Topic-1-Logic
Topic-1-Logic
In place of word ‘premises’, you can also put: ‘data’, ‘information’, ‘facts’.
Examples of Inferences:
(2) You count 19 persons in a group that originally had 20, and you
infer that someone is missing.
Note carefully the difference between ‘infer’ and ‘imply’, which are
sometimes confused. We infer the fire on the basis of the smoke, but we do
not imply the fire. On the other hand, the smoke implies the fire, but it does
not infer the fire. The word ‘infer’ is not equivalent to the word ‘imply’, nor is
it equivalent to ‘insinuate’.
Note that this is not a definition of a good argument. Also note that, in
the context of ordinary discourse, an argument has an additional trait,
described as follows.
it is raining
I am hungry
2+2 = 4
God exists
On the other hand the following are examples of sentences that are not
statements.
Here the argument consists of two statements, ‘there is smoke’ and ‘there is
fire’. The term ‘therefore’ is not strictly speaking part of the argument; it
rather serves to designate the conclusion (‘there is fire’), setting it off from
the premise (‘there is smoke’). In this argument, there is just one premise.
There are no hard and fast rules for telling when a collection of
statements is intended to be an argument, but there are a few rules of
thumb. Often an argument can be identified as such because its conclusion
is marked. We have already seen one conclusion-marker – the word
‘therefore’. Besides ‘therefore’, there are other words that are commonly
used to mark conclusions of arguments, including ‘consequently’, ‘hence’,
‘thus’, ‘so’, and ‘ergo’. Usually, such words indicate that what follows is the
conclusion of an argument.
On the one hand, we know that the existence of smoke does not
guarantee (ensure) the existence of fire; it only makes the existence of fire
likely or probable.
Thus, although inferring fire on the basis of smoke is reasonable, it is
nevertheless fallible. Insofar as it is possible for there to be smoke without
there being fire, we may be wrong in asserting that there is a fire.
Inductive logic is not the subject of this book. If you want to learn
about inductive logic, it is probably best to take a course on probability and
statistics. Inductive reasoning is often called statistical (or probabilistic)
reasoning, and forms the basis of experimental science.
Some arguments are not inductively correct, and therefore are not
deductively correct either; they are just plain unreasonable. Suppose you
flunk intro logic, and suppose that on the basis of this you conclude that it
will be a breeze to get into law school. Under these circumstances, it seems
that your reasoning is faulty.
The difference between the five letter word ‘water’ in English and the
liquid substance it denotes should be obvious enough, and no one is apt to
confuse the word and the substance. Whereas ‘water’ consists of letters,
water consists of molecules. The distinction between a statement and the
proposition it expresses is very much like the distinction between the word
‘water’ and the substance water.
snow is white
der Schnee ist weiss
la neige est blanche(French)
For the purposes of logic, terms divide into two important categories –
descriptive terms and logical terms. One must carefully note, however, that
this distinction is not absolute. Rather, the distinction between descriptive
and logical terms depends upon the level (depth) of logical analysis we are
pursuing.
Let us pursue an analogy for a moment. Recall first of all that the core
meaning of the word ‘analyze’ is to break down a complex whole into its
constituent parts. In physics, matter can be broken down (analyzed) at
different levels; it can be analyzed into molecules, into atoms, into
elementary particles (electrons, protons, etc.); still deeper levels of analysis
are available (e.g., quarks). The basic idea in breaking down matter is that in
order to go deeper and deeper one needs ever increasing amounts of
energy, and one needs ever increasing sophistication.
The same may be said about logic and the analysis of language. There
are many levels at which we can analyze language, and the deeper levels
require more logical sophistication than the shallower levels (they also
require more energy on the part of the logician!)
Note, however, that since the distinction between logical terms and
descriptive terms is relative to the particular level of analysis we are
pursuing, the notion of logical form is likewise relative in this way. In
particular, for each of the different logics listed above, there is a
corresponding notion of logical form.
As soon as we can get a clear idea about form and content, then we
can discuss how to classify arguments into those that are deductively correct
and those that are not deductively correct.
6. PRELIMINARY DEFINITIONS
In the present section we examine some of the basic ideas in logic
which will be made considerably clearer in subsequent chapters.
Neither of these arguments is good, but they are bad for different
reasons. Consider first their content. Whereas all the statements in (a1) are
false, all the statements in (a2) are true. Since the premises of (a1) are not
all true this is not a good argument as far as content goes, whereas (a2) is a
good argument as far as content goes.
Now consider their forms. This will be explained more fully in a later
section. The question is this: do the premises support the conclusion? Does
the conclusion follow from the premises?
In the case of (a1), the premises do in fact support the conclusion; the
conclusion does in fact follow from the premises. Although the premises are
not true, if they were true then the conclusion would also be true, of
necessity.
In the case of (a2), the premises are all true, and so is the conclusion,
but nevertheless the truth of the conclusion is not conclusively supported by
the premises; in (a2), the conclusion does not follow from the premises. To
see that the conclusion does not follow from the premises, we need merely
substitute the term ‘reptiles’ for ‘mammals’. Then the premises are both true
but the conclusion is false.
An argument is valid
if and only if
its conclusion follows from its premises.
An argument is sound
if and only if
it is both factually correct and valid.
An argument is valid
if and only if
it is impossible for
the conclusion to be false
while the premises are all true.
These will become clearer as you read further, and as you study particular
examples.
Prepared by: