Hegel On The State
Hegel On The State
the State arises as a solution for the class struggle between the agricultural class, i.e., the
nobility, and the business class, i.e., the bourgeoisie. But the point is that this phase of
the State is to be transcended, and the essential meaning of the State is unity,
specifically, the unity of the single individual and the universal. This is the meaning of:
“the family was the first, so the Corporation is the second ethical root of the state”
(§255). It is self-evident that class conflict and atomisation (“the civil life of business …
turns in upon itself, and pursues its atomising task” §256n.) which is a result of the
market must be overcome, before the unity of the universal and individual can be
attained. But Hegel is insistent that it is not the role of the State to moderate the conflict
between members of Civil Society – that is a task of Civil Society itself:
“If the state is confused with civil society, and if its specific end is laid
down as the security and protection of property and personal freedom, then
the interest of the individuals as such becomes the ultimate end of their
association, and it follows that membership of the state is something
optional. But the state’s relation to the individual is quite different from
this. Since the state is mind objectified, it is only as one of its members that
the individual himself has objectivity, genuine individuality, and an ethical
life. Unification pure and simple is the true content and aim of the
individual, and the individual’s destiny is the living of a universal life.”
(§258n.)
The State is meant to rest only lightly upon Civil Society, the embodiment of the
universal self-consciousness of its citizens, the realisation of their Free Will, both in
oversight of national affairs and in their action on the world stage.
describes exclusion of Jews from civil rights as “folly.” The conclusion is clear:
religious practice has no privileged place in political life.
The separation of powers is an essential principle in Hegel’s concept of the State. The
State is an autonomous organism and its various ‘powers’ are organs in just the sense
that the various organs of the body: each organ exclusively performs its specific
function for maintenance of the whole organism. The unity of the whole is true
irrespective of the fact that historically the components of the whole may have
originated independently. In becoming organs of the State they are transformed:
“The state is an organism, i.e. the development of the Idea to the
articulation of its differences. Thus these different sides of the state are its
various powers with their functions and spheres of action, by means of
which the universal continually engenders itself in a necessary way; in this
process it maintains its identity since it is presupposed even in its own
production. This organism is the constitution of the state; it is produced
perpetually by the state, while it is through it that the state maintains itself.
If the state and its constitution fall apart, if the various members of the
organism free themselves, then the unity produced by the constitution is no
longer an accomplished fact.” (§269ad.)
The internal and external powers of the State are united only in the Crown, and the first
division of powers is that between the civil and military powers. Conflicts within Civil
Society are the business of Civil Society and the military have no role there at all.
The other powers of the State are the components of the State’s Constitution: the
Crown, the Executive and the Legislature. Note that the judiciary is not included here as
a ‘power of the State’ because the judiciary is not part of this sphere – it belongs to Civil
Society. Hegel never foresaw the possibility of the intervention of the Courts in
conflicts between the powers of the State, which he saw as being resolved by
negotiation.
Marxists have rejected the notion of separation of powers ever since Marx (1871) noted
that the Paris Commune was “a working, not a parliamentary body, executive and
legislative at the same time.” Personally, I don’t think this has worked out all that well,
and it is worth re-assessing the doctrine of separation of powers in the light of Hegel’s
argument.
this role is entirely symbolic. Symbolism is something real, and in the matter of
achieving the unity of the individual and the universal, it is of the utmost importance. It
is of course precisely the symbolism that makes constitutional monarchy so repulsive to
the socialist or otherwise radical social movement activist. This needs to be kept in
mind in reading what Hegel has to say about the Crown.
a natural person with the highest possible standing and the best possible advice to make
their decision. Hegel rejects all ideas of an ‘artificial person’ to take the place of the
monarch (§279n.). The only guarantee is a Head of State whose development is tied up
with the development of the whole nation and is symbolically identified with the whole
nation.
Have you ever asked yourself what form the “withering away of the state” (Lenin
1917)? Does it not mean precisely the withering away of commanding or executive
functions to merely symbolic or ceremonial ones? and not necessarily their abolition.
This brings us to (2) – why Hegel thinks that a monarch self-selected by primogeniture
from the same noble family is the only rational determination of Head of State.
Hegel believes that a person representing the traditional owners of the land best fulfils
the symbolic role of the Crown. That this person is wealthy and privileged is incidental;
in Australia, it would be the senior Elder of the Ngunnawal people who would play that
role. It is the deep identification with the land where the government sits which is
important.
In principle, the monarch has no particular interest or talent:
“In a completely organised state, it is only a question of the culminating
point of formal decision (and a natural bulwark against passion. It is wrong
therefore to demand objective qualities in a monarch); he has only to say
‘yes’ and dot the ‘i’, because the throne should be such that the significant
thing in its holder is not his particular make-up. … Monarchy must be
inherently stable and whatever else the monarch may have in addition to
this power of final decision is part and parcel of his private character and
should be of no consequence.” (§280ad.)
It is very important that nothing particular is required of the monarch and consequently
that the monarch is selected by an ‘automatic’ process which is immune to particular
interests, etc. Primogeniture, which forbids the monarch from choosing his or her own
successor, is therefore the ideal means of determining the holder of the Crown:
“that the unity of the state is saved from the risk of being drawn down into
the sphere of particularity and its caprices, ends, and opinions, and saved
too from the war of factions round the throne and from the enfeeblement
and overthrow of the power of the state.” (§281ad.
And according to Hegel: “elective monarchy is the worst of institution” (§281n.)
because is guarantees the primacy of particularity and ‘drags down’ the monarchy into
‘factions and opinions’.
The Australia Republic referendum debate manifested the popular prejudice that the
Head of State must not be a ‘politician’ (and Hegel would agree) but at the same time
there was a fervent desire that the Head of State must be elected by the ‘people’ and not
the Parliament. This is of course is confused. As to the notion of ‘the people’, Hegel
says:
“… on the wild idea of the ‘people’. Taken without its monarch and the
articulation of the whole which is the indispensable and direct concomitant
of monarchy, the people is a formless mass and no longer a state. It lacks
every one of those determinate characteristics — sovereignty, government,
judges, magistrates, class-divisions, &c., — which are to be found only in a
whole which is inwardly organised.” (§279n.)
HEGEL ON THE STATE 6
Nonetheless, it is Hegel’s idea that the Crown, as a natural person, can establish a direct
relation to the people, a role which is inaccessible to the Executive and Legislature or
any committee.
It is self-evident that a Constitutional Monarchy is unsuited to the kind of State to which
readers of this would aspire, but we should not be too quick to dismiss the arguments by
means of which Hegel has rationalised this institution.
§3. The Executive, the Civil Service and the Public Authorities
Hegel mentions a “supreme council” which the Monarch appoints as his Counsellors. It
is not entirely clear, but I think the concept intended is a Cabinet appointed on merit by
the Crown, from the senior members of the Executive. This differs from the
Westminster model in which the Cabinet is recommended to the Head of State by and
from the Legislature, and is closer to the U.S. model, except that the Crown is not the
Chief Executive like the US President, but plays a mainly ceremonial role.
The Executive is the Senior Civil Service, a self-appointed meritocracy open to
individuals according to their talents and education — “every citizen the chance of
joining the class of civil servants” (§291). The Executive is responsible for interpreting
and administrating the law determined by the Legislature. But the Executive and its
lower ranks in the Civil Service ‘oversee’ the real work which is done within Civil
Society by the Public Authorities and the Courts.
This apparent duplication of functions between the State and Civil Society has deep
roots in mediaeval society, in which agents of the King (thegns in old England)
supervised Courts distributed around the land. Positions in the Corporations and Public
Authorities would be “a mixture of popular election by those interested with
appointment and ratification by higher authority” (§288). In mediaeval times, this
entailed a continuous struggle over control of these Civil Society organisations, but the
concept of Constitutional Monarchy suggests that the moment of appointment from
above wanes as the stability and cultural level of Civil Society and the State matures,
though in reality, this has not transpired.
The people working in the Executive branch of the State and in the Courts and Public
Authorities are members of the ‘universal class’ – the class of civil servants, and Hegel,
perhaps naïvely, presumes that the character and motivation of these individuals will be
shaped by their commitment to the universal interest.
representatives to the Legislature or to petition the King. The classes however are not
formal organisations at all but are constituents and products of the System of Needs and
Labour, reproduced by the Family. The Estates appear to be a duplication of the classes
of Civil Society, but this is not really the case – the Estates are the projection of the
classes on to political life.
Hegel never spells out the relation of the Estates to the Houses or the gives us any hint
as to how the Legislature should operate or how the two Houses interact with each
other. It seems though that each House elects representatives to one of the Houses
(much as the House of Lords and House of Commons operated in Britain), each of the
Houses determined laws by their own processes and then came to a three-way
consensus with the Executive, to produce an Act for the Crown’s signature. Hegel is at
pains to avoid a situation where the Legislature could come into direct conflict with the
Executive, and dividing the Legislature into two Houses seems to be a device to secure
this.
bureaucratic knowledge and work! The man within the civil servant is supposed to
secure the civil servant against himself” (p. 53).
Marx criticises the mediating role Hegel gives to the Estates:
“The Estates preserve the state from the unorganised aggregate only
through the disorganisation of this very aggregate.
“At the same time, however, the mediation of the Estates is to prevent the
isolation of the particular interests of persons, societies and corporations.
This they achieve, first, by coming to an understanding with the interest of
the state and, second, by being themselves the political isolation of these
particular interests, this isolation as political act, in that through them these
isolated interests achieve the rank of the universal.
“Finally, the Estates are to mediate against the isolation of the power of the
crown as an extreme (which otherwise might seem a mere arbitrary
tyranny). This is correct in so far as the principle of the power of the crown
(arbitrary will) is limited by means of the Estates, at least can operate only
in fetters, and in so far as the Estates themselves become a partaker and
accessory of the power of the crown.” (p. 68)
Marx claims that this arrangement is aimed at preventing the people from forming an
organised will, rather than at giving the people a means of expressing that will.
Marx rejects with contempt Hegel’s ‘deduction’ of primogeniture and monarchy:
“Hegel has accomplished the masterpiece: he has developed peerage by
birthright, wealth by inheritance, etc. etc., this support of the throne and
society, on top of the absolute Idea.” (p. 74)
and further rejects Hegel’s dismissal of a ‘representative constitution’, i.e., universal
suffrage. In considering the complex mediations Hegel creates between the various civil
powers, Marx comments in exasperation:
“The sovereign, then, had to be the middle term in the legislature between
the executive and the Estates; but, of course, the executive is the middle
term between him and the Estates, and the Estates between him and civil
society. How is he to mediate between what he himself needs as a mean
lest his own existence become a one-sided extreme? Now the complete
absurdity of these extremes, which interchangeably play now the part of
the extreme and now the part of the mean, becomes apparent. They are like
Janus with two-faced heads, which now show themselves from the front
and now from the back, with a diverse character at either side. What was
first intended to be the mean between two extremes now itself occurs as an
extreme; and the other of the two extremes, which had just been mediated
by it, now intervenes as an extreme (because of its distinction from the
other extreme) between its extreme and its mean. This is a kind of mutual
reconciliation society. It is as if a man stepped between two opponents,
only to have one of them immediately step between the mediator and the
other opponent. It is like the story of the man and wife who quarrelled and
the doctor who wished to mediate between them, whereupon the wife soon
had to step between the doctor and her husband, and then the husband
between his wife and the doctor.” (p. 87)
In the course of a long diatribe against Hegel’s obsession with mediation, Marx says:
HEGEL ON THE STATE 9
common life” but “infected by all the accidents of opinion, by its ignorance and
perversity, by its mistakes and falsity of judgment,” and Hegel quotes Goethe:
‘the masses are respectable hands at fighting, but miserable hands at
judging’.
The remainder of the Philosophy of Right covers sovereignty, external relations, war,
international law and World History. Consistent with my focus on those passages and
works which I believe are of especial interest to social movement activists, I will leave
it to the avid reader to explore the whole of the Philosophy of Right on their own.