
Reconciliation Process”, in Utrecht Journal of International and European Law, 2013, vol.
29, no. 76, pp. 102–105.
133
Ibid.
134
Anton Vukpalaj, “Acquittals at the International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia
(ICTY) in 2012-2013: the domestic implications”, in Studies of Transition States and Socie-
ties, vol. 10, no. 1, 2018, p. 8, citing D. Karabegović and O. Zorić, “Bosnian Consternation
at Serbian Security Officers IWPR”, in Institute for War and Peace Reporting, 2013.
135
Diane Orentlicher, Some Kind of Justice: The ICTY’s Impact in Bosnia and Serbia, Oxford
University Press, 2018, p. 186.
136
Soeren Keil and Valery Perry (eds.), State-Building and Democratization in Bosnia and
Herzegovina, Southeast European Studies, 2015, p. 153.
Srebrenica and Žepa Enclaves, Munira Subašić, and Murat Tahirović, Pres-
ident of the Organization of Victims and Witnesses of Genocide, came to
The Hague “to talk to the Tribunal’s officials and get some answers”. 137
Although they were received by Meron himself, 138 he refused to allow
them a further meeting with other judges. Instead, he suggested that they
write a letter to him specifying what they wanted to ask them, and then he
would talk to them – a proposal Subašić found useless considering how he
ignored their first letter. Generally, Subašić had little positive to say about
Meron on this particular occasion, characterizing him as “a very cunning
man – cunning as a man; cunning as a politician”, and claiming he was
holding monopoly power over the court, filling bottomless barrels, and tell-
ing tales for kids to the victims. 139 On the other hand, Tahirović stated that
the victims’ representatives would leave The Hague with a strong impres-
sion that there “is a clear conflict and disagreement” among the judges. 140
The victims’ associations had also written to the UN Secretary-
General Ban Ki Moon asking him to establish an independent commission
to investigate the allegations made in the Letter sent by Judge Harhoff, and
to see if the Tribunal had really ‘changed its course’ under the pressure of
‘military establishments’ of some influential countries, yet they never re-
ceived a response. It is important to note, that the acquittals, also driven by
Meron, which have granted the release of several genocide convicts at the
ICTR, have similarly caused shock in the affected communities and raised
calls for reviews, which were likewise ignored. IBUKA, the genocide sur-
vivors’ umbrella organization in Rwanda, has repeatedly called for an ur-
gent investigation of all the controversial decisions, which it said have only
served to benefit genocide perpetrators. In one of its protest letters to the
UN, it stated:
The international community failed Rwandans during the
Genocide against the Tutsi yet it had its mission present in the
country, today there’s an attempt, through international justice,
137
“Instead of Resignation, Meron Offers Victims ‘New Chapter’”, Sense Agency, 26 July 2013
(available on its web site) (‘Sense Agency’).
138
As well as the Tribunal’s Registrar John Hocking and Chief Prosecutor Serge Brammertz.
139
Govori priče za djecu, puni sode bez dna, TV Tribunal 596, video, 27 July 2013 (on file with
the authors).
140
Sense Agency, see above note 137.
25.4. Conclusion
As Lemoine noted, “[t]here can be no impartiality without independence
from outside influence and notably from governments, including, and per-
haps primarily, from one’s own”. 142 Speaking from his own experience,
Meron himself acknowledged the existence of governmental influence on
international judges by arguing for life-long appointments in order to offset
it. 143 Whether justified or not, imagined or real, suspicions of outside influ-
ence should be taken seriously when raised in an honest manner at such
high levels within an international tribunal.
The fact that both at the ICTY and the ICTR, calls for investigations
fell on deaf ears is a failure of the system to ensure impartiality. Further-
more, if there was, in fact, no direct outside influence that dictated the nu-
merous acquittals, raising open-ended questions such as the ones posed by
Judge Harhoff or Judge Pocar should not be considered something to fear,
prohibit or punish, but rather an opportunity to elaborate clearly on why
such perceptions are erroneous. Certainly, their suspicions were not merely
felt by them, but rather by numerous people affected by or having
knowledge of the relevant conflicts; thus, an open discussion would have
been invaluable.
The Appeals Chamber in Čelebići stated that “justice should not only
be done, but should manifestly and undoubtedly be seen to be done” 144 and
is founded on the need to ensure public confidence in the judiciary. 145 As
the Office of the Prosecutor rightly noted: “To preserve its positive reputa-
141
“Judge Who Freed 10 Genocide Convicts Seeks New UN Contract”, KT Press, 29 January
2018 (available on its web site).
142
Lemoine, 1995, p. 43, see above note 128.
143
Meron, 2005, see above note 117.
144
Furundžija Appeal Judgement, para. 195, see above note 52. See International Criminal
Tribunal for Rwanda (‘ICTR’), Prosecutor v. Seromba, The Bureau, Decision on Motion for
Disqualification of Judges, 25 April 2006, ICTR-2001-66-T, para. 9 (with references cited
therein) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/9d6128/).
145
Čelebići Appeal Judgement, para. 707, see above note 52; ICTR, Prosecutor v. Karemera et
al., Trial Chamber, Decision on Joseph Nzirorera’s Motion for Disqualification of Judge By-
ron and Stay of the Proceedings, 20 February 2009, ICTR-98-44-T, para. 6 (https://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/f27eb3/); Stanišić and Župljanin Appeal Judgement, para. 43, see
above note 42.
tion moving forward, the Tribunal must make allowance for valid criticism.
It must use the constructive aspects of the debate generated as a spring-
board for strengthening its processes”. 146 Instead, the Tribunal chose to
simply get rid of Judge Harhoff, “to wash away the stain that [his] email
had put on the court”. 147 One could argue that this reaction was the stain
itself, sending a signal to the public as well as other judges and insiders that
any criticism, whistleblowing or questioning would be severely punished
instead of being met with a response of self-reflection by the institution.
On a positive note, as the Office of the Prosecutor has noted, the
Court and its Appeals Chamber “demonstrated its independence, impartiali-
ty and capacity for critical reflection, strengthening the international justice
system and the rule-of-law” in overturning the Perišić Appeal Judgement’s
flawed holding. 148
146
Statement of Serge Brammertz, see above note 84.
147
Burcharth, see above note 33.
148
Statement of Prosecutor 2014, see above note 92.
Integrity in
International Criminal Law:
Post-Conviction Proceedings
Gregory S. Gordon *
26.1. Introduction
On 14 December 2016, based on a decision by the President of the United
Nations International Residual Mechanism for Criminal Tribunals
(‘MICT’), convicted Rwandan genocidaire Ferdinand Nahimana was
granted early release. 2 Nahimana, referred to by some as the ‘Rwandan
Goebbels’, is considered the propaganda master of the Rwandan Geno-
*
Gregory S. Gordon is Professor and formerly served as Associate Dean (Develop-
ment/External Affairs) and Director of the Ph.D.–M.Phil. Programme at the Faculty of Law,
The Chinese University of Hong Kong. Before joining the legal academy, he served as a
prosecutor with the United States Department of Justice and the International Criminal Tri-
bunal for Rwanda. Professor Gordon is also a Research Fellow at the Centre for Internation-
al Law Research and Policy (CILRAP). In 2017, his book Atrocity Speech Law: Foundation,
Fragmentation, Fruition (Oxford University Press), which coined a new term for the law re-
lated to hate speech in international criminal law, proposed a paradigm shift in the field with
introduction of the “Unified Liability Theory for Atrocity Speech Law”. The author would
like to thank Jan Stone for her outstanding research assistance on this project.
1
Theodor Meron, Speech before the UN Security Council, 7 June 2012, in United Nations
International Residual Mechanism for Criminal Tribunals (‘MICT’), “About” (available on
its web site).
2
MICT, The Prosecutor v. Nahimana, Public Redacted Version of the 22 September 2016
Decision of the President on the Early Release of Ferdinand Nahimana, 5 December 2016,
MICT-13-37-ES.I, para. 35 (‘Nahimana Early Release Decision’) (https://legal-tools.org/
doc/1l5p1y); Firouzeh Mitchell, “Early Release for Two ICTR Convicts, Possible War
Crimes in Aleppo, and Amnesty Law in Colombia”, ICL Media Review, 15 December 2016
(available on its web site).
cide. 3 His December 2003 conviction and 30-year sentence by the Interna-
tional Criminal Tribunal for Rwanda (‘ICTR’) on various hate speech-
related genocide and crimes against humanity charges was grounded in his
founding/guiding the operations of Radio Télévision Libre des Milles Col-
lines (‘RTLM’). 4 Also referred to as ‘Radio Machete’, RTLM urged Rwan-
dan Hutus to slaughter Tutsis over the airwaves, helping fuel a genocide
against the country’s ethnic minority in 1994, during which close to
800,000 victims perished in approximately three months. 5
From a superficial perspective, without studying the defendant’s
background too closely, the release decision raises no red flags. Nahimana
had hit the two-thirds mark of his 30-year sentence and a MICT practice
had developed allowing ad hoc tribunal convicts with good behaviour to be
set free after serving two-thirds of their sentences. 6
Yet, closer scrutiny raises troubling issues of integrity. The early re-
lease decision was made by Judge Theodor Meron, who had sat in judge-
ment of Nahimana during the merits phase of the proceedings against the
RTLM founder. 7 At that juncture, Meron took issue with the basis of Na-
himana’s liability and dissented on the grounds that the sentence was too
harsh. 8 Meron had disagreed with the other judges on his panel, finding
that Nahimana’s liability connected to hate speech was illegitimate in light
of freedom of expression concerns explicitly grounded in the zealous free
speech bent of US First Amendment jurisprudence. 9 Further, that appellate
3
Vincent Gasana, “When a Judge Undermines the Legacy of International Justice”, The New
Times, 4 June 2018 (available on its web site).
4
“Journalists Jailed for Inciting Rwandan Genocide”, The Guardian, 4 December 2003
(available on its web site).
5
Sharon Lafraniere, “Court Finds Rwanda Media Executives Guilty of Genocide”, The New
York Times, 3 December 2003 (available on its web site).
6
Barbara Hola, “Early Release of ICTR Convicts: The Practice Beyond the Outrage”, Jus-
ticeInfo.Net, 5 July 2019 (available on its web site).
7
James Karuhanga, “Government, Survivors Raise Concern over UN’s Early Release of
Genocide Convicts”, The New Times, 16 December 2016 (available on its web site).
8
International Criminal Tribunal for Rwanda (‘ICTR’), Prosecutor v. Ferdinand Nahimana et
al., Appeals Chamber, Judgement, 28 November 2007, ICTR-99-52-A (‘Nahimana Case
Appeals Judgement’), Partially Dissenting Opinion of Judge Theodor Meron, para. 22
(http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/4ad5eb/); Gregory S. Gordon, Atrocity Speech Law: Foun-
dation, Fragmentation, Fruition, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2017, pp. 235–236.
9
Ibid., pp. 235–236. (A previous chapter by the author on this case focused on the national
power politics underlying and surrounding the Nahimana Early Release Decision: “On the
Early Release of the “Rwandan Goebbels”: American Free Speech Exceptionalism and the
13
“Rwanda: How the Genocide Happened”, BBC News, 17 May 2011 (available on its web
site).
14
Ibid.
15
Ibid.
16
Chris McGreal, “Rwanda’s Himmler: The Man Behind the Genocide”, The Guardian, 18
December 2008 (available on its web site).
17
Godfrey Mwakikagile, Civil Wars in Rwanda and Burundi: Conflict Resolution in Africa,
New Africa Press, Pretoria, 2013, p. 269.
During his tenure there, in what some have referred to as a ‘dress re-
hearsal’ for the Rwandan Genocide, 18 Nahimana had Radio Rwanda broad-
cast a knowingly fabricated ‘news bulletin’ informing listeners that the Tut-
sis had compiled a list of Hutu targets to be murdered in Bugesera (a Tutsi
district in Eastern Province, Rwanda). 19 Radio Rwanda aired this fudged
‘news’ to extremist Hutu Interahamwe militias and members of the Presi-
dential Guard, who were synchronously being transported to that locale. 20
Nahimana’s voice soon came on the same airwaves and implored listeners
to “[a]nnihilate these Machiavellian plans of the enemy Inyenzi-
Inkotanyi”. 21 He then referred to the Tutsis as ‘cockroaches’ (inyenzi) and
warned that they were “preparing to overthrow the country”. 22 Enraged by
the broadcast and then deposited at the doorstep of an exclusive Tutsi en-
clave, these heavily armed militia, arriving in Bugesera by the truckload,
slaughtered scores of innocent civilians. 23
Most of Rwanda, and the international community at large, were in
an uproar over this orchestrated butchery. Bowing to the attendant pressure,
President Habyarimana fired Nahimana from his ORINFOR post. 24 Having
been sacked from his government position as head of communications, Na-
himana turned to the private sector to find a comparable position.
And this coincided with the extremist Hutus drawing up the burgeon-
ing template for a Tutsi genocide. In particular, as part of the mounting hate
speech campaign against the Tutsis, in July 1993, Nahimana spearheaded
the establishment of RTLM. 25 In the hate language it disseminated over the
airwaves, Nahimana’s station attempted to dehumanize the Tutsis by,
among other things, referring to them as ‘inyenzi’ (cockroaches) and using
other dehumanizing metaphors. 26 Additionally, it called for violence
18
Gordon, 2017, pp. 51–52, see above note 8.
19
Aimable Twagilimana, Historical Dictionary of Rwanda, Rowman & Littlefield, London,
2007, p. 123.
20
Linda Melvern, Conspiracy to Murder: The Rwandan Genocide, Verso, London, 2006,
pp. 26–28.
21
Dina Temple-Raston, Justice on the Grass: Three Rwandan Journalists, Their Trial for War
Crimes, and a Nation’s Quest for Redemption, Free Press, New York, 2005, pp. 27–28.
22
Ibid., p. 28.
23
Ibid., p. 27.
24
Ibid., p. 29.
25
Jolyon Mitchell, “Remembering the Rwandan Genocide: Reconsidering the Role of Local
and Global Media”, in Global Media Journal, 2007, vol. 6, no. 11, p. 3.
26
Ibid., p. 4.
27
Gordon, 2017, p. 53, see above note 8.
28
ICTR, Prosecutor v. Ferdinand Nahimana et al., Trial Chamber, Judgment and Sentence, 3
December 2003, ICTR-99-52-T, paras. 571–607 (‘Nahimana Case Trial Judgement’)
(http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/45b8b6/).
29
Frank Chalk, “Hate Radio in Rwanda”, in Howard Adelman and Astri Suhrke (eds.), The
Path of a Genocide: The Rwanda Crisis from Uganda to Zaire, Routledge, London, 2017,
p. 97 (noting that RTLM played an important role as an inciter and co-ordinator of the
Rwandan Genocide).
30
Gordon, 2017, p. 151, see above note 8.
31
Ibid., pp. 151–152.
32
Ibid., p. 152. Nahimana Case Trial Judgement, para. 563, see above note 28
33
Ibid., para. 8.
34
Ibid. Jean-Bosco Barayagwiza, another RTLM founder/director, was arrested in the same
raid and charged with the same crimes although supplemented in reference to his leadership
of a Hutu extremist political party (Coalition pour la Défense de la République or CDR) –
thus, CAH-murder was included in his indictment. Ibid., para. 14. Another Hutu extremist
journalist, Hassan Ngeze, editor-in-chief of the radically anti-Tutsi newspaper Kangura, was
arrested in Kenya in 1997, charged with similar crimes and tried with Nahimana and
Barayagwiza. Ibid., para. 19.
35
Ibid., para. 966.
36
Nahimana Case Appeals Judgement, see above note 8.
37
See, for example, ibid., para. 224 (rejecting argument that late filing of broadcast transla-
tions caused prejudice); para. 226 (rejecting argument regarding admission of evidence); pa-
ra. 229 (amending the prosecution list found not to be prejudicial); para. 235 (argument re-
garding obstruction to defense investigation found not to have merit); para. 257 (no proof
that right to have defense witnesses appear under the same condition as prosecution witness-
es was violated).
38
Ibid., para. 695.
39
Ibid., paras. 696, 697.
40
Ibid.
41
Ibid., paras. 986, 987.
42
Ibid., para. 986. I have been critical of this portion of the Appeals Chamber judgment as the
panel squandered a golden opportunity to clarify whether hate speech on its own, as part of a
widespread or systematic directed against a civilian population, can constitute the actus reus
for CAH-persecution. Gordon, 2017, pp. 233, 234, 335, 336, see above note 8.
43
Nahimana Case Appeals Judgment, para. 988, see above note 8 (ellipsis in the original).
44
Ibid., para. 1052. With reference to the other two Media Trial defendants, Ngeze’s sentence
was reduced to 35 years. Barayagwiza had been technically sentenced to life in prison but
had it reduced to 35 years, with credit for time served (bringing it to twenty-seven), due to
certain procedural irregularities). Ibid., para. 1039. Based on the portions of the convictions
that were overturned, he was granted a further sentence reduction of three years by the Ap-
peals Chamber. Ibid., para. 1097.
45
Nahimana Case Appeals Judgment, Partially Dissenting Opinion of Judge Theodor Meron,
para. 1, see above note 8.
46
Ibid., para. 13.
47
Ibid., para. 12.
48
Ibid. paras. 11–12, citing United States Supreme Court (‘US SC’), Texas v. Johnson, 21 June
1989, 491 U.S. 397, p. 414; US SC, Brandenburg v. Ohio, 9 June 1969, 395 U.S. 444, p. 447;
US SC, Watts v. United States, 21 April 1969, 394 U.S. 705, p. 708.
49
Judge Meron merely stated this with no authority supporting him – in point of fact, per ex-
isting law, no causal nexus need be shown – rather, the prosecutor must only prove that the
broadcasts were part of the attack, with the RTLM announcers being conscious that they
were part of the attack. See Gordon, 2017, p. 10, see above note 8, noting that the crime
against humanity of hate speech as persecution is committed as “part of a widespread or sys-
tematic attack directed against any civilian population, with knowledge of the attack”. This
does not mean that there must be a “causal nexus” between the hate speech and the attack.
Judge Meron merely asserted this without support.
50
Nahimana Case Appeals Judgment, Partially Dissenting Opinion of Judge Theodor Meron,
para. 1, see above note 8 (emphasis added).
68
For example, MICT Statute, Article 26, see above note 51; MICT Practice Direction, para. 9,
see above note 65.
69
MICT, Rules of Procedure and Evidence, 26 September 2016, MICT/1/Rev.2, Rule 150
(‘MICT RPE’) (emphasis added).
70
MICT Practice Direction, para. 7, see above note 65.
71
Ibid., Rule 151. In addition, Meron referred to Article 3(2) of the 13 May 2016 Agreement
between the United Nations and the Government of the Republic of Mali on the Enforce-
ment of Sentences Pronounced by the International Criminal Tribunal for Rwanda or the In-
ternational Residual Mechanism for Criminal Tribunals (https://legal-tools.org/doc/ulm6wv)
provides that the conditions of imprisonment shall be governed by the law of Mali Subject
to the Supervision of the Mechanism. Nahimana Early Release Decision, para. 10, see above
note 2. Article 8 of the Enforcement Agreement provides. inter alia. that, following notifica-
tion of eligibility for early release under Malian law, the President shall determine whether
early release is appropriate on the basis of the interests of justice and the general principles
of law, and the Registrar shall transmit the decision of the President to Mali, which shall ex-
ecute the terms of the decision promptly. Ibid. In this case, Meron observed, according to the
provisions of Article 35 of Mali’s Law No. 01-003 of 27 February 2001 on the prison system
and supervised education, “detainees who have provided sufficient proof of their improve-
ment could be eligible for parole or semi-custodial treatment”. Ibid., para. 11. Meron noted
in his decision that the Malian authorities state that Nahimana “meets the conditions set out
in Malian legislation for parole or semi-custodial treatment”, ibid. Meron noted, however,
that that even if Nahimana were eligible for early release under Mali’s domestic law, “early
release of persons convicted by the ICTR falls exclusively with in the discretion of the Pres-
ident pursuant to Article 26 of the Statute and Rules 150 and 151 of the Rules”. Ibid., pa-
ra. 12.
72
Ibid., para. 14.
73
Ibid., quoting Nahimana Case Trial Judgment, para. 945, see above note 28.
74
Ibid., quoting Nahimana Case Trial Judgment, para. 949, see above note 28
75
Ibid., quoting Nahimana Case Trial Judgment, para. 953, see above note 28
76
Ibid., quoting Nahimana Case Trial Judgment, para. 965, see above note 28
77
Ibid., para. 15, quoting Nahimana Case Trial Judgment, para. 966, see above note 28.
78
Ibid.
79
Ibid.
80
Ibid., para. 16, quoting Nahimana Case Trial Judgment, para. 1099, see above note 28.
81
Ibid., quoting Nahimana Case Trial Judgment, para. 1102, see above note 28
82
Ibid., quoting Nahimana Case Trial Judgment, para. 972, see above note 28.
83
Ibid., para. 19, see above note 2.
84
International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia, “Ljubomir Borovčanin Trans-
ferred to Denmark to Serve Sentence”, press release, 11 November 2011 (https://legal-
tools.org/doc/qw7qxb); MICT, The Prosecutor v. Borovčanin, Public Redacted Version of
the 14 July 2016 Decision of the President on the Early Release of Ljubomir Borovčanin, 2
August 2016, MICT-13-37-ES.I, para. 3 (‘Borovčanin Early Release Decision’) (http://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/2e491d/).
85
Borovčanin Early Release Decision, para. 3, see above note 84.
86
“Bosnian Serb Srebrenica Convict Ljubomir Borovčanin Freed”, in Balkan Transitional
Justice, 2 August 2016 (available on its web site).
ing Popović and Beara to life in prison, and Nikolić to 35 years, 87 helps
place Borovčanin’s subordinate role into its proper perspective.
26.3.3.2.2.2. The Prosecutor v. Bisengimana
The other case cited by Judge Meron in this portion of the early release de-
cision was the ICTR matter of Prosecutor v. Bisengimana. There, the de-
fendant was the mayor of a town called Gikoro in the Kigali-Rural Prefec-
ture of Rwanda. 88 In December 2005, he pled guilty to aiding and abetting
crimes against humanity (murder, extermination) committed against Tutsis
in his town between 13 and 15 April 1994. As with Borovčanin, this was a
rather low-level official. Even more striking, though, when contrasted with
Nahimana, was the fact that Bisengimana had actually co-operated with
prosecutors by pleading guilty.
26.3.3.2.2.3. The Absence of Legal Authority in Footnote 30
Quite conspicuously, Meron’s footnote 30 did not cite legal authority for
the proposition that “all convicts supervised by the Mechanism are to be
considered eligible for early release upon the completion of two-thirds of
their sentences, irrespective of the tribunal that convicted them”. He merely
referenced the two cases of Borovčanin and Bisengimana, suggesting this
had been the MICT’s practice (even though, as suggested above, the two
convicts in those cases do not seem to be similarly situated to the high-
ranking Ferdinand Nahimana). Meron did observe that a “convicted person
having served two-thirds of his or her sentence shall be merely eligible to
apply for early release and not entitled to such release, which may only be
granted by the President as a matter of discretion, after considering the to-
tality of the circumstances in each case”. 89 With this in mind, after first
confirming that, by Meron’s calculations, Nahimana served two-thirds of
his sentence by 27 March 2016, Meron went on to consider: (1) demonstra-
tion of rehabilitation; (2) substantial co-operation; and (3) “humanitarian
concerns”.
87
Ibid.
88
MICT, Prosecutor v. Bisengimana, Decision of the President on Early Release of Paul
Bisengimana and on Motion to File a Public Redacted Application, 11 December 2012,
MICT-12-07, para. 3 (‘Bisengimana Early Release Decision’) (http://www.legal-tools.org/
doc/a7d60f/; https://legal-tools.org/doc/urptdm).
89
Nahimana Early Release Decision, para. 19, see above note 2.
any point while serving his sentence”. So, despite no evidence or remorse
or co-operation, Meron was able only to wanly intone that “Nahimana’s
lack of cooperation with the Prosecution […] is a neutral factor in deter-
mining whether or not to grant him early release”. 96
26.3.3.2.5. Humanitarian Concerns
As for the final Rule 151 factor, “humanitarian concerns”, Meron alluded
to Nahimana’s Application submission that “his age and ill health are
grounds for early release”. 97 No substantiation or details regarding the “ill
health” were provided (it should be pointed out, though, once again, that
the Decision is heavily redacted). It is noted that, at the time the application
was submitted, Nahimana was in his mid-60s – not the sort of extremely
advanced age, where grave health problems could easily be supposed. Not
surprisingly then, Meron rejected the ill health assertion and was dubious
of Nahimana’s claim that his age was a factor. 98
26.3.3.2.6. Conclusion of the Rule 151 Analysis
This was followed by a concluding paragraph. Having checked off few of
the boxes he seemed to indicate were important, and acknowledging the
gravity of Nahimana’s crimes, Meron perfunctorily granted Nahimana’s
Application in one skeletal sentence: “While the crimes of which Nahima-
na was convicted are very grave, the fact that Nahimana already completed
two-thirds of his sentence as of 27 March 2016, and the fact that he has
demonstrated some signs of rehabilitation weigh in favour of his early re-
lease”. 99
26.3.3.3. MICT RPE Rule 150 Analysis
Up to now, we have examined Meron’s consideration of Nahimana’s Ap-
plication for Early Release pursuant to Rule 151 of the MICT RPE. Yet, the
RPE demands more – the President must also take into account Rule 150,
which requires him to consult with other judges (and, as we have seen,
Practice Direction 7 mandates this as well). But Meron gave only short
shrift to this provision, noting quite cursorily by way of footnote: “Other
96
Nahimana Early Release Decision, para. 30, see above note 2.
97
Ibid., paras. 32–33.
98
Ibid., para. 34. The then-86-year-old Meron could presumably speak from personal experi-
ence in that regard.
99
Ibid., paras. 35–37.
than myself, none of the Judges of the sentencing Chamber are judges of
the Mechanism. On that basis, no consultations with other Judges of the
Mechanism pursuant to Rule 150 of the Rules are required in determining
his Application”. 100
26.4. Overall Analysis of the Early Release Decision
26.4.1. Failure to Comply with MICT RPE Rules 151 and 150
The first aspect of the decision to consider is the coherence and probity of
the document itself. This, in turn, hinges on Meron’s analysis pursuant to
RPE Rules 151 and 150 – the heart of the early release merits decision.
Furthermore, here it is clear that Judge Meron failed to comply with the
spirit, if not the letter, of the explicit instructions provided in those rules.
26.4.1.1. The Rule 150 Analysis
In this respect, his treatment of Rule 150 stands out. As will be recalled,
that provision requires the President to consult “with any Judges of the sen-
tencing Chamber who are Judges of the Mechanism, whether pardon,
commutation of sentence, or early release is appropriate”. 101
In this regard, Judge Meron hung his hat on a technicality – it is true
that no member of the sentencing bench was on the MICT roster at that
time (again, it is not a group of full-time paid judges but persons on call
who are paid only for work performed when assigned to them). However,
Judge Fausto Pocar, a member of the sentencing panel who disagreed with
Meron, was still a judge at the ICTY – as was Meron himself. 102 It would
have been quite feasible to solicit Judge Pocar’s views given the close
structural and personnel link between the ICTY and the MICT. Regardless,
Judge Meron failed to do even that.
It is worth noting that the MICT seems to have taken cognizance of
the technical loophole Judge Meron exploited in the Nahimana Early Re-
lease Decision. The Mechanism recently amended Rule 150 to mandate
that “[i]f none of the Judges who imposed the sentence are Judges of the
Mechanism, the President shall consult with at least two other Judges”. 103
100
Ibid., para. 8, footnote 15.
101
MICT RPE Rule 150, see above note 69.
102
United Nations International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia, “The Judges”
(available on ICTY’s web site) indicating that Judge Fausto Pocar and Judge Theodor Mer-
on were still on the ICTY bench.
103
MICT RPE, 4 March 2019, MICT/1/Rev.5, Rule 150, cf. above note 69.
Going even further, and consistent with the practice of the Residual Mech-
anism for the Special Court for Sierra Leone, Rule 150 could be revised to
require the early release application decision-maker to consult with at least
one judge from the panel that issued the final version of the sentence im-
posed on the defendant. 104 In the age of the Internet, this is eminently fea-
sible.
26.4.1.2. The Rule 151 Analysis
26.4.1.2.1. Extreme Gravity and Non-Similarly-Situated Prisoners
Examining the Rule 151 analysis also reveals serious issues. The evalua-
tion begins auspiciously with consideration of the gravity of Nahimana’s
crimes. The gist of this section is that the RTLM founder was a principal
architect of the Rwandan Genocide and desired the impact ‘Radio Machete’
had on fomenting and fuelling the massacres. Yet, what follows can only be
described as cognitive dissonance. In particular, the “equal treatment of
similarly-situated prisoners” exposition is a non-sequitur and internally in-
coherent. How could Meron assert that a Bosnian Serb police brigade
deputy commander and a Kigali-suburb mayor were “similarly situated”
vis-à-vis the Rwandan Genocide’s propaganda master? The imbalance in
criminal responsibility alone renders the comparison absurd.
26.4.1.2.2. Absence of Rehabilitation or Co-operation
But that disparity is exacerbated when one considers that these lower-level
players co-operated (through a guilty plea and non-appeal) and expressed
contrition. Nahimana fought every step of the way and continued to deflect
blame for his actions until the day of his release. What is worse, a bit of
research by the MICT would have revealed that Nahimana’s lack of repent-
ance only intensified after he began serving his sentence.
In a document he published on the Internet titled “Debate on the
Book of Jean Baptiste Nkuliyingoma”, Nahimana passionately denied any
sort of responsibility whatsoever in reference to his hate media activities
both before and during the Rwandan Genocide. 105 In the document, he
104
Residual Special Court for Sierra Leone, Rules of Procedure and Evidence, 30 November
2018, Rule 124 (‘RSCSCL RPE’) (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/2b02c6/) (requiring the
early release decision-maker to consult “with the Judges who imposed the sentence”).
105
Ferdinand Nahimana, “Débat Sur le Livre de Jean Baptiste Nkuliyingoma: Inkundura. Ama-
teka y’intambara ya ruhekura yakuyeho igitugu ikimika ikindi”, 9 February 2012 (translated
by the author).
blanketly assigned all blame to the RPF and its alleged dissemination of
propaganda in the previous 20-plus years (alluding to, for instance, the
“propaganda, the rumor, and the false presentation of actual facts between
1990 and 1994 meant to demonize the opponents of the RPF and hide the
true nature of this movement”). 106 Among other core points of denial Na-
himana asserted here:
1. He alleged that the text of the communiqué read on Radio Rwanda,
when he was in charge of that radio station before the founding of
RTLM, as reported in various histories of Rwanda, was a fabrication
of Jean-Pierre Chrétien (Nahimana’s thesis supervisor) in his 1995
book Les Médias du Génocide and that the communiqué was selec-
tively redacted and read out of context without his knowledge and
contrary to his wishes. In any event, he insisted, the overall message
of the communiqué was an appeal for nonviolence. 107 (This assertion
is contrary to trial testimony as well as the histories of experts be-
yond reproach, such as Alison Des Forges in her book Leave None to
Tell the Story: “In March 1992 [when Nahimana was its director],
Radio Rwanda warned that Hutu leaders in Bugesera were going to
be murdered by Tutsi, false information meant to spur the Hutu mas-
sacres of Tutsi”. 108)
2. Similarly, Nahimana claimed that he was not responsible for the
reading of the communiqué and was sacked from ORINFOR [the
agency he directed that ran Radio Rwanda] by backchannel man-
oeuvrings of the RPF – not because of indignation throughout Rwan-
dan society and the international community, which, as we have seen,
pressured the government to remove Nahimana from the ORINFOR
post [as was widely reported]. 109 He also asserted that he was offered
a consular post in Germany but turned it down to return to the Uni-
versity. 110 (But according to Allison Des Forges: “He gave up teach-
106
Ibid., p. 6.
107
Ibid., pp. 13–14.
108
Alison Des Forges, “Leave None to Tell the Story”: Genocide in Rwanda, Human Rights
Watch, New York, 1999, p. 79.
109
Nahimana, 2012, pp. 14–18, see above note 105. See also Temple-Raston, 2005, p. 29, see
above note 21 (reporting that many in Rwanda and the international community at large
were appalled by the orchestrated slaughter in Bugesera and that, as a result of this, then-
Rwandan President Juvenal Habyarimana fired Nahimana from his ORINFOR post).
110
Ibid., pp. 15–16.
111
Des Forges, 1999, p. 85, see above note 108.
112
Nahimana, 2012, pp. 11–12, see above note 105.
113
Ibid., p. 12. Nahimana notes that Ngeze testified to this effect before the ICTR and has
maintained this claim ever since. Ibid.
114
Ibid., pp. 21–25.
115
Ibid., pp. 18–19, emphasis in the original and author’s translation from French.
116
Ibid., p. 19, referring to “accusations si infondées” and saying that anyone who believes this
have “manifestement tordu la verité” (author’s translation from French).
117
Ibid., p. 23 (author’s translation from French).
118
Jean-Baptiste Nkuliyingoma, “The Book Inkundura: Can Ferdinand Nahimana Be Both
Judge and Jury?”, in La Tribune Franco-Rwandaise, 19 February 2012 (available on its web
site) (author’s translation from French).
himana’s having arrived at the two-thirds mark of his sentence and having
shown “some signs of rehabilitation” (although Meron never indicated spe-
cifically what they were).
26.4.1.2.4. A Lack of Legal Support for the Two-Thirds Rule
Moreover, what is the legal support for eligibility for early release at the
two-thirds mark in the first place? As it turns out, there is no statutory sup-
port for it. 119 It was simply a practice adopted by the judges at the ad hoc
tribunal for the former Yugoslavia. However, the ICTR had a different
practice from the ICTY. In contrast to the ICTY, the ICTR used a three-
quarters standard. 120 The greater severity of the crimes before the ICTR,
which arose within the context of a widespread and systematic genocidal
campaign where approximately 800,000 were murdered in approximately
three months, accounted for the policy divergence between the two tribu-
nals. 121
Further, as noted by Jonathan Choi, this early release practice runs
against the policy aims of the ad hoc tribunal framers as it confuses parole
with commutation:
The ICTY seems to have implemented early release policies
that are significantly more generous than its framers intended.
It has adopted something like a presumption that prisoners
need only serve two thirds of their sentences, apparently out
of confusion between commutation and parole […] However,
it is important to note at this point that the Statute only con-
templates the convicted person’s eligibility for pardon or
commutation of sentence, not for parole. This is a crucial dis-
tinction because, as we will see, domestic actors grant com-
mutation much less often than they do parole. The plain lan-
guage of the Statutes suggests that their framers intended early
release to be similarly rare. 122
So, if the early release policy is problematic in the first place, it is
exacerbated at the ICTY, where a two-thirds standard was applied. How is
it, then, that the two-thirds standard was transposed to ICTR convicts at the
119
Jonathan H. Choi, “Early Release in International Criminal Law”, in The Yale Law Journal,
vol. 123, no. 6, 2014, pp. 1792–1793.
120
Ibid., p. 1793.
121
Ibid.
122
Ibid., pp. 1793–1794, emphasis added.
MICT? The answer is simple: Judge Theodor Meron. In the 2012 Be-
singimana early release decision, as President of the MICT, he simply
made a unilateral decision to apply the two-thirds rule to Rwandan geno-
cidaires. 123 In his words:
While I acknowledge that adoption of the two-thirds eligibil-
ity threshold might constitute a benefit not previously recog-
nised for persons convicted by the ICTR, I do not consider
that this can justify discriminating between the different
groups of convicted persons falling under the jurisdiction of
the Mechanism. 124
123
Bisengimana Early Release Decision, paras. 20–21, see above note 88.
124
Ibid., para. 21.
125
Milan Markovic, “International Criminal Trials and the Disqualification of Judges on the
Basis of Nationality”, in Washington University Global Studies Law Review, 2014, vol. 13,
no. 1, p. 2.
126
Ibid. See, for example, International Criminal Court, Code of Judicial Ethics, 9 March 2005,
Res. ICC-BD/02-01-05, Articles 3, 4 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/383f8f/).
the President shall assign another Judge to the case”. 127 Here, as Meron
was President at the time of the Nahimana Early Release Decision, Rule 18
also provides the most senior judge would appoint a new judge to the
case. 128
In the Nahimana matter, Rule 18(A) clearly suggests excluding Mer-
on as the decision-maker in reference to the early release application. Mer-
on had a “previous association with the case” as an appellate judge on Na-
himana’s merits adjudication, and he had an “association that might affect
his impartiality” given that he dissented as to one of the key bases of con-
viction that was upheld and he explicitly called for a reduction of the de-
fendant’s sentence.
Complementing Rule 18(A), the related Rule 18(D) provides that
“[n]o Judge shall sit on any appeal in a case in which that Judge sat in first
instance”. 129 Although this rule is not exactly on point here (as the early
release application was not technically an “appeal”), in conjunction with
Rule 18(A), Meron’s service on the merits appeal panel and then in the fol-
low-up early release application capacity also militates in favour of exclu-
sion for the latter.
These points are underscored by the MICT’s “Code of Professional
Conduct for the Judges of the Mechanism” (MICT Judicial Conduct Code),
which had been adopted in 2015 and was in place when Judge Meron ruled
on Nahimana’s early release application. The Preamble of the Code explic-
itly recognizes that the “impartiality of judges is fundamental to ensuring
public confidence in a fair and transparent international judicial pro-
cess”. 130 In addition, Article 3(1) of the Code mandates that “Judges shall
be impartial and ensure the appearance of impartiality in the discharge of
their judicial functions”. 131
This is in line with national judicial ethics rules. For example, on
lack of impartiality grounds, the American Bar Association Model Code of
1Judicial Conduct, Rule 2.11(A)(6)(d) requires disqualification of a judge
127
MICT RPE, Rule 18(A), see above note 69.
128
Ibid.
129
Ibid.
130
Mechanism for International Criminal Tribunals, Code of Professional Conduct for the
Judges of the Mechanism, 11 May 2015, MICT/14/Art. 3 (‘MICT Judicial Conduct Code’)
(http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/23cc92/) (current code date is 9 April 2018; language on this
article has not changed).
131
Ibid., Article 3.
132
American Bar Association, Model Code of Judicial Conduct, Rule 2.11(A)(6)(d).
133
Code of Conduct for United States Judges, 12 March 2019, Canon 3(C)(1)(e) (‘Code of
Conduct’). Although the Code of Conduct was created to govern the lower courts, for the
US Supreme Court, “the Code remains the starting point and key source of guidance for the
Justices”, John G. Roberts Jr., 2011 Year-End Report on the Federal Judiciary, THIRD
BRANCH (Admin. Office of the US Courts), December 2011, pp. 3–5. Similarly, Congress’s
enactment of 28 U.S.C. § 455 directing recusal circumstances for federal judges has been
used as a standard by the Justices, ibid. at 7-9, as noted in recent recusals by Associate Jus-
tice Neil Gorsuch in US SC, Royal v. Murphy, 2018 (a case denied an en banc hearing dur-
ing Gorsuch’s tenure on the appeals court); and Associate Justice Brett Kavanaugh, who has
recused himself from three cases for the 2018-2019 term: Jam v. International Finance Cor-
poration, Lorenzo v. Securities and Exchange Commission, and Azar v. Allina Health Ser-
vices (Kavanaugh served on the DC Circuit three-judge panel in two of these cases and par-
ticipated in an en banc order for the third).
134
Nicolas Boring, “Malian Rules of Judicial Ethics: A Comparative Study”, in United States
Library of Congress, September 2014 (“The Malian judicial system, like that of other former
French colonies such as Côte d’Ivoire, Senegal, Burkina Faso, and Benin, is strongly based
on France’s legal traditions”).
135
Ibid. Mali, Loi No. 02-054 du 16 décembre 2002 portant statut de la magistrature (Law No.
02-054 of December 16, 2002 on the Status of Judges), 31 December 2002, Articles 15, 16.
136
International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia , Prosecutor v. Furundžija, Ap-
peals Chamber, Judgement, 21 July 2000, IT-95-17/1-A, para. 189 (http://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/660d3f/).
137
Alfred and Bruce Gitelson, “A Trial Judge’s Credo Must Include His Affirmative Duty to be
an Instrumentality of Justice”, in Santa Clara Lawyer, 1966, vol. 7, no. 1, p. 24.
138
Ibid., p. 7.
139
MICT RPE, Rule 17, see above note 69.
140
MICT Judicial Conduct Code, Article 4, see above note 130.
141
Code of Conduct, Canon 3(A)(4), see above note 133.
142
Eric J. Maitrepierre, “Ethics, Deontology, Discipline of Judges and Prosecutors in France”,
Resource Materials Series No. 80, p. 266.
143
Judicial Group on Strengthening Judicial Integrity, The Bangalore Principles of Judicial
Conduct, 2002, Principle 5.
144
Ibid., Principle 5.3 (emphasis added).
145
Ibid., Principle 6.5.
146
Residual Special Court for Sierra Leone, Rules of Procedure and Evidence, 2 December
2017, Part IX, Rules 123, 124 (‘RSCSL RPE’) (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/76a01e/).
147
Ibid., Rule 124.
148
Residual Special Court for Sierra Leone, Practice Directions on the Conditional Early Re-
lease of Persons Convicted by the Special Court for Sierra Leone, 1 October 2013 (“SCSL
Practice Directions’) (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/0260c4/).
149
Ibid.
ly-designated reporting centres, at least twice every month; and (6) accept-
ing regular visits made by the office of the Registrar to provide assurance
of security to such vulnerable former witnesses as may desire it. 150
26.4.4. Summary of Integrity Deficits in the Nahimana Early Release
Decision
A review of the record and decision in the Nahimana application for early
release raises serious questions about whether the relevant proceedings ad-
hered to either the letter or spirit of the well-established principles just con-
sidered. The reasons for this are legion: (1) a unilateral, lone-judge deci-
sion-making process; (2) the judge ruling on the early release application
after having been a member of the merits appeals panel; (3) that judge, at
the merits stage, having dissented for policy reasons on the legal grounds
for the conviction and the appropriateness of the punishment; (4) an arbi-
trarily-imposed two-thirds-mark release eligibility policy imposed previ-
ously by that same judge with no chance to have it vetted or litigated; (5)
no independent office or agency, such as a ‘Prisoner Release Analysis Unit’,
capable of thoroughly reviewing the record and all other relevant materials,
conducting appropriate research and providing insights to the decision-
maker in advance of a decision on the merits; (6) the absence of a hearing
where prosecutors, victims and/or other witnesses could be heard; (7) fail-
ure to impose conditions for early release premised on meeting certain key
benchmarks, such as expression of remorse, assurances of refraining from
speaking in public to defend past criminal conduct or to justify new ethnic
animosity; (8) the absence of any monitoring authority in the release juris-
diction to ensure compliance with the conditions; (9) a heavily redacted
written decision on early release; and (10) the lack of a mechanism to allow
for review of the early release decision.
26.5. Recommended Reforms
So, in light of all the issues highlighted in this chapter, how can we reform
the system to avoid the problematic process and outcome seen in the Na-
himana case, as well as ensure adherence to principles of integrity in future
post-conviction proceedings? Here, the recommendations are related to
150
Residual Special Court for Sierra Leone, Prosecutor v. Moinina Fofana, Public Decision of
the President on Application for Conditional Early Release, 11 August 2014, SCSL-2004-14
(http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/1027ef/).
both deontology and system coherence or fairness (which also has deonto-
logical implications).
26.5.1. Providing for Broader Deontological Coverage Within the
Existing MICT Governing Documents
Although, as we have seen, the MICT RPE and Code of Judicial Conduct
contain some guidance regarding the deontological duties of its magistrates,
this is not sufficiently systemic or rigorous. For instance, while the Code of
Judicial Conduct deals with impartiality, it is only in very general terms.
The MICT RPE is more specific and bars judges from presiding over mat-
ters when having any association that might affect impartiality or sitting on
an appeal where having previously sat in first instance. Nevertheless, that
document does not address the precise situation of the judge who previous-
ly presided over the same matter in another court.
Moreover, the current RPE does not generally ensure that important
instances of adjudication, such as ruling on early release applications, gen-
erate sufficient judicial consensus via, at a minimum, three-judge panels (as
opposed to a single judge sitting alone). Nor does the RPE provide for the
bare due process guarantee of participation of all relevant stakeholders in
such proceedings or the opportunity for appeal (which, we have seen, has
adjudicator-ethics implications). These issues need to be fixed in both the
RPE and perhaps in the MICT Statute and the Code of Judicial Conduct
itself.
26.5.2. Fixing Early Release Decision Protocols and Procedure
The problems outlined above in respect of the Nahimana early release deci-
sion suggest the fixes necessary to make the system work properly. Those
will be considered in turn below.
26.5.2.1. Return to the Three-Quarters Early Release Eligibility
Standard
As we have seen, as a threshold matter, it is not clear whether there is bona
fide legal support for eligibility for early release in the first place.
Switching back to a three-quarters standard for ICTR convicts would
be an important first step. However, given that we are also dealing with
mass atrocity crimes in respect of ICTY convicts too, perhaps the three-
quarters standard should be applied to them as well.
151
Michigan Department of Corrections, “The Parole Process” (available on its web site).
152
France, Code de procédure pénale (Code of Criminal Procedure), 2 March 1959, Articles
729–733 (‘French Code of Criminal Procedure’) (https://legal-tools.org/doc/388101). See
also Christopher L. Blakesley, “Conditional Liberation (Parole) in France”, in Louisiana
Law Review, 1978, vol. 30, no. 1, pp. 2–3.
153
French Code of Criminal Procedure, Article 730, see above note 152; Blakesley, pp. 39–40,
see above note 152.
154
Radek Gadek, “Federal Probation Officer Career, Job Description & Salary Info”, Criminal
Justice Online Blog, 31 January 2019 (available on its web site) (describing qualifications of
personnel in comparable positions, in particular, US Probation Officers).
155
Ohio Revised Code, 22 March 2019, Title 29, Section 2967.19(F).
156
Ibid., Section 2967.19(H) (emphasis added).
157
British Embassy Paris, Information Pack for British Prisoners in France, British Embassy
Paris, 30 June 2014.
158
Ibid.
159
Daniel Medwed, “The Innocent Prisoner’s Dilemma: Consequences of Failing to Admit
Guilt at Parole Hearings”, in Iowa Law Review, 2008, vol. 93, pp. 493, 510, 511.
160
Hola, 5 July 2019, see supra note 6. Simba, a retired lieutenant colonel and former member
of parliament who had directed militias in the massacre of Tutsis in Gikongoro, had been
convicted by the ICTR of genocide and crimes against humanity (persecution) and sen-
tenced to twenty-five years imprisonment. See ICTR, The Prosecutor v. Aloys Simba, Trial
Chamber I, Judgement and Sentence, 13 December 2005, ICTR-01-76, (http://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/373ff0/).
161
Hola, 5 July 2019, see above note 6.
162
Ibid.
163
Residual Special Court for Sierra Leone, Practice Direction on the Early Release of Persons
Convicted by the Special Court for Sierra Leone, 1 October 2013, Annex C (http://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/0260c4/).
164
Ibid.
165
See, for example, California Department of Corrections and Rehabilitation, “Life Parole
Process” (available on its web site).
of being honest and having strong moral principles [and standards]”. 166 At
the same time, it encompasses the notion of “wholeness and unity”. Our
examination here of integrity in post-conviction proceedings in internation-
al criminal law has implicated both of these definitions.
Certainly, much of the analysis in this chapter has focused on the de-
ontological deficits in the Nahimana Early Release Decision. The anaemic
nature of the MICT’s governing documents insofar as judicial ethics are
concerned, the fact that a judge who had sat on the merits appeals panel,
and explicitly expressed dissatisfaction with the grounds for conviction and
the extent of punishment, then served as the lone decision-maker for an
application for early release, and the subsequent poorly reasoned and inter-
nally incoherent decision itself – all these factors raise serious questions
about the judge’s compliance with standard canons of professional respon-
sibility, particularly lack of impartiality and/or existence of bias. Thus, the
first aspect of ‘integrity’ has featured prominently in these pages.
Nevertheless, that other dimension of ‘integrity’, to wit, wholeness,
cohesion, coherence (which as explained by Alfred and Bruce Gitelson, has
deontological implications) 167 has also come into play. One must surely call
into question whether the early release decision-making regime at the
MICT reflects a holistic vision of the overall procedural scheme. In the first
place, only a rather myopic view of the ad hoc tribunal or MICT procedural
landscape would ignore the distinct possibility that a judge from the ICTY
or the ICTR might sit as a decision-maker in respect of an early release ap-
plication at the MICT. After all, the MICT judicial roster is nothing short of
an honour roll of emeritus ad hoc tribunal magistrates. ‘Integrity’, in this
context, would undoubtedly include a provision in the MICT Statute ex-
cluding the decision-maker from presiding over the early release decision if
he or she participated in making the ad hoc merits decision. This is doubly
true if he or she took issue with the grounds for conviction and/or the ex-
tent of punishment.
As well, ‘integrity’ in terms of wholeness or coherence comes into
play when the gravity of prisoners’ crimes vis-à-vis one another is ignored
and the voices of important stakeholders, most prominently victims, are
entirely excluded. Similarly, the absence of an unredacted written opinion
supporting the early release decision, as well as the right of appeal for
166
Cambridge Dictionary, “Integrity” (available on its web site).
167
Gitelson and Gitelson, 1966, p. 24, see above note 137.
those parties, including the prosecution, whose interests are affected by that
decision, betrays a substantial lack of inclusive perspective.
This chapter has explained how these deontological and tunnel-
vision problems can be remedied. Beefing up the imperatives in the exist-
ing MICT Code of Judicial Conduct, the RPE and the Statute regarding im-
partiality, bias, and prior service in the same matter would go a long way
toward ensuring that the Nahimana early release decision problems do not
replicate themselves going forward. At the same time, returning to the
three-quarters early release policy for ICTR convicts, expanding the scope
of process to include a prisoner release analysis unit, requiring submission
of a report featuring that unit’s analysis, identifying a local monitoring
mechanism to ensure compliance with conditions, and mandating a bal-
anced or participatory briefing regime or court hearing, transparent written
decisions and a right of appeal could remedy the structural integrity issues.
Unfortunately, in many ways, it is too late for meaningful change in
respect of ICTR defendants. As reported by Barbara Hola:
Between 1998 and 2015, the ICTR convicted 59 former gov-
ernmental and public officials, military, militiamen, journalists,
clergy and businessmen for their involvement in the genocide
of Rwanda’s Tutsis. By now […] twenty-one have been set
free from prisons in West Africa and Europe. Only five served
their whole sentences. 168
That said, important ICTR defendants are still incarcerated and re-
forming the early release regime may yet have a significant impact. Most
prominently, using the two-thirds rule, Théoneste Bagosora, the chief archi-
tect of the Rwandan Genocide, often referred to as ‘Rwanda’s Himmler’, is
now eligible for early release. 169 It is a given that he will file an early re-
168
Hola, 5 July 2019, see above note 6. As Hola notes, “[t]he proportion of those who were
granted early release before serving their full sentence is even higher at the ICTY. Out of 59
individuals who are by now out of prison, 55 (93%) have been released early by the Yugo-
slav Tribunal”. Ibid.
169
McGreal, 18 December 2008, see above note 16. As McGreal notes:
You might call him the Heinrich Himmler of Rwanda. Theoneste Bagosora was less
grand than the Nazi SS leader, eschewing pitch-black uniforms and grand military pa-
rades, but he espoused an ideology as hateful and ultimately as deadly as the man who
oversaw the Holocaust. And he was just as organised […] Bagosora was at the centre of
what the prosecution called ‘preparing the apocalypse’.
Bagosora was originally sentenced to life in prison but the sentence was reduced on ap-
peal to 35 years. See “Rwanda Genocide: Bagosora’s Life Sentence Reduced”, BBC News,
lease application, and so the clock is ticking. A lack of ethical and proce-
dural integrity has already resulted in the unjust early release of the
‘Rwandan Goebbels’; it is hoped that an integrity course correction will
mean a different result for the ‘Rwandan Himmler’.
14 December 2011 (available on its web site). Using the two-thirds formula, he is eligible
for early release beginning in July 2019. Hola, 5 July 2019, see above note 6.
27.1. Introduction
The legal profession has existed for over two thousand years. From the
Greek city-states and the Roman Empire to the present day, lawyers have
actively executed a vital role in the formulation and application of the law. 1
Because of this role and the nature of their duties and obligations to their
clients, lawyers are subjected to a higher standard of conduct than most
citizens in terms of personal integrity, professional conduct and ethics. Yet
the role of the judge is separate and apart from that of others in the legal
profession. Judges occupy the most prestigious role in the profession, hold-
ing positions of authority which presuppose respect for the highest stand-
ards of personal and moral responsibility. As a result, judges are expected
*
Judge Ivana Hrdličková holds a Ph.D. from Charles University. She is the President of the
Special Tribunal for Lebanon (‘STL’). She began her career as a Judge in the Czech Repub-
lic in 1990 and has presided over both civil and criminal cases. Since 2008, Judge Hrdličko-
vá also acts as a legal expert of the Council of Europe. She participated in a number of in-
ternational legal and judicial projects, such as the Euro-Mediterranean efforts to increase ju-
dicial co-operation between the Mediterranean-European Development Agreement countries.
Adrian Plevin obtained his LL.M degree from Leiden University. He is a Legal Officer in
the Office of the President and Appeals Chamber of the STL. He began his career in domes-
tic civil and criminal litigation practice, serving as a member of the Human Rights Commit-
tee of the Law Society of South Australia. He has since held positions in the Appeals Cham-
ber and Office of the President of the United Nations International Criminal Tribunal for the
former Yugoslavia (‘ICTY’). The authors are indebted to Nicolas Guillou, Cécile Ouba and
Helen Brown for their comments and contributions to earlier iterations of this chapter. Any
errors or inaccuracies remain the authors’ alone. The opinions, views, conclusions and rec-
ommendations contained in this chapter are expressed by the authors in their private capaci-
ty and do not necessarily reflect those of any respective national judiciary, the STL or ICTY,
nor can be attributed to those entities and institutions, nor the United Nations in general.
1
See, for example, Anton Hermann Chroust, “Legal Profession in Ancient Athens”, in Notre
Dame Law Review, 1954, vol. 29, no. 4, pp. 339–389; Anton Hermann Chroust, “Legal Pro-
fession in Ancient Imperial Rome”, in Notre Dame Law Review, 1955, vol. 30, no. 4,
pp. 521–616; Edward M. Harris and Lene Rubinstein (eds.), Law and the Courts in Ancient
Greece, Duckworth, London, 2004.
to adhere to even stricter standards than other lawyers. These factors are
equally true of the international judge. 2
Being an international judge entails occupying an office that society
views with prestige and vests with substantial power afforded only to a se-
lect few. At the same time, it presumes that the office-holder will embody
the highest standards of personal and professional moral conduct. For many,
being an international judge is more than a job; it is a calling and the cul-
mination of many years of experience in the profession. In this context, it
bears recalling the words of the American philanthropist J.D. Rockefeller
Jr., that “every right implies a responsibility; every opportunity, an obliga-
tion; every possession, a duty”. It is precisely because of the powers given
to international judges that it is crucial to ensure their responsibility and
accountability.
The accountability of judges entails, stricto sensu, an expectation of
transparent and well-reasoned decisions and judgments delivered in ac-
cordance with the law. In most jurisdictions, this is ensured through the
principle of open justice and by subjecting the vast majority of judicial de-
cisions to the possibility of appeal. 3 But judicial accountability is not lim-
ited to procedural remedies for litigants. It also entails accountability of the
judicial milieu: the responsibility of individual judges and judicial institu-
tions to perform their functions for the ultimate benefit of the communities
they serve, and the specific responsibility to account for the use of public
resources and expenditure of public finances. To adopt the words of Chief
Justice Tom Bathurst of the New South Wales Supreme Court:
The courts receive funds from the public purse. To my mind
that carries with it an obligation of accountability, not only to
deliver quality judgments, but to be able to demonstrate that
money is being spent efficiently. Accountability promotes
good decision-making and ensures that the power of courts to
spend money is not uncontrolled. 4
Bathurst distinguishes (legitimate) transparency and accountability
from (illegitimate) executive interference in the judicial branch. In this
chapter, we explore how the regulation of duties, obligations and responsi-
2
See Daniel Terris et al., The International Judge: An Introduction to the Men and Women
Who Decide the World’s Cases, Brandies University Press, Waltham, 2007.
3
See Tom Bathurst, “Separation of Powers: Reality or Desirable Fiction?”, Judicial Confer-
ence of Australia Colloquium, Sydney, 11 October 2013, para. 21.
4
Ibid., para. 22.
5
See, for example, Theodor Meron, “Judicial Independence and Impartiality in International
Criminal Tribunals”, in American Journal of International Law, 2005, vol. 99, no. 2, p. 359.
Throughout this chapter, the term ‘international judges’ is used in a general sense to denote
judges holding office at international courts and tribunals, irrespective of their status as na-
tional judges or international judges in the case of hybrid criminal tribunals such as the Spe-
cial Tribunal for Lebanon (‘STL’) or Extraordinary Chambers in the Courts of Cambodia
(‘ECCC’).
6
Morten Bergsmo, “Revisiting Integrity in International Justice”, FICHL Policy Brief Series
No. 93 (2018), Torkel Opsahl Academic EPublisher, Brussels, 2018, p. 1 (https://
www.toaep.org/pbs-pdf/93-bergsmo/).
7
Representatives of International Courts and Tribunals, Paris Declaration on the Effective-
ness of International Criminal Justice, 16 October 2017 (‘Paris Declaration’)
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/ow1amx/).
8
Honoré de Balzac, quoted in Otto Kirchheimer, Political Justice: The Use of Legal Proce-
dure for Political Ends, Princeton University Press, Princeton, 1961, p. 175. See Arthur
Selwyn Miller, “Public Confidence in the Judiciary: Some Notes and Reflections”, in Law
and Contemporary Problems, 1970, vol. 35, no. 1, p. 69.
9
Bergsmo, 2018, p. 2, see above note 6.
10
On the interplay between law, morality, and ethics, see, for example, Peter Michael Stephen
Hacker and Joseph Raz, Law, Morality, and Society: Essays in Honour of H.L.A. Hart, Clar-
endon Press, Oxford 1977; H.L.A. Hart, Law, Liberty, and Morality, Stanford University
Press, Stanford, 1963; Jocelyn M. Pollock-Byrne and Jocelyn M. Pollock, Ethics in Crime
and Justice: Dilemmas and Decisions, Brooks/Cole, Pacific Grove, 1989; Roscoe Pound,
“Law and Morals–Jurisprudence and Ethics”, in North Carolina Law Review, 1945, vol. 23,
no. 4, pp. 185–222; Joseph Raz, Ethics in the Public Domain, Clarendon Press, Oxford,
1994.
But what about when we speak of the intrinsically related yet sepa-
rate notion of integrity of judicial institutions? Here, integrity often de-
mands the adherence of individuals within a judicial system to a firm moral
code. But it also requires the application of rules or principles, by which
judicial institutions are governed, rather than the application of some com-
mon denominator of conduct of judicial office-holders. In this sense, the
strongest judicial institutions are those which are comprised of members
who uphold high standards of personal integrity and who are governed
equally by defined principles that permit institutional integrity to also
flourish. This notion was recognized in the preamble of the Bologna and
Milan Global Code of Judicial Ethics 2015, adopted at the International
Conference of Judicial Independence, which proclaims that:
Public confidence in the judicial system and in the moral au-
thority and integrity of the judiciary is of the utmost im-
portance in a modern democratic society and it is essential that
judges, individually and collectively, respect and honour judi-
cial office as a public trust and strive to enhance and maintain
confidence in the judicial system. 11
Maintaining public confidence in the integrity of the judiciary thus
requires not only the identification of applicable ethical and professional
standards, but the application and enforcement of them. Accountability,
therefore, serves as both a means of ensuring personal integrity of individ-
ual judges and as a method of assuring institutional integrity.
In the context of international criminal courts and tribunals, this insti-
tutional integrity is crucial to ensuring that international criminal justice
remains credible. Credibility does not demand that these courts and tribu-
nals strive for judicial outcomes that satisfy the interests of their myriad
stakeholders – such as prosecutors and defence counsel, victims of crimes,
accused persons, the legal community, civil society, or the States that pro-
vide the funding and diplomatic support necessary for these institutions to
function. Rather, credibility requires that stakeholders can be confident that
the exercise of judicial powers at these international bodies is professional,
ethical and motivated only by the fair interpretation and application of the
law, irrespective of the outcome of individual decisions.
11
Bologna and Milan Global Code of Judicial Ethics, June 2015, Preamble (‘Global Code of
Judicial Ethics’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/cq44mw/). See Bangalore Principles of
Judicial Conduct (‘Bangalore Principles’), 25–26 November 2002, Preamble
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/xwake8/).
12
The Republic of Kosovo, Law on Specialist Chambers and Specialist Prosecutor’s Office
(‘KSCSPO’), 3 August 2015, 05/L-053, Article 27(1) (‘Law on KSCSPO’)
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/8b71c3/); International Residual Mechanism for Criminal
Tribunals (‘IRMCT’), Statute of the International Residual Mechanism for Criminal Tribu-
nals, 22 December 2010, Article 9(1) (‘IRMCT Statute’) (http://www.legal-tools.org/
doc/30782d/); International Criminal Tribunal for Rwanda (‘ICTR’), Statute of the Interna-
tional Criminal Tribunal for Rwanda [as amended], 8 November 1994, Article 12 (‘ICTR
Statute’) (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/8732d6/); ICTY, Updated Statute of the Interna-
tional Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia, 25 May 1993, Article 13 (‘ICTY Statute’)
(http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/b4f63b/); Agreement between the United Nations and the
Lebanese Republic on the establishment of a Special Tribunal for Lebanon (‘STL Agree-
ment’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/e1635d/), Attachment: Statute of the Special Tribu-
nal for Lebanon, 30 May 2007, Article 9(1) (‘STL Statute’) (http://www.legal-tools.org/
doc/da0bbb/); Cambodia, Law on the Establishment of Extraordinary Chambers in the
Courts of Cambodia for the Prosecution of Crimes Committed during the period of Demo-
cratic Kampuchea (as amended), 27 October 2004, Article 10 new (‘Law on ECCC’)
(http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/9b12f0/); Agreement between the United Nations and the
Government of Sierra Leone on the Establishment of a Special Court for Sierra Leone, 12
April 2002 (‘SCSL Agreement’) (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/797850/), Attachment 1:
Statute of the Special Court for Sierra Leone, Article 13(1) (‘SCSL Statute’) (http://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/aa0e20/); Agreement between the United Nations and the Govern-
ment of Sierra Leone on the Establishment of a Residual Special Court for Sierra Leo-
ne(‘RSCSL’), 11 August 2010 (‘RSCSL Agreement’), Attachment: Statute of the Residual
Special Court for Sierra Leone, Article 11(2) (‘RSCSL Statute’) (http://www.legal-tools.org/
doc/4768bc/); Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court (‘ICC’), 17 July 1998, Arti-
cle 36.3(a) (‘ICC Statute’) (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/7b9af9/).
13
ICC Statute, Article 36.3(a), see above note 12; see ibid., Article 36.3(b); Law on KSCSPO,
Article 27(1), see above note 12.
14
Cf. IRMCT Statute, Article 9(1), see above note 12; ICTR Statute, Article 12, see above note
12; ICTY Statute, Article 9, see above note 12; SCSL Statute, Article 13(2), see above note
12.
15
STL Statute, Article 9(1), see above note 12.
16
Law on ECCC, Article 10 new, see above note 12; ICC Statute, Article 36.3(b), see above
note 12.
17
This expectation is given credence through the strong presumption in favour of judges satis-
fying these requirements (of impartiality) recognized in the jurisprudence of international
criminal tribunals. See, for example, ICTR, Nahimana v. The Prosecutor, Bureau, Decision
on Request for Disqualification of Judge Pocar, 6 June 2012, ICTR-99-52B-R, para. 9
(http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/c4c5ef/); ICTY, Prosecutor v. Furundžija, Appeals Chamber,
Judgement, 21 July 2000, IT-95-17/1-A, para. 197 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/660d3f/);
ICTY, Prosecutor v. Stanišić and Župljanin, Appeals Chamber, Judgement, 30 June 2016,
IT-08-01-A, para. 44 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/e414f6/); STL, In the matter of El
Sayed, The President of the Tribunal, Decision on Mr. El Sayed’s Motion for the Disqualifi-
cation of Judge Chamseddine from the Appeals Chamber Pursuant to Rule 25, 5 November
2010, CH/PRES/2010/09, para. 17 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/fda41c/); and decisions
of the plenary of judges of the international criminal court see, for example, ICC, Prosecutor
v. Nourain, Presidency, Annex to the Notification of the Decision on the Defence Request
for the Disqualification of a Judge, 5 June 2012, ICC-02/05-03/09-344-Anx (http://www.
legal-tools.org/doc/a15116/).
18
Expounding upon this view in the domestic context, Devlin and Dodek consider the ac-
countability of judges as one of the essential components of ensuring effective judicial inde-
pendence, together with selection criteria, the irremovability of judges, and the provision of
appropriate resources to the judiciary. Richard Devlin and Adam Dodek, “Regulating Judges:
Challenges, Controversies and Choices”, in Richard Devlin and Adem Dodek (eds.), Regu-
lating Judges: Beyond Independence and Accountability, Edward Elgar, Cheltenham, 2016,
pp. 5–11. But see Jeffrey L. Dunoff and Mark A. Pollack, “The Judicial Trilemma”, in
American Journal of International Law, vol. 111, no. 2, April 2017, pp. 225–276, who view
independence and accountability, along with transparency, as the three core values giving
rise to an interlocking series of trade-offs. Ibid., p. 225.
19
Throughout this chapter, the terms ‘international instruments’ and ‘international standards’
are used in a broad sense to denote instruments and standards adopted by States through the
UN General Assembly (‘UNGA’), by international organizations, such as the UN Economic
and Social Council (‘ECOSOC’), and through civil society organizations and initiatives. See
section 27.4. below.
20
UN, Basic Principles on the Independence of the Judiciary, 13 December (‘UN Basic Prin-
ciples’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/rnabsy/).
pable of implementation across all the world’s diverse legal systems and
cultures. 21 The Bangalore Principles, for example, describe ‘integrity’ as an
essential principle to the proper discharge of the judicial office, and empha-
size that a judge shall “ensure that his or her conduct is above reproach in
the view of a reasonable observer”. 22 They also state that “[t]he behavior
and conduct of a judge must reaffirm the people’s faith in the integrity of
the judiciary”. 23 The international standards examined in this chapter show
that this expectation is typically envisaged through the regulation of judges
through the prescription of standards of professional conduct, on the one
hand, and the existence of disciplinary mechanisms, on the other. 24
This leads us to conclude that the second aim for international courts
and tribunals, in order to ensure their integrity, is to strive for transparent
regulatory frameworks capable of ensuring professional and ethical con-
duct standards are consistently observed, applied and enforced. It is not
surprising, then, that the exploration of “individual awareness and integrity
as professionalism” and “institutional integrity measures available to inter-
national courts” are two of the key foci of the Integrity Project. 25 Cumula-
tively, these aims form a vital part of efforts to ensure a robust and trans-
parent system of international criminal justice, comprised of effective and
efficient bodies, capable of optimizing the resources provided to them in
pursuing justice for international(ized) crimes and protecting the funda-
mental rights of accused persons and the interests of victims.
27.3. Judicial Independence and Accountability
American statesman, and one of the founding fathers of the United States,
Alexander Hamilton, famously defended the role of the independent judici-
ary in his essay, Federalist No. 78, declaring:
Whoever attentively considers the different departments of
power must perceive, that, in a government in which they are
separated from each other, the Judiciary, from the nature of its
21
UNGA, Seventh United Nations Congress on the Prevention of Crime and the Treatment of
Offenders, UN Doc. A/RES/40/32, 29 November 1985 (https://www.legal-tools.org/
doc/qwiloh/); UN General Assembly, Human Rights in the Administration of Justice, UN
Doc. A/RES/40/146, 13 December 1985 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/qwiloh/).
22
Bangalore Principles, Article 3, see above note 11.
23
Ibid., Article 3.2.
24
See sections 27.4. and 27.5. below.
25
Bergsmo, 2018, pp. 2–3, see above note 6.
26
Alexander Hamilton, The Federalist Papers No. 78: The Judiciary Department (available on
the web site of the Congress of the United States of America).
27
Ernst-Ulrich Petersmann, “How to Constitutionalize International Law and Foreign Policy
for the Benefit of Civil Society”, in Michigan Journal of International Law, 1998, vol. 20,
no. 1, p. 13; cf. Dapo Akande, “The International Court of Justice and the Security Council:
Is There Room for Judicial Control of Decisions of the Political Organs of the United Na-
tions”, in International and Comparative Law Quarterly, 1997, vol. 46, no. 2, p. 309–343;
Stefan Talmon, “The Security Council as World Legislature”, in The American Journal of
International Law, 2005, vol. 99, no. 1, pp. 175–193.
28
Murray Gleeson, “The Role of the Judge and Becoming a Judge”, National Judicial Orienta-
tion Programme, Sydney, 16 August 1998.
29
Gerard Brennan, “Judicial Independence”, Australian Judicial Conference, Australian Na-
tional University, Canberra, 2 November 1996.
30
Hamilton, 1999, pp. 463–471, see above note 26.
31
England and Wales High Court (King’s Bench Division), R v. Sussex Justices, ex parte
McCarthy, Decision, 9 November 1923, [1924] 1 KB 256, p. 259. See Bangalore Principles,
Article 32, see above note 11.
32
Cf. Brennan, 1996, see above note 29.
33
See section 27.4 below.
34
See, for example, Amy B. Atchison, et al., “Judicial Independence and Judicial Accountabil-
ity: A Selected Bibliography”, in Southern California Law Review, 1998, vol. 72, no. 2–3,
pp. 723–810; Paul D. Carrington, “Judicial Independence and Democratic Accountability in
Highest State Courts”, in Law and Contemporary Problems, 1998, vol. 61, no. 3, pp. 79–126;
Francseco Contini and Richard Mohr, “Reconciling Independence and Accountability in Ju-
dicial Systems”, in Utrecht Law Review, 2007, vol. 3, no. 2, pp. 26–43; Consultative Coun-
cil of European Judges (‘CCJE’), Opinion No. 1 on Standards concerning the Independence
of the Judiciary and the Iremmovability of Judges, 23 November 2001 (http://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/ca5224/); CCJE, Opinion No. 3 on the principles and rules governing judges’
professional conduct, in particular ethics, incompatible behaviour and impartiality, 19 No-
vember 2002 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/81c8b5/); Devlin and Dodek, 2016, pp. 1–33,
see above note 18; Nuno Garoupa and Tom Ginsburg, “Guarding the Guardians: Judicial
Councils and Judicial Independence”, in The American Journal of Comparative Law, 2009,
vol. 57, no. 1, pp. 103–134; Charles H. Geyh, “Judicial Independence, Judicial Accountabil-
ity, and the Role of Constitutional Norms in Congressional Regulation of the Courts”, in In-
diana Law Journal, 2003, vol. 78, no. 1, pp. 153–221; Hoong Phuon Lee (ed.), Judiciaries
in Comparative Perspective, Cambridge University Press, 2011; Andrew Le Sueur, “Devel-
oping Mechanisms for Judicial Accountability in the UK”, in Legal Studies, 2004, vol. 24,
no. 1–2, pp. 73–98; Carlos Santiso, “Economic Reform and Judicial Governance in Brazil:
Balancing Independence with Accountability”, in VII Congresso Internacional de CLAD so-
bre la Reforma del Estado y de la Adminstración Pública, Panama, 28–31 October 2003,
pp. 1–16; Shimon Shetreet, “Judicial Independence and Accountability in Israel”, in Interna-
tional and Criminal Law Quarterly, 1984, vol. 33, no. 4, pp. 979–1012; Frances Kahn
Zemans, “The Accountable Judge: Guardian of Judicial Independence”, in Southern Cali-
fornia Law Review, 1999, vol. 72, pp. 625–655. The authorities cited in this footnote, and
footnotes 35 and 36 below, are not intended to represent exhaustive lists.
35
See Dunoff and Polack, 2017, see above note 18; Kenneth J. Keith, “Challenges to the Inde-
pendence of the International Judiciary”, International Law Programme Speech Transcript,
Chatham House, 26 November 2014; Kenneth J. Keith, “Challenges to the Independence of
the International Judiciary: reflections on the International Court of Justice”, in Leiden
Journal of International Law, 2017, vol. 30, no. 1, pp. 153–154.
36
See, for example, Michael G. Karnavas, “Judicial Ethics in the International Tribunals”,
drawn from Michael G. Karnavas’s lecture at the ADC-ICTY Twelfth Defence Symposium,
24 January 2014, Paul Mahoney, “The International Judiciary – Independence and Account-
ability”, in The Law and Practice of International Courts and Tribunals, 2008, vol. 7,
pp. 313–349.
37
R. Mackenzie and P. Sands, “International Courts and Tribunals and the Independence of the
International Judge”, in Harvard International Law Journal, 2003, vol. 44, pp. 271, 275.
38
On the academic debate in this context, see Lorne Neudorf, The Dynamics of Judicial Inde-
pendence, Springer, Cham, 2017, pp. 1–9.
39
UN, Universal Declaration of Human Rights, UN Doc. A/RES/217(III) A, 10 December
1948, Article 10 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/085437/).
40
UN, International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights, 23 March 1976, Articles 14, 26
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/2838f3/).
41
International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights, 3 January 1976, Preamble
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/06b87e/).
42
UN Basic Principles, Article 18, see above note 20. See also ibid., Preamble.
43
Bangalore Principles, Article 1, see above note 11.
44
Ibid., Preamble.
45
Commonwealth Heads of Government, Commonwealth (Latimer House) Principles on the
Three Branches of Government, November 2003, Article VII(b) (‘Latimer House Principles’)
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/c502bd/).
46
See, for example, Law on ECCC, Articles 41, 42 new, see above note 12; ICTY Statute,
Article 30(2), see above note 12; ICTR Statute, Article 29(2), see above note 12; STL
Agreement, Article 11, see above note 12; SCSL Agreement, Article 12(2), see above note
12. In the case of the KSCSPO, see Law on KSCSPO, Article 56.1, see above note 12 and
Netherlands-Kosovo, Agreement between the Kingdom of the Netherlands and the Republic
of Kosovo concerning the Hosting of the Kosovo Relocated Specialist Judicial Institution in
the Netherlands, 15 February 2016, Article 19 (‘KSCSPO Agreement’) (https://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/muyojl/). In respect of the RSCSL, see RSCSL Agreement, Article 10(1), see
above note 12 and UNGA, Convention on the Privileges and Immunities of the United Na-
tions, 13 February 1946, Section 20 (‘Privileges and Immunities Convention’)
(http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/f68109/).
47
For most international criminal tribunals, this power lies with the UN Secretary-General.
See STL Agreement, Article 11(2), see above note 12; Vienna Convention on Diplomatic
Relations, 18 April 1961, Article 32 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/fda998/). In the case of
the KSCSPO, the power appears to be vested with the President. See KSCSPO Agreement,
Article 30, see above note 46, referring to Kosovo, Law No. 04/L-274, On the Ratification
of the International Agreement between the Republic of Kosovo and the European Union on
the European Rule of Law Mission in Kosovo, 23 April 2014, Article 1.2.3, in turn, referring
to Kosovo, On the Status, Immunities and Privileges of Diplomatic and Consular Missions
and Personnel in Republic of Kosovo and of the International Military Presence and Its Per-
sonnel, 20 February 2008, Article 7. In respect of the RSCSL, see RSCSL Agreement, Arti-
cle 10(1), see above note 12, and Privileges and Immunities Convention, Section 20, see
above note 46.
48
Mackenzie and Sands, 2003, p. 275, see above note 37.
49
See, for example, Council of Europe (‘CoE’), European Convention on Human Rights, 4
November 1950, Article 23(4) (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/8267cb/); Organization of
American States (OAS) General Assembly, Statute of the Inter-American Court of Human
Rights, 1 October 1979, Article 20(1) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/3eb97d/); ICC Stat-
ute, Article 46.1, see above note 12; UN, Statute of the United Nations Administrative Tri-
bunal, 24 November 1949, Article 3(3) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/fwa4o9/); UN,
Statute of the International Court of Justice, 18 April 1946, Article 18 (https://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/fdd2d2/); UNGA, Administration of Justice at the United Nations, UN Doc.
A/RES/63/253, 24 December 2008, Annex I, Article 4(10) and Annex II, Article 3(10)
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/56xnx6/); International Tribunal on the Law of the Sea,
Statute of the International Tribunal for the Law of the Sea (Annex VI of the United Nations
Convention on the Law of the Sea), 10 December 1982, Article 9 (https://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/zlbrua/).
can be raised against judges and that judges are answerable for their actions
to an appropriate authority, in order to ensure that they comply with core
ethical principles and standards of conduct. Indeed, we can say that there is
a positive correlation between judicial accountability, on the one hand, and
effective judicial independence, on the other. In this sense, judicial ac-
countability is one among a number of key concepts central to promoting
and protecting judicial independence. Other such concepts include the
character requirements individuals must meet in order to be appointed to
judicial office in the first place, 50 the requirement that the judiciary be sup-
plied with appropriate resources to enable it to carry out its functions free
from external interference, and the general irremovability of judges. 51
Accountability serves as an agent of strengthening effective, inde-
pendent judiciaries for at least two principal reasons:
1. First, effective regulation is essential to ensure that all users of the ju-
dicial system – including judges themselves – know what is expected
of them, what they can do, and what they cannot do in the performance
of their duties. While this may seem self-evident, the reality of hybrid-
ized international criminal justice is that what may be considered total-
ly acceptable under the domestic legal tradition of one actor may be
considered unethical or improper in another. Insofar as international
criminal courts and tribunals are sui generis, the point must be made
that the creation of these institutions did not in and of itself instil them
with clear judicial ethical standards or professional conduct rules. All
the while, the judges appointed to these tribunals come from disparate
legal traditions, and no sui generis system of judicial ethics was likely
to emerge in a regulatory vacuum organically. Regulation then serves,
first and foremost, as a means of identifying – in a more concrete
manner than the references in foundational texts to ‘highest moral
standards’, ‘impartiality’ and ‘integrity’ – the professional and ethical
conduct standards that judges are expected to uphold.
2. Second, any judiciary is ultimately an arm of government, 52 and judg-
es ultimately perform a civil service, even if their independence makes
50
See Silvia Fernández de Gurmendi, “Judges: Selection, Competence, Collegiality”, in Amer-
ican Journal of International Law Unbound, 2018, vol. 112, pp. 163–167.
51
See Devlin and Dodek, 2016, pp. 5–11, see above note 18.
52
Bathurst, 1996, para. 3, see above note 3.
53
Ibid., para. 16.
54
Tim Dare, “Discipline and Modernize: Regulating New Zealand Judges”, in Devlin and
Dodek (eds.), Regulating Judges: Beyond Independence and Accountability, Edward Elgar,
Cheltenham, 2016, pp. 293–312, 295.
59
The Committee of Experts was organized jointly by the International Association of Penal
Law, the International Commission of Jurists, and the Centre for the Independence of Judges
and Lawyers.
60
See International Institute of Higher Studies in Criminal Sciences (‘IIHSCS’), “Draft Princi-
ples on the Independence of the Judiciary”, in Reed Brody (ed.), Centre for Independence of
Judges and Lawyers, No. 25–26, p. 59 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/p5qixp/).
61
Ibid., Article 13, see ibid., Articles 14–15.
62
Ibid., Article 16.
63
Ibid., Article 14.
64
Ibid., Article 23.
65
International Bar Association (‘IBA’), “Minimum Standards of Judicial Independence”, in
Reed Brody (ed.), Centre for Independence of Judges and Lawyers Bulletin, No. 25–26,
p. 105 (‘New Delhi Code’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/p5qixp/).
66
Ibid., Article 28.
67
Ibid., Article 31.
matters”. 68 The New Delhi Code also specified that, whether or not pro-
ceedings were in camera or public, judgments may be published. 69
The following year saw the adoption of the Universal Declaration on
the Independence of Justice at the First World Conference on the Independ-
ence of Justice in Montreal (‘Montreal Declaration’). 70 Uniquely, the Mon-
treal Declaration was the first instrument to recognize the distinction be-
tween principles applicable to national and international judges, respec-
tively. In respect of removal and discipline of judges, while the provisions
relating to national judges develop upon the Syracuse Principles and New
Delhi Code, 71 those relating to international judges are relatively barren,
providing that judges can only be removed from office by other members
of their court and in accordance with their Statutes. 72 Nominally rejecting
the universality of the principles applicable to domestic judges to interna-
tional judges, the Montreal Declaration also calls for the context-specific
application of conduct rules to ad hoc judges and arbitrators. 73
Although the Syracuse Principles, New Delhi Code and Montreal
Declaration represent international civil society initiatives (albeit with the
heavy involvement of judges from various legal systems), the ideas they
espouse largely inspired other instruments that were created in a multilat-
eral context in the years and decades that followed. Despite their nuances
and the key differences described above, these early texts otherwise remain
remarkably similar in scope and content. While in practical terms, this sim-
ilarity might be attributable to the involvement of key individuals in their
creation, 74 the very fact that the principles were adopted in a range of inter-
national fora speaks to their universal appeal.
68
Ibid., Article 32.
69
Ibid., Article 28.
70
Universal Declaration on the Independence of Justice, 10 June 1983 (‘Montreal Declaration’)
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/p6ek6z/).
71
For example, by providing for the presumption of confidentiality of complaints at the initial
stage, providing for the right of appeal, and providing protections for judges serving in
courts that are abolished. Montreal Declaration, Articles 2.32, 2.37, 2.39, see above note 70.
72
Ibid., Articles 1.18–1.19.
73
Ibid., Article 1.20.
74
See Neudorf, 2017, p. 4, see above note 38.
75
UN Basic Principles, see above note 20; see Neudorf, 2017, p. 4, see above note 38.
76
See above Section 27.2.
77
UN Basic Principles, Preamble, see above note 20.
78
Ibid., Article 1.
79
See, for example, ibid., Articles 1–7 (Independence of the judiciary), 8–9 (Freedom of ex-
pression and association), 11–14, (Conditions of service and tenure), 15–16 (Professional
secrecy and immunity).
80
See ibid., Articles 17–20.
81
Ibid., Article 17.
82
Ibid.
83
Ibid., Article 18.
84
Ibid., Article 20.
85
Ibid.
86
Singhvi Declaration, p. 1, see above note 58.
87
Ibid., Article 26(b).
88
Ibid., Article 30.
89
Ibid., Article 27.
90
Ibid., Article 28.
91
Ibid., Article 29.
Guidelines concern the separation of powers and ‘trias politica’ at the do-
mestic level and, in relation to the judiciary, echoed the core recommenda-
tions of earlier documents, limiting the grounds for removal of judges, 100
recognizing the legitimate role of independent disciplinary tribunals and of
the chief judge of the courts in disciplinary proceedings, 101 and also provid-
ing for the legitimate public criticism of judicial performance as a means of
ensuring accountability. 102 Importantly, they also called for the adoption of
codes of ethics to be developed and adopted by each judiciary as a means
of ensuring accountability. 103 The Latimer House Guidelines were supple-
mented by the Latimer House Principles, adopted by the Commonwealth
Heads of Government in 2003. The Latimer House Principles recognized
that:
Judges are accountable to the Constitution and to the law
which they must apply honestly, independently and with in-
tegrity. The principles of judicial accountability and independ-
ence underpin public confidence in the judicial system and the
importance of the judiciary as one of the three pillars upon
which a responsible government relies. 104
The Principles called for any disciplinary procedure to be “fairly and
objectively administered”, and prescribed that “proceedings which might
lead to the removal of a judicial officer should include appropriate safe-
guards to ensure fairness”. 105
27.4.4. Judicial Regulation in the Twenty-First Century
Perhaps the most important international instrument regarding judicial ac-
countability is the Bangalore Principles of Judicial Conduct. 106 Two rea-
sons are noteworthy: the duration and breadth of consultations leading to
its adoption – which involved judges from common law and civil law ju-
risdictions, as well as judges of the International Court of Justice and the
UN Special Rapporteur on the Independence of Judges and Lawyers, Dato′
Param Cumaraswamy – as well as the prescriptiveness and detail of the
100
Ibid., Articles VI(1)(a)(i).
101
Ibid., Articles VI(1)(a)(i)–(ii).
102
Ibid., Articles VI(1)(a)(iii).
103
Ibid., Articles V(1)(a).
104
Latimer House Principles, Article VII(b), see above note 45.
105
Ibid.
106
Bangalore Principles, see above note 11.
107
Ibid., Preamble.
108
UN Office on Drugs and Crime, Commentary on the Bangalore Principles of Judicial Con-
duct, 2007, p. 5 (emphasis added). Elsewhere, Appleby, Le Mire, Devlin, Dodek, Dare, and
Cravens note the reluctance of common law jurisdictions (Australia, Canada, New Zealand,
and the United States) to embrace judicial regulation. See Gabrielle Appleby and Suzanne
Le Mire, “The Australian Judiciary: Resistant to Reform”, in Devlin and Dodek, 2016,
pp. 35–54, see above note 18; Sarah M.R. Cravens, “Regulating Judges in the United States:
Concerns for Public Confidence”, in Devlin and Dodek, 2016, pp. 390–407, see above note
18; Dare, 2016, pp. 295–296, see above note 54; Richard Devlin and Adam Dodek,
“‘Fighting Words’: Regulating Judges in Canada”, in Devlin and Dodek, 2016, pp. 76–104,
see above note 18.
109
UN Commission on Human Rights, Independence and Impartiality of the Judiciary, Jurors
and Assessors and the Independence of Lawyers, 23 April 2003, p. 1 (https://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/17afdm/); ECOSOC, Strengthening Basic Principles of Judicial Conduct, UN
Doc. E/2006/INF/2/Add.1, 27 July 2006, para. 2 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/yiyqyy/).
110
Measures for the Effective Implementation of the Bangalore Principles of Judicial Conduct
(The Implementation Measures), 22 January 2010, p. 3.
111
Ibid., Article 15.1.
112
Ibid., fn. 9.
113
Ibid., Articles 15.2–15.4.
114
Ibid., Articles 15.5–15.6.
115
Ibid., Article 15.7.
116
Burgh House Principles on the Independence of the International Judiciary, August 2004
(‘Burgh House Principles’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/2cncgo/). See P. Sands et al.,
“The Burgh House Principles on the Independence of the International Judiciary”, in Law
and Practice of International Courts and Tribunals, 2005, vol. 4, no. 2, pp. 247–260.
117
See above note 27.
ty. 118 It also recommends that the governing instruments of the court shall
provide for appropriate measures, including the removal from office of a
judge, 119 and provides not for publication of disciplinary decisions, but
communication of the outcome of any complaint to the complainant. 120
These principles also appear in the Mount Scopus International Standards
of Judicial Independence, first adopted in 2008 and revised subsequently in
2011 and 2012. 121
When compared to the earlier European instruments, the CCJE’s
Magna Carta of Judges, adopted in 2010, is more detailed with respect to
judicial ethics and responsibilities, but less prescriptive in terms of the re-
quirements of disciplinary mechanisms. 122 Perhaps its key contribution to
regulation in this area is advocating for the creation of a Council for the
Judiciary or like body, “itself independent from the legislative and execu-
tive powers, endowed with broad competences” for all matters relating to
the status and organization of judges, that is, including disciplinary
measures. 123 Notably, the Magna Carta of Judges is intended to “apply mu-
tatis mutandis to judges of all European and international courts”. 124
In 2015, the Global Code of Judicial Ethics was adopted in an effort
to clarify standards of ethical conduct for judges and “to afford the judici-
ary a framework for regulating judicial conduct”. 125 Although its provisions
with respect to national judges and concerning ethical standards for inter-
national judges are far more prescriptive than those in the instruments that
preceded it, its provisions related to accountability mechanisms do not fur-
ther build upon the Burgh House Principles and Mt Scopus Standards. 126
118
Burgh House Principles, Article 17.1, see above note 116.
119
Ibid., Article 17.3.
120
Ibid., Article 17.4.
121
Mount Scopus Standards on the Independence of Judges, 19 March 2008, Articles 26.1–26.4
(‘Mt. Scopus Standards’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/gciwle/).
122
See CCJE, Magna Carta of Judges (Fundamental Principles), 19 November 2010, Articles
18–22 (‘Magna Carta of Judges’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/r7r1c2/). These funda-
mental principles built upon earlier studies of the CCJE in relation to the independence of
the judiciary. See CCJE, 2001, see above note 34; CCJE, 2002, see above note 34.
123
Magna Carta of Judges, Article 13, see above note 122.
124
Ibid., Article 23.
125
Global Code of Judicial Ethics, Preamble, see above note 11.
126
Ibid., p. 14.
127
See, for example, Alphons A.A. Orie, “Accusatorial v. Inquisitorial Approach in Internation-
al Criminal Proceedings Prior to the Establishment of the ICC and in Proceedings Before the
ICC”, in Antonio Cassese et al. (eds.), The Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court:
A Commentary, vol. 2, Oxford University Press, 2002, pp. 1439–1495 (http://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/01addc/).
1. The first was that available under Rule 15 of the ICTY Rules of Pro-
cedure and Evidence (‘RPE’), which enabled a party to seek the dis-
qualification of a judge where the judge has “a personal interest or
concerning […] or any association which might affect his or her im-
partiality”. 128 Analogous provisions were incorporated into the rules of
procedure and evidence of the ECCC, 129 the ICTR, 130 the SCSL, 131
and the STL, 132 as well as those of the International Criminal Court
(‘ICC’), 133 the Kosovo Specialist Chambers and Specialist Prosecu-
tor's Office (‘KSCSPO’), 134 the International Residual Mechanism for
Criminal Tribunals (‘IRMCT’), 135 and the Residual Special Court for
Sierra Leone (‘RSCSL’). 136
2. The second was by raising the issue through the course of litigation, as
was done, for example, by appellant Esad Lanžo, who complained in
arguments on appeal before the ICTY, that Judge Karibi-Whyte, the
Presiding Judge at trial, “was asleep during substantial portions of the
trial”. 137
The effectiveness of such mechanisms as a means for adjudicating
judicial conduct or capacity, however, is questionable. 138 This is true in ab-
128
ICTY, Rules of Procedure and Evidence, 8 July 2015, Rule 15 (‘ICTY RPE’) (http://www.
legal-tools.org/doc/30df50/).
129
ECCC, Internal Rules (Rev. 9), 16 January 2015, Rule 34 (‘ECCC Internal Rules’) (http://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/b8838e/).
130
ICTR, Rules of Procedure and Evidence, 13 May 2015, Rule 15 (http://www.legal-tools.org/
doc/c6a7c6/).
131
SCSL, Rules of Procedure and Evidence, 31 May 2012, Rule 15 (http://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/4c2a6b/).
132
STL, Rules of Procedure and Evidence, 10 April 2019, Rule 25 (https://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/qop639/).
133
ICC, Rules of Procedure and Evidence, 9 September 2002, Rule 43 (‘ICC RPE’)
(http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/8bcf6f).
134
KSCSPO, Rules of Procedure and Evidence before the Kosovo Specialist Chambers includ-
ing Rules of Procedure for the Specialist Chamber of the Constitutional Court, 25 August
2017, Rule 20 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/opmwoy/).
135
IRMCT, Rules of Procedure and Evidence, 18 December 2019, MICT/1/Rev.6, Rule 18
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/n7lau1/).
136
RSCSL, Rules of Procedure and Evidence of the Residual Special Court for Sierra Leone (as
revised), 6 November 2018, Rule 15 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/76a01e/).
137
ICTY, Prosecutor v. Delalić et al., Appeals Chamber, Judgement, 20 February 2001, IT-96-
21-A, para. 620. (‘Čelebići Case’) (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/051554/).
138
See Sands et al., 2005, p. 247, see above note 116.
stracto, as these procedures are only available to the litigating parties, and
thus exclude any prospect of other persons raising complaints regarding
judicial misconduct or incapacity. 139 It is also true in concreto. For example,
while the ICTY Appeals Chamber found that Judge Karibi-Whyte’s con-
duct “cannot be accepted as appropriate conduct for a judge”, 140 there is no
indication of whether any disciplinary action was taken against Karibi-
Whyte. To the contrary, Landžo’s Counsel was chastised for raising this
“opportunistic” ground of appeal rather than addressing the issue during
trial. 141 Indeed, according to the Appeals Chamber, the complaint of Kari-
bi-Whyte’s sleeping was only ever secondary to Counsel’s primary motiva-
tion, namely complaining about Karibi-Whyte’s “lack of judicial tempera-
ment, self-restraint and common decency”, 142 which itself was neither
raised before nor addressed by, the ICTY Appeals Chamber.
139
But, as is inherently recognized in codes of conduct subsequently adopted by international
courts and tribunals, it is not only in-court behaviour or judicial decision-making that ought
to fall under the purview of regulated judicial conduct. See in this section below.
140
Čelebići Case, Judgement, para. 629, see above note 137.
141
Ibid., para. 650. For criticisms, see, for example, Michael Bohlander, “The International
Criminal Judiciary – Problems of Judicial Selection, Independence and Ethics”, in Michael
Bohlander (ed.), International Criminal Justice: A Critical Analysis of Institutions and Pro-
cedures, Cameron May, London, 2007, pp. 375–383 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/774cfc/
); Mark S. Ellis, Sovereignty and Justice: Balancing the Principle of Complementarity be-
tween International and Domestic War Crimes Tribunals, Cambridge Scholars Publishing,
Cambridge, 2014, pp. 259–261. While it is true that Judge Karibi-Whyte’s mandate as an
ICTY Judge was not renewed, in the words of Grunstein and Banerjee “it is unclear whether
this was related to his somnolence during the trial”, see Ronald R. Grunstein and Dev
Banerjee, “The Case of ‘Judge Nodd’ and Other Sleeping Judges—Media, Society, and Ju-
dicial Sleepiness”, in Sleep, 2007, vol. 30, no. 5, p. 627. Moreover, the Appeals Chamber did
not find that Karibi-Whyte’s conduct amounted to “serious misconduct or incapacity”,
which if it was considered as a basis for his non-renewal, is equally concerning. Cf. the situ-
ation of Judge Frederik Harhoff, an ad litem judge of the ICTY, whose removal from office
ultimately followed his disqualification, as he was not seized of any other judicial proceed-
ings. Harhoff was disqualified following the decision of a Panel of three judges assigned
under Rule 15 of the ICTY RPE, on the basis of their finding of apprehended bias following
the publication of a letter written by Harhoff, which it considered indicated ‘reasonably ap-
prehended bias in favour of conviction […] further compounded by [his] clear difficulty in
applying the current jurisprudence of the Tribunal’. See ICTY, Prosecutor v. Šešelj, Rule 15
Panel, Decision on Defence Motion for Disqualification of Judge Frederik Harhoff and Re-
port to the Vice-President, 28 August 2013, IT-03-67-T (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/
5b4aa1/). Whether or not Harhoff’s actions amounted to serious misconduct was not ad-
dressed by the Panel.
142
Čelebići case, para. 658, see above note 137.
143
ECCC, Co-Prosecutors v. Chea et al., Ieng Sary’s Application to Disqualify Judge Nil Nonn
Due to his Personal Admission that he has Accepted Bribes and Request for a Public Hear-
ing or in the Alternative Leave to Reply to any Submissions Presented by Judge Nil Nonn in
his Response to this Application, 14 January 2011, 002/19-09-2007-ECCC/TC (https://www.
legal-tools.org/doc/a48970/).
144
Ellis, 2014, p. 261, see above note 141. See ECCC, Co-Prosecutors v. Chea et al., Trial
Chamber, Decision on Ieng Sary’s Application to Disqualify Judge Nil Nonn and Related
Requests, 28 January 2011, 002/19-09-2007-ECCC/TC, para. 9 (‘Nil Nonn case’) (http://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/e3e419/).
145
Nil Nonn case, para. 15 (emphasis added), see above note 144.
146
See above section 27.2.
147
ICC Statute, Article 46.1(a) see above note 12.
148
Ibid.
Statute. 149 Separate provisions in the ICC Statute provide for complaints
relating to, and the imposition of disciplinary measures for, “misconduct of
a less serious nature”, 150 a concept which is defined in the ICC RPE. 151
27.5.2. Codes of Conduct and Accountability Mechanisms
In addition to its regulatory framework, the judges of the ICC were first
among their counterparts at other contemporary international criminal
courts and tribunals to adopt a Code of Judicial Ethics. 152 They did so in
March 2005, some three months prior to the issuance of the first indict-
ments against Joseph Kony and others. 153 By that point, the ICTY and
ICTR had adopted Codes of Professional Conduct for Counsel, 154 but had
not yet taken the step of introducing instruments concerning the profes-
sional conduct of judges. At the ECCC, inspiration appears to have flowed
from the ICC Judicial Code. The Plenary of Judges at the ECCC adopted
its Code of Judicial Ethics in September 2008, 155 some six months prior to
the commencement of the Extraordinary Chambers’ inaugural trial pro-
ceedings the following February. 156
Judicial conduct standards appear to have gained greater attention
towards the end of the decade that followed, as the original ad hoc tribu-
nals prepared to close, and the IRMCT assumed their residual jurisdictions.
In May 2015, the IRMCT adopted its first Code of Professional Conduct
for the Judges of the Mechanism. 157 While the ICTR had closed its doors
by the end of 2014, the trend of codifying judicial ethics was followed by
149
Ibid., Article 46.1(b). With respect to the operation of this complaints mechanism, see, for
example, ICC RPE, Rules 23–32, see above note 133.
150
ICC Statute, Article 47, see above note 12.
151
ICC RPE, Rule 25(1), see above note 133.
152
See ICC, Code of Judicial Ethics, 9 March 2005 (‘ICC Judicial Code’) (https://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/383f8f/).
153
ICC, “Kony et al. Case” (available on the ICC’s web site).
154
See ICTY, Code of Professional Conduct for Counsel Appearing Before the International
Tribunal, 22 July 2009, IT/125 REV. 3 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/rtgkbb/); ICTR,
Code of Professional Conduct for Defence Counsel, 14 March 2008 (https://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/51efe3/); ICTR, Standards of Professional Conduct Prosecution Counsel, 14
September 1999 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/nz7gv4/).
155
ECCC, Code of Judicial Ethics, 5 September 2008 (‘ECCC Judicial Code’) (https://www.
legal-tools.org/doc/5dys4p/).
156
ECCC, “Initial hearing in Case 001” (available on the ECCC’s web site).
157
IRMCT, Code of Professional Conduct for the Judges of the Mechanism, 11 May 2015,
MICT/14 (‘IRMCT Judicial Code’) (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/23cc92/).
the ICTY in July 2016, 158 and the latter’s code remained in effect until the
institution’s closure at the end of 2017. The STL also followed suit in 2016,
adopting its own Code of Professional Conduct for Judges in September of
that year. 159 As well as defining concepts of independence, impartiality,
integrity, confidentiality and diligence, 160 these ‘ethical codes’ and ‘codes
of conduct’ typically govern conduct during proceedings, public expression
and association, and extra-judicial activity. 161 In this way, they cover the
conduct of judges both inside and outside of the courtroom and their par-
ticular institution. When compared to the Global Judicial Code of Ethics,
however, it is clear that that the instruments adopted at the international
courts and tribunals are the far less prescriptive of the two.
Up to this point, the ICC was the only international criminal court or
tribunal with a formal process for hearing complaints against the judiciary
outside of the litigation context, and the only to provide the possibility of
their removal from office as a disciplinary sanction or in response to prov-
en incapacity. That changed following the first plenary of the Roster of
Judges of the Kosovo Specialist Chambers in March 2018. 162 The KSCSPO
judges adopted a Code of Judicial Ethics for Judges, mirroring the ICC’s
model that, in addition to defining “serious misconduct” and “misconduct
of a less serious nature”, 163 provided for a disciplinary procedure for re-
ceiving, handling and adjudicating complaints against judges. 164 In doing
so, the KSCSPO seems to have spurred a small flurry of activity at other
tribunals. The judges of the IRMCT adopted a revised Code of Professional
158
ICTY, Code of Professional Conduct for the Judges of the Tribunal, 6 July 2016 (‘ICTY
Judicial Code’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/55lsey/).
159
STL, Code of Professional Conduct for the Judges of the Special Tribunal for Lebanon, 27
September 2016, STL-CC-2016-04 (‘STL Judicial Code’) (https://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/oird6k/).
160
ECCC Judicial Code, Articles 1–5, see above note 155; ICC Judicial Code, Articles 3–7, see
above note 152; IRMCT Judicial Code, Articles 2–6, see above note 157; ICTY Judicial
Code, Articles 2–6, see above note 158; STL Judicial Code, Articles 2–6, see above note 159.
161
ECCC Judicial Code, Articles 6–8, see above note 155; ICC Judicial Code, Articles 8–10,
see above note 152; IRMCT Judicial Code, Articles 7–9, see above note 157; STL Judicial
Code, Articles 7–9, see above note 159. The ICTY Judicial Code notably contained no such
clause.
162
KSCSPO, First Report, 2016–2018, March 2018, p. 9.
163
KSCSPO, Code of Judicial Ethics for Judges Appointed to the Roster of International Judges
of the Kosovo Specialist Chambers, 14 March 2017, KSC-BD-01/COR2, Articles 13–14
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/wl7m65/).
164
Ibid., Articles 15–23.
Conduct for the Judges of the Mechanism in April 2018, this time incorpo-
rating a disciplinary procedure. 165 For its part, on 1 March 2018, the STL
adopted a Judicial Accountability Mechanism, annexed to its Conditions of
Compensation and Service of Judges, upon the extension of its renewable
mandate. 166
As will be seen in the following section, this trend towards formaliz-
ing regulation of judicial ethics and professional conduct standards 167 has
not been limited to the above internal regulatory documents. To the contra-
ry, the issue of judicial accountability has been recognized on the world
stage, as a core consideration for the future viability of international crimi-
nal justice.
27.5.3. The Paris Declaration: A Vision of the Future? 168
In the autumn of 2017, the National School for the Judiciary (École natio-
nale de la magistrature or ‘ENM’) of France hosted an expert conference
on the topic of the effectiveness of international criminal justice, chaired by
former ICC Judge, Bruno Cotte (‘Paris Conference’). Delegates included
the Presidents of four international criminal courts and tribunals, 169 the
Head of the International, Impartial and Independent Mechanism for Syria,
and the President of the Extraordinary African Chambers.
The Conference resulted in the adoption of the Paris Declaration on
the Effectiveness of International Criminal Justice, consisting of 31 sepa-
rate, though interrelated recommendations focused around the central
themes of predictability (and transparency), expediency, and judicial gov-
165
IRMCT, Code of Professional Conduct for the Judges of the Mechanism, 9 April 2018,
MICT/14/Rev. 1 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/5deknw/).
166
STL, Conditions of Service and Compensation of Judges of the Special Tribunal for Leba-
non, 9 February 2018, Annex 2: Procedure Establishing a Judicial Accountability Mecha-
nism.
167
Although a conceptual distinction could be made between judicial ethics (that is, factors
guiding judicial decision-making) on the one hand, and professional conduct standards (that
is, rules of conduct governing the behaviour of judges) on the other, no clear distinction ex-
ists in the various instruments adopted by the ECCC, ICC, ICTY IRMCT, KSCSPO or STL.
Indeed, the ethical codes and professional conduct standards are largely similar, despite the
different lexicon used. For present purposes, this chapter does not seek to distinguish ‘pro-
fessional conduct standards,’ of judges from ‘judicial ethics’ and the terms are used variably,
as complementary or interchangeable.
168
The authors were delegates at the Paris Conference on the Effectiveness of International
Criminal Justice, Paris, 16 October 2017.
169
Namely, ICC, ICTY, KSCSPO and STL.
177
Ralph Zacklin, “The Failings of Ad Hoc International Tribunals”, in Journal of International
Criminal Justice, 2004, vol. 2, no. 2, p. 543.
178
Theodor Meron and Maggie Gardener, “Introduction to the Symposium on the Rome Statute
at Twenty”, in American Journal of International Law Unbound, 2018, vol. 112, p. 155.
179
Andrew Murdoch, “UK Statement to the ICC Assembly of States Parties 17th Session, ICC
ASP, 17th Session”, Gov.uk, 5 December 2018 (available on its web site).
the context of strengthening the credibility of the ICC, that it “surely goes
without saying that the Court must act in accordance with the highest pos-
sible standards of good governance and professionalism”. 180 While nega-
tive perceptions of the credibility of international criminal justice and pro-
posals for reform are neither unique to the judiciary nor particularly new, 181
the prevalence of the phenomenon should not lead to a false assurance that
the problem is benign. One need only recall the forewarning of the Perma-
nent Representative of New Zealand, that “[w]hen a Court loses credibility
in the eyes of a large sector of community opinion, then those with political
and legislative responsibility have a right, and a duty, to act to restore that
credibility and effectiveness”. 182 If the independence of international crim-
inal courts and tribunals is truly valued, it is incumbent upon their judiciar-
ies to welcome changes that ensure that such a threshold of credibility loss
is never crossed.
Merits aside, the Paris proposal raises a number of questions that
would have to be answered before a viable joint disciplinary mechanism
could be established. These range from questions about sustainable funding
models, to issues of competence (for example, how it might be possible
that such a body could investigate and determine allegations of judicial
misconduct across various international courts and tribunals) and even
whether a new joint mechanism could complement, for example, the statu-
tory procedures provided for at the ICC.
Each of these questions are worthy of further discussion and merit
considered debate. The protection of legitimate judicial independence
should feature heavily in future discussions in this regard. One can envis-
180
Meron and Gardener, 2018, see above note 178.
181
See, for example, Antonio Cassese, Report on the Special Court for Sierra Leone Submitted
by the Independent Expert, 12 December 2006 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/6tr996/);
Silvia Fernández de Gurmendi, “Enhancing the Court’s Efficiency: From the Drafting of the
Procedural Provisions by States to their Revision by Judges”, in Journal of International
Criminal Justice, 2018, vol. 16, no. 2, pp. 341–361; Open Society Justice Initiative and Coa-
lition for International Justice, “Unfulfilled Promises: Achieving Justice for Crimes Against
Humanity in East Timor”, 2004, pp. 34–45 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/06eaf7/); Carsten
Stahn, “The Future of International Criminal Justice”, in Hague Justice Journal, 2009, vol. 4,
no. 3, pp. 257–266; Hans-Peter Kaul, “Construction Site for More Justice: The International
Criminal Court after Two Years”, in American Journal of International Law, 2005, vol. 99,
no. 2, pp. 370–384; Zacklin, see above note 177.
182
Jim McLay, “Report of the International Criminal Court: Statement delivered by H.E. Mr.
Jim McLay, Permanent Representative of New Zealand”, New Zealand Foreign Affairs and
Trade, 31 October 2013 (available on its web site).
age, however, an entity legally separate from any individual court or tribu-
nal bound by procedures consistent with internationally recognized mini-
mum standards. Inspiration might be taken from the procedures applied by
bodies such as the UN Office of Internal Oversight, as a means of ensuring
fair, transparent, investigations of judicial complaints. Disciplinary pro-
ceedings could be determined by disciplinary boards composed of mem-
bers with extensive judicial experience who are shortlisted, selected, or
nominated by the judiciary. All protections of a fair hearing could be guar-
anteed to judges, and fair, consistent and transparent complaints, investiga-
tion and disciplinary processes could contribute to improved public confi-
dence and a greater understanding of the almost unexplored field of inter-
national judicial legal ethics in practice.
There is also impetus for the initiatives on the international stage to
continue. It must be observed that the uniform international standards of
ethics and professional conduct for international judges are comparatively
scarce in detail when compared with standards for national judges. At the
same time, the progressive development of the international standards
demonstrates that there is room and opportunity for international criminal
courts and tribunals themselves to contribute to the establishment of norms.
Representative, round-table conferences, like the Paris Conference, could
take a central role, for example, in formulating a uniform code of conduct
for judges of international criminal courts and tribunals. This would not
only supplement the judicial ethics and conduct codes already in force at
existing international criminal courts and tribunals but could be an essential
step in paving the way for cross-institutional initiatives such as a joint ac-
countability mechanism.
27.6. Conclusion
If effective international criminal courts and tribunals are intended as a key
feature of international criminal justice, it is essential to ensure their proper
functioning and credibility. The legitimacy – if not the very survival – of
these institutions and the contemporary system of international criminal
justice as a whole, depends upon it. Ensuring the accountability of judicial
institutions and the integrity and impartiality of individual judges who hold
office is an essential component of continuing to guarantee fair, free, inde-
pendent trials in accordance with the highest international standards.
International criminal courts and tribunals have recognized this. Alt-
hough standards relating to international judges have developed slower
than those relating to national judges, the ICC, the IRMCT, the KSCSPO
and the STL have each adopted disciplinary mechanisms designed to en-
sure that complaints of misconduct can be raised, heard and adjudicated to
promote accountability without compromising legitimate judicial inde-
pendence. In doing so, these courts and tribunals have recognized the ac-
countability of judicial institutions and personnel as an absolutely essential
component of judicial independence. International justice has both the ca-
pacity and impetus, however, to consolidate efforts to improve effective-
ness, including in the oversight of judicial accountability. If the Global
Code of Judicial Ethics presents model ethical standards applicable to judi-
cial office-holders at international courts and tribunals, the Paris Declara-
tion’s proposal for a joint accountability mechanism could represent the
current gold-standard in ensuring the highest quality of regulation of judi-
cial accountability. As a potential next step, consistent with the develop-
ment of international standards on the independence of the judge, judiciar-
ies in international criminal courts and tribunals should move towards the
development of a more detailed code of conduct, applicable to all of their
judges.
In attempting to secure the long-term credibility and legitimacy of in-
ternational criminal justice, there is impulse for common ethical and pro-
fessional conduct minimum standards applicable to all judges serving in
this field, and for a joint accountability mechanism to ensure they are re-
spected. The Paris Declaration could prove to be the first step in this direc-
tion, yet the proposal for a joint accountability mechanism should not be
considered in isolation. Rather, it should be viewed alongside other pro-
posals for reform and improvement of judicial governance generally. 183
Moreover, calls for reform on the international stage should be considered
in context. Since the beginning of the contemporary era of international
standards of judicial regulation, efforts to strengthen judicial independence
and accountability have developed side-by-side. The development of ethi-
cal and professional standards and minimum guarantees of accountability
rightfully go hand-in-hand with efforts to bolster the independence of the
judiciary, stave off unwarranted encroachment on the exercise of judicial
powers, and improve the quality of justice and the rule of law.
183
See, for example, Fernández de Gurmendi, above note 50, identifying potential improve-
ments in the procedures used to appoint international judges.
Prosecutorial Language,
Integrity and Independence
Richard J. Goldstone *
28.1. Introduction
Politics plays a crucial role in international criminal justice. It shapes inter-
national criminal law and establishes the institutions of criminal justice.
Indeed, without the politics, there would be no international criminal jus-
tice. The politics is at play both externally and internally with regard to
every such judicial institution. External politics includes the inevitability
that State officials will seek, whether directly or indirectly, to influence de-
cisions made by international criminal courts. Internally, there is the reality
that some judges will attempt, directly or indirectly, to influence the policy
and decisions of the office of the prosecutor. Those forms of political pres-
sures are the reality and the background against which one should consider
the language used by international prosecutors and their integrity and inde-
pendence. In what follows, I will rely primarily on my own experiences as
the first chief Prosecutor of the United Nations International Tribunals for
the former Yugoslavia (‘ICTY’) 1 and Rwanda (‘ICTR’). 2
I would add that the actual and perceived integrity and independence
of international prosecutors are essential not only to the office of the prose-
cutor, but to the court as a whole. Without it, the court will lose critical
support from governments and the prosecutor will lose crucial respect, con-
fidence and trust from the judges. 3
*
Richard J. Goldstone is a retired Justice of the Constitutional Court of South Africa. He
served as the first Chief Prosecutor of the International Criminal Tribunals for the former
Yugoslavia and Rwanda.
1
Established by Security Council Resolution 827, UN Doc. S/RES/827 (1993), 25 May 1993
(http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/dc079b/).
2
Established by Security Council Resolution 955, UN Doc. S/RES/955 (1994), 8 November
1994 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/f5ef47/).
3
Morten Bergsmo, “Revisiting Integrity in International Justice”, FICHL Policy Brief Series
No. 93 (2018), Torkel Opsahl Academic EPublisher, Brussels, 2018, p. 1 (https://www.
toaep.org/pbs-pdf/93-bergsmo/).
4
Compare, in this regard, ibid., p. 2, sect. 3.
5
Statute of the International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia (‘ICTY’), 25 May
1993, Article 16(4) (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/b4f63b/).
6
UN Security Council, Resolution 936 (1994), UN Doc. S/RES/936 (1994), 8 July 1994.
had been issued and there was thus no reason for the judges and Prosecutor
not to confer. That situation changed immediately when the first indict-
ments were issued. The relationship between the judges and the Prosecutor
became more formal. In all of those interactions with the judges, the use of
careful language was essential. The relationship was fraught with the dan-
ger of compromising the independence of the judges and the Prosecutor as
well as the institution as a whole.
Equally important was the use of careful language in relation to
briefings of the media. There was intense public interest in the first truly
international criminal court, and favourable press was highly relevant to
receiving adequate funding from the then cash-strapped United Nations. I
had to present an optimistic face to the public without disclosing sensitive
information relating to the detail or direction of investigations. I had learnt
from my South African experiences that the only safe policy was to say
nothing to journalists ‘off the record’ that might be embarrassing if it came
to be made public. I found that an open and transparent relationship with
journalists was appreciated and received by them with understanding. Sub-
ject to those restraints, I regularly provided the media with background
briefings and, in particular, explained what was to come in the following
days. Only on one occasion did that policy lead to a journalist ignoring an
embargo by using the information prior to a public announcement. In that
exceptional case, the information reported was accurate, but it was hardly
fair to those journalists who had respected the embargo.
No international prosecutor can or should avoid contact with outside
agencies, whether governmental or private. On my appointment as chief
Prosecutor of both the ICTY and the ICTR, I took the view that it was not
appropriate for an international prosecutor’s office to send investigators or
other officers to work in any country without consulting the government of
such country. That applied, in my opinion, notwithstanding that my ap-
pointment had been made by the United Nations Security Council acting
under its peremptory Chapter VII powers. It was the politics of the situa-
tion that dictated a diplomatic approach. To that end, I visited the capitals
of the relevant European countries in the case of the ICTY and African
countries in the case of the ICTR. I met with the respective ministers of
justice and foreign affairs. The response, with one exception, was that my
investigators would be welcome to work in their countries. In most cases, it
was suggested that their names and the details of their visits should be con-
terests of any defendant. The information could only be made public with
the express consent of the provider of the information. 7 That rule has been
replicated with regard to the ICTR and the International Criminal Court.
Fortunately, as a United National official, I was co-opted to the dip-
lomatic circuit in The Hague. I found it extremely useful to attend national
day celebrations at the various embassies. I found that these were more
working occasions than solely social. At one point, because of the serious
state of the United Nations finances, all travel by United Nations officials
had been put on hold. This was disastrous for the work of the ICTY, where
travel was crucial to our investigators’ work. I inquired from the finance
office at United Nations headquarters in New York whether we could use
unallocated funds from the ICTY Trust Fund for travel. The curt and un-
specific response was that the funds were not available. That was strange
indeed. At a national day reception, the following day, I found myself
speaking with the Ambassador of Pakistan. I informed him of my problem.
I reminded him that Pakistan had donated USD 1 million to the ICTY Trust
Fund. I informed him that what I had told him was on the record and that I
would appreciate it if he were to request his colleague in New York to in-
quire from the United Nations Secretariat why the Trust Fund could not be
used for travel by ICTY investigators. Whether that request was the cause,
I do not know, but within 24 hours the consent to use those funds was
granted. I would stress, in the context of this book, that the language in
which my request was formulated was important. I was not giving the Am-
bassador information that might in any way compromise the independence
of my Office or of the ICTY.
28.3. Relationship with the United Nations Secretary-General
My earliest discussions at the United Nations were with the then newly ap-
pointed Deputy Secretary-General for Legal Affairs, former Ambassador
Hans Corell of Sweden. I should mention that Hans Corell soon became a
good friend and that friendship continues to the present day. During my
time as a United Nations international prosecutor, Corell, sometimes to my
frustration, refused ever to give me advice. He considered that my inde-
pendence was so central to my mission as chief Prosecutor, that it was not
consistent with that independence for a senior United Nations official to
7
ICTY, Rules of Procedure and Evidence, Rule 70(B) (adopted 11 February 1994, amended 4
October 1994, 30 January 1995 and 12 November 1997) (https://legal-tools.org/doc/
30df50/).
place in the same courtroom. My host was the Lord Mayor of the City of
Nuremberg. The invitation was extended to my wife as well as a colleague
and his wife. It was arranged that we would fly from Amsterdam to Nu-
remberg on a Saturday morning. On the Wednesday prior to our visit, I re-
ceived a call from the Chef de cabinet of the Secretary-General, Jean-
Claude Aimee. He informed me that the Secretary-General understood that
I was traveling to Nuremberg on the weekend. When I confirmed that in-
formation, he informed me that he had to convey an instruction from the
Secretary-General to the effect that I was not to travel to Nuremberg.
Somewhat shocked, I inquired as to the reason for the instruction. He in-
formed me that he had no idea. I told Mr. Aimee that unless there was a
very good reason for my not going to Nuremberg, I was not prepared to
embarrass either my Office or the Mayor of Nuremberg. I asked to speak to
the Secretary-General. He was in the air, said Aimee, and would be in his
office at about 21:30 CET that evening. I requested Mr. Aimee to inform
the Secretary-General that I wished to discuss his instruction with him. I
gave him the telephone number of our dinner host that evening, the then
President of the International Court of Justice. That evening, the Secretary-
General did indeed call. He confirmed the instruction and explained that
because of the serious state of the United Nations finances, he had had to
cancel travel by all United Nations staff. I informed the Secretary-General
that we were going to Nuremberg as the guests of the City of Nuremberg
and that it would not involve any funding at all from the ICTY or the Unit-
ed Nations. “Oh”, said the Secretary-General, “that is very different. Enjoy
your trip!”. I had shared my problem with the small dinner group assem-
bled. They were as puzzled as I had been and amazed at the response I had
received from the Secretary-General. We agreed that the incident exempli-
fied the manner in which Boutros-Ghali micromanaged the huge United
Nations bureaucracy, and that it was important that my independence al-
lowed me to question instructions from the Secretary-General.
In short, it is necessary for any international prosecutor to have fre-
quent interactions with governments and, in the case of a United Nations
tribunal, with the Secretary-General and other high United Nations officials.
It is crucial in those contacts to be transparent and to use language that is
calculated to make apparent the independence and integrity of the office of
the prosecutor.
8
UN Security Council, Resolution 955, 1994, see above note 2.
vember 1994, there were no United Nations funds available for the ICTR.
It was a donation to the United Nations Trust Fund for Rwanda from Swit-
zerland that made it possible for me to visit Kigali in the first week of De-
cember 1994. President Bizimungu and Deputy President Kagame were
welcoming and agreed to assist me in setting up an office. I doubt that they
would have been so accommodating if I had delayed a visit to Kigali.
In all of my dealings with regard to the ICTR, language played a cru-
cial role. The United States was insisting that the word ‘genocide’ should
not be used as that might place on it burdens under the Genocide Conven-
tion. 9 The Rwandan survivors and the government that had put an end to
the killing and violence had no doubt that genocide had been committed.
Until the evidence to establish the commission of genocide became over-
whelming, diplomacy and the prospect of garnering funding for the ICTR
compelled me to speak with great circumspection. I referred to slaughter,
massive war crimes and so forth. I could not afford to antagonise either
side.
On the government side, apart from the physical establishment of an
office with staff including experienced investigators, I required the assis-
tance of the Rwandan police to accompany and guarantee the safety of in-
vestigators and their staff when they travelled around the country. This was
forthcoming, but at a price. The police were tipped off as to the identity of
the witnesses, and frequently they would question the witnesses in the days
after our interviews with them. Fortunately, we were on the same side.
It was difficult to recruit staff prepared to work in the very difficult
circumstances that prevailed in the months after the genocide had come to
an end. Accommodation was at a premium and not very pleasant. For secu-
rity reasons, the United Nations was not prepared to allow families to ac-
company any member of the ICTR staff. We required experts with the abil-
ity to converse in both English and French. The Rwandan government was
not prepared to have French nationals in Rwanda as they regarded France
as having been complicit in the commission of the genocide. So, too, Alge-
rians. Fortunately, we were successful in recruiting top-rate French-
Canadians to work for us in Kigali, including the first head of investiga-
tions.
9
The Convention on the Prevention and Punishment of the Crime of Genocide was adopted
by the United Nations General Assembly on 9 December 1948 as General Assembly Resolu-
tion 260, UN Doc. A/RES/260 (III) (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/cee5ed/).
Particularly in the early days of the ICTR, the use of careful language
was crucial if the independence and integrity of the Tribunal and the Office
of the Prosecutor were to be recognised and respected. That recognition
had to come from the government of Rwanda, the United Nations and the
global community. The difficulty of my task was substantially eased by the
advice and friendship of the head of the United Nations Mission in Rwanda,
Shaharyar Khan of Pakistan. Ambassador Khan, a former Pakistan Ambas-
sador to France and High Commissioner to the United Kingdom, was a
consummate diplomat who efficiently and helpfully steered me through the
political jungle that then obtained in Rwanda.
Perhaps the most difficult negotiation with Rwanda related to the
transfer to the ICTR of the real architect of the genocide, Théoneste Bago-
sora. He had been arrested in Cameroon and requests for extradition had
been made by both Rwanda and Belgium. The Security Council resolution
and the Statute for the ICTR gave the Tribunal primacy, and I insisted that
the main perpetrator of the genocide should be brought to trial before the
ICTR. When I met with the whole Rwandan cabinet, I made it clear that,
rather than agree to Bagosora being transferred to Rwanda, I would suggest
to the Security Council that the mission of the ICTR be brought to an end.
After a tense and rather unpleasant meeting, the government of Rwanda
conceded. There were no courts then sitting in Rwanda and Bagosora
would likely have been murdered if he had been transferred to the custody
of the Rwandan forces. He was subsequently convicted by the ICTR on
charges including genocide and ultimately sentenced to 35 years in pris-
on. 10 Yet again, appropriate language was crucial both in my dealings with
the Rwandan government and in the public statements and press confer-
ences that followed. It was essential to uphold the independence of the
ICTR and at the same time to avoid, to the extent possible, embarrassing or
alienating the government of Rwanda.
28.5. Civil Society
Non-governmental organisations have played an important role with regard
to international criminal justice. It was their pressure that galvanised West-
ern States during 1993 to support the establishment of the ICTY and later
the ICTR. They publicised the reports of journalists emanating from the
war zones in the former Yugoslavia.
10
ICTY, Prosecutor v. Bagosora and Nsengiyumva, Appeals Chamber, Judgement, 14 Decem-
ber 2011, ICTR-98-41-A (https://legal-tools.org/doc/52d501).
It was civil society that began the successful campaign to have rec-
ognised what, for centuries, had been ignored: the role played by gender-
related crimes in warfare and, in particular, systematic mass rape. Reports
emerged early of gender crimes having been committed in both the former
Yugoslavia and Rwanda. Soon after I arrived in The Hague in August 1994,
I began to receive what became a deluge of letters, many hand-written,
pleading for me to give appropriate attention to the investigation of mass
rape as a method of warfare practised by the Serb forces in Bosnia and
Herzegovina. What impressed me was that the letters were not stereotyped.
They came from women and men in many countries. I was more impressed
than I would have been by a petition signed by many thousands of people. I
decided that all the letter-writers were entitled to a personalised response. I
appointed Patricia V. Sellers, one of the lawyers in my Office, to take care
of gender-related issues, both internal and external. One of her first tasks
was to draft appropriate responses to the many letters. It was important to
acknowledge the importance of the issue that had been raised and to make
it clear that their calls would receive a positive response from the Office of
the Prosecutor.
I also tasked Patricia V. Sellers with ensuring that any gender issues
in our Office were promptly and efficiently investigated and resolved. This
was important in an Office in which the largest department was the almost
all-male Investigations Section. It was difficult in the middle of the 1990s
to find experienced female police investigators who were willing to move
to The Hague to work for an ad hoc Tribunal. Fortunately, there were no
serious issues, and those that did emerge were efficiently and successful
handled by Sellers. It was important that at each monthly meeting of the
whole staff of the Office, I would stress the importance for the gender issue
and make it clear that Sellers was acting on my behalf and with my full au-
thority. On one occasion, it was necessary to reprimand members of the
Investigations Section for telling sexist jokes. I made it clear that how they
behaved in their own homes was their business, but how they behaved in
our Office was my business.
When one of the female judges on the ICTY, Elizabeth Odio Benito
of Costa Rica, raised the absence of a charge of rape in one of the very first
indictments, it was made clear to her that at that time the only reference to
rape in the Statute was to be found in the definition of crimes against hu-
manity. Such crimes required the commission of widespread or systematic
attacks, and that was not a case that we were able to make. Judge Odio Be-
nito suggested that rape be included in grave breaches of the Geneva Con-
ventions. Whatever the demerits of that suggestion, the combined effects of
the push from civil society and from the judges left little doubt that we
were being called upon to give priority to gender crimes. Similar pressure
came from the only female judge of the ICTR, Navi Pillay.
Very quickly, gender-related crimes were included in indictments,
and in the ICTR, Judge Pillay wrote the judgment in which, for the first
time, mass rape was recognised as an act of genocide. 11 The campaign con-
tinued into the debate on the Rome Statute for the International Criminal
Court. The holistic definition of gender crimes to be found in that Statute is
the result. 12
So again, language became all-important in the relationship between
the members of staff of the Offices of the Prosecutor of the ICTY and the
ICTR, and in the relationship between those Offices, the media, civil socie-
ty organisations and the general public.
28.6. Conclusion
I hope that I have been able to demonstrate the importance of language and
its relationship to the integrity and independence of an international prose-
cutor. The politics relating to international criminal justice lies at the heart
of the issues that arise on an almost daily basis. The obligations make it
essential to meet and negotiate with governments, the United Nations, and
non-governmental institutions, including the media.
There are always people who, for good reason or bad, are opposed to
the very concept of international justice. As Morten Bergsmo points out,
they are waiting to expose any inappropriate conduct and to magnify it in
the public domain. 13 The attack by John Bolton, former National Security
Adviser of the Trump Administration, is a case in point. 14 More recently,
similar attacks have been made by the present Secretary of State Pompeo. 15
11
ICTR, Prosecutor v. Akayesu, Trial Chamber, Judgement, 2 September 1998, ICTR-96-4-T
(http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/b8d7bd/).
12
Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court, 17 July 1998, Articles 7(1)(g),
8(2)(b)(xxii), and 8(2)(e)(vi) (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/7b9af9/).
13
Bergsmo, 2018, p. 1, see above note 3.
14
See Olivia Gazis, “In first major address, John Bolton attacks old foe”, CBS News, 10 Sep-
tember 2018.
15
See Marlise Simons and Megan Specia, “U.S. Revokes Visa of I.C.C. Prosecutor Pursuing
Afghan War Crimes”, New York Times, 5 April 2019.
*
David Donat Cattin is the Secretary-General of Parliamentarians for Global Action
(‘PGA’). Over the last 20 years, he has worked to promote the universality and effectiveness
of the Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court in approximately 100 countries. He
holds a post-doctorate diploma from the Centre for Studies and Research of The Hague
Academy of International Law (2002), a Ph.D. in Public International Law (2000) from the
Faculty of Law of the University of Teramo (Italy). His writings on international criminal
law appeared on well-known scholarly works, such as Triffterer’s Commentary on the Rome
Statute of the ICC, Nomos; Flavia Lattanzi and William Schabas, Essays on the Rome Stat-
ute of the ICC, il Sirente, vol. I, 1999, vol. II, 2004; and Larissa van den Herik and Carsten
Stahn, The Diversification and Fragmentation of International Criminal Law, Brill, 2012.
He co-edited and contributed to the book in honour of Professor (Judge) Flavia Lattanzi en-
titled International Law and the Protection of Humanity, Brill, 2016. Since May 2012, he
has been Adjunct Professor of International Law at New York University Center for Global
Affairs. Melissa M. Verpile is a senior legal officer of the International Law and Human
Rights Programme at PGA, specifically incorporating international legal standards to do-
mestic legislation to strengthen the rule of law and the protection of human rights. She holds
a Master of Laws (LL.M.) in US and Comparative Law from Fordham University School of
Law and a Master of Public Policy and Development from University Paris Descartes (Paris
V). She is fluent in French, English, Spanish, Italian, Haitian Creole and Portuguese.
1
Jens Steffek and Kristina Hahn (eds.), Evaluating Transnational NGOs: Legitimacy, Ac-
countability, Representation, Palgrave Macmillan UK, Springer, 2010.
137 national and regional legislative bodies are members of PGA. The Sec-
retary-General of PGA heads the Secretariat, based in New York and The
Hague, and is appointed by the Board of the organisation. The Board is
comprised of 15 parliamentarians elected every two years by the PGA In-
ternational Council, the representative body of the global membership
composed of National Groups. The Secretary-General (or the Secretariat)
has a duty to carry out the result-oriented implementation of the organisa-
tion’s strategic plan and vision with integrity and efficiency.
Regarding these elected positions, Board members may not be re-
elected for more than two consecutive terms of two years, while the Secre-
tary-General may not be appointed for more than three terms of three years.
This shows how the leadership of an NGO can be the democratic emana-
tion of its constituency, which demands that service to the organisation be
carried out in line with principles of transparency, effectiveness and ac-
countability. These principles do not substantially differ from those dis-
cussed in the context of public entities, including inter-governmental or-
ganisations. The perspective of an NGO whose leadership is chosen
through a democratic process is not substantially different from the per-
spective of other stakeholders from democratic institutions.
Given that States historically failed to prevent and punish interna-
tional crimes, the global membership of PGA determined that it was neces-
sary to create and support an international legal order in which the exercise
of international criminal jurisdiction would address the impunity gap while
obligating States to exercise their duty to prosecute domestically. This was
discussed in a several debates held during PGA’s Annual Fora and at meet-
ings of its Board and International Council. Such a strong policy framing
the work of PGA has been undertaken under the assumption that the ‘inter-
national rule of law’ is not yet a reality, but a goal to be attained through the
progressive development and codification of international law.
In the framework of the ‘Integrity Project’ of the Centre for Interna-
tional Law Research and Policy (CILRAP) and the International Nurem-
berg Principles Academy, contributors have been invited to reflect on dif-
ferent aspects of the role of the individual in international judicial institu-
tions. In view of the first seventeen years of ICC praxis, this chapter will
try to shed light on the interplay between the notion of integrity and the
maintenance of a core pillar of the judicial mandate, that is, the independ-
ence of judges and prosecutors.
2
The rule of law and transitional justice in conflict and post-conflict societies: Report of the
Secretary-General, UN Doc. S/2004/616, 23 August 2004 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/
77bebf). On 30 April 2004, PGA organized a roundtable with States’ representatives and UN
officials to provide input to the drafting of this definition. See PGA, Annual Report 2004,
p. 19.
3
Fragmentation of international law: Difficulties arising from the diversification and expan-
sion of international law, UN Doc. A/CN.4/L.682, 13 April 2006, p. 246, para. 486 (https://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/dda184): “A key point made in this study is that normative conflict
is endemic to international law. Because of the spontaneous, decentralized and unhierar-
chical nature of international law-making - law-making by custom and by treaty - lawyers
have always had to deal with heterogeneous materials at different levels of generality and
with different normative force.”
4
For a description of the Rome Statute as a self-contained system, see David Donat Cattin,
“Decision-making in the International Criminal Court: Functions of the Assembly of States
Parties and Independence of the Judicial Organs”, in Flavia Lattanzi and William Schabas
(eds.), Essays on the Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court-volume II, il Sirente,
2004, pp. 69–84.
5
See Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court, 17 July 1998, Article 25, Part 3 (‘ICC
Statute’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/e5faa8/).
who correctly apply the Rome Statute display a level of competence that
protects the institution from external attacks on the soundness of its deci-
sions. In the Rome Statute, integrity seems to refer to competence linked to
the professional responsibility of the judges and Prosecutor as well as to
the fact that these individual organs shall be – and perceived to be – incor-
ruptible and impartial in all situations and cases before them.
29.4. The Preservation of Independence and Integrity at the ICC
Despite its Assembly of States Parties (ASP)
The Rome Statute established a system which, notwithstanding its weak-
nesses, deserves to be protected, effectively implemented, and, when useful
and appropriate, reviewed, reformed and improved. To do so, all stakehold-
ers, including civil society organisations, should strive to reduce the influ-
ence of politics in the conduct of prosecutorial and judicial affairs, as much
as the reality allows for. Actors, including PGA, have a propensity to call
for criticism of the ICC on issues that have now become apparent to inter-
national law practitioners. However, caution is essential: safeguarding the
Rome Statute system has become a pressing matter, and criticism should be
delivered in a constructive manner.
Integrity is a central component of complementarity in the sense that
the ICC is a ‘court of last resort’ where States are unable or unwilling to act
to genuinely investigate and prosecute individuals allegedly responsible of
committing international crimes, which may be a question of national in-
tegrity. When situations of inability or unwillingness arise, it means that
there is a disintegration of the State or bad faith on the part of its authorities,
which may result in ‘sham justice’ or inertia. In the face of these situations,
which are not uncommon in the twenty-first century, we can no longer let
impunity reign at the international and domestic levels.
To achieve the goal of effectively fighting impunity, ICC organs must
be credible, effective and independent. Integrity is, therefore, a pre-
condition of the Court’s effective operations. The effective realization of
the object and purpose of the Rome Statute is to be understood as integral
to that exercise of integrity and independence.
The Rome Statute explicitly set a requirement to preserve the inde-
pendence of the judges from the influence of the executive branch of gov-
ernment, as “[j]udges shall not engage in any activity which is likely to in-
terfere with their judicial functions or to affect confidence in their inde-
States Parties should be fully aware of the object and purpose of the
Rome Statute, which is – as the Romans used to say, ‘repetita iuvant’ – “to
put an end to impunity for the most serious crimes of concern to the inter-
national community as a whole”, in accordance with the Preamble to the
Statute. Yet, some stakeholders of the Court, including States Parties to the
Rome Statute, may forget this object and purpose and focus on the national
interests of their country in their relations with the Court. Another scenario,
albeit less common, is that diplomatic personnel interfacing with the ICC
as an international organisation may give precedence to their personal
agendas over a common agenda to protect the integrity of the Rome Statute
system. Such personal considerations are legitimate; however, they do not
justify any departure from the standards outlined in the Rome Statute. The
level of commitment required to exercise a judicial function at the ICC is
higher than the one we may be witnessing in some instances today. It is
imperative to recall that 123 States Parties have joined this accountability
system, and one of the roles and responsibilities of the ASP is to adopt
measures that ensure the protection of the integrity and independence of the
Court.
29.5. Reconciling Ideals and Reality: A Functional Approach
Public international law practitioners recall vividly the process and the
principled ideals underlying the creation of the ICC, echoed in the Pream-
ble to the Rome Statute. Twenty-two years later, this project to prevent and
punish the perpetrators of genocide, crimes against humanity, war crimes
and the crime of aggression is under attack, by States Parties and non-
States Parties alike. In the framework of a politically intricate global con-
text, the international community needs to adjust its course.
If the ICC issues an arrest warrant against former President Omar Al
Bashir, accused of five counts of crimes against humanity, two counts of
war crimes, and three counts of genocide, 12 and the warrant fully satisfies
the legal requirements, all actors of the international community and, in
particular, representatives of ICC States Parties should be aware that they
are under the obligation to refrain from ‘shaking hands’ with Al Bashir, a
fugitive from justice. Yet, the 2018 proceedings on this prominent case be-
fore the Appeals Chamber revolved around issues (primarily raised by Jor-
12
See ICC, Prosecutor v. Omar Hassan Ahmad Al Bashir, The Appeals Chamber, Judgment in
the Jordan Referral re Al-Bashir Appeal, 6 May 2019, ICC-02/05-01/09 OA2 (https://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/0c5307).
dan and the rather non-ritual and unusual amici curiae, the League of Arab
States and the African Union 13) that are part of the body of international
law since the Allied powers issued the 1943 declaration in Moscow. Ac-
cording to the declaration, the leaders of Axis powers did not have immuni-
ty from prosecution if an international jurisdiction concluded that the evi-
dence against them proved their individual responsibility for international
crimes, as enshrined in the 1945 London Charter, ratified by all members
of the international community at the time. Therefore, the debates before
the ICC Appeals Chamber should not have revolved around Jordan’s obli-
gation to arrest Al Bashir. On 6 May 2019, the ICC Appeals Chamber con-
firmed the ICC Pre-Trial Chamber II’s decision regarding the fact that Jor-
dan failed to comply with its obligations under the Rome Statute by not
arresting Al-Bashir and surrendering him to the ICC while he was on Jor-
danian territory attending the League of Arab States’ Summit on 29 March
2017. Despite the determination of lack of co-operation, there was no con-
sequence for Jordan at the ASP level or at the level of the UN Security
Council, which referred the Darfur situation to the ICC pursuant to resolu-
tion 1593 on 31 March 2005, given that Jordan was deemed to be construc-
tively engaging with the ICC.
Dissent is a key tool to make advancements in any institutional
framework, including the Rome Statute system, and uncritical support may
be analogous to a ‘kiss of death’ and be as detrimental to the system as the
above-criticized failure of some States Parties to enforce the arrest warrants
against Omar Al Bashir when he was the President of Sudan. NGOs who
supported and continue to support the implementation of the Rome Stat-
ute’s mandate have often made critical assessments of the ICC organs’ per-
formance at various stages of its institutional development.
For example, when the first ICC Prosecutor presented to States Par-
ties, NGOs and other stakeholders the OTP’s strategy for ‘focused investi-
13
An amicus curiae is ‘a friend’ of the Court, providing legal advice to the Judges in a gratui-
tous, free and independent manner in order to help the jurisdictional organ to fulfil its com-
plex mandate. While individual academics or practitioners advising the Court ‘pro bono
causa’ can fulfil adequately the role of amici curiae, it is questionable whether their input
may be equated to the one provided by academics or practitioners hired by an international
organization, which is paying these jurists in order to pursue and advance the official poli-
cies of the organization. It is hereby submitted that the role and locus standi of amici curiae
before the ICC should be reserved only to individual friends of the Court, who are not moti-
vated by the interest of a client, but only by their personal interest to assist the judges in
their interpretation of the Rome Statute and other sources of applicable law under Article 21.
gations’ during the early years of his mandate, PGA expressed serious con-
cerns. The rationale for ‘focused investigations’ hinged on the determina-
tion that ‘Milošević-like trials’ were not desirable for the ICC. It is the view
of the authors that the complexity of the Milošević ‘mega-trial’ did not rep-
resent a negative model, regardless of its procedural outcome, due to the
extreme gravity and complexity of the crimes for which a head of State or
government should be brought to justice. In fact, the concept of ‘focused
investigations’ may not be desirable in most situations and cases falling
under the ICC’s jurisdiction, given the need to investigate atrocity-type
crimes in a satisfactory manner, which entails the need to investigate their
contextual elements (for instance, the widespread or systematic attack
against any civilian population characterizing the notion of crimes against
humanity). It must be stressed that the PGA representative expressed con-
cerns regarding the idea of ‘focused investigation’ since the first consulta-
tions between NGOs and the OTP, and before the commencement of the
early ICC proceedings.
A few years later, the pre-occupation stemming from the policy of
the first Prosecutor of the Court was in some regards assuaged by the poli-
cy adopted by the second Prosecutor. The inclination to try to conduct rela-
tively fast and representative (focused) investigations, to be followed by
focused prosecutions and adjudications, did not bring about fast and fo-
cused criminal proceedings, as illustrated by the cases The Prosecutor v.
Thomas Lubanga Dyilo and The Prosecutor v. Germain Katanga. As such
proceedings developed, NGOs expressed other concerns to the OTP regard-
ing evidence-related matters, including methods of evidence collection and
digital and technologically derived evidence, as well as the excessive reli-
ance on witness evidence. These concerns have been partially addressed by
the second Prosecutor in her OTP policies.
But the most serious problem of integrity of the judicial process is
associated with the issue of competence of the prosecutorial and judicial
organs of the Court. As identified by one of the authors of this chapter, this
concerns, for example, the unsound decision of the pre-trial and trial cham-
bers in the cases of the Kenyan situation to continue issuing summons to
appear voluntarily in the courtroom against all accused, including the then
Deputy Prime Minister Kenyatta and Member of Parliament Ruto. In meet-
ings with NGOs and consultations with the OTP and representatives of the
Court’s chambers, one of the present authors highlighted the Rome Stat-
ute’s provisions requiring the issuance of an arrest warrant. Indeed, this
14
See Hans Corell, “Challenges for the International Criminal Court”, in International Judi-
cial Monitor, Winter 2014.
15
ICC Statute, Article 57, Part 5, see above note 5.
16
See David Donat Cattin, “Article 68: Protection of Victims and Witnesses and their Partici-
pation in the Proceedings”, in Otto Triffterer and Kai Ambos (eds.), Commentary on the
Rome Statute of the ICC, third edition, Beck/Hart Publishers/Nomos, 2015, pp. 1686–1687.
17
John Bolton, Protecting American Constitutionalism and Sovereignty from International
Threats, 10 September 2018, Address to the Federalist Society in Washington, D.C. (https://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/84c2b4/).
18
See Kofi Annan’s statement at the 18 July 1998 ceremony held at the Campidoglio, City
Hall of Rome, reproduced in UN Press Release. Secretary-General says Establishment of In-
ternational Criminal Court is Gift of Hope to Future Generations, UN Doc. SG/SM/6643-
L/2891, 21 July 1998 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/e7c55e).
19
See Independent Expert Review, Independent Expert Review of the International Criminal
Court and the Rome Statute System: Final Report, 30 September 2020 (https://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/cv19d5/).
20
PGA, “Conference on the Commemoration of the 20th Anniversary of the Statute of the
International Criminal Court”, 23 July 2018.
have not been fully implemented and, notwithstanding all the efforts to dif-
ferentiate the elections for the highest ICC officials from those of other in-
ternational organisations, States Parties have not yet ensured that only the
best candidates apply to judicial positions at the ICC. Within the frame-
work of nomination processes for international judicial institutions, a se-
conded judge of the European Court of Human Rights (‘ECtHR’) presented
a study on the correlation between the ECtHR’s impressive increase in
productivity derived from the reforms of the system of judicial nomination
and election. Reforms in the same vein as those of the ECtHR are needed
to professionalize and depoliticize the nomination process and, albeit to a
lesser extent, the election process of the ICC Judges. During the conference,
Judge Marc Perrin de Brichambaut rightly noted that ICC judges are elect-
ed by States and that one could not eliminate that element of legitimacy
from the system. As much as jurists like the idea of an independent body,
the Rome Statute system makes ‘full’ independence difficult to achieve.
However, States can take measures to increase the transparency of the pro-
cess, which will increase the faith and the integrity of the ICC.
In this respect, PGA has advocated for States to propose at the ASP a
resolution on enhanced procedures for the nomination of judicial candi-
dates. The resolution should include several concrete measures: (1) The
publicity of the calls for applications to become a candidate in each country
as a precondition for valid nominations; and (2) the binding nature of opin-
ions issued by the Advisory Committee on Nominations of Judges.
These two measures appear to be simple and they may not require an
amendment to Article 36 of the Rome Statute, which can be interpreted as
containing a minimum standard of qualifications and characteristics of a
valid judicial nomination, whereby nothing is provided in respect of the
domestic procedure to achieve nominations. One of the PGA proposals,
reflected in a non-paper submitted by Liechtenstein to a relevant Working
Group of the ASP set up in New York during 2019, regarded the possibility
for States to have confidential consultations with the Advisory Committee
on Nominations. As such, States would receive appropriate input in case
the Committee would make a determination that a candidate proposed by a
State would not comply with the requirements of competence, integrity and
‘high moral character’ under the Rome Statute. Even if the stand-alone res-
olution adopted by the 2019 ASP reinforces the role of this Advisory
Committee, the proposal was not accepted by some States, which used and
abused the argument that the process of nomination is a ‘State-driven’ pro-
21
ICC, Assembly of State Parties, Resolution on the review of the procedure for the nomina-
tion and election of judges, 6 December 2019, ICC-ASP/18/Res.4 (https://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/bswpis).
30.1. Introduction
Integrity and independence are key qualities required of persons appointed
as the Prosecutor and Judges of the International Criminal Court (‘ICC’).
Both Articles 36 and 42 of the Statute of the ICC 1 refer to persons of “high
moral character” and emphasize independence and impartiality. These qual-
ifications are reinforced by the undertaking in Article 45 of the Statute, to
enter into their respective duties impartially and conscientiously as well as
the elaboration of separate codes of ethical conduct for judges of the
Court, 2 the Office of the Prosecutor (‘OTP’) 3 and the staff of the Court. 4
These codes – for example, the Code of Conduct for the OTP – un-
derscore the importance of impartiality and independence as fundamental
attributes of the office. This chapter examines whether, and if so, to what
extent account should be taken of the diverse background of staff in evalu-
*
Professor Adedeji Adekunle is a Senior Advocate of Nigeria and Visiting Fellow of the
National Human Rights Institute of the Nigerian Human Rights Commission. He was Direc-
tor General of the Nigerian Institute of Advanced Legal Studies (‘NIALS’) until May 2019.
A former Special Adviser to Nigeria’s Attorney General and Minister of Justice on various
aspects of criminal justice administration. He was Secretary of the 2004 Law Revision
Committee. He has authored a Guide to Judicial officers on Nigeria’s Administration of
Criminal Justice Act 2015 and several other monographs. The author acknowledges with
gratitude the assistance of Joke Adediran and Bola Omojola, both promising researchers in
the International Law Department of NIALS.
1
Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court, 17 July 1998, Articles 36 and 42 (‘ICC
Statute’) (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/7b9af9/).
2
ICC, Code of Judicial Ethics, 2 January 2005 (‘ICC Code of Judicial Ethics’) (https://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/383f8f/).
3
ICC, Code of Conduct for the Office of the Prosecutor, 5 September 2013 (‘ICC Code of
Conduct for the OTP’) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/3e11eb).
4
ICC, Code of Conduct for Staff Members, 4 April 2011 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/
75f9db).
5
It has been suggested that the ambiguity produced by this confluence of legal traditions and
culture in international courts may be significant, and it cannot be dispelled by an assumed
“judicial instinct”. See Brandeis Institute for International Judges, “Toward the Develop-
ment of Ethics Guidelines for International Courts”, in Brandeis Institute for International
Judges, Authority and Autonomy: Defining the Role of International and Regional Courts,
Brandeis University, Waltham, MA, 2003.
6
Morten Bergsmo, “Revisiting Integrity in International Justice”, FICHL Policy Brief Series
No. 93 (2018), Torkel Opsahl Academic EPublisher, Brussels, 2018 (http://www.toaep.org/
pbs-pdf/93-bergsmo/).
7
Karl Theodor Paschke, “On the Efforts to Uphold Standards of Integrity Through the Work
of the United Nations Internal Oversight Services”, CILRAP Film, 2 December 2018
(https://www.cilrap.org/cilrap-film/181202-paschke).
other interests (States)). The pressure may also be political, economic, cul-
tural or even historical. While all international justice personnel subscribe
to a uniform code and are expected to suppress their subjective prejudices
in the discharge of their duties, this is easier said than done when external
challenges to their independence are presented.
30.2. Ethical Gaps in the Prosecutorial Function of the Court
Recent revelations about the conduct of Luis Moreno-Ocampo, the first
ICC Prosecutor, in office and also thereafter, have provoked discussions on
the effectiveness of the integrity requirements and safeguards, particularly
for the OTP. 8 It is no secret that whereas a draft code of conduct had been
elaborated for the OTP, it was only after the election of Fatou Bensouda as
the second ICC Prosecutor in 2012 that an ethics code for the Office was
adopted. 9
It may well be that the lateness in coming of the Code had a pro-
found effect on the conduct of Ocampo and some of his staff, as demon-
strated by a series of judicial disapprovals over some decisions of the OTP
in relation to charges brought against Thomas Lubanga. The latter was
charged for war crimes under Articles 8(2)(b)(xxvi) and 8(2)(e)(vii) of the
ICC Statute, namely the enlistment and conscription of children into the
Union des Patriotes Congolais and the Forces Patriotiques pour la Libéra-
tion du Congo in connection with the internal conflict in the DRC.
These unfortunate incidents 10 betrayed profound integrity gaps on the
part of the OTP and a preoccupation with a ‘winning at all costs’ mentality
even if this amounted to an abuse of the process of court.
In the first case, the Prosecutor had improperly sought to shield ex-
culpatory material from the defendant by invoking a limited power to enter
into confidentiality agreements with information-providers, under Article
8
Morten Bergsmo, Wolfgang Kaleck, Sam Muller and William H. Wiley, “A Prosecutor Falls,
Time for the Court to Rise”, FICHL Policy Brief Series No. 86 (2017), Torkel Opsahl Aca-
demic EPublisher, Brussels, 2017 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/41b41a/). It has also been
observed that a fallout of the first 15 years when the ICC was more mission oriented than
values driven is its weak culture of institutional integrity. See Brigid Inder, “Conformity,
Leadership and the Culture of Integrity”, CILRAP Film, 1 December 2018 (https://
www.cilrap.org/cilrap-film/181201-inder).
9
See above note 3.
10
For an extensive discussion of these incidents as well as others See Milan Markovic, “The
ICC Prosecutor’s Missing Code of Conduct”, in Texas International Law Journal, 2011, vol.
47, p. 201.
54(3) of the Statute. The Court criticized the prosecutor’s routine recourse
to Article 54(3)(e) for obtaining a wide range of materials under the cloak
of confidentiality, in order to identify from those materials evidence to be
used at trial. In the words of the Court:
This is the exact opposite of the proper use of the provision,
which is, exceptionally, to allow the prosecution to receive in-
formation or documents which are not for use at trial but
which are instead intended to “lead” to new evidence. The
prosecution's approach constitutes a wholesale and serious
abuse, and a violation of an important provision which was in-
tended to allow the prosecution to receive evidence confiden-
tially, in very restrictive circumstances. The logic of the pros-
ecution's position is that all of the evidence that it obtains
from information-providers can be the subject of Article
54(3)(e) agreements. 11
In the Court’s view, the Prosecution had incorrectly used Article
54(3)(e) when entering into agreements with information-providers, with
the consequence that a significant body of exculpatory evidence which
would otherwise have been disclosed to the accused is to be withheld from
him, thereby improperly inhibiting the opportunities for the accused to pre-
pare his defence.
In the second case, the Prosecutor had declined to comply with the
Trial Chamber’s order to disclose the identity of an intermediary to the de-
fence, citing grave security and safety concerns. The Court took a dim view
of this and observed that:
The Prosecutor has chosen to prosecute this accused. In the
Chamber’s judgment, he cannot be allowed to continue with
this prosecution if he seeks to reserve to himself the right to
avoid the Court’s orders whenever he decides that they are in-
consistent with his interpretation of his other obligations. In
order for the Chamber to ensure that the accused receives a
fair trial, it is necessary that its orders, decisions and rulings
11
ICC, Situation in Democratic Republic of the Congo, The Prosecutor v Thomas Lubanga
Dyilo, Trial Chamber, Decision on the consequences of non-disclosure of exculpatory mate-
rials covered by Article 54(3)(e) agreements and the application to stay the prosecution of
the accused, together with certain other issues raised at the Status Conference on 10 June
2008, 13 June 2008, ICC-01/04-01/06-1401 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/e6a054/).
12
ICC, Situation in Democratic Republic of the Congo, The Prosecutor v. Thomas Lubanga
Dyilo, Trial Chamber, Redacted Decision on the Prosecution’s Urgent Request for Variation
of the Time-Limit to Disclose the Identity of Intermediary 143 or Alternatively to Stay Pro-
ceedings Pending Further Consultations with the VWU, 8 July 2010, ICC-01/04-01/06-
2517-Red (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/cd4f10/).
13
ICC, Situation in Democratic Republic of the Congo, The Prosecutor v. Thomas Lubanga
Dyilo, Trial Chamber, Decision on the press interview with Ms Le Fraper du Hellen, 12 May
2010, ICC-01/04-01/06-2433 (‘ICC Lubanga du Hellen interview Decision’) (http://
www.legal-tools.org/doc/3b613a/).
14
Discussed in Markovic, 2011, p. 230, see above note 10.
15
Ibid., pp. 201 and 211.
tor cannot refrain from taking politically sensitive steps simply on the
ground that this would provoke controversy. However, “he is requested to
be fully aware of these human reactions and meticulously check himself so
that they are not permitted to influence his actions”. 20
Apart from the personal integrity of officials, there is also institution-
al integrity. This approximates to the values and norms that an institution
champions or through which it measures integrity and punishes infractions
and can often be located in the corporate ethics code or collectively in the
ethics codes for members of the Institution.
If prosecutorial discretion and choices are complicated in domestic
legal systems, the need for guidance in the ICC, which thrusts upon the
Prosecutor the unique responsibilities for seeking the truth (by according
equal weight to the investigation of incriminating and exculpatory materi-
al) 21 cannot be over-emphasized. A code of conduct provides a uniform,
objective and ethical rationale for the application of the provisions of the
Statute and Rules. Without it, uneven and subjective application of the hard
law to situations will be unavoidable. Such codes are characterized by Na-
khjavani as a set of fundamental beliefs, attitudes, habits of thought and
action, learnt and practised over time and in diverse contexts, which are
inseparable from the act of legal characterization itself and its occasionally
world-shaping effects. 22
30.3.1. Judges
Articles 3, 4 and 5 of the Code of Judicial Ethics require Judges of the ICC
to be independent, impartial and to demonstrate integrity in the course of
their duties. These provisions also emphasize the need for judges to avoid
putting themselves in situations that conflict with or interfere with their
integrity or duties.
in Morten Bergsmo, Klaus Rackwitz and SONG, Tianying (eds.), Historical Origins of In-
ternational Criminal Law: Volume 5, FICHL Publication Series No. 24, Torkel Opsahl Aca-
demic EPublisher, Brussels, 2017, p. 7 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/09c8b8).
20
Dan Hammarskjöld, “The International Civil Servant in Law and in Fact”, in Wilder Foote
(ed.), The Servant of Peace: A Selection of the Speeches and Statements of Dag Hammar-
skjöld, Secretary-General of the United Nations, 1953–1961, The Bodley Head, 1962, p. 348
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/64bcae/).
21
ICC Statute, Article 54(1)(a), see above note 1.
22
See Salim A. Nakhjavani, “The Origins and Development of the Code of Conduct”, in
Bergsmo, Rackwitz and SONG (eds.), 2017, p. 954, see above note 18.
23
Under Article 44 of the ICC Statute, these are personnel appointed by the Prosecutor and the
Registrar. Markovic rightly doubts the application of these Rules to the Prosecutor or Depu-
ty Prosecutor. Markovic, 2011, p. 206, see above note 10.
24
ICC Code of Conduct for the OTP, Section 2, para. 23(a), see above note 3.
25
Ibid., Section 9, para. 42.
Although the Code of Judicial Ethics did not contain similar illustra-
tions, they are of equal significance to Judges of the Court. Such pressures
can be characterized as political, economic, cultural or even historical. Fur-
thermore, they can vary in intensity and type depending on the socio-legal
background or even status of the official. Naturally, the higher the status of
the official, the more intense the pressure will be. The Prosecutor, Judges,
and other high officials necessarily find themselves in the eye of the public,
whether willingly or unwillingly. They must rise beyond showmanship and
focus on the essentials of their job. The internal conflicts are considerable.
Together with the inherently political nature of most international crimes
like war crimes and genocide, no one should doubt that States will exert
pressure on these officials directly or otherwise. While a code of ethics and
integrity will not prevent these pressures, it will greatly assist the Prosecu-
tor and the staff of the OTP in dealing with them. However, much more
needs to be done in order to secure widespread understanding and compli-
ance. In the next section, diverse scenarios of the pressure dynamics and
the impact of socio-cultural factors are examined with a view to demon-
strating the need for an institutional compliance mechanism.
30.4.1. Political Pressure
Political pressure is often brought to bear in the course of the appointment
or tenure of the official. In a seminal article on the international civil serv-
ant, Dag Hammarskjöld highlighted two complementary factors: first, that
international bodies must perforce work with persons from different na-
tionalities and second, that these persons more often than not have the po-
litical support of their country of origin or a bloc of States. 26 The motives
for support vary, but as Morten Bergsmo puts it, whatever the motive, there
is no lack of efforts by States to promote candidates that can be “influ-
enced” or subsequently shown up as ineffectual or ridiculed. 27 The ICC
operates in a complex political environment and depends greatly on gov-
ernments for wide-ranging matters such as the smooth conduct of prelimi-
nary examination or the exercise of investigation powers, witness protec-
tion or, indeed, its budget. In such circumstances, some measure of ‘politi-
cal protection’ from an influential State or bloc of interests is inevitable.
Where decisions or actions of the Court coincide with the interests of such
a ‘protector’, perceptions of bias cannot be avoided even if this is purely
26
Hammarskjöld, 1962, p. 339, see above note 20.
27
See Bergsmo, 2017 pp. 7, 8, 30 and 31, see above note 19.
28
Richard J. Goldstone, “Prosecutorial Language, Integrity and Independence”, CILRAP Film,
2 December 2018 (https://www.cilrap.org/cilrap-film/181202-goldstone).
29
Ibid.
30
This is a common feature of the dynamics of the UN political system and is alluded to also
by Paschke, 2018, see above note 7.
31
Brandeis Institute for International Judges, “Challenges to Judicial Independence” in
Brandeis Institute for International Judges, Toward an International Rule of Law, Brandeis
University, Waltham, MA, 2010. See also ICC Statute, Article 36(9) (Judges) and Article
42(4) (Prosecutor), see above note 1.
The nature of the work of the ICC Prosecutor and Judges involves
making decisions that many powerful States find unpleasant. This “step-
ping on toes” often places a judge in an adverse position for seeking future
job opportunities in such States. In reaction to the preliminary examina-
tions conducted by the Prosecutor on alleged war crimes in Afghanistan,
the United States issued a “warning” to the ICC to desist from conducting
the investigations and had threatened to “use any means necessary to pro-
tect its citizens from unjust prosecution by [the] illegitimate court”. 32 Part
of the threat was a “policy of U.S. visa restrictions on those individuals di-
rectly responsible for any ICC investigation of U.S. personnel” as well as
economic sanctions. 33 The US eventually revoked the visa of the Chief
Prosecutor in April 2019, 34 and subsequently imposed sanctions on her and
her staff member Mr. Phakiso Mochochoko. It is not surprising that, even-
tually, the ICC Pre-Trial Chamber II rejected the request of the Chief Pros-
ecutor to open an investigation probe into US involvement in Afghanistan,
albeit on the ground that “an investigation into the situation in Afghanistan
at this stage would not serve the interests of justice”. 35 The Chamber elabo-
rated further that although all the relevant requirements were met as re-
gards both jurisdiction and admissibility, the current circumstances of the
situation in Afghanistan were such as to make the prospects for a success-
ful investigation and prosecution extremely limited. 36 While the basis for
the decision is practical, it also demonstrates the delicate interplay between
international justice and international politics. The action of the US in this
situation is a form of economic pressure as judges of the Court may be
pressurized to consider the likelihood of losing career prospects in the US
after their tenure, if the threat by the latter is eventually carried out.
It is obvious also that some of the challenges or threats to independ-
ence outlive the position and do not necessarily disappear by foreclosing
32
See Al Jazeera, “Full text of John Bolton's speech to the Federalist Society”, 10 September
2018.
33
See Michael R. Pompeo, “Remarks to the Press”, US Department of State, 15 March 2019,
available on Department of State’s web site.
34
BBC News, “US revokes visa of International Criminal Court prosecutor”, 5 April 2019,
available on its web site.
35
ICC, Situation in the Islamic Republic of Afghanistan, Pre-Trial Chamber, Decision Pursu-
ant to Article 15 of the Rome Statute on the Authorisation of an Investigation into the Situa-
tion in the Islamic Republic of Afghanistan, 12 April 2019, ICC-02/17-33
(https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/2fb1f4).
36
Ibid., para. 96.
37
Brandeis Institute for International Judges, 2003, p. 6, see above note 5.
38
Stephanie Itimi, “Is Foreign Aid a facilitator of Neo-Colonialism in Africa?”, in Journal of
African Cultural Studies, 2018 (on file with the author).
standards. 39 An instance was the foreign aid cut to Uganda when it enacted
its anti-gay law. 40 This supports the view that foreign aid is a tool that can
be used by donor States to advance a specific agenda. In the light of histor-
ical pressure in this discourse, a justice official from a State that is depend-
ent on aids by some particular States may be pressurized by his or her
home State as regards the interests of the donor States.
30.4.4. Socio-Cultural Pressure
There are some other forms of pressure that are socio-cultural and which
may or may not be concerned with career prospects or job security. What,
for example, constitutes independence in terms of the OTP or a Judge? In-
dividual or cultural perspectives of the concept of independence vary.
Whereas in some countries, the duty of independence of a Prosecutor does
not prevent notification of an intended course of action to a supervisor or
superior official discussion of the case with the prosecutor’s colleagues,
expressing pre-determined views can be problematic in an international
court. 41 Considering the dynamics of the ICC, there are no clear answers.
Context, as usual, plays a role. We should not also forget that the duty of
independence is yoked with that of confidentiality, and even if the official
stoically rebuffs external pressure in such discussions, the mere fact of par-
ticipating in such discussions and disclosure of some material could
amount to a breach of the code.
Another area of difficulty is interaction and communication. Judges
in many countries are perhaps familiar with the need to be circumspect in
conversations concerning their work. The same cannot, however, be said
about prosecutors and investigators. In some national jurisdictions, for ex-
ample, in Nigeria, press releases and interviews concerning arrested sus-
pects or ongoing trials are routine – sometimes with damning conclusions
made on the guilt of the suspects. However, this should not be the case,
given the sensitive and inquisitorial nature of ICC investigations and pros-
ecutions. This was clearly the position of the Trial Chambers in the Luban-
ga case while criticizing the OTP when, in a press interview, an OTP staff
misrepresented proceedings in the Lubanga case and predicted a long jail
39
BBC News, “Cameron threat to dock some UK aid to anti-gay nations”, 30 October 2011,
available on its web site.
40
Al Jazeera, “Uganda hit with foreign aid cuts over anti-gay law”, 27 February 2014, availa-
ble on its web site.
41
See Goldstone, 2018, see above note 28.
term for Lubanga based on the “courageous and credible witnesses” of the
prosecution. 42
There are less subtle pressures such as monetary gifts or in-kind as-
sistance rendered to the official, relatives or associates. Some so-called ‘so-
cial obligations’ – customary gifts in societies where social events are intri-
cately connected with class or status are problematic. Events that provide
the challenge in Nigeria or for a Nigerian will probably not matter to offi-
cials of other nationalities. In some countries, for example, monetary gifts
during social events or welcome/farewell gifts are customary. For interna-
tional officials working in these environments, for example, examination or
investigation teams of the OTP, what is required is not simply an ethics
code but also guidance on these socio-cultural issues so as to conform to
the constitutional tone without offending host States.
It is instructive that the Code of Conduct for the OTP addresses this
kind of unethical conduct. It must always be remembered that officials
must guard against the appearance of bias as well as actual bias. The Code,
therefore, provides in Section 6.30 that:
impartial conduct includes
1. respect for the presumption of innocence. In particular,
Members of the Office shall not publicly express an
opinion on the guilt or innocence of a person under in-
vestigation or the accused outside the context of the pro-
ceedings before the Court;
2. refraining from expressing an opinion that could, objec-
tively, adversely affect the required impartiality, whether
through communications media, in writing or public ad-
dresses, or through any other actions outside the context
of the proceedings before the Court […].
In the absence of a generally applicable international standard to de-
termine the acceptable norms, judicial officers will be left to adhere to the
customary ethical norms in their States. The challenge this poses is that a
judicial officer whose socio-cultural background allows certain social in-
teractions and relationships may do so innocently meanwhile, it may later
give room for pressure. However, no one should be in doubt that judicial
officers cannot plead the customary gift excuse where this is offered by a
litigant or counsel to a litigant.
42
ICC Lubanga du Hellen interview Decision, see above note 13.
43
See Barney Thomson, “Former ICC prosecutor in Row over Lucrative Consultancy Work”,
Financial Times, 6 October 2017, available on its web site.
44
See Bergsmo, 2018, p. 2, see above note 6.
45
The applicability of these Rules to elected officials – for example, Judges, the Registrar and
the Prosecutor or Deputy Prosecutor – is in doubt. See Markovic, 2011, p. 206, see above
note 10.
46
ICC, Staff Regulations, 12 September 2003 (‘ICC Staff Regulations’) (https://www.legal-
tools.org/doc/3542d3).
50
ICC Staff Regulations, Section 1.2(i), see above note 46; ICC Staff Rules, Section 101.4(d),
see above note 47.
51
See also ICC Code of Conduct for the OTP, Sections 2.2.24 (independence) and 3.9.43 (con-
flict of interest), see above note 3.
52
Nakhjavani, 2017, p. 957, see above note 22.
53
Inder, 2018, see above note 8; See also Paschke, 2018 see above note 7.
54
Bergsmo et al., 2017, see above note 8; see also Karim A.A. Khan, “Integrity and the Limits
of Internal Oversight Mechanisms”, CILRAP Film, 2 December 2018 (https://
www.cilrap.org/cilrap-film/181202-khan/).
55
Ibid.
56
ICC, “The Independent Oversight Mechanism (IOM) Mandate”, available on its web site.
57
See Women’s Initiatives for Gender Justice, “A Critical Time for the ICC’s Integrity”, 12
October 2017 (http://www.legal-tools.org/doc/e2fbc7/), which called for two new compli-
ance mechanisms – an Integrity Advisory Board and an Ethics/Compliance Office in the
Court.
58
The UN Ethics Office was established in 2005 offers confidential ethics advice, ethics
awareness and education, protection against retaliation for reporting misconduct, financial
disclosure programme and promotion of coherence and common ethics standards across the
UN. See UN Ethics Office, “What is the UN Ethics Office”, available on its web site (‘UN
Ethics Office web site’).
59
See Nakhjavani, 2017, pp. 957–958, see above note 22.
60
See Bergsmo et al., 2017, see above note 8.
61
See Secretary General’s Bulletin – Ethics Office – Establishment and Terms of reference,
UN Doc ST/SGB/2005/22, 30 December 2005.
the world. 62 In its advisory mandate, the Office treats all requests and advi-
sories with confidentiality.
Through this service, the staff members are better able to describe
their problems or concerns, identify the rules and regulations that may ap-
ply, examine their options, and understand the consequences. Through the
advisory process, the staff is better able to make ethical decisions that serve
the interest of the UN. Ethics advice is confidential to the person requesting
assistance. The Office has also published several guides on conflicts of in-
terest, financial disclosures, and an Ethics Roadmap for the guidance of
staff. It is also instructive that a similar mechanism exists under the Euro-
pean Union where a Complaints and Inquiry Unit clarifies on request, in
concrete terms, the meaning of ethical principles on integrity and conflict
of interest to staff members of the European Union – another multi-cultural
organization. 63
30.6. Conclusion
Although the standards of independence and integrity are required for all
staff (including elected officials of the Court), the conduct of the Prosecutor,
members of the OTP, and the Judges command more attention, given that
international criminal trials are more complex, more expensive, and more
difficult to accomplish than domestic prosecutions. If proceedings are prej-
udiced on account of misconduct by the Prosecutor, it has a significantly
negative effect on the resources and time of the Court. 64
While Codes on ethical standards are important, the conflicts and
pressures inherent in the duties of the persons of diverse cultures and back-
ground that work as officials of the OTP, as Judges and indeed other staff
confront these officials in equally diverse ways. The establishment of a
proactive independent mechanism similar to the UN Ethics Office will ad-
dress these concerns by supporting staff compliance on ethics through
counselling and issuing guidelines.
62
UN Ethics Office web site, see above note 57.
63
Marta Hirsch-Ziembinska, “Integrity and the Work of the European Ombudsman”, CILRAP
Film, 2 December 2018 (https://www.cilrap.org/cilrap-film/181202-ziembinska).
64
Jenia Turner, “Policing International Prosecutors”, in NYU Journal of International Law and
Politics, 2012, vol. 45, no. 1, pp. 210–211.
A large amount of subject matter that could be said to fit under this title has
already been addressed by others. This contribution is, in fact, concerned
with one specific manifestation of the problem of political exposure, aris-
ing from the fact that certain aspects of the international criminal justice
system fall within the responsibility of political rather than independent
judicial or prosecutorial decision-makers.
If asked to what extent it is appropriate for aspects of the criminal
justice system to be entrusted to or influenced by political decision making,
the instinctive first reaction of many would be to respond that even the tini-
est amount of political influence would taint and corrupt the integrity of the
entire process. That view may, of course, be a fundamental truth in relation
to some parts of the system. When judges retire at the end of a case to con-
sider their verdict, they should obviously conduct their deliberations in
complete independence and with complete impartiality, without outside
influence of any kind, political or otherwise, and should base their decision
solely on the evidence before them and the law.
However, when the entire criminal justice system is considered as a
whole, it can be seen on reflection that it is simplistic to suggest that politi-
cal decision-making should never play any part anywhere in the system at
all. In a domestic legal system, where political decision-makers are the leg-
islature, the executive, or even the electorate as a whole, it will for instance
typically be a political decision-maker (the legislature) that creates and de-
fines substantive crimes and the maximum penalties for those crimes. It
*
Dr. Christopher Staker is a Barrister at 39 Essex Chambers in London. He has been coun-
sel in cases before the International Court of Justice, International Tribunal for the Law of
the Sea, International Criminal Tribunal for the Former Yugoslavia (‘ICTY’), Special Court
for Sierra Leone, and European Court of Human Rights. Previously, he has been Principal
Legal Secretary at the International Court of Justice; Deputy Prosecutor of the Special Court
for Sierra Leone; Senior Appeals Counsel at the ICTY; and Counsel Assisting the Solicitor-
General of Australia. He originally trained as a diplomat with the Australian Department of
Foreign Affairs. He holds a doctorate degree from Oxford.
1
See, for instance, J. van Zyl Smit, The Appointment, Tenure and Removal of Judges under
Commonwealth Principles: A Compendium and Analysis of Best Practice (Report of Re-
search Undertaken by Bingham Centre for the Rule of Law, British Institute of International
and Comparative Law, London, 2015, p. xvi:
Only 19% of Commonwealth jurisdictions have executive-only appointment systems in
this sense (appointments to the highest court are reserved for the executive in another
8% of jurisdictions, and the appointment of the Chief Justice in a further 23% of juris-
dictions). […] In 21% of Commonwealth jurisdictions there is some legislative in-
volvement in the appointment of judges, usually by way of confirmation of candidates
selected by a judicial appointments commission.
2
Jed Handelsman Shugerman, The People’s Courts, 2012, Harvard University Press, p. 3
(“Almost 90 percent of state judges [in the United States] face some kind of popular elec-
tion”); Michael J. Ellis, “The Origins of the Elected Prosecutor”, in The Yale Law Journal,
2012, vol. 121, no. 6, pp. 1528, 1530 (“The United States is the only country in the world
where citizens elect prosecutors”).
3
See, for instance, United Nations General Assembly, Human Rights Council, Report of the
Special Rapporteur on the independence of judges and lawyers, Gabriela Knaul, UN Doc.
A/HRC/20/19, 7 June 2012, para. 73 (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/dqtiml/) (“In order to
ensure a fair and consistent approach in criminal justice policy, general guidelines can be is-
sued by the prosecution service itself (internally) and by nonprosecutorial authorities (exter-
nally)”), para. 74 (“the issue of instructions by nonprosecutorial authorities should be: trans-
parent, consistent with lawful authority and subject to established guidelines to safeguard
the actuality and the perception of prosecutorial independence”), para. 116 (“Case-specific
instructions to prosecutors from external organs should be avoided. However, in extraordi-
nary cases, when such instructions are deemed necessary, they should be in writing and for-
mally recorded and carefully circumscribed to avoid undue interference or pressure. Prose-
cutors should have the right to challenge the instructions received, especially when they are
deemed unlawful or contrary to professional standards or ethics”).
4
For example, South Australia, Director of Public Prosecutions Act 1991, 6 July 1992, sec-
tion 9(2) (https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/zg1tc7/) (“The Attorney-General may, after con-
sultation with the Director [of Public Prosecutions], give directions and furnish guidelines to
the Director in relation to the carrying out of his or her functions”).
5
For instance, in certain jurisdictions, the Attorney-General, a government minister, has the
power to issue ex officio indictments or to terminate a prosecution by issuing a nolle prose-
qui.
6
United Kingdom, House of Lords (‘UKHL’), R. v. Withers, Judgment, 20 November 1974,
[1975] AC 842, pp. 854, 860, 863, 867, 877; England and Wales, Court of Appeal, R. v. Mis-
ra and Srivastava, Judgment, 8 October 2004, [2004] EWCA Crim 2375, [2005] 1 Cr App R
328, paras. 29–34; UKHL, R. v. Rimmington, Judgment, 27 October 2005, [2005] UKHL 63,
[2006] 1 Cr App Rep 17, paras. 33–35. See also UKHL, R. v. Jones, Judgment, 29 March
2006, [2006] 1 AC 136 dealing with the question whether crimes under international law are
automatically assimilated into UK domestic law, in which Lord Hoffmann referred at pa-
ra. 60 to “the democratic principle that it is nowadays for Parliament and Parliament alone to
decide whether conduct not previously regarded as criminal should be made an offence”.
7
See, for instance, the extrajudicial observations of a then justice of the High Court of Aus-
tralia in Michael Kirby, Judicial Activism: Authority, Principle and Policy in the Judicial
Method, Sweet & Maxwell, London, 2004, pp. 82–83:
the judicial abolition of spousal immunity for rape, without waiting for legislative
change, was informed by strong contemporary advances in the recognition of the rights
of women; […] In such a changed world, it was intolerable to expect contemporary
judges to give effect to the old rule, made by predecessors centuries earlier. […] [I]n do-
ing so, they gave voice to what would have been the overwhelming opinion of contem-
porary society. […] Who will say that the judges were wrong to redefine the common
law in that way? Be sure that some would denounce such action as egregious ‘judicial
activism’. If so, it is an epithet that the judges will gladly bear.
8
See, for instance, the extrajudicial observations of a then justice of the High Court of Aus-
tralia in Dyson Heydon, “Judicial Activism and the Death of the Rule of Law”, in Otago
Law Review, 2004, vol. 10, no. 4, p. 493:
The expression ‘judicial activism’ is here used to mean using judicial power for a pur-
pose other than that for which it was granted, namely doing justice according to law in
the particular case. It means serving some function other than what is necessary for the
decision of the particular dispute between the parties. Often the illegitimate function is
the furthering of some political, moral or social programme: the law is seen not as the
touchstone by which the case in hand is to be decided, but as a possible starting point or
catalyst for developing a new system to solve a range of other cases. Even more com-
monly the function is a discursive and indecisive meander through various fields of
learning for its own sake.
9
See, for instance, the extrajudicial observations of a judge of the United Kingdom Supreme
Court: Lord Hodge, “The scope of judicial law-making in the common law tradition”, Max
Planck Institute of Comparative and International Private Law Hamburg, Germany, 28 Oc-
tober 2019, para. 24 (“What have judges said about those boundaries? The answer is that
judges recognise that there is a boundary to judicial law-making but there is no consensus as
to where it is”) (available on the Supreme Court’s web site).
the Court or to make a declaration under Article 12(3) of the Statute. For
jurisdiction to be exercised under Article 13(b), the requisite precedent po-
litical decision is that of the Security Council to refer a situation to the
Prosecutor. For jurisdiction to be exercised under Article 13(a), a further
requisite precedent political decision is that of the relevant State to refer the
situation to the Prosecutor under Article 14(1) of its Statute. The exercise
of jurisdiction by the Court over the crime of aggression is subject to fur-
ther political decision-making, including the decision of the relevant State
whether or not to make or withdraw a declaration under Article 15bis(4),
and the decision of the Security Council to make (or not) a determination
under Article 15bis(6)-(8). Furthermore, the processes of the Court may be
interrupted by a political decision of the Security Council under Article 16
to request a deferral of an investigation or prosecution.
Thus, the question whether the International Criminal Court can or
cannot exercise jurisdiction in relation to a specific situation will depend
not just on political decisions taken at the time that the Court was initially
established, but by real-time political decisions taken by States contempo-
raneously with decision-making by the Prosecutor and Chambers of the
Court.
A further feature of the International Criminal Court that has no ob-
vious analogy with domestic legal systems is Article 127 of its Statute,
which confers on each State Party the right to withdraw from the Statute.
References to general principles established in domestic legal systems thus
provide no guidance on how the Prosecutor or Chambers of the Court
should react, for instance, to a situation where a group of States threatens to
withdraw from the Statute on the basis that those States are dissatisfied
with the direction that prosecutorial decisions are taking.
On one view, it might be said that such a situation would amount to
an unjustifiable attempt by the States concerned to exert political influence
over the Prosecutor, 10 and that maintenance of the integrity of the system
would require the Prosecutor to not be influenced or to be seen to be influ-
enced by such political pressures. This view might lead to the conclusion
that a Prosecutor of integrity should refuse to change course in response to
such threats to withdraw from the Statute, even in the hypothetical extreme
10
Compare the statement of Canada at the seventeenth session of the Assembly of States Par-
ties, December 2018, p. 5: “We remain concerned about efforts to undermine the Court’s
work, be it threats directed at the Court and its personnel, politically motivated withdrawals
or unexecuted arrest warrants”.
case where the result would lead to the withdrawal from the Statute of eve-
ry State Party, such that the Court itself would cease to exist.
However, a contrary view can also be put. A State which is not a par-
ty to the Statute might well decide against becoming a party – at least for
the time being – on the ground that it is not impressed by the current direc-
tion of prosecutorial decision-making. Nothing in the Statute could prevent
a non-State Party from so deciding or from publicly stating its reasons for
that decision, and it is unlikely that many would characterise such state-
ments by a non-State Party as an assault on the integrity of the Court. It is
difficult to see why the position is any different in the case of a State Party
contemplating withdrawal from the Statute, given that Article 127 of the
Statute gives States Parties an unequivocal right to withdraw. Any decision
by a State Party to do so will inevitably be a political decision. The Statute
in no way limits the reasons upon which a decision of the State Party to
withdraw may be based. 11 Indeed, some might argue that Article 127 is an
essential safety valve, enabling States Parties to decide to be no longer
bound by the Statute if they feel that the political compromises reflected in
the Statute are not being respected, or that the Court is not properly per-
forming the functions that it was set up to serve. Without that safety valve,
some States Parties might not have willingly become parties to the Statute
in the first place. While the Prosecutor and the Chambers clearly are not
bound to take any particular action in response to threats by a State to
withdraw from the Statute, it may be argued that it would be contrary to the
intentions of the Statute for the organs of the Court to remain totally oblivi-
ous to any expressions of dissatisfaction by States Parties. 12
Of course, it would be inherently contrary to the integrity of the sys-
tem for any organ of the Court to be influenced by threats of a State Party
to withdraw from the Statute if a particular verdict is not reached in a par-
ticular case. However, that does not necessarily mean that it would be con-
trary to the integrity of the system for organs of the Court to take into ac-
count the views of States Parties (or indeed, even non-States Parties) in re-
lation to more general matters of prosecutorial policy. It is noteworthy, for
instance, that a statement of Canada at the Assembly of States Parties in
December 2018, while criticising “politically motivated withdrawals”,
11
Roger S. Clark, “Article 127”, in Otto Triffterer and Kai Ambos (eds.), The Rome Statute of
the ICC, third edition, Nomos, 2016, mn. 1.
12
Ibid., pp. 5–6.
went on to call for “an exit strategy for ongoing preliminary investigations
where the evidence available does not support the timely or successful
prosecution”, adding that “[k]eeping these cases active is not an efficient
use of Court resources regardless of the political price of their withdraw-
al”. 13
This leads to consideration of a further difference between domestic
legal systems and international criminal courts and tribunals, which is that
international criminal courts are very selective in the prosecutions that they
bring. In domestic legal systems, the general position tends to be that all
cases are prosecuted where there is sufficient evidence to justify it, unless
there is some specific reason why it is not in the interests of justice to do so.
On the other hand, in the case of an international criminal court, there is
inevitably evidence of more crimes by more apparent perpetrators than
could ever be practicably prosecuted, thus requiring decisions to be made
as to which persons should be prosecuted for which particular crimes.
Again, it might well be contrary to the integrity of the system if political
decision-makers sought to influence which specific persons should be
prosecuted on which specific charges. However, it does not necessarily fol-
low that it would be inconsistent with the integrity of the institution for po-
litical actors to seek to persuade organs of the Court, for instance, that there
is good empirical evidence that a focus on certain types of crimes would
have the greatest effect of promoting peace and reconciliation in a particu-
lar post-conflict State, or would have the greatest effect in deterring the
commission of future crimes under international law.
Questions of fundamental importance thereby arise as to the appro-
priate limits of the matters within the international criminal justice system
that may or should appropriately be regulated or influenced by political
actors – and the line beyond which political influences cease to be proper
and become a threat to the integrity of the institution. A related issue is the
question of who has responsibility for recognising that this boundary has
been crossed, and for doing something about it. That in turn leads to the
further question of exactly what should be done about it. The answers to
these questions will not necessarily be uncontroversial.
13
See ibid.: “In the case of the Specialized Agencies, a custom has perhaps developed that that
States explain why it is that they are withdrawing, in order to give the entity an opportunity
to alter any course of action that the withdrawing State finds unacceptable”.
Although the theme of the conference and this book has been indi-
vidual integrity rather than institutional integrity, in any discussion of polit-
ical influences on the criminal justice process, the two inevitably overlap. A
political body seeking to influence the judicial or prosecutorial activities of
an international criminal court will likely focus its efforts on a judge or the
judges collectively, or on the prosecutor. It is the actions of those individu-
als in responding to such forces that will shape the integrity of the institu-
tions themselves. Institutional integrity therefore requires those individuals
to have an appreciation of what responses to such influences would be ap-
propriate or inappropriate, as well as a willingness and ability to act ac-
cordingly.
An essential step in preserving the integrity of the international crim-
inal justice system in the face of political exposure is thus to achieve a
common understanding of the appropriate role of political decision-makers
and its limitations. In the absence of such a common understanding, it is
hard for individual prosecutors or judges to know if they are appropriately
maintaining their own independence and integrity or not.
A worthwhile project for the future would be to try to establish some
kind of guidelines on these issues. Such guidelines, if formulated in calm
deliberation following full consultation and debate, would no doubt be of
great assistance to the prosecutors and judges of international criminal
courts. As well as being a point of reference for prosecutors and judges to
explain and justify their responses in particular cases, such guidelines may
assist in deterring inappropriate political pressures from being exerted in
the first place.
It is beyond the scope of this contribution to consider the detailed
process by which such guidelines might be adopted, let alone what the con-
tent of such guidelines might be. Addressing the issues above may well
prove to be a complex and difficult task. That, if so, would underscore the
need for a major initiative in this area. Preservation of the integrity of the
international criminal justice system is fundamental. If there are any uncer-
tainties about precisely what this requires, energetic and committed efforts
should be made to resolve them.
Some Reflections on
Integrity in International Justice
David Re *
In 2013, I wrote a short article with the bright and cheery title of “The
Glass is Half-full for International Criminal Law”. 1 Revisiting the topic
seven years later, however, my then more youthful sanguinity is now a far
more cautious optimism. This results from intervening personal experienc-
es and some institutional and political developments. My purpose here is to
briefly explore some of these issues.
Consequently, in sharing some of these personal experiences as I do
below, and my reflections on integrity in international justice generally, my
hope is that these concrete examples may inform where normative but
nonetheless more abstract notions may struggle. 2 The combination of expe-
rience and observation may help to illuminate some institutional obstacles
and challenges. The more important aim here, though, is to pose the slight-
ly more pessimistic question of whether too many structural impediments
exist to achieve a level of integrity that can ever match the high internal
and external expectations for international justice.
32.1. No International Justice System Exists
Comparing the national and international, and using the national as a pos-
sible model is useful, although the differences between the two are quite
*
David Re is the Presiding Judge of the Trial Chamber of the Special Tribunal for Lebanon.
(since 2013). Before that he was an international judge of the Court of Bosnia and Herze-
govina in Sarajevo and a prosecuting trial attorney and senior prosecuting trial attorney at
the International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia (‘ICTY’) in The Hague. He
has worked in international justice institutions since 2002. In Australia, between 1986 and
2001, he worked as a barrister, a prosecutor and a solicitor in private practice, and as a re-
search officer for the New South Wales Attorney-General’s Department. He was an NGO
observer at the negotiations for the Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court in 1998.
He has also legally consulted for the OSCE, and the UNDP in South Sudan.
1
David Re, “The Glass is Half-full for International Criminal Law”, in Global Policy, 2013,
vol. 4, no. 3, p. 317.
2
Some of these are eloquently expressed in chapters in this book such as Hans Corell’s Chap-
ter 5 (“The Dag Hammarskjöld Legacy and Integrity in International Civil Service”).
3
The international human rights courts, though, are in a slightly different category at the peak
of a treaty-based system applying international human rights law, by making declarations of
rights when domestic remedies are exhausted.
seven indicted counts (one count for each accused). The evidence was oth-
erwise insufficient to proceed to trial. Further investigation with an ad-
journment, or alternatively abandoning five counts, was required. A memo-
randum to this effect was prepared, bearing the signatures of the four pros-
ecuting lawyers. A very senior official, however, instructed the case to pro-
ceed, notwithstanding this assessment, and then, additionally, neglected to
inform the Prosecutor of the existence of the memo. The case commenced.
I moved to another one. As I believed that the Prosecutor should be made
aware of this evidentiary deficiency, I informed the Prosecutor of the true
state of the evidence. The case still proceeded, and eventually on appeal,
only two counts survived – namely, those for which there had been some
evidence at the trial’s commencement. The case should not have gone to
trial on the other counts: but it did at enormous cost to the institution and
the two accused. That this occurred reveals a major lapse in institutional
integrity. Was it avoidable? Absolutely. But why this course was taken was
never explained.
In raising this example, I recognise a counter-argument: namely, that
as a judge had confirmed the indictment it should be left to a trial chamber
at that point to determine the sufficiency of the evidence. However, against
this is that if the prosecutors in the case have formed the view that, based
on an insufficiency of evidence, ‘no reasonable prospect of conviction’ ex-
ists, the case should not proceed. I subscribe to this latter view: as a matter
of prosecutorial integrity, and hence that of the system itself, in these cir-
cumstances it is unconscionable to advance to trial.
In another case in which I was involved at a late stage, I became
aware that prosecution officials had deliberately failed to disclose to the
accused crucial exculpatory evidence during the phase of the case related to
that evidence. The suppressed evidence was disclosed only at a later point.
In a third case, the prosecution misled the Trial Chamber and the de-
fence by failing to disclose something that was highly relevant to an appli-
cation to amend an indictment. When I belatedly discovered this, I was in-
structed not to bring it to the attention of either the chamber or the defence.
Ultimately, however, no prejudice occurred as the prosecution failed in its
application, and, moreover, the accused was acquitted. Both factors, how-
ever, are beside the point regarding standing ethical obligations, especially
in something as fundamental as amending the charging instrument.
In a fourth case, in which I was the lead counsel, it became apparent
that certain investigators were being less than candid about the circum-
ters going to the heart of judicial integrity and, consequently, public credi-
bility. 4
Turning a blind eye to, or attempting to cover up, such transgressions
facilitates the degradation of standards and makes a mockery of the statuto-
ry requirements that judges serving in international institutions have high
moral character and integrity. As Judge Erik Møse points out,
it is important that the institution carries out thorough investi-
gations, even if the person accused of such behaviour has left,
in order to clarify whether the allegation has any factual basis
and, if so, to take necessary measures and demonstrate a rup-
ture with the past. 5
In this respect, sunlight is the best disinfectant.
Another institutional barrier to institutional integrity is the inade-
quate manner of dealing with applications to disqualify a judge from hear-
ing a matter. Lacking structural recourse to external judicial mechanisms,
international courts and tribunals must resort to using their own internal
means to decide these issues. Some use a panel of three judges (without
any appeal from the decision) while others sit in plenary to determine such
applications.
The drawbacks in having a full plenary of judges deciding applica-
tions to disqualify one or more of their own are obvious. The judges are
effectively deciding whether their judicial colleagues are actually biased or
could be perceived to be so. Further, potential future conflicts of interest
will inevitably arise, for example, an application to disqualify an entire trial
chamber may involve some potential appellate judges deciding in plenary
an issue that could reappear in an appeal. The non-appealable three-judge
panel model suffers exactly the same defects.
By contrast, in some national systems the judge first decides whether
they should continue in the case, and the applicant may appeal an adverse
decision to another court. This model, in my view, provides greater institu-
tional integrity and hence credibility. Again, the fact that the institutions
stand alone, unlike in national systems, with no appeal possible beyond the
4
Politicising the disciplining and removal of judges must be avoided. See for example, Re-
port of the Special Rapporteur on the independence of judges and lawyers, Diego García-
Sayán, A/75/172, 17 July 2020.
5
See Erik Møse, “Reflections on Integrity in International Criminal Justice and Regional
Human Rights Courts”, Chapter 19, Section 4 (“Personal Integrity – Some Illustrations”).
6
Promotion and Protection of all Human Rights, Civil, Political, Economic, Social and Cul-
tural Rights, Including the Right to Development. Opinions adopted by the Working Group
on Arbitrary Detention, A/HRC/10/21/Add.1, 4 February 2009, Opinion No. 37/2007.
7
I am excluding the work of the permanent international human rights courts here, although
all applications have a state as a respondent, and states naturally desire a favourable out-
come in each case against them.
legal rights. And like many others, I add that much greater care must be
taken in nominating suitable officials to serve in international justice insti-
tutions. Many reforms in this respect have been proposed, but short of
somehow magically removing the political dimension from the appoint-
ment, nomination and election process – or injecting into it a novel level of
transparency – probably little will change.
To conclude, attaining and maintaining adequate levels of integrity is
difficult. It requires recognition of the structural obstacles, and some ad-
justment of expectations to make achieving these goals even a semi-
realistic aim. External structural change is crucial. I remain an optimist but
now with a glass swishing between half-full and half-empty, depending on
the viewing angle.
International Criminal Tribunal for the former Stanišić and Župljanin case, 725, 959, 960,
Yugoslavia 969, 973
Blagojević and Jokić case, 966 State influence, 1068
Blagojević et al. case, 967 Tadić case, 692, 963
Blaškić case, 966 travel funds, 1069, 1072
Borovčanin case, 999, 1000 Vasiljević case, 963, 966
Čelebići case, 911, 980, 1055 International Labour Organization
convictions, 397 Administrative Tribunal. See International
co-operation (UN), 1070 Criminal Court
establishment, 497, 906, 1066 International Nuremberg Principles Academy, i,
fair trial rights, 442, 448, 454, 731 ii, iv, v, vi, viii, x, xiii, 1, 234, 845, 916,
Furundžija case, 455, 746, 965, 1013 1029, 1080
gender-related issues, 1076 Acceptance of International Criminal Justice
Gotovina case, 970, 977 in Situation Countries, 235
influence (UN), 1071, 1072 International Protocol on the Documentation
influence (United States), 1070 of Investigation of Sexual Violence in
Investigations Division, 413, 428 Conflict, 819
joint criminal enterprise, 955, 960, 964, 971, International Residual Mechanism for
977 Criminal Tribunals
Jokić case, 963 disciplinary procedures, 742
judicial conduct, 1055 Ngirabatware case, 919
judicial ethics (code), 754 investigations
Karadžić case, 703, 1070 deontology, 639, 815
Krajišnik and Plavšić case, 441 entrepreneurial justice, 626
Krstić case, 438, 451, 506 evidence collection (illegal), 618, 648, 664
Leadership Research Team, 420, 428 extra-investigatory context, 668, 731
Lukić and Lukić case, 967 fact-finding, relation with, 616
Lukić case, 453, 967 gender balance, 831
Military Analysis Team, 420, 428 integrity, 642, 738
Milošević case, 456, 464 inter-investigatory context, 665
Mladić case, 1071 intra-investigatory context, 667, 728
Mrkšić and Šljivančanin case, 967 monitoring, 820
Mrkšić case, 967 police investigators, 637
negotiations, 1067 prioritisation, 835
Nikolić case, 731, 910 private, 616, 623, 627, 733
Pakistan, 1069 private investigator (definition), 631
Perišić case, 951, 962, 967, 975, 976, 977, quality control, 908, 912
981 resource management, 908
political encroachment, 171 Syria (private), 624, 631
Popović case, 965 trial, separation with, 706, 715
propaganda (anti-), 476 victims and witnesses, 835, 839, 840
prosecutorial conduct, 1067 witness preparation, 909
recruitment, iii, 414 Iraq
resource management, 907 Kurdistan Regional Government, 841
Šainović case, 453, 965, 968, 976 Martyrs Foundation, 841
Šešelj case, 956, 960 United Nations. See United Nations, co-
Šljivančanin case, 967 operation (States)
specific direction (requirement), 962 Irfan, Hannah, 248
Standards of Professional Conduct for Islamic law. See Sharí‘ah
Prosecution Counsel, 437 Islamic State of Iraq and the Levant, 816
Stanišić and Simatović case, 951, 963, 977 accountability, 816, See also United Nations,
Investigative Team (Daesh/ISIL)
Editorial Assistants
Pauline Brosch
Marquise Lee Houle
Genevieve Zingg
Scientific Advisers
Professor Danesh Sarooshi, Principal Scientific Adviser for International Law
Professor Andreas Zimmermann, Principal Scientific Adviser for Public International Law
Professor Kai Ambos, Principal Scientific Adviser for International Criminal Law
Dr.h.c. Asbjørn Eide, Principal Scientific Adviser for International Human Rights Law
Editorial Board
Dr. Xabier Agirre, International Criminal Court
Dr. Claudia Angermaier, Austrian judiciary
Ms. Neela Badami, Narasappa, Doraswamy and Raja
Advisory Board
Mr. Hirad Abtahi, International Criminal Court
Judge Silvana Arbia, former Registrar of the International Criminal Court
Professor Olympia Bekou, University of Nottingham
Mr. Gilbert Bitti, International Criminal Court
Research Professor J. Peter Burgess, PRIO
Former Judge Advocate General Arne Willy Dahl, Norway
Professor Emeritus Yoram Dinstein, Tel Aviv University
Professor Jon Elster, Columbia University and Collège de France
Mr. James A. Goldston, Open Society Institute Justice Initiative
Mr. Richard J. Goldstone, former Chief Prosecutor, ICTY
Judge Hanne Sophie Greve, Gulating Court of Appeal, formerly ECtHR
Dr. Fabricio Guariglia, International Criminal Court
Professor Franz Günthner, Ludwig-Maximilians-Universität
Mr. Wolfgang Kaleck, European Center for Constitutional and Human Rights
Former Judge Erkki Kourula, International Criminal Court
Professor Claus Kreß, Cologne University
Professor David Luban, Georgetown University
Mr. Juan E. Méndez, former President, ICTJ
Dr. Alexander Muller, Director, The Hague Institute for the Internationalisation of Law
Judge Erik Møse, European Court of Human Rights, former President, ICTR
Dr. Gro Nystuen, Norwegian Judge
Mr. William Pace, Convener, Coalition for the International Criminal Court
Ms. Jelena Pejić, International Committee of the Red Cross
Mr. Robert Petit, former International Co-Prosecutor, ECCC
Dr. Joseph Rikhof, Ottawa University, Canada
Maj-Gen (ret’d) Anthony P.V. Rogers, Cambridge University
Professor William A. Schabas, Middlesex University
Professor James Silk, Yale Law School
Associate Professor YANG Lijun, Chinese Academy of Social Science
Professor Marcos Zilli, University of Sao Paulo
Viviane E. Dittrich, Kerstin von Lingen, Philipp Osten and Jolana Makraiová (editors):
The Tokyo Tribunal: Perspectives on Law, History and Memory
Torkel Opsahl Academic EPublisher
Brussels, 2020
Nuremberg Academy Series No. 3 (2020)
ISBNs: 978-82-8348-137-2 (print) and 978-82-8348-138-9 (e-book)
All volumes are freely available online at http://www.toaep.org/nas/. For printed copies, see
http://www.toaep.org/about/distribution/. For reviews of earlier books in this Series in academic
journals and yearbooks, see http://www.toaep.org/reviews/.
The International Nuremberg Principles Academy (Nuremberg Academy) is a non-profit
foundation dedicated to the advancement of international criminal law and human rights. It was
established by the Federal Republic of Germany, the Free State of Bavaria, and the City of Nu-
remberg in 2014. The activities and projects of the Academy are supported through contributions
from the three founding entities and financially supported by the Federal Foreign Office of
Germany.