60 1hohendahl
60 1hohendahl
60 1hohendahl
of the ugly but also to consider the signiWcance of the whole com-
plex in Adorno’s thought. The fact that Adorno discusses the ugly
before he turns to the beautiful must be taken seriously—as an index
of the importance that he gave to the ugly.
The obvious level, especially in Aesthetic Theory, is the role
assigned to the ugly in German aesthetics, beginning with Schiller
and Friedrich von Schlegel and culminating in Karl Rosenkranz’s
Ästhetik des Häßlichen (1853), to which Adorno explicitly refers. In the
architecture of Aesthetic Theory this element plays an important role
insofar as it underscores a larger theme in Adorno’s thought that is
concerned with the connection between classical aesthetics with its
emphasis on the autonomy of the artwork and the theory of mod-
ernism and the avant-garde.4 In this context the category of the ugly
receives increasing attention during the course of the nineteenth cen-
tury but remains in a secondary position as the negative of the beau-
tiful. Yet it is precisely this order that Adorno means to challenge.
Within the academic tradition that he invokes, this is a difWcult task,
because nineteenth-century aesthetics resisted the foregrounding of
the ugly as a threat to the autonomy of art, and Adorno is not pre-
pared to relinquish aesthetic autonomy. He must argue therefore that
the ugly is compatible with the autonomy of art. For this purpose,
Adorno introduces a second line of argument, namely the relevance
of the ugly for modern art, and for the avant-garde in particular. In
the context of modernist aesthetics the reversal between the beautiful
and the ugly becomes necessary for a defense of the artwork against
the impact of the culture industry and its commercialization of the
beautiful. Adorno mentions “Jugendstil” as a primary example for
this process. The autonomy of the artwork depends on its opposi-
tional force, a quality that is enhanced by the ugly. It is precisely the
violation of the traditional aesthetic code that separates the advanced
artwork from the threat of the culture industry.
The two strands mentioned above, however, do not exhaust the
signiWcance of the ugly in Adorno’s thought. In fact, they do not get
to the root of Adorno’s interest in the ugly. The third, and I believe
most important, aspect is the link to the primitive and archaic. It is
this nexus that raises the most fundamental and far-reaching ques-
tions, questions about the origins of art, its relation to myth and reli-
gion, and its changing function in human history. The relevance of
07Hohendahl.qxd 7/14/2005 10:27 AM Page 172
While the section on the ugly in Aesthetic Theory opens with a refer-
ence to the German aesthetic tradition, thereby placing Adorno’s
treatment of the concept in the context of German idealism and its
philosophy of art, in Adorno’s work the problem of aesthetic violence
through the ugly goes back to the 1930s, especially to The Philosophy
of Modern Music.5 Adorno’s interpretation of Schoenberg and Stravin-
sky (in the second part, written later) discusses the ugly as a speciWc
element of post-Romantic music, a moment that characterizes the mod-
ernist artwork as a radical opposition to the conventions of romantic
music. The ugly appears Wrst and foremost as a formal moment, the
result of techniques that refuse the Wnal return from dissonance to
consonance. In the case of Schoenberg, there is no question about the
legitimacy of this radical move. As Adorno argues, the emancipation
of the dissonance in the work of Schoenberg follows the historical
logic of the material. Adorno speaks of the necessity of art with re-
spect to its immanent development: “Under the coercion of its own
objective consequences music has critically invalidated the idea of
the polished work and disrupted the collective continuity of its
effect.”6 Not only does the rejection of the traditional masterpiece de-
serve attention but also the loss of the collective grounding of art. This
loss isolates the advanced artwork as a radical subjective expression
07Hohendahl.qxd 7/14/2005 10:27 AM Page 173
eye as deformed and therefore ugly and barbaric reveals its formal
consistency to a viewer who recognizes the cubic quality of the sculp-
ture and the logic of its form. Proportions do not follow the require-
ments of a realistic representation; instead, “it depends to what
extent the signiWcant depth quotients, by which I mean the plastic
resultant, are expected to express depth.”17 Einstein’s analysis under-
scores the totality of the form rather than the aspect of representation.
While he does not deny that the sculpture is meant to represent the
God, he takes the religious meaning more or less for granted.
This conscious disregard in the discussion of the cubic form draws
attention to the unacknowledged tension of Einstein’s approach. On
the one hand, he means to establish the unique cultural context of
African art by stressing the religious quality (cult practices); on the
other, he wants to isolate the formal structure. While the religious
emphasis would encourage the moment of representation (the God),
the formal emphasis allows the comparison with European art. Un-
like Adorno, Einstein sees a legitimate afWnity between African art and
European Cubism. Cubism, he suggests, rediscovered spatial princi-
ples that African art had already established. In Einstein’s mind, the
comparison legitimizes both sides. The truth of modern European art
supports the value of African art, while the authenticity of African art
(rooted in religion) underscores the legitimacy of the European
avant-garde. In Einstein’s approach the problem of primitivism dis-
appears, since the designation of African art as “primitive” is based
on a European misconception. By introducing a separate logic for
African art, Einstein can validate the inXuence of African art that
Adorno acknowledges with suspicion. Yet, we have to note that his
African logic remains rather static and, as Einstein concedes, without
historical depth. Therefore he contrasts European development with
African being—in Negerplastik with a preference for the African side.
At the same time, he remains attached to the concept of historical
development when he discusses European art, as his later work Die
Kunst des 20. Jahrhunderts (1926) makes quite clear. This raises the
question, then, of how the impact of non-European art on European
modernism around 1900 can be accounted for. The embrace of the
barbaric, which for Adorno remains potentially a moment of regres-
sion, is for Einstein primarily a shift in the framework, a merging of
two cultures, or, more precisely, a merging of formal structures.
07Hohendahl.qxd 7/14/2005 10:27 AM Page 180
that are either closely related to the central theme or surface only here
and there. One of them is the origin of art and the nature of archaic
art. A lengthy excursus is dedicated to questions of origin, which the
editors offer as part of the Paralipomena.19 It has the form of a critical
assessment of the existing literature on this topic. By and large,
Adorno remains unimpressed by the work that has been done in this
Weld, since he is dissatisWed with the prevailing methods. BrieXy put,
Adorno is equally suspicious of an ontological approach (Heidegger)
and the results of positivistic research. Still, he is also not satisWed
with Croce’s verdict that the question of the origin of art is aestheti-
cally irrelevant, for he maintains, against Croce, that art cannot be
categorized as “an invariant form of consciousness” (Aesthetic Theory,
326). Hence, the search for the origin of art is deWned as the search for
historical beginnings, more precisely for the moment when art sepa-
rates itself from the oldest known cultic practices. Ultimately, Adorno
is less interested in the distinction between the camp that under-
scores the naturalistic representation in the oldest works (Arnold
Hauser, for example) and scholars who stress the symbolic meaning.
When he speaks in his own voice, he foregrounds the beginnings of
subjectivity as a crucial step for the production of art: “Although
expression is seemingly an aspect of subjectivity, in it—externaliza-
tion—there dwells just as much that is not the self, that probably is
the collective. In that the subject, awakening to expression, seeks col-
lective sanction, expression is already evidence of a Wssure” (Aesthetic
Theory, 328).20 Adorno focuses neither on representation nor on sym-
bolic meaning; instead, he insists on the moment of expression as a
decisive element. Here we have to note that he deWnes expression as
always already mediated by the Non-Ego, namely the collective.
Therefore, as Adorno concludes, it is impossible to grasp the original
unity of art. “Wesenseinheit” (Gesammelte Schriften, 7:484), as the
philosophical point of departure, already presupposes a distinction
within the work, on the one hand (material and form), and the social
collective, on the other.
Following the direction of Dialectic of Enlightenment, Adorno’s own
understanding of early art emphasizes the moment of mimesis as the
oldest, pre-aesthetic approach in which, as part of the magic practice,
subject and object are not yet distinguished. In the earliest known art-
works, however, this state is already surpassed, for instance in works
07Hohendahl.qxd 7/14/2005 10:27 AM Page 183
that, in Adorno’s late thought, the ugly is not a purely formal ques-
tion; rather, it is closely linked to the larger issue of the origin of art
and the signiWcance of the cultic element. As long as one looks at
Adorno’s understanding of the ugly exclusively or primarily in the
context of the history of aesthetics, one will miss this crucial link. The
organization of Aesthetic Theory suggests such an approach, since
the question of the ugly is discussed in the traditional proximity to
the beautiful. However, this proximity is deceptive, for Adorno, not-
withstanding his high regard for Kant and Hegel, remains hostile to
the idea of classicism.23 Hence he insists not only on the historical pri-
ority of the ugly but also on its continued relevance in modern art.
As a critic of modern art (with an emphasis on music) Adorno
realizes that the conventional deWnition of the ugly as a negation of
the beautiful does little to explain the powerful presence of the ugly
in modern art, because a formal deWnition can at best acknowledge
the phenomena but not assess their origin and legitimacy. Yet it is
precisely the legitimacy of the ugly that is at the center of his analy-
sis. It determines both the content and the form of the artwork. The
representations of social misery in naturalist plays and novels vio-
lates the conventional aesthetic code; even more explicitly the “Wider-
wärtige und Abstoßende” make their appearance in avant-garde
poetry (i.e. in Baudelaire and Benn). Adorno comments: “The re-
pressed who sides with the revolution is, according to the standards
of the beautiful life in an ugly society, uncouth and distorted by
resentment, and he bears all the stigmas of degradation under the
burden of unfree—moreover, manual—labor” (Aesthetic Theory, 48).24
It is the task of modern art to be on the side of those social phenom-
ena that have been treated as taboo. Yet we have to note that Adorno
does not speak out in favor of the aestheticization of the ugly; in fact,
he explicitly problematizes the use of humor in Poetic Realism as a
means to tone down and integrate the abject. The critical function of
the modern artwork, speciWcally its opposition to the social status
quo, is supported and enhanced by the presentation of the ugly.
For two reasons, however, Adorno’s advocacy of the ugly should
not be confused with a naive commitment to naturalism. First of all,
Adorno resolutely rejects the poetic celebration of human suffering;
second, he underscores the formal demands of the artwork. The
transformation of the ugly into form results in the cruel. By opening
07Hohendahl.qxd 7/14/2005 10:27 AM Page 185
itself to the cruel, the artwork resists its own tendency to strive for
formal reconciliation. Adorno notes: “The subjective domination of
the act of forming is not imposed on irrelevant materials but is read
out of them; the cruelty of forming is mimesis of myth, with which it
struggles” (Aesthetic Theory, 50).25 The radical formal experiment, which
makes visible the cruel, repeats the moment of cruelty in myth, but it
does not stop there. At the same time, Adorno suggests, the cruel con-
tains a moment of critical self-reXection. Art “despairs over the claim
to power that it fulWlls in being reconciled” ( Aesthetic Theory, 50).26
While the representation of the ugly in the artwork as a form of
social criticism is an important point in Adorno’s inquiry; it by no
means exhausts the signiWcance of the ugly. Adorno’s brief discus-
sion of the cruel points to another, deeper level of his argument,
namely the banished but ultimately not overcome power of myth in
the modern world. This is the place where the central theme of Dialec-
tic of Enlightenment merges with the analysis of the origin of art in
Aesthetic Theory. Adorno’s resistance to the idea of formal reconcilia-
tion in German classicism, insofar as it denies or minimizes human
suffering, leads him to the archaic and primitive where the aesthetic
reconciliation has not yet occurred. Although he strongly empha-
sizes, as we have seen, the “Sprung” between magic practices and art,
he equally stresses the importance of the mythic ground. This, how-
ever, means that the ugly is prior to the beautiful: “If one originated
in the other, it is beauty that originated in the ugly, and not the re-
verse” (Aesthetic Theory, 50).27 This seemingly formal shift (the beauti-
ful becomes the negation of the ugly) opens up a dimension of art
that traditional aesthetic theory could not accommodate within its
system. Following the strategy of Dialectic of Enlightenment, Adorno’s
own theory embraces the ugly in both the archaic and the modern
work because they share, although in very different ways, the impact
of mythic structures; that is to say, they are participating in as well as
negating the power of myth. In the reversal suggested by Adorno, the
beautiful takes on a new meaning. It becomes part of the historical
process of a problematic human history. “In this principle [of order]
the antithesis to the archaic is implicit as the play of forces of the
beautiful single whole; the qualitative leap of art is a smallest transi-
tion. By virtue of this dialectic the image of the beautiful is metamor-
phosed into the movement of enlightenment as a whole” (Aesthetic
07Hohendahl.qxd 7/14/2005 10:27 AM Page 186
and early art is of great importance for Adorno. This means that
behind the question of the ugly lies the larger issue of the primitive
and its meaning in modern, enlightened society. Of course, Adorno
was not the Wrst theorist to discover this problem. Nietzsche and
Freud had offered decisive insights with which Adorno was familiar.
As we have seen, in The Philosophy of Modern Music his response to
Freud was brief and insufWcient; the implicit engagement with Nietz-
sche in Dialectic of Enlightenment, on the other hand, was more seri-
ous. But it is not the question of inXuence that is of interest for the
present discussion. Instead, the Wnal section will focus on Adorno’s
place within the theoretical constellation of modernism.
When Freud, in his essay “Animism, Magic, and the Omnipo-
tence of Thought,” mentions in passing that there is an area in mod-
ern culture that has remained close to the stage of animism, namely
art, the proximity to Adorno is hard to overlook. Freud writes, “Only
in art does it still happen that a man who is consumed by desires per-
forms something resembling the accomplishment of those desires
and that what he does in play produces emotional effects—thanks to
artistic illusion—just as though it were something real.”30 More speci-
Wcally, Freud suggests that art was originally not a purely aesthetic
phenomenon but served other purposes, among them magic func-
tions. At the same time, one must note that this observation—which
Adorno must have known—is part of a larger argument concerning
the place of animism and magic in human development. Conse-
quently, for Freud the proximity (if not the identity) of art and magic,
and not the difference, is the signiWcant insight. The essay develops
an evolutionary model in which Freud calls attention to and then
emphasizes the parallel between individual development and the
evolution of the species. Primitive thought, i.e. animism, corresponds
to narcissism in the same manner as the religious phase (the creation
of gods) corresponds to the stage of “object attachment” outside the
ego. In Freud’s model there is no attempt to give a complete explana-
tion of art or the aesthetic. The example he cites, namely the paintings
in French caves, emphasizes an early stage of art when magic and
aesthetic operated side by side. He assumes that the magic functions
are today for the most part extinct (“zum großen Teil erloschen,”
[Studienausgabe, 9:378]). Still, it is important to note that Freud writes
07Hohendahl.qxd 7/14/2005 10:27 AM Page 188
“zum großen Teil” and does not thereby exclude the continued effect
of older practices in art. In the area of art, the borderline between the
primitive and the more developed form appears to be less clearly
marked, which leaves art in an ambiguous position vis-à-vis the
developmental scheme that Freud uses. Still, Freud leaves no doubt
about the process of enlightenment and its goal. Human maturity is
reached in the scientiWc, postreligious stage when all thoughts of
omnipotence, which motivated primitive cultures to develop elabo-
rate animistic thought structures, have been relinquished. For Freud,
full enlightenment is not the equivalent of domination of nature but
the resigned insight that human beings have, individually as well
as collectively, only limited power. While Freud holds on to an evo-
lutionary scheme to map human history, he also questions it by
drawing attention to psychic pathology. In his comparison between
neurotics and primitives, he alludes to the insight that the narratives
of the Enlightenment (which Freud shared) must be regarded as fail-
ures, or, in a different reading, he points to the impossibility of the
Enlightenment.
The overlap between Freud and Adorno is considerable. Both
theorists underscore the ambiguity of art in the history of human cul-
ture. Both point to the proximity of magic and art, but they place the
emphasis differently. Where Freud highlights the proximity of art
and magic as a deWning moment of primitive culture but thinks of
modern art as mostly free of such elements, Adorno, as we have seen,
emphasizes the initial difference, thereby focusing on the speciWcity
of the aesthetic as a vital moment of its origin, but he allows for a
greater presence of the magic in the modern artwork. In other words,
by remaining attached to the primitive, the advanced artwork resists
the process of Enlightenment. Of course, there is considerably more
legitimacy to this resistance in Adorno’s thought than in Freud’s the-
ory. Still, Adorno recognizes the ambiguity of the modern artwork, its
tendency to return to the logic of mimesis. For Adorno there is no
longer a clear-cut distinction between modern and primitive culture,
which Freud takes over from the anthropologists of his time (i.e.
James George Frazer and E. B. Tyler), nor is there a Wrm belief in sci-
ence. The radical critique of historical progress in Dialectic of Enlight-
enment would have shocked even the Freud of “Das Unbehagen in
der Kultur.”
07Hohendahl.qxd 7/14/2005 10:27 AM Page 189
Notes
Primitivism in Modern Art; Colin Rhodes, Primitivism and Modern Art; also David
Pan, Primitive Renaissance: Rethinking German Expressionism.
15. “Den Fehler, die Kunst der Neger an einem unbewußten Erinnern
irgendwelcher europäischer Kunstform zu schanden zu machen, werden wir
vermeiden, da die afrikanische Kunst aus formalen Gründen als umrissener
Bezirk vor uns steht” (Werke, 1:254).
16. “HäuWg tadelt man an den Negerskulpturen die sogenannten
Proportionsfehler; man begreife, die optische Diskontinuität des Raumes wird in
Formklärung übersetzt, in eine Ordnung der, da es um Plastizität geht, nach
ihrem plastischen Ausdruck verschieden gewerteten Teile” (Werke, 1:258).
17. “. . .sind davon abhängig, wie sehr von entscheidenden Tiefenquo-
tienten aus, worunter ich die plastische Resultante verstehe, Tiefe ausgedrückt
werden soll” (Werke, 1:259–60).
18. Max Horkheimer and Theodor W. Adorno, Dialectic of Enlightenment.
19. Theodor W. Adorno, Aesthetic Theory, 325–31. The original German text
of Ästhetische Theorie is quoted from Gesammelte Schriften, 7:480–90.
20. “Während Ausdruck scheinbar zur Subjektivität rechnet, wohnt ihm,
der Entäußerung, ebenso das Nichtich, wohl das Kollektiv inne. Indem das zum
Ausdruck erwachende Subjekt dessen Sanktion sucht, ist der Audruck bereits
Zeugnis eines Risses” (Gesammelte Schriften, 7:485–86).
21. “Aber die ästhetische Verhaltensweise ist nicht durchaus rudimentär. In
ihr, die in der Kunst konserviert wird und deren Kunst unabdingbar bedarf, ver-
sammelt sich, was seit undenklichen Zeiten von Zivilisationen gewalttätig
weggeschnitten, unterdrückt wurde samt dem Leiden der Menschen unter dem
ihnen Abgezwungenen, das wohl schon in den primären Gestalten von Mimesis
sich äußert” (Gesammelte Schriften, 7:487).
22. “Sie [art] hat von den Kultobjekten sich losgerissen durch einen Sprung,
in dem das kultische Moment verwandelt zugleich bewahrt wird, und diese
Struktur reproduziert sich erweitert auf allen Stufen ihrer Geschichte” (Gesam-
melte Schriften, 7:426).
23. See Peter Uwe Hohendahl, Prismatic Thought: Theodor W. Adorno, 75–104.
24. “Das Unterdrückte, das den Umsturz will, ist nach den Normen des
schönen Lebens in der häßlichen Gesellschaft derb, von Ressentiment verzerrt,
trägt alle Male der Erniedrigung unter der Last der unfreien, zumal körperlichen
Arbeit” (Gesammelte Schriften, 7:78).
25. “Die subjektive Herrschaft des Formens ergeht nicht indifferenten
Stoffen, sondern wird aus ihnen herausgelesen, Grausamkeit des Formens ist
Mimesis an den Mythos, mit dem sie umspringt” (Gesammelte Schriften, 7:80).
26. “verzweifelt an dem Machtanspruch, den sie als versöhnte vollstreckt”
(Gesammelte Schriften, 7:81).
27. “Wenn überhaupt, ist das Schöne eher im Häßlichen entsprungen als
umgekehrt” (Gesammelte Schriften, 7:81).
28. “Die Antithesis zum Archaischen ist in diesem [the principle of order]
impliziert, das Kräftespiel des Schönen eines; der qualitative Sprung der Kunst ist
07Hohendahl.qxd 7/14/2005 10:27 AM Page 195
ein kleinster Übergang. Kraft solcher Dialektik verwandelt sich das Bild des
Schönen in der Gesamtbewegung von Aufklärung” (Gesammelte Schriften, 7:83).
29. “Die AfWnität aller Schönheit zu ihm hat ihren Ort in der Idee der reinen
Form, die Kunst der Mannigfaltigkeit des Lebendigen auferlegt, das in ihr er-
lischt” (Gesammelte Schriften, 7:84).
30. Sigmund Freud, The Standard Edition, vol. 13, here 90; subsequently cited
as Standard Edition in the text. The German quotations are taken from Freud,
Studienausgabe, vol. 9, here 378; subsequently cited as Studienausgabe in the text.
“In der Kunst allein kommt es noch vor, daß ein von Wünschen verzehrter
Mensch etwas der Befriedigung ähnliches macht und daß dieses Spielen—dank
der künstlerischen Illusion—Affektwirkungen hervorruft, als wäre es etwas
Reales” (Studienausgabe, 9:378).
31. Friedrich Nietzsche, The Birth of Tragedy and Other Writings, 21; subse-
quently cited as Birth of Tragedy in the text. Quotations from the original German
text are taken from Werke in drei Bänden, 2nd edition, vol. 1; subsequently cited as
Werke in drei Bänden in the text. “Jener scheußliche Hexentrank aus Wollust und
Grausamheit war hier ohne Kraft: nur die wundersame Mischung und
Doppelheit in den Affekten der dionysischen Schwärmer erinnert an ihn” (Werke
in drei Bänden, 1:27).
32. “gänzlich mit dem Ur-Einen, seinem Schmerz und Widerspruch, eins
geworden . . . produziert das Abbild dieses Ur-Einen als Musik” (Werke in drei
Bänden, 1:37).
33. “nimmt auch vollen Anteil an dieser metaphysischen Verklärungs-
absicht der Kunst überhaupt” (Werke in drei Bänden, 1:130).
34. Friedrich Nietzsche, Human, All Too Human, 100. “Sodann ist die
häßliche, den Sinnen ursprünglich feindselige Seite der Welt für die Musik
erobert worden; ihr Machtbereich namentlich zum Ausdruck des Erhabenen,
Furchtbaren, Geheimnisvollen hat sich damit erstaunlich erweitert” (Werke in drei
Bänden, 1:575).
35. “die ungeheure Überzahl, welche alljährlich immer unfähiger wird, das
Bedeutende auch in der Form der sinnlichen Häßlichkeit zu verstehen und
deshalb nach dem an sich Häßlichen und Ekelhaften, das heißt dem niedrig
Sinnlichen in der Musik mit immer mehr Behagen greifen lernt” (Werke in drei
Bänden, 1:575).
Works Cited
Bernstein, I. M. The Fate of Art: Aesthetic Alienation from Kant to Derrida and Adorno.
University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press, 1992.
Einstein, Carl. Werke. Vol. 1. Ed. Rolf-Peter Baacke. Berlin: Medusa, 1980.
Freud, Sigmund. The Standard Edition. Vol. 13. London: Hogarth Press, 1955.
———. Studienausgabe. Vol. 9. Ed. Alexander Mitscherlich, Angela Richards, and
James Strachey. Frankfurt: Fischer, 1974.
Goldwater, Robert. Primitivism in Modern Art. New York: Random House, 1938.
Hohendahl, Peter Uwe. Prismatic Thought: Theodor W. Adorno. Lincoln: University
of Nebraska Press, 1995.
Horkheimer, Max, and Theodor W. Adorno. Dialectic of Enlightenment. New York:
Herder and Herder, 1972.
Huhn, Thomas. “Diligence and Industry: Adorno and the Ugly.” Canadian Journal
of Political and Social Theory 12 (1988): 138–46.
Hullot-Kentor, Robert. “The Philosophy of Dissonance: Adorno and Schönberg.”
In The Semblance of Subjectivity: Essays on Adorno’s Aesthetic Theory, ed. Thomas
Huhn and Lambert Zuidervaart, 309–20. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1997.
Huyssen, Andreas. “Adorno in Reverse: From Hollywood to Richard Wagner.”
NGC, no. 29. (Spring–Summer 1983): 5–29.
Jauß, Hans Robert. Die nicht mehr schönen Künste. Grenzphänomene des Ästhetischen.
Munich: Wilhelm Fink Verlag, 1968.
Menke-Eggers, Christoph. The Sovereignty of Art: Aesthetic Negativity in Adorno and
Derrida. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1998.
Nietzsche, Friedrich. Human, All Too Human. Trans. R. I. Hollingdale. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1996.
———. The Birth of Tragedy and Other Writings. Ed. Raymond Geuss and Ronald
Speirs. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999.
———. Werke in drei Bänden, 2d ed. Vol. 1. Ed. Karl Schlechta. Munich: Hanser,
1960.
Oesterle, Günter. “Entwurf einer Monographie des Häßlichen.” In Zur Modernität
der Romantik, Literaturwissenschaft und Sozialwissenschaft 8, ed. Dieter
Bänsch, 217–97. Stuttgart: Metzler, 1977.
Pan, David. Primitive Renaissance: Rethinking German Expressionism. Lincoln: Uni-
versity of Nebraska Press, 2001.
Rhodes, Colin. Primitivism and Modern Art. London: Thames and Hudson, 1934.
Roberts, David. Art and Enlightenment: Aesthetic Theory after Adorno. Lincoln: Uni-
versity of Nebraska Press, 1991.
Rosenkranz, Karl. Ästhetik des Häßlichen. Ed. Walther Gose und Walter Sachs.
Stuttgart: F. Frommann, 1968.
Schmidt, Siegfried J. “Der philosophische Begriff des Schönen und des Häßlichen
in Adornos Ästhetischer Theorie.” Zeitwende 43 (1972): 94–104.
Wellmer, Albrecht. The Persistence of Modernity: Essays on Aesthetics, Ethics and
Postmodernism. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1991.