Collins SyntaxLess 2007
Collins SyntaxLess 2007
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
and Oxford University Press are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend
access to Mind
Much of the best contemporary work in the philosophy of language and content
makes appeal to the theories developed in generative syntax. In particular, there is a
presumption that-at some level and in some way-the structures provided by syn-
tactic theory mesh with or support our conception of content/linguistic meaning as
grounded in our first-person understanding of our communicative speech acts. This
paper will suggest that there is no such tight fit. Its claim will be that, if recent gener-
ative theories are on the right lines, syntactic structure provides both too much and too
little to serve as the structural partner for content, at least as that notion is generally
understood in philosophy. The paper will substantiate these claims by an assessment
of the recent work of King, Stanley, and others.
1. Introduction
This position is most closely associated with Jeff King; we shall also see
that Stanley shares much the same conception. Many others, less
directly concerned with the ontology of propositions, also make the
presumption that, at some level, syntactic structure encodes the organ-
The phrasing here is intended to be ecumenical between various conceptions of the relations
between sentences, propositions, and truth conditions. On one view, there is a two stage process,
where a proposition is determined from a sentence (relative to context) and truth conditions are
then assigned to the proposition (e.g. King 1995). This dual process allows for distinct processes of
composition between proposition and truth conditions. For my purposes, this complication may
be sidelined (for discussion, see King and Stanley 2005). As we shall see, the problem I present is
one of an overdetermination of syntactic structure vis-is propositional structure, not underde-
termination between a sententially determined proposition and its truth conditions.
2 Many 'traditionalists' would reject this reasoning in toto, claiming that there is no structural
map between language and thought (cf. Fodor 2001; Schiffer 1987). For the purposes of this paper,
I shall ignore any such position. For the record, however, I share the view of the theorists with
whom I shall be concerned that natural language semantics is a serious pursuit and is not merely
an indirect way of thinking about thought, whatever that might be.
5 See, for example, Lasnik and Uriagereka 2005 for a textbook account of these claims. The basic
idea that any sentence-like structure (featuring tense) will involve movement in fact follows from
the verb-internal subject hypothesis that has been discussed since the early 198os. For the classic
defence of the hypothesis, see Koopman and Sportiche 1991; for an overview of the hypothesis, see
McClosky 1997. See den Dikken 2006 for the hypothesis in a minimalist setting.
(TEN) Tense heads are merged post the formation of verbal domains
and carry uninterpretable features.
6 Theta roles are features constituents of a structure have in relation to verbs and other theta-
assigning items, such as prepositions. For example, in Mary hit Bill with a bat, Mary is the agent,
Bill is the patient (the thing affected), and the bat is the instrument. For our purposes, the details of
theta roles and their assignment may be happily sidelined.
c. [T' {+Pres, -3rd Per, -Sing Num, -EPP} [vp Bill{ + 3-rd, +sing, -Nom} sleep]
d. [Tp Bill{ +3rd, +sing, -Nom} [T' {+Pres, -3rd Per, -Sing Num, -EPP}
[VP <Bill{+3rd, +sing, _Nom}> sleep]
There are two crucial things to note here. Firstly, the derivation is driven
to value uninterpretable features, not to provide a propositional struc-
ture. This motive is semantic in nature, for an uninterpretable feature is
precisely a feature that has no semantic significance, but the structure
produced departs from what we have been imagining is required for
propositional structure. This is the second point. The copying of Bill
higher up the structure creates an item that looks to be surplus relative
to property instantiation; that is, the lower copy of Bill exhausts what
propositional structure appears to be interested in, namely, Bill is fixed
as the agent of sleep, the instantiater of the property of sleeping.' Fur-
ther, after the introduction of tense, we have a temporal dimension.
Still, Bill gets copied for a reason that is not recorded in the proposition,
7A common idea is that EPP is in fact reducible to Case valuation. This would be a nice result,
but would create complications for the simple picture I am presenting here. For our purposes, the
reason for the copying is much less important than the fact that the copying appears to lack the
'right' semantic significance.
Propositions might feature the same object twice, if we are dealing with a reflexive relation
(e.g. suicide). My present point is that the syntax appears to demand at least a pair of copies inde-
pendently of the conceptual adicity or reflexivness of the verb.
h. [vp seem [Tp Bill [T, to [vp <Bill> [v v+love [vp <love> Mary]]]
i. [T, (13. [vp seem [Tip Bill [T to [vp <Bill> [vv+love [vp <love> Mary]
j. [Tp Bill [T, 43. [vp seem [Tp <Bill> [T, to [vp <Bill> [vv+love
[vp <love> Mary] ]
Again, we see an item Bill copied (this time twice) so as to value unin-
terpretable features on functional heads-in order: infinite T to and
finite T -s. Semantically, such structure appears not to be required, for
the predicate seem appears to express the character of an experience
that Bill loves Mary (technically, seem assigns just the single theta role to
its TP complement; Bill does not do any seeming). The confirmation of
this is given by the paraphrase It seems that Bill loves Mary, where the
subject of seem is pleonastic and Bill is the agent of love.
The details of these constructions and movement/copying in general
are quite complex, but a generalization can be readily extracted: copy-
ing occurs after everything relevant to a propositional (truth condi-
tional) structure has been determined. But copying creates new
structure, and so there is more structure than appears to be demanded
9 This situation also threatens Stanley and Williamson's (2001) analysis of 'know how'. They ar-
gue that 'know how' is a species of 'know that' in part on the basis that the infinite complements of
complementiser how are propositional due to the presence of covert PRO in subject position (see
below for more on PRO). As far as it goes, this thought is accurate, but infinite complements, as
we are seeing, contain structure that looks redundant if the complement is simply taken to encode
or reflect propositions. For example:
(i) Bill knows [cp how [Tp PRO to [vp <PRO> swim]
(ii) Bill knows [cp how [Tp PRO to [ vp <PRO> v+ride [VP <ride> a bike]
1 Chomsky's (2001, 2004, 2005a, 2005b, 2007) speculation that semantic interpretation has a
dual interface would establish a 'functional' semantic role (independent of the syntax that operates
blindly) for every element of a structure, most typically an operator-variable relation (especially
see Chomsky 2007, p. 12). Serious complications abound. The semantic role of the later structure
is speaker/discourse-information orientated; further, the proposal is made in a level-free setting,
under which there would be no unitary proposition structured by the syntax, for there would be
no unitary structure. This, note, makes perfect sense if the later structure serves to situate the ear-
lier structure relative to speaker/discourse-information.
If we assume ... that any two objects that are combined by Merge stand in
the same syntactic relation R, this means that in a given tree all we will ever
have are pairs of expressions standing in R ... This means that to give an ac-
count of what sentential relations are, all we need to do is say what R is.
(King 2007, p. 48)
King (2007, p. 48, n. 45) notes that in now standard treatments, syntac-
tic movement/copying is construed as a species of Merge (Internal
Merge'), so, again, copying or movement in itself does not raise any
additional worries for the very idea of syntactic structure doubling as
propositional structure. I think King's reasoning is correct as far as it
goes, and he is certainly correct to think that the ultimate question of
what syntactic relations really are need not be settled before we can
constructively employ the notion (King 2007, pp. 49-50). None of this,
however, speaks to my concerns. King (2007, p. 47) is concerned to
answer a Benacerraf-style problem of the overdetermination of propo-
sitional structure by the potential myriad of ways of understanding syn-
tactic structure. That is not my concern. However we ultimately
understand the notion of a syntactic relation, if current theory is on the
right lines, then syntactic structure realizes relations between items that
go beyond what propositions require. King's reasoning, as presented,
can only be an answer to this problem if his hypothesis is merely that
propositional structure realizes the same kind of relations as syntax
realizes. Yet that is not King's claim, for he explicitly holds that LF rep-
resentations map onto structured propositions (King 2007, p. 29);
indeed, they are 'identical' save for a surplus on the propositional side to
accommodate the same syntactic organization realising distinct instan-
tiation functions (King 2007, p. 38). Thus, King's hypothesis is not
merely that the same kind of relations are realized in language and
"One might take propositions to determine less than truth conditions, but such a complica-
tion does not by itself ameliorate the present problem, where we have too much structure, not too
little (cf. Soames's, 2005, change of mind from his 2002).
One can imagine various options to make the bullet more palatable.
One thought might be that only one aspect of the syntactic structure
goes to structure the proposition, the rest is somehow periphera1.12 This
is an old demarcation. Certain aspects of a structure, such as theta
assignment, are determined initially, that is, no item is copied so as to
get a theta role, while other aspects, more discourse related, are deter-
mined later or by copying, such as scope, topic, focus, and elements of
mood (see n. io). This is one reason for the positing of levels within
syntax. But a syntactic derivation is not complete until a structure is
built that does not correspond to a structure apt to encode a proposi-
tion. Again, from the point of view of the syntax, the task is to value the
features that have mere morphological significance; the task is not to
deliver a structure for a proposition. I do not wish to be dogmatic here.
Syntax, as currently understood, does contain sub-structures that look
like propositional structures. The problem is to isolate them in a princi-
pled way-that is, to define a structure that is complete relative to syn-
tactic demands and the putative demands of propositional structure.
Such a demarcation is what looks to be unavailable. The problem is
exacerbated in the recent phase derivation model. Here, uninterpretable
features are valued in, following Chomsky's proposal, something like a
'propositional' structure (Chomsky 200oa, 2001), but it is not the prop-
ositional structure itself that becomes interpretable, it remains uninter-
pretable; it is only the complement of the phase head that becomes
interpretable. For example, if we look at a derivation of Bill loves Mary
at the stage [vp Bill love [vp <love> Mary] ], we have a 'propositional'
structure (a phase) with all theta roles assigned, but it remains 'incom-
plete' relative to interface demands: inter alia, the uninterpretable Case
of Bill remains unvalued. So, in effect, the only thing the derivation has
finished with is [vp love Mary], which, needless to say, is not the struc-
ture of a proposition. We have perhaps already ventured too far into
technicalities. The basic idea that syntactic structure has an inherent
duality, with one aspect dealing with propositional structure, is not a
12 A natural way of substantiating this idea would be to take propositions to be the values of a
function from S*+X, where `Si' is a partial aspect of the syntactic structure and 'X' is the other in-
gredient. The problem here is to say what goes into `S*' without merely imposing a top-down con-
dition from our inchoate notion of a proposition, for such a move would apparently exclude
interpretable copies that satisfy all syntactic and interface demands.
There is a principled argument for an operation of 'deletion' of all but the highest copy based
on the need for linearization at PF (see Nunes 2004). Such reasoning, however, does not translate
into a reason for deletion at LF, or its equivalent, at least not straightforwardly. Firstly, lower copies
are interpretable at the 'semantic' interface, even if theta roles are featural rather than configura-
tional. Secondly and correlatively, because linearization does not apply at the 'semantic' interface,
there is an absence of an independent reason to view any process of deletion as applying at LF.
daft idea at all; it is probably true. The present point is simply that how
this duality appears to play out precludes the recovery of a level of syn-
tax that codes just for propositional structure, at least if that notion is
intimate with that of truth conditions.
Biting the bullet also has empirical consequences. On the proposal
envisaged, we should let the notion of a proposition float until
anchored to some settled syntactic account. Yet, without getting into
any technicalities at all, there is a problem here. The proposal cuts
propositions as finely as syntax, but there are surface 'transformations'
that preserve something we might wish to call synonymy, although dis-
course factors change, for example:
Passives: Bill kicked the ball - The ball was kicked by Bill
Clefts: Bill wants a car - What Bill wants is a car - It is a car that
Bill wants
13 For suspicions over QR, see Hornstein 1995; Kitahara 1996; Uriagereka 1998; but see also Fox
2000, 2003.
which I shall sideline." Let us, though, consider the proposal in rough
outline to see how far it might take us.
It is certainly true that intermediate copies have scopal and binding
effects. Consider, for example, the following case:
Here we see that, where X = himself, the intermediate copy in the sub-
ject position of to appear acts as a clause-mate antecedent, thus ruling
out X = herself. Thus, we may construe the highest copy as an operator
and all lower copies as bound items (cf. Chomsky 2007). This produces
a propositional form along the following lines:
(7) Bill is such that it seems to her that Bill appears to himself to be
such a Bill that is a Bill that likes Mary
Here we have four instances of Bill to match the four copies of Bill in
(6). Similarly, our simple example of Bill sleeps should be rendered as,
say, Bill is a Bill that sleeps. Questions might be raised about the fidelity
of such forms to the original 'meanings', but, in such cases at least, let us
accept them as accurate full-reconstructions. Two problems face this
general strategy, one conceptual, one empirical.
The conceptual problem is one suggested above. Were we to follow
this line, we would radically depart from any intuitive idea of a proposi-
tion that encodes truth conditions, or something as simple as, say, Bill
instantiating the property of sleeping. Now this might be a price many
would happily pay, but then they land in the problems above that face
the 'empirical' idea of a proposition. Perhaps all the reconstructions
show us is that all copies in this case must be interpretable at the seman-
tic interface; why should we conclude from that that a proposition is
thus structured? Indeed, if the phase derivation model is accepted, then
the syntax will not deliver the structure of a proposition even in the
case of (6), for the VP like Mary, will be spelt out once the phase [ vp Bill
like Mary] is constructed. This problem will hold for all structures that
feature copying through phases. At best, then, the proposal will give us
the structure of a proposition for non-phase including TP comple-
ments of phase CP. It bears emphasis here that this does not affect the
14The status of reconstruction is very much a live one. Suffice it to say that issues turn on which
copies should be interpretable and which should be, in some sense, deleted; thus, there is broad
consensus that low A-bar copies are uninterpretable. The status of A-copies is much less certain
(e.g. Chomsky 1995b; Boecloc 2001). In general, therefore, the idea that a proposition is going to be
reconstructed from the full set of copies looks to be a non-starter.
The problem here is to say what the semantic relation is between the
copies of love. It is not difficult, of course, to find paraphrases of (8)a
that feature two instances of Bill and love. The problem is to relate the
copies of love so that they might realize a semantic relation analogous
to an operator-variable relation that might be underwritten by the syn-
tax. For example, Bill is a Bill that loves the loving of Mary gets the
meaning wrong. Worse, Bill is a Bill that loves and the loved is Mary (or,
say, ... the loving is of Mary) just signals a surrender of the idea that
syntax is to be a guide to the proposition-that is, while the meaning is
in some sense captured, the reconstruction has, in effect, the verb love
agreeing with the DPs, as if there were two distinct relations in the syn-
tax, one for Bill and one for Mary. It might be that the syntax works in
this manner, distinguishing internal and external arguments as mon-
adic predicates of the same event, but the proposition appears to
involve just the one dyadic relation. The problem becomes more vivid if
we look at ergative/causative verbs, such as break, sink, boil, etc. With
such verbs in transitive form, it is plausible to take the copied verb as
expressing causation:
c. [Tp Bill [T,(13. [vp <Bill> [v v+boil [vp <boil> the soup] ]
15 The general strategy of taking lower copies to be bound items of a higher operator within a
phase depends upon the integrity of chains as syntactic objects legible at the SEM interface. Al-
though chains are widely assumed, it is far from obvious that chains in general should be sanc-
tioned; see Epstein and Seely 2006. A rejection of chains would, in effect, be a rejection of any
reading of copies as related as operator to a variable.
(Thus, we take the verb boil to be the same item in both constructions
that assigns a theme role to the soup; boil acquires the causative reading
via copying to the functional v head, this option being necessary, if
there is another nominal available to serve as the agent.16)
There are many other instances of movement/copying, including
topicalization, passives, unaccusatives, the full range of interrogatives,
focus constructions, relative clause formation, 'tough movement',
quantifier floating. Indeed, the problem looks insuperable if we take
projection itself to be copying, as in bare phrase structure. Correla-
tively, if labels are required, perhaps for purposes of extension and line-
arization, then they too must be rendered semantically interpretable.
To account for all of these varied structures in terms of some form of
reconstruction, which does indeed appear to work in some cases for
argument copying to an operator position, is an onerous task. I should
not want to say that the task is impossible, but I suspect that once the
complexity of the problem is clearly in view, the likely return on the
effort will be seen to be not worth the outlay.
As an addendum, it is worth noting the difference between traces and
copies. Traces look amenable to a variable construal, for they are not
proper lexical items; they merely mark a position in a relation (a so-
called `chain'). Copies are different; they are genuine lexical items with
a full set of features-a copy is not simply a variable. From the point of
view of the syntax, copies are much to be preferred. Traces must be
added to a derivation, but it is opaque from whence they might come. It
appears that they are simply posited to account for movement. Copies,
on the other hand, come for free. The lexical items are already there and
the copying of them is too in so far as they are copied from the lexicon
16 See Pietroski 2003 for an interesting account of the semantics of causatives in line with the
presented syntax. More generally, Pietroski (2005a) has presented a framework where lexical items
are interpreted as monadic predicates of event variables The structures, however, clearly do not
support the linguistically structured proposition idea; the structures are, rather, an interpretation
the syntax provides that treats Merge as conjunction.
'Stanley 2000, 2002a, 2002b, 2005; Stanley and SzabO 2000a, 2000b. Stanley's thesis amounts
to the denial of unarticulated constituents: constituents of a proposition that are not expressed by
any lexical item of the sentence that express the proposition (see Perry 1986; Crimmins and Perry
1989). Taylor (2001) also appeals to covert variables in the syntax to account for putative contextual
effects on content. Unlike Stanley, however, he neglects to offer any syntactic argument for his the-
sis.
18 From Carston (2002a, 2002b), Breheny (am), Bach (2000), Neale (moo, 2004, 2005), Reca-
nati (2002, 2004), Cappelen and Lepore (2002, 2005a, 2005b), Elgardo and Stainton (2004), Lepore
(2004), and Pagin (2005).
19Breheny (2002, p. 183), Recanati (2004, p. io8, n. 19), and Cappelen and Lepore (2005b, Ch. 6)
express some doubt about the justification for (not the truth of) Stanley's syntactic assumptions,
although neither press the issue. To my knowledge, only Blair (2005) questions Stanley on syntax,
in relation to cross-over effects.
tradition, provides too little for this thesis to be true. I should empha-
size that my arguments are not intended to lend weight to the positions
of Stanley's critics; indeed, Stanley is to be commended for taking seri-
ously the syntactic constraints on semantic interpretation, which are
highly problematic for `contextualise positions. My complaint is only
that such constraints do not play out in favour of Stanley's positive
view.
Stanley does not present a full-dress account of logical form; rather,
he simply appeals to 'correct syntactic theory' (2000, p. 397), and
assumes that such a validated theory will (i) vindicate a level of logical
form and (ii) support the presence of items at logical form that may
serve as vehicles for 'all truth-conditional effects of extra-linguistic con-
text'. Stanley (2002b, 2005) does acknowledge, of course, that this thesis
about syntax can not be beamed directly from semantics, as it were..
some syntactic motivation must be provided for the claim that the rele-
vant items occur at 'logical form'. It is this syntactic argumentation that
will be my focus.
This relatively narrow approach might seem to leave me open to a
simple polemical rejoinder: 'So much the worse for generative theory!'
My intent, however, as expressed in my introductory remarks, is not to
categorically refute Stanley's thesis and his attendant semantic account.
My contention is conditional: if recent generative theory is correct,
Stanley's account is incorrect, or at least lacks the support he claims for
it, for there is too little syntax. The imagined rejoinder, then, is at least
coherent, but it has little impact. It is crucial for Stanley's account and
his general anti-(contextualise stance that some syntactic theory does
actively support his account, and he assumes that the generative
approach does so; as we shall see, he is perfectly explicit in this regard.
So, one committed to a Stanley-style approach to the relevant semantic
phenomena is free to pick any syntactic account that coheres with it,
but, if I am right, recent generative theory is not such an account.
Further, for present purposes, it might well be that Stanley has the
semantics right; my concern is only to cast doubt on his syntactic
assumptions. To repeat, this is not a marginal issue, but one that goes to
the heart of Stanley's approach and those of many others. Stanley
(2000, p. 413, 2005, p. 235, n. 8) readily admits that variables of the kind.
he posits are often appealed to in the semantics literature; what distin-
guishes his position is precisely the thought that such variables are 'syn-
tactically represented'. If Stanley's position has no support from
syntactic theory, then the values of his posited variables would be de
facto unarticulated constituents. But Stanley's very claim is that there
20 The following considerations also critically bear on other theorists; for example, King (2001)
suggests that where a bare demonstrative forms the subject of a clause, then it has an empty nomi-
nal complement; thus, e.g. [Tp [DP That till [is tall]]. This posit is required to support King's gen-
eral account of demonstratives as 2-place quantifiers (in fact, his theory posits two more places,
but these are not lexically realized). There is, however, no clear syntactic reason for such a phono-
logically null item outside of ellipsis. Further, it would appear that demonstrative determiners
(that, these, those) along with many other kinds, although not all, carry the right (13s-features (3rd
person, singular/plural-number, perhaps null Case) to match and value uninterpretable features of
T (their external Merge or raising from vP eliminates the EPP feature of T). Thus, syntactically, it is
not obvious that there is a nominal apart from ellipsis. See Longobardi 2001 and Chomsky 2001.
'In certain respects, the proposal is a development of Partee's (1989) model of implicit varia-
bles. Partee, however, is very cautious indeed about her proposal (especially see pp. 267-8). Fur-
ther, her semantic model is DRS, and, in general, she seeks no support from a notion of 'logical
form'.
So, the evidence is that the domains of the DPs-every question, three
Frenchmen, every bottle-are fixed by a preceding DP. In (13)a, not
every question, just every question asked every student, was answered;
in (13)b, not any three Frenchmen were failed, but three each in most of
Bill's classes; and in (13)c, not every bottle is in the corner, but only every
bottle in every room. Thus, the hypothesis is that the three latter DPs
contain a variable whose value may be fixed by the nominal of the pre-
ceding DP. For example, the object variable of the complex 'associated'
with question is satisfied by students, which then serves as the argument
of a function contextually fixed that maps to the domain of the
quantifier-perhaps, the set of questions students were asked, or
maybe the set of questions on the students' exam. Let us accept these
readings.
22 Minimalist scruples, in the form of inclusiveness (see below), might lead us to view indexes as
merely notational, for their only mandate appears to be the construals they mark; that is, indexes
are extra-syntactic posits. For perhaps the most fully developed non-index account of binding, see
Safir (2004a, b). For a defence of indexes as inherent features of nominals, see Baker (2003), espe-
cially pp. 96-7.
23 Here I assume that distinct scope readings are supported by distinct c-command relations. It
might be noted, familiarly, that c-command is not necessary for semantic binding:
(i) [Every lover [of Mozart]] thinks hei was the greatest of composers
(ii) [The men [who prepared the fishi]] hated theiri smell
24 Being an adjunct is not a property of a kind of lexical item, but a configurational position
items can realize. The operation of adjunction may be viewed as a deviant form of Merge. Merge
extends a structure to create a new kind of projection. Adjunction, on the other hand, adds a sec-
ond tier, as it were, to an extant projection. Being hierarchically outside of the SPEC-head-com-
plement configuration, adjunction creates familiar ambiguities, for the site of adjunction is
thematically open and not marked by agreement (e.g. Bill shot the elephant in his pajamas).
25 This is not to say that items cannot be construed as variables. Such an understanding is what
animated the early work on 'logical form' (Chomsky 1975, 1977; Chomsky and Lasnik 1977; May
1977). It bears emphasis, however, that the 'variable' construals proposed covered PRO and trace t,
i.e. items that are bound. Free variables, of the kind required by Stanley to take contextual values,
were strictly ruled out within the syntax (Chomsky 1977, pp. 10-11; Chomsky and Lasnik 1977,
pp. 429, 432). Similar remarks apply to covert operators posited to account for 'tough construc-
tions' (inter alia), i.e. the operator has to move in order to bind a lower copy/trace, with the whole
structure forming a complex predicate. By more recent theory, we can say that free variables are
uninterpretable.
26 Adjuncts do enter into binding relations and negative polarity/parasitic gap licensing, which
appears to establish that adjuncts enter into c-command relations. The fact of their inability to af-
fect acceptability, however, remains unaffected. Chomsky's (2004) pair-set account of adjuncts
views them as entering the derivation late at the interface. The account is designed to cater for ad-
juncts' extra-dimensionality while establishing a c-command relation. None of this complexity
appears to offer succour to Stanley.
(15) The ship was sunk {by the crew i } [PROi to <PRO> collect the
insurance]
Stanley claims that his argument from binding rehearsed above is 'of the
very same structure', that is, the postulation of phonologically null items
28 If we grant 'PRO', we ought not to conceive of it as a peculiar lexical item that essentially
serves the special role of realising semantic arguments for control infinitives etc. We take the lexi-
con to contain a generic item PRONOUN, which is merged at SPEC vP to satisfy theta require-
ments. The merging of infinitive T to (with EPP and Case valuing features) attracts PRONOUN to
its SPEC, where its Case is valued as [null], and the uninterpretable features of T are eliminated.
This entails that the item has no spell-out, it remains covert. 'PRO' simply marks the fact that
there is a non-spelt-out item in the structure. Thus, the structures support control construals
without the derivation being driven to realize any such readings. For a contentious overview of
PRO and control, see Hornstein 2003.
The adjuncts in (16)c and (16)e imply agency and are perfectly accepta-
ble; the same adjuncts in d. and f. create unacceptable structures
because the ergative verbs do not imply agency. It seems, therefore, that
semantic agency is certainly obligatory in these cases, but it just does
not follow that this is recorded syntactically.
The phonologically null phrase to which Stanley appeals is usually
referred to as an implicit argument. Such items are perhaps the worst
possible for Stanley's analogising purpose, for such arguments are typi-
cally taken not to project in the syntax and are so precluded from syn-
tactic relations: plausibly, relations that involve implicit arguments are
ones of construal rather than being clearly syntactic (see, for example,
Williams 1985; Chomsky 1986a; Rizzi 1986; Jackendoff 1987; Brody and
Manzini 1988; Bhatt and Pancheva 2006). For example, theta conditions
do not demand the occurrence of thematic agents for passive predi-
cates. Likewise, no agreement or EPP factors demand their occurrence.
To see the point here note that, in (14)b, whoever does the sinking need
not be the person or persons who collect the insurance; it is left open
that, say, the crew sank the ship under the orders of the owner, who col-
lects the insurance; that is, control is optional, and so a phonologically
null phrase is not necessary. Likewise, a clever burglar who engineers it
so that a security guard breaks a glass (in order to cause a distraction)
might rightly be said to be the agent of the distraction. The case of
adverbial adjuncts is clearer still: deliberately (and similar intentional
adverbs) imply agency, but they do not require a syntactically realized
agent. In sum, the effect appears to be semantic, not syntactic.
(17)a. The ship was sunk by an iceberg [in order [PRO to <PRO> col-
lect the insurance without arousing suspicion] ]
These are fine to my ears, even though an iceberg is not the kind of thing
that can collect insurance and the guard is clearly not the agent of the
subordinate clause. Both DPs (an iceberg' the guard) play a kind of
instrument role, normally introduced by with, which in turn 'implies' an
agent or perhaps serves as an analogue of one. We can look at the struc-
tures as specifying an event in the matrix passive, with the subordinate
clause explaining the reason for the event.' In both cases PRO is not
controlled. If the clauses are preposed, then PRO is clearly arbitrary as
opposed to controlled and the proposed readings are readily available:
(18)a. [In order [PRO to <PRO> collect the insurance without arous-
ing suspicion] ], the ship was sunk by an iceberg
All of this suggests that the implicit control readings do not lead to any
covert item in the syntax.
'Some informants have reported a slight infelicity, but this is ameliorated once the 'rationale'
clause is fronted (see below). This suggests that the degree of unacceptability is pragmatic, not
syntactic.
Control is also affected by semantic features. Consider:
(i) Mary did not want to be parked outside the pub all evening
(ii) The Anglo-French decision to ban the exports angered the
In (i), it is understood that it is not Mary herself that is to be parked but her vehicle, which is not
mentioned. Similarly, in (ii) there is no controller at all, but we understand the agent of the ban to
be the English and the French, rather than arbitrary. These uses might be peripheral in the sense of
Chomsky 1981. My present point is just to suggest that determination of control is not well-suited
to Stanley's analogical purpose.
'The implicit argument data are somewhat variable. I have discussed the best and most famil-
iar case. Stanley (2002a) also appeals to the following pair, with a covert prepositional phrase ap-
parently required in (ii):
31 The assumption here fuses two earlier assumptions for convenience: full interpretation and
inclusiveness. See Chomsky 1986a, 1995a,b. Both assumptions are methodological (guides to re-
search); they are not a priori truths.
32 Neale (2004, p. 113, n. 59, and 2005, p. 230, n. 107) rightly chides his earlier self (Neale 1994)
and various others for treating LF as a receptacle for semantics as opposed to a level of syntax. It is
curious, therefore, that Neale should focus on what an element is 'doing' at LF vis-is semantics
instead of focusing on how the syntactic derivation treats the element such that it has its particular
LF position.
Stanley further explains that context 'help [s] us to decide which logical
form is the one that has been uttered', where this solves the equation:
'utterance + X = logical form' (2000, p. 399). If this is intended as an
account of the notion of 'logical form' (= LF) as it occurs in contempo-
" No level of syntactic structure has ever essentially implicated a truth conditional conception
of semantics: Stanley's equation is devised from a certain conception of semantics and how that
conception might integrate into syntactic theory (e.g. Higginbotham 1985; Larson and Segal 1995).
Indeed, Chomsky (2000b, p.132, 2003, p. 295) has remarked that his implicit notion of 'meaning'
has always been more akin to Austin's or Wittgenstein's. Notice that where truth conditional se-
mantics has been most clearly fruitful is in exploring certain structural properties of constructions
that have little to do with mind-world relations or inchoate notions of communication and pub-
licity. For discussion, see Chomsky 1977, 1996, 2000b; Hornstein 1984; McGilvray 1998; and Piet-
roski 2003a.
Stanley and SzabO explain that the variable complex `f(i)' is 'associated'
with the nominal and 'co-habits a node with it'. This proposal might
attract some plausibility if one is treating structures like (19) as repre-
sentations mapped onto utterances by an interpreting speaker, but it is
not a serious proposal about LF unless a story is told about from where
the variable complex arises. That is, it is one thing to say where the
complex should occur, it is quite another thing to say how it arrives in
that position. Without an explanation of the origins of the complex, the
structure is effectively unconstrained by syntax. The problem for the
proposal is that, derivationally, the complex has no place in LF struc-
ture: it is parachuted in from semantics. This essential syntactic con-
straint will be missed if LF is construed as a representation of properties
of a sentence, rather than as the output of a derivational process.
By minimalist assumptions, every element at LF must be drawn from
a selection from the lexicon; no element can be present that is not a lex-
ical feature. Well, are variable complexes in the lexicon? All we are told
is that they are 'associated' with nominals and 'co-habit' nodes.
First, as Stanley (2002b) tentatively suggests, we might try to read the
variables as incorporated into the nominal projection (see Baker 1988,
for the classic account of incorporation). This would make the relation
between variable and nominal much like the relation between the noun
deer and the verb hunt in the complex intransitive verb deer-hunt. In
general, cases of incorporation reflect thematic assignment. But
Stanley's proposed covert variables are not constrained to satisfy the-
matic roles; quite the opposite: they appear to be intended to be inter-
preted as adjuncts, which, as we saw above, are essentially optional
elements of strucutre. It thus seems that there is no basis to view the
relation between overt noun and covert variable as one of incorpora-
tion.
A related option is take the relation to be one of conflation in the
sense of Hale and Keyser (2002). Conflation may be understood as 'lex-
ical internal incorporation'. For example, we may view the unaccusative
redden as a deadjectivalised verb, of the form [v red-en [ADJ <red>]].
Yet the internal structure hypothesized by Hale and Keyser does not
project in the 'sentential' syntax; in particular, the structure does not
fall under c-command relations from outside the particular lexical
items. Thus, no binding relation will be supported. Again, it seems that
we lack an extant model for what Stanley requires.
One might suggest the idea that the complexes are 'triggered' by the
merging of N with Det. This is another non-starter. Nothing can occur
in the merged object that is not present in the constituent objects; this
4. Concluding remarks
We have seen that syntactic structure, as understood in recent gener-
ative theory, is out of step with the kinds of demands philosophers
make of it. It contains both too much and too little. As hopefully made
clear, this dissonance is by no means problematic for the linguistic the
ories, for they do not presume to capture the same intuitions or notions
that animate philosophical research. They might be off course in other
ways, but it would be obtuse to condemn them on grounds quite out-
side their empirical and theoretical range. Equally, my plea is not for a
veil of silence to fall between linguists and philosophers-quite the
opposite. The work of King, Stanley, and others exemplifies the fecun-
dity of a philosophy of language oriented to our best science of
language. If my considerations show anything, it is perhaps only that a
closer integration is required if linguistic results are to play a genuine
role in shaping philosophical accounts of language, as they must, if
such philosophy is to be a serious area of inquiry.'
References
m My thanks go to Dan Blair, Noam Chomsky, Gareth Fitzgerald, Keith Hossack, Jeff King, Pe-
ter Ludlow, Gabe Segal, and Barry Smith. I am especially grateful to Guy Longworth, for getting
me to see what I wanted to say, and to Paul Pietroski, for more than this note will accommodate.
Versions of the first half of this paper were delivered at the Dubrovnik Philosophy of Linguistics con-
ference in September 2006 and at the Joint Session meeting in Bristol, July 2007.
Rizzi, L. 1986: 'Null Objects in Italian and the Theory of pro'. Linguistic
Inquiry, 17, pp. 501-57.
Rooryck, J. and L. Zaring (eds.) 1996: Phrase Structure and the Lexicon.
Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Safir, K. 2004a: The Syntax of (In)Dependence. Cambridge, MA: MIT
Press.