Phenomenological Psycho Note 2
Phenomenological Psycho Note 2
Table of Contents
What is Phenomenology?
Method vs. Movement
Avoiding Psychologism
Transcendental Analysis and Attitude
What is Psychology?
Natural Science vs. Human Science
Naturalistic vs. Personalistic Standpoint
Elimination vs. Reduction vs. Supervenience
Which Husserl? Whose Phenomenology?
Husserl’s Five Different Introductions to Phenomenology
Husserl’s Three Different Ways to Phenomenological Reduction
Phenomenological Psychology as a Science
Phenomenology vs. Phenomenography
Descriptive Phenomenology
Interpretive-Hermeneutic Phenomenology
Phenomenological Psychology as the Analytic of Ontic Dasein
Heidegger and Science
Heidegger and Psychology
The Therapeutic Value of Minding the Clearing
Conclusion
References and Suggested Further Reading
1. What is Phenomenology?
It has become customary when discussing the origin of the term “phenomenol-
ogy,” to refer to Christoph Friedrich Oetinger’s (compare Kant, 1900) 1762 use
of the term and to invoke, following Martin Heidegger, a reference to Johann H.
Lambert’s 1764 New Organon (Neues Organon) from where it appears Kant ob-
tained the term. In a 1770 correspondence with Lambert, the outline of Kant’s
appropriation of the term into the Critique of Pure Reason can already be seen.
According to Kant,
The most universal laws of sensibility play an unjustifiably large role in meta-
physics, where, after all, it is merely concepts and principles of pure reason
that are at issue. It seems to me a quite particular, although merely negative
science, general phenomenology (phaenomenologia generalis), must precede
metaphysics. In it the principles of sensibility, their validity and their limita-
tions, would be determined, so that these principles could not be confusedly
applied to objects of pure reason (Kant, 1986, p. 59, translation slightly modi-
fied; compare Heidegger, 2005, p. 3).
Two pieces are of the utmost importance in this passage from Kant. First, Kant
makes a distinction between the impure and the pure use of reason. Impure
reason refers to the a priori aspects of experience, and these aspects are uni-
versal within the human experience. Further, impure reason is differentiated
from pure reason insofar as impure reason includes what Kant in the above
passage calls “sensibility.” Hence, “phenomenology,” for Kant, should be under-
stood as the “science” that studies the aspects universal to human experience.
The second important piece of the Kant passage is his explicit description of
phenomenology as determining the “principles of sensibility.” Here, “principle”
should be understood in terms of the structural origins of human experience. In
other words, Kant understands the principles of sensibility to belong to the or-
der of necessary and universal conditions of human experience, a.k.a. the
“structure of experience.” Already in this earliest definition by Kant, phe-
nomenology pertains to human experience and, thereby, takes the first-person
perspective of some subject as a point of departure. However, because phe-
nomenology studies the universal and necessary aspects of such experience, it
is neither merely subjective, nor concerned with a particular psychological sub-
ject.
G.W.F. Hegel inherited this understanding of phenomenology from Kant. Accord-
ing to Joseph Kockelmans, “it was only with Hegel that a well-defined techni-
cal meaning became attached” to the term phenomenology. For “Hegel, phe-
nomenology was not knowledge of the Absolute-in-and-for-itself, in the spirit of
Fichte or Schelling, but in his Phenomenology of Spirit [(Phänomenologie des
Geistes)] he wanted to solely consider knowledge as it appears to conscious-
ness” (Kockelmans, 1967, p. 24). Further, beyond the emergence of the term
“phenomenology” in the eighteenth century, Heidegger traces its etymology to
the terms phainomenon and logos in Aristotle, especially Book II of De Anima
(On the Soul), where Aristotle discusses “seeing” (compare Heidegger, 2005,
pp. 3-18).
b. Avoiding Psychologism
Not only is Husserl’s statement above helpful toward getting a sense of the
theme of Husserl’s philosophy, it also invokes the important role of the a priori
in his understanding of phenomenology. Contents of experience derived from
the senses, that is the a posteriori, cannot provide universal and necessary
knowledge. Similarly, “empiricism expressly teaches” “more or less vague prob-
abilities resting on experience and induction, concerned with matters of fact in
the life of man” (Husserl, 2001a, p. 56). Hence, Husserl’s concern to uncover
the universal and necessary, that is the a priori, conditions of possible experi-
ence reveals a deep kinship with Kant’s critical philosophy generally, and
specifically his Critique of Pure Reason (compare Kant, 1998; compare Allison,
1975; compare Heidegger, 1997).
Husserl depends on Kant in a number of ways: for example, his concern for phi -
losophy as a rigorous science, his conception of phenomenology as transcen-
dental idealism, the relation of transcendental phenomenology to the life-world,
and, above all, the problem of psychologism. This problem, which arises in
Kant’s criticism of Lockean so-called physiology, leads to a conception of the
subject as a later version of the Kantian transcendental unity of apperception
running through Husserl’s positon from beginning to end (Rockmore, 2011, p.
101).
This last insight, namely that the phenomenological method provides access to
the necessary, and human species universal, a priori conditions for the possibil-
ity of experience, helps to contextualize Max Scheler’s (1874-1928) characteri-
zation of the “phenomenological attitude.” According to Scheler, phenomenol-
ogy “is the name of an attitude of spiritual seeing in which one can see or expe-
rience something which otherwise remains hidden” (Scheler, 1973, p. 137).
Then, understanding phenomenology as either a movement or method, it may
also be understood as an “attitude.” Since a “method is a goal-directed proce-
dure of thinking about facts, for example, induction or deduction” or “a particu-
lar procedure of observation and investigation, with or without experiment and
with or without instrumental support for our senses, in the form of micro -
scopes, telescopes, etc.” Scheler argues “Phenomenology, however, has a fun-
damentally different attitude. That which is seen and experienced is given only
in the seeing and experiencing act itself … It does not simply stand there and
let itself be observed” (Scheler, 1973, pp. 137-138). Hence, “attitude” refers to
the relation to a phenomenon which allows it to show itself as itself (compare
Heidegger, 1962, p. 51), when to a different attitude it would have shown itself
differently. That the phenomenological attitude has the character of a science
is ensured by the universality and necessity of what shows itself to observers
who have gained such a relation to phenomena.
As the remaining sections explicate more fully, the discussion so far may al-
ready allow for a preliminary understanding of how phenomenology may be
thought of as a descriptive psychology, and how a descriptive psychology may
be understood as a phenomenological psychology. Whether considered as a
movement, method, or attitude, phenomenology is understood to involve obser-
vation of phenomena yielding results of a specific kind. What is at stake, then,
for observational research to be identified as phenomenological psychology,
will involve the kind of results the research seeks to yield. Contextualizing phe-
nomenological psychology as such, despite the claims of researchers from di-
verse movements utilizing diverse methods and with various attitudes to be en-
gaged in some type of “phenomenology,” will help clarify whether such re-
search is truly “phenomenological” psychology.
2. What is Psychology?
It is, therefore, insufficient to simply suggest, along with the Oxford Encyclope-
dia of Psychology, that “The term phenomenological is often used by psycholo-
gists to refer simply to the subjective point of view” (Kazdin, 2000, p. 162). On
one hand, phenomenological analysis proper seeks the universal and necessary
conditions for the possibility of human experiential phenomena. On the other
hand, there is a paradigm for research in psychology as a natural science that
seeks to isolate subjective phenomena, for example qualia, for example,, for
the sake of discovering a correlation with natural phenomena such as electro-
chemical activity of the central nervous system. Despite a departure from phe-
nomenology proper, phenomenological psychology still refers, though ambigu-
ously, to meaningful research projects; however, the specific difference be-
tween phenomenological and non-phenomenological projects in psychology is
not “simply” “the subjective point of view” (compare Husserl, 1977, pp. 110-
115).
Yet, as indicated with the primary division of psychology into natural and hu-
man science, psychology tends to take a psychophysical understanding of hu-
man being as a point of departure for further research (compare [../hard-con/]).
In fact, psychologists may be classified by a taxonomy of relations between the
psychological and the physical. There are those who seek an elimination of ei -
ther the psychological or the physical in favor of the other, and there are a
number of ways to take up such a position. However, the most popular of such
ways today is, perhaps, “eliminative materialism” (compare Churchland, 1981).
Next, there are those who seek a reduction of either one of the psychological,
or the physical, to the other. Though, again, it seems more popular and plausi-
ble today to find the reduction of the psychological to the physical advocated.
Lastly, there are those who seek to characterize the relation in terms of super -
venience. The perhaps most popular articulation suggests that psychological
states cannot be eliminated in favor of, or reduced to, physical states; how-
ever, there can be no changes to psychological states without there being ac-
companying changes to physical states (compare Kim, 1984; compare Kim,
1987).
To sketch a brief response to this question, beyond the gestures already made
above (for example, the third general identification of phenomenological psy-
chology), consider the following comments from a section titled “The delimita-
tion of somatology and psychology” in Book III of Ideas. According to Husserl,
What one has here, from the point of view of natural science, is a number of in -
dividual human beings each with a particular consciousness, a particular psy-
che … belonging to each. In the psycho-physical interrelated context that is
made possible by the material interrelations of the animate organisms, there
arise in the individual psyches acts that are intentionally directed at something
psychically external. But what appears here is always only new states of the in-
dividual psyches (Husserl, 1980, p. 18).
Simply put, “one must not confuse noema (correlate) and essence” (Husserl,
1980, p. 73). Wherever we go, we bring the necessary and universal conditions
for the possibility of experience to our experiences. Both the naturalization
project and the merely subjective point of view project are misidentified with
phenomenological psychology, considering phenomenology proper; moreover,
both of these projects may fail at avoiding psychologism (compare Husserl,
2001b, p. 86, quoted above; compare Husserl, 1977, p. 38).
Since each of the ways explained by Kern are ways into the transcendental
phenomenological attitude, only their differences will be briefly characterized
here. The characterization of their differences is helpful toward clarifying what
is meant by phenomenological psychology. This is because across the differing
introductions, it is not difficult to lose sight of the many different unifying
themes with which to coherently understand the relation between phenomenol-
ogy and psychology. The key is to see that the introductions, rather than being
set against one another, should be unified around Husserl’s attempts to in-
struct readers into the transcendental phenomenological attitude.
The Cartesian way seeks an absolute starting point from which philosophy may
be understood as a science. This starting point demands absolute evidence,
and this means simply clear and distinct evidence that cannot be doubted. Be -
lief in the mind-external world is then to be doubted, since there is supposed to
be no absolute evidence for belief in the mind-external world. Yet, knowledge
about the world is based on belief in the world’s existence, and experience of
what was previously believed to be the world does not cease when belief in the
world is doubted. Hence, this relation to the experience of the “world,” is a re-
duced relation. The final step in the Cartesian way is to understand the inten-
tional relation to the “world” as that of the “cogito,” that is the intentionality of
the acting ego, such that the cogito provides absolute evidence for itself as the
starting point for philosophy understood as a science. Notice, phenomenology
involves understanding how the intentional structure of the subject provides
objective knowledge of the mind-external world, and as such phenomenology’s
interest in the intentional structure of the subject is not “subjective.”
The way through “intentional psychology,” then, according to Kern, takes the
“physical sciences, which are interested purely in the physical and abstracts,
from everything psychic. In opposition to these sciences, Husserl conceives
the idea of a complementary science which is interested purely in the psychic
and abstracts from everything physical” (compare Kern, 1977, p. 134). By point-
ing out that relations between objects in the lived experience of humans are
not relations between those objects in mind-external reality, Husserl points the
way to “lived experience.” This may be compared to the focus on the inten-
tional relation to the “world” in the Cartesian way. Moreover, the lived experi-
ence pertains to the subject, but it is not “subjective.” Kern provides the follow-
ing two quotes from Husserl’s The Crisis of the European Sciences as convinc-
ing evidence of Husserl’s view: “Psychology, the universal science of the purely
psychic in general – therein consists its abstraction” (Husserl, 1978, p. 252) and
“in the pure development of the idea of a descriptive psychology, which seeks
to bring to expression what is essentially proper to souls, there necessarily oc-
curs a transformation of the phenomenological-psychological epoché and re-
duction into the transcendental” (Husserl, 1978, p. 257).
Lastly, the “ontological” way may be seen as a direct attack on the psycholo-
gist who might mistakenly think phenomenology to refer “simply to the subjec-
tive point of view” (compare Kazdin, 2000, p. 162). According to Kern, “Rather,
the objective ‘theme’ is implied intentionally in the subjective ‘theme’ (in the in-
tentional life of subjectivity)” (compare Kern, 1977, p. 137). Further, “The
change of attitude is to be compared with the transition from the second to the
third dimension of space, which contains in itself the second dimension. This
subjectivity [emphasis added], in which everything objective is constituted, is
the transcendental one” (Kern, 1977, p. 137). Hence, the psychologist who
takes phenomenological psychology to be an investigation of “the subjective
point of view” understood as a “perspective through which the individual expe-
riences his or her world [emphasis added]” (compare Kazdin, 2000, p. 164) is
not actually engaged in phenomenological psychology. Further, the popular ten-
dency to emphasize a subject’s “perspective” as transcending both other sub-
jects and the potential truth value of criticism from other subjects stems from a
misunderstanding of phenomenological psychology. As Kern explains, “This
subjectivity … is exhibited as an intersubjectivity, made communal through the
common objectivity,” and this science is an “exploration of the universal tran-
scendental life, in which worldly objectivity [emphasis added], with its ontologi-
cal a priori, is constituted” (Kern, 1977, p. 137).
With this distinction in mind, there are a number of research methods classified
as within phenomenological psychology to consider. In Phenomenological Psy-
chology: Theory, Research, and Method, Darren Langbridge explains, “when ap-
plying phenomenological philosophy to psychology, we aim to focus on people’s
perceptions of the world in which they live and what this means to them: a fo -
cus on people’s lived experience” (Langbridge, 2007, p. 4). Langbridge links
“developments” of phenomenology in philosophy with their corresponding re-
search methods in psychology. For example, he claims “phenomenology” refers
to a “descriptive approach,” “existentialism” refers to an “interpretive ap-
proach,” and “hermeneutics,” refers to a “narrative approach” (Langbridge,
2007, p. 5). Though not listed by Langbridge, the perhaps most promising of the
approaches to phenomenological psychology may be seen in Aron Gurwitsch’s
work in the phenomenology of Gestalt psychology (compare Gurwitsch, 1966).
b. Descriptive Phenomenology
c. Interpretive-Hermeneutic Phenomenology
The term “existential” should invoke the notion of freedom. As disclosing the
existentials (existentialia), then, phenomenology may be used as a method to-
ward an awareness, which is psychologically therapeutic, in its affirmation of
human freedom. Just as existentialism and freedom belong together, so too
awareness of the conditions making human experiences possible, when consid-
ered from the first-person perspective regarding lived experience, may be ther-
apeutic. In essence this is the training of a client seeking psychotherapy to per-
form a phenomenological reduction to accomplish a transcendental attitude to
their own lived experience. This is Da-sein analysis. This may be accomplished
through analysis of the existentials conditioning the person-seeking-therapy’s
being. Ultimately this is ontology, through psychology, not psychology; how-
ever, it is still related to psychology as being psychotherapeutic. By bringing
each (human) being to an awareness of the clearing of being in which their be-
ing human in accomplished, they may “take hold of” their being differently
(compare Heidegger, 1962), and this is an affirmation of the person’s freedom,
which may be therapeutic given the everyday possibilities through which hu-
mans may forget the be-ing which allows beings to be.
6. Conclusion
Author Information
Frank Scalambrino
Email: Scalambrinof9@gmail.com
University of Dallas
U. S. A.