Micro Physics and Power
Micro Physics and Power
Micro Physics and Power
REFERENCES
Linked references are available on JSTOR for this article:
http://www.jstor.com/stable/191008?seq=1&cid=pdf-
reference#references_tab_contents
You may need to log in to JSTOR to access the linked references.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
Sage Publications, Inc. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to
Political Theory
A Problem in
Radical Translation?
MARK PHILP
Jesus College
A UTHOR'S NOTE: I am most grateful to Charles Taylor, Steven Lukes, Jim Tully,
William Connolly, Wendy Brown, Michael Brint, and Bob Ashcroft for their comments
on earlier drafts of this article. In particular, I would like to thank John Gray for his
continued encouragement and his detailed criticism. Remaining errors are, of course, my
own.
0090-5917 83 010029-24$2.65
29
power, using a good deal of quotation but also attempting to render his
thought rather more accessible than it usually appears to be. I then raise
three problem areas in Foucault's account: his conception of the
political, his ideas about repression, and his view of resistance. Finally, I
conclude by asking how far his account of power can be considered as a
contribution to the broader debate on the definition of the concept.
some sense intentional, and it must also be possible to state that without
A's action, B would have acted differently.
The power of a class refers above all to its objective place in economic, political and
ideological relations-a place which overlies the practices of the struggling classes
(that is, the unequal relations of domination-subordination among classes rooted
in the social division of labour) and which already consists in power relationships.
The place of each class, and hence its power is delimited (i.e., at once designated
and limited) by the place of the other classes. Power is not, then, a quality attached
to a class in-itself, understood as a collection of agents, but depends on, and springs
from, a relational system of material places occupied by particular agents.'7
Putting aside for the moment the fraught question of agency, let us
summarize the point of the relational view of power. Relational views
see power as a term applying to a set of relations in which there are
conflicts of interests, goals, desires, preferences, and so on, and where
one side is able to attain its interests, goals, desires, preferences, and so
on at the expense of the other. We have suggested that there are four
components that a relational theory of power might invoke, the first
two being common to both Lukes and Poulantzas: significant affect-
ing, a characterization of interests (goals, desires, preferences, and
so on), agency/intention, and the counterfactual case.
Although Foucault uses a relational conception of power, he rejects
both Lukes's radical conflict model and Poulantzas's structural conflict
view. He rejects the former on the grounds that it retains an individualist
account of agency, and the latter on the grounds of its assumption of a
general and organized domination. More significantly, he also rejects
both on the grounds that they use the concept of repression, which
Power's condition of possibility ... is the moving substrate of force relations which,
by virtue of the inequality, constantly engender states of power, but the latter are
always local and unstable.22
The manifold relationships of force that take shape and come into play in the
machinery of production, in families, limited groups, and institutions, are the basis
for wide ranging effects of cleavage that run through the social body as a whole.26
Global domination is, then, the end point of an analysis of power, not its
starting point. Third, concerning agency and intention Foucault argues:
Power relations are both intentional and non-subjective. . . there is no power that is
exercised without a series of aims and objectives ... the logic is perfectly clear, the
aims decipherable, and yet it is often the case that no one is there to have invented
them and few can be said to have formulated them.27
II
In a society such as ours, but basically in any society, there are manifold relations of
power which permeate, characterise and constitute the social body, and these
relations of power cannot themselves be established, consolidated nor imple-
mented without the accumulation and functioning of a discourse. There can be
no possible exercise of power without a certain economy of discourses of truth
which operate through and on the basis of this association. We are subjected to
the production of truth through power and we cannot exercise power except
through the production of truth. [In our society] power never ceases its
interrogation, its acquisition, its registration of truth: it institutionalises and
rewards its pursuit.
It is, then, only at the level of discourse and the production of truth
that the strategies that integrate the relations of force operate. The
intentionality of such strategies is thus discursive, rather than indi-
vidual. Foucault is clearly issuing a challenge to both radical and
Marxist theories. Against Marxism he poses the view that one cannot
simply identify a mode of production and its dominant class and then
deduce from this everything one needs to know about the operation of
power in that society. Domination does not radiate from the peak to the
depths; this is to be too glib. Rather, we need to see domination in terms
of a "microphysics" of power: the way in which particular mechanisms
of power, with particular histories and rationales, are colonized,
invested, utilized, and so on, by ever more general mechanisms, which
built up into forms of global domination. Against liberalism and the
radicals Foucault poses the absence of an originating subject or actor.
Individuals are the effect of power, they are its subjects and its vehicles,
not its point of origin. The intentionality of power is not individual,
though it is articulated through individuals:
The other,
focused on the species body, the body imbued with the mechanics of life and
serving as the basis of the biological processes: propogation, births and mortality,
the level of health, life expectancy and longevity, with all the conditions that can
cause these to vary. Their supervision was effected through an entire series of
interventions and regulatory controls: a biopolitics of population.34
III
implies that the relations of power that function in a society such as ours essentially
rest upon a definite relation of forces that is established at a determinate,
historically specifiable moment, in war and by war.... If it is true that political
power puts an end to war. . . this by no means implies that it suspends the effects of
war or neutralises the disequilibrium revealed in the final battle. The role of
political power, on this hypothesis, is perpetually to re-inscribe this relation
through a form of unspoken warfare: to re-inscribe it in social institutions, in
economic inequalities, in language, in the bodies themselves of each and every one
of us.36
It is one of the essential traits of Western societies that the force relationships which
for a long time had found expression in war, in every form of warfare, gradually
became invested in the order of political power.39
It seems to me that power is "always already there, that one is never outside it, that
there are no margins for those who break with the system to gambol in.43
But, if there are no margins, is it possible to break from the system at all?
We seem to have a dead end. Foucault offers us three conflicting
If the fight is directed against power, then all those on whom power is exercised to
their detriment, all who find it intolerable, can begin the struggle on their own
terrain.... In engaging in a struggle that concerns their own interests, whose
objectives they clearly understand and whose methods only they can determine,
they enter the revolutionary process.... Women, prisoners, conscripted soldiers,
hospital patients, and homosexuals have now begun a specific struggle against the
particularised power, the constraints and controls, that are exerted over them.
Such struggles ... are radical, uncompromising and non-reformist, and refuse any
attempt at arriving at a new disposition of the same power with, at best, a change of
masters.53
There is indeed always something in the social body, in classes, groups and
individuals which in some sense escapes the relations of power, something which is
by no means a more or less docile or reactive primal matter, but rather a centrifugal
movement, an inverse energy, a discharge. There is ... a certain plebian quality or
aspect .... There is [sic] plebs in bodies, in souls, in individuals, in the proletariat,
in the bourgeoisie, but everywhere in a diversity of forms and extensions, or
energies and irreducibilities.54
There are no relations of power without resistances; the latter are all the more real
and effective because they are formed right at the point where relations of power
are exercised; resistance to power does not have to come from somewhere else to be
real, nor is it inexorably frustrated through being the compatriot of power. It exists
all the more by being in the same place as power; hence, like power, resistances are
multiple and can be integrated into global strategies.56
For if power is already there, if every power situation is immanent in itself, why
should there ever be resistance? From where would resistance come, and how
would it even be possible?57
Machiavelli was among the few ... who conceived of the power of the Prince in
terms of force relationships.... Perhaps we need to go one step further ... and
decipher power mechanisms on the basis of a strategy that is immanent in force
relationships. 59
Stressing this, we might then claim that force and resistance are
related analytically (that to force A to x is just to overcome A's
resistance to x) and thus that, since power is predicated on force
relations, resistance is always evident at points where power is. But this
only moves the process further back to the ill-defined terms "force" and
"resistance." However, although Foucault would probably not accept
this account, there is one that is similar that he might well recognize. We
might suggest that resistance is the "other" of power-just as sickness is
the "other" of health, madness is the "other" of reason, and deviance is
the "other" of normality. In the History of Sexuality, for example,
Foucault shows how sexuality itself is produced through the techniques
of discourse; and in Discipline and Punish he shows in a similar way how
the body of the prisoner is subjected to rigorous discursive control-in
both the individual is made a subject by his or her sexual or criminal
identity. In both cases, however, (and here the "plebs" find an echo) we
can see Foucault as positing a prediscursive unformed primal bodily
matter, which is worked up in discourse into a discursive subject. In this
working up an "other" is created-in creating a subject, those elements
of this primal matter that cannot be incorporated in the discursive
identity are subjugated. A biopolitics of health produces disease; a
discourse of fidelity produces of itself its subjugated other, infidelity;
and as we search for normal sexuality we uncover only ever more
perversion. In this sense, an "other" is always inscribed in discourse-it
is an inescapable conceptual condition of possibility.
But, it remains unclear how far the power-resistance relation really
parallels this process. First, is the "other" of a discourse necessarily a
power is tolerable only on condition that it mask a substantial part of itself. Its
success is proportional to its ability to hide its own mechanisms. Would power be
acceptable if it were entirely cynical? For it, secrecy is not in the nature of an abuse;
it is indispensable to its operation.... Would [those it dominates] accept it if they
did not see it as a mere limit placed on desire, leaving a measure of freedom-
however slight-intact?62
Knowledge does not slowly detach itself from its empirical roots, the initial needs
from which it arose, to become pure speculation subject only to the demands of
reason; its development is not tied to the constitution and affirmation of a free
subject; rather it creates a progressive enslavement to its instinctive violence.
Where religion once demanded the sacrifice of bodies, knowledge now calls for
experimentation on ourselves, calls us to the sacrifice of the subject of knowledge.65
In general terms I believe that power is not built up out of 'wills' (individual or
collective) nor is it derivable from interests.66
And if power is not built from wills or interests, and resistances stem
from power, then resistance cannot be said to be on the basis of these
factors either. Yet Foucault does seem to have some alternative
conception-how else could he write: "The rallying point for the
counter-attack against the deployment of sexuality ought not to be sex
desire, but bodies and pleasures."67
In summary, on the question of resistance, we can see that Foucault's
methodology makes sense largely in terms of Nietzsche's concept of
genealogy: It is the undercutting of the knowledge claims of the social,
medical, and paramedical sciences by reference to their obscure and
frequently iniquitous origins, and by revealing the normative and
delusive nature of the truths that they produce. The polemical and
political purposes of such an analysis can also be understood: It is an
attempt to break up areas of congealed knowledge by a careful
delineation of the structural cracks within them, and by pulling the ru
of epistemological validity from under their feet. Nietzsche might hav
seen himself as giving a helpful push to the crumbling buildings of
Christianity. But to claim a more practical political motivation, and to
be something more than a nihilistic anarchist, the genealogist must surely
have some conception of the steps to be taken once the dust has settled.
There must be a conception of new horizons, something that could be
generated, for example, by recourse to Nietzsche's will to power.68 But
Foucault rejects this aspect of Nietzsche, and he also rejects the
IV
in which accounts of human nature and action are given. In effect, rival
paradigms involve different commitments to philosophical positions in
the philosophies of mind, language, action, and so on. Gray's criticism
of structural Marxism points out that it suppresses its anthropological
assumptions, but that the commitments that it would have to have
would undermine the determinism of the approach. The argument is
complex, but we need not pursue it for our present purposes. The points
that Gray makes that are of relevance to our evaluation of Foucault's
work are that accounts of power and social structure involve a range of
metaphysical commitments, that there is room for criticism where there
is a hiatus between those commitments and the account developed, and
that although empirical evidence and debate in the philosophy of mind
underdetermine such commitments, they nevertheless limit the range of
commitments we can make.
My account of Foucault's conception of power has suggested that,
although he maintains what appears to be a view of significant affecting,
he avoids the question of conflicts of interests. He substitutes for this
question the claim that power is productive of resistance. This is not
necessarily incoherent. However, he does radically underspecify such
terms as "force," which leaves us feeling that his claim that resistance
occurs is simply an assertion, unbacked by argument and lacking any
explanatory account to back it up. But even if we were to accept that
Foucault's account of force and resistance could be formulated in an
explanatory form, we are still left with the question ofjustification. Here
his view breaks down, and it breaks down less into incoherence than into
an impenetrable silence. He refuses to elaborate the anthropology that
evidently does underlie his work. Counterfactually, if he holds no such
anthropology, then he is offering us a naturalistic description of the
operation of power that cannot form the basis for a politically relevant
critique of practice. If we are right to see Foucault as seeing himself as a
radical, we must recognize that he remains silent and elusive about the
philosophical position from which he is working.
There is one way in which Foucault might claim to be able to remain
both silent and politically radical. He might wish to argue that
discussions of power and of "Man," except where they are genealogical
in form, contribute to the will to truth, and as such are further instanc
of the domination by that will of Western civilization. But this simply
postpones the real question. If power is ubiquitous, if it comes from
everywhere, if force is everywhere, if, that is, Foucault has rejected a
view of a society without conflict, then are all societies equally valid?
NOTES
Mark Philp is Research Fellow in Social Science at Jesus College, Oxford. He has
published work on the philosophy and sociology of welfare and is currently
engaged in work on William Godwin and British radicalism in the 1790s.