SSRN Id445982
SSRN Id445982
SSRN Id445982
(Published in Stanford Social Innovation Review, Vol. 1, Issue 1:51-59, Spring 2003; also in Exempt
Organization Tax Review, Vol. 41, issue 3:421-428, September 2003)
Michael Klausner
when
time
money isn’t
Foundation Payouts and the Time Value of Money
counting exercise would reduce the vaccine’s value to a fraction – very likely
a small fraction – of the benefit that the vaccine will produce when it is actu-
ally distributed. Thus, more immediate grants to charity would appear
www.ssireview.com S TA N F O R D S O C I A L I N N O VAT I O N R E V I E W 51
If the McKinsey
authors are right, then
the Gates Foundation
may need to reassess
its AIDS strategy.
52 S TA N F O R D S O C I A L I N N O VAT I O N R E V I E W www.ssireview.com
Looking out to the 50th year, the 365 days of food is
barely worth a breakfast today
Sounds like a valuable social institution to me, but the authors THE HYPOTHETICAL MCKINSEY FOUNDATION
are not sanguine about this foundation. They calculate the pre-
sent value of the foundation’s grants to society by discounting Year Assets Grants at Present Present
the 50-year stream of grants at two alternative rates: the 10 per- 5 percent Value of Value of
cent rate that the foundation earns on its investment portfolio, per year Grants at Grants at
and a 15 percent rate that they say the foundation could earn for 10 percent 15 percent
society by making grants today.6 Running these calculations, the Discount Discount
authors find that the foundation’s $6,355 in grants over 50 years Rate* Rate*
is actually worth less to society than the $1,000 with which the 1 $1,000 $50 $50 $50
foundation started. It is worth $830 using a 10 percent discount 2 1,034 52 47 45
rate and $500 using a 15 percent rate.They run various scenar- 3 1,069 53 44 40
ios through their spreadsheet to show that foundations that want · · · · ·
to increase their value to society should increase their payout rates · · · · ·
above 5 percent. They neglect to point out, however, that under · · · · ·
their valuation approach, the best a foundation can do is break 48 4,814 241 2.73 .34
even in terms of creating social welfare, and that, with the 15 per- 49 4,977 249 2.57 .30
cent discount rate, the only way a foundation can do even that 50 5,164 257 2.41 .27
well is to distribute 100 percent of its assets immediately – and TOTAL $6,355 $830** $500**
to do so without incurring any administrative costs. With a 10 per-
McKinsey’s hypothetical foundation begins with a $1,000 in total
cent discount rate, the foundation would break even over 50 assets. It then assumes annual disbursement of 5 percent of assets
years – or an infinite number of years – so long as it has no through grants, administrative costs of 1 percent of assets, and a
return on the remainder invested of 10 percent. While grants grow
administrative costs. With administrative costs, the foundation to $257 in year 50, the present value of the grants decline to $2.41
is a money loser from the start. The McKinsey authors explain using a 10 percent discount rate and to 27 cents using a 15 percent
discount rate. The present value of all disbursed grants and the
that skilled grant making can offset the ravages of time on a foun- remaining principal after 50 years is $830 at the 10 percent discount
dation’s social worth, but holding the quality of grants constant, rate and $500 at the 15 percent discount rate.
their point is simple: Future charity is worth less than present char- * Assumes, as McKinsey authors do, that grants are made at the beginning of each year.
ity, and it is the time value of money that makes the difference. ** Total includes net present value of remaining principal.
www.ssireview.com S TA N F O R D S O C I A L I N N O VAT I O N R E V I E W 53
Foundation payout rates come down to a
tradeoff between charity for the current generation
and charity for future generations.
54 S TA N F O R D S O C I A L I N N O VAT I O N R E V I E W www.ssireview.com
the discounted cash flow approach assumes that this return will This approach would maximize the social return to the founda-
be maintained over the long run – 50 years in their hypothetical tion dollar. But efficiency is not the only value that guides foun-
foundation. When one applies a 1.1550 discount factor to a grant dation policy or public policy toward the nonprofit sector. Foun-
to be made 50 years from now, one says that the money could dations support diverse activities in the charitable sector, some
be invested today to generate a 15 percent return for 50 years. At constituting valuable social investment and some providing valu-
that level of sustained social gain a grant of $100,000 – say, to fund able consumption, some providing goods that other sectors do
a college scholarship for at-risk youth, or to support the local sym- not provide and some redistributing wealth. The application of
phony – would yield $108 million worth of gains to society at the the discounted cash flow approach to evaluate grants would sac-
end of 50 years. This seems unlikely, and it certainly has no basis rifice this diversity and with it values of equity, fairness, and
in REDF’s experience. community.
Fifth, even if a current grant to charity does yield a long-term
social return, unless the return continues in perpetuity, applying Balancing Current and Future Charity: A Fresh Start
a discount rate to future charity gets us back to the problem with So if the discounted cash flow approach is not useful, how should
which I began this analysis: the favoring of one set of beneficia- foundation managers think about the tradeoff between current
ries over another based simply on the period of time during and future charity? I will address this question in another article,
which they live. As I discuss below, there may be justifications to but here are the basics.
such a preference, but they are not found in the discounted cash The tradeoff between current and future charity is a version
flow analysis. of a problem with which policymakers, economists, and philoso-
Finally, if the discounted cash flow approach were applicable phers grapple when considering very long-term public investments
to the timing of grants, it would be applicable to the evaluation in energy production and environmental protection. How much
of grants themselves. The McKinsey authors do not extend their sacrifice should the current generation make so that future gen-
discounted cash flow approach this far, but let’s see what would erations can have a cleaner environment, cheaper energy, better
happen if we extend the approach to its logical conclusion. To health, and longer lives? The question for foundations is similar.
evaluate a grant, a foundation manager would discount its pro- How much charity should we withhold from the current gen-
jected social return. The discount rate, at a minimum, would have eration in order to provide more charity for future generations?
to equal the rate of return earned on the foundation’s investment The challenge of how to allocate resources among gener-
portfolio – 10 percent in the McKinsey authors’ hypothetical. This ations is fundamentally an ethical question, with economics
would lead a foundation to forgo grants that are expected to yield helping to highlight the tradeoffs. One realization that has
social benefits, if those benefits are less than the expected finan- come out of the debate over long-term public investment is that
cial return on the foundation’s investments. In other words, if the pure timing of a social benefit – whether this generation
grants to a soup kitchen or an opera or a school are not expected or a future generation enjoys the benefits – should be irrele-
to yield what the bank or the stock market will pay, the founda- vant to its social value from either an ethical or economic per-
tion should not make the grants. This surely is not a proper spective. So, for instance, if greenhouse gas regulation today
comparison. To compare the private return available in the mar- improves the lives of people living 100 years from now, the mere
ket with the social return available in the charitable sector, which fact that the benefit will be enjoyed by people living so far in
one implicitly does by using the former to discount the latter, is the future doesn’t make its social value smaller.14 The same is
an error of the apples-and-oranges variety. true of the future benefit that comes from a foundation’s deci-
Similarly, if a foundation were to follow the discounted cash sion to adopt a low payout rate today in order to support char-
flow approach, it would have to discount the projected social ity in future generations. There may be a temptation to care
returns from one grant by the social returns available on other more about the current generation than about faceless gener-
grants. Foundations already do this implicitly when they compare ations in the future. The economist Kenneth Arrow and his co-
two grants in the same field. But the discounted cash flow authors describe this temptation as discounting future gener-
approach takes it a step further. If, for instance, a foundation funds ations for “empathetic distance (because we may feel greater
research on the history of western civilization, the discounted cash affinity for generations closer to us).”15 Others explain the incli-
flow approach would require the foundation to discount the nation as “impatience” or “myopia.”16 No doubt this gut reac-
projected social returns from that research by the social return tion exists among us, but it does not amount to an ethical
it could achieve with a grant anywhere else in the charitable sec- principle or policy prescription. The philosopher John Rawls
tor – a grant to an enterprise that REDF supports, for example. concludes that “the different temporal positions of persons and
www.ssireview.com S TA N F O R D S O C I A L I N N O VAT I O N R E V I E W 55
COST-EFFECTIVE GRANT MAKING IN PRACTICE
The Review asked Richard N. Goldman, co-founder of
the Goldman Environmental Prize, why they pay out
more than the traditional 5 percent.
I
n 1785 a Frenchman named and Philadelphia with specific condi- some of the money on public works
Charles-Joseph Mathon de la Cour tions that the money could only be and loan out the rest for 100 years.
wrote a parody mocking Benjamin paid out after accruing interest for Two hundred years after his death,
Franklin’s American optimism. In 100 – then another 100 – years. He Franklin’s legacy would, according to
the story, a man leaves a small sum of hoped that the people of those cities his projections, total £4,061,000 (or
money in his will and after collecting would see his plan as “a testimony of about $9 million for each city).
interest for 500 years, it becomes a my earnest desire to be useful to Franklin died in 1790, and his plan
fortune. Ben Franklin wrote back to them after my departure.” The inter- was subsequently put in motion,
the Frenchman and thanked him for est on the money would be earned though not exactly as he had hoped.
the inspirational idea. from loans to “young married artifi- Because the loan program was not
And so instead of leaving £2,000 to cers, under the age of twenty-five administered vigilantly and because
Pennsylvania to make the Schuylkill year, as have served an apprenticeship the trade and apprentice systems
River navigable, which was his origi- in said town,” to assist them in setting waned with industrialization, neither
nal plan, Franklin left £1,000 (about up their business. At the 100-year city’s fund grew to Franklin’s expecta-
$4,500 at the time) each to Boston mark, each city was required to spend tions. After 100 years, Boston’s fund
56 S TA N F O R D S O C I A L I N N O VAT I O N R E V I E W www.ssireview.com
How much sacrifice should the current generation make so
that future generations can have a cleaner environment,
cheaper energy, better health, and longer lives?
federal policymakers set the balance of environmental benefits rent charity in areas such as these, and surely others, produces
and burdens across generations. But the allocation of charity is benefits that compound in perpetuity at a higher rate than assets
decentralized. Each foundation, therefore, must consider these in the foundation’s portfolio, then not only will the current gen-
issues in the context of its own mission and the types of charity eration benefit from a grant today but future generations will be
it supports. better off as well.
Cost-Effectiveness A Brighter Tomorrow?
The first issue that a foundation should consider in setting a pay- Before salting its money away for future generations, a founda-
out rate is how cost-effective a grant to current charity would be, tion should also ask itself whether future beneficiaries of its mis-
compared to future charity, in providing a charitable service. sion are likely to be better off than current beneficiaries.20 For
Despite the fact that a dollar of today’s charity comes at the example, perhaps with continued economic growth over the
price of many dollars of future charity, certain kinds of charity generations, art aficionados of future generations will be wealth-
today will be more cost-effective; current and future generations ier than the art aficionados of today. If so, there is less reason to
will be better off if these charitable services are provided sooner save today in order to support the arts in the future. In addition,
rather than later. For example, if a foundation’s goal is to preserve economic growth over the generations is likely to mean more
open space, doing so sooner may be better than doing so later, donations to the nonprofit sector in the future. More immediately,
when the choice of open space to preserve will be more limited. some expect a massive flow of funds to the nonprofit sector as
Early preservation may mean better preservation for all gener- the baby boomers pass on their wealth over the next 20 years. If
ations. The same may be true of efforts to reduce population the charity sector of the next generation will have more funds
growth in an overpopulated region or to protect the envi- than the sector has today, then there is less need to sacrifice cur-
ronment (Sidebar, facing page), or to cure an infec- rent for future charity. Or perhaps the needs that a foun-
tious disease. It may be true as well of some edu- dation serves will be less severe in the future. A
cational programs, but only if one expects problem may be solved, or a service now in
the benefits of current education to have short supply may be abundant.21 If, for any of
indirect effects on the descendants of these reasons, future generations of chari-
current students in perpetuity. If cur- table beneficiaries are expected to be bet-
www.ssireview.com S TA N F O R D S O C I A L I N N O VAT I O N R E V I E W 57
There may be a temptation to care more about the current
generation than about faceless generations in the future,
but that temptation does not amount to an ethical
conclusion or a policy prescription.
ter off than the current generation, then a foundation should put later to combat the disease. Delivery of the vaccine, even to the
a thumb on the scales of the current generation. This does not next generation (or the one after that), may well be more bene-
amount to discounting the future generation because it will ficial to society over time than adding yet more Gates Founda-
arrive on the scene in the future. Rather, it is a matter of giving tion funds to the AIDS effort today. This is the type of judgment
resources to those who are worse off rather than those who will that individual foundation donors and executives must make. If
be better off. there is a flaw in the Gates Foundation strategy, it is that there may
be more philanthropic dollars available to support the delivery
Intergenerational Equity of an AIDS vaccine when it is developed. At the margin, Gates
Intergenerational equity provides a basis for a foundation choos- Foundation funds may better used sooner. That, however, is also
ing to give a dollar of charity today rather than more dollars in the type of judgment that must be left to foundation donors and
the future. In contrast to the first two issues, this issue is not a mat- executives.
ter of maximizing welfare across generations. It is a potential rea-
son to favor the current generation at the expense of future gen- The Mandatory Payout Requirement
erations. This principle weighs against the goal of maximizing If there is not necessarily a downside to society for a foundation
aggregate welfare in the charity sector over the generations. As to favor future charity over current charity, then why do we
an ethical matter, there must be a limit to the extent of sacrifice need a mandatory payout rate? It is not because there is a mis-
any generation can be asked to make for future generations, even match, as Congress believed in 1969, between the value of the
if further sacrifice would lead to net gains in the future. In addi- tax deduction and the value of charity given in the future. As
tion, there may be situations in which certain members of the cur- explained above, there is no valid reason to conclude that future
rent generation have a particularly strong ethical basis for deserv- charity is necessarily worth less than current charity. Furthermore,
ing something more than members of future generations (and since future charity benefits from compound growth, the tax
more than others in the current generation). Innocent victims of deduction for a donation to a foundation is equal to the present
a war waged by the current generation, for example, may have value of the foundation’s future grants.
an ethical claim to funds that the current generation has accu- So why not allow foundations to distribute less now and defer
mulated for charity. Ideally, each foundation would strike a balance more resources to future generations? If foundation managers
between equity and wealth maximization as it deems appropri- were guided entirely by social welfare considerations in setting
ate for society as a whole. Just as foundations distribute their their payout policies, then no minimum payout law would be
funds across the charitable sector as they choose – focusing on max- needed. Foundation managers, however, seem to be influenced
imizing social returns or on other ethical considerations – they by the prestige associated with large endowments, and foun-
should do the same with their distributions over time. dation donors seem to be influenced by notions of immortal-
So how does the Gates Foundation’s AIDS strategy look ity associated with perpetual existence. Consequently, donors
under this approach? First, Gates should not worry about dis- and managers seem to have a personal bias toward lower pay-
counting the value of lives saved in the future as a result of an out rates. The minimum payout requirement responds to this
AIDS vaccine. The Foundation’s strategy should be analyzed self-interest in a fairly moderate way. It basically allows a foun-
based on the cost-effectiveness of providing less now and more dation to maintain its principal and to make grants in perpetuity
at the 5 percent rate. This allows donors immortality and forces
foundations to treat current generations at least equally with
FOUNDATIONS THAT PAY OUT 5 PERCENT future generations. In the long run, the minimum payout
Rockefeller Foundation requirement is expected to hold foundation endowments con-
John D. and Catherine T. MacArthur Foundation stant, so it inhibits foundation executives from vying for pres-
Pew Charitable Trusts tige by growing their endowments.22
Should the minimum payout requirement be increased as
FOUNDATIONS THAT PAY OUT AT some advocates have urged? This is a difficult issue that goes
ACCELERATED RATES beyond the scope of this article. If the personal biases of foundation
Tides Foundation executives play too strong a role in allocating funds between cur-
Olin Foundation rent and future charity, an increased payout requirement might
Goldman Foundation be reasonable. Of the factors described above, the one that might
push in favor of a higher payout requirement across the board is
58 S TA N F O R D S O C I A L I N N O VAT I O N R E V I E W www.ssireview.com
IMPLICATIONS TO MANAGERS
• Payout rates are a tradeoff between current and future charity.
• If a problem can best be solved now, for the benefit of current and future generations, we should spend more on it now.
• If we expect future generations to be better able to provide for themselves, we should spend more on today’s charity.
www.ssireview.com S TA N F O R D S O C I A L I N N O VAT I O N R E V I E W 59