General Equilibrium With Imperfect Competition
General Equilibrium With Imperfect Competition
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
http://about.jstor.org/terms
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted
digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about
JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
Wiley, European Economic Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend
access to Journal of the European Economic Association
This content downloaded from 155.69.24.171 on Thu, 12 May 2016 14:38:35 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM WITH IMPERFECT
COMPETITION
Abstract
The objective of a firm is not well-defined if firms have market power. We present an example
of Cournot-Walras competition in order to shed light on this problem and to motivate the
concept of real wealth maximization that B. Grodal and E. Dierker have proposed as the firm's
objective. (JEL: (JEL:
(JEL: D21,
(JEL: D21, D42, D42,
D21, D21, D42,D42,
D43, D43,
D43, L13,
D43, L13,L13,
L13,L21)
L21) L21)
L21)
1. Introduction
In Birgit Grodal's view, General Equilibrium (GE) Theory relies on the following
principles: All consequences of any economic decision must be fully taken into
account. Thus, a GE model must be closed. In a GE model all concepts must have
an unambiguous, well-defined meaning.
GE Theory is not based on the assumption of perfect competition. One of
Grodal's major goals over many years has been to improve our understanding of
GE Theory with firms that possess market power or with firms that act within an
incomplete system of markets. The central question is: What is the objective of a
firm?
This content downloaded from 155.69.24.171 on Thu, 12 May 2016 14:38:35 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Dierker and Dierker General Equilibrium with Imperfect Competition 437
What should be the objective of a firm that is not a price taker? Gabszewicz
and Vial (1972) present a GE model in which firms act a la Cournot. In their
framework, shareholders are allowed to consume the goods produced by their
firm and its rivals. Like all other consumers, shareholders contribute to the gener-
ation of profits and they pay the same prices as all other consumers.1 Following
Gabszewicz and Vial, a Cournot- Walras (CW) game can be described as fol-
lows. Each firm j chooses a production plan yK These production plans are
allocated to the consumers according to their shares and determine, together with
the original initial endowments, consumers' intermediate endowments. The inter-
mediate endowments are traded in an exchange economy at Walrasian equilibrium
prices. The equilibrium prices are only determined up to a positive scalar. The
comparison of profits associated with different relative price systems constitutes
a serious conceptual difficulty referred to as the price normalization problem.
Gabszewicz and Vial use price functions to formulate the objective of a firm.
A price function ix takes a selection from the Walras equilibrium correspondence
and specifies a price normalization rule. More precisely, a price function assigns
to every profile (j1, y2, . . .) of production plans an absolute equilibrium price
vector n(yl, y2, . . .) £ M1 of the associated exchange economy. Each firm j
maximizes profits as given by iz(yl, y2, . . .)y7. CW-equilibria depend on the
selection of the price function in a critical way.
In Grodal (1984) the following embarrassing consequence of the price nor-
malization problem is shown.2 A profile of production plans is called p-dominated
if, for one of the firms, there exists another production plan that gives precisely
the same relative price system but higher profits. In a CW-equilibrium produc-
tion plans cannot be p-dominated. However, arbitrary production profiles can be
turned into CW-equilibria if they are not p-dominated. Thus, in a CW-equilibrium,
a production plan yj may lie in the interior of j 's production set YK The reader
is also referred to Bohm (1994).
H. Dierker and B. Grodal (1986) contains two examples. In the first example,
firms maximize profits on the basis of some price function. The price function
can be chosen such as to obtain any one of the following three cases: First, the
CW-game has an equilibrium in pure strategies. Second, the CW-game has no
equilibrium in pure strategies, but a mixed strategy equilibrium exists. Third, the
CW-game does not even have an equilibrium in mixed strategies. In the second
example, each firm has a single, utility maximizing owner. Again, no mixed
strategy equilibrium needs to exist.
1. In Denmark and various other countries pension funds constitute an essential column of the
pension system. A large part of the population holds shares through its contributions to pension
funds and mutual funds.
This content downloaded from 155.69.24.171 on Thu, 12 May 2016 14:38:35 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
438 Journal of the European Economic Association
In this paper, we present an example that has been developed together with
Birgit Grodal. The example illustrates, in the context of Cournot-Walras compe-
tition, the price normalization problem and a solution concept, called real wealth
maximization. This concept can be described as follows: A firm maximizes the
real wealth of its shareholders if the firm cannot choose another strategy that
makes its shareholders so rich that they can buy a larger bundle. Real wealth max-
imization is closely related to the impossibility of potential Pareto improvements
among the group of shareholders and independent of any price normalization.
Birgit Grodal was determined to solve the question of how a firm should measure
the wealth of its shareholders without reference to utility functions. In order to
illustrate the approach taken by Grodal and her collaborators, we present and
analyze different objectives in the framework of one simple example.
There are two firms 7 = 1,2 and two consumption goods, denoted x and y.
Following Gabszewicz and Vial (1972), each firm is endowed with a certain
amount of a factor that can only be used as an input in that firm. Firm 1 is charac-
terized by its transformation curve X\ + Y\ = 9 and firm 2 by X2 + Y2 = 9.3
Inputs and costs are ignored because there is no factor market.
Firm 1 is owned by / = 1,2 and firm 2 by / = 3, 4. Each owner possesses
half of the firm. The owners have no initial endowment other than their share in
the factor endowment of their firm. Their utility functions are
at (X2, Y2).
Firms choose their production plans simultaneously. The production plans
determine new, intermediate endowments, because each shareholder obtains half
of the production of a firm. The intermediate endowments are exchanged in a
Walrasian economy. Each firm foresees the associated Walrasian equilibrium price
3. We use capital letters to denote production plans and lowercase letters otherwise.
This content downloaded from 155.69.24.171 on Thu, 12 May 2016 14:38:35 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Dierker and Dierker General Equilibrium with Imperfect Competition 439
ratio perfectly. Markets in the exchange economy associated with the production
plans (X\, Y\), (X2, Y2) clear if and only if
_7Xi+5X2_7X!+5(9-y22)
Py'Px- 5Y1+1Y2 -5(9-X2) + 7F2' ()
provided that the aggregate production Y\ + Y2 of good y is positive.4
The mechanism just described does not define an oligopoly game because
the payoffs become specified only if prices are normalized. There are many ways
to normalize prices. We shall look at three specific price normalizations.
In our first specification, we measure profits in units of jc, that is to say, we consider
price systems of the form (1, py). Let the production plans (X\, Y\) and (X2, Y2)
be given. Replacing X2 by 9 - F2 and Y\ by 9 - X2, the profit of firm 1 becomes
45 + 7Xi -5F92 , 9x
n,(x,,r2) = x, + 45_5x; + 7i,M9-xj). , 9x (2)
Similarly, the profit of firm 2 equals
, 45 + 7Xi-5F?2
™'-ri>-'-ri , + 43-,xi + mri- (3)
Measuring profits in units of x can lead to an extreme underprovision of
good y. Assume that each firm believes that its opponent produces only good x.
Consider firm l's response to (X2, Y2) = (9,0). Because rii(Xi,0) = 9 +
12Xi/5, firm 1 has an incentive to increase X\ and to decrease its supply of y
as long as X\ < 3, that is, as long as the supply of y is positive. Inserting the
market-clearing price system and the corresponding demand of the owners of
firm 1 into their utility functions we obtain
4. In the present example, we choose Xi and F2 as the strategic variables of the firms. Therefore,
we will often express prices, profits, and other relevant concepts as functions of (Xi , Y2).
This content downloaded from 155.69.24.171 on Thu, 12 May 2016 14:38:35 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
440 Journal of the European Economic Association
arbitrarily steep if the supply of y approaches 0. In the limit, the budget sets of j 's
shareholders coincide with the x axis of M^_ and contain no utility maximizing
consumption bundle. On a formal level, the production plans (X\,Y\) - (3, 0)
and (X2, Y2) = (9, 0) do not constitute a Cournot-Walras equilibrium, because no
Walrasian exchange equilibrium exists. Profit maximization entails the minimum
wealth problem which causes nonexistence.5
The game possesses the (unique) CW-equilibrium X* « 2.23, F2* ^ 0.77,
in which the overproduction of the numeraire occurs in a less extreme form. We
consider this equilibrium and ask the question: Do the shareholders of a firm
want to instruct its management to change their firm's objective unilaterally? The
answer is yes. Given the strategy of its opponent, a reduction in the production
of the numeraire enables any one firm to make both of its owners better off.
We abandon the asymmetry of the price normalization but retain the assumption
that both firms measure profits in the same way. If profits are measured in units
of the bundle (jc, y) = (1, 1), then (px, py)(l, 1) = px + py = 1.
Using the market clearing condition (1), we obtain the following profit
functions in the (1,1) normalization:
5. The reader is referred to Debreu (1959), Section 4.8, or to Mas-Colell, Whinston, and Green
(1995), in particular, Proposition 16.D.2.
This content downloaded from 155.69.24.171 on Thu, 12 May 2016 14:38:35 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Dierker and Dierker General Equilibrium with Imperfect Competition 441
In an economy with a functioning stock market, firms cannot control how profits
are distributed among consumers because each individual agent decides how many
shares he acquires. Accordingly, we assume that firms disregard all aspects related
to distributional justice. We assume that firms are only interested in shareholders'
aggregate real wealth, that is to say, wealth in terms of their aggregate consump-
tion. We formulate the objective of firm 1 in the framework of our example where
firms' strategies are X\ and Y2 • The analogous definition for firm 2 is obvious.
This content downloaded from 155.69.24.171 on Thu, 12 May 2016 14:38:35 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
442 Journal of the European Economic Association
strategy X\ such that the aggregate demand D\(X\,Y2) of firm l's shareholders
satisfies
(px,py)Di(Xl,Y2)<hi, (4)
where (px , py) and ft i denote the market clearing price system and the associated
profit at (Xi, Y2).
In the case of our example, the system (5) has the unique solution X* = YJ ^
0.997. This solution constitutes a symmetric CW-equilibrium with real wealth-
maximizing firms.
The baskets in which profits are maximized in a real wealth equilibrium are
determined endogenously. In the particular case of our example, each firm's basket
corresponds to the aggregate expenditure shares of its shareholders, which equal
This content downloaded from 155.69.24.171 on Thu, 12 May 2016 14:38:35 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Dierker and Dierker General Equilibrium with Imperfect Competition 443
(5/12, 7/12) in the case of firm 1 and (7/12, 5/12) in the case of firm 2. Our
model is symmetric and p* - p* Therefore, shareholders' expenditure shares
are proportional to shareholders' consumption.
We list the equilibrium utility profiles of the three games analyzed herein and of
the perfectly competitive Walrasian equilibrium. We also list the profits in those
three case in which equilibrium prices equal /?* = p* = 0.5.
It is apparent from Table 1 that all four equilibria are Pareto comparable. In
games 2-4, equilibrium prices always equal 0.5. Profits increase if one moves
from game 2 towards game 4.6
In equilibrium, game 3 has several closely related properties that the other
games do not possess. First, each firm maximizes profits measured in units of the
aggregate demand of its shareholders. Second, if an individual firm chooses any
other strategy, the change in profits (measured with respect to any basket) does
not enable its shareholders to maintain their aggregate consumption, that is to say,
shareholders' real wealth decreases. Third, if a firm chooses another strategy, the
change in profits does not enable its shareholders to maintain their equilibrium
utility levels even if redistribution among them is allowed.
Maximization of shareholders' real wealth is related to the maximization of
shareholders' social surplus because it encompasses profits, namely, producer
surplus, as well as shareholders' consumer surplus as represented by their expen-
ditures. Producer surplus alone suffers from the price normalization problem,
but social surplus does not. Let (X*, Y£) be a CW-equilibrium with real wealth
maximization and D* the aggregate equilibrium demand of firm y's sharehold-
ers. Take any positive bundle (jq, X2) and normalize prices and profits such that
x\px + X2Py = 1. Define the social surplus of, say, firm l's shareholders with
respect to (X*, F2*) as Si(Xi) = (rii(Xi, F2*) - (px, py)D\? Then S\(X\) is
6. Remember that costs are normalized to zero. Therefore, it is not astonishing that revenues in a
perfectly competitive equilibrium exceed those in the Cournot- Walras games.
7. Because real wealth maximization is not utility based, consumers' expenditures are computed
with respect to shareholders' demand rather than shareholders' utility levels.
This content downloaded from 155.69.24.171 on Thu, 12 May 2016 14:38:35 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
444 Journal of the European Economic Association
References
Bohm, Volker (1994). "The Foundation of the Theory of Monopolistic Competition Revisited."
Journal of Economic Theory, 63, 208-218.
Debreu, Gerard (1959). Theory of Value. John Wiley.
Dierker, Egbert, Hildegard Dierker, and Birgit Grodal (2001). "Objectives of an Imperfectly
Competitive Firm: A Surplus Approach." In Economic Essays. A Festschrift for Werner
Hildenbrand, edited by Gerard Debreu, Wilhelm Neuefeind, and Walter Trockel. Springer-
Verlag.
Dierker, Egbert, and Birgit Grodal (1998). "Modelling Policy Issues in a World of Imperfect
Competition" Scandinavian Journal of Economics, 100, 153-179.
Dierker, Egbert, and Birgit Grodal (1999). "The Price Normalization Problem in Imperfect
Competition and the Objective of the Firm." Economic Theory, 14, 257-284.
Dierker, Hildegard, and Birgit Grodal (1986). "Non-Existence of Cournot-Walras Equilibrium
in a General Equilibrium Model with Two Oligopolists." In Contributions to Mathematical
Economics, edited by Werner Hildenbrand and Andreu Mas-Colell. North-Holland.
Gabszewicz, Jean, and Jean-Philippe Vial (1972). "Oligopoly 'a la Cournot' in a General
Equilibrium Analysis." Journal of Economic Theory, 4, 381-400.
This content downloaded from 155.69.24.171 on Thu, 12 May 2016 14:38:35 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Dierker and Dierker General Equilibrium with Imperfect Competition 445
Grodal, Birgit (1984). "Profit Maximizing Behavior in General Equilibrium Models with
Imperfect Competition" [in Danish]. Economic Essays, 28, 79-89.
Grodal, Birgit (1996). "Profit Maximization and Imperfect Competition." In Economics in a
Changing World 2, edited by Beth Allen. Macmillan.
Kreps, David (1990). A Course in Microeconomic Theory. Harvester Wheatsheaf.
Mas-Colell, Andreu, Michael Whinston, and Jerry Green (1995). Microeconomic Theory.
Oxford University Press.
This content downloaded from 155.69.24.171 on Thu, 12 May 2016 14:38:35 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms