Free Will
Free Will
Free Will
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
Brown Judaic Studies is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to
Two Treatises of Philo of Alexandria
This content downloaded from 31.60.32.154 on Sat, 21 Nov 2020 22:52:47 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
III. PHILOSOPHICAL THEMES IN THE BE GIGANTIBUS
This content downloaded from 31.60.32.154 on Sat, 21 Nov 2020 22:52:47 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
This content downloaded from 31.60.32.154 on Sat, 21 Nov 2020 22:52:47 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
A. Philo's Doctrine of Free Will*
181
This content downloaded from 31.60.32.154 on Sat, 21 Nov 2020 22:52:47 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
182 Two Treatises of Philo
This content downloaded from 31.60.32.154 on Sat, 21 Nov 2020 22:52:47 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Philo's Doctrine of Free Will 183
bad upbringing, and that this could lead to its being overcome
by the passions {Tim. 86B). In Laws 644DE, Plato speaks more
bluntly of the ultimately determined character of man's moral
nature:
when Philo says that God gave to the human mind a portion
"of that free will which is His most peculiar possession
and most worthy of His majesty" and that by this gift of
free will the human mind "in this respect has been made
to resemble Him," it is quite evident that by man's free
will Philo means an absolutely undetermined freedom like
that enjoyed by God, who by his power to work miracles
can upset the laws of nature and the laws of causality
which He himself has established. [Philo 1.436]
The fact is, however, that Philo is only adapting here for his
own use a characteristically Stoic notion. Epictetus, for
example, writes:
This content downloaded from 31.60.32.154 on Sat, 21 Nov 2020 22:52:47 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
184 Two Treatises of Philo
Now the Stoics held a relative free will theory of the causal
type, and all they meant by saying that God has given us a por-
tion of himself thereby enabling us to make choices is that
(as A. A. Long has neatly put it) "the logos, the causal prin-
ciple, is inside the individual man as well as being an external
force constraining him. . . . This is but a fragment of the
whole, however, and its powers are naturally weak, so weak that
'following1 rather than 'initiating' events is stressed as its
o
proper function." For the Stoics, man is not a mechanical link
in the causal chain, but an active though subordinate partner of
God. It is this which allows them to shift the responsibility
for evil from God to man. Cleanthes says as much in his famous
g
Hymn to Zeus. According to Long,
Cleanthes is thinking of God as an absolute power, embracing
all things and uniting good and evil. Yet evil actions are
not planned by God in his identity as one omnipotent ruler.
What he does is to unite all things in a harmonious whole.
Can we say that evil actions are ones purposed by certain
fragments of his logos? They would bear no more resemblance
to God as such than does a brick to the house it helps to
form.10
Philo's meaning, then, is that in so far as man shares
in God's Logos, he shares to some extent in God's freedom. That
this is only a relative freedom is actually emphasized by Philo
when he says that God gave man such a portion of his freedom
"as man was capable of receiving" and that he was liberated "as
far as might be." Yet this relative freedom, in Philo's view,
is sufficient for placing the onus of moral responsibility on
man and clearing God from any blame for man's sins. It is
impossible, then, to locate in our Philonic text an explicit
statement of absolute free will. For the sake of the argument,
however, let us follow up the logical consequences of an abso-
lute free will doctrine and see how these would chime with
Philo 1 s philosophical system as a whole. If absolute free will,
for Philo, means that man's will is completely autonomous and
independent of God, then he would be ascribing to God the ability
to do something involving a contradiction. It seems, however,
highly unlikely that Philo's formula TidvTa deep 6uvaxd would
include the logically absurd. For Philo (as later for Saadia),
This content downloaded from 31.60.32.154 on Sat, 21 Nov 2020 22:52:47 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Philo's Doctrine of Free Will 185
This content downloaded from 31.60.32.154 on Sat, 21 Nov 2020 22:52:47 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
186 Two Treatises of Philo
accounted for only by the fact that the point which Philo
was going to make in this homily was that only the choice
This content downloaded from 31.60.32.154 on Sat, 21 Nov 2020 22:52:47 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Philo's Doctrine of Free Will 187
This content downloaded from 31.60.32.154 on Sat, 21 Nov 2020 22:52:47 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
188 Two Treatises of Philo
"God has not fashioned beforehand any deed of his, but produces
him [Melchizedek] to begin with as such a king, peaceable and
worthy of his own priesthood" (LA 3.79). Similarly, we read in
Ben Sira: "To fear the Lord is the beginning of wisdom, and
with the faithful was she created in the womb" (1:14).
More decisive, however, for the interpretation of the
fragment from the Legum Allegoria, is that its plain meaning is
fully consonant with the rest of Philo 1 s writings and is actually
reinforced by them. The theme of man's nothingness and utter
passivity runs through much of Philo 1 s works. In Cher. 11,
for example, he writes:
What more hostile foe could there be for the soul than one
who in his boastfulness claims for himself what is proper
to God? For to act is the property of God, something which
may not be ascribed to created beings whereas it is the
property of creation to suffer. Ke who recognizes this in
advance as something fitting and necessary, will readily
endure what befalls him, however grievous it may be.2 3
This content downloaded from 31.60.32.154 on Sat, 21 Nov 2020 22:52:47 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Philo's Doctrine of Free Will 189
NOTES
This content downloaded from 31.60.32.154 on Sat, 21 Nov 2020 22:52:47 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
190 Two Treatises of Philo
This content downloaded from 31.60.32.154 on Sat, 21 Nov 2020 22:52:47 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Philo's Doctrine of Free Will 191
This content downloaded from 31.60.32.154 on Sat, 21 Nov 2020 22:52:47 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
192 Two Treatises of Philo
This content downloaded from 31.60.32.154 on Sat, 21 Nov 2020 22:52:47 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Philo's Doctrine of Free Will 193
you may refer to God, but all the evil you must attribute to
yourselves" (55b). See Joseph Weiss "The Religious Determinism
of Joseph Mordecai Lerner [sio] of Izbica," Yitzhak F. Baer
Jubilee Volume (eds. S. W. Baron, S. Ettinger, et al.; Jerusalem
1960) 447-53.
18
C f . Plato, Laws 9.860E (Loeb ed., 2.223, 225): "If
this is the state of the case, Stranger (i.e., that all bad men
are in all respects unwillingly b a d ) , what counsel do you give
us in regard to legislating for the Magnesian State? Shall we
legislate or shall we not? 1 'Legislate by all means' I shall
reply."
19
Fragments of Philo Judaeus (ed. James Rendel Harris;
Cambridge 1886) 8. (I have quoted the Drummond-Wolfson transla-
tion of this fragment, but have made a number of modifications.)
For the two principles "God is as a man, God is not as a man,"
cf. Deus 60-68.
Drummond observes that this fragment "reduces the
belief in free will to a useful delusion of the less educated."
He concludes, however, that "if this passage has been correctly
preserved, it stands alone among Philo's utterances, though not
without important points of contact with them, and I must be
content to leave it without attempting a reconciliation" (James
Drummond, Philo Judaeus [reprint, Amsterdam 1969] 1.347, note).
E. Goodenough, on the other hand, has correctly understood
Philo's intent (see his The Theology of Justin Martyr [reprint,
Amsterdam 1968] 229).
21
H . Wolfson, Philo 1.442-46 (I have somewhat abbrevi-
ated his remarks).
This content downloaded from 31.60.32.154 on Sat, 21 Nov 2020 22:52:47 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
194 Two Treatises of Philo
5.4 ff.: "Good men labor, spend, and are spent, and withall
willingly. Fortune does not drag them--they follow her, and
match her pace. If they had known how, they would have out-
stripped her. Here is another spirited utterance which, I
remember, I heard that most valiant man, Demetrius, make:
'Immortal gods, 1 he said, 'I have this one complaint to make
against you, that you did not earlier make known your will to
me; for I should have reached the sooner that condition in which
after being summoned, I now am. Do you wish to take my chil-
d r e n ? - - ^ was for you that I fathered them. Do you wish to take
some member of my body?—take it; no great thing am I offering
you; very soon I shall leave the whole. . . . What, then, is
my trouble? I should have preferred to offer than to relin-
quish. What was the need to take it by force? You might have
had it as a gift. Yet even now you will not take it by force,
because nothing can be wrenched away from a man unless he with-
holds it. '"
26
S e e , for example, Post. 73; Bet. 178; Somn. 2.195;
Abr. 115; Ebr. 140; Mut. 144; Speo. 1.281, 2.17, 3.11; Virt. 4;
Deus 89; Spec. 4.82; Decal. 142; Virt. 13; Billings, Platonism
(cited n. 22) 93-95; Volker, Fortschritt (cited n. 16) 47-95,
115-22.
27
For the Stoic doctrine of ciTOvia see SVF 3.473, 2.531;
J. M. Rist, Stoic Philosophy (Cambridge 1969) 87-95. Conf. 166:
"For when the bonds of the soul which held it fast are loosened,
there follows the greatest of disasters, even to be abandoned by
God who has encircled all things with the adamantine chains of
His potencies and willed that thus bound tight and fast they
should never be unloosed." See Volker, Fortschritt, 93; cf.
Sacr. 81; Ebr. 95, 122 (here he implies that when the T 6 V O Q of
the soul is loosened, man can no longer act voluntarily).
28
See, for example, Bet. 90: "How, then, was it likely
that the mind of man being so small (cf. Aristotle, EN 10.7.7),
contained in such small bulks as a brain or a heart, should have
room for all the vastness of sky and universe, had it not been
an inseparable portion of that divine and blessed soul? For no
part of that which is divine cuts itself off and becomes sepa-
rate, but does but extend itself. The mind, then, having
obtained a share of the perfection which is in the whole, when
it conceives of the universe, reaches out as widely as the bounds
of the whole, and undergoes no severance; for its force is
This content downloaded from 31.60.32.154 on Sat, 21 Nov 2020 22:52:47 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Philo's Doctrine of Free Will 195
D. Winston
This content downloaded from 31.60.32.154 on Sat, 21 Nov 2020 22:52:47 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
This content downloaded from 31.60.32.154 on Sat, 21 Nov 2020 22:52:47 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms