0% found this document useful (0 votes)
42 views10 pages

Hegel On The State

Uploaded by

Pritha Maitra
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
42 views10 pages

Hegel On The State

Uploaded by

Pritha Maitra
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 10

Hegel on the State

A commentary on the last section of The Philosophy of Right


Andy Blunden June 2018

§1. The State is the march of God on Earth.


The State is the crowning concept of the Philosophy of Right, the realisation of Freedom
and the basic unit of World History, with supreme Right as against the individual.
“The state is the actuality of the ethical Idea. It is ethical mind … knowing
and thinking itself, accomplishing what it knows .... The state exists
immediately in custom, mediately in individual self-consciousness,
knowledge, and activity, while self-consciousness … finds in the state, as
its essence and the end-product of its activity, its substantive freedom.”
(§257)
and:
“The state is absolutely rational inasmuch as it is the actuality of the
substantial [and] … has supreme right against the individual, whose
supreme duty is to be a member of the state.” (§258)
and:
“The march of God in the world, that is what the state is.” (§258ad.)
but:
“The state is no ideal work of art; it stands on earth and so in the sphere of
caprice, chance, and error, and bad behaviour may disfigure it in many
respects. But the ugliest of men, or a criminal, or an invalid, or a cripple, is
still always a living man.” (§258ad.)
It is very likely that the modern reader will have great difficulty in swallowing this. But
Hegel’s Germany was not the Germany of Bismarck, Hitler or Merkel, but more like the
Vietnam of Ho Chi Minh with Kant and Beethoven thrown in. The “State as the
realisation of Freedom” has to be seen in this light.
But the real gap between a progressive modern attitude to the State and Hegel’s is that
Hegel in no way saw the State as “an organ of class rule, an organ for the oppression of
one class by another” (Lenin, 1917), as Marx and Engels (1848, 1884) and most readers
of this would see it.

State as Moderator of Class Struggle


Insofar as the State was used as a weapon of a feudal nobility against the bourgeoisie
(which was still the main axis of class struggle in Hegel’s day), Hegel would have seen
this as either a deformation of the state or a symptom of a state which was still not
worthy of the name of ‘State’ at all. Suppression of riots, crime and other disorders was
a function of Civil Society, not the State, and which Hegel would have seen in the frame
of ‘social problems’, not political challenges.
We have recalled how Hegel insists that the historical origins of the State are “no
concern of the Idea of the State,” that the State may have originated in violence, but its
raison d’être and concept was Freedom. Along the same lines, he notes that “Town and
country constitute the two moments, still ideal moments, whose true ground is the state,
although it is from them that the state springs” (§256n) and “The family is the first
precondition of the state, but class divisions are the second” (§201ad.). This implies that
HEGEL ON THE STATE 2

the State arises as a solution for the class struggle between the agricultural class, i.e., the
nobility, and the business class, i.e., the bourgeoisie. But the point is that this phase of
the State is to be transcended, and the essential meaning of the State is unity,
specifically, the unity of the single individual and the universal. This is the meaning of:
“the family was the first, so the Corporation is the second ethical root of the state”
(§255). It is self-evident that class conflict and atomisation (“the civil life of business …
turns in upon itself, and pursues its atomising task” §256n.) which is a result of the
market must be overcome, before the unity of the universal and individual can be
attained. But Hegel is insistent that it is not the role of the State to moderate the conflict
between members of Civil Society – that is a task of Civil Society itself:
“If the state is confused with civil society, and if its specific end is laid
down as the security and protection of property and personal freedom, then
the interest of the individuals as such becomes the ultimate end of their
association, and it follows that membership of the state is something
optional. But the state’s relation to the individual is quite different from
this. Since the state is mind objectified, it is only as one of its members that
the individual himself has objectivity, genuine individuality, and an ethical
life. Unification pure and simple is the true content and aim of the
individual, and the individual’s destiny is the living of a universal life.”
(§258n.)
The State is meant to rest only lightly upon Civil Society, the embodiment of the
universal self-consciousness of its citizens, the realisation of their Free Will, both in
oversight of national affairs and in their action on the world stage.

Internal and External Relations


The State acts as an Individual in relation to other states. Hegel allows that there can be
alliances and treaties, but he absolutely rejects the idea of a World Government or some
supra-national entity that has authority over a State. Every State has the right to make
War, and the idea of a “perpetual peace” which Kant had proposed, was anathema to
Hegel. In relation to internal matters, Hegel was a collectivist; in relation to external
relations, Hegel was a libertarian. “The one and only absolute judge, which makes itself
authoritative against the particular and at all times, is the in- and for-itself existing Spirit
(an und für sich seiende Geist) which manifests itself in the history of the world”
(§259n.).
But the State is not an absolute power.
The State has no business dabbling in religious matters. This separation of spheres also
goes to Science, Art and Philosophy. Hegel counts all these pursuits as ‘higher’ than
Right inasmuch as they are components of Absolute Spirit, which transcends Objective
Spirit. The State has no business in restricting or directing the practice of Science or
Art. The question of allocating funds for public pursuit of Science or Art had simply
never arisen in Hegel’s times, but while the practice of these “modes of existence” were
undoubtedly essential to humanity, it was equally essential that they flourished
independently of civil and political life. (See §270 and its remarks and footnotes).
Conversely, Hegel is at pains to point out that the clergy has no place in affairs of State,
and he likens the idea of “the unity of church and state” to “oriental despotism.”
Churches are landowners and employers like any other actor in civil society and is
subject to the same laws, and Hegel subsumes them under Corporations. He also
HEGEL ON THE STATE 3

describes exclusion of Jews from civil rights as “folly.” The conclusion is clear:
religious practice has no privileged place in political life.
The separation of powers is an essential principle in Hegel’s concept of the State. The
State is an autonomous organism and its various ‘powers’ are organs in just the sense
that the various organs of the body: each organ exclusively performs its specific
function for maintenance of the whole organism. The unity of the whole is true
irrespective of the fact that historically the components of the whole may have
originated independently. In becoming organs of the State they are transformed:
“The state is an organism, i.e. the development of the Idea to the
articulation of its differences. Thus these different sides of the state are its
various powers with their functions and spheres of action, by means of
which the universal continually engenders itself in a necessary way; in this
process it maintains its identity since it is presupposed even in its own
production. This organism is the constitution of the state; it is produced
perpetually by the state, while it is through it that the state maintains itself.
If the state and its constitution fall apart, if the various members of the
organism free themselves, then the unity produced by the constitution is no
longer an accomplished fact.” (§269ad.)
The internal and external powers of the State are united only in the Crown, and the first
division of powers is that between the civil and military powers. Conflicts within Civil
Society are the business of Civil Society and the military have no role there at all.
The other powers of the State are the components of the State’s Constitution: the
Crown, the Executive and the Legislature. Note that the judiciary is not included here as
a ‘power of the State’ because the judiciary is not part of this sphere – it belongs to Civil
Society. Hegel never foresaw the possibility of the intervention of the Courts in
conflicts between the powers of the State, which he saw as being resolved by
negotiation.
Marxists have rejected the notion of separation of powers ever since Marx (1871) noted
that the Paris Commune was “a working, not a parliamentary body, executive and
legislative at the same time.” Personally, I don’t think this has worked out all that well,
and it is worth re-assessing the doctrine of separation of powers in the light of Hegel’s
argument.

§2. The Crown.


Hegel’s idea of the State was a constitutional monarchy. The Prussia of his time was an
absolute monarchy and all progressive people in Germany aspired to a constitutional
monarchy, not a Republic such as existed in the United States.
Among EU nations today, Belgium, Denmark, the Netherlands, Spain, Sweden and
Britain are constitutional monarchies and are hardly less perfect realisations of Freedom
than Portugal, Bulgaria, Croatia, the Czech Republic, Finland, France, Germany,
Greece, Hungary, Ireland, Italy, Poland and Portugal. While the idea of socialism is
patently incompatible with constitutional monarchy, it needs to be understood that (at
least as Hegel saw it), a constitutional monarchy is the more perfect insofar as the
monarch has no political function beyond placing his or her signature on legislation and
participating in ceremonies of various kinds. Hegel’s model, as outlined in the
Philosophy of Right, has not quite reached that point, but it is clear enough that this is
the concept of constitutional monarchy. Hegel’s monarch remained Commander in
Chief of the armed forces, but again, the concept of constitutional monarchy is that even
HEGEL ON THE STATE 4

this role is entirely symbolic. Symbolism is something real, and in the matter of
achieving the unity of the individual and the universal, it is of the utmost importance. It
is of course precisely the symbolism that makes constitutional monarchy so repulsive to
the socialist or otherwise radical social movement activist. This needs to be kept in
mind in reading what Hegel has to say about the Crown.

Constitutional Monarchy and the personification of the State


In Hegel’s conception, the State is divided into three powers: the Legislature, which
determines the Universal by making laws, the Executive, which determines Particular
cases under the Universal, and the Crown — “the will with the power of ultimate
decision … the different powers bound into an Individual unity” (§273). The State thus
reproduces the structure of the concept derived in the Logic, as the unity of Universal,
Particular and Individual.
In relation to the Crown, there are two important issues: (1) Why the Crown must be an
individual, not a committee or indeed an empty space, and (2) Why the Crown must be
chosen by primogeniture from a noble family.
(1) I am not aware of any state ‒ monarchy or republic, or even any organisation, which
does not have a Head who is an individual, differing mainly by whether that individual
normally plays a symbolic role or is a real commander-in-chief or somewhere in
between. The only exceptions to this rule that I know of are protests and social
movements which through immaturity, incapacity or as an ideological signal, refuse this
individual moment of their self-concept. And Hegel explains why this must be so.
“this freedom which makes the ultimate self-determining certitude — the
culmination of the concept of the will — the function of a single
consciousness. This ultimate self-determination, however, can fall within
the sphere of human freedom only in so far as it has the position of a
pinnacle, explicitly distinct from, and raised above, all that is particular and
conditional … (§279n.)
“[This] is not to say that the monarch may act capriciously. As a matter of
fact, he is bound by the concrete decisions of his counsellors, and if the
constitution is stable, he has often no more to do than sign his name.”
(§279ad.)
To be free, the State of which you are a member must be free, free to make decisions
which are unquestionable and subject to no committee or such which would thereby
usurp that decision. Even the Houses of the Legislature each have a Speaker who
conveys messages to and from the Legislature. The Quakers make do with a Clerk and
many voluntary organisation have a President or Secretary who merely formally
conveys decisions, etc., but is not the pinnacle. But Hegel insists that this role of being
the actual subject is seen as the pinnacle, since the monarch must unite not only a
deliberative committee, but an entire nation.
The personality of the State is actual and the unity of the State secured only when it is a
natural person. Absolute monarchies, from which constitutional monarchies originate,
had this power of personality, but these States were subject to the whims and caprice of
the monarch. But in the mature, stable State, the processes of decision-making have
developed to such an extent that all necessary and possible deliberation has already
taken place when the document is ready for signing — at least in normal, stable times.
In exceptional times or times of crisis, the necessity of a natural person with the
authority of the State is crucial. In such times the only rational decision procedure is for
HEGEL ON THE STATE 5

a natural person with the highest possible standing and the best possible advice to make
their decision. Hegel rejects all ideas of an ‘artificial person’ to take the place of the
monarch (§279n.). The only guarantee is a Head of State whose development is tied up
with the development of the whole nation and is symbolically identified with the whole
nation.
Have you ever asked yourself what form the “withering away of the state” (Lenin
1917)? Does it not mean precisely the withering away of commanding or executive
functions to merely symbolic or ceremonial ones? and not necessarily their abolition.
This brings us to (2) – why Hegel thinks that a monarch self-selected by primogeniture
from the same noble family is the only rational determination of Head of State.
Hegel believes that a person representing the traditional owners of the land best fulfils
the symbolic role of the Crown. That this person is wealthy and privileged is incidental;
in Australia, it would be the senior Elder of the Ngunnawal people who would play that
role. It is the deep identification with the land where the government sits which is
important.
In principle, the monarch has no particular interest or talent:
“In a completely organised state, it is only a question of the culminating
point of formal decision (and a natural bulwark against passion. It is wrong
therefore to demand objective qualities in a monarch); he has only to say
‘yes’ and dot the ‘i’, because the throne should be such that the significant
thing in its holder is not his particular make-up. … Monarchy must be
inherently stable and whatever else the monarch may have in addition to
this power of final decision is part and parcel of his private character and
should be of no consequence.” (§280ad.)
It is very important that nothing particular is required of the monarch and consequently
that the monarch is selected by an ‘automatic’ process which is immune to particular
interests, etc. Primogeniture, which forbids the monarch from choosing his or her own
successor, is therefore the ideal means of determining the holder of the Crown:
“that the unity of the state is saved from the risk of being drawn down into
the sphere of particularity and its caprices, ends, and opinions, and saved
too from the war of factions round the throne and from the enfeeblement
and overthrow of the power of the state.” (§281ad.
And according to Hegel: “elective monarchy is the worst of institution” (§281n.)
because is guarantees the primacy of particularity and ‘drags down’ the monarchy into
‘factions and opinions’.
The Australia Republic referendum debate manifested the popular prejudice that the
Head of State must not be a ‘politician’ (and Hegel would agree) but at the same time
there was a fervent desire that the Head of State must be elected by the ‘people’ and not
the Parliament. This is of course is confused. As to the notion of ‘the people’, Hegel
says:
“… on the wild idea of the ‘people’. Taken without its monarch and the
articulation of the whole which is the indispensable and direct concomitant
of monarchy, the people is a formless mass and no longer a state. It lacks
every one of those determinate characteristics — sovereignty, government,
judges, magistrates, class-divisions, &c., — which are to be found only in a
whole which is inwardly organised.” (§279n.)
HEGEL ON THE STATE 6

Nonetheless, it is Hegel’s idea that the Crown, as a natural person, can establish a direct
relation to the people, a role which is inaccessible to the Executive and Legislature or
any committee.
It is self-evident that a Constitutional Monarchy is unsuited to the kind of State to which
readers of this would aspire, but we should not be too quick to dismiss the arguments by
means of which Hegel has rationalised this institution.

§3. The Executive, the Civil Service and the Public Authorities
Hegel mentions a “supreme council” which the Monarch appoints as his Counsellors. It
is not entirely clear, but I think the concept intended is a Cabinet appointed on merit by
the Crown, from the senior members of the Executive. This differs from the
Westminster model in which the Cabinet is recommended to the Head of State by and
from the Legislature, and is closer to the U.S. model, except that the Crown is not the
Chief Executive like the US President, but plays a mainly ceremonial role.
The Executive is the Senior Civil Service, a self-appointed meritocracy open to
individuals according to their talents and education — “every citizen the chance of
joining the class of civil servants” (§291). The Executive is responsible for interpreting
and administrating the law determined by the Legislature. But the Executive and its
lower ranks in the Civil Service ‘oversee’ the real work which is done within Civil
Society by the Public Authorities and the Courts.
This apparent duplication of functions between the State and Civil Society has deep
roots in mediaeval society, in which agents of the King (thegns in old England)
supervised Courts distributed around the land. Positions in the Corporations and Public
Authorities would be “a mixture of popular election by those interested with
appointment and ratification by higher authority” (§288). In mediaeval times, this
entailed a continuous struggle over control of these Civil Society organisations, but the
concept of Constitutional Monarchy suggests that the moment of appointment from
above wanes as the stability and cultural level of Civil Society and the State matures,
though in reality, this has not transpired.
The people working in the Executive branch of the State and in the Courts and Public
Authorities are members of the ‘universal class’ – the class of civil servants, and Hegel,
perhaps naïvely, presumes that the character and motivation of these individuals will be
shaped by their commitment to the universal interest.

§ 4. The Legislature, the Estates and the classes of Civil Society


Exactly how the Houses of the Legislature and the Estates are to be structured and
operate is left open by Hegel and is somewhat unclear. All we have to go on is the real
models that were available in the Europe of his times and earlier.
The Estates were a political institution of mediaeval times which survived into the 19th
century. The constitution of the Estates varied from country to country and century to
century, but generally there were three: the nobility (which was initially the only Estate,
but referred to in the plural in reference to the various fiefdoms of the nobility), the
bourgeoisie (generally organised via the Corporations) and the clergy, with its own
hierarchies. In Hegel’s case, the clergy are excluded, so there are just two Estates. The
civil servants were not included in the Estates and nor is there a precedent for that.
The Estates differ from the classes of Civil Society because the Estates are political
entities, generally convened periodically to deliberate on political issues and appoint
HEGEL ON THE STATE 7

representatives to the Legislature or to petition the King. The classes however are not
formal organisations at all but are constituents and products of the System of Needs and
Labour, reproduced by the Family. The Estates appear to be a duplication of the classes
of Civil Society, but this is not really the case – the Estates are the projection of the
classes on to political life.
Hegel never spells out the relation of the Estates to the Houses or the gives us any hint
as to how the Legislature should operate or how the two Houses interact with each
other. It seems though that each House elects representatives to one of the Houses
(much as the House of Lords and House of Commons operated in Britain), each of the
Houses determined laws by their own processes and then came to a three-way
consensus with the Executive, to produce an Act for the Crown’s signature. Hegel is at
pains to avoid a situation where the Legislature could come into direct conflict with the
Executive, and dividing the Legislature into two Houses seems to be a device to secure
this.

§5. The Young Marx vs. Hegel on the State.


In the Spring of 1843, the young Karl Marx made critical notes on the section of
Hegel’s Philosophy of Right on the State (although he references earlier sections in the
course of his commentary), abandoning the work in disgust at §313, about where we
have got to in this commentary just now.
At this point in his life, Marx read Hegel as a Feuerbachian – that is, criticising Hegel
for inverting the subject-predicate relationship, and most of his commentary is rather
tiresome ridicule of Hegel’s idealistic forms of argument and expression. Marx regarded
almost everything Hegel said as a rationalisation of the status quo. Most of the
substantive criticisms he made have been at least mentioned here, but some were more
significant than others. Criticisms worth making particular note of are as follows:
Marx observes how in Hegel’s scheme, the State reinforces already existing hierarchy
and privilege in civil society and further that there is a ‘civil society’ within the civil
service:
“The corporations are the materialism of the bureaucracy, and the
bureaucracy is the spiritualism of the corporations. The corporation is the
bureaucracy of civil society, and the bureaucracy is the corporation of the
state. In actuality, the bureaucracy as civil society of the state is opposed to
the state of civil society, the corporations. Where the bureaucracy is to
become a new principle, where the universal interest of the state begins to
become explicitly a singular and thereby a real interest, it struggles against
the corporations as every consequence struggles against the existence of its
premises. On the other hand once the real life of the state awakens and civil
society frees itself from the corporations out of its inherent rational
impulse, the bureaucracy seeks to restore them; for as soon as the state of
civil society falls so too does the civil society of the state.” (Marx, 1843, p.
45)
This passage is followed by an extended criticism of bureaucratism and hierarchy, upon
which Hegel relies for the rationality of the State – the civil servant “is like a hammer
vis-à-vis those below he is like all anvil in relation to those above” (p. 53). And the civil
servant’s “office is indeed his substantial situation and his bread and butter. Fine, except
that Hegel sets direct education in thought and ethical conduct against the mechanism of
HEGEL ON THE STATE 8

bureaucratic knowledge and work! The man within the civil servant is supposed to
secure the civil servant against himself” (p. 53).
Marx criticises the mediating role Hegel gives to the Estates:
“The Estates preserve the state from the unorganised aggregate only
through the disorganisation of this very aggregate.
“At the same time, however, the mediation of the Estates is to prevent the
isolation of the particular interests of persons, societies and corporations.
This they achieve, first, by coming to an understanding with the interest of
the state and, second, by being themselves the political isolation of these
particular interests, this isolation as political act, in that through them these
isolated interests achieve the rank of the universal.
“Finally, the Estates are to mediate against the isolation of the power of the
crown as an extreme (which otherwise might seem a mere arbitrary
tyranny). This is correct in so far as the principle of the power of the crown
(arbitrary will) is limited by means of the Estates, at least can operate only
in fetters, and in so far as the Estates themselves become a partaker and
accessory of the power of the crown.” (p. 68)
Marx claims that this arrangement is aimed at preventing the people from forming an
organised will, rather than at giving the people a means of expressing that will.
Marx rejects with contempt Hegel’s ‘deduction’ of primogeniture and monarchy:
“Hegel has accomplished the masterpiece: he has developed peerage by
birthright, wealth by inheritance, etc. etc., this support of the throne and
society, on top of the absolute Idea.” (p. 74)
and further rejects Hegel’s dismissal of a ‘representative constitution’, i.e., universal
suffrage. In considering the complex mediations Hegel creates between the various civil
powers, Marx comments in exasperation:
“The sovereign, then, had to be the middle term in the legislature between
the executive and the Estates; but, of course, the executive is the middle
term between him and the Estates, and the Estates between him and civil
society. How is he to mediate between what he himself needs as a mean
lest his own existence become a one-sided extreme? Now the complete
absurdity of these extremes, which interchangeably play now the part of
the extreme and now the part of the mean, becomes apparent. They are like
Janus with two-faced heads, which now show themselves from the front
and now from the back, with a diverse character at either side. What was
first intended to be the mean between two extremes now itself occurs as an
extreme; and the other of the two extremes, which had just been mediated
by it, now intervenes as an extreme (because of its distinction from the
other extreme) between its extreme and its mean. This is a kind of mutual
reconciliation society. It is as if a man stepped between two opponents,
only to have one of them immediately step between the mediator and the
other opponent. It is like the story of the man and wife who quarrelled and
the doctor who wished to mediate between them, whereupon the wife soon
had to step between the doctor and her husband, and then the husband
between his wife and the doctor.” (p. 87)
In the course of a long diatribe against Hegel’s obsession with mediation, Marx says:
HEGEL ON THE STATE 9

“Actual extremes cannot be mediated with each other precisely because


they are actual extremes. But neither are they in need of mediation,
because they are opposed in essence. They have nothing in common with
one another; they neither need nor complement one another. The one does
not carry in its womb the yearning, the need, the anticipation of the other.”
(p. 88)

Hegel, Marx and universal suffrage


Hegel argues consistently for highly mediated forms of representation and against
universal suffrage. Marx responds by pointing out:
“The question whether all as individuals should share in deliberating and
deciding on political matters of general concern is a question that arises
from the separation of the political state and civil society.” (p. 118)
and
“It is not a question of whether civil society should exercise legislative
power through deputies or through all as individuals. Rather, it is a
question of the extension and greatest possible universalisation of voting,
of active as well as passive suffrage. This is the real point of dispute in the
matter of political reform, in France as well as in England.”
Marx does not proffer solutions to this problem, but makes an extended criticism of
Hegel which brings out the contradictions entailed in his construction of representative
politics.
Without meeting the problems raised by Marx, Hegel makes a powerful argument
against universal suffrage.
“As for popular suffrage, it may be further remarked that especially in
large states it leads inevitably to electoral indifference, since the casting of
a single vote is of no significance where there is a multitude of electors.
Even if a voting qualification is highly valued and esteemed by those who
are entitled to it, they still do not enter the polling booth. Thus the result of
an institution of this kind is more likely to be the opposite of what was
intended; election actually falls into the power of a few, of a caucus, and so
of the particular and contingent interest which is precisely what was to
have been neutralised.” (§311n.)
According to Hegel, the deputies in the Legislature have to do with the various
branches of society, and the electorate must not be seen an agglomeration of atoms
(§311). Deputies should represent the various groups in society and give them equal
weight. Universal suffrage on the contrary requires every individual to cast their vote
privately, as an isolated atom.
Hegel believes that the public must be educated in national affairs, and he sees the
assemblies of the Estates as the means of achieving this, while political discussion “at
his fireside with his wife and his friends” can never be better than “building castles in
the air.” Participation in assemblies is essential for political education, and this can only
be achieved in the bodies mediating between the associations of civil society and the
Legislature.
‘Public opinion’ is the name given to “individuals … in their having and expressing
their own private judgments, opinions, and recommendations on affairs of state” (§316).
Public opinion is therefore “a repository of genuine needs and correct tendencies of
HEGEL ON THE STATE 10

common life” but “infected by all the accidents of opinion, by its ignorance and
perversity, by its mistakes and falsity of judgment,” and Hegel quotes Goethe:
‘the masses are respectable hands at fighting, but miserable hands at
judging’.
The remainder of the Philosophy of Right covers sovereignty, external relations, war,
international law and World History. Consistent with my focus on those passages and
works which I believe are of especial interest to social movement activists, I will leave
it to the avid reader to explore the whole of the Philosophy of Right on their own.

Andy Blunden’s Home Page

You might also like

pFad - Phonifier reborn

Pfad - The Proxy pFad of © 2024 Garber Painting. All rights reserved.

Note: This service is not intended for secure transactions such as banking, social media, email, or purchasing. Use at your own risk. We assume no liability whatsoever for broken pages.


Alternative Proxies:

Alternative Proxy

pFad Proxy

pFad v3 Proxy

pFad v4 Proxy