4775-Article Text-15508-1-10-20240523
4775-Article Text-15508-1-10-20240523
4775-Article Text-15508-1-10-20240523
177
Amos Ameh Ichaba & Peter Adinoyi
Introduction
The 'mind-body problem' is the challenge of explaining how the mind and body
interact. What is a man? Is he only his physical body? Does he have a spiritual
aspect? Are mind and body distinct or identical? If distinct, how do they interact?
Are mind and brain the same? These are some of the puzzles that perplex us when we
try to grasp the intricacies of man. These questions which jointly constitute the
mind-body problem lie at the heart of philosophy of mind. The mind-body problem
is therefore, a philosophical puzzle about the nature and relation of the mind and the
body. It stems from Rene Descartes' 17th century view that the mind and the body
are two different substances that can exist separately. However, this raises the
question of how they can causally interact with each other.
Different philosophical theories have attempted to answer these questions in
various ways. Two main categories of such theories are dualism and monism.
Dualism holds that there are two distinct kinds of substances or entities in the world:
material and immaterial. The mind belongs to the immaterial category, while the
body belongs to the material category. Monism holds that there is only one kind of
substance or entity in the world, either material or immaterial. The mind and the
body are either both material or both immaterial. This view was first supported in
Western philosophy by Parmenides and later by Spinoza. There have been some
monist ideas of the mind, such as idealism and materialism. Materialism or
physicalism, is a view that matter is the basic thing in nature and everything,
including mind and consciousness, is caused by matter. This idea is different from
idealism, which says that everything is made of mental ideas or thoughts. Within
materialism are other theories like behaviourism, functionalism, identity theory or
central state materialism which says that mental states are the same as physical
states of the brain or nervous system.
Behaviourism is a materialist theory of mind that rejects the idea of the mind
as an object. It says that having a mind means behaving or having dispositions to
178
NJPS Vol. 3, No. 1, 2024 ISSN: Online - 2971 - 5296 Prints - 2971 - 5288
behave in certain physical ways. Gilbert Ryle is a key supporter of this theory. He
thinks that the mind is not a 'mysterious internal realm' like Descartes' spiritual
substance, but just part of the physical behaviour.
The focus of this essay is on the theory of mind with particular reference to
central state materialism. Its major proponents include: Herbert Feigl, Paul
Feyerabend, U.T. Place, Hilary Putnam, J. J. C. Smart and David Malet Armstrong.
Amongst these central state materialists, we shall dwell on David M. Armstrong's
version, which combines elements from Descartes' dualism and Gilbert Ryle's
behaviourism. Armstrong argues that mental states and processes are nothing but
physical states and processes of the central nervous system, but that they also have
dispositional properties that explain their causal relations with behaviour. He also
contends that there are no good philosophical reasons for denying that humans are
entirely physical beings. It is left to be seen in this paper the extent to which
Armstrong's theory is formidable and relevant in contemporary times.
Materialist Theories of Mind
The bid to resolve the mind-body problem successfully led to the emergence of two
main materialist theories of mind, namely: behaviourism and the central state theory
or identity theory of mind. These materialist theories made tenable and viable by the
radical advancements in science, have today become popular amongst
contemporary philosophers in responding to the problem of how the mind and body
interact. Furthermore, in these theories, the mind is no longer seen as a spiritual
entity or as an entity distinct from the body, but rather the mind is explained in purely
physical terms. In what follows, the behaviourist and central state theory of mind
will be examined with reference to the types and also their proponents after which a
groundwork for understanding David Armstrong's theory of mind would have
already been laid.
179
Amos Ameh Ichaba & Peter Adinoyi
Behaviourism
According to Raymond Osei, behaviourism, as a philosophical theory of the
mind sprang from one of the cognitive sciences – psychology.1 Moreover, in the 19th
century, psychology was seen as the science of conscious phenomena. Here, man
was studied by analogy and by examining his thoughts and feelings through a
process called introspection.
Behaviourism came about as a reaction to the 19th-century idealist approach
of psychology. Behaviourists considered the concept of consciousness to be
mysterious, elusive and too hard to understand or define. In addition, they argued
that 'consciousness' was neither a definable nor a usable concept; that it was merely
another word for the 'soul' of more ancient times. Similarly, they rejected the idealist
approach of introspection as being too subjective and prone to discrepancies
between individual researchers, which could result in conflicting results. To avoid
this issue and ensure objectivity in the study of human beings, behaviourists chose
to focus on observable actions or behaviours instead. There are two types of
behaviourism, namely, logical behaviourism and psychological behaviourism.
Psychological Behaviourism: Psychological behaviourism is attributed to John
Watson and Burrhus Skinner. It tries to explain mental phenomena in terms of the
relation between observable behavioural inputs (the stimuli) and outputs (the
responses to the stimuli). John Watson is the founder of behaviourism. His 1913
paper “Psychology as the behaviourist views it” is the manifesto of early
behaviourism. Watson declared that psychology is a purely objective science that
aims to predict and control behaviour, and introspection has no role in its methods.
Watson rejected the idealist method of introspection and detailed his inquiry on
what psychology should be – the science of behaviour, which he called
2
'behaviourism'. Burrhus F. Skinner, taking a departure from the thought of Watson
Skinner, aimed to give psychology a scientific status by studying the link between
1. Raymond Oseyi, The Mind-Body Problem in Philosophy: An Analysis of the Core Issues
(Ibadan: Hope Publications Ltd, 2006), 87.
2. John Watson, “Psychology as the Behaviourist Views It.” Psychological Review 20, no. 2
180
NJPS Vol. 3, No. 1, 2024 ISSN: Online - 2971 - 5296 Prints - 2971 - 5288
behaviour and environment. He was of the opinion that human actions were
responses to stimuli and could be predicted and controlled through environmental
study.³
Logical Behaviourism: Logical behaviourism, which is also called analytical or
philosophical behaviourism falls under the monist school of thought on the mind
and explains mental states in terms of behaviour, unlike psychological
behaviourism which explains human behaviour in response to stimuli. Logical
behaviourism is called “philosophical” to distinguish it from the kind of
behaviourism that is done in psychology. It is called “logical” or “analytic” because
it expresses the thesis of behaviourism in terms of the logical relation between
mental terms and behavioural terms.
Logical behaviourism, according to Raymond Osei, is therefore a “thesis
that tries to explain how it is possible for sentences that contain mental terms like
'thought', 'belief', 'image' or 'memory' to be translated into public observable
behaviour.4 From the foregoing, we can infer that philosophical behaviourism is a
thesis that claims that we can analyse mental concepts in terms of concepts that
relate to the body, and in particular, the concept of 'behaviour'. This thesis is often
attributed to the British philosopher, Gilbert Ryle.
The Logical Behaviourism of Gilbert Ryle
Gilbert Ryle was a British philosopher, principally known for his critique of
Cartesian dualism. According to Julia Tanney, Ryle, in his book, The Concept of
Mind, is thought to have accomplished two major tasks. “First, he was seen to have
put the final nail in the coffin of Cartesian dualism. Second, he was said to have
5
suggested as dualism's replacement, the theory called analytical behaviourism.” .
Ryle was in some ways influenced by Ludwig Wittgenstein, who held that
many philosophical problems were caused by the misuse of language. Thus, it is no
wonder that Ryle adduced that philosophers like Plato and Descartes, misused
ordinary language and created an unwarranted dichotomy between mind and body.
As earlier noted, Descartes saw the mind to be an immaterial substance and the body
to be a material substance, yet he also asserted that the mind controlled the body in
some way. Ryle criticized this idea as the 'ghost in the machine' fallacy.6 Ryle
questioned how a non-physical mind could impact a physical body, and his critique
aimed to expose the mistake behind this philosophical puzzle.
Ryle argues that considering the mind as a non-physical entity embedded in
the body is a 'category-mistake', which involves mistakenly attributing properties
from one class to concepts of another class.7 Descartes committed this error by
conflating the categories of mind and body. He failed to recognize that the terms
'mind' and 'body' belong to distinct categories. To clearly explain what he meant by
category mistake, Ryle gave an illustration:
A foreigner visiting Oxford or Cambridge for the first time is shown
a number of colleges, libraries, playing fields, museums, scientific
departments and administrative offices. But yet asks; 'but where is
the University'? He makes a category mistake. The visitor treats the
university as if it were part of the category of buildings, rather than
what it actually is: a collection of institutions.⁸
Similarly, Ryle argues that people also make category mistakes when they try to
explain the mind as if it were a separate entity from the body, when in fact the mind is
the result of the activities of the brain.
182
NJPS Vol. 3, No. 1, 2024 ISSN: Online - 2971 - 5296 Prints - 2971 - 5288
Ryle does not expressly give an account of what the mind is. However, he
asserts that the mind, like the concept of university as illustrated above, is a
construction out of some more basic kind of things. These basic things are what he
calls mental states. Hence, he asserts that just as explaining what colleges are, is
enough to explain what university is, so too, explaining mental states, is enough to
explain what the mind is. Thus, as noted by David Chalmers, when a person has been
told about thinking, imagining, believing, knowing, desiring choosing and so on,
but still asks “what is the mind?”, Ryle asserts that he will be making mistake of
thinking that the mind is an entity different from what he has been told.
Consequently, according to Napoleon Mabaquiao, Ryle asserts that to talk of
mental states and processes is to talk not only of actual behaviour, but also of
'dispositions' to behave in certain ways. For him, “behaviours are actual when they
are currently being exhibited, whereas they are dispositional when they are yet to be
exhibited by someone who is inclined to exhibit them.”9 Ryle also maintained that
mental concepts have no meaning on their own and only derive their meaning from
observable behaviour.10 In other words, mental states can only be understood in
relation to how people act or are likely to act.
Furthermore, Raymond Osei opines that in giving an account of
dispositions, Ryle defines dispositions as how something will behave under
11
certain circumstances, without attributing them to inner states. Mental
concepts are therefore dispositional and not causal, and it is a mistake to see
them as denoting categorical causes. When we say someone has a certain
disposition, we mean that certain conditional sentences are true of them, such as
'if I am about to go out, then I will pick my umbrella.'
9. Napoleon Mabaquiao, Mind, Science and Computation (Quezon: Vibal publishing House
Inc, 2012), 25.
10. Ryle, The Concept of Mind, 93
11. Oseyi, The Mind-Body Problem in Philosophy, 92
183
Amos Ameh Ichaba & Peter Adinoyi
14. Ullin Place, “Is Consciousness a Brain Process?” British Journal of Psychology 47, no. 1
(1956): 48-49.
185
Amos Ameh Ichaba & Peter Adinoyi
Which is the mistake of supposing that when someone describes his or her
experience, he or she is describing the literal properties of mental states.
Commenting on the above, Jullian Leslie affirms that Place thinks that we
should stop assuming that we only know what is in our minds, and start thinking that
we experience things and events in the world rather than in our heads.16 Only then
we can agree that brain processes and what we say about our mental processes are
related. Thus, according to Armstrong, Place maintained that seeing a green after-
image is not having something green. Instead, “when we describe the after-image as
green… we are saying that we are having the sort of experience which we normally
have when and which we have learned to describe as looking at a patch of green
light.17 It is this experience Place contends, that is to be identified with a brain
process.
J. J. C. Smart
According to Steven Schneider, John Jamieson Carswell Smart, popularly
known as Jack Smart was a British-Australian Philosopher. He is known to have
further developed the identity theory of mind in his paper “Sensations and Brain
Processes”. His theory was inspired by the identity theory proposed by Ullin Place.
Like Place, Smart also applied his theory to mental concepts that analytic
behaviourism could not explain well, such as sensations, mental imagery, and
experience.
As remarked by Shanjendu Nath, Smart argued against two ideas. One, that
physics can explain everything except sensations and consciousness. Two, that the
mind and the body are different things; one spiritual and one physical. He used
16. Jullian Leslie, “Broad and Deep, but always Rigorious: Some Appreciative Reflections on
Ullin Place's Contributions to Behaviour Analysis.” Behaviour and Philosophy 29 (2001):
161.
17. David Armstrong, The Mind-Body Problem: An Opinionated Introduction (New York:
Routledge, 2018), 7
187
Amos Ameh Ichaba & Peter Adinoyi
But it is a way of talking about a process, and that process happens in the brain.
David Armstrong's Theory of Mind
David Armstrong's theory of mind, which is the Central State theory of mind
is quite unique as it tries to give a comprehensive materialistic account of all mental
states; a feat that prior materialist theories of mind failed to achieve. By synthesizing
two diverse views of mind – Rene Descartes' dualism and Gilbert Ryle's analytic
behaviourism, Armstrong gives a new touch to the identity theory or central state
theory. Banking on the modified theory, Armstrong uses a causal analysis and an
empirical identification to present a materialist account of mind. In what follows, an
attempt will be made to expose Armstrong's central state theory, making reference to
his account of the nature of mental states, nature of dispositions, the movements of
his central state theory and nature of consciousness.
David Armstrong and the Authority of Science
As earlier noted, Armstrong was interested in the mind-body problem, and
being a materialist, was determined to resolve the problem by giving a complete
analysis of man in purely physical terms. This he thought would be possible only
through science. Indeed, Armstrong argued that the achievements recorded in the
sciences pointed towards the possibility of explaining man in purely physical terms.
He contended that scientists and philosophers who resisted this idea, did so because
of their philosophical or moral or religious prejudices. Armstrong further noted that
in the future, new evidences and new problems may come to light that will make
science reconsider the physico-chemical view of man. However, he maintained that
the drift of scientific thought in present times was clearly set towards the physico-
chemical hypothesis.
Moving forward, Armstrong posed these questions: why should we concede
science a special authority to decide questions about the nature of man? What of the
authority of philosophy, of religion, of morality, or even of literature and art? Why
189
Amos Ameh Ichaba & Peter Adinoyi
do I set the authority of science above all these? Why this "scientism"? His answer
was simple – that science, despite its occasional mistakes provided the only tool to
achieve intellectual consensus about contentious issues. He maintained that other
non-scientific disciplines were yet to achieve such consensus.20 Consequently,
Steven Schneider remarks that, Armstrong decided to ply the route of science to
address the mind-body problem which had lingered on for years. Adopting straight
away the scientific view that humans are nothing more than physico-chemical
mechanisms, Armstrong declared that the task for philosophy was to work out an
account of the mind which is compatible with this view. He therefore embarked on
the journey to formulate an account of the mind that would be compatible with the
materialist's view of science.
David Armstrong's Concept of a Mental State
The early precursors of the identity theory or central state theory – U.T Place
and J.J.C Smart, developed their theories solely for mental states such as conscious
experiences and sensations. They opined that these mental states could be reduced
to specific brain patterns of neural activity in the brain. However, when it came to
other mental states such as beliefs or desires, they took a more behaviourist
approach. In contrast, David Armstrong sought to provide a general account of all
mental states, since he was of the opinion that all mental states could be reduced to
the central state of the nervous system. Similarly, Armstrong asserted that Place and
Smart's identity theories could not be applied to all mental states because they were
primarily concerned with identifying the specific neural activity or brain state that
gave rise to a particular mental state. In other words, they were interested in the
stimulus that caused mental state. For instance, Smart wrote:
When a person says, 'I see a yellowish-orange after-image', he is
saying something like this: 'There is something going on which is
20. David Armstrong, “Epistemological Foundations for a Materialist Theory of the Mind.”
Philosophy of Science 40, no. 2 (1973): 180.
190
NJPS Vol. 3, No. 1, 2024 ISSN: Online - 2971 - 5296 Prints - 2971 - 5288
like what is going on when I have my eyes open, am awake, and there
is an orange illuminated in good light in front of me, that is, when I
really see an orange.'21
Here, the having of an orange after-image is explicated in terms of the stimulus: an
orange acting on a person in suitable conditions. Place used a similar approach.
Thus, their approach did not account for the response that followed from a mental
state. In other words, their approach did not explain how mental states could
causally interact with the physical world. In contrast, Armstrong's central state
theory focused on both stimulus and response. He maintained that mental states
were caused by central states of the nervous system but that mental states also had
causal efficacy in producing behaviour, which he considered was the response.22
In the light of the above, Armstrong asserted that “the concept of a mental
state essentially involved, and was exhausted by, the concept of a state that is apt to
23
be the cause of certain effects or apt to be the effect of certain causes.” However,
this conception of Armstrong did not arise just like that. It was greatly influenced by
Descartes' dualism and Gilbert Ryle's analysis of dispositions.
The Movements of David Armstrong's Central State Theory
According to Stephen Mumford, Armstrong's central-state theory involves a
two-stage argument or rather two distinct 'movements'. Armstrong maintains that
the first step involves a logical analysis of mental concepts. This is a conceptual
thesis. It is also called the Causal analysis of mind. It does not entail, but neither does
it exclude, materialism. The second step of the argument is to identify these inner
states with physico-chemical states of the brain. This is a contingent or scientific
identification, and it yields Central-state Materialism.
21. Jack Smart, “Sensations and Brain Processes.” The Philosophical Review 68, No. 2.
(1959): 142.
22. Armstrong, Nature of Mind, 20
23. Armstrong, “Epistemological Foundations for a Materialist Theory of the Mind.” 180
191
Amos Ameh Ichaba & Peter Adinoyi
25. David Armstrong, A Materialist Theory of the Mind (New York: Routledge, 1968), 209
26. Oseyi, The Mind-Body Problem in Philosophy, 109
193
Amos Ameh Ichaba & Peter Adinoyi
the causal analysis does not disclose the ontic nature of the mind.27 Thus, for
Armstrong, since the ontic nature of the mind cannot be fleshed by a conceptual
analysis alone, the question then is to consider what empirical grounds sustain the
identification of mental states with brain states.
The Identification of Mind and Brain
The second step of David Armstrong's argument for his central state theory
involves a scientific identification. Consequently, Armstrong opened this discourse
by noting that this empirical step in his argument had already been defended at
length, by a number of writers such as Ullin Place and Jack Smart. For instance, in
the identification of the mind and brain, Place used the following as his model
statement: "Lightning is an electric discharge". He opined that the 'is' in the
statement was the 'is' of composition. In other words, that the terms on either side of
the 'is' referred to the same thing. Finally, Place maintained that just as “Lightning is
28
an electric discharge” so too 'consciousness is a brain process'. However,
Armstrong maintained that Place's model statement was inadequate as it failed to
capture the point about causal role.
Thus, Armstrong being influenced by the Australian Materialist, Brian
Medlin, went on to assert that the statement: “The gene is the DNA molecule” was
the sort of model that the Causal theory required. Indeed, Armstrong noted that just
as mental states are states of the person defined solely in terms of causal relations to
the objects or situations that bring the mental states about and the physical behaviour
that constitutes their expression, in the same way, genes are defined solely in terms
of their causal relations to hereditary characteristics. These hereditary
characteristics could be said to be the 'expressions' of the genes and for Armstrong,
there are good theoretical scientific evidence to identify genes with the DNA
molecule at the centre of living cells.
27. Armstrong, The Mind-Body Problem, 355
28. Place, “Is Consciousness a Brain Process?” 45
194
NJPS Vol. 3, No. 1, 2024 ISSN: Online - 2971 - 5296 Prints - 2971 - 5288
Armstrong's final submission is that once it was affirmed that the concept of
a mental state is the concept of a state of the person apt for the production of certain
sorts of behaviour, the identification of these states with physico-chemical states of
the brain was, nearly as good a bet as the identification of the gene with the DNA
molecule.
David Armstrong on the Nature of Consciousness
Finally, to end the account of his central state theory, Armstrong considers an
objection to his view of the mind; an objection which he says is shared by a good
number of philosophers. Thereafter, he proceeds to show how the objection can be
met. Armstrong asserts that the objection to his theory is that his view of mind as an
inner principle apt for bringing about certain sorts of behaviour, would be a
satisfactory account of the mind from an 'other-person' point of view, but will not do
as a first-person account. To neutralize this objection, Armstrong makes special
reference to the mental state – 'perception' and building on his causal analysis of this
mental state, he posits that we should consider consciousness as an awareness
(perception) of inner mental states by the person whose states they are. In other
words, consciousness is a further mental state, a state 'directed' towards the original
inner states. To buttress this point, he writes:
If I perceive a physical situation, then we have an inner mental state
'directed' in a certain way towards a certain physical situation. Now,
if I am aware, not only of the physical situation, but also of the fact
that I am perceiving, then we have a further mental state 'directed' in
the same sort of way towards the original mental state. And if this
further mental state, which qua mental state is simply a state of the
person apt for the production of certain behaviour, can be
contingently identified with a state of the brain, it will be a process in
which one part of the brain scans another part of the brain. In
perception, the brain scans the environment. In awareness of the
195
Amos Ameh Ichaba & Peter Adinoyi
29. Armstrong, “Epistemological Foundations for a Materialist Theory of the Mind”, 178
30. Armstrong, The Mind-Body Problem
196
NJPS Vol. 3, No. 1, 2024 ISSN: Online - 2971 - 5296 Prints - 2971 - 5288
brain. For example, studies have shown that different emotional states such as fear,
happiness, and anger correspond to specific patterns of neural activation in certain
brain regions. This suggests that mental states and processes are not independent of
physical states and processes in the brain, but are instead rooted in them as
Armstrong has opined.
Another strength of Armstrong theory is its simplicity. Armstrong's Central
state theory offers a simpler explanation of the mind-body problem than other
theories, such as dualism or idealism. By reducing mental states to physical states in
the brain, Armstrong's theory eliminates the need to posit a separate, non-physical
realm of existence for mental states. This is consistent with Ockham's razor, which
states that the simplest explanation is usually the best one.
Another strength of Armstrong's theory is that it provides a compelling
explanation for how mental causation can occur. Mental causation is the idea that
mental states can cause physical events in the world. Early proponents of the central
state theory like U.T Place and J.J.C Smart did not address this issue. They simply
identified mental states with processes without showing how mental states can
cause physical events in the world. Conversely, Armstrong's theory provides an
account of how mental causation can occur. For example, in Armstrong's theory,
when I want to pick up a pen, my desire to pick up the pen causes a specific pattern of
neural activity in my brain. This neural activity, in turn, causes the behaviour of my
arm moving in a certain way. In this way, mental causation is reduced to physical
causation. Thus, in the theory, mental events are simply a subset of physical events,
and their causal powers are explained in terms of physical processes.
Furthermore, according to Armstrong, Central state materialism avoids the
interaction problem, which is the difficulty in explaining how mental states and
processes interact with physical states and processes in the brain. Dualism, for
example, posits that mental states and processes are separate from physical states
and processes, which makes it difficult to explain how they interact with each other.
197
Amos Ameh Ichaba & Peter Adinoyi
Armstrong's theory on the other hand, explains that mental states and processes are
simply the result of physical states and processes in the brain, and therefore there is
no need to posit a separate realm of existence for mental phenomena.
Thus, as noted by Stephen Mumford, in Armstrong's theory, there is the
unity of mind and body. The mind and body are parts of a unified whole as the mind
is identified with some part of the body. However, the mind is not identified with
body parts such as the feet or the navel, but it is identified with those parts that
biologists pick out as the central nervous system.
The Downside of David Armstrong's Theory of The Mind
Despite the contributions made by Armstrong to the philosophical discourse
about the mind, his central state theory has been criticized by different philosophers
on different grounds.
First, Hilary Putnam avers that Armstrong's central state materialism is
faced with the problem of multiple realizability. Multiple realizability refers to the
idea that the same mental or physical phenomenon can be realized by different
underlying physical or biological and non-biological systems. For example, in
Armstrong's theory, pain is viewed as a particular pattern of neural activity in the
brain. However, Putnam argues that this is not the case because pain could also be
realized in other physical systems that do not have brains, such as a computer
simulation of a brain or a robot that is programmed to respond to harmful stimuli.
This implies that pain is not just based on the physical features of brain activity, but
rather comes from a more general functional structure of the system.
Another objection to Armstrong's central state theory, is its inability to
adequately account for qualia. Qualia, are the subjective qualities of conscious
experience; they are often described as the 'what it is like' of an experience, such as
the way a particular colour looks or the way a certain taste feels.31 Armstrong did
well in accounting for consciousness in his theory; he saw it as “perception or
31. Frank Jackson, “David Malet Armstrong (1926–2014).” Routledge Encyclopaedia of
Philosophy. https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/biographical/armstrong-david-malet-
1926-2014/v-1. Accessed 30/12/2022
198
NJPS Vol. 3, No. 1, 2024 ISSN: Online - 2971 - 5296 Prints - 2971 - 5288
awareness of the state of our own mind, or a self-scanning system in the central
nervous system.”2 However, he did not account for subjective aspect of
consciousness – he did not account for qualia. Proponents of this objection against
Armstrong's theory include Frank Jackson and Thomas Nagel. Frank Jackson's
argument against central state materialism is known as the 'knowledge argument for
qualia'. He argues that even if we had a complete understanding of the physical
processes in the brain that underlie colour perception, for example, we would still
not know what it is like to experience the colour red. In other words, there is
something about the subjective experience of seeing red that cannot be reduced to or
explained by the physical activity of the brain. Similarly, Thomas Nagel in his essay
“What Is it Like to Be a Bat?” argues that there is something fundamentally
subjective about the experience of being a conscious being, and that this subjective
element cannot be reduced to or explained by physical processes alone.
As earlier noted, in Armstrong's theory, the mind and its processes are
reduced to and explained by the physical processes that occur in the brain. This
materialistic approach to understanding the mind has often been seen as
incompatible with religious values, which often posit the existence of a non-
physical, spiritual realm that is separate from the physical world. As such,
Armstrong's theory has been criticized by some for its potential to undermine
religious beliefs and values. The materialistic worldview that Armstrong's theory
espouses can be seen as fostering an atheistic society since it suggests that there is no
need to appeal to the supernatural to explain the world and its workings.
Another argument against Armstrong's theory is that from inadequacy of
science. As earlier stated, Armstrong noted that he utilized science in formulating
his theory because it was the sole discipline capable of arriving at a consensus on
what was factual. He further argued that individuals in the scientific and
philosophical communities who opposed this notion did so due to their moral,
200
NJPS Vol. 3, No. 1, 2024 ISSN: Online - 2971 - 5296 Prints - 2971 - 5288
201
Amos Ameh Ichaba & Peter Adinoyi
https://www.thoughtco.com/behaviorism-in-psychology-4171770.
Accessed November 18, 2022.
Mabaquiao, Napoleon. Mind, Science and Computation. Quezon: Vibal publishing
House Inc, 2012.
Nath, Shanjendu. “Behaviourism as a Precursor of Identity Theory of Mind.”
International Journal of Scientific and Research Publications 3, no.6
(2013): 1-7.
Omoregbe, Joseph. Philosophy of Mind: An Introduction to Philosophical
Psychology. Lagos: Joja Educational Research and Publishers, 2001.
Osei, Raymond. The Mind-Body Problem in Philosophy: An Analysis of the Core
Issues. Ibadan: Hope Publications Ltd, 2006.
Place, Ullin. “Is Consciousness a Brain Process?” British Journal of Psychology 47,
no. 1 (1956): 44-50.
Ryle, Gilbert. The Concept of Mind. New York: Routledge, 2009.
Smart, Jack. “Sensations and Brain Processes.” The Philosophical Review 68, No.
2. (1959): 141-156.
Tanney, Julia. “Gilbert Ryle”, The Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy (Summer
2 0 2 2 E d i t i o n ) , E d w a r d N . Z a l t a ( e d . ) ,
https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2022/entries/ryle/. Accessed
28/11/2022.
Watson, John. “Psychology as the Behaviourist Views It.” Psychological Review
20, no. 2 (1913): 158-177.
202