Fulltextczapanskiy
Fulltextczapanskiy
Fulltextczapanskiy
INTRODUCTION
By definition, a democratic nation has some mechanism through
which leaders hear from the people. Ordinarily, the mechanism is a
periodic election during which the people have an opportunity to hold
leaders accountable. Between these traditional opportunities for
democratic involvement, however, should a democratic nation have
mandatory mechanisms for give and take between legislative leaders
and the public? The South African Constitutional Court held that the
South African Constitution answered that question affirmatively in
1
Doctors for Life v. Speaker of the National Assembly. By way of
contrast, no such requirement has been found in the United States
1
KC & RM__FMT3.DOC 11/20/2008 9:34:45 AM
2. While the right to petition the Congress is well-established, as is the Congressional duty
to maintain a public journal of its activities and its custom of open hearings, no authority exists
for a requirement that a member, committee or a house of Congress must solicit input, much
less facilitate its delivery. See generally U.S. CONST. art. I.
3. International Convenant on Civil and Political Rights art. 25, Dec. 16, 1966, 999
U.N.T.S. 171 (“Every citizen shall have the right and the opportunity, without any of the
distinctions mentioned in article 2 and without unreasonable restrictions: 1. To take part in the
conduct of public affairs, directly or through freely chosen representatives; 2. To vote and to be
elected . . . ; 3. To have access, on general terms of equality, to public service in his [sic]
country.”).
4. Doctors for Life, 2006 (12) BCLR 1399 (CC) at 36-37 (S. Afr.); see also King & Others
v Attorneys Fund Bd. of Control & Another 2006 (4) BCLR 462 (SCA) (S. Afr.); Minister of
Health & Another v New Clicks S. Afr. (Pty) Ltd & Others 2006 (1) BCLR 1 (CC) (S. Afr.);
Matatiele Municipality & Others v President of the Republic of S. Afr. & Others 2006 (5) BCLR
622 (CC) (S. Afr.).
5. Doctors for Life, (12) BCLR 1399 (CC) at 36-37 (S. Afr.); see also King & Others, 2006
(4) BCLR 462 (SCA) (S. Afr.); Minister of Health & Another, 2006 (1) BCLR 1 (CC) (S. Afr.);
Matatiele Municipality & Others v President of the Republic of S. Afr. & Others 2006 (5) BCLR
622 (CC) (S. Afr.).
6. Doctors for Life, 2006 (12) BCLR 1399 (CC) at 36-37 (S. Afr.).
7. Id. The separation of powers question is addressed in Dennis M. Davis, Transformation
and the Democratic Case for Judicial Review: The South African Experience, 5 LOY. INT’L L.
REV. 45 (2007).
8. Doctors for Life, 2006 (12) BCLR 1399 (CC) at 36-37 (S. Afr.).
KC & RM__FMT3.DOC 11/20/2008 9:34:45 AM
9. Carolyn Evans & Simon Evans, Evaluating the Human Rights Performance of
Legislatures, 6 HUM. RTS. L. REV. 545, 548 (2006).
10. See generally, Doctors for Life, 2006 (12) BCLR 1399 (CC) (S. Afr.).
11. Evans & Evans, supra note 9, at 550-51.
12. Doctors for Life, 2006 (12) BCLR 1399 (CC) at 103-04 (S. Afr.).
KC & RM__FMT3.DOC 11/20/2008 9:34:45 AM
18. Doctors for Life, 2006 (12) BCLR 1399 (CC) at 117 (S. Afr.).
19. See S. AFR. CONST. 1996 ch. 2, §§ 16, 19.
20. Doctors for Life, 2006 (12) BCLR 1399 (CC) at 105 (S. Afr.).
21. Comm’n on Gender Equality Act 39 of 1996 pmbl.
22. Hum. Rts. Comm’n Act 54 of 1995 pmbl.
23. Doctors for Life, 2006 (12) BCLR 1399 (CC) at 115 (S.Afr.).
KC & RM__FMT3.DOC 11/20/2008 9:34:45 AM
elected.24 Furthermore, the ICCPR guarantees not only the ‘right’ but
also the ‘opportunity’ to take part in the conduct of public affairs. The
Court viewed the ICCPR as imposing an obligation on states to take
positive steps to ensure that their citizens have an opportunity to
25
exercise their right to political participation. In addition to specific
articles in the ICCPR, the United Nations Human Rights
Committee’s General Comment No. 25 encourages States to “adopt
such legislative and other measures as may be necessary to ensure
that citizens have an effective opportunity to enjoy the rights it
protects.”26
The African [Banjul] Charter on Human and Peoples’ Rights
(African Charter) is the applicable regional human rights instrument.
The relevant sections include Article 9 on freedom of expression and
information, Article 13 on freedom to participate in government of
country either directly or through freely chosen representatives, and
Article 25 on the obligation of the state to promote and ensure,
through teaching, education and publication, respect of the rights and
freedoms contained in the Charter. The Court affirmed that this last
provision in the African Charter is more specific than the ICCPR in
spelling out the obligation of state parties to ensure that people are
well informed of their political rights.27
24. See International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights, Dec. 16, 1996, 999 U.N.T.S.
171.
25. Doctors for Life, 2006 (12) BCLR 1399 (CC) at 115 (S. Afr.). Also, in the
environmental rights sector, the United Nations Economic Commission for Europe’s (UNECE)
“Convention on Access to Information, Public Participation in Decision-making and Access to
Justice in Environmental Matters”, recognizes the right of people to live in a healthy
environment, and calls for officials and agencies to provide information and to facilitate
participation in decision-making. The Declaration links environmental rights and human rights
and affirms that the involvement of all stakeholders is crucial for sustainable development. The
principles underlying the adoption of this Convention include government accountability,
transparency and responsiveness; the granting of rights to the public and the imposition on
signatories and public authorities obligations regarding access to information and public
participation and access to justice; and the forging of new processes for public participation in
the negotiation and implementation of international agreements. Convention on Access to
Information, Public Participation in Decision-making and Access to Justice in Environmental
Matters, June 25, 1998, 38 I.L.M. 517.
26. Office of the U.N. High Comm’r for Human Rights [OHCHR], International Covenant
on Civil and Political Rights, General Comment No. 25, adopted July 12, 1996, para. 1,
http://www.unhchr.ch/tbs/doc.nsf/0/d0b7f023e8d6d9898025651e004bc0eb?Opendocument.
27. Doctors for Life, 2006 (12) BCLR 1399 (CC) at 100-01 (S. Afr.).
KC & RM__FMT3.DOC 11/20/2008 9:34:45 AM
28. According to the website of Doctors for Life International, “Doctors for Life stands for
the following 3 principles: For sound science in the medical profession, the sanctity of life from
conception till death, and for a basic Christian ethic.” Doctors for Life International, Mission
Statement, http://www.doctorsforlifeinternational.com/about/mission.cfm (last visited July 29,
2008).
29. See Doctors for Life, 2006 (12) BCLR 1399 (CC) at 36-37 (S. Afr.). The health statutes
mentioned included the: Traditional Health Practitioners Act 35 of 2004 (intending to bring
about a new dispensation of recognizing and regulating traditional health healers); Choice on
Termination of Pregnancy Amendment Act 38 of 2004 (making provision for registered nurses,
other than midwives, to perform termination of pregnancies at certain public and private
facilities); Dental Technicians Amendment Act 24 of 2004 (making provision for persons who
have been employed as dental laboratory assistants for a period of not less than five years under
the supervision of a dentist or dental technician, and who have been trained by these
professionals, to perform the work of a dental technician); and the Sterilisation Amendment
Act 3 of 2005. There was no dispute as to whether the National Assembly had fulfilled its
constitutional obligation to facilitate public involvement in connection with the ‘health statutes.’
This had taken place through the acceptance of written submissions made to the National
Portfolio Committee on Health, and also by the holding of public hearings.
KC & RM__FMT3.DOC 11/20/2008 9:34:45 AM
30. See generally Doctors for Life, 2006 (12) BCLR 1399 (CC) at 146-47, 177 (S. Afr.)
(outlining and giving examples of reasonableness and unreasonableness in regard to legislative
consultations with the public).
31. See Id. at 163-64.
32. S. AFR. CONST. 1996 § 59, pt. 1 (regarding hearings at the national level).
33. Doctors for Life, 2006 (12) BCLR 1399 (CC) at 173 (S. Afr.).
KC & RM__FMT3.DOC 11/20/2008 9:34:45 AM
34. The constitutional challenges relating to two other bills, the Dental Technicians
Amendment Act and the Sterilisation Amendment Act, were dismissed. This last statute had
not been passed by Parliament at the time of the application, and, although the statute was
already passed at the time of writing of the judgment, the Court reached a decision that it did
not have jurisdiction to hear this, as the legislative process was not complete at the time of
application. The challenge to the Dental Technicians Amendment Act was dismissed as, after
having considered the nature of the Bill and the views of the provinces and the NCOP, the court
concluded that it could not find that the respondents had acted unreasonably in not inviting
written representations or holding public hearings on this Bill. Furthermore, the Bill had not
elicited public interest, as evidenced by the fact that no submissions were received when the bill
was first published for public comment. Hence, there was no breach of the duty to facilitate
public involvement and the applicant’s challenge to this Bill failed. Id. at 70-76, 174-75, 177-78.
35. Id. at 188-89. Three dissenting judges each issued an opinion. Judge Westhuizen agreed
with the majority position on the importance of public involvement for democracy, and was
convinced that there is a constitutional obligation, which must be fulfilled. Nevertheless, he
argued that section 72(1)(a) does not mandate that the legislature has to hold public hearings,
nor is it a specific requirement for the passing of every Bill. Also, the provision is not
constitutionally intended to result in specific legislation being declared invalid by the Court. Id.
at 212-21 (Westhuizen, J., dissenting). Judge Yacoob’s detailed dissenting judgment had the
support of both Judge Westhuizen and Judge Skweyiya. His focus was on determining what the
Constitution required both textually and historically, as opposed to using international law
provisions above constitutional principles, or what the merits of public participation were. Id. at
221-307 (Yacoob, J. dissenting). He agrees that the Constitution envisions a relationship
between representative and participatory elements in South Africa’s democracy. He identifies
three elements which emphasize the participatory aspects of democracy: universal adult
suffrage, a national common voters’ roll, and regular elections. The multi-party democracy
aspect, he argues, points to the representative nature of the democracy contemplated in the
Constitution. He argues that “[T]he object of all these elements of democracy is to ensure
accountability, responsiveness and openness. . . . It implies that our democracy requires citizens
to vote for members of a political party who would represent them. Public involvement in the
legislative process is not mentioned at all as an essential principle of the Constitution. . . . In our
constitutional scheme, laws passed by representatives of the people must be regarded as
government by the people and as laws passed by the people. This is a vital contextual factor in
determining what ‘public involvement’ in the Constitution means.” Id. at 250, 256-57 (Yacoob,
J., dissenting).
KC & RM__FMT3.DOC 11/20/2008 9:34:45 AM
39. Minister of Health & Another v New Clicks S. Af. (Pty) Ltd & Others 2006 (1) BCLR 1
(CC) at 344-47 (S. Afr.).
40. Doctors for Life, 2006 (12) BCLR 1399 (CC) at 24 (S. Afr.).
41. Id. at 127.
KC & RM__FMT3.DOC 11/20/2008 9:34:45 AM
courts. For example, the Court cited the King case, where the
Supreme Court of Appeal, in dealing with the concept of public
involvement, made the following observation:
Public involvement might include public participation
through the submission of commentary and representations:
but that is neither definitive nor exhaustive of its content.
The public may become ‘involved’ in the business of the
National Assembly as much by understanding and being
informed of what it is doing as by participating directly in
those processes. It is plain that by imposing on Parliament
the obligation to facilitate public involvement in its
processes, the Constitution sets a base standard, but then
42
leaves Parliament significant leeway in fulfilling it.
The Court acknowledged that the legislature will have considerable
discretion in determining how best to achieve the facilitation of public
participation. Hence, Parliament must be free to carry out its
functions without interference and, in terms of section 57 (1) (a) of
the Constitution it has the power to “determine and control its
internal arrangements, proceedings and procedures. The business of
Parliament might well be stalled while the question of what relief
should be granted is argued out in the courts. Indeed the
parliamentary process would be paralyzed if Parliament were to
spend its time defending its legislative process in the courts. This
would undermine one of the essential features of our democracy: the
43
separation of powers.”
The determination by the Court is based on a reasonableness test
that takes into account the factual basis. The Court took into account
42. Doctors for Life, 2006 (12) BCLR 1399 (CC) at 141-42 (S. Afr.) citing King & Others v
Attorneys Fidelity Fund Bd. of Control & Another 2006 (4) BCLR 462 (SCA) at 23-24 (S. Afr.).
43. Doctors for Life, 2006 (12) BCLR 1399 (CC) at 59-60 (S. Afr.). The Court was clear
that the separation of powers principle is not simply an abstract notion. It “. . . has important
consequences for the way in which and the institutions by which power can be exercised. Courts
must be conscious of the vital limits on judicial authority and the Constitution’s design to leave
certain matters to other branches of government.” In a context where the Constitution is the
supreme law, and where it imposes binding obligations on all branches of government, Courts
are required by the Constitution ‘to ensure that all branches of government act within the law’
and fulfill their constitutional obligations. In terms of section 2 of the Constitution, the
Constitutional Court “has. . .the responsibility of being the ultimate guardian of the
Constitution and its values.” “[Y]et, however great the leeway given to the legislature, the
courts can, and in appropriate cases will, determine whether there has been the degree of public
involvement that is required by the Constitution.” Thus the Court has a role in deciding whether
Parliament has fulfilled its obligations, including in providing citizens with a meaningful
opportunity to be heard. Id. at 60-63, 128 (citations omitted).
KC & RM__FMT3.DOC 11/20/2008 9:34:45 AM
questions such as, amongst others, the following: what action has
Parliament taken? Is it reasonable in all the circumstances? Are the
rules of Parliament relating to public participation reasonable? How
controversial is the Bill, and is there a reasonable degree of public
44
interest in it? Did the legislation need to be passed urgently?
good even when their individual good may be disserved.52 It can serve
53
as an antidote to apathy and a tonic for empathy.
The judgment in Doctors for Life does not reject representative
democracy as fundamental to the structure of the South African
government under the post-apartheid constitution. Instead, it insists
that representative democracy is not the only aspect of democracy
contemplated by that constitution. In addition, the Court concludes
that the constitution requires some participation between elections.
The question, then, is what kind of participation is consistent with
what is fundamentally a representative democratic structure.
While the boundary between strong democracy and dialogic
democracy may not be entirely plain, the path taken by the Court in
Doctors for Life is more within the territory mapped by dialogic
democracy than strong democracy. For example, while Barber posits
that agenda-setting must be done through strong democratic talk,
Doctors for Life puts the question of agenda-setting mainly in the
hands of the legislature. Legislators must facilitate input, according to
the court, only as to controversial questions and only using the means
chosen by the legislators. The decision does not demand, as may be
54
true in a strong democracy, the reconsideration of basic substantive
premises concerning, for example, the structure of government and
the nature of fundamental rights. Under the decision, the process may
be as limited as the legislature inviting input from the public, but the
Court encourages legislators to go further. Among the means
identified by the Court are educating the public about controversial
topics, soliciting views from affected groups, seeking both oral and
written submissions, and holding hearings around the country. A
reader of Habermas would find these techniques for democratic
participation quite familiar, although Habermas would surely
encourage the legislature to go further along the road to greater
social learning, with its concomitant political activity.55
The process of social inquiry which creates social learning
includes four aspects: discourse among the actors must create inter-
subjective meaning and express shared understanding, “discussion
must create and authenticate ‘true’ statements of conditions,” a
“deliberative process must establish the moral and ethical basis for
56. Id.
57. Id.
58. See YASH GHAI & GUIDO GALLI, INTERNATIONAL INSTITUTE FOR DEMOCRACY AND
ELECTORAL ASSISTANCE, CONSTITUTION BUILDING PROCESSES AND DEMOCRATIZATION 14-
15 (2006) (arguing that public participation can help create a more tolerant and democratic
society); see Jim Rossi, Participation Run Amok: The Costs of Mass Participation for
Deliberative Agency Decisionmaking, 92 NW. U. L. REV. 173, 196-206 (1997) (stating that to be
legitimate, decisionmaking must allow some degree of nonexpert participation, and arguing that
civic virtue is necessary for a deliberative democracy).
KC & RM__FMT3.DOC 11/20/2008 9:34:45 AM
63. See 5 U.S.C. § 553 (2000); Lloyd Noland Hosp. & Clinic v. Heckler, 762 F.2d 1561, 1565
(11th Cir. 1985); see also 1 RICHARD J. PIERCE, JR., ADMINISTRATIVE LAW TREATISE § 7.1
(4th ed. 2002); Tracy-Lynn Field, Public Participation in Environmental Decision-Making:
Earthlife Africa (Cape Town) v. Director-General: Department of Environmental Affairs and
Tourism, 122 S. AFR. L.J. 4, 748, 757 (2005).
64. JAMES BOHMAN, PUBLIC DELIBERATION: PLURALISM, COMPLEXITY, AND
DEMOCRACY 187 (1996).
65. Id.
66. Id.
67. See id. at 55 (stating that public deliberation requires a plural accountability).
KC & RM__FMT3.DOC 11/20/2008 9:34:45 AM
minds, and be prepared to justify their decisions in the same fair and
open participatory process.
A criticism of participatory democracy is that it allows the
majority to overwhelm minorities while, at the same time, does not
68
affirm the unchangeable character of certain core values. Doctors for
Life does not go that far down the route toward participatory
democracy because of its insistence that, whatever participation the
legislature must facilitate, the process is part and parcel of the
representative democracy and the unwavering values embodied in the
South African Constitution. Indeed, Doctors for Life probably serves
to enhance the power of minorities, rather than the majority, because
it provides for specific spaces in which the voices of those affected by
the legislature must be heard. The plaintiffs in Doctors for Life itself
are a good example – a group of advocates opposed to broad access
to abortion is not, in South Africa, a widely popular organization, but,
under the decision, legislators are required to listen to their views.
A second criticism of participatory democracy is that it does
nothing to counteract the silencing of groups historically silenced in
69
society. In part for that reason, Iris Marion Young recommends
renaming deliberative democracy “communicative democracy.”70 She
posits that the argumentative norms of discourse sometimes advanced
by advocates of deliberative democracy privilege speakers who enjoy
political and economic advantage and devalue the speech of others.
Communicative democracy, on the other hand, “attends to social
difference, to the way that power sometimes enters speech itself,
recognizes the cultural specificity of deliberative practices and
proposes a more inclusive model of communication.”71 Her more
inclusive model aims, like deliberative democracy, to make room for
people to change their ideas because of their interactions with others,
including others whose experiences and discursive methods are
different from their own. To achieve the goal, she recommends
adopting a discourse that includes narrative, preservation of
differences in respectful exchanges that enhance social knowledge of
all participants, caring for the participants in the exchange, and strong
72
rhetoric.
In addition to changing the norms of discourse, feminists have
pointed to the experiences of women within families as a source of
their silence in public life. For example, family life historically has
been viewed as a private realm, whereas politics is a public realm.
Feminists have critiqued this division of the public and the private as
a way of validating the absence of women from public life, since
women who can be subject to violence and sexual domination at
home can be viewed as lacking the agency necessary for participation
in the public sphere. Further, women have been tasked with the
responsibility for home while also participating in the paid economy,
73
leaving them little time for participation in political activity.
The judgment in Doctors for Life specifically identifies the
historical silencing of the majority of the country’s residents as one of
the reasons underlying the need to incorporate aspects of
participatory democracy into its representative democracy. People of
color were the principal targets of the system of political and
economic exclusion called apartheid, but white women, and gay men
and lesbians of all colors, suffered some of its impact as well. Many of
the same groups have been the targets of political and economic
74
exclusion in other countries, including the United States. Making
room at the political table for historically silenced groups may be
essential to the functioning of a good government, as the court in
Doctors for Life argues. At the same time, making room is important
72. Id. See generally MARTHA MINOW, MAKING ALL THE DIFFERENCE: INCLUSION,
EXCLUSION, AND AMERICAN LAW (1990); Barbara Bezdek, Silence in the Court: Participation
and Subordination of Poor Tenants’ Voices in Legal Process, 20 HOFSTRA L. REV. 533 (1991-
92).
73. See, e.g., SUSAN MOLLER OKIN, JUSTICE, GENDER, AND THE FAMILY 110-33 (1989);
CAROLE PATEMAN, THE DISORDER OF WOMEN: DEMOCRACY, FEMINISM AND POLITICAL
THEORY 118-40 (1989).
74. See, e.g., PATEMAN, supra note 73; Mary G. Dietz, Hannah Arendt and Feminist
Politics, in FEMINIST INTERPRETATIONS AND POLITICAL THEORY 232-52 (Mary Lyndon
Shanley & Carole Pateman eds., 1991); Evans v. Romer, 882 P.2d 1335 (Colo. 1994)
(overturning referendum adopted by state’s voters that prohibited legislature from adopting
measures to protect people from discrimination on the basis of sexual orientation as a denial of
the fundamental right to participate equally in the political process), upheld on different
grounds, 517 U.S. 620 (1996). Compare Lynn A. Baker, Direct Democracy and Discrimination:
A Public Choice Perspective, 67 CHI.-KENT L. REV. 707 (1991) (rejecting the claim that laws
created by referenda are more likely to produce discrimination than laws created by elected
officials) with Derrick A. Bell, Jr., The Referendum: Democracy’s Barrier to Racial Equality, 54
WASH. L. REV. 1 (1978-79) (suggesting the trend towards using referenda to create laws
promotes racial inequality).
KC & RM__FMT3.DOC 11/20/2008 9:34:45 AM
75. Dietz, supra note 74; OKIN, supra note 73, at 124-33; Katharine T. Bartlett, Feminist
Legal Methods, 103 HARV. L. REV. 829 (1989-90). Cf. Sherrilyn A. Ifill, Creating a Truth and
Reconciliation Commission for Lynching, 21 LAW & INEQ. 263 (2003).
76. The notion that deliberative democracy can contribute to the achievement of social
rights is not self-evident, but some commentators point to a connection, particularly in the need
to “integrate groups that were improperly marginalized by the political system.” See Roberto
Gargarella, Should Deliberative Democrats Defend the Judicial Enforcement of Social Rights?,
in DELIBERATIVE DEMOCRACY AND ITS DISCONTENTS 244-51 (Samantha Besson & José Luis
Martí eds., 2006).
77. CASS R. SUNSTEIN, THE SECOND BILL OF RIGHTS: FDR’S UNFINISHED REVOLUTION
AND WHY WE NEED IT MORE THAN EVER 184 (2004).
KC & RM__FMT3.DOC 11/20/2008 9:34:45 AM
process may increase the capacity of groups in civil society who face
84
some of the greatest economic, social and cultural disadvantage. It
may give members of this group reasons to see themselves as citizens
and to develop the skills and self-respect necessary for fuller
participation in society. Developing civil society in this way can be
seen as a type of capacity building that is as important in the long run
as other forms of capacity building advocated by Sunstein.
Another reason to think that the judgment in Doctors for Life is
not unrelated to the achievement of social and economic rights is that
the South African Constitution, unlike the constitutions of most
countries, protects social and economic rights and makes them
judicially enforceable.85 When social and economic rights are not
justiciable, courts have little incentive to be concerned with whether
the legislative process is open to hearing claims from disadvantaged
groups about their needs for economic and social justice. Where the
court is an alternative forum for the achievement of economic and
social justice, however, it is in the best interests of judges for the
legislature to be seen as an appropriate and responsive institution for
such claims. With its judgment in Doctors for Life, the South African
Constitutional Court could be seen as encouraging Parliament to
become more open and responsive to claims for economic and social
justice and to relieve the Court of having to take on the primary role.
As the South African Constitutional Court has seen, tasking courts
with enforcing social and economic rights is tricky; for example, the
South African Constitutional Court lacks the power to appropriate
funds and create organizations to implement its judgments.86 The
84. An important example of the government assisting the development of civil society
occurred during the War on Poverty in the United States in the latter part of the 1960s, when
the Office of Economic Opportunity devoted resources to help communities create and sustain
local advocacy and service organizations. These organizations included welfare rights groups,
which were successful, for a time, in expanding access by low-income women to public benefits.
See FELICIA KORNBLUH, THE BATTLE FOR WELFARE RIGHTS: POLITICS AND POVERTY IN
MODERN AMERICA 33-36 (2006).
85. See generally Balakrishnan Rajagopal, Pro-Human Rights but Anti-Poor? A Critical
Evaluation of the Indian Supreme Court from a Social Movement Perspective, 8 HUM. RTS. REV.
157 (2007) (discussing judicial practice in India and comparing it to other countries); Robin
West, Katrina, The Constitution, and the Legal Question Doctrine, 81 CHI.-KENT L. REV. 1127
(2006) (discussing Constitutional jurisprudence in the United States).
86. Taunya Lovell Banks, Balancing Competing Individual Constitutional Rights: Raising
Some Questions, in LAW AND RIGHTS: GLOBAL PERSPECTIVES ON CONSTITUTIONALISM AND
GOVERNANCE 27, 37 (Penelope E. Andrews & Susan Brazilli eds., 2008) (“[T]he Constitutional
Court’s approach to the enforcement of socio-economic rights is cautious and largely declarative
rather than transformative.”); Dennis Davis, Adjudicating the Socio-Economic Rights in the
South African Constitution: Toward “Deference Lite?”, 22 S. AFR. J. HUM. RTS. 301 (2006).
KC & RM__FMT3.DOC 11/20/2008 9:34:45 AM
87. See generally Rajagopal, supra note 85 (discussing judicial practice in India and
comparing it to other countries).
88. An important critique of deliberative democracy is that, as deliberative processes
increase, the speed of legislative process and the power of experts to decide policy both decline.
The question is whether the tradeoff is worthwhile. One part of the response is that the answer
to the question is political, not empirical. What the Doctors for Life Court assumes, it appears,
is that the political claim was decided in favor of deliberation when the constitution was
adopted. It is hard to make same claim, of course, based on the language of the US
Constitution. At the same time, given how slowly important legislation has moved through
Congress in recent years despite the absence of a mandatory process for public input, the
efficiency claims may not be empirically accurate even if the writers of the US Constitution
were satisfied as a political matter with representative democracy.
89. Doctors for Life Int’l v the Speaker of the Nat’l Assembly & Others 2006 (12) BCLR
1399 (CC) at 36-37 (S. Afr.).
KC & RM__FMT3.DOC 11/20/2008 9:34:45 AM
90. Peter Kimenia, South Africa: Public Participation – Need for a Re-definition, LOC.
GOV’T TRANSFORMER, Oct./Nov. 2007, available at http://www.africafiles.org/article.asp?ID=1
6327. See generally Parliamentary statements and Annual Reports of the Commission for
Gender Equality, www.cge.org.za.
91. Kimenia, supra note 90.
92. Older Persons Bill, 2003, Bill B68B-2003 (GA).
KC & RM__FMT3.DOC 11/20/2008 9:34:45 AM
93. See Older Persons Bill: Hearing on B68B-2003 Before the Portfolio Comm. On Social
Development, 1 (2005) (Oral Submission of S. Afr. Human Rights Comm’n).
KC & RM__FMT3.DOC 11/20/2008 9:34:45 AM
94. South African Human Rights Commission [SAHRC], Case Study - The Older Persons
Bill 10 (undated & unpublished document, on file with authors).
95. Id.
KC & RM__FMT3.DOC 11/20/2008 9:34:45 AM
96. Id.
97. Id.
98. Id.
KC & RM__FMT3.DOC 11/20/2008 9:34:45 AM
administrative costs substantially reduce any benefit from child support); Chien-Chung Huang,
Ronald Mincy, Ronald & Irwin Garfinkel, Child Support Obligation of Low Income Fathers, 67
J. MARR. & FAM. 1213 (2005).
102. See Nancy E. Dowd, Parentage at Birth: Birthfathers and Social Fatherhood, 14 WM. &
MARY BILL RTS. J. 909 (2006); Memorandum from Paula Roberts, Ctr. For Law & Soc. Policy,
to Interested People, Preliminary Analysis of Child Care Support Cooperation as a Condition of
Eligibility for Subsidized Child Care (Nov. 19, 2004), available at http://www.clasp.org/publicatio
ns/cs_cc_subsidy.pdf (reviewing pros and cons of imposing requirement).
103. Having been involved in representing women who had been battered by partners, I
knew this was not a purely theoretical concern. It finds support in the scholarly literature. See
SHARON HAYS, FLAT BROKE WITH CHILDREN: WOMEN IN THE AGE OF WELFARE REFORM
82-83 (2003); Karen Syma Czapanskiy, Domestic Violence and the Maryland Family Violence
Option, 11 AM. U. J. GENDER SOC. POL’Y & L. 447 (2003); Susan Notar & Sharon Turetsky,
Models for Safe Child Support Enforcement, 8 AM. U. J. GENDER SOC. POL’Y. & L. 657 (2000).
104. HAYS, supra note 103, at 80-81.
105. See Czapanskiy, supra note 101.
KC & RM__FMT3.DOC 11/20/2008 9:34:45 AM
106. Another advocacy project I was involved with around the same time involved
extending unemployment insurance benefits (UIB) to part-time workers on the same basis as
provided for fulltime workers. Finding people denied UIB was even more difficult than finding
disappointed applicants for the child care subsidy program. Applications were taken only over
the phone, and applicants were required to work through a telephone decision tree before
speaking with a claims representative. The decision tree was unambiguous when it comes to
benefits for part-time workers. Applicants were told that they are ineligible for benefits, and
they were provided with no opportunity to contest the decision. They are not connected with a
claims representative to talk over the issue, and they are not provided with a denial letter.
Because they were never informed that the question might be decided differently if the law
were changed (or, in a few cases, if they come within one of the exceptions to the exclusion),
they had no incentive to create or even contact a legal or advocacy group. From the perspective
of the unemployed worker, it must have appeared that their exclusion was inevitable and
unquestionable.
KC & RM__FMT3.DOC 11/20/2008 9:34:45 AM
C. Reflections on the case studies from South Africa and the United
States of America
The process leading to the adoption of the Older Persons Bill
contrasts rather sharply with the US experience. In both countries,
the proposed legislation primarily affected people with few economic
resources. The South African legislation addressed a large number of
issues affecting an important group of people in the population, which
helps to explain the significant amount of consideration it was given
by the executive department, the SAHRC and advocacy groups. The
US example involved modest changes to an existing program, which
helps to explain why the attention paid to the proposal was not
substantial. In both countries, however, the judgment in Doctors for
Life would have made a difference in the process and in the outcome.
In South Africa, the adoption of a more expansive and
consultative process by the SAHRC reflected a shift in the
methodology regarding public participation. As noted above, this was
not due to the judgment in Doctors for Life, but rather to the
identification of problems in the draft law and also the recognition
that the older persons sector was not sufficiently well-organized to
make an impact on its own. The judgment in Doctors for Life
confirmed that the nature of South Africa’s democracy was
participatory, inclusive and responsive, and that the values of dignity
and respect are engendered by public participation in the law-making
process. Both the imposition of a constitutional mandate to facilitate
public participation, and the creation of constitutional bodies to
strengthen democracy, allow for the realization of deliberative
democracy goals. The existence of a court with the power to oversee
the implementation of the Constitution also assists enormously in this
mission.
In the absence of a judgment such as Doctors for Life, the
Constitutional Court would likely face similar complaints in the
future. The striking down of laws in this case serves to send a stronger
message to the Legislature regarding a violation of its constitutional
mandate. This will hopefully lead to greater awareness and changes in
the Legislature in its future facilitation of public participation. The
judgment also clarified that there is a mandatory duty to facilitate
public participation and that there are two aspects to this duty.
Contextualizing the duty in terms of human rights obligations as well
as historical and contextual approaches is another innovative aspect
of the judgment. The recognition of political citizenship as being
more than just the right to vote shows respect for citizens and allows
KC & RM__FMT3.DOC 11/20/2008 9:34:45 AM
109. See U.S. CONST. amend. I (“Congress shall make no law respecting . . . the right of the
people peaceably to assemble, and to petition the Government for a redress of grievances.”).
110. See AKHIL REED AMAR, AMERICA’S CONSTITUTION: A BIOGRAPHY 82-83 (2005).
111. In terms of section 193 of the RSA Constitution, members of Ch. 9 institutions are
appointed through a public participation process when calls for nominations are made. This is
followed by a Parliamentary process of short-listing, interviews and a voting exercise by both
KC & RM__FMT3.DOC 11/20/2008 9:34:45 AM
Houses of Parliament. The names of nominees are then submitted to the State President for
assent and appointment.
112. Jane Mansbridge, Conflict and Self-Interest in Deliberation, in DELIBERATIVE
DEMOCRACY AND ITS DISCONTENTS 107, 128 (Samantha Besson & José Luis Martí eds., 2006).
KC & RM__FMT3.DOC 11/20/2008 9:34:45 AM
CONCLUSION
The Court in Doctors for Life looked to international and
regional human rights instruments for guidance on the parameters
and importance of citizen participation in the legislative process.
Through its decision, the Court has also advanced our understanding
of respect and dignity as components of political citizenship in the
international human rights context, with lessons of importance to
both old and new democracies.
The court stressed that legislatures must facilitate input, and not
simply wait for people to provide it between elections. By inviting
participation, legislators not only garner information on which to base
better legislation, they also express their respect for the citizens
whom they consult. In turn, those citizens may become more engaged
and less apathetic about public life. The two-way street contemplated
KC & RM__FMT3.DOC 11/20/2008 9:34:45 AM