The Emotions in Early Phenomenology
The Emotions in Early Phenomenology
The Emotions in Early Phenomenology
Abstract: This paper offers an overview of certain key features of the accounts
of emotion defended by the early phenomenologists. After briefly presenting
the movement of early phenomenology and describing its historical context, I
shall elaborate the main claims about the emotions defended by this group, ar-
ticulating them through the following five topics: 1) the stratification of emo-
tional life; 2) the qualitative aspect of emotional experience; 3) the foundation
of the emotions in cognitive acts; 4) the intentionality of feeling and the emo-
tions; and 5) their moral dimension. The paper finishes with some concluding
remarks about the significance of the early phenomenological discussion of the
emotions for the debate on this topic in contemporary analytical philosophy.
1
Fortunate exceptions to this neglect can be found in the work of Eberhard Avé-Lallemant,
Manfred Frings, Dermot Moran, Kevin Mulligan, Juan Miguel Palacios, Barry Smith, Anthony
Steinbock, Kenneth Stikkers and Dan Zahavi.
330 Íngrid Vendrell Ferran
2
This new paradigm is nowadays illustrated by Peter Goldie’s concept of “feeling towards”
(Goldie 2002).
The Emotions in Early Phenomenology 331
On the one hand, one could mention the vicissitudes of the First World War,
and the loss of one of its main figures in Adolf Reinach. This last event proved
particularly devastating for the group as a whole. On the other hand, Hus-
serl’s “idealistic turn” after the publication of Ideas disappointed those of his
pupils who had a more realistic orientation, fracturing the unity of the earlier
years. After the later transformations of phenomenology through the work
of Heidegger, Sartre, and Merleau-Ponty—thinkers who certainly exercised
a greater influence upon the developments of 20th century philosophy—the
lively debates and rich analyses of the early movement fell into oblivion.
Consequently, and with a few exceptions, the authors under consideration
here remain largely unknown, despite the detailed analyses of the affective
life undertaken during this period. In fact, two systematic accounts of the
emotions can be found in early phenomenology: Pfänder’s work on the will,
motivation, and the sentiments and Scheler’s reflections on the relation be-
tween feeling and value, as well as in his detailed analyses of specific emotions,
including love, resentment, humility, shame, and sympathy, to name just a
few.3 Aside from these two broader theories, we can also find detailed accounts
of specific emotional phenomena. Else Voigtländer wrote a dissertation on
self-directed emotions; Willy Haas focused mainly on the authenticity of the
emotions; Moritz Geiger worked on emotional atmospheres, empathy and
emotional delusions; Edith Stein offers the first detailed account of empathy
and intersubjectivity; and Gerda Walther considered the ontology of social
communities. Also in the line of the early phenomenologists are Dietrich von
Hildebrand’s analysis of value-perception and social communities, José Orte-
ga y Gasset’s studies of emotional expression, types of love, and their relation
to history and culture, and Aurel Kolnais’ essays on disgust, pride, and hatred.
While these texts were written after the early phenomenological movement
had reached its peak, they can be regarded as belonging to this group never-
theless, because they share not least a methodological attitude, a conception of
mind, and the conviction that emotions are relevant to ethics.4
The philosophical context in which the early phenomenological contri-
butions emerged was dominated by feeling theories, which conceived of the
emotions as felt qualities. Two models were widely discussed at the time. On
the one hand was Wundt’s tridimensional theory, according to which all feel-
ings oscillate in three dimensions, pleasure-pain, excitement-inhibition, and
tension-relaxation, the first one of these dimensions being the most impor-
tant (Wundt 1887). On the other hand, was the James-Lange theory of the
emotions, according to which emotions are reducible to complexes of bodily
feelings (James 1905). In contrast to these dominant theories and following
3
For a detailed account of Scheler’s theory of feeling, see Henckmann 1998 and Mulligan
2008.
4
Cf. Vendrell Ferran 2008.
332 Íngrid Vendrell Ferran
5
The early phenomenologists applied the eidetic reduction without performing the tran-
scendental reduction. It is nevertheless possible to apply the eidetic reduction to the results
obtained from a transcendental one.
6
The way in which Husserl understood phenomenological methodology in his Logical
Investigations differs significantly from his later understanding after the “transcendental turn”.
The Emotions in Early Phenomenology 333
7
My interpretation of Husserl’s account of intentionality and the conception of phenom-
enological method may seem one-sided to contemporary Husserl scholars. Nevertheless, my
understanding of the concept of intentionality, following a distinction between a “subjective”
and “objective” phenomenology and its methodological implications, follows a possible line
of Husserl interpretation inaugurated by Geiger. Without ignoring the fact that other inter-
pretations are possible, Geiger’s interpretative line is useful for explaining the methodological
attitude of the early phenomenologists as focusing on the object as given (Geiger 1933: 13).
334 Íngrid Vendrell Ferran
This controversial thesis was later discussed by his pupils in the Graz School
(Ehrenfels, Meinong and Höfler) and within phenomenology (Stumpf, Hus-
serl and Scheler). Their alternative thesis will consist in dividing this class in
two main types: emotions and volitions.
The second Brentanian claim developed by his pupils was the thesis that
emotions depend on cognitive acts. According to Brentano each psychic act
is a presentation or is itself founded on a presentation (Brentano 1924: 112).
Thus, judgments and emotions (in Brentano’s general sense) are founded acts.
For the emotions, this means that they are necessarily founded on presenta-
tions and on judgments. Also this thesis of the dependence of emotion on
cognition was inherited by the early phenomenologists, although they intro-
duce at least three important alterations. In their accounts, the term “emo-
tion” becomes used in a more restrictive sense—a sense closer to our cur-
rent use, and of which shame, fear, disgust etc. count as paradigmatic cases.
Further, they consider the cognitive basis of the emotions in a broader sense
which does not necessarily imply judgments. Finally, in contrast to Brentano’s
intellectualistic model, they give a greater primacy to the affective dimension
of human experience than to its cognitive one.
In what follows I will focus on five topics around which the authors of
this group articulated their discussions. I begin here with the taxonomy of the
emotional life according to different levels of depth. The stratification of the
emotional life is one of the most important discoveries of early phenomenol-
ogy. These authors recognized that affective phenomena are not all of the same
The Emotions in Early Phenomenology 335
8
Scheler follows in this respect Husserl’s critique of Brentano’s thesis that all psychic phe-
nomena are intentional. According to Husserl, sensation does not bear intentionality. Cf. Hus-
serl 1992a: 383
9
An interesting discussion of the different ways one can attend to an emotion can be found
in Geiger 1911b.
The Emotions in Early Phenomenology 337
bodily moment, i.e. they are bodily felt, even though we cannot localize them
in a specific part of the body. They are also intentional, directed towards ob-
jects and related to the following couples of values: “beautiful” and “ugly,”
“fair” and “unfair,” and “true” and “false”.
The fourth stratum belongs to the “spiritual feelings” (“geistige Gefühle”)
or “feelings of the personality,” such as bliss or desperation. There are two
very controversial theses related to this kind of feelings. According to Scheler
spiritual feelings are related to a special kind of value, those of the sacred and
the profane. With this claim one can see the influence of a book that was
very popular at the time, namely Otto’s Das Heilige. In my opinion, however,
a further study of the spiritual feelings or feelings of the personality should
examine the possibility that other values might be included in this domain.10
The other controversial claim defended not only by Scheler, but broadly by
the early phenomenologists, is that spiritual feelings do not have a bodily mo-
ment, i.e. that they are not “body-bound” (Scheler 1973b: 332 and 336; Stein
1989: 50). The argument for this claim is as follows: any given spiritual feeling
will remain wholly intact if we abstract from the stratum of bodily experience,
thus disregarding such felt phenomena as the quivering of the hands or the
rapid beating of the heart. The feeling in its purity will remain, even while the
bodily sensations disappear. Despite the appeal of this thought experiment,
the notion of a type of feeling that is not bodily felt is strikingly odd, or at
least in need of further clarification. It certainly may be the case that the “way”
in which a feeling of this sort is experienced bodily is very different from the
way in which shame, disgust or envy is felt. But this difference need not entail
that the feeling involves no bodily moment. In section 3 I will return to this
question, making use of the phenomenological distinction between physical
and living body.
I argued earlier that feelings which belong to different layers can co-exist
without blending into a unique general feeling. It should be noted, however,
that this impossibility of fusion does not necessarily exclude their mutual in-
fluence. In fact, on this point the early phenomenological accounts are not
in unanimous agreement. For Scheler, on the one hand, the strata are quite
independent of each other. Two feelings that are opposed in their valence but
belong to different strata, such as pain and bliss, can co-exist simultaneously
without influencing one another. Stein’s view, on the other hand, seems to me
more plausible, as the following illuminating example encapsulates: “For ex-
ample, suppose I take a trip to recuperate and arrive at a sunny, pleasant spot.
While looking at the view, I feel that a cheerful mood wants to take possession
of me, but cannot prevail because I feel sluggish and tired” (Stein 1989: 49).
Such examples seem to suggest that feelings belonging to different strata may
in fact exercise influence on one another.
10
Cf. For a detailed account on mystical experiences Steinbock 2007.
338 Íngrid Vendrell Ferran
11
Similar considerations concerning the relation between emotions and moods have been
recently articulated by Peter Goldie (Goldie 2002: 8).
12
Compare for example Ryle’s classification of the emotions in The Concept of Mind (Ryle
1949).
The Emotions in Early Phenomenology 339
The aspect of the feelings with which we are more familiar is their “felt”
dimension, i.e. the qualitative phenomenal way in which they are given to us
in experience.
Early phenomenologists claimed that the feelings (with the notable excep-
tion of the spiritual ones) characteristically involve a phenomenal aspect. This
bodily felt dimension of an emotion should not be understood as a complex
of concomitant sensations, that is, of sensations that appear in addition to the
emotion as a pure mental act. The bodily dimension of shame, for instance,
cannot be reduced to the acceleration of the cardiac rhythm, or to blushing
and sweating. It is also essential to this emotion that we experience a “pre-
formed action,” an “intention to move” or an “action tendency” to leave the
shameful scenario (Ortega y Gasset 1966; Scheler 1973a: 234; and in the
current literature Elster 1999: 246), and that we feel as if our body were be-
coming smaller.
Such qualitative aspects of emotional experience cannot be easily explained
with sole recourse to bodily sensations, but they nevertheless constitute an im-
portant part of the experience. In order to do justice to this aspect of the emo-
tions, the early phenomenologists introduced a helpful distinction between
“physical body” (“Körper”) and “living body” (“Leib”). The “physical body”
is given to us in external perception, and just like any other physical thing
it can be considered in quantitative and objective terms. To consider again
the bodily dimension of shame, we can exactly measure the pulsations of our
heart, the intensity of the blushing in our face, the warmth of the skin, and so
on. The “living body,” on the other hand, is that dimension of our body that
can be felt without our making use of sense perception. The felt dimension of
vitality, tiredness, or shame cannot be measured, and is rather a phenomenon
of the living body.
One can find rich descriptions of the living body in the work of Scheler,
Ortega y Gasset, and Kolnai, but it seems to me that Stein’s definition of the
living body is the most accurate:
For even if we shut our eyes tightly and stretch out our arms, in fact allowing
no limb to contact another so that we can neither touch nor see our physical
body, even then we are not rid of it. Even then it stands there inescapably in
full embodiment (hence the name), and we find ourselves bound to it per-
ceptually. Precisely this affiliation, this belonging to me, could never be con-
stituted in outer perception. A living body [Leib], only perceived outwardly
would always be only a particularly disposed, actually unique, physical body,
but never “my living body”. (Stein 1989: 42)
Unlike the physical body, the living body is always given to me as a whole,
and simultaneously as the “zero point” in my orientation towards the world.
340 Íngrid Vendrell Ferran
With the living body we have an intimate awareness of our own body and its
surroundings, one that doesn’t involve the externality or objectivity of outer
perception. While a detailed elaboration of the distinction between living and
physical body would move beyond the scope of this article, my aim is to focus
on its implications for the early phenomenological theory of the emotions.
I am especially interested in applying the concept of the living body to the
different strata of “feelings” mentioned in the previous section. I will focus
mainly on the question of how one could, without abandoning the early phe-
nomenological framework, consider the spiritual feelings as essentially bodily
felt—a proposal that stands in contrast to the position actually defended by
the early phenomenologists.
In light of the distinction between physical and living body, it is possible
to account for the qualitative aspect of emotional experience in a detailed
way, one which takes into consideration the complexity of the phenomenon.
Whereas the physical concomitant manifestations of an emotion on the side
of the physical body are not essential to the emotion itself, it is impossible to
dissociate the emotional experience from the way in which it is qualitatively
experienced in the living body. Thus, with respect to shame, while blushing
or sweating may occur during an episode of shame, they are not essential to
this emotion; what is essential to it is rather the action tendency to abandon
the situation and the feeling of our body becoming smaller. This way of ex-
periencing an emotion can only be described with reference to the body as
a living body (“Leib”), as opposed to as a physical body. This idea that the
emotions are felt in a particular way, that is, that each emotion is characterised
by a particular phenomenology of the body, can also be found in the work of
Ortega y Gasset, who distinguishes between the body as a mineral and as flesh
(Ortega y Gasset 1966), as it can in Kolnai when he, for instance, claims that
emotions are “body-bound” (“Leibgebundenheit,” Kolnai 1974: 120). This
aspect of the corporeality of feeling has been further developed by Hermann
Schmitz in the framework of the “New-Phenomenology” (Schmitz 1998: 12).
The early phenomenologists, however, claim that this thesis does not ap-
ply to the class of the “spiritual” or / and “personality feelings”: They do not
require a living body to be felt. While this thesis was consistently defended
within early phenomenology, it seems to me difficult to give any sense to the
notion of a feeling being experienced in a wholly disembodied fashion. While
spiritual feelings are not bodily-bound in the sense of the physical body—
since their concomitant manifestations are inessential to their phenomenolog-
ical structure—if we interpret the importance of the body for the emotions in
the sense of a living body, then we can also maintain that spiritual feelings are
bodily-bound. The distinction between physical and living body, then, enables
us to give sense to the claim that spiritual emotions are body-bound. Spiritual
desperation and bliss, paradigmatic cases of spiritual feelings, are “felt” in the
sense that our living body is experienced in a certain way. In appealing to the
The Emotions in Early Phenomenology 341
concept of the living body to account for the qualitative dimension of the
emotions, then, we are able to say that all feelings are bodily felt.
[…], these feelings are always feeling of something. Every time I feel, I am
turned toward an object, something of an object is given to me, and I see a
level of the object. But, in order to see a level of the object, I must first have
it. It must be given to me in theoretical acts. Thus, the structure of all feelings
13
“Es kann ein Wahrnehmen, ein anschauliches Vorstellen oder auch ein unanschauliches
‘Denken an etwas’ sein.”
342 Íngrid Vendrell Ferran
requires theoretical acts. When I am joyful over a good deed, this is how the
deed’s goodness or its positive value faces me. But I must know about the deed
in order to be joyful over it— knowledge is fundamental to joy. An intuitive
perceptual or conceptual comprehension can also be substituted for this this
knowledge underlying the feeling of value. (Stein 1989: 100–101)
In this paragraph Stein speaks about the double aspect of the intentionality
of feelings. Feelings are characterised as intentional, they are always feelings of
something. They are “intentional” and according to Stein’s quotation they are
simultaneously directed towards two different kinds of objects: we are turned
towards a given object and we see a level of this object. Using the current
terminology of the analytical philosophy introduced by Kenny and adapted
from Scholasticism, I will refer to the given object of a feeling as the “mate-
rial object” and to refer to the level of this object I will speak of the “formal
object” (Kenny 1963). In this section I will focus only on the “material object”
and how it is given to me in the experience. In the next section I will develop
further the notion of “formal object”.
Stein claims that being directed towards the given object of a feeling (the
“material object”) requires that this object has first been given to me. This
having or representing the object can only be achieved by means of acts which
are “theoretical”—in contemporary language we would say “cognitive”—in
nature. The idea here is that experiencing an emotion is a matter of being di-
rected towards a specific “material object”. The reference to a “material object”
in this context should be understood in a very general sense, such that it can
apply to a thing, a person, a situation or a state of affairs. The important point
for Stein is rather that we need to first be conscious of something in order to
experience it emotionally, and for this it is necessary that we have perceived,
imagined, or thought about it.
The virtues of the broad form of cognitivism are fairly obvious. It accom-
modates certain cases that the strict version simply cannot account for. Con-
sider, for example, the disgust that we occasionally feel without passing any
judgement on the object which disgusts us, and which is rather based on
our perceptual experience of it. There are also cases in which an emotion is
grounded in imagination or supposition, such as when a child is fearful of a
ghost in her room, despite knowing it to be merely imaginary. That is, the
strong cognitivist is unable to account for those emotions that base themselves
in perceptions, fantasies or suppositions. To illustrate that such emotional
phenomena are in fact possible, we can consider a series of cases in which fear
is grounded in different cognitive bases: a) perception: The perception of a
dog, i.e. my seeing or hearing it, may suffice to arouse fear in me; b) fantasy:
just as my merely imagining it can do; c) belief: I may feel fear when I posi-
tively believe that the cage in a zoo is not strong enough to contain the gorilla
The Emotions in Early Phenomenology 343
inside it; d) supposition: I can also feel fear based on the mere supposition
that the gorilla is strong enough to break open its bars. It is worth noting
that broad cognitivist positions, resembling in many respects those offered by
early phenomenologists, can also be found in some contemporary analytical
accounts of the emotions (Goldie 2002, Mulligan 1998b).
The thesis that emotions are grounded in cognitive acts, does not apply
to all affective phenomena. On this point we can see a further difference be-
tween Brentano’s cognitivism and the modified form of it defended by early
phenomenologists. Whereas for Brentano, all psychic phenomena of the third
class are based on presentations and judgements, this claim is not defended by
the early phenomenologists. In early phenomenology, love and hatred count
as exceptions to the cognitivist model. This concession is based on a peculiar
feature of these affective phenomena, namely that when we love or hate some-
body it is not simply because we judge or perceive this person to be in a cer-
tain way. After all, it is possible to love somebody despite his mistakes and the
imperfections of his character, and to hate somebody despite all his virtues.
The early phenomenologists understand love and hate, not as emotions in the
strict sense, but rather as primary attitudes towards the world. Love and hate
are affective ways of being in the world, and such attitudes are not only pos-
sible without being grounded in “theoretical” or “cognitive acts,” they rather
constitute a basis for cognition and volition. I will come back to this point at
the end of the paper with the concept of “ordo amoris”.
that they are directed towards aspects of the object. These aspects of the object
which feelings are directed towards are “values” or—as we can say using the
current terminology—“formal objects”. To clarify this idea, we should recon-
sider Brentano’s famous claim that intentionality is “the mark of the mental,”
his analogy between emotions and judgements, and the further developments
of this claim among early phenomenologists.
According to Brentano, the different classes of psychic phenomena each
involve a distinct way of being directed towards an object. The intentional
directedness of the class of the emotions consists in “loving” or “hating” their
objects, i.e. in positioning us with a pro or contra attitude towards them. This
intentionality is specific to the emotions and cannot be founded in presen-
tations—which are characterized by a neutral way of being related to their
object—or in judgements—which aim at the truth or falsehood of the state of
affairs they intend. For the Brentano of the Psychology, the objects of the emo-
tions are simply ordinary things, such as persons, animals, objects, situations
and the like. We can, however, interpret Brentano as proposing that emotions
are related to objects of another kind. In particular, in his short treatise The
Origins of Our Knowledge of Right or Wrong he offers some suggestive hints
on the essential relation between the emotions and value. More precisely, he
argues in this text that it is correct to love the good and bad to love the bad,
and he spells this idea out in terms of the ‘fittingness’ of the emotions to the
things they are directed towards (Brentano 1921: 11). Emotions, thus, are not
only directed towards material objects but also to formal objects, i.e. to values.
Values are thus the formal objects of the emotions.
An interesting consequence of this definition is that while the range of
possible material objects for a specific emotion are individually and culturally
variable, the formal objects are always the same. While I can fear an inexistent
ghost, a storm, a dog, a situation or a state of affairs (i.e., a variety of different
material objects), my fear always announces that the feared object is some-
thing “dangerous” (i.e., a unitary formal object). A similar claim has been
defended by Ronald de Sousa (de Sousa 1987: 149 and 159).
A further consequence of this claim concerns the fact that emotions can
fit their formal objects or not. To illustrate this point, Brentano introduces
an analogy between emotions and judgements that was also developed by
the early phenomenologists. Emotions—just like judgements—have condi-
tions of satisfaction with respect to their objects. But while judgements can
be true or false it would be inadequate to speak about truth conditions for the
emotions, and Brentano and the phenomenologists will rather refer to their
appropriateness or inappropriateness. Brentano claims that when the love for
the lovable object is right, we speak of an appropriate emotion. He defends a
so called “fitting attitude theory” of value, a concrete form of “dispositional-
ism,” according to which values are assimilated to our possible dispositions
The Emotions in Early Phenomenology 345
to feel an affective phenomenon in the case that the material object has some
properties. The early phenomenologists, on the contrary, defend a more ro-
bust form of value realism. Like Brentano, they also maintained that emotions
have “conditions of satisfaction”. Value qualities demand certain emotional
responses and these reactions “reach their goal” in the value qualities. This
demanding character is clear when a value-demand remains unfulfilled and
we suffer as a result: “we are sad because we cannot be happy about an event
to the degree that its felt value deserves, or we cannot be as sad as the death of
beloved persons ‘demands’” (Scheler 1973b: 259).14 Values are the objective
correlates of the emotions. Following the line of argumentation developed
in the last two sections, we can specify two conditions which, for the early
phenomenologists, an emotion must fulfill in order to be appropriate: 1) its
“material object” is given by a perception, a fantasy, a judgement or a supposi-
tion; and 2) its “formal object” or “value” is the one that corresponds to the
emotion in question. An example in which the first condition fails is the case
of a person who feels disgust but no material object is given; a person feeling
disgusted by something fearful would fail to satisfy the second condition.
Brentano’s account of value is not a realist account, but it leaves the door
open for realism. He does not claim that “love and hate” discover the good or
the bad, but that we discover that something is good, because we love it (Bren-
tano 1921: 11). The early phenomenologists, on the other hand, speak of the
objective correlates of the emotions. On their accounts, values are regarded
as axiological properties that exist in an “objective” way—and this despite of
the fact that to be grasped they need the existence of subjects equipped with
the corresponding capacities needed to grasp them. One of the advantages of
value realism is that it permits an explanation of the “contrast phenomenon,”
i.e. the possibility of feeling a value from a determinate valence despite being
in another emotional state. We are able to grasp the charm of a landscape de-
spite being sad. Those accounts that make values dependent upon a subjective
stance encounter difficulties in accounting for this phenomenon.
Such a realist ontology requires a special epistemology, an account of how
it is possible for us to gain access to value. On the early phenomenological
account, human beings can grasp value in virtue of their capacity to feel, just
as we can grasp sounds through our capacity to hear and colours due to our
visual capabilities. The strong epistemological thesis defended by early phe-
nomenologists is the following one: the domain of values is only accessible
to affective beings because it is a domain of reality inaccessible to reason. As
Scheler claims reason is blind to values. Talking about feelings he puts it: “It is
a kind of experience that leads us to genuinely objective objects and the eternal
14
The case is different, however, for affects such as anger which are—according to Sche-
ler—not intentional. In this case, anger is caused by a thought, a representation or a perception
but it is in itself not an emotional response to a felt value.
346 Íngrid Vendrell Ferran
order among them, i.e., to values and the order of ranks among them” (Scheler
1973b: 255). In a similar vein, Stein writes as follows: “For, as physical na-
ture is constituted in perceptual acts, so a new object realm is constituted in
feeling.” (Stein 1989: 93). As affective beings equipped with the correspond-
ing epistemic tools, those that enable us to grasp values, we have access to a
domain of reality hidden to mere reason. The cognitive role of affective acts
consists in the disclosing or grasping of values. They have intentionality in
the strong sense of the word: they are not only directed to values but also are
responsible for their apprehension.
While unanimously agreeing that affective acts are responsible for grasp-
ing, apprehending and disclosing values, the early phenomenologists disagreed
about which concrete affective acts are responsible for such value-apprehen-
sion. Within the group, two distinct positions were formulated. While some
of the early phenomenologists maintained that the emotions (“Gefühle”) and
the feelings of value (“Fühlen”) comprised two distinct classes of affective ex-
perience, others rejected such a distinction and claimed that emotions are
feelings of value. Both positions are analysed in what follows.
People want to distinguish between “feeling” [Fühlen] and “the feeling” [Gefühl].
I do not believe that these two designations indicate different kinds of experi-
ences, but only different “directions” of the same experience. Feeling is an expe-
rience when it gives us an object or else something about an object. The feeling is
the same act when it appears to be originating out of the “I” or unveiling a level
of the “I”. (Stein 1989: 98–99; in a similar sense Stein 2000: 159)
The argument here is that the feeling of a value is also a way of experiencing
ourselves in an emotional experience. To this argument we can add a second.
While it seems coherent to think that the feeling of values is also bodily felt
in an emotion; it seems absurd to speak about a feeling of values that is not
felt as emotional experience. Furthermore, and this is the third argument,
both perception and emotion are object-directed acts. This directness explains
how we can speak of the emotions as appropriate or inappropriate reactions
to their objects, just as, in relation to its object, a perception can be either
veridical or illusory. Inspired by the phenomenological tradition, Christine
Tappolet claims that emotions are perceptions of values (Tappolet 2000: 8–9),
while Mark Johnston speaks about an authority of affect, in the sense that
the emotions simultaneously present us with a quality of the world and make
our desires and actions intelligible. In both of these respects, they are loosely
analogous to perception (Johnston 2001: 189).
Despite the intuitive appeal of the thesis that emotions disclose values, this
claim faces important problems.15 I will mention only two of them here, in
order to spell out why some phenomenologists decided to defend an alterna-
tive position, according to which emotion and the feeling of value should be
considered as distinct phenomena. The first problem is that there is no one to
one correspondence between emotion and value. Rather, the nuanced ways
in which the world presents itself to us is richer than the repertoire of emo-
tions that we as human beings can feel. The second difficulty derives from our
everyday experience: we can feel a value without necessarily living through an
emotional episode. We can grasp the melancholy of a picture without becom-
ing melancholic, just as we can see the injustice of a situation without neces-
sarily being outraged. Stein, who defends the claim that the feeling of value
is an emotional response, conceives of these as cases of an “empty grasp”. I
can grasp a value and remain “cold” about it. In these cases, “I’m empty in-
side” (2000, 161). According to Stein, to fully grasp a value requires that we
emotionally respond to it with a vital, psychological, or spiritual feeling. One
group of phenomenologists, however, argued for a clear separation of both
phenomena: the intentional and cognitive feeling of values and the emotional
response to them.
15
For a detailed account on the problems of the theory, see Mulligan 2009.
348 Íngrid Vendrell Ferran
something’ and mere feeling states” (Scheler 1973b: 255). Scheler regards in-
tentional feelings as a kind of “organ” for comprehending values (in the same
sense that the eyes are the organ for seeing or the ears the organs for hearing)
and he speaks of an “original emotive intentionality,” underscoring that the
intention “feeling of something” is responsible for grasping values (Scheler
1973b: 256).
In order to elaborate this thesis, Scheler distinguishes three main classes
of feelings: states, functions and acts of feeling. “Feeling-states,” under which
Scheler includes the moods and pleasure and pain, should be distinguished
from “intentional feelings”. This distinction is especially clear in those cases in
which different acts of feeling can be directed towards the same feeling-state
(Scheler 1973b: 256). Once aroused, a feeling of pleasure or pain can be suf-
fered, endured, tolerated or enjoyed. The feeling state then remains the same,
and what changes is only the way in which we feel it. An important trait of
feeling-states concerns the relation towards their objects: this connection is
mediated by experience and thinking. Feeling-states do not grasp the objects
they are directed towards, i.e. they are not intentional.
The second class is that of the intentional feelings, which Scheler describes
as a “goal-determined movement” essentially related to their objects (Scheler
1973b: 257). Intentional feelings can be of three different kinds: 1) The feeling
of feeling-states described above; 2) the feeling of objective emotional characteris-
tics of the atmosphere, as when we feel the restfulness of a river or the sadness of
a landscape16; and 3) the feeling of values such as the agreeable or the beautiful.
For Scheler, only this third class of intentional feelings have a cognitive func-
tion, since in such feelings values are grasped (Scheler 1973b: 257).
The third type of feeling is the emotional act-experiences, which can be
divided into two categories. 1) Preferring and placing after which are respon-
sible for the apprehension of the rank in which values are organised. Prefer-
ring takes place on the basis of the felt value-material. 2) Love and hate, as
the highest level of affective life. According to Scheler, love and hate are not
responses to felt values, but spontaneous acts: “In love and hate our spirit
does much more than ‘respond’ to already felt and perhaps preferred values.
Love and hate are acts in which the value-realm accessible to the feeling of a
being […] is either extended or narrowed” (Scheler 1973b: 261). These higher
emotional acts are responsible for the discovery of values: they designate an
attitude of openness (in love) or closedness (in hatred). In a similar fashion,
Pfänder claims that love and hate are sentiments, and that through them we
are open or closed to the world (Pfänder 1922).
To return to our original question, where should we place the emotions
in this theory? On Scheler’s view, vital, psychological and spiritual feelings
16
This point is also developed by another early phenomenologist: Moritz Geiger (Geiger
1911a).
The Emotions in Early Phenomenology 349
(“Gefühle”) are responses to values but they have to be separated from the
feeling of value itself (“Fühlen”). As we have seen, for Scheler only the inten-
tional feelings of value and the feeling-acts are intentional and cognitive in
the strong sense of the word, i.e. are responsible for disclosing values and their
hierarchy and for discovering them. Vital, psychological and spiritual feelings,
on the other hand, do not have an intentional and cognitive function of this
kind. They are intentional in the weak sense of being directed towards values
and responding to them, but not in the sense of grasping them! According to
Scheler’s theory, the grasping of value is essentially prior to any emotional re-
sponse. We can lead some support to this claim by noting that we often grasp
a value without emotionally responding to it. One can, for instance, grasp the
unfairness of a situation. Grasping this value, however, does not necessarily
entail that one reacts to it with an emotional response. This account is not,
however, without its problems. In particular, Scheler’s claim that the feelings
of value (“Fühlen”) are not bodily felt is somewhat mysterious, since it is dif-
ficult to make sense of the notion of a feeling that is not in some way given
bodily. An interesting solution to this problem can be found in Dieter von
Hildebrand’s distinction between two forms of the intuitive apprehension of
value (“Werterfassen”): the seeing of value (“Wertsehen”) and the feeling of
value (“Wertfühlen”). In the first case, we are able to grasp a value in a distant
way without necessarily having a feeling; while in the second case, we feel it
and are able to experience it (von Hildebrand 1982: 29).
Other phenomenologists have defended accounts similar to Scheler’s, no-
tably Geiger, who in his analysis of aesthetic pleasure, argued for a separation
of feeling and emotion (Geiger 1974: 8) and Ortega y Gasset, who adopts
a similar mode to Scheler (Ortega y Gasset 1966: 325, 328, 331). More re-
cently, Mulligan has developed Scheler’s theory further, claiming that emo-
tions and desires do not have any cognitive function, that they are not able
to grasp values, and that only the feeling (“Fühlen”) can fulfil this function
(Mulligan 2009).
of the world of values.” (Scheler 1973c: 116). Stein also stresses this correlation
between the hierarchy of the personality and the hierarchy of values: “Person
and world (more exactly, value world) were found to be completely corre-
lated” (Stein 1989: 103 and 108). The ontological claim of value realism has
its epistemological counterpart in the thesis that affective beings are able to
grasp values. Affectivity is seen not as a complex of irrational and blind states
of the soul but as an organized constellation, encompassing, on the one hand,
the function of feeling, which is responsible for grasping values, acts of prefer-
ence, which are responsible for grasping the relations between them, and love,
which is responsible for their discovery; on the other hand, they encompass
vital, psychological, and spiritual emotional responses to those grasped values.
Each affective being is a counter-image and microcosm of the world of values.
Second, to emphasize the moral dimension of the emotions we can also
formulate a motivational consideration. For the early phenomenologists, affec-
tive acts do not only open us up to the value of things, they also provide mo-
tives for action. In some cases, this tendency to action would be prudential,
as in the case of feeling a fear of heights where this fear motivates the agent to
avoid high places. In some other cases, however, the tendency to act is moral,
as when shame motivates the agent to protect her intimate self. Only in this
last case are the emotions morally relevant. This idea contrasts starkly with
the Kantian view, according to which the realm of affectivity can only distort
the morality of our behaviour. For the early phenomenologists, on the other
hand, the emotions provide a valid and important motive for good behaviour.
It is crucial, however, not to misunderstand their position as asserting that
action ought to be guided by the emotions alone. An ethics grounded only in
emotion would be mistaken, and the emotions always need the corrective of
reason (Kolnai 1974).
Third, consider the justification consideration. Affective acts ground and
justify judgements of value. Many of our deeply held beliefs, attitudes, and
judgements are grounded in emotional experience. For example, suppose that
I notice the behaviour of a person and feel insulted by his actions, even if I do
not know exactly what he is doing and why he is doing it. Taking this feeling
as my point of departure, I might then think that the behaviour was offensive,
and on this basis negatively evaluate the person in question. As such cases
show, emotions often play a crucial role in evaluation. They cannot, however,
always justify our evaluative judgements alone, and the mediation of evalua-
tive thinking is often required.
Another point is also relevant here. The phenomenological claim that
emotions may be fitting, i.e. that they present their objects as having cer-
tain evaluative features, does not imply a “moralistic fallacy” (d’Arms and
Jacobson 2000). As stated above, an emotion may be considered a fitting re-
sponse in light of its cognitive basis and the value towards which it is directed.
This, however, should be distinguished from the fact that we can evaluate an
The Emotions in Early Phenomenology 351
7. Concluding Remarks
To conclude, we can note that a new conception of the relation between af-
fectivity and reason emerges from the early phenomenological investigations.
Affectivity and reason are not two separate spheres, but rather interrelate in
multiple and varied ways. The central insight found in the early phenomeno-
logical discussions of the emotions is that the intentional and cognitive feeling
of values and the emotional responses are not a chaotic mixture of blind and
irrational affects but an organized system with a cognitive and a moral func-
tion. These claims are also constitutive of theories of affective intentionality
found the current analytical debate on the emotions. As I have shown in this
paper, there are important parallels between the most relevant theses devel-
oped by the early phenomenologists and some fundamental claims found in
recent analytic discussion of the emotions. These parallels are not only of
historical interest, since they suggest that early phenomenology placed weight
on the development of a new paradigm of affectivity and, for this reason, that
352 Íngrid Vendrell Ferran
the contemporary debate might gain significant insights from attending to the
work of the early phenomenologists.
Works cited: