International Research Ethics
International Research Ethics
International Research Ethics
net/publication/230886774
CITATIONS READS
9 5,297
3 authors, including:
Douglas P Olsen
SEE PROFILE
All content following this page was uploaded by Douglas P Olsen on 04 June 2014.
Key words: ethics; institutional review board; international nursing research; local
research ethics committee; research
Ethical issues in international nursing research are identified and the perspectives of the
International Centre for Nursing Ethics are offered in an effort to develop an interna-
tional consensus of ethical behaviour in research. First, theoretical issues are reviewed,
then initial conditions for ethical conduct are defined, and protocol design and procedure
considerations are examined. A concerted effort is made to identify and avoid a western
bias. Broad guiding principles for designing and reviewing research are offered:
(1) respect for persons; (2) beneficence; (3) justice; (4) respect for community; and (5) con-
textual caring. A collaborative model of the researcher–participant relationship is sug-
gested and discussed.
Introduction
The International Centre for Nursing Ethics (ICNE) is a world-wide association
of university research and teaching centres that focuses on issues of morality, pro-
fessional ethics, philosophy of care, cultural and religious values, law and
Scope of consideration
Most recent efforts to examine issues in international research ethics in some
developed countries focus on medical research. The executive summary of the US
National Bioethics Advisory Commission’s (NBAC) report, Ethical and policy issues
in international research, specifically states ‘the Commission’s attention was focused
on the conduct of clinical trials . . . in particular those trials such as Phase III drug
studies’ (p. ii).1 In the UK, the Nuffield Council on Bioethics report, The ethics of
clinical research in developing countries, lists the scope of research considered:
clinical trials of new drugs, vaccines and diagnostics, or improved clinical management
strategies . . . basic clinical research studies on the natural history of a disease, the func-
tioning of the body or on behaviour . . . Epidemiological studies may be aimed at iden-
tifying risk factors (p. 3).2
Although not excluding research of primary interest to nurses, these reports are
clearly focused on medical research. A recent more comprehensive report from
the Nuffield Council, The ethics of research related to healthcare in developing coun-
tries, does more to recognize the need to broaden consideration beyond clinical
trials, stating:
In the developing world, research to find new or improved medicines and vaccines is
often given high priority . . . but research to find better ways of delivering existing
products and services to those in need is often equally or more important (p. 5).3
However, this Nuffield report still does not deal specifically with nursing.
This article addresses international nursing research, that is, research where
investigators and participants are from different countries, rather than research
targeting populations by race or ethnicity. Although cultural differences between
researchers and participants are often an essential consideration in international
research, it is not the only consideration. Furthermore, situations where
researchers from one culture study persons from a distinctly different culture
within national boundaries occur frequently in multi-ethnic countries like the USA
and South Africa, or in countries with indigenous populations such as Australia
and Finland. When research is conducted within national boundaries on minority
Theoretical issues
A discussion of theoretical issues provides a background for the ethical consid-
eration of specific design and procedure aspects of international nursing research.
In any discussion of ethics with an international scope, an inherent tension exists
between conceptions of ethics as a set of universal principles and ethics as con-
tingent norms relative to culture. The position adopted by researchers and review-
ers along the continuum between relativistic and universal ethics has practical
implications. The degree of credence, acceptance and personal endorsement
accorded to codes of ethics and guidelines intended to apply across national
boundaries depends on an individual’s beliefs regarding the balance between uni-
versalism and relativism or, from a more relativistic perspective, how well the
‘universal’ code of ethics fits with local custom.
Suggestions for approaches to the relativism issue in the international regula-
tion of medical research have ranged from the emphasis on uniform international
standards13 to stressing ethical procedure to negotiate the specific content of pro-
tocols.14 The ICNE adopts the intermediary position that general principles can
be articulated with sufficiently broad international support to offer a framework
for considering the various facets of the research process. Although providing a
useful guide, these principles would also allow sufficient latitude to negotiate
specific research activities when substantive variation in behavioural and ethical
norms exists between the researchers and the local population being recruited.
This is in accordance with Nagel’s idea that ‘[morality involves] occupying a
position far enough outside your own life to reduce the importance of difference
between your self and other people, yet not so far outside that all human values
vanish . . .’ (p. 222). 15
In endorsing the possibility of stating broad principles that can be widely
accepted across national and cultural boundaries, it is essential that we do not
assume that these principles are coincident with western values. Such ‘ethical
imperialism’ in medical research has been widely criticized. 16–18 In relation to
nursing, Davis states:
The use of western philosophical ethics, sifted through the USA’s cultural lens, as a
standard by which all else is compared, contrasted and judged, reflects a type of ethical
influence that may be harmful. This influence combines attitudes and actions that essen-
tially support the idea that all other people and cultures should have and use the same
values and ethics as are found in America (p. 123). 19
The ICNE suggests five broad principles to frame the initial discussion and
development of guidelines for the ethical conduct of international nursing
research: (1) respect for persons; (2) beneficence; (3) justice; (4) respect for com-
munity; and (5) contextual caring. To be useful in an international context, these
principles must be understood in the broadest sense as overarching ideals of
behaviour and not as prescriptive rules. The first three are the touchstones of the
western bioethics tradition 20 and are articulated with respect to research in the
Belmont Report.21 In this report the principle of ‘respect for autonomy’ is a key
feature to the implementation of ‘respect for persons.’ Although the principle of
respect for persons is inclusive enough to garner broad acceptance in the inter-
national community, the emphasis placed on respect for autonomy has been fre-
quently criticized as idiosyncratic to the West and the USA in particular.19,22 Thus
the ICNE follows the Belmont Report in ‘respect for persons’ without the speci-
fication that the chief method of showing respect for competent persons is to
respect their autonomy.
The next two suggested principles, beneficence and justice, are also part of
the standard Western canon.20,23,24 Beneficence, the principle that one should act
for the benefit of others, encompasses both maximizing positive good and mini-
mizing or preventing harm.21 In the context of research ethics, justice means fair
treatment of participants and communities, and the fair distribution of both the
benefits and burdens of research at individual and community levels.25
The fourth principle, respect for community, goes beyond the standard appli-
cation of western bioethics to the research situation requiring consideration of a
wider context than concern for the individual participant. Researchers and
research ethics committees should consider the effects of possible results on a
community’s self-conception, altered perceptions outside the community, changes
to health care delivery methods by implementing results or potential problems
with implementing results, as well as any effects on the entire community arising
from individual participation. This principle recognizes that ‘individualism (the
cornerstone of western nursing) may often be inappropriate where the concept of
individual rights does not exist’ (p. 222). 26 This principle should serve as a guide
for research in all countries and not be taken as a supplemental guide for con-
sidering research protocols only in nonwestern countries. Respect for community
is intended as a corrective to the overly intense focus on individual rights found
in most western guides to research ethics.
Although intrinsic tension can exist between the good of the individual and the
community, it cannot be said that the solution always resides in the priority of
one over the other. Always to value the good of the collective over the individ-
ual can lead to oppression,27 while always to give priority to the individual over
the community can lead to ethical isolation and the overemphasis of rights, as
boundaries, to the detriment of attention to relationships and responsibilities.
The final guiding principle, contextual caring, entreats the researcher to behave
towards each participant as a person within an ethical relationship of caring
concern grounded in the researcher ’s personal values. This differs from benefi-
cence, the abstract principle that one’s behaviour should be guided by the desire
to do good for others.20 In contextual caring one acts in accord with personal
caring concern for the concrete specific other within one’s immediate scope. The
call to caring behaviour is more difficult to prescribe than a beneficence because
it is more closely bound to an individual’s emotional reactions; however, there is
increasing recognition that emotion is inextricably bound to moral good.28,29 The
principle of caring concern encourages the consideration of what good can and
may be done for another to whom one feels responsible beyond the obligatory
dictates of what must and must not be done.30–33
However, considerations of respect for the community and the sense of unique
local perspective to which the researcher may not be privy must be balanced with
the researcher ’s scientific autonomy and integrity. Part of this balance would be
a consideration of why an outsider conducts this particular research in this par-
ticular locale: is it a matter of technical know-how in performing something for
the local community that they would otherwise do for themselves, or does the
researcher have some unique interest, possibly born from his or her position as
an outsider?
In an effort to build local capacity towards just and effective negotiations with
foreign researchers, one conceptual guide for a method to gain true consensus
between the parties is offered by Habermas’ 41 conditions of discourse:
All participants in the discourse must have the same chance to speak so that
at all times they may open and perpetuate discourse through address and
reply, question and answer.
All participants must have the same chance to put forward interpretations,
assertions, recommendations, explanations and justifications.
Discourse allows only for speakers who have an equal chance to express
views, feelings and wishes, and make them known without omission or decep-
tion.
All participants have an equal chance to employ regulative acts of speech, such
as to command, to resist, to allow, to forbid and to make and retract promises.
Foreign research efforts would be expected to work towards fulfilling these con-
ditions and for assessing progress by reference to the conditions.
The second condition for carrying out research using a population sample
outside one’s own country is the intention to generate knowledge of direct benefit
to the population from which the sample is drawn. This requirement helps to
prevent exploitation. Specific groups should not be targeted because of conve-
nience, particularly if the convenience is in the form of reduced regulatory
requirements or easy recruitment based on power differentials between the
researcher and the participants. The abuses of the Tuskegee study, in which the
natural progress of syphilis was allowed to continue in African-American men
after treatment was available, were made possible by such a power differential. 42
Local benefit is a well-established standard in guides to research on specific
populations (e.g. US regulations on using prisoners as participants 43) and guide-
lines for the use of international samples.1,3,40 This requirement has a fairly
straightforward application in clinical drug trials but it may require some reflec-
tion in the ethical justification of certain types of nursing research.
An honest declaration of local benefit further requires that any intervention that
may be shown to be successful is affordable and practical in the local milieu.
Although this stipulation is often applied to drug research, much nursing research
involves testing person-to-person interventions, which can also be economically
costly and may need to be implemented or administered by personnel with
training that is largely unavailable in the local community.
In nursing research where the objective is to learn more about cultural attitudes
and customs regarding health, it must be presumed that the intent is for that
knowledge to lead to better local health care. The connection between under-
standing a culture and giving quality nursing care will be direct in many studies;
examples are those by Åstedt-Kurki et al.44 and Konishi and Davis.45 However, in
some cases, the presumption of benefit through cultural understanding may be
inferential.
In meeting the third initial condition for conducting international nursing
research, the justification of targeting participants from another country, the fol-
lowing criteria should be considered: (1) the phenomenon under consideration is
biologically unique to that group or relates to a phenomenon that is biologically
unique to that group (e.g. thalassaemia, sickle cell anaemia); (2) the phenomenon,
although culturally mediated, is widely known to be group specific (e.g. the effect
of local diet or sexual practices); (3) there is an empirically demonstrated ratio-
nale for targeting a specific group (e.g. there is a demonstrated difference in inci-
dence, rate of detection or recovery); (4) extensive normative data exist that do
not include the targeted population – if it is reasonable to believe that the targeted
population may vary from the general population described by the data; or (5)
comparative data between groups would be helpful to mutual understanding or
in designing treatment, service delivery or education (e.g. efforts to understand
differences in ethical concepts cross-culturally).
western people to confront and, thus far, ethical guidelines and literature
considering international research ethics consistently include a strong endorse-
ment of individual informed consent.1,3,49,50
Obtaining proper informed consent, as it is conceived in the West, requires
shared assumptions about the nature of decision making, and at least some degree
of shared understanding of the meaning of the research and the nature of the
risks and benefits involved in the particular study. Reliance on informed consent
is problematic when the assumptions of researchers and participants differ in any
of these areas. Although the therapeutic misconception (a person’s belief that the
researcher is acting for his or her benefit in the manner expected of clinicians) fre-
quently occurs in the USA,51–53 the researchers participating in the NBAC study38
suggested a widespread occurrence of the therapeutic misconception in research
in developing nations. Some of these researcher participants noted that the word
‘research’ did not exist in the native language and was translated as ‘medicine’.38
With growing experience in cross-national research there has been increased
interest in potential alternative strategies, such as the consent of community
leaders.38 In the NBAC study of international researchers, 51% said they enrolled
participants with the consent of community leaders and 19% enrolled them with
the consent of a family member.38 In any arrangement where one person’s delib-
erations determine the inclusion of another person in a study, the possibility
of individual dissent presents a problem. Situations may occur where some
individuals, although acknowledging that either a collective or a paternalistic
decision-making process is their cultural norm, disagree with that norm and
prefer that the usual process should not hold sway over them. Culture is dynamic
and dissent fosters change. Women in many industrialized countries would not
be allowed to vote if dissent against cultural assumptions and accepted proce-
dural norms could not occur. Culture is not a fixed entity and individuals make
their own interpretation of cultural norms and the value of those norms.
Researchers and members of review committees must strike a balance between
overvaluing western ideals in the form of written, individually-signed informed
consent documents, while not supporting oppression in the name of cultural rel-
evancy. The use of a male family member to provide consent for a female
member’s participation because males in that culture are the sanctioned decision
makers presents such a dilemma.
Confidentiality
Control over the way one is viewed by others is a fundamental mechanism of
personal identity that sets the foundation for social relations. 55,56 Thus, the assur-
ance and maintenance of confidentiality in research serves both ethical and prac-
tical functions. Researchers respect participants by granting them control over
personal information and protecting them when they are vulnerable from unwar-
ranted revelations. This demonstrates researchers’ respect for both the participant
and the community. Confidentiality is also of practical concern because
researchers often seek information that participants would prefer to keep private
from the community at large; thus they will not reveal such information unless
the promise of confidentiality is credible. In this way researchers have a respon-
sibility not only to the individuals in a specific protocol but also to the culture,
community and future researchers for maintaining the credibility of assurances
of confidentiality.57
The embarrassment and shame that individuals experience when others
observe behaviours or personal characteristics that are considered to be aberrant
or undesirable lead them to seek privacy.58,59 Privacy also allows persons some
opportunity to express characteristics and desires that they do not wish revealed
to others. An inability to maintain some secrecy about aspects of the self can result
in a profound loss of identity.57 Despite variations in the content of what is con-
sidered as private, all cultures maintain and value this concept.60
The international research situation is problematic because norms in the assess-
ment of what embarrasses or shames vary considerably among cultures.58
Research ethics guidelines written from the western perspective deal with confi-
dentiality mostly in terms information and record keeping, generally echoing the
way in which medical records are handled. Western guidelines are also prob-
lematic because some cultures rely more on oral communication and tradition
than on written record keeping. Therefore, international researchers need to attend
to the broader concept of privacy, which encompasses confidentiality of informa-
tion as well as privacy of person. Such attention is particularly significant in
anthropological or other research that describes people, their behaviours or their
social environment.
In international research, researchers are inevitably outsiders who are
Conclusion
In general we advocate a flexibility of approach, an emphasis on the ethical
conduct of researchers, as driven by researchers’ responsibilities to the partici-
pants within a collaborative relationship, an attention to detail that demonstrates
respect for the local community (such as accurate translation and knowledge of
the local situation) through researchers’ own efforts and the judicious reliance on
local input. The goals of the ICNE here, as elsewhere, are twofold: to demonstrate
the possibility of a dialogue moving towards an ethical framework that is inclu-
sive enough to achieve widespread consensus; and to further that pursuit through
inclusion of the widest possible range of ethical paradigms from the international
community.
References
1
National Bioethics Advisory Commission. Ethical and policy issues in international research:
clinical trials in developing countries, 2 vols. Rockville, MD: US Government Printing Office,
2001. Available from: URL: http://www.georgetown.edu/research/nrcbl/nbac/pubs.html
[Accessed 30-Oct-2002]
2
Nuffield Council on Bioethics. The ethics of clinical research in developing countries. London:
Nuffield Council on Bioethics, 1999. Available from: URL: http://www.nuffieldbioethics.
org/filelibrary/pdf/clinicaldiscuss1.pdf [Accessed 30-Oct-2002]
3 Nuffield Council on Bioethics. The ethics of research related to healthcare in developing
countries. London: Nuffield Council on Bioethics, 2002. Available from: URL: http://
www.nuffieldbioethics.org/publications/developingcountries/rep0000000942.asp [Acessed
30-Oct-2002]
4 Joint United Nations Programme on HIV/AIDS. Ethical considerations in HIV preventive
vaccine research: UNAIDS guidance document. Geneva: UNAIDS, 2000. Available from: URL:
http://www.unaids.org/publications/documents/vaccines/vaccines/Ethicsresearch.pdf
[Accessed 30-Oct-2002]