BruceDMarshall 2000 9TrinityTruthAndBelie TrinityAndTruth

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 41

All rights reserved.

May not be reproduced in any form without permission from the publisher, except fair uses

Page 242

9—
Trinity, Truth, and Belief

Truth under Theological Discipline

Truth Borne by a Person

In a theological account of truth, as Donald MacKinnon suggests, any understanding we may acquire of that notion without reference to Christian beliefs will no doubt
be "radically disciplined and changed," although — we hope — ''not annihilated."1 The New Testament seems to regard "is the truth" as a genuine predicate both of
Jesus Christ (see Jn. 14:6) and of the Holy Spirit (see I Jn. 5:6). The discipline to which theology subjects any philosophical proposal about truth is thus obvious, and
radical: if Jesus Christ is the truth, then truth is borne, not only or chiefly by sentences and beliefs, but by a person. More than that: if the New Testament is right, then
in the end truth is a person. The same applies, though differently, to the person of the Spirit.
permitted under U.S. or applicable copyright law.

Should the Tarski­Davidson notion of truth outlined in the previous chapter prove incompatible with the claim that truth is each of these persons, and so intractable to
Copyright 2000. Cambridge University Press.

theological discipline, it faces annihilation (to use MacKinnon's term). At first glance, though, it might seem that a Tarski­Davidson account of truth states the truth
conditions, and so displays the workings of "is true," for statements which express central Christian beliefs as well as it does for any other statements. Surely Christians
want to say, for example, that the following sentence is true:
(1) "Jesus is risen" is true if and only if Jesus is risen.

1
"The Problem of the 'System of Projection' Appropriate to Christian Theological Statements," Explorations in Theology 5: Donald MacKinnon (London: SCM Press, 1979), p.
81.

EBSCO Publishing : eBook Academic Collection (EBSCOhost) - printed on 1/10/2024 5:46 PM via NATIONAL LIBRARY OF KOREA
AN: 55703 ; Bruce D. Marshall.; Trinity and Truth
Account: s7192646.main.ehost
Page 243

Jesus is risen, so Christians proclaim; therefore "Jesus is risen" is true. The person who holds "Jesus is risen" true therefore has a true belief, and the person who holds
it false has a false belief. This not only looks theologically acceptable, but appears to capture in a more informative and less misleading way at least part of what
traditional theological appeals to truth as correspondence were driving at, especially where the traditional view stressed sentences rather than mental contents as truth
bearers. So far, it seems, so plain. Theological discipline appears to leave a Tarski­Davidson account of truth pretty much intact — indeed untouched.

We do not, however, learn anything from (1) about how a person is the bearer of truth. The person Jesus figures in the truth conditions specified by the right branch of
(1), such that if and only if he is risen, ''Jesus is risen" is true, but this does not make Jesus himself "true," still less "the truth," with respect to the sentence "Jesus is
risen." Or, if you like, it makes the person Jesus a truth bearer for "Jesus is risen" in exactly the same sense as grass is a truth bearer for "Grass is green." If having this
location on the right branch of a T­sentence makes Jesus "the truth," it equally well makes grass "the truth" — not, presumably, what John's Gospel means when it
predicates "is the truth" of the person Jesus.

This may prompt the thought that when Davidson and the Gospel of John speak of "truth," they are simply talking about two different things. Truth as borne by
sentences and beliefs has nothing in particular to do with "the truth" as borne, according to the New Testament, by the person Jesus. Supposing otherwise, so it might
be argued, is to read passages like Jn. 14:6 in a needlessly literalistic way. We do not suppose that we need a theological biology because Jesus there says "I am the
life," or a theological geography because he says "I am the way." Why do we need a theological aletheology — an account of truth for sentences and beliefs —
because Jesus says "I am the truth"?

Standard exegetical approaches do not suggest that a passage like Jn. 14:6 may be taken as utterly metaphorical, so that "I am the truth" amounts to something like "I
am the most important thing there is." To be sure, even when exegetes draw freely on philosophical ideas to interpret the concept of truth in John, they tend to connect
it at best loosely to truth as applied to sentences and beliefs.2 But a link between the two uses
2
As, for example, in Heinrich Schlier's broadly Heideggerian"Meditationen über den Johanneischen Begriff der Wahrheit," Besinnung auf Das Neue Testament. Exegetische
Aufsätze und Vorträge II (Freiburg: Herder, 1964), pp. 270–8.

EBSCOhost - printed on 1/10/2024 5:46 PM via NATIONAL LIBRARY OF KOREA. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
Page 244

of "truth" is nonetheless implicit in the common view of recent exegesis that in Jn. 14:6 (as also in 1:7), Jesus is "the truth" in that he is the unique "revelation" of the
Father, the one who alone adequately makes the Father known.3 Jesus is able to bring about knowledge of the Father by others on account of his own unique relation
to the Father: as the Father's Word become our flesh, this human being is the one who ''expresses the total being of the Father."4

For human beings, however, having knowledge requires having true beliefs. To have a belief is to have the disposition to hold sentences true which express the
contents of the belief. The knowledge of the Father which Jesus brings about — and this is the crucial point for present purposes — is thus impossible for us save by
having beliefs and holding sentences true. The text of John seems to confirm this. Jesus' unique relation with the Father is what enables him to make the Father known,
but he imparts the knowledge in words: "I declare what I have seen in the Father's presence" (8:38) and thus, in a different context, "The words that I have spoken to
you are Spirit and life" (6:63; cf. 18:37: "Everyone who is of the truth listens to my voice").

The following conditionals therefore seem exegetically sound:


(2) If Jesus Christ is the truth, then he imparts knowledge of the Father to us

and

(3) If Jesus Christ imparts knowledge of the Father to us, then we have some true beliefs (and we hold true some true sentences).

Taken together, these two conditionals imply


(4) If Jesus Christ is the truth, then we have some true beliefs (and we hold true some true sentences).

Exegetically, therefore, "truth" as applied to sentences and beliefs is logically necessary for the "truth" which the person Jesus Christ is. However
3
Cf. Ignace de la Potterie, La vérité dans Saint Jean, 2 vols. (Rome: Biblical Institute Press, 1977): "The truth of Christ is the unveiling of his Sonship, in his life of love and
obedience to the Father. This revelation of Christ, this truth, has to reach its culmination on the cross" (p. 1011), also Raymond E. Brown, The Gospel According to John, 2 vols.
(Garden City, NY: Doubleday, 1966), vol. II, p. 630. The connection between the truth which Jesus is and the knowledge he brings about was not missed by classical exegesis of
John, though generally without reliance on the notion of revelation. "Truth belongs to [Christ] on account of who he is, namely the Word . . . And because no one can know the
truth unless he clings to it, it is necessary that everyone who desires to know the truth cling to this Word" (Thomas Aquinas, In Ioannem 14, 2, no. 1869). This sort of remark
suggests that our grasp of truth (both the concept and its application to each sentence) depends universally, and not just in some cases, on Jesus' being the truth; we will return
to this point.
4
To recall Aquinas, In Ioannem 1, 1, no. 29.

EBSCOhost - printed on 1/10/2024 5:46 PM via NATIONAL LIBRARY OF KOREA. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
Page 245

we connect more precisely these two applications of "truth," it seems clear that the Gospel of John and Davidson are not simply talking about different things when
they use the term.

We confront, therefore, the following problem. A Tarski­Davidson approach cannot by itself be adequate for a theological account of what truth is, because it gives us
no clue about how to connect truth to a person as its bearer. At the same time, the concept of truth as applied to sentences and beliefs cannot be utterly disparate from
the concept of truth which applies to the person Jesus. Assuming that a Tarski­Davidson approach gives us the best available account of truth for sentences,
theological discipline will have to go beyond merely showing that this approach is compatible with central Christian claims. We need an explanation as to why the
content of the concept of truth as characterized by Tarski and Davidson should be regarded as incomplete, and how it may be expanded theologically without losing
an intelligible tie to the characterization Tarski and Davidson give.

Truth as an Act of the Trinity

Did this characterization of truth capture adequately the way "is true" works for "Jesus is risen," then the truth (or falsity) of "Jesus is risen" would be, as it were,
automatic. Tarski's schema for T­sentences, after all, states not simply necessary (''only if . . .") but sufficient ("if . . .") truth conditions for the sentence described on its
left branch. Should a sentence conforming to this schema express a grasp of the concept of truth adequate to "Jesus is risen," then anyone's utterance, "Jesus is risen,"
will be true depending only on what she means by the words and whether Jesus turns out to be risen (and not dead), just as her utterance, "Grass is green," will be true
if she interprets it in the usual way and grass is green (and not orange). Since the truth of beliefs depends on the truth of the sentences which express them, if Jesus is
risen anyone who holds "Jesus is risen" true will have a true belief, brought about by the attitude he has toward that sentence. The truth of the belief, like that of the
interpreted sentence which states the contents of the belief, will be automatic.

Why should the truth of the belief that Jesus is risen not be automatic in this sense? Here we need to bear in mind two points.

1. Having true beliefs is a necessary condition for having knowledge of Jesus, and so of having any relation to Jesus which depends upon having knowledge of him.
Knowing the risen Jesus requires having the belief that Jesus is risen, and it requires that the belief be true. If (as we

EBSCOhost - printed on 1/10/2024 5:46 PM via NATIONAL LIBRARY OF KOREA. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
Page 246

have argued in chapter 2) having the belief that Jesus is risen is requisite for identifying him, then knowing Jesus at all requires having the true belief that he is risen. To
have knowledge of Jesus is to have a certain relation to him, but many other relations to Jesus depend on having knowledge of him, and in that sense have a cognitive
component: loving, worshipping, following, and so forth. (Relations to Jesus which require no cognitive component, like sharing descent from Abraham, can
presumably obtain for someone who lacks the belief that Jesus is risen, or any other belief about him.) To be sure, one can apparently worship a figure who does not
exist (though whether one can love the inexistent is perhaps less clear), and to that extent worship requires only that one have certain beliefs, not that the beliefs be
true. For the worshipper's intention to succeed, however — for his attitude to relate him to a really existent term — he not only has to hold the relevant beliefs; the
beliefs also have to be true. Having (successful) love or reverence for Jesus does not, of course, consist wholly in having true beliefs about him, but such relations
apparently cannot do without true beliefs sufficient to identify him.

2. Any relations which created reality has to Jesus depend as a whole on Jesus himself. This comes out perhaps most clearly in the way the New Testament
characterizes Jesus' resurrection. The Father raises Jesus by his own free and sovereign action, which is to bestow his Spirit upon the slain Jesus. This gift to the
crucified Jesus fully enacts the Spirit's mission, begun at Jesus' baptism, to abide in and on the Son. The Spirit gives the dead Jesus the divine freedom to rise from the
dead, by including Jesus once again in an ordered but mutual bond of being, knowledge, and love with the Father. Jesus rises, therefore, in the utterly sovereign, self­
determining freedom of God.5 The action of the risen Jesus thus takes place in the full spontaneity of the being and all the acts of the triune God. The risen Jesus is not
passive or inert, and therefore not at the disposal of human beings, or of anything created — except, of course, insofar as he freely gives himself to them. Jesus' being
at their disposal, one could say, is not itself at their disposal, but only at his own. Upon his own action, therefore, depends any relation to him which creatures may
come to have.6
5
For a reading of the resurrection narratives along these lines, see Hans Urs von Balthasar, Mysterium Paschale, trans. Aiden Nichols (Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 1993), pp. 203–
15; on the pneumatological aspect in particular, see pp. 210–12.
6
At this point the logic of genuinely transcendent and therefore non­competing agency (as articulated, e.g., by Tanner in God and Creation) seems indispensable to making sense of
the narratives which identify Jesus. If the human being Jesus is God, he cannot simply be

(footnote continued on next page)

EBSCOhost - printed on 1/10/2024 5:46 PM via NATIONAL LIBRARY OF KOREA. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
Page 247

Taken together, these observations suggest why the truth of the belief that Jesus is risen cannot be automatic. The content of the belief itself seems to preclude the
possibility that the relations of the rest of humanity to the risen Jesus could be brought about save by Jesus' own action. Any element necessary for such relations to
obtain must, it seems, depend in some way upon Jesus' action. Cognitively dependent relations of other human beings to the risen Jesus, relations like knowing and
(successful) loving, require having the true belief that he is risen. Therefore the truth of this belief must itself be brought about by an action which belongs to Jesus.

The resurrection narratives indicate this in a striking way: even though they see him and talk to him, the two disciples on the Emmaus road and Mary Magdalene at the
empty tomb cannot recognize Jesus, and so have the belief that he is risen, until his own deliberate action — his eucharistic blessing in the one case (Lk. 24:30), his
personal address in the other (Jn. 20:16) — enables them to do so.7 Their true belief that he is risen depends on his self­presentation to them, his utter self­giving. This
goes a fortiori for those who have not seen the risen Jesus, and whose belief must come by way of the worship and witness of the Christian community. The point is
not that believers are passive. They hold "Jesus is risen" true, and this is obviously their own attitude and, in some circumstances, their explicit act. The point is rather
that this attitude and act seem not, even in conjunction with the state of affairs that Jesus is risen, sufficient to yield a true belief. A Tarski­Davidson approach cannot,
therefore,

(footnote continued from previous page)

at the disposal of creatures, but his divine agency cannot be defined simply as the negation of creaturely disposability, lest he fail to be a genuine human being. The divine
agency of the human being Jesus must rather include his unlimited freedom to put himself at the disposal of creatures. Karl Barth puts the point with characteristic expansiveness:
"God in Christ . . . is no doubt absolute, infinite, high, active, untouchable, and transcendent. But he is in all this the one who loves in freedom, who is free in his love and thus not
his own prisoner. He is all this instead as the Lord, and thus in such a way that he embraces the oppositions designated by these concepts, while he is at the same time superior to
them. He is all this as the creator, who has made the world as that reality different from him, but willed and affirmed by him, and thus as his own — as the world which belongs to
him. In relation to it he can be God and act as God both in an absolute and in a relative, in an infinite and in a finite, in a high and in a lowly, in an active and in a passive, in a
transcendent and in an immanent, and finally: both in a divine and in a human way" (Kirchliche Dogmatik IV/1 [Zurich: Evangelischer Verlag, 1932–67 — for the complete work], p.
204; ET, pp. 186–7).
7
This point about the resurrection narratives has long been noticed. See, for example, Gregory the Great (Homilia in Evangelia 25, 5; PL 76, 1192C–D): " 'Jesus says to her: Mary' [see
Jn. 20:16]. After he had called her by the common word for her gender, and had not been recognized, he calls her by name. It is as if he said openly: 'Recognize him, by whom you are
recognized . . . I do not know you in a general way, along with everyone else, but in a special way.' And so Mary, because she is called by name, recognizes the one who is speaking."

EBSCOhost - printed on 1/10/2024 5:46 PM via NATIONAL LIBRARY OF KOREA. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
Page 248

offer an adequate characterization of what it is for the belief that Jesus is risen to be true.

This may seem to go a step too far. That someone has the true belief that Jesus is risen, it might be argued, may depend on Jesus' own action, but that the belief is true
does not: it depends only on whether the sentence "Jesus is risen" is true. A belief, in other words, has two components: an interpreted sentence which expresses its
contents, and a holding true of that sentence. The argument so far shows only that the holding true, not the truth of the sentence, depends on something more about
Jesus than that he is risen. Crediting Jesus, or indeed any person of the Trinity, with bringing about the attitude of believing does not, it seems, add anything to the truth
conditions for the sentence as captured by the Tarski­Davidson schema. Having the belief that Jesus is risen is not automatic, but the truth of the belief still is,
assuming that the biconditional truth conditions for the sentence which states its content are met.

Just because the distinction between these two components is basic to the notion of belief, though, the truth of the belief that Jesus is risen has to depend on the
deliberate act of the risen Jesus. If the risen Jesus is not at all at the disposal of creatures, then creatures will have whatever they need in order to acquire a certain
relation to him only because he wills that they have it. Cognitively dependent relations like knowing and loving require not only that we have the attitude of holding
suitable sentences true, but that the sentences be true. So the truth of ''Jesus is risen," and not only the attitude which holds it true, must depend on Jesus' own will and
action. It cannot, by contrast, depend only on his being risen. That Jesus is risen does not seem subject to being taken as an "arrangement of the world," on hand to
make our sentences (automatically) true in Tarski's biconditional fashion when we get their meanings right.8

Were it otherwise, then we could know the risen Jesus regardless of whether he wanted us to — he would be cognitively at our disposal. Presumably it is possible to
generate the attitude of belief toward "Jesus is risen" (or some other sentence with the same meaning) on our own,
8
Barth insists on this point in his own way, though it is not unique to him. "The fact [of the existence of Jesus Christ] which God has posited is not a mute but an eloquent fact, a
fact which speaks for itself, which bears witness to and explains itself; it has and uses the power to proclaim itself adequately in its truth, and thereby to communicate and share
itself in its reality" (Kirchliche Dogmatik IV/3, p. 253; ET, p. 221). God — here precisely the crucified Jesus — "does not deliver himself captive to human thought and speech . . .
God himself alone can make [human thought and speech] true" (p. 473; ET, p. 410).

EBSCOhost - printed on 1/10/2024 5:46 PM via NATIONAL LIBRARY OF KOREA. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
Page 249

though this attitude best comes to us, so Christians suppose, as a gift from Jesus himself. If the truth of "Jesus is risen" (suitably interpreted) depended only on Jesus'
being risen, then anyone who held this sentence true would have a true belief, even when the holding true was her own doing rather than his. She would thereby know
the risen Jesus, it seems, against (or at least without) his will, and might (other things being equal) have further cognitively dependent relations to him as well. That the
risen Jesus is not at our cognitive disposal cannot, it seems, be guaranteed simply by regarding him as the primary cause of the attitude of belief.9

In any case credit for bringing about the attitude of belief towards the rightly interpreted sentence "Jesus is risen" belongs, among the divine persons, chiefly to the
Spirit, not to the Son. Our having the true belief that he is risen cannot be the work of the risen Jesus alone; all three persons of the Trinity consort to bring this result
about. It is the Spirit who acts immediately upon human beings to elicit the belief that Jesus is risen, who directly leads the world "into all the truth" (see Jn. 16:13).
Jesus himself is, of course, the truth into which the Spirit's action leads the world. Were responsibility for creating the attitude of believing sufficient to characterize
Jesus' own action in bringing about the true belief that he is risen, there would be no distinction between Jesus' role in the one divine action of bringing about this true
belief and the role of the Spirit in that action.

Perhaps when it comes to creating true beliefs about him, the Son's distinctive role is simply to send the Spirit, who does the actual work of bringing about the attitude
of belief. Jesus does send the Spirit for this purpose. But limiting Jesus' work in the creation of true beliefs about him to the job he sends the Spirit to do would miss
the distinctive relation to each of the three persons which any divine action creates, in virtue of the particular role each person has in the action. In bringing about true
beliefs, as in carrying out any divine action, Jesus brings about in us a direct and immediate relation to him, and not only to the other persons of the Trinity. John
16:12–15 indicates this: the Holy Spirit is to lead us into all truth, in the first place by bringing about the attitude of believing true
9
The tradition has often distinguished sharply between the cognitive situation of a person who holds sentences of scripture and creed true by God's grace, and that of a person
who does so "by his own will.'' Aquinas, for example, argues that those who assert "Deus est" (and presumably also "Iesus Christus resurrexit a mortuis") "by a certain opinion
rooted in their own will" rather than by the grace of God (he takes heretics for the chief instance of the class) lack a true belief that God exists (Summa theologiae II–II, 5, 3, c; cf. 10,
3, c; for the argument see "Faith and Reason Reconsidered," The Thomist 63/1 [1999] pp. 8–13).

EBSCOhost - printed on 1/10/2024 5:46 PM via NATIONAL LIBRARY OF KOREA. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
Page 250

sentences about Jesus, like "Jesus is risen." Jesus cannot be the truth into whom the Spirit leads us in that he too brings about the same attitude. Otherwise there would
be no distinction between the Spirit's leading and what the Spirit leads us into; instead of leading us into the truth (by way of leading us to have true beliefs), the Holy
Spirit would, redundantly, lead us into leading us into the truth.10 Jesus must be "the truth" with respect to a sentence like "Jesus is risen" in some other way than that he
elicits the attitude of assent to it which yields a true belief.

For cognate trinitarian reasons — and not simply because it would put him involuntarily at the disposal of creatures — Jesus' role in creating the true belief that he is
risen cannot consist in his being risen (that is, in having a property such that Tarski­style truth conditions for ''Jesus is risen" are met). In the action of bringing about the
true belief that he is risen, Jesus' role needs to be distinguished from that of the Father as well as from that of the Spirit. The Father's role is to raise Jesus from the
dead, to bring it about that Jesus is risen.11 The Father's own part in the action is, as it were, to see to it that Tarski­type truth conditions for "Jesus is risen" are met.
Jesus cannot be responsible for this, since the Father acts to raise a person who has gone to the dead, and the dead do not themselves act.12 Did Tarski's conditions
adequately capture what it is for "Jesus is risen" to be true, then Jesus himself would have no place in the divine action of bringing about the true belief that he is risen.
The Father's act would bring it about that the relevant biconditional truth conditions were met, and the Spirit's act would see to it that people actually held "Jesus is
risen" true; the Son would have nothing to do.

If Jesus is to have a role of his own in this action, the truth of our belief that he is risen requires not only that the Father act on him, but also that he act on us. Since the
Spirit brings about the will to believe, Jesus has to act on
10
Jesus also has to do something other than send the Spirit in order clearly to distinguish his role in the action of leading us into the truth from the Father's, since the Father also
sends the Spirit. See Jn. 14:16–17, 26 (where the Father gives and sends the Holy Spirit) over against Jn. 15:26 and 16:7 (where Jesus promises to send the Spirit). As the tradition
has noted, though, Luke/Acts suggests that the action of sending the Spirit is itself not undertaken in exactly the same way by the Father and the Son; having received the Spirit
in fulfillment of the Father's promise, the risen and exalted Jesus "pours out" the Spirit on all flesh (Acts 2:33; see Acts 1:4; Lk. 24:49).
11
In the action of raising Jesus — which is, of course, not the same as the action which yields the true belief that Jesus is risen — the Spirit too has a distinctive role; the Father raises
Jesus by persevering in his baptismal donation of the life­giving Spirit to Jesus even in Jesus' "going to the dead" (to borrow Balthasar's phrase).
12
Belief in Jesus' resurrection brings particular clarity to the different way in which each of the divine persons undertakes the act of creating true beliefs, since at least in this case the
specific action of the person the belief is about apparently cannot consist in causing the state of affairs or "arrangement of the world" in virtue of which the belief is true.

EBSCOhost - printed on 1/10/2024 5:46 PM via NATIONAL LIBRARY OF KOREA. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
Page 251

us in a different way. He must, it seems, make himself accessible to the person who (at the Spirit's bidding) believes that he is risen; he must act upon the mind as the
Spirit acts upon the will. For someone who assents to "Jesus is risen" to have a true belief, Jesus must not only be risen, he must bring it about that the sentence they
hold true, is true. When the Father has done his work on the dead Jesus, and the Spirit has done his work on us, whether our belief that Jesus is risen is true depends
on Jesus himself, on his free self­presentation, his spontaneous creative willingness that the belief that he is risen be true. In at least this specific sense he is "the truth."

That the truth of "Jesus is risen" depends on Jesus' own spontaneity does not make its truth serendipitous or occasional. This sentence and the belief expressed by
assenting to it are true without any such qualification if Jesus freely gives himself to make them true without such qualification, which he does. Theologians have
regularly held that at least some people who hold creedal sentences like "Jesus is risen" true nonetheless lack a true belief, but even on quite traditional grounds we
may grant that Jesus' gracious self­presentation reaches them, and grants them too a true belief.13 The tradition has usually supposed, after all (following Jas. 2:19), that
even demons have a true belief in Jesus' resurrection, though they hate what they find themselves compelled to believe. This suggests a fortiori that people who hold
''Jesus is risen" true apart from the grace of God, or who do so even though they have spurned Spirit­wrought love, may also have a true belief.14 The conditional "If
Jesus did not act to make it so, then 'Jesus is risen' would not be true" does not assert that Jesus fails to act, any more than "If humans had not sinned, God would have
become incarnate" asserts that human beings have not sinned (to recall another, widely discussed, counterfactual scenario). Our argument does not, therefore, fall afoul
of the traditional thought that even the demons can have the true belief that Jesus is risen. On the contrary, that they have this true belief simply suggests the generosity
of God: though the demons wish it otherwise, the gracious act by which Jesus makes the belief that he is risen true extends even to them.

Divine Action and Appropriation

The foregoing argument against taking the truth of "Jesus is risen" as automatic presumes that Jesus' action must be different from those of the
13
Cf. note 9 above. There might, of course, be other reasons why their belief was not true, e.g., that what they meant by "Jesus Is risen" did not make for a true belief.
14
See Thomas Aquinas, In Gal. 5, 2 (no. 287): "What demons believe displeases them, and the baseness of will in a human being who refuses to believe is not so great as that in a
demon who hates what he believes."

EBSCOhost - printed on 1/10/2024 5:46 PM via NATIONAL LIBRARY OF KOREA. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
Page 252

Father and the Spirit. His presentation and gift of himself to the world as the risen one belongs to a single act by which the Trinity brings about the true belief that he is
risen. In this unitary act each of the persons has, however, his own distinctive role: the Father gives Jesus the freedom to rise in their common Spirit, so that the risen
Jesus' free self­presentation to the world, grasped through the gift of that Spirit, is itself sustained by the Father's absolute initiative.

This may seem incoherent. If three agents engage in actions which are alike in the relevant ways, we may say that they do the same thing — that their actions are
qualitatively identical. Should Peter, James, and John all make sandals, we may say that they do the same work, meaning that they perform the same kind of action.
We do not mean by this, however, that they perform the very same action — that their actions are numerically identical. In this sense we normally count actions and
agents together: one agent for each action, and conversely. Peter's sandal making is one action, James's another, and so forth. If the Father, the Son, and the Holy
Spirit engage in a single action, therefore, it seems natural to count them as a single agent. But this is hard to square with the way the narrative which identifies the three
depicts the interaction between them. The Father sends the Son, and the Son obeys the Father (by accepting the Father's mission); if these two were the same agent,
the Father would send himself, the Son would obey himself, and so forth. Taking the three as the same agent threatens, moreover, to eradicate any distinction between
them at all.15 If the numerical unity of their action eliminates Father, Son, and Spirit as distinct agents, it eliminates a fortiori the differences between their actions
proposed in the foregoing account of the way they bring about true beliefs, differences which apparently rule out qualitative (to say nothing of numerical) identity.
15
In the following way. If the divine action is numerically one, then when we assert (e.g.) "The Father creates," we can equally well substitute salva veritate "the Son," "the
Spirit," "the Trinity," or "God'' for "the Father." This is just what we want theologically, since it allows us to say both that Father, Son, and Spirit all create, and that they are one
God and one creator. But it also means that the intersubstitutable terms should all refer to the same thing (assuming that the substituted position is, in Quine's phrase, "purely
referential" — roughly, that these assertions do not take place in indirect discourse, statements of propositional attitude, or some other context which obscures reference). And
this implies that the Father, the Son, and the Spirit are the same thing, viz., are numerically identical with one another. One could of course argue that while Father, Son, and Spirit
are one agent, they are distinct in some other way. Assuming, though, that only individuals act (in traditional terms, only hypostases or supposita, so that "actus sunt
suppositorum"; cf. Aquinas, Summa theologiae I, 29, 1, c; 39, 5, ad 1), if Father, Son, and Spirit were one agent, they wold have to be one individual (one hypostasis or
suppositum), which presumably they are not. The main difficulty posed by the numerical unity of divine action therefore lies not, as is often supposed, in explaining how it allows
us to know that the divine persons are distinct from one another, but how it allows there to be any distinct persons to know.

EBSCOhost - printed on 1/10/2024 5:46 PM via NATIONAL LIBRARY OF KOREA. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
Page 253

This might induce us simply to drop the thought that the three divine persons can undertake numerically the same action. Bringing about the true belief that Jesus is risen
should be taken not as a single action, but as a class name for three different actions, one for each divine agent. This gives us the desired difference of Jesus' action
from those of the Father and the Spirit, frees us from having to take the Father's raising of Jesus and Jesus' self­presentation to the world (or the Father's sending and
Jesus' obedience, and so on) as somehow belonging to the same action, and leaves us with three numerically distinct agents.

Yet from an early point reflection on the works of the triune God has tended to insist that every action shared by the Father, the Son, and the Spirit has to be
numerically, and not simply qualitatively, the same for all three. On the numerical unity of the divine action has seemed to depend the possibility of taking the three as
one God who acts in the world, rather than three gods who do similar things. Did Father, Son, and Spirit not undertake numerically the same action, they could no
more be one God than Peter, James, and John, plying generically the same trade, could be one tradesman.16 The coherence of the Christian identification of the one
God as the Trinity seems to require that Father, Son, and Spirit, while numerically distinct agents, share the very same action.17
16
Gregory of Nyssa is among the first to argue this point explicitly. "The Holy Trinity undertakes no action which is divided according to the number of hypostases, but there
takes place one motion . . ." Ad Ablabium: Quod non sint tris dii, Gregorii Nysseni Opera, vol. III, part 1: Opera Dogmatica Minora, ed. Frideric Mueller (Leiden: Brill, 1958), p. 48,
20–4. "No activity is separated with regard to the hypostases, as though it were brought to completion by each of them individually or separately, apart from their shared
oversight" (p. 50, 17–20). Consequently, "we cannot count as three gods those who surely enact their divine power and activity of overseeing us and the whole creation in
complete agreement and inseparable mutuality" (p. 49, 4–7). Augustine argues, similarly, that Father, Son, and Spirit have to be distinct agents, since (e.g.) only the Son was born
of the Virgin Mary and rose from the dead, only the Spirit descended in the form of a dove upon the baptized Jesus, and only the Father spoke from heaven, "You are my Son.'' In
each case the action (or passion) belongs to one, "and not to all three" (nec eandem trinitatem), "yet just as the Father, the Son, and the Holy Spirit are inseparable, so they also
act (operentur) inseparably." De Trinitate I, 4, 7 (CCL 50, pp. 35–6).
17
Concern to avoid tritheism sometimes leads to the suggestion that Father, Son, and Spirit not only undertake a single action, but are a single agent. Karl Rahner, for example,
apparently rules out taking them as three agents ("three different centers of action"), and thus as three "subjectivities" capable of saying "you" to one another ("Der dreifaltige Gott
als transzendenter Urgrund der Heilsgeschichte," Mysterium Salutis, vol. II: Die Heilsgeschichte vor Christus, ed. Johannes Feiner and Magnus Löhrer [Einsiedein: Benziger Verlag,
1967], pp. 343, 366, note 29. ET: The Trinity, trans. Joseph Donceel, 2nd edn [New York: Crossroads, 1997], pp. 43, 76). In part for these reasons he shares Karl Barth's hesitation about
thinking of the three as "persons," and proposes an alternative ("distinct ways of subsistence") similar to Barth's (see pp. 385–93 [ET, pp. 103–15], and Barth, Kirchliche Dogmatik
I/1, pp. 370, 374–83 [ET, pp. 350–1, 355–63]). Some of the obstacles to taking the three as a single agent — at least when this is played off against the thought that each is himself an
agent — have already been pointed out.
The issue might, however, be parsed so that the triune God came out as a single agent,

(footnote continued on next page)

EBSCOhost - printed on 1/10/2024 5:46 PM via NATIONAL LIBRARY OF KOREA. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
Page 254

We need, then, a way to count agents without counting actions. "Appropriation" is the traditional technical device for accomplishing this. The term is medieval; as
Aquinas defines it, "to appropriate" is "to draw that which is shared" by all three persons ''toward that which is unique" to each (commune trahere ad proprium).18
So defined, "appropriation" labels two different though related thoughts.19

1. Every attribute and action common to the three persons belongs primarily to one of them. The primacy here in question is that of likeness (similitudo, as the
medievals put it) rather than of causality or existential dependence, where the Father always comes first (the Son and the Spirit, since they come forth from the Father,
depend for their being and all their attributes on him; correlatively, he can receive no attribute from them). The content of each attribute and action shared by the three
persons will naturally have a special fitness with features unique (or "proper") to one of the persons. In virtue of this likeness that person "draws" or appropriates the
common attribute or action to himself. Noticing the way each action of the divine persons displays this likeness of what they share to what (as unique or proper) they
do not, we in turn ascribe or "appropriate" each attribute and action chiefly to one of the persons.20 In this sense "truth" has often been taken as a shared attribute
appropriated to the Son; to this thought we will return in the next section.

2. Every attribute and action common to the three persons belongs to each of them in a different way. The difference stems from the characteristics, unique to each, by
which the persons are distinct from one another. Just as the propria of one person establish an especially intimate likeness of a shared attribute or action to that
person, so each person possesses each attribute or action in a unique way. This idea precedes the use of the term "appropriation" to label it. Athanasius already notes
that Father, Son, and

(footnote continued from previous page)


while each person remained an agent in his own right. This would relocate the problem we are trying to solve, and perhaps make it more daunting: we would need to look not only
for a way of counting agents without counting actions, but also for a way of counting individuals who act without necessarily counting agents. Some terms do need to be
predicated in the singular both of the three persons taken one by one and of the three taken together; the most basic case is "God": the Father is God, the Son is God, and the
Holy Spirit is God, yet they are not three gods, but one God (see Augustine, De Trinitate v, 8, 9; for a later semantic analysis see Aquinas, Summa theologiae I, 39, 3). Whether "is
an agent" conforms to the semantic pattern of "is God," and so whether Father, Son, and Spirit are in a sense one agent as well as three performers of a single action, we can leave
undecided for present purposes.
18
De Veritate 7, 3, c.
19
On this see also Bruce D. Marshall, "Action and Person: Do Palamas and Aquinas Agree about the Spirit?" St. Vladimir's Theological Quarterly 39/4 (1995), pp. 394–401.
20
As Aquinas puts the point, "each divine action is better suited to be appropriated to one of the persons than to another, insofar as the attribute which is appropriated to that person
is more clearly manifested by the action." In III Sent. 4, 1, 1, i, c (no. 18).

EBSCOhost - printed on 1/10/2024 5:46 PM via NATIONAL LIBRARY OF KOREA. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
Page 255

Spirit undertake each shared action in an irreversible sequence, and thereby in a certain fixed relation to one another: "In effect, the Father does everything through the
Word, in the Spirit, and it is in this way that the unity of the Trinity is preserved."21 The unique place of each person in this sequence is sufficient, so Nyssa and others
suggest, to establish that each person undertakes the shared action in a different way.22

The Western middle ages develop fuller accounts of the propria of each person, and with that strive to specify how each possesses in a unique way what is common
to all. Aquinas's account of divine "adoption" furnishes a clear example. For God to adopt Adam's fallen offspring as his own children (cf. Rom. 8:15–17, 23, 29; Gal.
4:5) is a single act undertaken by all three persons, but each in his own way. The Father is the source of this act. He not only initiates it, but has the prerogative to
share with those who are not his natural offspring the goods he imparts to the one who is, so that we become his adopted children ("to adopt" thus belongs primarily to
the Father). As the Father's natural offspring by eternal generation, the Son is the pattern or exemplar of our adoption; in his infinite possession of the Father's
goods — the divine nature itself — the divine act of adoption gives us a share. And the Spirit joins us to the Son; he ''imprints" upon us the pattern constituted by the
Son, and so completes the divine act which adopts us.23
21
Epistulae ad Seraptonem I, 28 (PG 26, 596A).
22
"There takes place one motion and distribution of the good will which passes from the Father, through the Son, to the Spirit" (Ad Ablabium, p. 48, 22–49, 1). God's power to oversee
creation (viz., God's providence) "is one in Father, Son, and Holy Spirit . . . it starts out from the Father as its source, it is enacted by the Son, and its grace is completed in the power of
the Holy Spirit" (p. 50, 13–17).
23
See Summa theologiae III, 23, 2 ad 3: "Adoption, while it is common to the whole Trinity, nonetheless is appropriated to the Father as source (auctori), to the Son as exemplar, and
to the Holy Spirtt as the one who impresses upon us the likeness of this exemplar."
Recent discussions of appropriation sometimes take the point of the notion to be the opposite of that stipulated by this sort of remark, apparently assuming that to appropriate a
shared attribute or action denies, rather than asserts, that it is possessed or undertaken by each of the three divine persons in a unique way. Rahner, for example, habitually speaks of
"merely" appropriated relationships of the divine persons to creatures, contrasting these unfavorably with "proper" or "not­appropriated" relationships (see "Der dreifaltige Gott," pp.
329, 336–7, 366–7; ET, pp. 23, 34–5, 76–7). He seems to regard appropriation as a symptom, and perhaps a cause, of the eclipse of the Trinity as a vital mystery of salvation (see pp.
322–3; ET, pp. 14–15); at best it admits of a harmless construal which keeps it from getting in the way of what Rahner apparently fails to notice is its traditional point: that "the activity
which is common to all three persons . . . is (like the divine essence) possessed by each of the three persons in the way unique to him" (p. 367; ET, p. 77). Though doubts about
"merely appropriated" relationships were on the scene before Rahner's treatise, one is a bit puzzled to find him concerned about this; if each of the divine persons fails to be an agent
in his own right, how can his action set up a relationship to creatures in any sense different from that of the other two persons? In any case, Thomas's own rejection of "mere"
appropriations is unmistakable: "The likeness of the appropriated attribute to that which is unique to the person [to whom it is appropriated] establishes the fitness of the
appropriation ontologically (facit convenientiam appropriationis ex parte ret); it would obtain even if we did not exist." In I Sent. 31, 1, 2, c.

EBSCOhost - printed on 1/10/2024 5:46 PM via NATIONAL LIBRARY OF KOREA. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
Page 256

So understood, appropriating a divine action differently to each of the three persons apparently gives us a way of counting agents without counting actions. With
regard to the case at hand: in the sentence
(5) God brings about the true belief that Jesus is risen

we can substitute "the Father," "the Son Jesus," and "the Holy Spirit" salva veritate for "God.'' This displays the numerical unity of the divine action, and with that the
unity of God. At the same time we can give descriptions of the action which specify the unique role of each person in it:

(6) The Father brings about the true belief that Jesus is risen by raising Jesus

(7) The Holy Spirit brings about the true belief that Jesus is risen by enabling people to hold this belief true

(8) The Son Jesus brings about the true belief that he himself is risen by freely presenting himself such that when this belief is held true, it is true.

In these sentences we cannot substitute salva veritate "the Father," "the Son" and "the Holy Spirit" for one another. Failure of intersubstitution in these cases
guarantees that the referents of these terms are not identical, despite their intersubstitutability in (5), and so displays that Father, Son, and Spirit are agents numerically
distinct from one another.

Ascribing to Jesus his own unique role in the divine action of bringing about the true belief that he is risen is thus compatible with the unity of the triune God, and
conversely. Jesus' action is different from that of the Father and the Holy Spirit not numerically, but in the manner in which he carries out the very same act.

This perhaps begins to give a sense of what it might mean to say that truth is, and is borne by, a person. Theological discipline modifies — though it does not, I think,
annihilate — the Tarski­Davidson account of truth in two ways.

1. Jesus is the ultimate bearer of the truth of "Jesus is risen," and of the belief expressed by this sentence. At least in this life, human beings can have the true belief that
Jesus is risen only by holding this sentence (or one which translates it) true. The sentence therefore remains a genuine truth bearer for us, without any need to invoke
mental contents. But it is a secondary and dependent, rather than a primary, truth bearer. It bears truth only because the person Jesus does, and causes it to do so.

2. Jesus' own unique role in the action of the triune God which presents him risen to the world is necessary in order for "Jesus is risen" and

EBSCOhost - printed on 1/10/2024 5:46 PM via NATIONAL LIBRARY OF KOREA. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
Page 257

its cognates to be true. Reference to this action thus seems necessary in order to capture the way "is true" works for "Jesus is risen." It is probably not most useful to
interpret the modification which the Christian doctrine of God brings to a Tarski­Davidson account of truth as an addition of further truth conditions beyond those
specified by Tarski's schema.24 This would require eliminating the biconditional in T­sentences, which would doubtless have unfortunate repercussions elsewhere —
not least in the theory of meaning and interpretation, since speaker and interpreter alike have to be able to grasp when truth conditions for a speaker's utterance are
met, which requires the capacity to locate sufficient, and not simply necessary, conditions. A further, more theologically pertinent reason is that the truth conditions for
a sentence are unique to it (and to sentences which translate it), and apply to it regardless of whether it is true or false; the biconditional brings both of these features
out. Jesus' truth­bestowing action, by contrast, is not similarly unique to any particular batch of intertranslatable sentences, but applies — with one important type of
exception, as we shall argue in the next section — to all true sentences; it obtains, however, only for true sentences and not for false ones.

To be sure, a puzzle here arises which there may be no conceptually satisfactory way to solve. By taking the role of Jesus himself in bringing about the true belief that
he is risen as part of the concept of truth for this belief, rather than as a condition of its truth, we avoid one problem, but create another, equally serious. It seems
incoherent to grant that a Tarski­style biconditional gives the truth conditions for this belief, and then to insist that an action of the risen Jesus is necessary in order for
the belief to be true. How can necessary and sufficient truth conditions for a belief be met, and the belief still not be true — at least not yet?

The specter of incoherence here can, I think, be put down, but at a cost. Tarski's and Davidson's T­sentences can be taken as giving the sufficient created conditions
for the belief that Jesus is risen to be true. But the truth of the belief also requires a divine action: not simply, we have argued, the action of creating the arrangement of
the world which would make the belief true, but also an action, admittedly somewhat elusive, of the risen Jesus, which we have characterized as his self­presentation.
A specific divine action is thus requisite for the truth of the belief. Since this action is uncreated, however, it fails to compete with
24
I mistakenly thought otherwise in '''We Shall Bear the Image of the Man of Heaven': Theology and the Concept of Truth," Modern Theology 11 (1995), pp. 108–9.

EBSCOhost - printed on 1/10/2024 5:46 PM via NATIONAL LIBRARY OF KOREA. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
Page 258
25
the created truth conditions for the belief. Because it is of course the divine persons themselves (chiefly the Father) who create these conditions, this comes to saying
that the components of the triune act of bringing it about that we have the true belief that Jesus is risen fail to compete with one another.

We have thought clarity best served by taking Jesus' truth­bestowing act as part of the content of the concept of truth, rather than as a further truth condition (lest
Tarski­style conditions be taken as insufficient), but one could equally well parse the matter by saying that the action of the risen Jesus is the specifically uncreated (or
divine) truth condition for the belief, in contrast with the created conditions isolated by Tarski. In either case, the appearance of contradiction — of saying that
sufficient truth conditions are insufficient — is removed, because we cannot group divine and created conditions together under a single notion of "condition," and so
cannot suppose that "sufficient conditions" means the same thing in each case. The cost is obscurity. We cannot conceive of uncreated truth conditions except by
qualifying and negating elements in our concept of created conditions, which avoids the suggestion of competition but denies us a clear concept of the truth­bestowing
role of divine action. As a result we have no clear way now to explain how two elements which we take to be necessary to the concept of truth, at least for one
belief — Tarski­style conditions and the action of the risen Jesus — fit together in a single concept, even though we are committed to thinking that they have to do so.
The best we can do is block the suggestion that they are positively incompatible. This is what theological discipline regularly does to philosophical notions. It exacts a
price in obscurity which one perhaps has to have distinctively Christian epistemic priorities to think worth paying.

There cannot, at any rate, be any objection on Davidsonian grounds that there is more to what truth is for sentences than their truth conditions as specified by Tarski,
since Davidson often insists on this with regard to the bearing of truth on meaning and belief. Only a strict minimalist about truth could raise an objection on this
score — which suggests that minimalism about truth would have to be theologically unsatisfying, even if it were philosophically preferable.
25
There is a parallel here with the relation between genuinely sovereign divine agency and free human action (see note 6 above and chapter 7, note 29), and also with the
conceptual limitations imposed by the need to characterize that relation as non­competing. This is not surprising, since the case at hand — where we find reason to assert both a
divine act of making true and a human act of locating truth conditions — is itself an instance of the relation between divine and human agency.

EBSCOhost - printed on 1/10/2024 5:46 PM via NATIONAL LIBRARY OF KOREA. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
Page 259

The Trinitarian Shape of the Concept of Truth

So far we have indicated how an action of the Trinity, undertaken differently by each of the persons, belongs to the concept of truth for one belief. If we had to take
beliefs one by one this would not be much of an advance, but it ought to be possible to take "Jesus is risen," and the belief expressed by holding that sentence true, as
a pattern for the way the action of the Trinity shapes the concept of truth for sentences and beliefs generally.

We are looking, after all, for a single concept of truth applicable to all true sentences and beliefs. Suppose the action of the Trinity bore in a different way, or not at all,
on the concept of truth for each belief — differently, say, on what truth is for "The Holy Spirit is poured out on all flesh'' or for "Grass is green" than for "Jesus is risen."
In that case we would have a different concept of truth for each sentence and belief, rather than the unitary concept we are looking for. We would, in effect, be back
to the minimalist view, where each sentence, since it has truth conditions unique to it, has its own concept of truth. Philosophers from Plato to Davidson have argued
against breaking up the concept this way, and in any case it seems ruled out theologically. If Jesus Christ and the Holy Spirit are, each in his own way, "the truth," then
it seems as though the action of each has to bear on what truth is for all sentences and beliefs (otherwise each would be at best "a truth"), and that it has to do so in
basically the same way for all sentences and beliefs (otherwise each would be a plurality of truths, for a plurality of sentences).

It will, however, be useful to distinguish, in accordance with their contents, between two sorts of beliefs: those about the Trinity and those about creatures. Roughly
put, we will treat separately sentences (like "The Holy Spirit is poured out on all flesh") whose Tarski­style truth conditions include terms referring to the persons of the
Trinity, their attributes and actions, and sentences (like "Grass is green") whose truth conditions lack such terms, but may include terms referring to anything else.

Beliefs about the Trinity

Not only in the raising of Jesus, but in their totality, the being and acts of the triune God are not at the disposal of anything created. What applies to relations to the
persons of the Trinity which depend on holding "Jesus is risen" true applies, therefore, to relations which depend on any belief about the divine persons. Since the
relations themselves depend on the

EBSCOhost - printed on 1/10/2024 5:46 PM via NATIONAL LIBRARY OF KOREA. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
Page 260

action of the Trinity, the truth of those beliefs which the relations require must do so as well.

Together with the need for a unitary concept of truth for all sentences and beliefs, this apparently licenses us to take the belief that Jesus is risen as the pattern for any
true belief about the Trinity: a unitary action of the divine persons, undertaken differently by each, belongs to the concept of truth for any such belief and the sentences
which express it. With regard to the belief that the Holy Spirit is poured out on all flesh, for example, the Father sees to it that the truth conditions for sentences
expressing this belief are met — sees to it, in other words, that the Holy Spirit is poured out on all flesh. The Spirit himself sees to it that people hold these sentences
true, that they form the conviction that he has been outpoured. And the risen Jesus sees to it that the belief which people thus hold true, is true.

The roles of the persons in the action by which they see to it that we have true beliefs should not, however, be confused with their roles in the actions the beliefs are
about. As the Greek fathers suggested early on, the Father initiates every divine action. When it comes to our having true beliefs concerning the Trinity, the Father's
initiative brings it about that "the world is arranged" such that sentences expressing those beliefs are true, but this does not mean that the Father is always either the
primary or the immediate divine agent by which that "arrangement of the world" comes to be. Depending on the action — especially the actions of the divine persons in
relation to one another, which are our present concern — any of the persons might be the primary agent (the one with whose propria the action has the greatest
likeness) or the immediate agent (the one whose role terminates the action). So the Father is the primary agent of Jesus' resurrection, and the Spirit apparently the
immediate agent; the same goes for our adoptive share in Christ's natural relation to the Father. The Father sometimes seems to be both the primary and immediate
agent of the outpouring of the Spirit, though sometimes he seems to have entrusted the latter, and perhaps the former, role to the risen Jesus.26 By contrast the Spirit
seems to be both the primary and immediate agent of the conception of Jesus as the incarnate Word in Mary's womb.27

Our having true beliefs about these various divine actions appears to depend upon the immediate agency of the Spirit, since the Spirit leads us
26
See note 10 above.
27
See Aquinas's account of the appropriations pertinent to this action in Summa theologiae III, 32, 1, c; ad 1.

EBSCOhost - printed on 1/10/2024 5:46 PM via NATIONAL LIBRARY OF KOREA. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
Page 261

to hold true the appropriate sentences about these actions, namely those whose truth conditions the Father, by ensuring that the actions get done, guarantees are met.
It seems right, however, to take the risen Jesus as the primary agent of the divine action by which we come to have true beliefs regarding the Trinity, the one to whom
this action is chiefly "appropriated.'' None of the divine persons is at the disposal of creatures. It belongs to the risen Jesus, however, to display the specifically
cognitive indisposability of the triune God in the most unambiguous way. He retains (as the appearance narratives suggest) his indisposability even in the face of his
apparent spatio­temporal availability, and at the same time grants cognitive access to the Trinity by that self­bestowal which makes beliefs we have about the divine
persons true. In this sense it belongs chiefly to the risen Jesus to manifest the Trinity to the world — not only by making it possible for us to identify the Father and the
Spirit along with him (as we discussed in chapter 2), but by bringing it about that the beliefs which constitute the identification of the triune God are true.

What exactly does the risen Jesus manifest? We have been concerned so far only with the actions of the Trinity in time, but basic Christian practices suggest that the
creative, redeeming, and consummating work of the Trinity gives us access to the divine persons themselves, and not only to the work they do. We have already
indicated how the liturgy, especially in the creed and the eucharistic prayer, ascribes to the divine persons not only features which enable us to identify them, but
features which seem genuinely constitutive of their identities, of who they are. To recall the creedal cases: the Father eternally "begets" the Son, the Son is eternally
"begotten" by the Father, and the Spirit "proceeds" from both (in the case of our sample liturgy).28 Chiefly by way of the risen Jesus' self­bestowal, the Trinity
apparently grants us true beliefs sufficient to acquaint us with the persons themselves, and not just with their temporal actions.

It may be tempting to suppose that knowing the persons of the Trinity just is knowing their actions toward us — that to grasp their personal identities just is to have
true beliefs about their actions. But this is implausible. As we have observed in chapter 2, Christian liturgy and scripture characterize the whole life of Jesus as a gift of
the Father to the world, and the outpouring of the creator Spirit on all flesh likewise as a gift of the Father and his risen Son. That these are gifts implies that the acts
which give them — the sendings; of the Son and of the Spirit — are free.
28
See chapter 2, pp. 27–8, 40.

EBSCOhost - printed on 1/10/2024 5:46 PM via NATIONAL LIBRARY OF KOREA. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
Page 262

If they are free, then they are contingent: the acts themselves do not have to take place, and likewise any event which depends on those acts. The whole redemptive
and consummating work of the Trinity depends on the incarnation of the Son and the outpouring of the Spirit, and so is contingent as a whole. Creation too, it is often
argued, depends on the Trinity's resolve that the Son be incarnate and the Spirit be outpoured, but in any case liturgy and scripture give adequate witness to creation's
contingency. The totality of the temporal works of the Trinity — or more precisely, of all divine acts whose description includes reference to actual creatures — are
therefore contingent.

The identity of a person x, to recall our earlier formulation, is made up of whatever must be true of some person in order for him to be x — in order, we might
roughly say, for a person to be himself, and not someone or something else. If the sending of the Son and the Spirit, or more broadly any divine work of creation,
redemption, or consummation, belongs to the identity of any of the divine persons, then those persons cannot fail to engage in that action and still be themselves. In that
case there would be two possibilities. (1) The missions or other temporal actions would not be contingent, and so would not be free and would not be gifts. Just
because they are Father, Son, and Spirit, the divine persons could not help undertaking these actions; they would have to create, redeem, and consummate the world
lest they cease to be themselves and become some other persons. (2) The personal identities of Father, Son, and Spirit would be as contingent as the temporal acts
they undertake. Some divine persons with other identities would become Father, Son, and Spirit by creating, redeeming, and consummating the world. These seem
like equally unacceptable outcomes. They alike fall afoul of the liturgical and scriptural conviction that on Easter and Pentecost Father, Son, and Spirit give themselves
to us in their personal uniqueness, even though they — these same persons — did not have to make us at all, let alone give themselves to us without reserve.

The point is not that free acts (or more likely patterns of free acts) can never be identity­constituting for persons. At least when it comes to created persons, it is
plausible (if controversial) to say that who a person is — her very identity — depends upon her actions and reactions in particular settings. The personal identities of
created agents may, in other words, plausibly be regarded as contingent. But whatever may be the case with created persons, it seems impossible that the identities of
the divine persons could be contingent. Christian liturgy and scripture variously

EBSCOhost - printed on 1/10/2024 5:46 PM via NATIONAL LIBRARY OF KOREA. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
Page 263

embody the belief that the Father, the Son, and the Spirit who freely allow us to become acquainted with them in time also freely create the total situation in which they
graciously give themselves to us. That this creative act is free implies that these same agents might not have made this — or any — world at all. Each would be the
person he is, the person with whom we are allowed to become acquainted in time, even if there were no creatures — nothing besides these three divine persons. So
whatever features of the divine persons constitute the identity of each, the possession of these features by each cannot be contingent on any act which involves
creatures.29 In traditional terms: the Father would beget, the Son would be begotten, and the Holy Spirit would proceed just as they do even if there were no
creatures, and in these relations of origin the identities of the three consist (there is not, to be sure, universal agreement that precisely these three features do the job of
constituting personal identity in God).30 We may be able to take the creative, redeeming, and consummating actions of the Trinity as a basis for grasping the identities
of the divine persons, but we cannot take our grasp of their identities to consist in the knowledge of these actions.

Recent discussions of how to link up the divine persons with their actions toward us tend to insist on the principle that the "economic Trinity" and the "immanent Trinity"
are identical.31 The term "economic Trinity'' apparently refers to three divine persons who undertake the actual "economy" of salvation which scripture narrates; they
create, redeem, and consummate the world. The referent of "immanent Trinity"
29
The same result could be obtained simply by taking non­contingency as a basic feature of divine (as opposed to created) being; the task would then be to find a way of
distinguishing divine being from divine acts, since the latter are contingent.
30
The tradition has tended to distinguish between those features which are common (though differently appropriated) to the persons, those features which are unique to each (their
propria), and that sub­class of propria which are genuinely person­constituting for each (see, e.g., Aquinas's summary in Summa theologiae I, 32, 3, c). Identity­constituting features
have to be propria in the traditional sense, but not all propria can be identity­constituting, since they include features (like the Son's being incarnate and the Spirit's being poured out
on all flesh) which, as the results of contingent acts, cannot belong to the identities of the persons who possess them. Any proprium can, by contrast, be a feature by which we pick
out or identify its possessor. Whether there is anything to be made of the distraction between propria which are identity­constituting and those which are person­constituting we can
leave aside for present purposes.
31
Here too Rahner has been especially influential; see "Der dreifaltige Gott," especially pp. 327–9, 382–4 (ET, pp. 21–4, 99–103), also "Bemerkungen zum dogmatischen Traktat 'de
Trinitate'," Schriften zur Theologie (Einsiedeln: Benziger Verlag, 1954–84), vol. IV, pp. 115ff. (ET, pp. 87ff.). Whether or not they take it from Rahner, however, most extended treatments
of the Trinity in the last generation or so have accepted the principle he articulates, if often with qualifications. Basically the same thought, if not the formulation, predates Rahner.
Barth, for example, is emphatic about it; see Kirchliche Dogmatik I/1, pp. 352, 503 (ET, pp. 333, 479).

EBSCOhost - printed on 1/10/2024 5:46 PM via NATIONAL LIBRARY OF KOREA. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
Page 264
32
is more elusive. In Rahner's formulation, the term refers to three divine persons who are "in God, setting aside his free self­communication." Presumably no divine
persons actually exist apart or "aside" from the economy of salvation; the point seems rather to be that the "immanent Trinity" consists of three persons considered
"aside from'' any reference they may have to actual creatures — three divine persons as they would be even if there were no economy of salvation. The principle that
these two trinities are identical is thus the claim that the persons in one Trinity are the same as the persons in the other.

Much is often thought to hang on this principle, from whether belief in the Trinity has any relevance for Christian life and experience to whether it is possible for us to
know the persons of the Trinity at all. Depending on how one takes it, though, the principle seems either trivial or absurd. It might be taken to assert that the three
persons who make up the "economic" Trinity are the same persons as the three who make up the "immanent" Trinity, and conversely. Surely this is right, but it fails to
make a claim which anyone ever thought to deny. No one has maintained that there are six divine persons, three who act in the "economy" and, with personal identities
different from any of the economic agents, three others who do not. Taken this way, the principle simply seems like an awkward way of making a point upon which
trinitarian theology has pretty much uniformly insisted since the Nicene settlement: the identities of the three divine persons who freely give themselves to us in creation,
redemption, and consummation are the same as they would be even if the three had not decided to create and give themselves to us. If this is its sense, the principle
turns out to eliminate the possibility that any features the persons of the Trinity have because they undertake the economy of salvation (such as the Son's being human,
or the Spirit's being poured out) can belong to their identities; this would contradict the claim that the persons who act in the economy are the same three as they
would be "aside" from it.

The tone in which the principle is often put forth indicates, however, that it is not intended to be taken as trivial. Asserting the identity of the economic and the
immanent Trinity is supposed to correct a profound error which has long crippled trinitarian theology (at least in its "Western" versions), perhaps as far back as
Augustine. This suggests that the principle be taken differently. Not only do the same persons make up
32
"Der dreifaltige Gott," p. 383 (ET, p. 101).

EBSCOhost - printed on 1/10/2024 5:46 PM via NATIONAL LIBRARY OF KOREA. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
Page 265

both the economic and the immanent Trinity, but their features or characteristics are the same in both cases: being incarnate belongs to the Son immanently as well as
economically, being poured out on all flesh belongs to the Spirit immanently as well as economically, and so forth. Taken this way, the principle asserts that the divine
persons have the same features because they enact the economy of salvation as they would have had if there had been no economy of salvation for them to have these
features in. If this is its sense, the principle is not just false, but self­contradictory.33

The persons of the Trinity, it seems, bring it about that we have true beliefs sufficient to grasp their identities, and not only their actions toward us. At the same time, we
apparently cannot reduce the contents of true beliefs about the identities of the divine persons to the contents of true beliefs about their actions.

Correspondence

Under theological discipline the concept of truth has to include the action, ascribed chiefly to the risen Jesus, by which the triune God enables us to have true beliefs
about him. Reflection on the outcome the Trinity apparently intends by this truth­bestowing act indicates a second basic way in which the notion of what truth is —
precisely for sentences and beliefs — needs theological expansion.

Jesus' resurrection — the act in which the Father freely initiates and
33
That the "economic" features of the persons also somehow belong to them "immanently" is sometimes thought necessary in order to avoid the thought that the Son's cross and
the Spirit's outpouring fail to convey to us what God is really like. It might seem, for example, that Barth's doctrine of election requires this doubtful trinitarian claim. Barth insists
that God's decision to be the particular human being Jesus, and therewith to live in covenant love with human beings, is an act by which God has primally "determined himself, so
that this determination now belongs to him as much as everything which he is in and for himself'' (Kirchliche Dogmatik II/2, p. 6 [ET, p. 7]); this decision therefore precedes and
controls God's resolve to create a world and rescue it from sin. That this primal decision is contingent (and Barth, at least, seems to think it is: "it is not as though this relationship
were necessary for God," II/2, p. 4 [ET, p. 6]) means, however, that it is not identity­constituting for Father, Son, or Spirit, and so cannot be an "immanent" feature of any of them.
This is not to say, however, that the decision, once made, is somehow less true of God than "everything which he is in and for himself," nor that it might be revoked or
superseded, nor that its enactment fails to give access to the non­contingent identities of the three persons who undertake it. Even less does the standard medieval view (see
chapter 5, note 8) that the acts which result in the possession by the divine persons of "economic" features are eternal, while the features themselves are temporal, require the
claim that "economic" features are also "immanent." This view is compatible both with the contingency of the possession of "economic" features by the three persons and with
various ways of thinking about the sequence of divine decisions (e.g., with the view that God's decision to be incarnate is in fact contingent upon human sin).

EBSCOhost - printed on 1/10/2024 5:46 PM via NATIONAL LIBRARY OF KOREA. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
Page 266

sustains by his Spirit the self­presentation of the crucified Jesus to the world for the life of the world — affects creation radically. The New Testament describes the
effect of Jesus' rising on the world, and on human beings in particular, in terms of a distinctive relation between the risen Jesus and human beings affected by his
resurrection: we will be his icons. Even as we have borne the image " to the risen Christ (Rom. 8:29; cf. Phil. 3:21).

This conforming of human beings to the crucified and risen Christ is a unitary action of the whole Trinity, and indeed seems to realize the most interior and primal
purposes of the triune God. The Father has eternally and effectively willed — predestined — our conformity to his Son (cf. Rom. 8:29; Eph. 1:5), who, by accepting
incarnation and the death from which the Father raises him, constitutes that original form of which we are the intended images. The Spirit is the agent who, poured out
from the Father by the risen Son and dwelling in us, immediately joins us to Christ and makes us his icons (see Rom. 8:9–11, 14). The New Testament of course talks
about the outcome of Jesus' resurrection in many other ways, but the notion of "bearing the image of the man of heaven" seems to express both the final aim and the
original intention not only of the resurrection, but of the totality of divine acts involving creatures. While for now we are icons of the risen Christ in fragmentary and
partial ways, in the end the Spirit will enable us to see him as he is, and so be as much like God as it is possible for creatures to be (see I Jn. 3:2). With the perfection
of this work of the Spirit will coincide the liberation of all creation; no further divine aim for creation will remain to be realized (see Rom. 8:22–3). The notion that we
will be Jesus' icons thus seems as basic as any description of the outcome of his raising.

Though conformity to the risen Jesus in heart, mind, and will preserves the distinction between the particular person Jesus and those persons who are conformed to
him, it nonetheless involves a sharing by others in his own affections, thoughts, and desires. Being a bearer of Christ's image is therefore a cognitively dependent
relation. Having affections, thoughts, and desires which succeed in making us like

EBSCOhost - printed on 1/10/2024 5:46 PM via NATIONAL LIBRARY OF KOREA. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
Page 267

another person requires having a range of true beliefs — in this case not only the belief that Jesus is risen, but countless others about the way his action and passion
embody the purposes of the triune God, about what counts as virtuous action and affection, about how we should treat our neighbors, and so forth. To be sure, the
belief­dependence of this relation may not be permanent. At the last, when we have become Christ's icons in a fully unsurpassable way, our cognitively dependent
likeness to him may be able to do without true beliefs and the sentences which express them (''we shall see him as he is").34 At least in this life, though, being Christ's
icon apparently depends on having some true beliefs. Their truth, like that of any belief which a particular relation to the persons of the Trinity may require, depends on
the action by which these persons together bring it about that we have true beliefs.

The act by which we come to have true beliefs concerning the divine persons is therefore apparently not an end in itself, but serves the Trinity's purpose of making us
bearers of Christ's image. This is the intended term or goal of the act, and as such a feature or component of the act itself. Given the unrestricted freedom shared by
the divine agents, this outcome cannot fail to be present where the act occurs. And since the act itself belongs to what truth is for this belief, so does its term. That
believers bear the image of the risen Christ itself belongs to the concept of truth for whatever beliefs this relation requires, and similarly for the sentences which express
those beliefs.

But bearing the image of another is obviously a relation of correspondence. Between those who bear Christ's image and him whose image they bear obtains a complex
likeness or similarity (indeed a participatory likeness), that is, a correspondence. While "mysterious" in the standard theological sense — its richness is ever greater
than our fullest apprehension of it — the relation to the risen Jesus by which we become his icons is not, in contrast to the notion that the truth of a sentence consists in
its correspondence to reality, "mysterious" in the pejorative philosophical sense: conceptually empty or hopelessly puzzling. It is a relation among persons, in which one
person joins numerous others to himself by faith, hope, and love, and in that way makes them like himself in mind, heart, and will. It is thus a relation of subject to term
in which the subject can, in an unpuzzling sense, be like — correspond to — the term.
34
As Luther, for example, suggests: "In the future life believing will cease . . . When faith ceases the brilliant light (claritas) of glory will follow, in which we will see God just as he
is" (WA 40/I, 428, 29–429, 13).

EBSCOhost - printed on 1/10/2024 5:46 PM via NATIONAL LIBRARY OF KOREA. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
Page 268

This correspondence belongs to the concept of truth for at least some sentences and beliefs (we will see momentarily whether it may be extended to all true sentences
and beliefs). It is not that the sentences or beliefs correspond to anything. But when assented to as the term of the threefold truth­conferring action of the Trinity, they
are an indispensable means by which a definite relation of correspondence comes about, and this is part of what it is for them to be true. In the correspondence of
person to person by which the Trinity makes us Christ's icons one may hear an echo of the ancient idea that truth is the correspondence of mind to reality, though here
it is the whole self, and not just the intellect, which shares in the relevant conformity. In this sense the created persons affected by the truth­bestowing action of the
Trinity may themselves be seen as truth bearers. As whole selves, they can become "true" when the action by which the triune God enables them to have the relevant
true beliefs brings about their conformity to the risen Christ.35

This need not, I think, fall afoul of our earlier scruples about correspondence. On Davidson's account T­sentences give us the basis of an adequate grip on what it is
for each sentence (on the left) to be true; "correspondence" adds nothing to the understanding of "is true" we already have for sentences. In effect the foregoing
argument reverses, on trinitarian grounds, this sequence of inference, at least for some sentences. An account of "is true" for these sentences has to include a distinctive
way in which persons are "true,'' namely by sharing in a philosophically unmysterious relationship of correspondence to one person in particular. Truth for these
sentences must consist at least in part in their having a share in constituting this relationship; therefore T­
35
On this see Anselm's De Veritate, which also links in an ordered way different aspects of the concept of truth with different bearers. The rectitudo of each bearer unifies the
elements which make up the concept of truth. A truth bearer has rectitudo when it "does what it ought" (De Ver. 2, p. 179, 2). Divine purpose determines what each truth bearer
ought to do (see De Ver. 3, p. 180, 12–13, 15). Each ought to do something different, but there are relations of dependence among truth bearers, and with that among aspects of the
concept of truth. Thus the truth of utterances (enuntiationes) depends, in a fashion not far removed from Tarski's ("to signify that what is, is," De Ver. 2, p. 178, 22–3), on what
Anselm calls "the truth of the essence of things," which in turn depends on the summa veritas ("There is truth in the essence of all things which are, because they are in essence
what they are in the highest truth," De Ver. 7, p. 185, 18–19), as does the truth ascribed to all other bearers (see De Ver. 10, p. 190, 1–12). The summa veritas is Jesus Christ himself
(De Ver. 4, p. 180, 21–2: "veritas ipsa"; see Monologion 46, p. 62, 22–6), and not only the divine nature (see Monologion 18, p. 33, 22–3). References are to F. S. Schmitt, ed., S.
Anselmi Opera Omnia, vol. I. For a theologically provocative analysis of Anselm's treatise, see Michel Corbin, "L'événement de Vérité," L'inouï de Dieu (Paris: Desclée de
Brouwer, 1980), pp. 59–107.

EBSCOhost - printed on 1/10/2024 5:46 PM via NATIONAL LIBRARY OF KOREA. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
Page 269

sentences cannot by themselves give an adequate grip on what it is for these sentences to be true. But at no point have we suggested that by understanding truth for
sentences as some sort of correspondence, we understand how persons can correspond to (bear the image of) the risen Christ; rather the reverse. Thus while there
are good theological reasons for thinking precisely of truth as involving a certain kind of correspondence, in abstraction from Christian belief there may be no need —
and perhaps no coherent way — to do this.

The Spirit creates, moreover, a twofold conformity or correspondence: not only of us to Christ, but also of us, in and with Christ, to the Father. As we have already
observed in another connection, Jesus Christ crucified and risen (not only the eternal Logos, but precisely that Logos become our flesh) is himself "the icon of the
unseen God" (Col. 1:15; cf. 1:20). He is the "exact imprint" or representation (Heb. 1:3: ) of the Father, other than the Father yet completely expressive of
the Father's total reality, and as such perfectly conformed to him. Consequently we cannot be bearers of Christ's image without sharing in his own correspondence to
the Father, and so bearing, like him if imperfectly, the imprint of the Father himself.36

Since Jesus is presumably the Father's fully adequate image because of the unique way in which he comes forth from the Father — as the Father's only "Son,'' who as
such fully possesses the Father's divinity — the New Testament also expresses the correspondence to the Father which we gain through Jesus by speaking of us as the
Father's adopted children. Conformed to the Son by the indwelling Spirit's love, we share Jesus' own sonship, his own complete likeness to the Father; we become by
adoption what he is by nature (cf. Rom. 8:15–17, 29; Gal. 4:4–7). In this way the Spirit gives us a share — as much as we creatures can take — in God's own life.
By acquiring (in Thomas's phrase) a "participated likeness" of features unique to Jesus Christ (as the Father's only­begotten Son and perfect image), we not only share
in those characteristics which the three have in common (see II Pet. 1:4), but take up a particular place in the non­contingent pattern of their personal relations to one
another. We share, that is, in the very features which at once distinguish the Son
36
This was noticed early on. Thus Ignatius of Antioch: "In love, the faithful bear the imprint ( ) of God the Father through Jesus Christ" (Magnesians 5:2). Ignace
d'Antioche et Polycarpe de Smyrne, Lettres (Sources Chrétiennes 10), ed. P. Th. Camelot (4th edn, Paris: Cerf, 1969), p. 82.

EBSCOhost - printed on 1/10/2024 5:46 PM via NATIONAL LIBRARY OF KOREA. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
Page 270
37
from, and unite him to, the Father and the Spirit, and so constitute his identity.

Conformity to the Father, and not only to Jesus Christ himself, apparently belongs to what truth is, at least for beliefs concerning the Trinity. Granting to creatures a
participated likeness in the incarnate Son's correspondence to the Father seems to be the final goal of the act by which the Trinity brings it about that we have true
beliefs. There the matter ends: as the unoriginate origin of all things, the Father can have an image, but he is himself in no way the image of any other. He can be
corresponded to — above all by his incarnate Son Jesus, in a conformity of one person to another than which a greater cannot be conceived — but he himself
corresponds to nothing.

The correspondence to the Father at which the triune God aims by granting us true beliefs about himself is available to us only as a participated likeness of the
incarnate Word's own perfect conformity to the Father. Insofar as correspondence is an element in what truth is for our sentences and beliefs, it therefore seems that
the most basic form of correspondence belongs not to us, but to Jesus himself. Our conformity to him and (in him) to the Father both depend upon his own perfect
likeness to
37
To show that being the Father's Son (non­contingently the recipient and full possessor of his nature) and thereby his image are genuinely constitutive of Jesus' identity as
rendered in the Gospels would require an extended argument for which there is not room here. The argument would proceed by linking the uniquely divine actions Jesus performs,
the mission from the Father in virtue of which he performs them, and the identity­constituting relation of origin to the Father which this mission assumes. It would have to address
the conceptual problems posed by (1) the need to show that the Spirit, even though he is the full possessor of the Father's nature, is neither Son nor image, and by (2) the
seemingly paradoxical result that being the Father's Son and image is identity­constituting for Jesus, but being Jesus is contingent, and therefore not identity­constituting, for the
Son.
For present purposes we may simply observe that Jesus' capacity to impart to us the Father's likeness depends upon his own fully adequate possession of it, and his possession of it
depends upon the relation of origin by which he receives the Father's entire divinity. That the Son terminates this relation of origin cannot, in classic accounts of "adoptive sonship,"
be a feature which he has contingently, and so is identity­ (indeed person­) constituting for him. As we have briefly outlined, for Aquinas the Father freely grants us a "participated
likeness" (participata similitudo) in Christ's own ''natural" relation to himself (Summa theologiae III, 23, 4, C), assimilating us to "the eternal Word precisely in his unity with the
Father," that is, to the non­contingent and identity­constituting filiatio of the incarnate Son (III, 23, 3, c). One may find this thought in perhaps unexpected places, as when Karl Barth
describes unio cum Christo as the goal of God's call to Christian faith and discipleship. "Granted all their difference from one another," the bond of the Christian with Christ "is
accomplished and consists in a complete self­giving (Hingabe) from both sides," from which issues "a single whole, one reality, an internally differentiated and animated, but pure,
solid, unity." Therefore "when [Christians] are in Christ, they have and receive an immediate share precisely in that which, because in the first place and above all God is in him . . . is
shown and given to them by God" (Barth's emphasis). Kirchliche Dogmatik IV/3, pp. 621, 627 (ET, pp. 540, 546).

EBSCOhost - printed on 1/10/2024 5:46 PM via NATIONAL LIBRARY OF KOREA. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
Page 271

the Father. So if our sentences and beliefs cannot be true without yielding our own correspondence to the Father, then their truth depends upon Jesus being the
Father's Son and (as such) his perfect image. The truth which Jesus brings about with respect to us depends, in other words, on Jesus' unique relation to the Father,
and not only on his leading role in the truth­bestowing action of the Trinity toward us. As the incarnate Word or image Jesus Christ is, as the medievals liked to say,
the veritas Patris, "the truth of the Father."38 To the extent that shared actions belong (and so are ascribed or "appropriated") differently to each of the divine persons
on account of characteristics unique to each, the Son's perfect correspondence to the Father seems to be the basis for taking the divine act of granting us true beliefs
as belonging chiefly, though of course not solely, to the Son.

If correspondence to the Father is itself identity­constituting and non­contingent for the Son, then "truth'' belongs, in a sense, to God's own identity, in the form of the
Word's perfect correspondence to the Father whose total reality he expresses. The Son would then correspond to the Father — would be "the truth of the Father" —
even if he were not incarnate, and there were no world for him to be incarnate in. His identity­constituting relation to the Father would thus be basic to the truth of all
possible true beliefs, even if there were no actual beliefs to be true. We have elsewhere suggested that the Son is the Father's way of uttering or expressing the whole
Trinity, and not only himself.39 The Son can have this role because of his distinctive place, as Word and image, in the pattern of personal relations constitutive of the
identities of the divine persons — because, in other words, of his perfect correspondence to the Father. In that the Son cannot fail to be the Father's Word and image,
there cannot fail to be an utterance (in an extended sense, to be sure) whose truth depends on the Son's perfect correspondence to the Father: the Father's utterance
of the whole Trinity to himself, the Spirit, and also the Son. On account of the Son's correspondence to the Father, there would in a sense be truth, even if there were
no world, no sentences, and no beliefs.
38
See Anselm, Monologion 46 (Schmitt, vol. I, p. 62, 22–6): "The Son may most suitably be called the truth of the Father, not only in the sense that his truth is the same as the
Father's . . . but also in the sense that we find in him not some imperfect imitation, but the complete truth of the Father's substance, since he is nothing other than what the Father
is." The phrase shows up early in Lombard's Sententiae (Book I, Dist. 3); see the comment by Bonaventure, In I Sent. 3, 1, Dubium 4 (Opera Selecta, vol. I, pp. 57b–58a); see also
Aquinas, In I Cor. 2, 2(no. 100).
39
See Chapter 5, note 24.

EBSCOhost - printed on 1/10/2024 5:46 PM via NATIONAL LIBRARY OF KOREA. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
Page 272

Beliefs about Creatures

If Jesus Christ is "the truth," then we should expect the truth­bestowing action of the triune God to unify all true beliefs, and not simply those about the Trinity. We are
looking for a single, theologically adequate concept of truth for all true beliefs. It may seem as though the argument so far inevitably limits a trinitarian account of what
truth is to sentences about the divine persons, their attributes, and their actions. Our point of entry for the thought that there is more to the concept of truth than Tarski
and Davidson suppose was the observation that the persons of the Trinity are not at our disposal. That Jesus is risen — that this crucified Jew lives, presently available
to the world — is wholly at the disposal of the Trinity; the truth of the belief that he is risen cannot therefore be automatic. That grass is green is, by contrast, not at all
at the disposal of grass. This might lead one to suppose that the truth conditions Tarski provides adequately capture what it is for "Grass is green" to be true, and that
the truth of the belief that grass is green may safely be taken for automatic.

Of course our account of truth has already implicated countless sentences which contain no terms referring to the triune God or his actions, since the cognitively
dependent relation to the Trinity which we acquire by "bearing the image of the man of heaven" demands myriad beliefs about ourselves, the sort of life we ought to
lead, the future of the world, and so forth. It seems unlikely, though, that the truth­bestowing action of the Trinity extends to sentences like "Grass is green'' by making
anyone who holds this sentence true an eschatological bearer of the risen Christ's image. In that case anyone who had a true belief would be a bearer of Christ's
image, regardless of what the belief was. A cognitively dependent relation requires, however, some beliefs specifically about who or what the believer is related to.
When it comes to beliefs about creatures, we need to account for the truth­bestowing role of the Trinity in some other way.

Everything corresponds to the Father in some fashion, however distant and remote. He is the unoriginate source of all things, and even the humblest creature is like him
in some respect. In contrast with the perfect likeness of himself whom the Father eternally generates, those things the Father freely creates by way of the Son resemble
him (whether individually or collectively) in more or less partial and incomplete ways. Part of this contrast between the perfect likeness of the Son to the Father and the
limited likeness of creatures is that creatures resemble the Father only by resembling his image, who is as such the exemplar of all creation. The Father creates by
giving all things a greater or lesser share not only in

EBSCOhost - printed on 1/10/2024 5:46 PM via NATIONAL LIBRARY OF KOREA. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
Page 273

the Son's likeness to him, but also in the love which they have for one another through their Spirit. In all creatures there lies at least a trace, a vestigium, of the Trinity,
such that they both resemble and desire the Father. Not only human beings, but all creatures, are ordered toward a share in the risen Christ's correspondence to the
Father, if not precisely to being personal bearers of his image. The Spirit is conforming everything to the crucified and risen Christ, in and for whom all things were
made and in whom all things hold together (see Col. 1:16–17); he is giving everything a more or less intimate share, depending on the kind of thing it is to be, in
Christ's perfect likeness to the Father.

This suggests, however, that all truth conditions — the truth conditions for all sentences and beliefs — are wholly at the disposal of the Trinity. That Jesus' self­
presentation is completely at the disposal of the Trinity may seem relatively obvious, because there the presented is also a presenter, and shares fully in the act of
presentation. The "arrangement of the world" that grass is green does not display its presenter, or that there is an act of presentation in the first place, quite so clearly.
Yet that grass is green is as much presented to the world by the triune God as that Jesus is risen. The Father as much sees to it that the truth conditions for "Grass is
green" are met as that those for ''Jesus is risen" are met. As Jesus Christ presents the truth conditions for the belief that he is risen to the world, in order that this belief
may actually be true, so also he presents to the world all the truth conditions which the triune God wants to see met, and in this way brings about the truth of every true
belief. And as the Spirit creates the conviction that "Jesus is risen" is true, so the Spirit may also be credited with creating the conviction that grass is green; any holding
true of a true sentence, he brings about.

Moreover, "Grass is green" will be true not just if and only if grass is green, but also if green grass (more precisely: that grass is green) is a created trace, however
remote, of the unoriginate Father. It will be like the Father, however, only if it can count as a vestige of the crucified and risen Son, in whom, as the exemplar of
creation, all things hold together. The same goes for every sentence whose truth conditions the triune God contingently wills to meet, and for the beliefs expressed by
these sentences.40 For a sentence about creatures to be true, the "arrangement of
40
Problems arise, to be sure, with regard to sentences (e.g., in mathematics or logic) whose truth is not evidently contingent. Whether the truth conditions for such sentences can
plausibly be regarded as in some way at God's disposal depends on a number of considerations (such as whether the analytic/synthetic distinction holds up) which we lack the
space to pursue here.

EBSCOhost - printed on 1/10/2024 5:46 PM via NATIONAL LIBRARY OF KOREA. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
Page 274

the world" which would make it true, as specified by Tarski­style truth conditions, has to be at least a vestige of the Son's correspondence to the Father. In this way
"the firstborn from the dead" (Col. 1:18) is the truth — the veritas Patris not just for some, but for all sentences whose truth conditions he wills, together with the
Father and the Spirit, to present to the world.

This trinitarian account of truth conditions cannot, however, be applied to all sentences in quite the same way. Some sentences, like "Florensky was murdered in the
Gulag," are obviously true, but the "arrangement of the world" which makes them true is not in any way an image or vestige of the Trinity.41 Because there is evil in the
world traceable to the doings of created free agents, there will be some actual states of affairs which correspond to nothing in God, arrangements of the world for
which there is nothing in God of which they are the likeness, even remotely. The truth conditions for sentences about persons who suffer or do voluntary evil, events
which are the outcome of voluntarily evil acts, and so forth, will remain at the disposal of the Trinity, granted genuine divine sovereignty over evil (an assumption
which, to be sure, creates significant conceptual problems). But any evil state of affairs is not one which God actually wills to be. Sentences for which such states of
affairs constitute truth conditions are not, therefore, sentences whose truth conditions the triune God wills to meet, nor are they sentences whose truth conditions the
risen Jesus presents to the world. In these cases, while the sentences are true, there is no divine truth­bestowing act.

For this reason there will be some sentences for which a Tarski­Davidson account of truth is indeed adequate, and needs — indeed admits of — no trinitarian
extension. "Florensky was murdered in the Gulag' is true if and only if Florensky was murdered in the Gulag; there is nothing further — in particular, nothing about
God — to be said about the way "is true'' works for this sentence (though there is much more to be said because the sentence is true). Though informative
generalization is a bit difficult here (recall our reservations at the end of chapter 8 regarding the notion of what sentences are "about" or "describe"), we can perhaps
state that a Tarski­Davidson account of "is true" will be adequate for those sentences, but only those, whose Tarski­style truth conditions one can say are, or are the
result of, voluntary evil. That Florensky
41
On the fate of the great Russian theologian and scientist, see Sieglinde and Fritz Mierau, eds., An den Wasserscheiden des Denkens: Ein Pawel Florenski Lesebuch (Berlin:
Kontext Verlag, 1991), p. 258.

EBSCOhost - printed on 1/10/2024 5:46 PM via NATIONAL LIBRARY OF KOREA. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
Page 275

was murdered in the Gulag locates the truth conditions for "Florensky was murdered in the Gulag," and that Florensky was murdered in the Gulag is, one can surely
say, evil. It is precisely not the triune God who sees to it that the truth conditions for sentences which follow this pattern are met. With regard to these sentences, a
trinitarian account of what truth is does not want to say anything more than the Tarski­Davidson approach already does.42 This does not, I think, signal a weakness in
the account; rather it signals that there are some sentences to which we should not expect the account to apply in full.

Trinity, Justified Belief, and Truth

Our final task is to spell out the connection between truth and belief. We have developed a theological account of how to decide which beliefs are true, and we have
just outlined a theological account of what truth is. It remains to make their coherent relation explicit — to say what holds together truth, justified belief, and the
willingness to believe, or, if you like, keeps them from coming apart in the first place.

One way to see the issue clearly is to recall the ancient problem of skepticism. The skeptic worries that his beliefs, or those of human beings generally, might be largely
or wholly false. The skeptic's problem has not to do with the justification of beliefs, or even with willingness to believe, but with the link of belief to truth. He worries
that precisely those beliefs he is justified in holding and willing to hold might turn out to be false, and sees no good grounds for supposing that in deciding what to
believe, we have thereby decided what is true.

Foundationalism is of course designed to overcome skepticism, by giving access to beliefs which cannot turn out to be false, and which can be recognized as such.
Previous reflection has suggested that skepticism, especially when it comes to beliefs about a mind­independent
42
The history behind this thought is long, and cannot be analyzed here. By way of example, Aquinas argues that "things" (states of affairs, let us say) can be "false'' when there is
no original in the triune God to which, in some manner, they conform. This happens when free agents "withdraw themselves from the ordering of things in the divine intellect; in
this consists the evil of guilt" (Summa theologiae I, 17, 1, c. See 18, 4, ad 4: "Evil things are in God's knowledge . . . but not in the sense that they are created by God or conserved
by him, nor in the sense that they have a likeness [rationem] in God; rather they are known by God through the likenesses of good things"; on the latter see 14, 10). But of course
the fact that there is nothing in God to which this withdrawal — this "falsity" — corresponds does not make sentences describing the agents who engage in it false (see I, 16, 2;
17, 3). For an analysis of Thomas's texts, see Bernard Lonergan, Grace and Freedom (London: Darton, Longman and Todd, 1971), pp. 111–15.

EBSCOhost - printed on 1/10/2024 5:46 PM via NATIONAL LIBRARY OF KOREA. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
Page 276

spatio­temporal world, actually depends on foundationalism in order to create the conceptual space in which it can arise in the first place. Should foundationalism be
necessary for skepticism, then cutting the foundationalist ground out from under the skeptic (in the Davidsonian fashion outlined in chapter 4, for example) renders
senseless his worry that his beliefs might be largely or wholly false; it deprives him of an idiom he needs to state his worry in the first place. But surely this leaves the
job at best half done. Once we have gotten rid of the foundationalist idiom, the question still remains as to how even the most determined skeptic cannot help getting it
right most of the time, how it is that his beliefs have to turn out true for the most part.

It is sometimes argued that we need not and perhaps cannot answer this question, and may safely content ourselves with showing that the skeptic's worry is baseless.
Absent some positive account of what links belief and truth, however, even the most convincing narrative of foundationalism's collapse will perhaps only prompt the
suspicion that skepticism has other plausible sources.

In particular, it may seem that skepticism depends on realism about truth, and that realism can create the conceptual space for skepticism even in the absence of a
foundationalist epistemology. Realism ordinarily includes a correspondence theory of truth, but even where it does not, the realist is apparently committed to the
bivalence thesis — the view that every meaningful sentence is determinately either true or false. Bivalence in turn seems to require that truth cannot be an epistemic
notion: if bivalence holds, then a meaningful sentence is determinately either true or false regardless of whether we have any way of finding out what its truth value is,
and regardless of whether we have any good reasons for holding it true or false.

We have avoided the label "realist" for views which reject the correspondence theory, even when they also deny that truth is epistemic (including those of Frege,
Davidson, and Fine). Accepting even this much of realism, though, may seem to permit belief to become parted from truth. To say that truth is not epistemic is to say
that with regard to any particular belief, truth, so to speak, outruns justification. On a view where truth is not epistemic and justification is not foundationalist (including
the one developed here), the truth conditions for a belief (as located by the right branch of a T­sentence) fail to be identical with what gives us the right to hold the
belief (namely some other beliefs that we hold). And this inherently leaves open the possibility that even a belief

EBSCOhost - printed on 1/10/2024 5:46 PM via NATIONAL LIBRARY OF KOREA. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
Page 277

which we have very good reasons to hold true might in fact be false. So, the skeptic wants to know, what keeps this from happening all the time? What, in other
words, keeps truth from being inaccessible, not just in particular cases, but on the whole? At this point we may, of course, be tempted to block truth's inaccessibility
by suggesting that truth is epistemic after all. But if, as we have argued, this suggestion makes the cure seem worse than the disease, we need an account of truth's
accessibility which does not force truth to go epistemic.

One such account is Davidson's. He proposes that we treat meaning as the tie which, on the whole, binds belief to truth. Meaning, as it were, makes truth accessible to
belief, by requiring that belief be "intrinsically veridical."43 Davidson's suggestion has given rise to controversy. Even if his argument holds its own against standard
criticisms, however, it will be of little use to us here. Since we have found theological grounds for supposing that Davidson's notion of truth is incomplete, we cannot
help ourselves to it when the time comes to connect truth with justified belief. Though the argument of this chapter still allows us to agree with Davidson that the
sentences people hold true can only mean what they do if their truth conditions are generally met, truth under theological discipline cannot on the whole be made
accessible to belief by way of meaning. With the exceptions (having to do with evil) which we have recently discussed, the truth of beliefs cannot be automatic — it
cannot consist only in the truth conditions of the beliefs (or the sentences which express them) being met. For the most part the truth of beliefs requires the truth­
bestowing act of the triune God, and in particular the free presentation of their truth conditions by the risen Christ. Davidson's aim is to show that our beliefs are mostly
true when we take them to be. We need a reason for saying this — for supposing that justified beliefs are generally veridical — which squares with the theologically
disciplined notion of truth at which we have arrived.

The chief standard for justified beliefs, we have argued, is that they at least be consistent with the narratives which identify Jesus and the triune God. These
epistemically primary beliefs cannot, of course, serve as reasons for holding most beliefs, since reasons need to be in the logical neighborhood of the beliefs they
support. To say that beliefs are generally true when we take them to be — when we regard them as justified — is therefore to say that beliefs which are at least
consistent with
43
See chapter 8, p. 237.

EBSCOhost - printed on 1/10/2024 5:46 PM via NATIONAL LIBRARY OF KOREA. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
Page 278

the identification of Jesus and the triune God, and which we otherwise have reason to hold true (which largely fit with the rest of our beliefs), for the most part actually
are true.

According to our theologically disciplined notion of truth, beliefs justified according to these standards will generally be true just in case the triune God — and
especially, in his distinctive way, the risen Christ — undertakes his truth­bestowing act (1) with regard to belief in the narratives which identify him, (2) with regard to
no belief inconsistent with these narratives, and (3) with regard to beliefs which there is otherwise good reason to hold. Truth will be accessible to belief if we can
count on the triune God to do just this — if, when it comes to our own beliefs, his truth­bestowing act is not for the most part inaccessible to us. Presumably God
bestows truth on no false beliefs, since true beliefs are all and only those to which he has granted truth.44 But we need not always be able to tell which beliefs God
makes true; it suffices that we can tell for the most part, and especially with regard to those beliefs which are epistemically primary. There need be no guarantee that a
justified belief is true (there hardly could be, since in some cases people are justified in holding incompatible beliefs), only that justified beliefs are true on the whole.

Which beliefs get their truth conditions met is chiefly up to the Father, with the Spirit as his immediate agent. The Christian community's epistemic priorities cannot be
the right ones, and nor can they rightly be taken as unrestricted, unless the Father sees to it that such beliefs as hold true the narratives identifying Jesus (and with him
the whole Trinity) unfailingly get their truth conditions met, and any beliefs incompatible with this narrative identification never get their truth conditions met. The Father
can be counted on to distribute truth conditions in just this way because, as we have observed, the narratively identified Jesus is his own image become our flesh, the
one who perfectly expresses the Father's own reality. Around him the Father orders all things, and so determines which beliefs will have their truth conditions fulfilled.
The Father cannot, indeed, fail to order all things around his own uniquely adequate
44
Beliefs pertaining to evil are again in part an exception, since there is no divine truth­bestowing act in their case (though if the beliefs are true, actually holding them depends on
the Spirit; see below). But since no belief can be justified which fails to hang together with most of the rest of what we believe, beliefs pertaining to evil cannot themselves be true
unless most of the rest of what we believe, which does not pertain to evil, is also true. In this way the truth of beliefs pertaining to evil depends upon the triune God's truth­
bestowing act, even though they do not themselves receive it.

EBSCOhost - printed on 1/10/2024 5:46 PM via NATIONAL LIBRARY OF KOREA. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
Page 279

icon. The Father's icon might not have been incarnate, but in any case that image (as Logos) fully expresses the Father's knowledge of himself, the whole Trinity, and
all things as the Father actually wills them to be, and he orders them according to this definitive knowledge. Just because he has Jesus Christ for his incarnate icon, the
Father can be counted on to do his part in seeing to it that the beliefs which the Christian community takes to be primary in the order of justification are actually true,
and that any belief which fails of consistency with them is false.

But the Son also needs to do his part. Truth will be accessible to belief only if the risen Jesus bestows truth on all the beliefs, and only the beliefs, whose truth
conditions the Father sees to it get met. In particular, the beliefs which are epistemically primary for the Christian community cannot be true, nor can their epistemic
primacy be unrestricted, unless the risen Jesus spontaneously but unfailingly presents truth conditions to the world as the Father has distributed them. This means
presenting to the world, and so making accessible to belief, the very truth conditions for the narratives which identify him and the Trinity which the Father himself
provides, and presenting truth conditions for no beliefs inconsistent with these narratives — no beliefs which the Father has declined to see get their truth conditions
met.

The Son can be counted on to do this just because he has the Father as the one to whom he perfectly corresponds. As the incarnate Son, Jesus perfectly corresponds
to the Father because the Father fully expresses himself in the person of the Son; expression and correspondence are here what the scholastics call relationes
oppositae, relations where being the subject of one necessarily goes together with being the term of the other. Though other than the Father, the incarnate Son fully
possesses everything the Father can give to another without ceasing to be himself. To him belongs, in the creedal formulation, the Father's own or essence,
everything (numerically, not just generically) which makes the Father God. As full possessor of the Father's own will and knowledge, but in the mode of recipient, not
of giver, the Son cannot fail to order truth­bestowal the way the Father orders truth conditions. Taken together, the actions of the Father and the Son ensure that the
beliefs which make up the Christian communitys' epistemic priorities are true, and any belief inconsistent with these priorities is false.

The actions of the Father and the Son settle which sentences and beliefs are true, and secure the basic connection between truth and

EBSCOhost - printed on 1/10/2024 5:46 PM via NATIONAL LIBRARY OF KOREA. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
Page 280

justified belief by ensuring that the church's epistemic priorities are correct. By itself, however, this does not guarantee that most of the beliefs we take to be true
actually are true. The Christian community's primary beliefs do not for the most part enable us to tell which sentences to hold true, since countless competing truth
claims are alike consistent with these beliefs. Granting the truth and unrestricted epistemic application of the church's central beliefs on trinitarian grounds still leaves
open the question why we should take most of the rest of what we believe to be true.

Here the action of the Spirit is decisive. The Spirit, as we have observed, brings about the conviction that the church's central beliefs are true, and teaches the
community's members to order the rest of their beliefs accordingly. But all true beliefs are the Spirit's work: the Spirit sees to the holding true of any sentences whose
truth conditions are met by the Father and presented to the world by the Son. The Spirit can be counted on to do this because he is, in the Johannine idiom, "the Spirit
of truth," the one who will lead first Jesus' own followers, but through their communal life the world, to grasp not just some truths, but "all the truth" (Jn. 16:13). As the
Spirit of the Father and the Son, he is sent by both to convince the church and the world of those beliefs the Father and the Son have, each in their own way, secured:
"he will take what is mine and declare it to you'' (Jn. 16:15).Just as Jesus Christ himself possesses all that belongs to the Father — the Father's own divinity — so also
the Spirit possesses all that belongs to the incarnate Son. He is thereby uniquely in a position to declare, and will declare only, those beliefs which the Father and the
Son have seen to it are true.45

This does not yet solve the problem at hand, since knowing that the Spirit brings us to hold all our true beliefs, and only our true beliefs, does not enable us to tell
which beliefs the Spirit brings us to hold. There is probably no way to tell this on a case­by­case basis, especially when we are
45
Dispute arises concerning the inner­trinitarian background of the Spirit's work, or more precisely concerning which identity­constituting features enable the Spirit to accomplish
his mission in the world — especially those features which bear on his relation to the Son. Jn. 16:13–15 has often been taken to imply, with particular stringency, the Filioque.
Taken this way it provides especially strong background for the Spirit's role in uniting truth and justified belief, but of course this inference is much contested. Similar results
might be obtained by conceiving the relevant background in terms of the Spirit's eternal coming forth from the Father to rest upon the Son (temporally manifested especially in
Jesus' baptism) or in terms of the Spirit's place as personal bond of love between Father and Son (which it might be possible to work out without assuming the Filioque).

EBSCOhost - printed on 1/10/2024 5:46 PM via NATIONAL LIBRARY OF KOREA. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
Page 281

at some distance in logical space from the Christian community's central convictions, and surely not on any large scale. But there is no need for one. Part of the Spirit's
business in leading us "into all the truth" is to make sure that we never stray too far from the truth — that for the most part our beliefs are true.

Ultimately, we recall, the triune God grants us true beliefs in order to give us a share in his own life. Countless beliefs about creatures are tied up with beliefs about the
triune God and his purposes in the world, and there is probably no clear or effective way to draw a line between those which are and those which are not. The Spirit
cannot, it therefore seems, lead us into the life of God without seeing to it that we hold mostly true beliefs, not only about God, but about everything else. Since we
hold beliefs at all only insofar as they fit with the rest of what we suppose to be true, this is to say that the Spirit guarantees that our beliefs are generally — though of
course not always — true when we take them to be. An account of truth, meaning, and belief like Davidson's might — now that the coincidence of true beliefs with
those whose truth conditions are met has been christologically secured — be taken to describe the mechanism by which the Spirit accomplishes this. So at least we
have argued here, but in the end we have trinitarian reasons for supposing that truth and justified belief will generally cohere, regardless of the created means by which
one supposes that this takes place.

Evidently the coherence of truth, justified belief, and willingness to believe finally depends upon the unity of the triune God. Were the Son and the Spirit not united to
the Father by full possession of the Father's own essence, received from him — the creedal homoousion — we would lack adequate grounds not only for upholding
the Christian community's central convictions, but for supposing that the beliefs we take to be true, generally are true. There is, to be sure, more to it than this. The
divine persons are united with one another, and live in one another, in more than one way — by will and not just by essence, in love as well as in being. In more than
one way each can thereby count on the other, and we can count on them all, to do his part in the act by which together they bring it about that we have true beliefs,
which we can recognize as such.

In what ways Father, Son, and Spirit may coherently be thought of as one God is a large topic, and one for another day. For now we may simply observe that when
our beliefs are true — as they usually are — we are led by the Spirit's grace, though perhaps without yet knowing it, to retrace the

EBSCOhost - printed on 1/10/2024 5:46 PM via NATIONAL LIBRARY OF KOREA. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
Page 282

pattern of relationships by which he and the Son are eternally united to the Father in being and love. When we get our epistemic priorities straight, we become
acquainted with the divine persons in the intimacy of their relations to one another as well as to ourselves. More than that: we begin to take part in the love which is
eternally the being and the life of the triune God.

EBSCOhost - printed on 1/10/2024 5:46 PM via NATIONAL LIBRARY OF KOREA. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use

You might also like

pFad - Phonifier reborn

Pfad - The Proxy pFad of © 2024 Garber Painting. All rights reserved.

Note: This service is not intended for secure transactions such as banking, social media, email, or purchasing. Use at your own risk. We assume no liability whatsoever for broken pages.


Alternative Proxies:

Alternative Proxy

pFad Proxy

pFad v3 Proxy

pFad v4 Proxy