Morgenthau 1952
Morgenthau 1952
Morgenthau 1952
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
American Political Science Association is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to
The American Political Science Review.
http://www.jstor.org
a law of nature, allows of, and even presupposes, conduct in violation of the principle.
Robert W. Tucker, in "Professor Morgenthau's Theory of Political 'Realism'" in this
REVIEW, Vol. 46, pp. 214-224 (March, 1952), has missed this and many other points in his
zeal to find contradictions where there are none.
"This [the realist] doctrine," writes one historian-Frank Tannenbaum, "The
Balance of Power versus the Co6rdinate State," Political Science Quarterly,Vol. 67, p. 173
(June, 1952)-"is confessedly, nay gleefully, amoral. It prides itself upon being realistic
and takes Machiavelli as its great teacher. It is contemptuous of the simple beliefs of
honest men, jeers at the sentimentalism of those who believe that men may strive for
peace among nations, and looks upon democracy as a hindrance to skilled diplomacy. It
looks with a certain derisive superiority upon the great leaders of this nation from Jeffer-
son and John Quincy Adams to Woodrow Wilson and Franklin Delano Roosevelt and
describes them as moralistic and sentimental, and suggests that our models ought to be
emperorsand popes were doing if they did not apply the principles
of the balance of power; and how the nations which eitherneglected
these principlesor applied themwronglysuffered political and military
defeatand even extinction,whilethe nationwhichapplied these princi-
ples most consistentlyand consciously,that is, Great Britain,enjoyed
unrivalledpower foran unparalleledlengthof time.
The historianwho wishesto replacethe balance of poweras the guid-
ing principleof Americanforeignpolicy with the "humanitarianand
pacific traditions"of the coordinatee'state"7 must firstof all explain
how it has come about that the thirteenoriginalstates expanded into
the full breadth and a good deal of the length of a continent,until
today the strategicfrontiersof the United States.run parallel to the
coastline of Asia and along the River Elbe. If such are the resultsof
policies based upon "humanitarian and pacific traditions,"never in
the historyof the world has virtue been more bountifullyrewarded!
Yet our historianmust explain not only the great sweep of American
expansion,but also the specificforeignpolicies which in theirhistoric
succession make up that sweep. Is it easier to explain.the successive
shiftsof American support from Great Britain to France and back
again fromthe beginningof King George's War in 1744 to the War of
1812 in termsof the "coordinatestate" than in termsof the balance of
power? The same question mightbe asked about the postponementof
the recognitionof the independenceof the Spanish coloniesuntil 1822,
whenthe Floridas had been.acquiredfromSpain and Spain had thereby
been deprivedof the abilityto challengethe United States fromwithin
the hemisphere.The same question mightbe asked about the Monroe
Doctrine itself, about Lincoln's policies toward Great Britain and
France,and about our successivepolicies withregardto Mexico and the
Caribbean. One could go on and pick out at randomany foreignpolicy
pursuedby the United States fromthe beginningto 1919 and one would
hardly finda policy, with the exceptionperhaps of the War of 1812,
which could not be made intelligibleby referenceto the national
interestdefinedin termsof power-political, military,and economic-
rather than by referenceto the principleof the "coordinate state."
This inevitableoutcomeof such an inquiryis well summarizedin these
words:
Ease and prosperityhave made us wish the whole world to be as happy and
well to do as ourselves;and we have supposed that institutionsand principles
like our own werethe simple prescriptionformakingthem so. And yet, when
7Tannenbaum, "The Balance of Power versus the Co6rdinate State," (cited above,
note 3), p. 173.
issues of our own interestarose, we have not been unselfish.We have shown
ourselves kin to all the world,when it came to pushing an advantage. Our
action against Spain in the Floridas, and against Mexico on the coasts of the
Pacific; our attitude toward firstthe Spaniards, and then the French, with
regard to the control of the Mississippi; the unpityingforcewith which we
thrustthe Indians to the wall wherevertheystood in our way, have suited our
professionsof peacefulnessand justice and liberalityno betterthan the aggres-
sions of other nations that were strong and not to be gainsaid. Even Mr.
Jefferson, philanthropistand champion of peaceable and modest government
thoughhe was, exemplifiedthis double temperof the people he ruled. "Peace
is ourpassion," he had declared; but the passion abated whenhe saw the mouth
ofthe Mississippiabout to pass intothe hands of France. Though he had loved
France and hated England, he did not hesitate then what language to hold.
"There is on the globe," he wroteto Mr. Livingstonat Paris, "one singlespot
the possessorof whichis our naturaland habitualenemy.The day that France
takes possessionofNew Orleansseals the unionoftwo nations,who,in conjunc-
tion,can maintainexclusivepossessionofthe sea. From that momentwe must
marryourselvesto the Britishfleetand nation." Our interestsmustmarchfor-
ward, altruiststhoughwe are; othernationsmustsee to it that theystand off,
and do not seek to stay us.
This realist appraisal of the Americantraditionin foreignpolicy was
published in 1901 in the AtlanticMonthly.Its author was a professor
of jurisprudenceand political economy at Princetonby the name of
Woodrow Wilson.8
Nothingmoreneeds to be said to demonstratethat factsdo not sup-
port a revisionof Americandiplomatichistorywhichtriesto substitute
"humanitarianand pacifisttraditions"and the "coordinatestate" for
power politics and the balance of power as the guiding principleof
American foreignpolicy. What, then, does support it? Three things:
the way American statesmen have spoken about American foreign
policy; the legal fictionof the "coordinatestate"; finally,and foremost,
an emotionalurge to justifyAmericanforeignpolicy in humanitarian,
pacifistterms.
It is elementarythat the characterof a foreignpolicy can be ascer-
tained only throughthe examinationof the political acts performed
and of the foreseeableconsequences of these acts. Thus we can find
out what statesmen have actually done, and from the foreseeable
consequencesof theiracts we can surmisewhat theirobjectives might
have been. Yet examinationof the factsis not enough.To give meaning
to the factual raw material of history,we must approach historical
realitywitha kind of rational outline,a map whichsuggeststo us the
* "Democracy and Efficiency," Atlantic Monthly,Vol. 87, pp. 293-294 (March, 1901).
York, 1934).
a recent Moon Mullins cartoon. An elderly representative of the utopian school asks little
Kayo:- "Remember the golden rule. Now, supposing that boy slapped you on the right
cheek, what would you do?" Whereupon Kayo replies realistically: "Jest how big a boy
are you supposin'?"
date for the utopian justificationof such policies has been made by
RepresentativeCharles J. Kersten of Wisconsinwho pointed to these
four"basic defects" of the "negative policy of containmentand nego-
tiated coexistence
It would be immoraland unchristianto negotiatea permanentagreement
withforceswhichby everyreligiouscreed and moralpreceptare evil. It aban-
dons nearlyone-halfofhumanityand the once freenationsof Poland, Czecho-
slovakia, Hungary, Rumania, Bulgaria, Albania, Lithuania, Latvia, Esthonia
and China to enslavementof the Communistpolice state.
It is un-Americanbecause it violates the principleof the AmericanDeclara-
tion of Independence,whichproclaimsthe-rightsof all people to freedomand
theirrightand duty to throwofftyranny.
It will lead to all-out World War III because it aligns all the forcesof the
non-Communistworld in militaryoppositionto and against all the forcesof
the Communist world, including the 800,000,000 peoples behind the Iron
Curtain.
The policy of mere containmentis uneconomic and will lead to national
bankruptcy.18
IV
The foregoingdiscussionoughtto shed additionallight,if this is still
needed,upon the moralmeritsofthe utopian and realistpositions.This
question, more than any other,seems to have agitated the critics of
realismin internationalaffairs.Disregardingthe voluminousevidence,
some ofthemhave picked a fewwordsout oftheircontextto provethat
realismin internationalaffairsis unprincipledand contemptuousof mo-
rality.To mentionbut one example,one eminentcriticsummarizesmy
position,whichhe supposes to deny the possibilityof judgingthe con-
duct of states by moral criteria,in these words: "And one spokesman
finds'a profoundand neglectedtruth,'to use his words,in the dictumof
Hobbes that 'there is neithermoralitynor law outside the state.'"9
These are indeed my words,but not all of them. What I actually said
was this:
Thereis a profoundand neglected truthhiddenin Hobbes'sextreme dictum
thatthestatecreatesmoralityas wellas law andthatthereis neithermorality
norlawoutsidethestate.Universalmoralprinciples,suchas justiceorequality,
are capableofguidingpoliticalactiononlyto theextentthattheyhave been
givenconcretecontentand havebeenrelatedtopoliticalsituationsbysociety.20
It mustbe obvious fromthispassage and fromall my other writings
on the subject21 that my positionis the exact oppositefromwhat this
criticmakes it out to be. I have always maintainedthat the actions of
states are subject to universalmoral principlesand I have been careful
to differentiatemy positionin this respectfromthat of Hobbes. Five
points basic to my positionmay need to be emphasizedagain.
The firstpoint is what one mightcall the requirementof cosmic hu-
19 A. H. Feller, "In Defense of International Law and Morality," The Annals of the
American Academy of Political and Social Science, Vol. 282, p. 80 (July, 1952).
20 In Defense of the National Interest: A Critical Examination of American Foreign
22 Morgenthau,PoliticsAmongNations,pp. 174-175.
trate the same point. There can be littledoubt that the Soviet Union
could have achieved the objectivesof its foreignpolicyat the end ofthe
Second World War withoutantagonizingthe nations of the West into
that encirclingcoalition which has been the nightmareof Bolshevist
foreignpolicy since 1917. It could-have mitigatedcunningforits own
sake and the use of forcewith persuasion,conciliation,and a trustde-
rived fromthe awarenessof a partial communityofinterestsand would
therebyhave minimizedthe dangersto itselfand the rest of the world
whichare inherentin the objectivesofits policies.Yet the Soviet Union
was precludedfromrelyingupon thesetraditionalmethodsofdiplomacy
by its generalconceptionofhumannature,politics,and morality.In the
general philosophyof Bolshevismthereis no room forhonest dissent,
the recognitionofthe intrinsicworthofdivergentinterests,and genuine
conciliationbetween such interests.On all levels of social interaction
oppositionmust be destroyedby cunningand violence,since it has no
rightto exist,ratherthan be met halfway in view of its intrinsiclegiti-
macy. This being the general conceptionof the political moralityof
Bolshevism,the foreignpolicyof the Soviet Union is limitedto a much
more narrowchoice of means than the foreignpoliciesof othernations.
The United States, for instance,has been able, in its relationswith
the nations of Latin America,to replace militaryinterventionand dol-
lar diplomacy with the policy of the Good Neighbor. That drastic
changewas made possibleby the generalconceptionofpoliticalmorality
whichhas been prevalentin the United States fromits very inception.
Thd United States is a pluralistsocietywhichpresupposesthe continu-
ing existenceand legitimacyof divergentinterests.These interestsare
locked in a continuingstrugglefor supremacyto be decided by force
only as a last resort,but normallythrougha multitudeof institutional
agencies which are so devised as to allow one or the other interesta
temporaryadvantage but none a permanentsupremacyat the price of
the destructionof the. others. This moralityof pluralism allows the
United States, once it is secure in that minimumof vital intereststo
which we have referredabove, to transferthose principlesof political
moralityto the internationalscene and to deal withdivergentinterests
there with the same methods of genuine compromiseand conciliation
whichare a permanentelementof its domesticpolitical life.
The thirdpoint concernsthe relationsbetweenuniversalmoral prin-
ciplesand politicalaction.I have always maintainedthattheseuniversal
moral principlescannot be applied to the actions of states in theirab-
stractuniversalformulation, but that theymust be, as it were,filtered
throughthe concretecircumstancesof time and place. The individual
may say for himself:"Fiat justitia, pereatmunrdus";the state has no
rightto say so in the name of those who are in its care. Both individual
and state must judge politicalaction by universalmoralprinciples,such
as that of liberty.Yet whilethe individualhas a moralrightto sacrifice
himselfin defenseofsuch a moralprinciple,the state has no moralright
to let its moral disapprobationof the infringement of libertyget in the
way ofsuccessfulpoliticalaction,itselfinspiredby the moralprincipleof
national survival.There can be no politicalmoralitywithoutprudence,
that is, withoutconsiderationofthe politicalconsequencesof seemingly
moral action. Classical and medieval philosophyknew this and so did
Lincoln when he said: "I do the verybest I know how, the verybest I
can, and I mean to keep doingso untilthe end. If the end bringsme out
all right,what is said against me won't amount to anything.If the end
bringsme out wrong,ten angels swearingI was rightwould make no
difference."The issue between utopianismand realism,as it bears on
this point, has been put most succinctlyby Edmund Burke, and what
he has to say in the followingpassage about revolution,that is, civil
war, may well be applied mutatismutandisto all war.
Nothing universalcan be rationallyaffirmedon any moral or any political
subject. Pure metaphysicalabstractiondoes not belong to these matters.The
lines of moralityare not like the ideal lines of mathematics.They are broad
and deep as well as long. They admit ofexceptions;theydemandmodifications.
These exceptionsand modificationsare not made by the process of logic-,but
by the rules of prudence.Prudence is not only the firstin rank of the virtues
politicaland moral,but she is the director,the regulator,the standardofthem
all. Metaphysicscannot live withoutdefinition;but Prudence is cautious how
she defines.Our courtscannot be morefearfulin suffering fictitiouscases to be
broughtbeforethem forelicitingtheir determinationon a point of law than
prudent moralistsare in puttingextremeand hazardous cases of conscience
upon emergenciesnot existing.Withoutattempting,therefore, to define,what
nevercan be defined,the case of a revolutionin government, this,I think,may
be safelyaffirmed-thata sore and pressingevil is to be removed,and that a
good, great in its amount and unequivocal in its nature,must be probable al-
mostto a certainty,beforethe inestimablepriceofour own moralsand the well-
being of a number of our fellow-citizensis paid for a revolution.If ever we
ought to be economistseven to parsimony,it is in the voluntaryproduction
ofevil. Every revolutioncontainsin it somethingofevil.23
23 The Works of The Right Honorable Edmund Burke, 4th ed. (Boston, 1871), Vol. 4, pp.
80-81. Cf. also Burke, "Speech on A Bill for Shortening the Duration of Parliaments,"
May 8, 1780, in Works, Vol. 7, p. 73: "I must see, to satisfy me, the remedies; I must see,
fromtheir operation in the cure of the old evil, and in the cure of those new evils which are
inseparable from all remedies, how they balance each other, and what is the total result.
The excellence of mathematics and metaphysics is, to have but one thing before you; but
he forms the best judgement in all moral disquisitions who has the greatest number and
variety of considerations in one view before him, and can take them in with the best pos-
sible consideration of the middle results of all."
Review of Politics, Vol. 14, pp. 367-393 (July, 1952); L. Susan Stebbing, Ideals and II-
lusions (London, 1941); Vernon H. Holloway, Religious Ethics and the Politics of Power
(New York, 1951); and Dorothy Fosdick, "Ethical Standards and Political Strategies,"
Political Science Quarterly,Vol. 57, pp. 214 ff. (1942).
The reasons for this failure of the concept as an analytic tool are
numerous. One is the ambiguous nature of the nation and the
difficulty of specifying whose interests it encompasses. A second is
the elusiveness of criteria for determining the existence of interests
and for tracing their presence in substantive policies. Still another
confounding factor is the absence of procedures for cumulating
the interests once they have been identified. This is in turn com-
plicated by uncertainty as to whether the national interest has been
fully identified once all the specific interests have been cumulated
or whether there are not other, more generalized, values which
render the national interest greater than the sum of its parts.5
5
James N. Rosenau, The Scientific Study of Foreign Policy (New York,
1971), p. 243.
80 THE REVIEW OF POLITICS
6
This critique can be found in Graham Allison, Essence of Decision:
Explaining the Cuban Missile Crisis (Boston, 1971); Roger Hilsman, The
Politics of Policy Making in Defense and Foreign Affairs (New York 1971);
Morton Halperin and Arnold Kanter, Readings in American Foreign Policy:
A Bureaucratic Perspective (Boston, 1973); and Morton Halperin, Bureaucratic
Politics and Foreign Policy (Washington, 1974).
7
See Henry A. Kissinger, American Foreign Policy (New York, 1974), pp.
11-50; Roger Fisher, International Conflict for Beginners (New York, 1969);
and Hans J. Morgenthau, "The American Tradition in Foreign Policy: An
Overview," in Foreign Policy in World Politics, ed. Roy C. Macridis, 4th ed.
(Englewood Cliffs, 1972), pp. 389-412.
"NATIONAL INTEREST" IN WORLD POLITICS 81
NATION A . Intergovernmental _
Organizations
i Subnational Subnational
I (bureaucratic Decision- . Inter- , Decision- (bureaucratic
and societal) ' Makers /Nation > Makers ' "and societal)
I interest groups Politics interest groups
Nongovernmental^.
~~ Organizations
"NATIONAL INTEREST" IN WORLD POLITICS 83
Intergovernmental Nongovernmental
Organizations Organizations
NATION B
Subnational interest
•> groups
Decision-Makers
84 THE REVIEW OF POLITICS
within and from without, and that a new and more complex web
of relationships is forming inside and across national boundaries.
It must be noted that, at the same time, countertrends have been
cited by others which reinforce the traditional paradigm. Let us
examine some of these apparent trends and countertrends in an
effort to assess which of the two paradigms is a better model of
contemporary reality. The author does not propose here to "test"
the paradigms through systematic analysis of empirical data—which
would be a task well beyond the scope of this essay—but rather to
make some "face validity" judgments about their relative merits
based on a survey of present conditions in the international system.
10
See Keohane and Nye, Power and Interdependence: World Politics in
Transition; Lawrence Juda, Ocean Space Rights: Developing U.S. Policy
(New York, 1975); Young W. Kihl, Conflict Issues and International Civil
Aviation Decisions: Three Cases (Denver, 1971); John R. Handelman, Howard
B. Shapiro, and John A. Vasquez, Introductory Case Studies for International
Relations (Chicago, 1974); and Jonathan Aronson, "Multiple Actors in the
Transformation of the International Monetary System" (Paper presented at
the International Studies Association Annual Meeting, Toronto, February 25,
1976).
11
See, for example, Robert L. Friedheim, "The 'Satisfied' and 'Dissatisfied'
States Negotiate International Law," World Politics, 18 (1965), 20-41.
8& T H E REVIEW OF POLITICS
26
T r e n d d a t a c a n b e found in Charles W. Kegley, J r . a n d J. Martin
Rochester, "Assessing the I m p a c t of T r e n d s on t h e International System: T h e
Growth of Intergovernmental Organizations," in A Multi-Media Introduction
to International Politics, eds. William D . Coplin a n d Kegley (Chicago, 1971),
pp. 401-412.
27
See James N . Rosenau, "Adaptive Politics in an I n t e r d e p e n d e n t World,"
Orbis, 16 ( 1 9 7 2 ) , 153-173.
28
K e n n e t h N . Waltz, " T h e M y t h of National Interdependence," in The
International Corporation: A Symposium, ed. Charles P. Kindleberger ( C a m -
bridge, 1970), p p . 205-223.
29
Edward L. Morse, "The Politics of Interdependence," International
Organization, 23 (1969), 311-327 and "Interdependence in World Affairs,"
in World Politics: An Introduction, eds. James N. Rosenau, Kenneth W.
Thompson, and Gavin Boyd (New York, 1976), pp. 660-681; Richard N.
Rosecrance and Arthur Stein, "Interdependence: Myth or Reality?" World
Politics, 26 (1973), 1-27; Joseph S. Nye, Jr., "Independence and Interdepen-
dence," Foreign Policy, 22 (1976), 130-161; and Peter J. Katzenstein, "Inter-
national Interdependence: Some Long-Term Trends and Recent Changes,"
International Organization, 29 (1975), 1021-1934.
"NATIONAL INTEREST" IN WORLD POLITICS 93
Conclusion
30
Mansbach et al., The Web of World Politics: Nonstate Actors in the
Global System.
31
Kenneth Simmonds, "Ethnocentric a n d Geocentric Multinational Cor-
porations," in World Business: Promise and Problems, ed. C . C . Brown (New
York, 1970).
94 THE REVIEW OF POLITICS
I
All of the five "cardinal premises" upon which Carter argued a new i
American foreign policy should rest had a familiar ring to them, '
particularly the need to "encourage all countries to rise above 1
narrow national interests [italics added] and work together to solve |
such formidable global problems as the threat of nuclear war, racial |
hatred, the arms race, environmental damage, hunger, and disease." -
It is perhaps not surprising that the president has encountered much r
puzzlement and resistance in his attempt to recast foreign policy i
since his own "state-centric" rhetoric tends to reinforce traditional t
views of the world. If he is to succeed in reorienting United States »
foreign policy, he will have to do a better job than he has thus far '
of educating the American people to the "brave new world" and |
the nature of American "interests" in it. f
i