0% found this document useful (0 votes)
10 views

Tensions in Calvin

Uploaded by

ROLDAN
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as DOCX, PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
10 views

Tensions in Calvin

Uploaded by

ROLDAN
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as DOCX, PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 7

ensions in Calvin’s Idea of Predestination

BY WING-HUNG LAM




A couple of weeks ago I had an opportunity of talking with a friend about the credibility of the
Christian faith. When the conversation became somewhat personal, he bluntly said: ‘You don’t
need to urge me to consider Christianity. I know there is a thing called ‘predestination’ in your
religion. Now, if I am elected by God, I will be saved with or without your persuasion. If I am
not chosen to heaven, why waste your time to convince me of the Christian belief? In either way,
human effort has little place.’ The theological implication of this comment is significant.

Many an educated evangelical layman knows that the doctrine of predestination has a strong
advocate in John Calvin, the sixteenth-century Protestant reformer. But not many are familiar
with the strength and the weakness of his theology of predestination which is a central theme in
the era of Reformation. As Philip Schaff, a prolific church historian, has observed: ‘All the
Reformers of the sixteenth century, … under a controlling sense of human depravity and saving
grace, in extreme antagonism to Pelagianism and self-righteousness, and … in full harmony not
only with the greatest of the fathers, but also with the inspired St Paul, came to the same doctrine
of a double predestination which decides the eternal destiny of all men.’1 In this essay we attempt
to analyse several areas of tension in Calvin’s thought.

In the first edition of Calvin’s Institutes of the Christian Religion in 1536, the doctrine of
predestination is only briefly discussed in connection with the Apostle’s Creed and the definition
of the church. During his exile in Strasbourg, Calvin expanded his concept which betrays his
Augustinianism and attentive reading of Martin Bucer’s Commentary on the Epistle to the
Romans. In the final edition of the Institutes in 1559, the setting of the doctrine is changed but
not the essential content. Certainly, Calvin’s controversies with Bolsec, Pighius, Melanchthon,
and Castellio over the years had enriched his thought.

Calvin regarded soteriological predestination as God’s eternal decree, by which he compacted


with himself what he willed to become of each man. For all are not created in equal condition:
rather, eternal life is fore-ordained for some, eternal damnation for others. Therefore, as any man
has been created to one or the other of these ends, we speak of him as predestined to life or to
death.2

The logical counterpart of election is reprobation, since election cannot, in Calvin’s view, stand
unless it is set over against reprobation. He continued:

God is said to set apart those whom he adopts into salvation; it will be highly absurd to say that
others acquire by chance or by their own effort what election alone confers on a few. Therefore,
whom God passes over, he condemns: and this he does for no other reason than that he wills to
exclude them from the inheritance which he predestines for his own children.3

Theological tensions in the idea of predestination are contained in his definition of the doctrine.
And in Calvin’s exposition the motivation in resolving them is easily recognizable.

The first tension is epistemological. Since the decree is eternal, how can we identify the God-
favoured or the God-condemned? In the Institutes of 1539 Calvin warned against wishing to
know too much about the mystery of predestination, probably as a reply to Zwingli’s The
Providence of God. He acknowledged the incomprehensibility of God but not divine
unknowability. However, he disapproved Melanchthon’s fear that investigation of the subject
would harm the faith of believers. It is wrong to expound only that part of the doctrine
understandable to our mind in order to make it more acceptable as if God’s honour were
protected by our hiding the truth. He was willing to go as far as scriptural revelation allowed.

Predestination, in Calvin’s thought, is an article of faith, and reprobation, a doctrine of the elect.
The non-elect never know that they are the reprobate. The logical opposite of the grace of
salvation is known only to the believer who has experienced redemption, from which perspective
the double decree is to be viewed. Every age has its number of reprobate. Calvin never spoke
specifically of the reprobate in the present or future tense. Even Michael Servetus, who was
burned at the stake in Geneva, was not regarded as such in his time. It is sacrilegious to exclude
from the number of the chosen a sinner as being already lost. Calvin taught a ‘certain judgment
of charity’ that Christians should consider as elect those who profess faith in Christ. From the
inspiration of St Augustine’s The City of God, Calvin admitted that the reprobate will dwell side
by side with the elect until the Day of Judgment.

How is election confirmed? Although it is impossible to be certain of the electing activity of


God, assurance can be secured in Christ. The grace of election is where Christ is. Calvin
regarded Christ as the ‘mirror of election’ in whom to contemplate our predestination. He did not
imply a passive role occupied by Christ, for Christ also ‘claims for himself, in common with the
Father, the right to choose’.4 No human factor would have influenced the electing process or
would undo the benefits of it. Both Scripture and the sacraments of the church are objective
evidences of Christ’s presence in the community of the elect, and the prompting of the Holy
Spirit enlightens and convinces us of its reality. Thus divine election is to be apprehended by
faith in the gospel, but not dependent upon it. Calvin pointed out two misconceptions regarding
faith: ‘Some make man God’s co-worker, to ratify election by his consent’ and others ‘make
election depend upon faith, as if it were doubtful and also ineffectual unless confirmed by
faith.’5 When he spoke of faith, he often came back to the conviction that the elect cannot lose
their salvation, for Christ will not let his members be estranged from him.

The second tension in Calvin’s doctrine is: If God foreordained every event to happen, is he the
author of evil in reprobation? This question involves the relation of predestination to providence,
foreknowledge, and causality.
Predestination presupposes providence, and in Calvin there is a remarkable continuity between
the two. The notion of providence means that God’s rule is extended to all parts of the world by
his infinite wisdom and justice. Some medieval theologians, like Thomas Aquinas, regarded
predestination as a particular application of the universal providence to the redemptive activity of
God. Calvin saw the unifying cause of all phenomena in an omnipotent and omniscient deity,
who is the author and consummator of all things. For ‘not only the heaven and the earth and the
inanimate creatures, but also the plans and intentions of men, are so governed by his providence
that they are borne by it straight to their appointed end’ (Institutes. I, 16, 8).

In late medieval time, the nominalist idea of potentia absoluta and potentia ordinata of God was
popular. This signified divine, gratuitous mercy according to which ‘he chose, absolutely free
from external interference, undetermined by any cause whatever apart from himself, to accept
man’s moral virtue as meritorious for his salvation’.6 God does not impart salvation without
merits. Man’s free will should decide between good and evil. And predestination depends on
divine knowledge of man’s future response. To help man attain personal virtues God has
graciously assisted him to do his best. On the principle that the end includes the means, Thomas
Aquinas held that predestination of the individual to eternal life includes in it all necessary
graces and qualifications as effects, not causes, of predestination. In Thomas’s view, God
predestines grace to the elect that they may merit glory. Following this tradition, Pighius,
Calvin’s contemporary, argued that the reprobate are those foreknown by God to be unworthy of
his goodness. This was the case with God’s discrimination between Esau and Jacob.

But in Calvin’s understanding, foreknowledge does not mean prior in time but transcendent in
time. God operates in the realm of eternity, which is qualitatively, not quantitatively, different
from the temporal continuum. He embraces the entire human history in his eternal present. This
simultaneous knowledge implies that God does not make a decision at some past moment and
then, after an interval, brings it into action. Only human activity goes this way. God does not
only conceive events through ideas but ‘he truly looks upon them and discerns them as things
placed before him’.7 He is no passive observer of events to occur.

Like foreknowledge, predestination is not to be understood in temporal terms. It does not depend
on foreknowledge. Both belong to God, and it is preposterous to represent one as contingent
upon the other. No causal connection between foreknowledge and predestination can be
established, whether this foreknowledge is of human merits or of divine grace imparted to man.
To say that predestination is conditioned by foreknowledge is to introduce an indirect human
factor, outside the divine intellect, that will destroy the absoluteness of the sovereign will.

Calvin maintained two important premises regarding foreknowledge and causality. First,
foreknowledge is properly so called only if what it foreknows happens. Secondly, purely on the
level of foreknowledge, no causal necessity is imposed on men. These two assertions exposed
Calvin to the criticism, launched by Jerome Bolsec, that he had made God the author of sin. As
Bolsec argued, the grace of God enlightens every man, enabling him to believe in Christ if he
wishes. The cause of predestination, conceived by God in eternity, is not to be found in God’s
will but in man’s work. Election and reprobation are divine confirmation of human response.
The whole issue has much to do with the meaning of causality in Calvin’s double decree.
Predestination, according to his definition, is an a priori, exclusive business within the triune
Godhead. It is an eternal decision for the eternal destiny of each human individual. Nothing
about the temporal world is yet mentioned. Viewing from this perspective, the question, Is God
the author of evil? is wrongly asked, because it is an a posteriori question, taking the ethics of
human history into consideration. Sin and evil are categories of the created order, and they
cannot be applied to the Creator. If man were to peep into the realm of divine logic, he would
from that standpoint comprehend the rationale of the divine decree. However, to say this much
was not enough to silence his foes in the controversial situation of Calvin’s day.

Calvin continued to point out two kinds of causality. Primary causality belongs to God alone, an
activity beyond external interference. This causality is different from the human understanding
of cause and effect, such as smoke coming from fire. Predestination has been wrongly regarded
as a projection of this kind of rational causality to the divine plan. Understood in this manner,
when God reprobates some to damnation, he cannot escape the title of being the author of evil.
But Calvin’s view of primary causation is different. He admitted his ignorance of, and forbids
any human inquiry into, the eternal and concealed counsel of God in predestination. The question
‘Is God the author of evil?’ is a challenge to God’s primary causality, which Calvin could not
answer logically. He only dogmatically defended the wholesomeness of the first cause by
affirming that God’s will is just and that God is not the author of evil. He appealed to the holy
and gracious nature of deity rather than the consistency of human logic which he disparaged as
invalid description of the eternal purpose.

However, when predestination is to be preached and historical contingency is considered,


another kind of causality comes into play: proximate causality. God displays his power through
secondary media and his power is never separated from these media. In rebutting Pighius, Calvin
argued that the origin of man’s ruin was in Adam and that each man finds the proximate cause of
his ruin in himself. There is no parallel treatment between election and reprobation. In election
there is a direct relation between God and man. But in reprobation, there is a proximate factor in
the process. A judicial element is present which has no counterpart in election.8 Election
presupposes no human merits, but sheer grace. Reprobation results in eternal damnation which
presupposes human sin. Such proximate cause, the solution offered by Calvin, enabled him to
ascribe all praise to God for his election and all blame to man for his damnation. For him the two
causalities always harmonize in the sovereign will. Thus a twofold theodicy is developed.

The third tension deals with morality. If man’s destiny has been fixed from eternity, how can he
be a free and responsible agent? If he is made unable by God to choose for salvation, why should
he be condemned?

In criticizing Calvin’s view of predestination, Pighius, followed by the Armenians in the


seventeenth century, argued from the assumption that divine sovereignty and human
responsibility are mutually exclusive. The fall has not disrupted man’s volitional faculty in such
a way that he cannot choose what is good. God has never forced men into his kingdom for to do
so would violate his principle of justice. Faith is not divinely given, but generated and sustained
by the believer himself. The entire human race is elected in Christ, and only personal refusal can
relinquish it.

The divine will is undoubtedly holy, just, and good. From this conviction Calvin derived courage
to defend the ethics of God’s will by asserting that it is the ‘highest rule of perfection’ and ‘the
law of all laws’. There is an intrinsic correlation between divine nature and divine will. In
predestination God’s ethical nature conditions his will; therefore, God is not the author of sin.
Reciprocally, God’s will governs his nature as he is the author of reprobation. Absolute
sovereignty is the necessary function in predestination and the final court of appeal for Calvin.
The divine will is self-reasoning and self-judging, and is entirely beyond human understanding.
Consequently it is impious to investigate the cause of the will of God, than which nothing is
higher.

How does man’s will operate? In the original creation Adam was given an integral, free will to
choose good or evil. But after the Fall, this genuine liberty has been forfeited to his posterity.
Calvin accepted St Bernard’s threefold analysis of liberty that man is free from necessity, which
characterizes man as man, but not free from sin and misery. Because of this man sins ‘inevitably’
yet ‘responsibly’, and it is man’s own choice without coercion.

Calvin emphasized both the difference and the coincidence of God’s will and man’s will. He
maintained with St. Augustine

that both man and apostate angels, as far as they were themselves concerned, did that which God
willed not, or which was contrary to his will; but that, as far as God’s overruling omnipotence is
concerned, they could not, in any manner, have done it without his will.9

Man may will ‘contrary to God’s will’ but ‘not without his will’. In the same event two different
wills, sinful and holy, are in joint function. For ‘it came to pass that by this same will of the
creature, God, though in one sense unwilling, yet accomplished what He willed’.10 ‘In one sense
unwilling’ is to be understood as due to the disobedience of man, but the omnipotence of God
overrules the situation to achieve the divine purpose. God’s will is simple, never at war with
itself, although it appears manifold to us because of our mental incapacity to understand how in
diverse manner it can will and does not will the same thing. Both wills converge on the same
event. Man’s will stands to be judged and God’s will, to judge. With this dynamic relationship of
wills, Calvin dismissed the charge of fatalism and determinism.

With respect to evangelism, Calvin sought to reconcile the two facts that by external preaching
all are called to repentance and yet that the Spirit of repentance is not given to all. Would God be
contrary to himself if he universally invites all but admits only the elect? Herein lies the fourth
tension.

In Calvin’s opinion, vocation is the work of the Spirit employing the means of the external word.
Word and Spirit have to proceed together for effectual calling. The preaching of the Word itself
does not constitute vocation. Nor does the efficacy of divine vocation depend on the receptivity
of man, otherwise man may at least boast that he has answered the call and has offered himself.

Calvin acknowledged the reality of an external call in which the preached Word is not
accompanied by the internal testimony of the Spirit. This is seen in the history of salvation and in
the development of the covenantal relationship. After the creation of Adam, a universal covenant
was established between God and man. Man is categorically different from animal and is to rule
over the earth. Then precedence was given to one race over others. Abraham was chosen, and
God freely offered to grant blessing to his children. The third stage consisted in a distinction
within Abraham’s family, a more limited scope of election. Later on when the whole Israel was
chosen as a nation, only a spiritual remnant shared the grace of salvation. In this context the final
stage of election is set: the election of individuals. For ‘God has made a covenant of eternal life
and calls any people to himself; a special mode of election is employed for a part of them, so that
he does not with indiscriminate grace effectually elect all.’11 Equal distribution of grace is not
divine obligation, and inequality indicates that it is free.

General election is not always effectual because the Spirit of regeneration is not immediately
bestowed on those with whom God has made a covenant. And the external calling, without the
internal illumination of the Spirit, is an intermediate stage between the rejection of some and the
election of others. God has the full right to give or to withhold the working of the Spirit. Thus the
entire Israel was called the inheritance of God, but there were many foreigners.

What, then, is the relation between election and vocation? Will the eternal counsel of God
conflict with the temporal proclamation of the gospel? In resolving these apparently opposite
motifs, Calvin insisted that the two standpoints must not be mixed. On the divine side, there is no
duality of will, though it is not demonstrable to us. On the human side we should confine our
attention to scriptural instruction. The invitation of the gospel always has existential significance
for the audience. When the Word is preached, it means a time for decision. The election of some
through universal invitation does not rule out a sincere offer of the gospel to the non-elect.
Calvin repudiated the way of preaching which consists in telling the people that if they do not
believe, the reason is that they have already been destined for destruction. Sloth and bad
intention will be produced by this perversion of the gospel message. This will be cursing rather
than teaching.

Calvin’s basic approach in dealing with the tensions in his concept of predestination is to keep
both the human and the divine perspective unconfused. The inadequate human way of knowing
cannot scrutinize the infinite counsel of the eternal decree, which is only partially revealed in
Scripture. Man should stay within scriptural limits and be satisfied. This theological division of
labour enables Calvin to resolve the conflicts in his theology. Reckless consistency is applied to
the hermeneutic of the two fold decree. After human effort has been exhausted, Calvin seeks
‘refuge’ in the realm of divine mystery in face of irreconcilable tenets. His argument stems from
sound reasoning although his theology may not be convincing enough to some people at this
point.
1
Creeds of Christendom, 1 (1877), p. 451.

2
Institutes, III, 21, 5; trans. by F. L. Battles (Westminster, 1960).

3
Institutes, III, 23, 1.

4
Institutes, III, 22, 7.

5
Institutes, III, 24, 3.

6
H. Oberman, The Harvest of Medieval Theology, p. 186.

7
Institutes, III, 21, 5.

8
Commentary on Romans, 9:11, 30.

9
Calvin’s Calvinism, trans. by H. Cole, p. 126.

10
Ibid., p. 43.

11
Institutes, III, 21, 7.

You might also like

pFad - Phonifier reborn

Pfad - The Proxy pFad of © 2024 Garber Painting. All rights reserved.

Note: This service is not intended for secure transactions such as banking, social media, email, or purchasing. Use at your own risk. We assume no liability whatsoever for broken pages.


Alternative Proxies:

Alternative Proxy

pFad Proxy

pFad v3 Proxy

pFad v4 Proxy