1956, Gallie, Essentially Contested Concepts
1956, Gallie, Essentially Contested Concepts
1956, Gallie, Essentially Contested Concepts
Author(s): W. B. Gallie
Source: Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society , 1955 - 1956, New Series, Vol. 56 (1955 -
1956), pp. 167-198
Published by: Oxford University Press on behalf of The Aristotelian Society
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
The Aristotelian Society and Oxford University Press are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize,
preserve and extend access to Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society
By W. B. GALLIE.
INTRODUCTORY.
(IV) Just as there is no " marking " or " points " system to
decide who are the champions, so there are no official judges
or strict rules of adjudication. Instead what happens is this.
Each side has its own loyal kernel group of supporters, and
in addition, at any given time, a number of " floating "
supporters who are won over to support it because of the
quality of its play-and, we might add, the loudness of its
kernel supporters' applause and the persuasiveness of their
comments. Moreover, at any given time, one side will have
the largest (and loudest) group of supporters who, we may
say, will effectively hail it as " the champions ". But (V)
the supporters of every contesting team regard and refer to
their favoured team as "the champions " (perhaps allowing
such qualifications as "the true champions ", " the destined
champions ", " morally the champions " . . . and so on).
To bring out the importance of this point, we may suppose
that all groups of supporters would acknowledge that at a
given moment one team T1 are "the effective champions ".
Yet the property of being acknowledged effective champions
carries with it no universal recognition of outstanding
excellence-in T 's style and calibre of play. On the
contrary, the supporters of T2, T3, etc., continue to regard
and to acclaim their favoured teams as " the champions "
and continue with their efforts to convert others to their
view, not through any vulgar wish to be the majority party,
but because they believe their favoured team is playing the
game best. There is, therefore, continuous competition
between the contestant teams, not only for acknowledgement
as champions, but for acceptance of (what each side and its
supporters take to be) the proper criteria of championshiip.
2 Are all four conditions necessary? I suggest that proof of this could be
found along the following lines. Given conditions (II) and (III) we have
the sort of situation where a multi-dimensional description or classification of
certain facts is possible. But in any such situation, specific evidential or
methodological reasons apart, it would be absurd to prefer one style of possible
description or classification to the others. But substitute achievements for
facts, i.e., an appraisive concept or classification for a purely naturalistic one,
and the absurdity disappears, since for the purpose of moral or aesthetic
persuasion one style of description or classification may very definitely be
preferable to another which is logically equipollent with it. Here is a strong
reason for thinking that condition (I) is necessary. But even in a situation
which conforms to conditions (I), (II) and (III) it is conceivable that
experience should establish one style of description as, again for the purpose
of moral or aesthetic persuasion, universally more acceptable than any other
This result could hardly be expected, however, if condition (IV) be added,
i.e., if the kind of achievement which our concept or classification accredi
is, in my sense, an " open " one; for what this condition ensures is, in term
of my artificial example, that to-morrow's circumstances may bring out hither
latent virtues in the play of any of the contestant teams. There remains the
possibility that the addition of condition (IV) renders condition (I) superfluou
This could be maintained if, and only if, instances could be produced of a
concept which conforms to my conditions (II), (III) and (IV) and which
is yet wholly non-appraisive in character. My suspicion is, however, that no
purely naturalistic concept will be found conforming to my conditions (II),
(III) and (IV).
delusion, viz., the deluded belief that the different teams are
all playing the same game."
It turns out, then, that this objection is a request, not
for further refinement of our definition of an essentially
contested concept, but for an indication of the conditions in
which the continued use of any such concept, as above
defined, can be defended. And this is a perfectly fair
request, since it is always reasonable to urge the parties
contesting the rightful use of such a concept to bethink
themselves with all seriousness, whether they are really
alleging the same achievement. For instance, in our
artificial example, might it not simply be said that T1 is
trying to put on a first class performance of (primarily) fast
bowling; T2 of (primarily) straight bowling, and so on, and
that these quite proper but quite different aims of our
different teams are not essentially, but only accidentally and
as a result of persistent confusion, mutually contesting and
contested ?
I shall at once sketch the outlines of the required defence
in terms of my artificial example, but must add that until
it is interpreted in the live examples which follow, it may
well seem somewhat specious. In defence, then, of the
continued use of the concepts " championship " and " the
champions " in my example I urge: each of my teams could
properly be said to be contesting for the same championship
if, in every case, its peculiar method and style of playing
had been derived by a process of imitation and adaptation
from an examplar, which might have the form either of one
prototype team of players, or of a succession (or tradition)
of teams. This examplar's way of playing must be recog-
nized by all the contesting teams (and their supporters) to
be " the way the game is to be played "; yet, because of the
internally complex and variously describable character of
the examplar's play, it is natural that different features in
it should be differently weighted by different appraisers,
and hence that our different teams should have come to
hold their very different conceptions of hiow the game should
be played. To this we should add that recognition or
3 I say confused, because it seems to me that the claim that description (a)
is of absolute, paramount (and perhaps also of logically sufficient) character,
is commonly grounded upon two liberal principles or beliefs, viz., (I) that those
political liberties that are enjoyed by all (or almost all) our citizens deserve
protection primarily because all traditionally accepted liberties (no matter
how restricted the enjoyment of them) are things that prima facie deserve
protection, and (II) that the existence of a wide variety of liberties (enjoyed
by different ranges of our citizens) has been historically and remains to-day a
necessary condition of our specifically democratic values and achievements. Both
these claims, I would say, reflect our grasp of a particular historical truth of
immense importance, viz., as to how democracy has taken root and flourished
in the west. But if they are put forward as universal political truths expressing
the necessary conditions of any genuinely democratic aspirations or achieve-
ments, then they are surely open to question. To many people in the world
to-day they must seem indeed, not so much questionable as utterly-and in
a sense insultingly-irrelevant to their actual situation. What is the relevance
of a Burkian philosophy of political liberties to the great majority of Asians
and Africans to-day?
s 2
4 Cf. my " Liberal Morality and Social Morality " in Philosophy, Vol.XXIV,
No. 91, 1950, pp. 318-334,
OUTSTANDING QUESTIONS.
way ". This tips the scale for him and he is converted to
being a supporter of T1. But now we may assume that the
same particular performance (or shrewd appraisive com-
ment) has had a comparable-though not so dramatically
effective-influence upon other staunch supporters of T2.
It has slightly shaken them, we might say. At least it has
made them aware that, in comparable circumstances T2
must make a comparably effective adaptation of its style
of play if it is to keep their unwavering support. Further,
we may assume that although supporters of T3 are less shaken
by the particular performance, they have at least been made
to " sit up and take notice "; and similarly, with decreasing
degrees of force for supporters of other teams whose styles of
play are still remoter from that of T1.
Put less artificially, what I am claiming is that a certain
piece of evidence or argument put forward by one side in an
apparently endless dispute can be recognized to have a
definite logical force, even by those whom it entirely fail
to win over or convert to the side in question; and that whe
this is the case, the conversion of a hitherto wavering
opponent of the side in question can be seen to be justifiable
-not simply expectable in the light of known relevant
psychological or sociological laws-given the waverer's
previous state of information and given the grounds on
which he previously supported one side and opposed the
other. It is for this reason that we can distinguish more
or less intellectually respectable conversions from those of a
more purely emotional, or yet those of a wholly sinister kind.
To be sure, our previous wavering opponent of one use of
an essentially contested concept would not be justified in
transferring his allegiance in the circumstances outlined if
he were able, for an indefinite length of time, to withhold
his support.from any of its possible uses, i.e., to take up an
entirely uncommitted attitude. But as in our artificial
example, so in life this possibility is often precluded. The
exigencies of living commonly demand that " he who is
not for us is against us ", or that he who hestitates to throw
in his support or make his contribution on one side or the
CCNCLUDING REMARKS