9781040186039
9781040186039
This series provides a forum for established and emerging scholars to dis-
cuss the latest debates, research and practice in the evolving field of Special
Educational Needs.
Joseph Mintz
First published 2025
by Routledge
4 Park Square, Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon OX14 4RN
and by Routledge
605 Third Avenue, New York, NY 10158
Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group, an informa business
© 2025 Joseph Mintz
The right of Joseph Mintz to be identified as author of this work has been asserted in
accordance with sections 77 and 78 of the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988.
All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or utilised
in any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now known or
hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, or in any information
storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publishers.
Trademark notice: Product or corporate names may be trademarks or registered trademarks,
and are used only for identification and explanation without intent to infringe.
British Library Cataloguing-in-Publication Data
A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library
ISBN: 978-1-032-27996-1 (hbk)
ISBN: 978-1-032-27995-4 (pbk)
ISBN: 978-1-003-29489-4 (ebk)
DOI: 10.4324/9781003294894
Typeset in Galliard
by Newgen Publishing UK
This book is dedicated to my parents, Professor Barrie Mintz
and my late mother Mrs Jennifer Mintz (may her memory be
a blessing).
Contents
Introduction 1
7 Conclusions 125
Index 137
Introduction
I myself am pursuing the same instinctive course as the veriest human animal you
can think of…staring at particles of light in the midst of a great darkness –without
knowing the bearing of any one assertion, of any one opinion…
John Keats, Letters, 1819
In 2020 the BBC released the television short film Education as part of the
Small Axe series directed by Steve McQueen, a Londoner of West Indian
heritage.1 The series focused on various aspects of the experience of the
West Indian community in London from the 1960s through to the 1980s
and Education tells the story of a 12-year-old boy Kingsley who is sent to
an ESN (“Educationally Subnormal”) special school in the mid-1970s. The
film portrays the cultural racism inherent in English society and the educa-
tion system, and the ways in which the label of ESN was applied particularly
to black boys. Kingsley is clearly very bright, but perhaps has some specific
learning difficulties with reading, although this is not explicitly made clear
in the film. The head teacher at his mainstream school uses IQ results to
“objectively” justify the need for Kingsley to be transferred to special educa-
tion. The ESN school he is sent to has very low expectations of its students
and sub-standard teaching. The message conveyed is that of special education
at the time as essentially serving as a means to hide away and not very much
bother about a group of people not much valued by society. However, the film
goes on to show how, through local community action, Kingsley’s family are
empowered to fight back against the system, at the same time as reclaiming
an understanding of the richness of African history and culture.2 It is fiction,
but it is nevertheless based on clear evidence about what happened to immi-
grant black children in that period in England.3,4 Although the picture is more
complex than in the 1970s, fairly recent research has shown that in England,
children identified as Black Caribbean and Mixed White and Black Caribbean
are twice as likely to be identified with Social, Emotional and Mental Health
needs as White British pupils.5 Research in the US has shown similar disparities
continue to the present day.6
DOI: 10.4324/9781003294894-1
2 Introduction
in the very act of thinking. For many people, particularly those whether nom-
inally on the right or the left, who feel a commitment to the ideals of a liberal
democratic state, October 7th and its aftermath was such a caesura. In par-
ticular, the realization, which was perhaps too long in coming, that much of
left politics truly excluded Jews from its preoccupations, inevitably raised the
question of what was in fact the basis for those preoccupations. Just as Western
communists could not escape questioning the basis of Marxism in the wake of
Stalin’s atrocities, so today we similarly have to ask what values and frameworks
underpin the political agenda of the left, and are these ones that we can share
in? Inescapably, this also involves probing what values underlie the activism
of those adopting a sociological critique of education and inclusion, and are
those values that we can all share? As an orthodox Jewish writer on inclusion,
I cannot but contend that this is a crucial, inescapable question for education
and inclusion.
Answering such questions involves grappling with the challenge and diffi-
culty of uncertainty. This is something Bion was not afraid of and in this he
followed in the footsteps of Keats. As Keats illuminates for us in the quote
from his letters at the start of the book, uncertainty can have a terrifying
quality. This is not though, a reason to turn away from the fray.
In this book I refer to education and inclusion, as opposed to inclusive edu-
cation, or inclusive pedagogy. This is because I feel that these terms come with
an unwarranted unity, i.e. that they suggest a settled and uncomplicated pos-
ition on what they mean. My aim with this book is to illuminate and explore
how complicated and importantly unsettled inclusion is as a term. Specifically,
I explore the values and political value systems that underpin the ways in which
difference is conceived broadly, consider how these values are often in tension
with each other, and then consider the implications of that tension for edu-
cation, with a particular focus on the classroom and the class teacher. Thus,
I aim to provide further theoretical underpinnings for the concept of inclusion
through an examination of tensions inherent within current approaches to it.
In particular, I use the lens of value pluralism11 to interrogate such tensions.
I explore the implications of a range of political value systems, including clas-
sical liberalism, much neglected in debates in the field. Drawing on Berlin’s
idea of negative liberty, I explore the extent to which sociological perspectives
on inclusion, which might be considered as having resonance with Berlin’s
notion of positive liberty, have drawn on hegemonizing conceptualizations
of inclusion rooted in social justice perspectives. Through identifying and
exploring the tensions such approaches have tended to ignore, and identi-
fying the different value positions entailed, I consider the extent to which such
tensions can or cannot be resolved in the classroom.
This does not make the book an argument for a liberal approach to educa-
tion or to inclusion, but rather its aim is to highlight the ways in which varying
political value positions, including liberalism, are inescapably embedded
within practice in education. This I believe then serves to open up a space for
a debate on the ensuing complexity, which I argue is more useful than current
4 Introduction
References
1. Education review: how we taught Black boys to fail. BFI. Accessed February
21, 2024. www.bfi.org.uk/sight-and-sound/reviews/education-steve-mcqueen-
small-axe-british-school-institutional-racism
2. Bebbington C. Reflection on Steve McQueen’s ‘Small Axe: Education’ Film. Allfie.
Published December 21, 2020. Accessed February 21, 2024. www.allfie.org.uk/
news/blog/refl ection-on-steve-mcqueens-small-axe-education-film/
3. Coard B. How the West Indian Child Is Made Educationally Subnormal in the
British School System: The Scandal of the Black Child in Schools in Britain. New
Beacon Books, Ltd; 1971.
4. Wallace D, Joseph-Salisbury R. How, still, is the Black Caribbean child made
educationally subnormal in the English school system? Ethn Racial Stud.
2022;45(8):1426–1452. doi:10.1080/01419870.2021.1981969
5. Strand S, Lindorff A. Ethnic Disproportionality in the Identification of Special
Educational Needs (SEN) in England: Extent, Causes and Consequences (Report
on DfE/ESRC Funded Study). University of Oxford Accessed February 4, 2024.
https://ora.ox.ac.uk/objects/uuid:a28b7858-994a-4474-9c4b-6962d1f6da41/
files/maea51f1ea29cde0e36c13a9e2a9dd838
6. Department for Education. 2020 Individuals with Disabilities Education Act
Annual Report to Congress; 2020. Accessed February 21, 2024. https://sites.
ed.gov/idea/2020-annual-report-congress-idea/
7. Finklestein V. Attitudes and Disabled People: Issues for Discussion. World
Rehabilitation Fund, Inc; 1980.
8. Oliver M. The Politics of Disablement. Palgrave Macmillan; 1990.
9. Barton L. Disability, Politics and the Struggle for Change. Routledge; 2013.
10. Bion WR. Two Papers: ‘The Grid’ and ‘Caesura’. Routledge; 1977.
11. Berlin I. Two Concepts of Liberty. Clarendon Press; 1958.
1 What Is Wrong with
Inclusion Today
applied to gaze of the human sciences falling on the disabled body and indi-
vidual, and then by extension the child with special educational needs. As
Olssen21 notes, Foucault and indeed other deconstructive thinkers, particu
larly Derrida, use such models to play with how we might interpret the actions
of social actors, shying away from actual prescriptions about the real-world
policy implications of their work. This, as Ball22 identified, derives at least from
some extent from their recognition of the relativism of their position in that if
social practices and rules are inescapably historically and culturally constructed,
then it’s not immediately clear what the basis is for privileging one model or
approach over another. Indeed, one of the key critiques that Foucault makes of
Marxism is that it fails to recognize its positioning as an Enlightenment mode
of thinking tied to the conditions of the late 20th century.21 Foucault is also
critical of Marxism for its underlying rationalist focus on human agency. We
can perhaps extend this criticism to Soviet psychology and cultural-historical
theory. For Foucault, a key element of his thought is the deconstruction of the
pre-social autonomous human agent –regarding the subject as both arising
from the social field, and not having an existence that can meaningfully be
considered as separate from the social field. It is of course this insight that,
perhaps sometimes too simplistically, underlies the critique made in the social
model –that to regard the individual as having internal (and thus autonomous)
qualities that exist separately from the social field, is untenable. Linked to this,
Foucault’s positioning of power and knowledge as mutually constitutive, and
at play in all social fields, similarly suggests that it is through discovering their
particular applications now and in the past (i.e. “archaeology”), for disability
theorists at least, that patterns of oppression instantiated through the operation
of the human sciences could be uncovered and remedied. As noted though, the
extent to which Foucault himself argued for an activist position, i.e. to make
recommendations for social change based on his philosophy and analysis, is
somewhat unclear.22 Olssen21 suggests that Foucault may have considered his
approach suited to bringing about change in a local rather than global way,
whereby local patterns of power, subjectification and resistance can be explored
and revealed thus allowing the actors in the social field to at least understand
experiences more clearly, or change them to bring about, in local contexts the
equalization of power relations. Thus, Foucault, answering the question, “what
replaces the system?”, responds:
Thus, it seems that Foucault, in terms of the possibility for change, could
be seen as setting out a non- idealist perspective, i.e. one that recognizes
the impossibility of idealism. However, it’s fair to say that the translation of
Foucault’s ideas into the sociological critique of the medical model in dis-
ability studies and the field of special educational needs, has been much more
8 What Is Wrong with Inclusion Today
sanguine in calling for both local and global change.24–26 It’s hard not to see
the supranational movement around inclusion in educational settings as indeed
pointing towards some sort of utopia. However, as Berlin notes,27 utopian
movements carry a risk of a form of oppression themselves, particularly if their
underlying rationales remain unclear. The more salient point for the argument
I am making here is that in this move to activism, and the specific content of
what precisely we might draw from sociological critiques, as translated into a
“movement” for inclusion, is unclear.
At the same time, in material reality, of course, no one can doubt the
importance and force of this movement. There is, for example, near universal
acceptance that, in terms of special educational needs, nobody wants to go
back to the situation in many countries in the 1940s, 1950s and later, where
some children were regarded as “educationally subnormal”, and consigned in
some cases to bleak specialist provision where they were both conveniently out
of sight and out of mind, and where no real thought was given to their poten-
tial, their agency or their needs. There is, as Nussbaum28 might put it, a broad
agreement on the “conception of the good”, in terms of thinking about diffe-
rence in educational contexts. However, this wide acceptance has masked con-
siderable complexity and tension.11 The term inclusion, widely accepted as such
a conception of the good, lacks conceptual clarity and specificity. It is true that
approaches such as the biopsychosocial model have attempted to overcome
the unresolved tensions between sociological and psychological perspectives
on difference, particularly by recognizing the bodily reality of impairment.29–
31
I would posit that the actuality is that despite these efforts, the tensions
remain unresolved. The evidence for such lack of resolution is all around us.
Anyone who has attended an academic conference in the field of education
or examined the papers published in many leading education journals will
have seen the presentation of papers and research, which whilst no doubt not
decrying the broad conception of the good of inclusion, come from radically
different epistemological positions on how to conceive of difference. In parallel,
despite the warm sounding preambles of international agreements and local
legislation, following the trajectory of policy development post Salamanca, the
phrase “reasonable adjustments” or “reasonable accommodations” invariably
appears in the text.3,32 One does not need to consider in depth the political
debates, primarily led by communal and activist groups, about the problematic
nature of this language,33,34 to understand that the word reasonable reflects
a significant site of unresolved tension. Some of this tension, in fact a cru-
cial element of it, arises, I propose, from the idealist underpinnings of the
inclusion movement. Sociological perspectives on difference, whether deriving
from discursive sociological approaches such as Foucault or Derrida (at least
in their activist forms), or from Marxist perspectives, tend, as Berlin35 pointed
out, to have an idealist underpinning, in that they at least create the impres-
sion that a final undisputed resolution to the question of how to deal with
social issues, including the issue difference, is possible to achieve. It is this
that has led us, in contemporary debates on inclusion in education, to naively
What Is Wrong with Inclusion Today 9
consider that there are simplistic solutions to the complexity of dealing with
difference in the classroom. If only we can make sure that teachers have the
correct attitudes and beliefs,9 if only we can get schools to adopt the right
leadership models, if only we can get the correct mix of placement decisions
and parental choice, if only we can have some more funding, then we can
achieve truly inclusive schools, and a truly inclusive educational system.36 It is
not, of course, that we should not debate these matters, nor that they are not
of crucial importance in the lives of children with special educational needs,
their families and their communities. Indeed, they are of crucial importance
to school leaders and teachers, particularly those teachers at the “chalk face”,
who are at the locus where tensions in policy get played out. However, the
point I am making is that the conceptual emptiness of the term inclusion, the
lack of definition of what it might actually mean, prevents us from properly
engaging in this debate. Conceptual terms which lack proper definition and
derive from critically undertheorized idealism have a tendency to undergo a
sort of mission creep. In respect of the term inclusion in the education space,
this means that inclusion has at times been considered as equivalent to, or to
encompass, concepts such as equity, democracy, diversity and so on.37 Yet too
often this happens by a sort of sleight of hand, whereby this conceptual elision
is just accepted as unproblematic. However, it is not at all unproblematic, as
it deprives us of the very critical conceptual tools that we need to make sense
of the sites of tension, and the resulting debates about what actually we can
do, and the limits of what we can do, in terms of working with difference in
educational settings. I will return to some of the ways in which this happens in
more depth in the next chapter.
One consequence of this conceptual elision in current debates on inclusion
is that, in a sense, only one side of the argument is being properly considered.
There are plenty of accounts of education and inclusion from the perspective
of the sociological critique6,38,39 and from a sociocultural perspective.40–42 Yet
there has been, in my view largely due to the underlying idealizing tendency
in how the term inclusion has been conceived of and deployed, a lack of con-
sideration of other perspectives, which implicitly adheres to critique of psy-
chological perspectives. Specifically, classical liberal, neoliberal, communitarian
and indeed neo-conservative perspectives on underlying concepts including
the purposes of education, the positioning of agency and autonomy in society,
and political perspectives on the responsibilities or not of the state to individ-
uals and families, and the resultant implications of such concepts for notions of
inclusion in the educational field, are to a significant extent underplayed in the
literature. This means that the relevance and implications of the value priorities
of these perspectives, which cannot be ignored given their penetration into the
real world, are largely absent from the debate. Now I should note that arguing
for a full consideration of perspectives is not the same as arguing that the
missing perspectives are, in some sense, correct or the right ones. It is rather
to argue that the conceptual elision of the term inclusion, in masking over the
different perspectives that can be taken, renders the debates that do take place
10 What Is Wrong with Inclusion Today
Identification/Resource-Stigma
Norwich considers that these include primarily identification, i.e. the act of
applying the categorization and label to the child. In the dilemma of diffe-
rence framework, identification (or as Norwich puts it the resource-stigma
dilemma) is considered as providing a gateway for the allocation of resources
and required provision, but at the same time carries with it the stigma of the
label. In relation to provision, Daniels45 has questioned whether in educational
settings this is meaningful, pointing out the frequent lack of connection, in his
view, between traditional diagnostic categories and educational strategies. In
respect of stigma, there is also the linked issue of teacher expectations and of
fixed notions of ability.46,47 In other words, the teacher, and indeed the wider
community of school adults, can translate a diagnostic label, or even a fuzzy
label such as special educational needs itself, or terms just used to denote that
children need a bit more help, such as the use of “SEN Support” as a category
in England mainstream schools, into a perception of individual children as
inherently lacking potential, and not just lacking potential now, but in a fixed
way throughout their school careers and beyond.48
Placement
Curriculum
the school leadership corporately, might make about the issue of resourcing
valid? What if the teacher feels overwhelmed by the complexity of the task of
meeting all these needs –how should that be regarded?
These are questions primarily of resource allocation, including importantly
the allocation of a key limiting resource –that of the teachers. Political values
are the level at which such issues, i.e. dilemmas of and choices about resource
allocation, occur. We can attempt some mapping between the legal and pol-
itical value level to exemplify this. Thus, the identification dilemma could be
mapped to a site of tension between the value of participation or belonging
versus a value of equality of opportunity. Such a tension could operate in mul-
tiple ways. For example, the stigma attached to identification could reduce
participation or belonging, yet labelling could allow for targeting of needs
leading to more equal participation in learning. Alternatively, the identifica-
tion dilemma could be considered a site of tension for the value of liberty (i.e.
the free opportunity to maximize one’s individual potential) versus the value
of equality of outcome in that identification implies preferential resource allo-
cation or changes to the classroom to meet the needs of individual children
which may not always be optimal for other children. Liberty versus equality of
outcome as a site of tension can also be considered to apply in the placement
and curriculum dilemmas. Placement in mainstream might imply differential
resource allocation to meet individual needs and specific curriculum adap-
tation which implies tension between meeting the needs of the individual
(equality of outcome) and the needs of the wider group of children in the
school (liberty). The dilemma of difference, as a legal and thus process level
analysis, tends, I argue, to mask these value-based tensions, which operate
at a wider political value level. Its application in the field may also mask the
resource restraints which underpin sites of tension. Mapping the dilemma to
value tensions shows how the dilemma is usually about how to allocate scarce
resources, i.e. how much scarce resource could be allocated to meet the needs
of an individual child as opposed to meeting the needs of the whole class.
A focus on value tensions I contend has more potential to illuminate the actual
sites of tension, particularly in regard to limited resources. Thus, the dilemma
of difference does indeed help in identifying these questions and tensions, but
perhaps does not give enough purchase in terms of working through in more
useful depth how these questions might be properly answered. For example,
how much time and effort should the class teacher allocate to the needs of our
putative actor? What are the limits? Is there a minimum and maximum expect-
ation? Where does the responsibility for effort lie? How much responsibility
in terms of effort (also a resource issue) devolve on the child themselves (or
their family), or are considerations of individual effort extraneous (whether
in whole or in part) to what we should be thinking about with regard to
inclusion? The point is that the current debates in the field about inclusion
too often refuse, often due to ideological overdetermination on the part of
theorists, to dig under assumptions about the political values and frameworks
we might use in answering such questions.
14 What Is Wrong with Inclusion Today
The issue of resources and how they are allocated, and how we might think
about whether this allocation is fair, and what impact that might have on
others either in society more widely or in the microcosm of the society of
the classroom or school, is a fundamental underlying issue in philosophical
debates about the political structures of society and formulation and applica-
tion of public policy in modern day societies, and in terms of debates on the
aims, purposes and formulation of education policy in particular.59,60 Yet there
is currently limited discussion of the underpinnings of such debates on pol-
itical values in relation to the issue of inclusion in education. I propose that
by delving in these underlying debates on political values, we can further illu-
minate the answers to some of the questions I have identified. The importance
of such an endeavour can be seen by reflecting for a moment on the point that
these are questions which, whether explicitly or implicitly, are “live”, every day,
in the minds of all teachers and school leaders.
Hegemony
There is, as noted, a sense in which inclusion as a term has undergone a form
of “conceptual creep”. Some have referred to this as a form of conceptual
hegemony.61,62 Hegemony in modern times is a term heavily influenced by
Gramsci’s63(3.2) use of it in Marxist theory to indicate the development of
consensus in society by which modern states, often through the activities of
intellectuals, won over “potentially hostile social groups and classes”64 and
thus deflected threats to the power of the state. Thus, hegemony involves
a mix of both consensus and compromise in relation to ideology (which
penetrates through structures of civil society, such as the church, schools etc.)
and which is operationalized in a pragmatic political sense, thus requiring a
level of consensus across potentially disparate positions. It is in this sense of
trying to achieve consensus across positions that are actually disparate that
we might apply the term hegemonic to inclusion. The epistemological point,
independent of the term used, though, is that inclusion has tended to expand
the reach of areas that it covers and often is presented in the literature as being
either equivalent to or overlapping with terms such as democracy, equality,
equity and social justice.65–67 As Norwich13 has noted, if it means all these
things or equates to any or all of them, then it is hard to specify what it
does mean as a differentiated concept. Putting this in Gramsci’s terms, con-
sensus might be achieved, but importantly what is meant in terms of material
relations might be unclear. Consensus for Gramsci is linked to the “foun-
dational Marxist principle that social consciousness ‘corresponds’ to material
relations of production”.64(3.5) I would propose that a Marxist view of material
relations is not fundamental to recognizing, as Gramsci does, that political
economic questions underpin ideological consensus and cannot be ignored.
In other words, we need to understand what a concept means in terms of its
implications for resource allocation to make sense of it in a political sense.
Thus, although I make use of the term hegemony in this book in relation to
What Is Wrong with Inclusion Today 15
Such a move often involves a particular positioning which even though it may
conceptualize democracy as deliberative, i.e. as a process for the negotiation of
different perspectives within society, ultimately uses the force and authority of
the majority to come to decisions on such different perspectives. This is often
linked to a universalizing function, in which once such decisions are made, the
state takes on a role to promote such perspectives as a good within society,
the authority for such positioning as a good comes through the decision of
the majority. Olssen’s discussion of thin communitarian perspectives on edu-
cation,21 and Carr and Kemmis’69 (broad) critical perspective on education,
are two good examples of this approach. Of course, there have been consid-
erations of the relationship between inclusion and democracy, with Marion
Young70 in particular focusing, through a critical theory lens, on how inclu
sion in respect of democracy needs more focus on facilitating participation in
the political process, specifically for marginalized groups in society, in add-
ition to notions of deliberative democracy. As Biesta71 discusses, considering
Young’s approach in relation to education, schooling plays a central role in the
question of how and under what circumstances the capacity for participation is
developed. However, for both Young and Biesta, a detailed discussion of what
inclusion might mean in this context is lacking, except for their assertion that
it has some connection, as above, with a critical, revolutionary concept of the
“good”, which is unproblematically to be imposed via democratic processes.
Yet there is of course a quite different liberal perspective on democracy, the
tradition of Mill, Locke, de Tocqueville, and Berlin, which sees the primary
function of democracy as a structure and associated processes to defend the
rights of the individual against the power of the state, a key element of which is
to protect private property rights. One could consider these two quite different
approaches as, in Berlin’s terms, a positive liberty versus a negative liberty
approach to democracy. These different approaches potentially imply quite
contrasting emphasis on political values and on resource allocation –most
16 What Is Wrong with Inclusion Today
However, quite how these are selected, established and derived, who they
apply to or indeed how they might intercalate with each other is somewhat
underexplored by Booth and by most writers making use of the list. Nor is
it very clear how conflicts between these values might be considered in the
practice of inclusion. Some of the terms are also used in a particular way –
so for example courage is used perhaps in the sense of being courageous in
overcoming oppression. This is of course a perfectly laudable value in itself,
but it is also quite different from how courage, or other omitted values such
as loyalty and responsibility, might be employed if coming from a classically
liberal or conservative, as opposed to, as Booth does, a postmodern largely
Foucauldian-inspired perspective.
Going back to our fictional classroom story, might there be a conflict
between compassion and honesty, for example? Could honesty involve an
evaluation of the limits of ability for example, and would this be in conflict
with the values of hope or compassion? Putting this another way, should the
teacher have realistic limits on the expectations for what individual children
can achieve, i.e. expectations and thus curriculum aims which are tailored
to their needs? If so, is that in conflict with maintaining their self-esteem?
It’s not clear to me that this list, and others like it, in their raw form, do
particularly help teachers in understanding what inclusion might mean for
classroom practice. It’s also notable that in Booth’s list and others,77,78 no in-
depth account is taken of resource constraints. Thus, in these lists of values
for education and inclusion, the omission of consideration of the tensions
between equality of opportunity, equality of outcome, and liberty, contingent
on resource limitations, central to such debates in all spheres of the work of
the welfare state, including very much in education,59 seems a notable absence.
I argue that at least part of the reason for this lack of clarity and indeed preci-
sion in terms of what value conflicts there might be is due to the hegemonic
quality that inclusion as a concept has taken on in its trajectory from discursive
sociological critique through to activist agenda in education, which has served
to empty it of truly useful content. In order to arrive at a more productive
account of inclusion, one which takes proper account of underlying conflicts
about values, I will turn in the next chapter to a more in-depth discussion of
political values in relation to public policy.
References
1. Foucault M. Madness and Civilization: A History of Insanity in the Age of Reason.
Psychology Press; 2001.
2. The Salamanca Statement and Framework for Action on Special Needs Education.
Published online 1994. Accessed January 24 2024. www.unesco.org/education/
pdf/SALAMA_E.PDF
3. United Nations. Convention on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities Treaty Series,
2515, 3.; 2006.
4. Barton L. The Politics of Special Educational Needs. Routledge; 1988.
18 What Is Wrong with Inclusion Today
5. Hodkinson A. Key Issues in Special Educational Needs and Inclusion. Sage; 2015.
6. Hodkinson A. Special educational needs and inclusion, moving forward
but standing still? A critical reframing of some key issues. Br J Spec Educ.
2020;47(3):308–328. doi:10.1111/1467-8578.12312
7. Hedge N, MacKenzie A. Putting Nussbaum’s Capability Approach to
work: Re-visiting inclusion. Camb J Educ. 2012;42(3):327–344. doi:10.1080/
0305764X.2012.706252
8. Terzi L. Beyond the Dilemma of Difference: The Capability Approach to
Disability and Special Educational Needs. J Philos Educ. 2005;39(3):443–459.
doi:10.1111/j.1467-9752.2005.00447.x
9. Mintz J, Wyse D. Inclusive pedagogy and knowledge in special educa-
tion: Addressing the tension. Int J Incl Educ. 2015;19(11):1161–1171.
doi:10.1080/13603116.2015.1044203
10. Oliver M. The Politics of Disablement. Palgrave Macmillan; 1990.
11. Hegarty S. Inclusive Education—a case to answer. J Moral Educ. 2001;30(3):243–
249. doi:10.1080/03057240120077246
12. Reindal SM. What is the purpose? Reflections on inclusion and special educa-
tion from a capability perspective. Eur J Spec Needs Educ. 2010;25(1):1–12.
doi:10.1080/08856250903450806
13. Norwich B. Addressing Tensions and Dilemmas in Inclusive Education: Living with
Uncertainty. Taylor and Francis; 2013. doi:10.4324/9780203118436
14. Hodkinson A, Vickerman P. Inclusion: Defining Definitions. In: Brown, Zeta,
ed. Inclusive Education: Perspectives on Pedagogy, Policy and Practice. Routledge;
2016:7–13.
15. Obrusnikova I, Block ME. Historical context and definition of inclusion.
In: Haegele J, Hodge S, Shapiro D, eds. Routledge Handbook of Adapted Physical
Education. Routledge; 2020:65–80.
16. Norwich B. Recognising value tensions that underlie problems in inclusive educa-
tion. Camb J Educ. 2014;44(4):495–510. doi:10.1080/0305764X.2014.963027
17. Florian L. Preparing Teachers to Work in Inclusive Classrooms: Key Lessons for the
Professional Development of Teacher Educators from Scotland’s Inclusive Practice
Project. J Teach Educ. 2012;63(4):275–285. doi:10.1177/0022487112447112
18. Bromley M. Teaching pupils with SEN. SecEd. 2018;2018(25):8–9. doi:10.12968/
sece.2018.25.8a
19. Education Endowment Fund. Special Educational Needs in Mainstream Schools: A
Guidance Report. EEF; 2020. Accessed February 21, 2024. https://files.eric.
ed.gov/fulltext/ED612231.pdf
20. Foucault M. Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison. Pantheon Books; 1977.
21. Olssen M. Liberalism, Neoliberalism, Social Democracy: Thin Communitarian
Perspectives on Political Philosophy and Education. Routledge; 2010.
22. Ball SJ. Foucault, Power, and Education. Routledge; 2012.
23. Foucault M. Revolutionary Action. In: Bouchard D, ed. Language, Counter-
Memory, Practice: Selected Essays and Interviews. Cornell University Press;
1977:218–233.
24. Ainscow M. Taking an inclusive turn. J Res Spec Educ Needs. 2007;7(1):3–7.
doi:10.1111/j.1471-3802.2007.00075.x
25. Ainscow M. Towards Self- Improving School Systems: Lessons from a City
Challenge. Taylor and Francis Inc.; 2015. doi:10.4324/9781315818405
26. Slee R. Inclusive Education Isn’t Dead, It Just Smells Funny. Routledge; 2018.
What Is Wrong with Inclusion Today 19
Forms of Liberalism
Classical liberalism takes many forms although most would agree that in its
initial forms it developed as a reaction against the unrestrained power of the
monarch over the individual in the 17th century.8,9 Laissez-faire liberalism,
associated with Adam Smith, Hayek, Locke and Nozick, has a more economic
focus, positioning private property rights and the working of the market, along
with restrictions on the role of government in interfering with either of these.
Of course, concerns about a particular sense of justice also interpenetrate in
this mode of thinking with concerns about the right of the individual and the
family to be free from interference from the state, particularly in terms of cul-
ture and family and religion, in a much wider sense than the purely economic.
In contrast, social liberalism8,9 has a modified conception of justice, privileging
a concern for fair allocation of resources to ensure that all members of society
have a minimum set of those required to achieve their goals. Rawls, Dworkin,
Kymlicka and even perhaps Nussbaum are commonly associated with this type
of liberalism,10 which tends to give a greater role to the state, particularly in
terms of ensuring that resources are shared out in a more equal fashion.
The focus on what Berlin would call negative liberty in liberal thought
raises the issue, as noted, of the warrants, in liberal thought, for privileging
the ideas of non-interference by the state given the commitment to pluralism.
A universalist perspective on liberalism, based on the liberal conception of
the free agentic individual coming in a Kantian sense via rational enquiry to
an understanding of the untethered ideal, proposes that liberal principles and
structures (most commonly the structures of liberal democracy) are the best
possible form of government, and have a universal application independent
of culture, geography or time. In contrast, a particularist perspective on liber-
alism makes more restricted claims, namely that liberal principles and structures
might best apply to those who have a tradition aligned to liberal values or
value ordering. Therefore, the idea that liberal democracy is something that
should be promulgated across the world has less resonance. Crowder8,9 notes
that the most common approach in the literature to justify liberalism is neutral
universality, which Crowder argues Rawls11 adopts in his influential Theory of
Justice. Such a conception draws on Locke and Mill in setting out that the role
of the state should be restricted, as in Berlin’s negative liberty, to preventing
harm to others in a narrow sense, tolerating (neutrally) a range of conceptions
of the good life and associated modes of community living and operation.
calls this the original position and in this there is a “veil of ignorance” which
prevents the individuals in the situation knowing anything about people in the
situation, including themselves, such as their age, gender, wealth, religion, or
their conception of the good. This means that, as Mandle and Roberts-Cady12
note, they must consider the principles from the perspective of everyone. What
they do know, Rawls explains, is that rationally they would prefer a particular
share of what he calls primary social goods, such as basic political freedoms, and
fair equality of opportunity to access positions within society. Rawls argues then
that the principles which would be derived from the first position are:11(p.266)
First principle: Each person is to have an equal right to the most extensive
total system of equal basic liberties compatible with a similar system of lib-
erties for all. [the liberty principle]
Second principle: Social and economic inequalities are to be arranged so
that they are both:
(a) to the greatest benefit of the least advantaged [the difference principle]
and (b) attached to offices and positions open to all under conditions of fair
equality of opportunity [fair equality of opportunity principle]
underlying liberalism in that it reflects his belief, shared with Berlin, that it is
the ability for the individual to make choices that is an overarching value.
which underpin liberal democracy constitute the path to the good life, and
the state is fully justified in intervening, all the way down through public
and private structures, to promote this. Thus, from the perspective of Raz, in
respect of education, the state is justified in promoting a required curriculum
that actively promotes liberal values, even where they conflict with the private
values of families.
Such debates are represented in the influential writings of Terry Mclaughlin35
on political values in education, particularly in relation to civics. He discusses
how, whether in terms of a specific civics curriculum, or more widely in terms
of the broader hidden curriculum of the school, civics can be positioned as
either thick, actively promoting liberal values, or thin, minimizing the extent
to which such values, beyond a minimum required for social functioning
within the school, are promoted. Mclaughlin’s importance is his reminder to
us that the extent to which common schools (i.e. mainstream schools funded
by the state and potentially open to all children) should or should not be
involved in promoting a particular conception of the good life has been an
area of considerable debate.
A thick position such as that adopted by Raz is, in Berlin’s terms, much
closer to a view of positive rather than negative liberty. For Berlin, the danger
of such a position, in my reading, is the risk of the active denial of freedom by
the state. Berlin, in Two Concepts of Liberty, argues that the dangers of positive
liberty, as proposed by theorists such as Raz, are that once this view is taken,
once it is assumed that the real self, perhaps unknown to the individual, can
be uncovered through his education into the true morality, then the natural
tendency is for those who know best to “bully, oppress, torture them…”2(p.180)
in the name of freedom. As Gray4 notes, Berlin argues that counter to the
Enlightenment, there is such real “higher” self that can be so differentiated.
Of course, there is potentially quite a distance between bully and torture, and
as Olssen7 rightly points out, considerable difference between oppression in
authoritarian states and oppression in liberal democracies. However, I tend
to disagree with Olssen, as indeed did Berlin,4 that somehow the mere fact of
democratic structures or consensus obviates the risk of state oppression. It’s
also the case that Berlin did not make this critique specifically in relation to
universalist liberal thinkers (although neither did he exclude them). His target
was more widely all hegemonic modes of thinking, all approaches which he
saw, as outlined in his essay on Historical Inevitability,3 as predicated on a view
of the one true approach to the good life –idealist perspectives (including
those stemming from the Enlightenment) which privileged the march of his-
torical forces, such as in Marxism, and which we could extend, I think, to the
hegemonic tendency implicit in activist forms of the sociological critique. It
is also relevant to note again here that Berlin did not have a simplistic view of
positive versus negative liberty –he saw a place for both, but wanted neverthe-
less to emphasize the risks of positive liberty.9
30 Value Pluralism and Liberalism
Communitarian Perspectives
The communitarian critique of Rawls in particular challenges the liberal
account of justice, arguing that it fails to adequately consider the relationship
between individuals and their communities, leading to a limited view of the
state’s role. This critique is particularly focused on Rawls’ concept of the self,
which is seen as overly individualistic and detached from communal values.36,37
Sandel’s20,25 well-known communitarian critique of Rawls argues that Rawls’
(and other social liberals) argument that the asocial Kantian individual is a pre-
attached consciousness that is split off from ends when making decisions about
them, i.e. that they somehow choose in some disinterested way, is untenable.
Sandel argues that in fact ends are constitutive of identity (as the self is at
least partially socially situated), and thus decisions about ends involve an intra-
subjective awareness of how the individual is linked to wider community-based
ends as well as ends purely related to the individual’s own self-interest. This
ontological reality, Sandel argues, is masked, for example, by the way Rawls’
constructs the first position scenario. Rawls’ response to these critiques in his
later writing13 is that he does not set out a metaphysical account of the person
overall but rather an account located in relation to the political sphere only,
i.e. people can have ends and attachments and community and identity in the
private sphere and this is to be expected as long as this is voluntary (although
communitarians might ask how voluntary).27 Thus, Rawls argues that it is in
the political sphere that it is important to preserve a democratic space for the
“right” before the ‘good’. However, as discussed, it is questionable whether
the private and public can be so neatly split off either ontologically or prac-
tically, and if they can, whether this then reduces the scope of the claims of
liberalism.
Communitarians such as Sandel also make the useful distinction between
identity formation and agentic action, arguing that rather than being asocial,
identity is created through positioning in community, and that a distinction
can be drawn between the creation of the self and the self as an active agent.
Thus, it can be argued that for Sandel and other weaker communitarian
critiques, their position is not to suggest a full-blown deconstruction of the
subject as an active agent,8 and the debate may be considered more practically
as being about how we balance these values with others in the political and
policy structures within liberal democracies.13 However, this still leaves the
question as to practically how such balancing should happen or what values
should be involved.
local level, resources are a key issue, as the neoliberal policy trajectory suggests,
for any aspects of the operation of public policy.43
[coercion is] … made to serve another man’s will, not for his own but for
the other’s purpose.
These are both economic and political concerns. Decisions on taxation, the
public administration of the welfare state, public pronouncements on what
the good life should be by government, the “nudging” of people’s behaviour
proposed by some thin communitarians,7,47 all involve, in social democratic
policy, the coercion that neoliberal thinkers like Hayek fear. However, des-
pite these concerns, in terms of public policy, the imperative to consider and
respond to difference or disadvantage, and to provide for these via the welfare
state, is one of the defining aspects of neoliberalism, in contrast to classical
liberalism.38 However, neoliberal thought has also set limits on the welfare
state and its size, and prioritized personal responsibility and choice in ways
which often contrast, significantly, with “progressive” perspectives.48 Yet in
bringing a critique of neoliberalism in public policy, many coming from an
activist sociological, Marxist, or social democratic positions have failed to give
a proper consideration to the actual positions made by theorists such as Hayek.
As Kristol noted,49 the tendency is to just assume the argument, and thus to
avoid debating whether there might be sites of tension to be considered. From
the perspective of education and inclusion, such an approach fails to consider
that there are different values and perspectives which are inevitably in play
Value Pluralism and Liberalism 33
how this intercalates with the private domain and the rights of, for example,
minority groups who opt for an unexamined life for their children.
Hayek felt, as with Friedman, that the state’s involvement in directly pro-
viding education, in order to obviate risks to freedom, should be minimized
and in particular argued, in common with Adam Smith,59 that the state should
not be involved with the training and provision of teachers and thus for an
independent market for teachers to offer their services, as state control would
‘corrupt’ the teachers as well as erect unnecessary barriers to entry to the pro-
fession.40 Thus, they argued for a position which was common in England prior
to the 1870 Education Act and the advent of universal state education. Of
course, such an argument may well appear, to many of us, as jarring in the 21st
century, although it is relevant to note that historically, in general, the advent of
mass schooling preceded government regulation of education.59 Further, quite
a few modern theorists (not least Foucault) have argued for greater consider-
ation of the negative impacts of state regulation in the caring professions.60-62
I spend time reflecting on these historical trajectories not to bring an argu-
ment for some kind of laissez-faire utopia (or dystopia), but rather to note
that the common international consensus about both education and educa-
tion for inclusion obscures, as perhaps Foucault might have argued, particular
patterns of thinking, which have a history and derivation, and that uncovering
these may allow us to better understand, in my terms, the tensions (if not the
power relations) that we need to deal with in approaching difference in the
classroom.
and critical reasoning, i.e. the ability to discern between different propositions
and make choices, independently of their parents or community. The fact
that universally in criminal systems, account is taken of a child’s age and that
they are treated differently from adults in terms of their choices and actions,
provides an acknowledgement that children are not viewed as inherently
autonomous and that although they may well be borne with the capacity for
autonomy, in its application this is a skill that they need to develop.69 Children
are inescapably borne into particular societies and particular families, with par-
ticular parents. In fact, it can be argued, as in communitarian approaches, that
the development of autonomy is dependent on networks of social relations
and on a process of learning.70–72 Children are thus, in such a framework,
inherently non-autonomous as they start out and gradually develop the skill
of autonomy. We are not therefore self-creating as autonomous individuals, in
some rationalist asocial Kantian sense, but can, as we achieve maturity, develop
(or have developed) our capacity for autonomy, i.e. we can develop the cap-
acity for self-direction.57 Some theorists, though, such as Galston,58 privilege
concerns about negative liberty, arguing that, as with critical thinking, as some
groups do not value autonomy, a commitment to diversity of the concep-
tion of the good life means that autonomy is not necessarily something that
the liberal state should actively promote even in the public sphere. Galston58
overall argues that what is most important for the liberal state to value is tol-
erance of diversity of opinion, and that all but a very minimal promotion of
civics should not be undertaken by the state in the public sphere, particularly
in terms of what the state mandates in relation to education provision. Thus,
a Rawlsian delineation between public and private spheres is unworkable, as it
runs the risks of the state actively promoting autonomy as a value which may
be antithetical to the private values held by particular groups in society, with
the caveat common to many liberal thinkers that there remains a right of exit
from the sub-group protected by the state.8
One way in which the issue of resources and disadvantage has been addressed
is in the work of Amartya Sen94 and Martha Nussbaum95 on capability theory.
Sen’s key point, as expressed by Anderson,96(p.320) is that:
Thus, Sen notes that in order to ensure equality in the social goods required
to participate in society, account needs to be taken of the fact that people have
different abilities to convert economic resources (i.e. money or services) into
such goods (capabilities for functioning) and that social constraints may simi-
larly cause differential ability to make use of resources. Both Sen and Nussbaum
see education as a central capability. Terzi97 has considered in some depth how
the capability approach can be applied to inclusion and education, arguing
Value Pluralism and Liberalism 41
Critiques of Participation
Autonomy
Liberal perspectives on autonomy and agency also have wider relevance for
inclusion and education. Autonomy provides the foundation for agency, and
in the liberal tradition, part of the rationale for autonomy is very much its
role in facilitating agency. Agency in Kantian terms is the rational individual
mind exercising the right to choose, whether this is through, as McGee100
puts it, the classic case of deciding whether or not to raise your finger in the
air, or by extension in any number of other arenas areas such as, for example,
deciding as a teenager to go to the shops after school rather than come home.
Liberal thinking positions autonomy and by corollary agency as central values,
although as we have seen in communitarian and conservative critiques of
liberalism, this is balanced by social concerns or competing values such as
duty. Thus, Rawls and his communitarian critics don’t deny the importance
of autonomy but rather debate what emphasis should be given to it. Thus,
it may well be that other values and related needs suggest there are good
reasons to constrain autonomy, particularly when this is about protecting
others from harm.
Implications in School
space, we can come back to everything else tomorrow. Yet in the real word of
limited time and resources, there are losses involved for the children, perhaps
for the state even, in making such a decision. So I think it’s quite safe to say
that in the vast majority of classes in the vast majority of countries, the teacher
would say no, or might perhaps spend a limited time on learning about space,
because of the need to balance the autonomy and agency of this one child
with both the autonomy of other children (let’s assume that not all of them
want to spend the day learning about space) and wider concerns about limited
resources for teaching the rest of the curriculum. Concerns about resources
then intercalate with concerns about autonomy and agency in the classroom.
If we now consider a child identified as having special educational needs, say
age 6, in a mainstream primary classroom. Let us say that this child has some
specific learning difficulty and finds it more difficult than her classmates to
recognize phonemes and blend words. The teacher prepares some scaffolding
for her in the afternoon before the lesson, to help her access the written work.
This helps but still during the lesson the child keeps calling the teacher over
to help her with the blending. What should the teacher do? Perhaps she could
sit her next to a more able child by her to help with the reading? Perhaps
she should come and sit with the child for an extended period, leaving other
children in the class who might also need her attention? Perhaps she should
encourage the child to try and work by herself, looking out to praise her when
she makes this effort? Perhaps she should give her in the moment an alterna-
tive text that is easier for her to access even if it does not help her develop her
reading skills? Now, of course, there is considerable literature on these kind
of issues on education and inclusion and literacy teaching, which proposes
many helpful things to consider in terms of classroom organization and peda-
gogy,101 particularly around differentiated instruction and universal design for
learning102,103 and the teacher and the school may well be able to make sig
nificant use of these suggestions in making decisions both in the moment and
reflectively later on how best to approach supporting this individual child in the
context of the whole class. Nevertheless, these approaches are not, I contend,
a complete solution to the issues of limited resources and of conflicts in rela-
tion to autonomy and agency that this case and the million others like it that
take place in classrooms across the world every day throw up. In an obvious
sense, the time that the teacher spent on for example developing scaffolding
resources for one child is a limited resource that cannot then be used on doing
something else, whether that something else is something in the teacher’s life
(from the perspective of work/life balance) or preparing other things for the
class as a whole. The case also raises issues of autonomy, agency and liberty –
thus what if the child asked to help with the reading does not want to, and
even if they are willing, harbour somewhere a resentment that they could not
get further with reading the book they wanted to at the pace they wanted
to. There is also an intercalation between ability and effort, linked to agency.
When deciding whether to ask the child to essentially be more independent
and try harder, the teacher needs to make a judgement and thus a decision on
44 Value Pluralism and Liberalism
the balance between ability and effort on the part of the child. How much is it
about an impairment in their ability to do the task (or a variation in capability)
and how much is it about the amount of effort that they are making. Putting
this another way, to what extent are they exercising the agency that they do
have to decide to or to not make that effort, and if they are not making it,
then there is a wider value that the teacher is likely wanting to promote about
“working hard” or “doing our best”, which is an emphasis on excellence as
a value. As Pogge and Pogge10 note, although they might want to make a
judgement about this, differentiating between ability and effort (for anyone
making such a judgement in any context) is not always very straightforward,
and as such, this makes it more difficult for the teacher to make a decision.
However, whatever decision is made is a balancing between issues of equality
in terms of how resources are allocated to ensure equality of opportunity, and
agency. Lukianoff and Haidt,104 writing about higher education, suggest that
from a liberal perspective there should be more emphasis in education on the
old aphorism of “Prepare the child for the road, not the road for the child”,
i.e. in dealing with difference in education we should give more primacy to
matters of simple equality in resource allocation, partly because a principle of
equal treatment (an aspect of strict justice) places limits on the extent to which
we should vary resource allocations. In my view, this is inescapable in any real
world where resources are limited. Of course, in terms of both national and
supranational policies, which are inevitably located in the real world, there is
clear recognition of resource limitations, which is why phrases like “reason-
able accommodations” are a feature of their language. The word reasonable
implies that because resources are not unlimited, there are limits, based on a
principle of justice, to how far the state or organizations (or individuals) can
go in terms of meeting individual needs. Shakespeare105 has shown, in respect
of disability studies and sociological activism, the importance of considering
real-world constraints and the limits of how the social model can be applied.
Thus, Shakespeare notes how the idea of universal wheelchair accessibility is
subject to real-world constraints, such as the fact that it would be virtually
impossible to make the “mountains, bogs, beaches” 105(p.213) of the world fit
for wheelchair use.2
It is the case that many who disagree with the liberal and neoliberal concep-
tion of education have objected to the inclusion in policy documents of this
phrasing. Sometimes this is aligned to a sociological critique of disability.106,107
Sometimes the critique goes further and is aligned to a wider critique of capit-
alism in general, and/or that sees the political structures of liberal democracy
as reflecting historical patterns of unequal resource allocation which needs
to be corrected.108 These are legitimate positions to take, although they are
only positions that are themselves subject to critique and debate, and it’s also
unclear, in my view, how useful they are to teachers and schools in most of
Value Pluralism and Liberalism 45
the real world in terms of thinking about policy and practice. The concept of
inclusion, particularly as it is applied in respect to education in the academic
literature, tends however to ignore such issues of resource limits, resource allo-
cation decisions and value conflicts. Inclusion is seen in an idealized way, and
the process of idealization that it undergoes in its application in the real world,
means that it becomes somewhat denuded of content. Cigman109 has argued
that inclusion used in this way can become blind to suffering, suggesting for
example that sometimes when inclusion activists argue for mainstreaming
for all, this involves a lack of consideration of how this might work in prac-
tice, and a lack of concern for potential harms, in that some children may
well be much happier in special rather than mainstream settings. I think this
overstates the case in that inclusion theorists and activists are, I think, usually
very concerned with individual suffering –they are certainly not, as perhaps
implied, Robespierres of 21st century education. However, I think the sub-
stantive point is that the idealizing tendency in inclusion does often mean
that there is a lack of sufficient consideration of how things might actually
work in practice. The argument I am making is not that the concerns of inclu-
sion in education are not important, they are, but that in order to properly
understand those concerns and how they can be addressed, we need to con-
sider more precisely the different values involved, and the tensions and clashes
between them. I shall turn now to Berlin’s account of value incommensur-
ability and Crowder’s account of Berlin’s value pluralism, which will provide
some tools for considering this matter.
could equally consider, as I have noted before, value system conflicts between
liberal and communitarian perspectives –freedom versus solidarity; diversity
versus community, or between liberal and conservative views –debate versus
agreement, experiment versus tradition, and the liberal downplaying of other
values such as duty, courage and perhaps love. Berlin’s point is as much that
when we have such value conflicts, choosing one over the other leads to an
absolute loss, and as Crowder notes, “the losses that result from trade-offs
cannot be wholly compensated but will inevitably possess an absolute and
perhaps tragic quality”.8(p.62) In my classroom example above, the child who is
asked to help with the reading absolutely loses the time that they could have
spent pursuing reading at their own level and interest. One of the notable
things about education is that the time that children are children is short and
limited, and I think, as Berlin suggests, that whatever the social recompense,
the impact on “neighbourhood effects”, you cannot ever get the time back.
This argument is also at the core of those liberal thinkers (such as Hayek111 or
more recently Stokes112) who argue that social justice is a meaningless or at
least misleading term, in that social effects and strict justice, in liberal terms,
are not commensurable. Berlin also uses this point of value incommensur-
ability to (heavily) critique idealist philosophies and theorists who think that
such value conflicts are easily resolvable or that if they are not resolved, this
is not due to actual conflicts between values but rather to human wickedness,
ignorance or self-interest, particularly class self-interest.3 For Berlin, this con
cern plays a central role in his preoccupation with negative liberty, as a bul-
wark against the idealizing tendency and its inherent dangers in thinking that
(a) simple solutions are possible, and that (b) the state can impose their view of
simple solutions on individuals and families without costs. At least in part, his
experiences during the Russian Revolution persuaded him that they cannot.
If we apply this to education and inclusion, there are a number of resonances.
For example, the idea that there are simple solutions or formulations such as
“Good teaching for children with SEN is good teaching for all children”113
that can allow us to escape the need to think about the trade-offs involved in
dealing with difference in the classroom. As well, the idea that simply chan-
ging attitudes and beliefs, that is teacher self-interest, or teacher ignorance or
indeed teacher wickedness in not having the right attitudes and beliefs, in and
of itself can somehow solve these tensions. There are more areas which can
be noted, but the point is that inclusion as an unexamined concept does not
obviate the value tensions involved in education.
Critics of Berlin, notably Dworkin,114 have suggested that Berlin overplays
incommensurability, and that by restricting the scope of their conception of
values, i.e. so that (in some ways similarly to Rawls) more recognition is given
to their contingent composite nature (for example, liberty means freedom
to do what you want as long as it does not impinge on others), the issues
identified by Berlin become much less troubling. Berlin and others argue in
response that many people hold perspectives that are deeply attached to the
“pure” conceptualizations.115 However, if Berlin is right in proposing that
Value Pluralism and Liberalism 47
values are incommensurable and that there are absolute losses involved in
making decisions, then, as such, decisions and trade-offs still need to be made.
Crowder8,9 highlights that Berlin wants to highlight that national and local pol
itical decisions about such trade-offs are very serious and significant. Crowder
agrees with Berlin that compromise is possible and that this can best come
about through processes that are both democratic and liberal and that pay due
regard to the importance of the values at stake; it involves “negotiat[ion] in
the spirit of … pluralist virtues”.8(p.255) Further, Berlin, in common with Kekes,
and as agreed with largely by Gray, argues that cultural tradition should play
a significant part in making choices amongst incommensurable values,8 and
linked to this, Gray4 argues that this implies that it is the pragmatic, con
crete particulars of individual conflicts (which are inevitably cultural in a wide
sense) that need to be taken into account, as opposed to higher level idealist
perspectives, when making decisions.
Implications?
If then value pluralism is viewed as important in public policy, and there is
no easy idealist set of measures that can be appealed to in deciding between
different values, what should we do?
Mclaughlin53 adopts a similar stance to Berlin in his proposal that in
addressing such value conflicts in the classroom, teachers should adopt an
approach based on (an Aristotelian) phronesis, whereby teachers exercise
their localized professional expertise and experience. Thus, judging indi-
vidual situations based on our local practical wisdom offers the best approach
to choosing between values in day-to-day experience. Such decisions in rela-
tion to the particulars of cases will involve qualitative judgements based on
the ethical experience of that situation, rather than any quantitative measure.
In the context of education and inclusion, this might be considered a call
for the exercise of professional judgement based on both experiential know-
ledge116 and an individual’s wider understanding of their own individual con
ception of the good life and what is accepted (in a limited fashion which
respects individual and family autonomy and diversity of perspectives) in
their society as constituting the good life.2,91 From Berlin’s perspective and
that of liberal educational theorists, as I have noted, that conception of the
good life would recognize that civics in common schools needs to be limited
in its scope. It would include a recognition that a range of values could be
recognized as worthy of note. It would hold a neutral perspective on the
good life.
Relativism?
The issue of how to think about difference in the classroom inevitably relates to
the sociology of knowledge and the role of categorization. The sociological cri-
tique of the medical model, derived from a discursive approach, problematizes
the way in which, in education and more widely, the lens of the human sciences
focused on the child with special educational needs masks the ways in which
power might be wielded and abused. Thus, as in the Short Axe Education film,
the seeming objectivity of the IQ test is used to reinforce false assumptions about
the ability of boys of Caribbean heritage and then to use labelling, falsely, to allow
teachers to have low expectations about them and to impose those expectations
on the child, their family and their wider community. The sociological critique
deconstructs the very basis for the knowledge represented by the IQ test or psych-
ology more widely, positing the medical idea that some objective deficit in the
child themselves is based on a false ontological and epistemological assumption.
The idea of deficit thinking is prominent in contemporary educational
thought and practice, often linked to accounts of racist and classist modes
of thinking.120 Anecdotally, in teacher education, certainly in England, par
ticular approaches to special educational needs which are based on categoriza-
tion and labelling are often criticized with phrasing such as “Oh that’s deficit
thinking”. Yet this is only one way in which this can be viewed. Mapping this
onto debates about liberal political values, there is unquestionably a link to
differing perspectives on knowledge. This is something I will explore in more
depth in Chapter 3. Broadly, scientific realism in some form112 which considers
knowledge, to a lesser or greater degree, as having a purchase independent of
what is perceived, i.e. to represent something that can be objectively known,
and that has some freedom from the social and cultural context in which the
knower and the known are embedded, is associated with classical and neo-
liberalism. Berlin in Historical Inevitability3(p.150) notes that if all things are
regarded as inherently subjective, then (a) they have no meaning particularly if
terms such as subjective cannot be taken to mean their opposite, and (b) such a
position robs us of the possibility of assigning choice (agency) or desert to indi-
vidual actors, who cannot logically be taken to have the possibility of escaping
their local contextualization. Thus, for Berlin and indeed most classical liberal
thinkers, notions of the objectivity of knowledge and of agency, responsibility
and by extension individual justice, are inherently linked. A liberal perspective,
whilst not at all ignoring concerns about differential treatment based on false
assumptions, nor the issues identified in the dilemma of difference at a process
level, raises the question of whether there is some sense in which we can and
indeed should sometimes, on ethical grounds, make empirical determinations
50 Value Pluralism and Liberalism
about individuals and their capacities that have some independent reality. This
raises a number of questions for education and inclusion, including the status
and role of assessment; whether there are truly deficits internal to the child;
and the status and relevance (e.g. for teacher education) of evidence on special
educational needs derived from the human sciences.
Disability as Identity
Disability activists have for some time made the argument to “re-classify” dis-
ability not as a negative marker but as a form of identity. The sociological cri-
tique of the medical model, particularly in terms of its use of Foucault, provides
the space for resistance, and one way that can be seen to have occurred is
by oppressed groups taking the label applied as an act of oppression, and
subverting or reclaiming this as a badge of identity.121 Although originally more
visible in respect of clearly recognizable disabled groups such as the deaf com-
munity,122 in recent years the move towards such a reclassification has spread
more widely in terms of general societal perceptions, notably in relation to
the autistic community.123 Debates about perceived language markers have also
accompanied this development, and the move to use an adjectival label (i.e.
autistic person rather than person with autism) links directly to the move to
re-claim autism as a badge of identity. The move towards disability as identity is
linked to motivations around representation, autonomy and agency, as well as
the desire to promote a sense of pride, and to autonomously negate the nega-
tive associations of the label. One can view such a move perhaps as part of a
biopsychosocial perspective on difference, in that it seeks to mediate between
internal characteristics (by positioning these as markers of identity), whilst not
denying their reality, and providing an alternative lens through which the inter-
action of internal characteristics with societal mechanisms can be viewed. They
also stake out a position on entitlement. They argue, in contrast to much of the
liberal perspective on difference and economics, that the criteria by which, for
example, resource allocations are judged, and thus what justice might be taken
to mean, are flawed. Thus, they argue against a social liberal Rawlsian notion of
justice as fairness, in terms of how difference is positioned as a deficit in terms
of mutual cooperation. They also reject a Rawlsian (and certainly more liber-
tarian) perspective on justice, which sees limits to the extent to which resources
should be allocated towards the needs of individuals with disabilities.
In the classroom, such considerations intercalate with previous questions
raised in this section, particularly the extent to which difference should be
accommodated to meet the needs of the minority, even when this conflicts
with the needs of the majority.
Earlier I set out a particular position on the child in relationship to parents and
the family in relation to the state, which might be called traditional, and which
Value Pluralism and Liberalism 51
Performative Assessment
The sociological critique suggests that the way that the lens of the human
sciences is brought to bear on difference assumes a range of normative
52 Value Pluralism and Liberalism
Notes
1 I do not use neoconservative in its “everyday” use which is usually conceived of
in terms of a particular stance on US and Western policy on foreign intervention.
Rather, I use it in the sense it is applied to Scruton, Hazony and other conservative
thinkers such as Robert George, in the last two decades, to denote those theorists
who have wished at least to some extent disaggregate traditional conservative from
classical liberal thought, particularly in terms of how the rationality of the liberal
Enlightenment opposed the idea of tradition and natural law. This is not to argue
that there are no connections from this mode of approaching neoconservatism
to the everyday use of the term, but rather to note the focus in neoconservatism
on the recovery of tradition on the political right, which is the sense in which
I approach it in this book.
2 I would contend that it is situations of resource constraint such as this that the cap
ability model fails to provide a solution for.
References
1. Berlin I. Political ideas in the Twentieth Century. Foreign Aff. 1950;28(3):351–358.
2. Berlin I. Two Concepts of Liberty. Clarendon Press; 1958.
3. Berlin I. Historical Inevitability. Oxford University Press; 1954.
4. Gray J. Isaiah Berlin | Princeton University Press. Princeton University Press; 2013.
Accessed April 3, 2024. https://press.princeton.edu/books/paperback/978069
1157429/isaiah-berlin
5. The Influence of Russia and 1917. Isaiah Berlin Online. Accessed February 23,
2024. https://isaiah-berlin.wolf.ox.ac.uk/node/4424
6. Popper KR. The Open Society and Its Enemies. Fifth edition, revised. Princeton
University Press; 1971.
Value Pluralism and Liberalism 53
33. Galston WA. Realism and Moralism in Political Theory: The Legacies of John
Rawls. In: Shaun Y, ed. Reflections on Rawls. Routledge; 2009:111–129.
34. Raz J. The Morality of Freedom. Clarendon Press; 1986.
35. McLaughlin TH. Citizenship, diversity and education: A philosophical perspec-
tive. J Moral Educ. 1992;21(3):235–250.
36. Sandel M. The procedural republic and the unencumbered self. In: Avnieri S,
de-Shalit A, eds. Communitarianism and Individualism. Oxford University Press;
2011:12–28.
37. Sarma AJ. Rawls’ Idea of a Liberal Self: A Communitarian Critique. J Indian
Counc Philos Res. 2020;37(3):383–402. doi:10.1007/s40961-020-00212-8
38. Biebricher T. Globalists: The End of Empire and the Birth of Neoliberalism.
Perspect Polit. 2018;16(4):1157–1159. doi:10.1017/S1537592718002219
39. Whyte J. The Morals of the Market: Human Rights and the Rise of Neoliberalism.
Verso Books; 2019.
40. Tooley J. E.G. West: Economic Liberalism and the Role of Government in Education.
Continuum; 2008.
41. Monbiot G. Neoliberalism–the ideology at the root of all our problems. The
Guardian. www.theguardian.com/books/2016/apr/15/neoliberalism-ideol
ogy-problem-george-monbiot (Published April 15, 2016). Accessed March
4, 2024.
42. Bourassa G. Neoliberal multiculturalism and productive inclusion: Beyond the pol-
itics of fulfillment in education. J Educ Policy. 2021;36(2):253–278. doi:10.1080/
02680939.2019.1676472
43. Njoya W. Free Markets and Economic Progress. In: Njoya W, ed. Economic
Freedom and Social Justice: The Classical Ideal of Equality in Contexts of Racial
Diversity. Palgrave Studies in Classical Liberalism. Springer International
Publishing; 2021.
44. Hayek FA. Individualism and Economic Order. University of Chicago Press;
1980.
45. Hayek F. The Road to Serfdom. (Caldwell B, ed.). The University of Chicago
Press; 2007.
46. Hayek F. The Constitution of Liberty. The Definitive Edition. University of Chicago
Press; 2011.
47. Einfeld C, Blomkamp E. Nudge and co-design: Complementary or contradictory
approaches to policy innovation? Policy Stud. 2022;43(5):901–919. doi:10.1080/
01442872.2021.1879036
48. Slee R, Tait G. Ethics and Inclusive Education: Disability, Schooling and Justice.
Springer; 2022.
49. Kristol I. The Neoconservative Persuasion: Selected Essays, 1942-2009. Hachette
UK; 2011.
50. Friedman M. The Role of Government in Education. In: Solo RA, ed. Economics
and the Public Interest. Rutgers University Press; 1955:123–144.
51. Suissa J. Anarchism and Education: A Philosophical Perspective. Routledge; 2006.
52. Kymlicka W. Education for Citizenship. In: Halstead, J, McLaughlin H, eds.
Education in Morality. Routledge; 1999: 78–102.
53. McLaughlin TH. The Burdens and Dilemmas of Common Schooling. In: Carr
D, Halstead M, Pring R, eds. Liberalism Education and Schooling: Essays by
T.H. Mclaughlin. Imprint Academic; 2008:137–174.
54. Gutmann A. Democratic Education. Princeton University Press; 1999.
Value Pluralism and Liberalism 55
79. McLanahan S, Sandefur GD. Growing up with a Single Parent: What Hurts, What
Helps. Harvard University Press; 2009.
80. Parke M. Are Married Parents Really Better for Children? What Research Says
about the Effects of Family Structure on Child Well-Being. Centre for Law and
Social Policy. Accessed 24 March 2024. https://eric.ed.gov/?id=ED476114
81. Brighouse H, Swift A. Family Values: The Ethics of Parent-Child Relationships.
Princeton University Press; 2014.
82. Dwyer JG. Moral Status and Human Life: The Case for Children’s Superiority.
Cambridge University Press; 2010.
83. James MR. Deliberative Democracy and the Plural Polity. University Press of
Kansas; 2004.
84. Levinson ML. Taking action: What we can do to address the civic achievement
gap. Soc Stud Rev. 2009;48(1):33– 36. doi:dash.harvard.edu/handle/1/
10860768
85. Munoz- Dardé V. Is the family to be abolished then? Proc Aristot Soc.
1999;99(1):37–56. doi:10.1111/1467-9264.00044
86. Noddings N. The Language of Care Ethics. Knowl Quest. 2012;40(5):52–56.
87. Arneil B. Becoming Versus Being: A Critical Analysis of the Child in Liberal
Theory. In: Archard D, Macleod CM, eds. The Moral and Political Status of
Children. Oxford University Press; 2002:70–96.
88. Ramaekers S, Suissa J. The Claims of Parenting: Reasons, Responsibility and Society.
Springer; 2011.
89. Winnicott DW. Playing and Reality. Routledge London; 1971.
90. Burtonwood N. Cultural Diversity, Liberal Pluralism and Schools: Isaiah Berlin
and Education. Routledge; 2006.
91. Kekes J. The Morality of Pluralism. Princeton University Press; 1993.
92. Ferber MA. A Feminist Critique of the Neoclassical Theory of the Family.
In: Moe, K ed. Women, Family, and Work. John Wiley & Sons, Ltd; 2003:9–24.
93. Roberts-Holmes G, Moss P. Neoliberalism and Early Childhood Education: Markets,
Imaginaries and Governance. Routledge; 2021.
94. Sen A. Development as capability expansion. Community Dev Read. 1990;41:58.
95. Nussbaum MC. Frontiers of Justice. Harvard University Press; 2007.
96. Anderson ES. What is the Point of Equality? Ethics. 1999;109(2):287–337.
doi:10.1086/233897
97. Terzi L. Beyond the Dilemma of Difference: The Capability Approach to
Disability and Special Educational Needs. J Philos Educ. 2005;39(3):443–459.
doi:10.1111/j.1467-9752.2005.00447.x
98. Hodkinson A. Key Issues in Special Educational Needs and Inclusion. Sage;
2015.
99. Mintz J, Wyse D. Inclusive pedagogy and knowledge in special educa-
tion: addressing the tension. Int J Incl Educ. 2015;19(11):1161–1171.
doi:10.1080/13603116.2015.1044203
100. Magee B. Confessions of a Philosopher: A Journey Through Western Philosophy.
Random House; 1998.
101. Mitchell D, Sutherland D. What Really Works in Special and Inclusive
Education: Using Evidence-Based Teaching Strategies. Routledge; 2020.
102. King-Sears ME. Facts and fallacies: Differentiation and the general educa-
tion curriculum for students with special educational needs. Support Learn.
2008;23(2):55–62. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9604.2008.00371.x
Value Pluralism and Liberalism 57
DOI: 10.4324/9781003294894-4
60 Knowledge and Liberal Perspectives on Inclusion
adopting such a position, has in fact done real harm, not least because by
decrying realist perspectives on knowledge, and particularly the place of know-
ledge within the curriculum, it has denied oppressed groups the chance to use
such knowledge to help themselves overcome that very oppression. However,
in making such an argument, Young5 does tend somewhat towards the polem
ical and somewhat elides the complex debates about realism, putting the horse
rather too much before the cart. Others have made similar moves. Stokes13 for
example has also critiqued decolonization as a movement within higher edu-
cation, without staking out the connection between accounts of realism and
its critiques and such a position. A particular gap in such accounts is to make
a reasoned connection between public policy positions, values and knowledge.
horizon that is knowable. As per Berlin, in the extreme, the positioning of the
knower rather than knowledge as the arbiter of truth can be seen as lying at
the root of totalitarian abuses of the individual.
Young also suggests that the straw man argument put forward, as he sets
out, by some postmodernists against knowledge, by only engaging in a some-
what extreme position on knowledge, effectively avoids having to engage in a
proper debate about knowledge, and debates about knowledge become a form
of “attack”.5(p.25) I would argue that one could see this as a form of defended
idealism (not something picked up on by Young), which we can see in the
instantiation of inclusion as a concept without very clear content. Although
not directly stated perhaps in the postmodernist sociological critique, for some
academics and activists it still represents something of a final, even teleological
truth, and that leads to a monist tendency whereby critical engagement with
content becomes undesirable, leading eventually to a concept that is somewhat
empty. One aspect of this emptiness, following Young’s logic, would be an
inadequate account of both what knowledge is or could be, and its potential
or actual role in either policy or practice. In terms of teacher education for
inclusion, for example, following Young, if process and product in relation
to what we know about difference in the classroom are elided as in the post-
modernist critique, then there is no external independent purchase point for
determining criteria for what is true or useful for teachers to know. Further,
particularly relevant in terms of education and inclusion, if identitarian pos-
ition, i.e. who knows rather than what is known –another aspect of denying
a properly independent purchase point for truth or value –are given primacy,
as in some views within postcolonial15 and critical theory,16 then it is unclear
whether we have a useful or indeed true basis for deciding what it is that
teachers should know about that may help them with effectively dealing with
difference in the classroom. It can be argued that understanding the social and
cultural contexts of knowledge production and use, one aspect of which is
how individuals may feel about such production processes that exclude them,
or understanding the false application of such knowledge and its consequences
is important. I would strongly agree that it is. Social realism, however, argues
that equating this with the position that knowledge itself is relativist (the straw
man argument) is false.
Social Realism
Durkheim’s social realism attempts to give a more effective account of the
social context of knowledge by proposing that we can split off the social and
historical context of knowledge production from the independent constituent
features (the truth value) of such knowledge.17,18 All knowledge is produced
by social actors working in a particular time, place and a particular social and
cultural context. Thus, there is always a risk that there are cognitive biases in
what knowledge producers (science and scientists in its wider sense) choose
to focus on, the methods they use, and the way they interpret the evidence
64 Knowledge and Liberal Perspectives on Inclusion
that they procure. This can indeed result, taking the sociological critique
of the positioning of children with special educational needs by the human
sciences has demonstrated as one example, in unequal opportunity. However,
whilst recognizing these constraints, social realism simultaneously notes that
such biases are not inherent to the process of knowledge production and use,
nor are they necessarily the dominant factors. The development of systems
of knowledge, including the relationships between concepts, and their differ-
entiation from every day concepts are a key part of Durkheim’s theory,5 and
are linked to disciplinary rules and processes, which tend to be agreed across
groups of scientists. Such processes and rules thus provide a warrant for know-
ledge as justifiable belief. Thus, Durkheim was interested to seek out a demar-
cation, or the possibility of a demarcation between what is social and what is
independently true in knowledge production and use.
Durkheim also proposes a particular ontological basis for knowledge, based
on its social nature. Starting with the observation that social ideas such as reli-
gion arise from social fields yet are not linked to actual phenomena in nature,
Durkheim theorizes that this demonstrates the way in which networks of
concepts arise, which are validated and given their truth value by their social
acceptance within the group, and argues that scientific concepts, albeit linked
to observable phenomena, develop and are validated in a similar way. Durkheim
further argues18 that this validation arises from a correspondence between the
structure of society and the structure of knowledge. Thus, Durkheim’s view
on knowledge can be seen to be a quasi-Kantian view where social structures,
which have an independence from (albeit supervening on) individual minds,
provide the inescapable structures through which knowledge is produced and
used. Within that context, classifications of structures of knowledge then have,
through their mapping back onto such (a priori) social structures, a claim to
objectivity.
However, as Young5 notes, Durkheim’s theory has a distinctly modernist
and indeed idealist flavour in that it suggests that the social structures that
map onto knowledge structures are often common across different societies,
which opens it up to the (sociological) critique that is ahistorical and indeed
even asocial (as if every society is essentially the same in these structures, soci-
etal differences, at least in terms of their mapping to knowledge structures,
dissolve). Thus, some argue that Durkheim either collapses back into a naive
realism (or positivism) or makes the perhaps more limited point that external
biases can impact on knowledge producers, which is something that we should
be careful to monitor for.5 I would argue that liberal/traditional “natural law”
arguments, following Kant (discussed below), in terms of common societal
structuring (such as Kekes19), do provide further support, albeit not without
possible critique, for some common social knowledge structures across soci-
eties. However, I contend, as does Young, that despite these critiques, the
differentiation between external and internal factors is the most important con-
tribution that Durkheim’s theory makes, in that it provides support for a view
of knowledge that differentiates clearly between the value of what is known
Knowledge and Liberal Perspectives on Inclusion 65
and the knower, at the same time as recognizing the potential biases arising
from the cultural and historical location of knowledge in a wider social field.
law, which also derives from his Copernican revolution and the idea that the
laws we have are necessary in nature and also related to the structuring of our
sensory equipment. At the same time, for Kant, autonomy is the autonomy to
make choices (i.e. first cause choices as ends and not means) in relation to such
natural moral law, and thus to do the right thing.23(p.152) Thus, for Kant, people
are autonomously moral and, within the phenomenal world, are also ration-
alist knowing subjects. We can trace a connection between Kant’s approach
to rationalist autonomy and choice and classical liberal ideas.26 Although it is
true that Kant’s transcendental idealism simultaneously opened up the idea of
constructionism, and thus perhaps also laid a path which lead to the decon-
struction of the knowing subject,27 Kant’s Copernican revolution lays out a
particular view of the knowing subject which is quite different in terms of its
focus on autonomy, agency, freedom and responsibility from that laid out in
postmodern frameworks.23 It also crucially implies a minimum common set of
values (as in Kant’s categorical imperative), based on the idea that as everyone
has fundamentally the same sensory apparatus, natural laws will be common
across culture, temporally and spatially.
Durkheim’s social realism, as I noted, follows Kant in its idealist positioning;
however, it moves the locus of the ideal “apparatus of perception” from the
individual to the social.
categorize between one thing and another, in a general sense, that leads to
the ability to differentiate between good and evil, or between one value and
another and make choices in relation to them. Similarly, Furedi,33 mirroring
Adorno,34 has argued that this ability to differentiate between values is a fun
damental ethical function, and that such differentiation interpenetrates with
how we ethically make sense of foundational knowledge concepts in society
as well. This can be linked to how we might make sense of difference in the
classroom so, for example, the very idea of different versus normal or typical
could be considered as consequent to the idea of a moral agentic knower
differentiated from what is known. This presents quite a different perspective
on the role of categorization in special educational needs from that of the
sociological critique. Such a position resonates with Young’s5 and Moore and
Muller’s12 consideration of an emphasis on “voice discourses” coming out
of postmodernist and other progressivist positions as being a threat, perhaps
similarly to Putnam, to the application of useful knowledge in society. Thus,
an interrogation of what knowledge is is recast as not just a debate on know-
ledge but on values as well.
Teacher Education
I have elsewhere argued that a similar critique to Rata’s can be brought to bear
upon the relevance of disciplinary knowledge from science, mainly psychology,
for children with special educational needs, in terms of teacher education
and inclusion.2 Such knowledge might include disciplinary knowledge from
psychology about for example autism as a diagnostic category, or could also
encompass knowledge often straddling psychology and education about the
effectiveness of particular evidence-based practices3,42 in relation to different
categories of need such as social, emotional and mental health or areas of phys-
ical disability. This could also include knowledge about typical and atypical
child development, and common pedagogies that are thought to be effective
or helpful.
70 Knowledge and Liberal Perspectives on Inclusion
References
1. Lewis A, Norwich B. Special Teaching for Special Children? Open University
Press; 2005.
2. Mintz J, Wyse D. Inclusive pedagogy and knowledge in special educa-
tion: Addressing the tension. Int J Incl Educ. 2015;19(11):1161–1171.
doi:10.1080/13603116.2015.1044203
3. Mintz J, Seleznyov S, Peacey N, Brown C, White S. Evidence informed prac-
tice for autism, special educational needs and disability in schools: Expanding the
scope of the research learning community model of professional development.
Support Learn. 2021;36(2):159–182. doi:10.1111/1467-9604.12349
4. Norwich B. Addressing Tensions and Dilemmas in Inclusive Education: Living
with Uncertainty. Taylor and Francis; 2013. doi:10.4324/9780203118436
5. Young M. Bringing Knowledge Back In: From Social Constructivism to Social
Realism. Routledge; 2008.
6. Deng Z. Michael Young, knowledge and curriculum: An international dialogue. J
Curric Stud. 2015;47(6):723–732. doi:10.1080/00220272.2015.1101492
7. Scott D. Knowledge and the curriculum. In: Wyse D, ed. Creating Curricula: Aims,
Knowledge and Control. Routledge; 2017:13–28.
8. Sayer A. Realism and Social Science. Sage; 2000.
9. Potter VG. On Understanding Understanding. Fordham University Press; 1993.
doi:10.1515/9780823296330
10. Hetherington S. Gettier Problems. In: The Internet Encyclopaedia of Philosophy.
Accessed March 4, 2024. https://iep.utm.edu/gettier/
72 Knowledge and Liberal Perspectives on Inclusion
Teachers and school leaders are faced with choices all the time, about how to
put to best use the inevitably limited resources they have. I contend that these
choices usually involve tensions about which values to give primacy to. As a
way of illuminating who this operates concretely, particularly within the class-
room, I set out in this chapter a number of scenarios and then explore the
value tensions at play. Firstly, I draw on a recent study by Tse.1 Tse, writing
in 2023, explores the value tensions that school leaders and teachers experi-
ence in working with children with special educational needs in kindergarten
settings in Hong Kong. Hong Kong has a significant level of private provision
of early years education, and principals in such settings have considerable lati-
tude in setting their own admissions criteria and in making decisions about
whether or not to admit individual children with special educational needs.
There are also considerable pressures on principals (i.e. leaders of settings)
in the early years sector in terms of expectations from parents with regard to
the academic level that children will achieve. This is particularly so in relation
to early reading, in the context of significant competition for places in well-
regarded elementary and higher-level educational institutions. Such parental
expectations also create pressure, at least in the minds of principals, about
the potential impact on resources and the overall academic success profile of
all students that might arise from admitting children with special needs into
their settings. In Tse’s study, in two kindergartens, both principals and class-
room teachers were concerned about the impact of children with special edu-
cational needs, who had been admitted to their settings in some numbers, on
resources, particularly the (limited) resource of teacher attention. Teachers’
perceptions were that some children with special needs, in their classes,
required them to give them more individual time and attention, raising the
question of how “teaching resource should be allocated between the majority
and the minority”.1(p.156) One of the teachers in the study expresses the view
that “everyone is equal” and that it is not fair that the “bright ones get less
attention”.1(p.157) One of the principals suggests that with the right training
and “accommodations” teachers can effectively deal with children with
DOI: 10.4324/9781003294894-5
Implications for Education and Inclusion in the Classroom 75
special educational needs in their classrooms; however, she adds the caveat
of “even if it requires slowing down on academic learning…”.1(p.159) Although
the teachers in her study were not inexperienced, Tse goes on to consider the
extent to which additional training about how to deal with varieties of need
in the classroom might alleviate the concerns of the teachers in the study, a
point also reflected upon by the principals themselves.
This example illustrates value tensions between equality of opportunity
and equality of outcome, pithily expressed in the teacher comment “it’s not
fair that the bright ones get less attention”. Equality of opportunity would
suggest that all children independent of their background are entitled to
equal teacher attention. In contrast, a Rawlsian social perspective on justice as
fairness might well suggest that there is a sufficitarian argument for resources
to be unequally distributed to ensure that everyone gets to a minimum
level of outcome. A social relational perspective on rights, such as Felder’s2
emphasis on the need to promote equal representation, would suggest that
children with special educational needs should be given more attention and
time so that they can develop the capacity for representation, an argument
that also resonates with a classically liberal perspective on education’s role
in promoting autonomy. A postmodernist or postcolonial sociological cri-
tique would significantly discount strict justice and equality of opportunity,
and regard a Rawlsian sufficitarian redistributive theory of justice as unten-
able, and rather emphasize the achievement of equality of outcome as a key
value. There is also a further evidentiary aspect to the discussion in that the
question of whether additional training in “inclusive” approaches would
allow teachers, even if resources of time and attention remain limited, to use
that time more effectively to meet the needs of all students. Some theorists
argue forcefully that universalist approaches involving modified pedagogy can
overcome, at least in many cases, resource constraints and attendant tensions.
A particular example is Universal Design for Learning (UDL) which involves
varying (a) presentation of content in different modes to meet different
needs, (b) engagement, particularly promoting small group collaborative
learning, and (c) expression/assessment, giving children choices in how to
present their knowledge and understanding.3 However, given in particular
the lack of penetration of UDL into compulsory phase education or strong
evidence for its impact,4 although I agree that considering the potential of
such approaches is important, whether they can actually in many case over-
come the reality of resource constraints and value tensions in the classroom
is I contend much less clear. Other theorists, such as Florian,5 suggest that
resource limitations and attendant tensions can be resolved in the classroom
by the right mix of attitudes, techniques and training for teachers. I contend
that this is similarly unrealistic, and serves to place too much of the burden
for resolving resource constraints on teachers, treating their time and energy
as far too elastic in character.
76 Implications for Education and Inclusion in the Classroom
Teacher Deliberation
Tse’s study illustrates well how value tensions are very often played out in
the thinking and ongoing reflection on practice (as per Schön6) of teachers.
Mclaughlin7 places an emphasis on phronesis, noting that the tensions over
political values in education usually (although not exclusively) play out in the
decisions that teachers have to make in the course of teaching. For education
and inclusion, as with education in general, these tensions imply value choices
that teachers have to make. To explore these tensions in more depth, I now
bring a series of further case studies which illuminate particular value choices
facing teachers in the classroom.
Consider the following imaginary but, I would argue, quite realistic scenario.
It involves a fifth grade (age 10–11) public school classroom with 25 chil-
dren in a relatively affluent but still socially and ethnically mixed suburb of a
medium-sized city in New England. A new child, Daniel, joins the class after
his parents moved from another city for work. The class has an experienced
teacher, Mrs Marks, who takes the class for most subjects, and a teaching aide
who is there with the class in the mornings. Daniel is a personable child but
Mrs Marks notices fairly quickly that Daniel finds it difficult to sit still in class
or to focus during whole class teaching. Despite using a range of well-honed
classroom management strategies, Mrs Marks feels after a couple of weeks
that Daniel has not really settled well. This is a small school and Mrs Marks
has a strong relationship with the school principal Dr Clancy and Mrs Marks
meets with her to discuss Daniel. Mrs Marks recounts that Daniel frequently
gets up to move about the class, constantly fidgets, and quite often provokes
or distracts other children by poking them or pulling funny faces. Although
Mrs Marks employs a range of positive behaviour management strategies with
Daniel and the class, and she feels that there is not significant disruption to the
learning of other children, she is concerned that Daniel seems both socially
isolated and is not really engaging with learning. Mrs Marks and Dr Clancy
spend time discussing potential approaches. They touch on the question of
whether Daniel might have attention deficit hyperactivity disorder (ADHD)
but don’t feel that seeking a formal diagnosis at this stage is warranted, nor that
this might make any difference to the pedagogical approaches they would con-
sider. They agree that Mrs Marks will arrange to meet with Daniel’s parents.
Mrs Marks does this, and the parents report that Daniel has similar issues at
home and at his previous school, and that they feel that his academic self-
concept as a learner is very low, and they are happy to work with the school in
any way to support his learning and development. Mrs Marks comes up with a
plan for Daniel, based on her discussion with Dr Clancy, the parents, her pro-
fessional experience of working with children with similar issues to Daniel over
her career, and various post qualification programmes on inclusion that she has
Implications for Education and Inclusion in the Classroom 77
attended. The plan includes providing Daniel with a visual schedule outlining
the programme for each day designed to help him stay organized and on track,
and a sensory tool (stress balls) that Daniel can ask to access during the day
if he is finding it hard to concentrate. Mrs Marks also tells Daniel that if he is
finding it particularly hard to concentrate, he can ask for a “time out” and Mrs
Marks will give him a task to do which involves getting up and moving around,
like taking something to the office or another class. Over the next few weeks,
this plan has a positive effect: Daniel becomes calmer in class, the provocation
of other children stops, and he begins to contribute to class discussions. Mrs
Marks notices that at break times he is becoming more socially integrated
with the other children. Mrs Marks also skilfully leverages the sense of cama-
raderie and caring for each other that she had already fostered in the class, to
help the other children recognize that Daniel has particular needs (such as
accessing the stress balls), which the children seem to accept with equanimity.
Mrs Marks is pleased with how things have gone and meets with Dr Clancy to
review the progress made. Dr Clancy congratulates and praises her but at the
end of the meeting also asks how Mrs Marks’ plans for a reading group were
going. Mrs Marks and Dr Clancy had in the last month discussed setting up
a reading group for some of the more advanced readers in the class who were
particularly interested in current events. Mrs Marks says that she has not had
time yet to think about this but will get on to it. At home that evening, talking
to her husband Mrs Marks discusses what has been happening at school, and
expresses some resentment that teachers are just supposed to deal with any
new student who might turn up to their class out of the blue on top of every-
thing else they have to do.
This is an imaginary example but not, I think, an unrealistic one, and many
teachers and academics will no doubt recognize elements of it, and indeed
there are many such accounts in the literature.8,9 In this example, the concept
of inclusion might be seen as the implementation of a set of pedagogical and/
or classroom management strategies to address difference in the classroom
and meet the needs of individual students. Imaginary Mrs Marks demonstrates
that such a body of knowledge exists, as well as perhaps that this might indeed
involve differential pedagogical strategies for students with different needs. It
illustrates that professional experience and training can be brought together
by teachers to meet individual needs. It is also an account, albeit in a restricted
context, of what might be thought of as successful inclusion in that Daniel has
his needs met, at the same time as the needs of the rest of the class also being
attended to. Yet, even in this successful restricted scenario, value tensions are
of course not absent. In my design, Mrs Marks’ concerns about workload,
again something which I think is quite realistic in terms of teacher experience,
raise value tensions. Meeting Daniel’s specific needs, although in this scenario
possible and successful with an attention to individual pedagogic adaptations
and thus satisfying from an equality of outcome perspective Daniel’s partici-
pation and achievement, does come with a resource cost that may impinge on
the equality of opportunity of others. As in the previous example, the time
78 Implications for Education and Inclusion in the Classroom
and attention resource directed to Daniel has to come from somewhere. Mrs
Marks’ capacities are, as with anyone, limited, just as are those of the school
as a whole. The group of children with more ability and/or interest and/or
effort in reading did not benefit from the additional pedagogic input that Mrs
Marks may have had time for if Daniel had not arrived in her class. These chil-
dren thus suffered a loss, in terms of having elements of their needs met, or
having them met in a timely fashion. The argument is also, of course, poten-
tially iterative, in that the allocation of time to the specific needs of the chil-
dren due to having the reading group could be similarly judged or weighed
against a notion of equal time allocation to all children in the class.
This (constructed) scenario also serves the purpose of highlighting how the
issue of where this resource comes from can be glossed both from the per-
spective of the sociological critique in education and inclusion and, indeed, as
argued by Done and Murphy10 in neoliberal accounts of the welfare state which
assign an unmeasured elasticity and associated unlimited locus of responsibility
to staff such as Mrs Marks in this example. It could be argued, as many do,11–13
that this is “part of the job”, and that an open-ended commitment to meeting
all and every need is one of the virtues12 that we might in the modern world
expect of teachers and indeed of schools as institutions. It is also legitimate to
argue that a loss of a fair allocation of resources is reasonable, particularly if
we might argue that in the round –although at certain times certain children
will have particular needs that require more attention,over say for example
the whole of a school year, this roughly equals out. It could be that Daniel’s
needs are temporary, or that the time and attention required by Mrs Marks to
meet them will reduce over time, especially as Daniel settles and the particular
pedagogic approaches put in place become just a routine part of classroom life.
What, though, if this scenario worked out differently? Teachers, whatever their
experience, can be challenged at any point in their career.14 What if, despite the
good intentions and hard work of Mrs Marks and the school, Daniel did not
settle? What if over the rest of the school year he continued to be distracted
in class, and his provocation of other children became worse and really started
to disturb lessons? What if his social integration into the class went back-
wards, and he became unhappy at school and started to refuse to come to
school on some days, making it even more difficult for Mrs Marks to attempt
to include him in class and ensure he progressed in his learning, when he was
in school? What if Daniel’s parents’ marriage happened to break down, and
his self-concept deteriorated further, and he became even more demotivated
in class? Again, although fictional, I think it is as much a plausible scenario
as the first iteration –one that many teachers will recognize and instances of
which also feature, perhaps with even more regularity than the first, in the
literature.15–17 Mapping out fictionally what might happen with this turn of
event –let’s say that Mrs Marks in conjunction with the Dr Clancy, Daniel’s
parents and other staff members of the school and outside agencies –all spend
considerable time thinking about how to address Daniel’s needs and in trying
out different pedagogic approaches with Daniel. Mrs Marks never has time to
Implications for Education and Inclusion in the Classroom 79
come back to the idea of the reading group, and Dr Clancy knows better than
to raise it with her as he is well aware of the limits on her time and energy and
indeed is concerned that even with her extensive experience, the issues with
Daniel are taking a considerable toll on her. It could be argued that there is an
absolute loss in terms of equality of opportunity for other children in the class.
Their teacher has less time for them, gives them less attention, and perhaps
even has less energy and creativity as a teacher. One could argue that there
are compensations –perhaps the children in the class both learn about values
such as kindness, compassion or caring, or even love. Perhaps Mrs Marks still
maintains a collaborative ethos within the class in which there is still a sense of
joint camaraderie and enterprise as a class and as a school in working together
to help Daniel. Yet children are required to go to school. They do not get to
choose the classes they are in or who their classmates are, and in this scenario,
they do not get a choice as to whether or not they want their teacher to spend
far more time with Daniel and his needs than on them and their needs. A lib-
eral political perspective highlights the question of whether the exercise of
values such as kindness or compassion and their consequences can be imposed
on people without limit, as opposed to freely chosen, even in the case of chil-
dren. If we take Berlin’s point that values are incommensurable, the loss of
equal opportunity –of teacher attention, and of learning that might otherwise
have happened –for the children, and perhaps by extension for their parents,
has an absolute quality. In that sense, equality of opportunity for all is not so
easily resolved with differential resource allocation to achieve equality of out-
come for some. There is also a values issue in terms of the loss of energy and
time for Mrs Marks. Perhaps she takes the problems in class with Daniel home
with her, worrying about what else she could do to help him. We know from
a fair bit of literature18–20 that teachers often take intractable problems in the
classroom home. She likely also spends far more time now on planning and
preparing for Daniel’s needs, on top of all the other planning and assessment
commitments that are just there as for any teacher. She spends far more of her
time, a limited resource, on her job than would otherwise be the case. This
is an absolute loss in terms of strict justice for Mrs Marks, as the effort of her
(unchosen) labour goes unrewarded.
Impact on Teachers
Salamanca,21 and other supranational and national legislation all have clauses
about reasonable adjustments/accommodations. They tend, though, to say
little substantively about justice as a value as applied to teachers. A reason-
able adjustment implies that value tensions in relation to limited resource
allocation can be resolved, as long as the trade-off is reasonable, and usually
this is about what might be reasonable in terms of school budgets or impacts
on other children, not in terms of teacher welfare. Berlin’s liberal account
of value pluralism22 reminds us that such trade-offs are not so simple. They
may well be necessary in modern technological societies. They may well be
80 Implications for Education and Inclusion in the Classroom
unavoidable. Yet they have, as Berlin insists, as public policy approaches, ser-
ious consequences.22 In the example above, they are serious for the other chil
dren in Daniel’s class who in the second iteration of the scenario lose out on
the time and attention of their teacher for a large segment of the year. They
are serious for Mrs Marks and her work/life balance. They are of course ser-
ious as well for Daniel and his parents. Deciding what is the best decision or
decisions in such situations is not easy. It’s not easy at a policy level and it’s not
easy for teachers and schools. Mclaughlin’s focus on phronesis7 highlights that
whatever the policy context, it’s teachers who take on the brunt of the respon-
sibility for making these decisions in the context of the day-to-day life of the
classroom. The point I draw from this extended-thought experiment about
Daniel and Mrs Marks is that it is unclear precisely how our current notion
of inclusion, with its tendency to elide these tensions, helps in grappling with
these decisions.
Case 2: Prepare the Child for the Road, Not the Road for the Child?
This again is a fictional but, I would argue, potentially highly realistic scenario.
Alexia is a “high functioning” autistic girl in grade 6 (11 to 12 years of age)
in a class of 30 children at Condol Elementary, a large mainstream elemen-
tary school in a medium-sized city in New Mexico with a diverse cultural and
linguistic intake and many children from lower socioeconomic backgrounds.
Implications for Education and Inclusion in the Classroom 81
A relatively new Charter school in the area with stronger academic results
has recently started to attract parents away from Condol, leading to a fall in
enrolments, and this in conjunction with wider budget cuts by the school dis-
trict has led to significant budgetary pressures on the school leadership team.
Ms Rivera, the class teacher, has ten years of experience and has had consider-
able training in inclusion in the classroom including specific courses on meeting
the needs of children with autism. Alexia’s revised Individual Education Plan
(IEP), following consultation with the school’s educational psychologist at
the end of the summer term in the previous school year, recommended that,
due to her sensory sensitivities, she would benefit from a low arousal envir-
onment. During the previous school year, with a newly qualified teacher with
the class, Alexia’s behaviour had deteriorated, with an increasing frequency of
“acting out”, which caused considerable disruption to the learning of other
children. The psychologist was aware of both practice related to comprehen-
sive frameworks for autism education and support such as TEACCH,25 which
included low arousal as an element, and wider research independent of such
frameworks which shows the potential benefits of a low arousal approach as
a generalized strategy to managing challenging behaviours with autistic chil-
dren.26 The psychologist consulted with Ms Rivera and Alexia’s parents before
the beginning of the new school year and they all agreed that aiming for a
low arousal approach might give a new start to Alexia after the summer break.
However, Ms Rivera found implementing this low arousal approach challen-
ging at the start of the term. In particular, the grade 6 classroom was a new
build construction compared to the lower age groups and has bright fluores-
cent lighting. Ms Rivera worried that his may be over stimulating for Alexia.
Ms Rivera aims, in line with the low arousal principal in the IEP, to mitigate
noise levels in the classroom; however, Ms Rivera tends towards a high-energy
teaching style, and her training and experience in terms of what works for chil-
dren of this age, in general, gravitate towards lots of open discussion, group
collaboration and fun. Despite her best efforts to minimize noise levels, Ms
Rivera struggles to strike a balance between meeting Alexia’s need for a low
arousal environment and facilitating active engagement among the other chil-
dren. As part of the IEP, Ms Rivera set up a quiet space area at the back of the
classroom, which is a desk facing the wall with two wooden panels on either
side to provide a barrier to reduce distractions. Alexia does make use of this
space quite frequently during the school day, but Ms Rivera notices that she
seems quite sad when she is there, and Ms Rivera has a sense, when Alexia
comes back to the class as a whole, that she is lonely and misses the closer com-
pany of her peers in the main classroom area. As part of the IEP, Ms Rivera
restricts the amount of colourful display on the walls of the classroom, out
of concern that this may add to visual over stimulation for Alexia. However,
the grade 6 school curriculum includes an extended art project during the
term, and the children create a series of colourful images based on the work
of impressionist period painters. Ms Rivera feels that it would really add to the
class’s sense of achievement from this project to have this work prominently
82 Implications for Education and Inclusion in the Classroom
displayed within the classroom, but at the same time does not want to further
increase the visual clutter for Alexia. Alexia also very much enjoyed the art
project and produced some of the most high-quality work in the class.
Although this is, again, a fictitious scenario, I think it is one quite recog-
nizable in many classrooms, and is also reflected in the literature. Jordan27 in
particular has pointed out that it is difficult to see how making such changes
in mainstream classroom settings for autistic children will necessarily be peda-
gogically effective for other children. She has considered the type of concerns
in this vignette, i.e. that some, perhaps most children, particularly in elemen-
tary school settings, will benefit from the use of involved classroom displays
and effective “social constructivist” learning may often involve reasonable
levels of noise which would not align with a low arousal approach. This scen-
ario exemplifies in particular tensions between equality of opportunity for the
majority versus equality of outcomes for minority of children. It also illustrates
issues about autonomy, and about the place of knowledge concerning special
educational needs in teacher practice.
From Berlin’s28 perspective, this exemplar case could be considered to
illustrate incommensurability in value pluralism, i.e. that meeting the needs
of individuals causes a loss for the wider group. This case also illuminates
tensions in relation to autonomy. Issues of autonomy and identity have had
particular resonance in relation to autism over a number of decades.29 Of
course, issues of autonomy in the context of education apply to all children.
It is an issue which every teacher (and every parent) negotiates every day, in
every classroom. The child wants to do A and the adult wants them to do
B, often because the adult thinks that A is not good for them or not good
for them at that particular time, and B is. A parent wants their 15-year-old
to stop playing their video game and take out the trash. A teacher wants a
child to read their book in silence with the rest of the class, not chat to their
friend next to them. A parent wants their six-year-old to go to school even
though they really want to stay at home, and forces them to go, perhaps with
the child crying on the way. Discussions about issues of autonomy in rela-
tion to autism tend, though, to have a more intense quality. Peter Hobson,
an influential theorist on psychoanalysis and on autism,30 argued that autism,
with its impairments in intersubjective experience, pushes difference right up
in the face of society. As I have argued,31 how far we should go in chan
ging the environment to meet the needs of autistic individuals, as opposed
to working to increase their capacity to engage with others on their terms,
is a key question for autism education. Hobson30 made this point particu
larly in relation to impairments in social communication and social imagin-
ation. He proposed that the relationships resulting from these are “gifts”,
and not gifts which we should so lightly exclude autistic individuals from. In
2024, these are much less fashionable views. Rather, it is more fashionable
to consider autism, or more widely neurodivergence, from an identity per-
spective, in which any concept of deficit or indeed impairment is excised.32,33
A sociological critique proposes that it is society that needs to change, not
Implications for Education and Inclusion in the Classroom 83
communication) that they want her to develop, even if it is difficult for her.
Ms Rivera may have a similar view to the parents in terms of the value of
cultural tradition, and may also feel that this intercalates with an idea of the
school culture. Alexia herself may also, particularly in terms of friendship,
want to develop the capacity to have friends. There is extensive literature
showing how many autistic children want to be engaged in meaningful social
relationships and friendship,39–41 even if it involves difficulty and effort. Both
her parents and Ms Rivera may think that she is too young (too immature, yet
lacking in capacity) to understand how developing collaborative skills today
may help her with friendship and belonging now and in the future. This
myriad web of interlocking values and tensions are likely at least in parts
incommensurable. For example, some of the suffering by Alexia now would
be absolute, as all suffering is, when offset against future gains in friendship
and participation. Thus, I contend that there are no easy answers. If inclu-
sion means something, it means not an empty idealism, not one rationalist or
Hegelian answer, but a series of complex choices about values. Usually, what-
ever the wider public policy context, these are messy, difficult choices made
by teachers. They are often painful choices as they involve choosing value
A over value B, and not even being sure that what you choose will lead to A or
B. They are painful because they are choices about other people’s lives, and
inevitably sometimes they are wrong and don’t work out. Of course, some-
times they do, which leads to the magical moments, too far and few between,
that make the life of the teacher worthwhile.
I positioned quite a few of the tensions in this case along the classical social
model /sociological critique axis, i.e. –in Lukianoff and Haidt’s42 terms –
should we prepare the child for the road or the road for the child? The socio-
logical postmodernist critique posits a different pattern of emphasis for the
values that I set out above as being in tension. In particular, the value of
tradition and the notion of a set of cultural norms for the classroom, along
with associated pedagogical practices, would have less primacy compared to
equality of outcome linked to ensuring the freedom of particular groups from
oppression. This critique would posit that the emphasis on the knowing sub-
ject and the human sciences in knowing about Alexia in a particular way fun-
damentally misconceives the way in which learning happens for Alexia and
the class. It is from this misconception that the difficulties perceived by the
school, by Ms Rivera and indeed by Alexia and her classmates arise. In terms
of values, resistance might be considered important in the actions of both
Alexia and Mrs Rivera. Losses in terms of justice as desert –for example the
desert of individual children say in terms of having their individual artistic
efforts celebrated by displaying their work within their own classroom, given
that the very idea of the knowing individual subject is questioned –would
take on a different weight. It also accords different weight to the issue of
Implications for Education and Inclusion in the Classroom 85
This case also raises the issue of the place of knowledge about special edu-
cational needs. Molloy and Vasil noted in a well-cited paper on Asperger’s
Syndrome, which effectively lays out the sociological critique of knowledge
(the “voice discourse” in Muller and Moore’s terms), the following in respect
of special needs:47(p.410)
This succinctly sets out the “voice discourse” critique of knowledge in educa-
tion and inclusion and its intimate connection to political values, particularly
liberal or conservative values about tradition and normality. The application
of Molloy and Vasil’s analysis to the case of Alexia is clear. Autism and know-
ledge about it represent an accretion of culturally and historically laden asso-
ciations of power and privilege, predicated on a particular view of normality,
which is designed to position difference as of lesser value. As Young points out
in his analysis of the knowledge turn, such knowledge definitely can be this,
and definitely has been this. Yet as I have noted, if we adopt a Durkheimian
realist view of bias, we can contend that we can split off the accretions of
bias from what might be actual knowledge. This may be knowledge about
people and their lives that could have the capacity to help them in some ways.
Earlier I referred to the evidence on team teaching and its potential. As Cook
et al.23 discuss, the evidence of effectiveness in terms of student outcomes is
mixed, but Scruggs et al.48 set out how theoretically its focus on collaboration,
planning and joint content mastery can bring benefits when dealing with diffe-
rence in the classroom. A school interested in evidence-informed practice and
in developing its organizational capacities around this might through, for
example, a teacher study group engage with this literature.49 The school lead
ership might consider that, as with Daniel’s case, for classes with children with
differences in learning, spending resources on hiring an additional teacher to
team-teach might be worth exploring. They might pilot this say with a supply
teacher for a while, and then if it proved effective, decide to make a permanent
appointment. They might decide to reduce their budget in other areas –say for
Implications for Education and Inclusion in the Classroom 87
example two teaching assistants retire or resign, and they decide not to replace
their posts. They might monitor the impact, for example, on social engage-
ment and friendships of autistic or otherwise neurodivergent children in the
classes, and make further decisions on whether or not to roll the approach out
more widely. In doing so, they would be dealing with knowledge –knowledge
about special educational needs and knowledge derived from academic work
in the human sciences. A fictional example perhaps; however, there are plenty
of examples in the literature about the use of evidence to inform practice in
working with children with special educational needs.50,51 A social realist per
spective on knowledge would admit of the risks of bias, but would maintain
that there is the potential for an independent purchase point on what we can
know and understand about special needs and effective teaching practices that
can add value to practice.
References
1. Tse R. Inclusion of Students with Special Educational Needs: Leadership Values,
Dilemmas and Their Influence on School Practices. PhD (unpublished). UCL
Faculty of Education and Society; 2024.
2. Felder F. The Ethics of Inclusive Education: Presenting a New Theoretical Frame.
Routledge; 2022.
3. King-Sears ME. Facts and fallacies: Differentiation and the general education
curriculum for students with special educational needs. Support Learn. 2008;
23(2):55–62. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9604.2008.00371.x
4. Deunk MI, Smale-Jacobse AE, De Boer H, Doolaard S, Bosker RJ. Effective dif-
ferentiation Practices: A systematic review and meta-analysis of studies on the
cognitive effects of differentiation practices in primary education. Educ Res Rev.
2018;24:31–54. doi:10.1016/j.edurev.2018.02.002
5. Florian L. Special or inclusive education: Future trends. Br J Spec Educ.
2008;35(4):202. doi:10.1111/j.1467-8578.2008.00402.x
6. Erlandson P, Beach D. The ambivalence of reflection –rereading Schon. Reflective
Pract. 2008;9:409–421. doi:10.1080/14623940802475843
7. McLaughlin TH. The Burdens and Dilemmas of Common Schooling. In: Carr
D, Halstead M, Pring R, eds. Liberalism Education and Schooling: Essays by T.H.
Mclaughlin. Imprint Academic; 2008:137–174.
8. Jiménez TL, Venegas CC, Monsalve JT, Calderón AU. Inclusive learning
practices: A multiple case study in early childhood education. Reg –Educ Res Rev.
2023;5(3):42. doi:10.32629/rerr.v5i3.1279
9. Makoelle TM. Exploring Effective Teaching Practices for Inclusion: A Case of a
South African Secondary School. Int J Educ Sci. 2014;7(1):183–192. doi:10.1080/
09751122.2014.11890181
10. Done EJ, Andrews MJ. How inclusion became exclusion: Policy, teachers
and inclusive education. J Educ Policy. 2020;35(4):447– 464. doi: 10.1080/
02680939.2018.1552763
11. Avramidis E, Bayliss P, Burden R. Student teachers’ attitudes towards the inclu-
sion of children with special educational needs in the ordinary school. Teach Educ.
2000;16. doi: 10.1016/S0742-051X(99)00062-1
88 Implications for Education and Inclusion in the Classroom
Other quotes from the young people in this study indicate a similar pattern
of perceptions of differential treatment in terms of behaviour and in terms of
expectations for academic success. As Waitoller15 and Artiles16,17 have noted,
there remains a need to think, beyond simplistic notions of colour blindness,
more deeply about how such issues can be effectively addressed in schooling.
The parallels to some of the debates around difference as special educa-
tional needs are clear –notions of fixed ability, bias in relation to labels, the
sociological construction of deficit, ideas of normality, and so on. How the
sociological critique of classical liberal perspectives could be applied is also
quite apparent –particularly in terms of how models of knowledge and
accretions of power, which have a historical and cultural trajectory, could be
masked as asocial rationality.18 The use of intersectionality as a lens also has
the potential to further unmask such biases. Crenshaw’s19 seminal analysis of
overlaps between employment discrimination of Black women illustrated how
sometimes a focus on just individual elements can obscure the full picture.
As discussed earlier on, in terms of education and inclusion, there is evidence
about how the (low) expectations of teachers20 and the achievement of chil
dren who are both black and classified as having special educational needs is a
particular intersectional locus of concern.21,22
There is much which could be written about the above, but space is limited,
and in terms of the aims of this book to consider the implications of liberal
perspectives on education and inclusion, it will be fruitful to be more focused.
Based on my concerns about value tensions in education and inclusion,
92 Wider Aspects of Education and Inclusion
fact no evidence for this and later research,34,35 which has been critical of the
whole idea of different learning styles for different groups, tends to reinforce
this conclusion. Reich6 also similarly objects to the idea that there is a par
ticular set of knowledge, a particular curriculum, which is the property of one
group as opposed to another, and in keeping with his focus on a thin liberal
policy perspective on education suggests that the limits of multicultural educa-
tion, in such a framework, imply a common civics and a common knowledge
set across society. In proposing this, Reich does not it seems, any more than
Rawls, have a formulation for solving the issue of how, for minority groups,
a delineation in civics between public and private in education might work
in practice. Thus, it could be argued, for example, that the oppositional sub-
culture identity that some groups of young people might form in school36,37
precisely demonstrate the difficulty in proposing a public civics that is split off
in school from the private experiences that young people have of their home
culture and identity.
Critiques
Culturally responsive pedagogy, at least in its earlier iterations, has also been
criticized for having too restricted a view of cultures, seeing it as something
both too undifferentiated, and lacking a perspective on the agency of individ-
uals to use or respond to their culture in a flexible and responsive way.33,38,39
Linked to this, the focus on modifying teacher patterns of interactions, in
some way, was critiqued for ignoring wider structural perspectives, i.e. not
giving enough emphasis to culturally and historically embedded aspects of
perceived power differentials between different communities.40 Thus, cultur
ally responsive pedagogy can be seen as essentializing (and thus homogenizing)
the cultural practices of minorities. A shift to postmodernist critiques26,28,32 in
response to such concerns has, however, meant that issues of resourcing and
of what values might be at play, the potential tensions, and what this means
for teachers on the ground are, I would contend, mostly absent from the field.
Value Tensions
and teachers in particular can think and crucially talk about them, which might
then develop their professional capacity for working through these difficult
decisions that they meet every day.
full account, this is not an overtly party political, but rather more personal
position he is taking. Nevertheless, from the perspective of education and
inclusion, the segment does illuminate different value positions. Affirmative
action programmes through their aim to compensate for perceived structural
inequalities promote equality of outcome by distributing resources differen-
tially to ensure that different groups, with different resources, can achieve
more similar outcomes. They involve unequal allocation of limited resources
(in this case the limited resource of places at elite academic institutions). As
Professor Loury forcefully points out, such programmes, for particular indi-
viduals, inevitably represent losses in respect of other values. In his case, a
loss of dignity (perhaps a particular value) came about through a societal per-
ception that his abilities were or would not be recognized for what they are.
Professor Loury, in focusing on ability as an inherent quality –an intrinsic
and internal attribute of the individual –also, I think, implicitly illustrates the
point that allocating the scarce resources of elite university places based on the
social, cultural or ethnical background of individuals may mean that others
not within those groups, who do have innate exceptional academic ability
(and/or extraordinary effort), will lose out on access to that scarce resource.
Thus, from the perspective of justice as desert and liberty (i.e. the freedom of
people to make free use of their abilities and their effort), some people will
lose out. What then is an inclusive position in relation to affirmative action
programmes? I chose this example because when watching Professor Loury
speak about his experiences and the force and passion with which he speaks,
there is a real sense of something being lost for him. Yes, we can strive for
criteria with which to judge between these competing values, and perhaps as
Olssen45 suggests democratic debate, deliberative or otherwise, is an effective
way of making such judgements. However, to propose that there are some
overarching “inclusive values” that can be applied to this scenario is I believe
false. There are rather competing incommensurable values that are in tension,
and there is a dilemma about their resolution and the inescapable fact that any
resolution involves an absolute loss on one side or the other.
Although I am arguing that the possibility of full resolution of value
tensions in relation to education and inclusion may, as per Berlin, be unreach-
able, that does not mean that the overall aims (the common human horizon)
of the good life in relation to difference in the classroom are not amenable
to critical analysis or frameworks that may serve to promote, particularly for
teachers, ways of at least promoting more effective professional reflection on,
and thus resolution of, the issues they need to deal with. We have in the litera-
ture a rich development of tools, interventions and pedagogies –such as for
example the considerable evidence base about how carefully considered school
programmes based on culturally responsive pedagogy as a framework have
been successful in promoting the success of children from minority groups.26
Rather, what I am arguing is that we need frameworks for helping teachers
consider the value frameworks and tensions that lie at the heart of decision
making when working with difference in the classroom. I propose that such
Wider Aspects of Education and Inclusion 97
Funds of Knowledge
Funds of Knowledge sits within a set of attempts in the 1980s and 1990s to use
anthropological approaches to consider how to link home and school cultures.46
However, it has undoubtedly been the most successful and influential of these
over time.47 Moll and González’s48 initial work on US-Mexican households,
drawing on Wolf’s49 research into household economies, focused on using
anthropological approaches to allow schools and teachers to better understand
the individual lives, culture and knowledge of the children in their classes,
particularly through the use of a type of ethnographic home visit. Home visits
were, in the fully developed model, followed up with new classroom practices
developed by teachers based on the visits and reflective teacher study group
meetings. González et al.50(p.133) define funds of knowledge (FoK) as “histor
ically accumulated and culturally developed bodies of knowledge and skills
essential for household or individual functioning and well-being”, related to
“social, economic, and productive activities of people”50(p.139) in local commu-
nities, including “social history of households, their origins and development
… the labour history of families”, and “ ‘how families develop social networks…
including knowledge skills and labour, that enhance the households’ ability to
survive and thrive”.50(p.133) The implications of this knowledge for schools is a
key outcome of their analysis, and González et al.50 themselves consider the
FoK approach as one way of conceiving of a culturally responsive pedagogy.
González et al.50 present their notion of FoK from a (sociologically) crit
ical pedagogy perspective, although the specific type of critical stance they
take is not always fully clear, and their roots in anthropological methods open
up, I would argue, at least the possibility of considering the FoK approach as
having elements of compatibility with more realist perspectives on knowledge.
Thus, it does not seem necessarily the case within the approach to adopt a
deconstruction of the knowing subject, and the FoK approach could equally
be considered as a way of presenting children and families as knowing subjects
drawing on and interacting with cultural knowledge. I contend that this gives
the potential to open up dialogue between teacher, school, child and parents
that allows for a growing shared understanding of knowledge and what this
might mean for pedagogy. In particular, I think this can be considered from
the perspectives of a social realist division between external bias and internal
knowledge in relation to epistemology, pedagogy and curriculum in the
classroom. In particular, the FoK approach eschews a biased deficit view of
marginalized communities, or just communities that are different from the
98 Wider Aspects of Education and Inclusion
Since the original work on FoK in the 1980s and 1990s, it has been applied
in a range of contexts, across an increasing range of curriculum subject areas.
There has also been some limited application to approaches to disability in
schools (see for example Stone-MacDonald47). There has also been a move
away from the emphasis in the earlier applications on parental knowledge
towards greater recognition of children’s own knowledge, as well as commu-
nity situated contexts for knowledge such as churches.52 Theoretically, there
has been a developing focus on co-construction with children, as well as links
to social capital models, particularly of note being Yosso’s53 critical theory-
based “Community Cultural Wealth” model which focuses on illuminating the
cultural capital held by minority and marginalized children.52 Finally, there has
also been developing interest in the idea of difficult knowledge,54 accounting
for traumatic aspects of culture such as migration experiences.52
Wider Aspects of Education and Inclusion 99
An Example
In the case presented, set in the 1990s, Hortencia and Tomas are in their fifties
and have four children, three of whom are married and live by with their chil-
dren. Hortencia’s parents live very close by. She has worked as a bank teller
for many decades. As with Hortencia, Tomas’s family had migrated to Mexico
within the last generation, but Tomas, born in Phoenix, was “repatriated ” to
Mexico with his parents. After his father’s death in 1945, Tomas migrated to
Tucson by himself at ten years old. He was placed in foster care and at 18, with
the equivalent of a seventh-grade education, joined the army and was trained
as a maintenance mechanic. Tomas now works (at the time of writing of the
case study) in a maintenance role for the Arizona national guard.
The idea of passing on of parental technical and economic skills is also
an important element in the reported case50 –Hortencia spent much time
and effort teaching her children and now grandchildren maths computational
skills, which she was expert in due to her many years as a bank teller. Tomas
also exposed his children and grandchildren to his own skills, engaging them
in woodwork and getting them to assist him in making and repairing house-
hold items, and learning from the process. The case, as mentioned, also gives
an account of the importance of the Catholic faith for both parents, ritual
activities with the children in the household and wider engagement with the
Church and Church social and other activities.
Structural aspects are also presented as part of the case as sadly Tomas
developed a debilitating long-term reaction to the toxic chemicals that he was
exposed to spraying industrial cleaning solvents, without any personal pro-
tective equipment over many years. When asked by the researchers why he did
not ask for gloves and a mask, he said that wearing them slowed him down and
he did not want to be seen as a “lazy Mexican”.50(p.57)
It is a compelling case and I think a fine piece of ethnography that illustrates
both how the FoK approach can uncover, for the outsider, something of what
community and identity means for a family, with a particular focus on the
interplays between “economic” knowledge embedded within kin networks.
It does, though, I think, also illustrate some value tensions, which I think are
not clearly articulated in González et al.’s account, but could be considered
if an openness to a range of perspectives, including liberal and neoconserva-
tive ones, as held by the actors in the field, were allowed. In this specific case,
although it inescapably includes the emphasis on faith within the family, as
noted, there is something of an almost dismissive way in which this is handled,
which does not fully reflect an openness to differing value systems.
For example:50(p.59)
Well, on one level this may well be true, but it also illustrates a perspective on
faith as something which is largely instrumental. It ignores, or more than that
denies, as Mclaughlin60 puts it when discussing Phillip’s61(p.186) view of religion
and faith, that “believing in G-d…equates…with participating in the religious
attitude, the eternal, and living according to it”. Although space precludes
getting into the full complexity of these arguments, the point is that, as argued
by Scheffler,62,63 faith has a meaning on the inside, which cannot be adduced
from external critical analysis of it. There is a similarity here to Ramaekers and
Suissa’s argument about the unique intimacy of the family and parent-child
relationships.64 They are uniquely and mutually constitutive on the inside, and
they go “all the way down”64(p.ix) –i.e. that one element such as holding a
lavish event cannot stand in isolation from the faith context in which it takes
place. Hortencia and Tomas place a value, a conservative traditional value,
on tradition and family which is entwined with and inseparable from belief.
Their identity is not just as a family, nor just as an extended kin network, but
as a part of a wider faith community which is an important part of their iden-
tity as Mexicans. This aspect of tradition (perhaps tradition in its conservative
sense) is, clearly, for the researchers, somewhat in tension with the sociologic-
ally critical lens that they wish to bring on the case. Such tensions are of course
much more widespread than just this case –see for example Lewis and Lall’s65
account of the subversion (in their view) of postcolonial theory in tradition-
alist /authoritarian regimes.
The case as presented thus may well be in conflict with the values weighting
of educators aligned with Marxist or postmodern perspectives, and indeed
it is possible that some of the views within the faith tradition might be in
conflict more widely with liberal or communitarian theorists (and indeed the
state) adopting a thick perspective on civics, such as in relation to the rela-
tive emphasis placed on values of experiment and debate. However, it is still
the case that the FoK approach serves to bring these different value systems,
at least to some extent, out into the open. I am drawn to the FoK approach
in respect of inclusion and education in terms of the capacity it offers to,
in a sense, stake the ground for the values and perspectives of children and
families from minorities, and open up the possibility for debate by schools
and teachers. Thus, the anthropological basis of FoK inescapably positions
the different localized political value systems of the actors in the social field as
matters for consideration.
102 Wider Aspects of Education and Inclusion
The unit of work went on to cover aspects of maths, science, health, adver-
tising, food production and the children also generated their own questions
such as “What is candy like in Africa?” and “What candy do they eat in China?”.
It is interesting how in this case there is not a clear break between natural
versus scientific knowledge,66 but also that there is at the same time quite
a realist view of knowledge. In the case description, we learn that Carlos’
parents, as was likely with many other parents in the class, put a high value on
education, as well as on good behaviour, respect for teachers and hard work.
There was not a sense in the case of there being, for example, either on the
part of the parents, or the children, for some radically different curriculum,
or in Young’s terms, a more voice-based discourse on knowledge. It was not
that particular forms of knowledge seemed to be valued because of who held
them or where they came from, but more of a recognition that the children’s
home lives and cultures were also sources of knowledge, and that their home
lives involved sophisticated application of such knowledge. It could be argued
that the case study did, for the teacher, help to reduce, in Durkheimian social
Wider Aspects of Education and Inclusion 103
realist terms, external cognitive biases about the children and their lives, or
alternatively opened up horizons for responding in pedagogically valid terms
to the culture(s) of her students. There was also a sense, in this case, and others
presented by González et al.50 and later González and Moll67 of a process
of negotiation, whereby the teacher, the class and more widely the parents
reflected on what might be taught, why it would be taught, and what would
be achieved. Such a process of negotiation did not necessarily negate or gloss
over differences and value tensions, but at the same time a space was created
for them to be considered, particularly by the teachers and the schools. In the
accounts of González et al.50 and González and Moll,67 this is not always fully
worked through, although there is some limited attention in later studies with
the FoK approach68,69 of how to take into account differences in political value
perspectives within the context of classroom teaching. So, for example, there
may well be considerable tensions, in many classrooms and schools, in going
off topic to focus on a particular area of interest to one particular child, given
the need quite often to follow a prescribed scheme of work and curriculum.
As well, as noted, in approaching other areas such as faith traditions in their
wider sense, there may well be value tensions, in varying ways, between the
perspectives of the teacher, the school, the state and those of the child and the
family.
Towards Negotiation
Different positions on the public role of the state in promoting civics also raise
some potential tensions with FoK as an approach. Still, what is striking about it
is, perhaps because of its diverse roots in critical perspectives and anthropology,
is the space that FoK opens up for bringing out the different perspectives
between school and home for discussion, and from that the potential for dis-
cussion of those different perspectives. I would take this further, and argue
that both from the perspective of a culturally responsive pedagogy and more
broadly for education and inclusion, this idea of discussion or better negoti-
ation is what is needed. Inclusion as an idealist position is a limited concept.
There are no simplistic rules for teacher decision making in respect of working
with difference in the classroom, just problems that involve trade-offs. For me,
what the FoK approach highlights with its emphasis on uncovering different
perspectives and its respect of local cultural contexts and knowledge is that we
need to think of inclusion not as an ideal, not even as one specific question
to be answered, but a whole series of interlinked questions that require nego-
tiation. A “realist” negotiation centred on culturally responsive pedagogy,
then, would be one that recognizes that (a) biases exist and need to be and
can be countered, and (b) that there are different perspectives and values
across home and school which can be in tension in multiple ways, and that by
bringing these out into the open, this can lead to negotiation, and ultimately
to decisions. This is somewhat different both to critical perspectives on FoK
and specifically the idea of co-production, a term associated and aligned with
104 Wider Aspects of Education and Inclusion
both later FoK trajectories and more broadly voice discourses across educa-
tion.70 Co-production implies that knowledge subsists in the process of inter
action, and implies a deconstruction of the knowing subject, as well as a range
of assumptions about power being at the root of such knowledge creation. As
a concept, it assumes too much. Negotiation is a much more open and flex-
ible concept that accepts, from liberalism, that positions and values, including
about epistemology itself, are multiple and in conflict. It recognizes that chil-
dren and adults are inherently in different positions, that families and schools
may have much to disagree about, that families and children may have much
as well to disagree about, but that crucially through dialogue we can come to
understand what we agree on, what we don’t agree on, what we know from
multiple sources, what we don’t know and what we might want to know and
why. Inclusion as negotiation then becomes a series of questions to be posed,
and answered, as best we can.
However, the questions that are posed, and the answers that can be
considered, are not without limits. The question of limits is complex. In com-
pulsory phase education, there is, though, wider acceptance that there are
limits to both questions and answers. A concern with values of protection
and the development of autonomy and agency, and freedom from oppression,
converge at least to some extent across liberal, communitarian and post-
modern /postcolonial modes of thinking, in terms of some of the things we
should teach children in schools. The rules of the playground in early years
and elementary schools have a sort of universal acceptance. There are few
teachers who think that keeping your hands and feet to yourself, learning
to share your toys, not stealing your friend’s pencil or snack, or even not
leaving people out of your games so that they feel sad are areas of disagree-
ment. Berlin’s common human horizon71 seems, at least within limits, to be
somewhat simpler in compulsory teaching phases. However, when we start
to think about education and adults, and post-compulsory education, things
are not so simple.
Note
1 The role of the state and common schools in promoting a thick or thin public
common set of values, or common culture, and how this relates to the rights of
minority communities, are, as discussed, one of the key issues considered within lib-
eral perspectives on education.
References
1. Hick P, Matziari A, Mintz J, et al. Initial Teacher Education for Inclusion: Final
Report to the National Council for Special Education. National Council for Special
Education; 2019:1– 220. Accessed March 5, 2024. https://ncse.ie/research-
repor ts
2. Mintz J, Hick P, Solomon Y, et al. The reality of reality shock for inclusion: How
does teacher attitude, perceived knowledge and self-efficacy in relation to effective
Wider Aspects of Education and Inclusion 105
inclusion in the classroom change from the pre-service to novice teacher year?
Teach Teach Educ. 2020;91:103042. doi: 10.1016/j.tate.2020.103042
3. Cruz RA, Firestone AR, Love M. Beyond a seat at the table: Imagining educational
equity through critical inclusion. Educ Rev. 2024;76(1):69–95. doi:10.1080/
00131911.2023.2173726
4. Furedi F. Reflections on the medicalisation of social experience. Br J Guid Couns.
2004;32:413–415. doi:10.1080/03069880410001723611
5. Rata E. Knowledge-rich teaching: A model of curriculum design coherence. Br
Educ Res J. 2019;45(4):681–697. doi:10.1002/berj.3520
6. Reich R. Bridging Liberalism and Multiculturalism in American Education.
University of Chicago Press; 2002.
7. Reich R. How and Why to Support Common Schooling and Educational
Choice at the Same Time. J Philos Educ. 2007;41(4):709–725. doi:10.1111/
j.1467-9752.2007.00578.x
8. McLaughlin TH. National Identity and the Aims of Education. In: Carr D,
Halstead M, Pring R, eds. Liberalism Education and Schooling: Essays by T.H.
Mclaughlin. Imprint Academic; 2008:79–93.
9. Kymlicka W. Education for Citizenship. In: Halstead M, McLaughlin TH, eds.
Education in Morality. Routledge; 1999:79–102.
10. Kymlicka W. Deschooling multiculturalism. Ethnicities. 2019;19(6):971–982.
doi:10.1177/1468796819840722
11. Clotfelter CT, Ladd HF, Vigdor JL. Public Universities, Equal Opportunity,
and the Legacy of Jim Crow: Evidence from North Carolina. National Bureau of
Economic Research; 2015.
12. Marrus E. Education in black America: Is it the new Jim Crow. Ark Rev.
2015;68:27.
13. White AO. The Black Movement against Jim Crow Education in Buffalo,
New York, 1800–1900. Phylon (1960-). 1969;30(4):375–393.
14. Hope EC, Skoog AB, Jagers RJ. “It’ll Never Be the White Kids, It’ll Always
Be Us”: Black High School Students’ Evolving Critical Analysis of Racial
Discrimination and Inequity in Schools. J Adolesc Res. 2015;30(1):83–112.
doi:10.1177/0743558414550688
15. Waitoller FR. Dismantling the “Hobson Choice” Conundrum: Leveraging UDL
for Educational Equity and Justice. Mult Voices Disabil Race Lang Intersect Spec
Educ. 2023;23(2):52–60. doi:10.56829/2158-396X-23.2.52
16. Artiles A. Interdisciplinary Notes for Research on Teacher Learning for Inclusion.
Presented at: Teacher Education for Inclusion: International Perspectives and
Possibilities; 2023; Seminar at Faculty of Education and Society (IOE), University
College London. Accessed October 15, 2023. www.eventbrite.co.uk/e/teac
her-education-for-inclusion-international-perspectives-possibilities-tickets-67362
7165987
17. Artiles AJ. Toward an interdisciplinary understanding of educational equity and
difference: The case of the racialization of ability. Educ Res. 2011;40(9):431–445.
doi:10.3102/0013189X114293
18. Slee R, Tait G. Ethics and Inclusive Education: Disability, Schooling and Justice.
Springer; 2022.
19. Crenshaw K. Demarginalizing the Intersection of Race and Sex: A Black Feminist
Critique of Antidiscrimination Doctrine, Feminist Theory and Antiracist Politics.
Univ Chic Leg Forum. 1989;140:139–167.
106 Wider Aspects of Education and Inclusion
20. Pit-ten Cate IM, Glock S. Teacher expectations concerning students with immi-
grant backgrounds or special educational needs. Educ Res Eval. 2018;24(3–
5):277–294. doi:10.1080/13803611.2018.1550839
21. Department for Education. 2020 Individuals with Disabilities Education Act
Annual Report to Congress.; 2020. Accessed February 21, 2024. https://sites.
ed.gov/idea/2020-annual-report-congress-idea/
22. Wallace D, Joseph-Salisbury R. How, still, is the Black Caribbean child made
educationally subnormal in the English school system? Ethn Racial Stud.
2022;45(8):1426–1452. doi:10.1080/01419870.2021.1981969
23. Waitoller FR, Thorius KK. Sustaining Disabled Youth: Centering Disability in
Asset Pedagogies. Teachers College Press; 2022.
24. Waitoller FR. An Intersectional Framework for Teacher Education for Inclusion.
Presented at: Teacher Education for Inclusion: International Perspectives and
Possibilities; 2023; Seminar at Faculty of Education and Society (IOE), University
College London. Accessed October 15, 2023. www.eventbrite.co.uk/e/teacher-
education-for-inclusion-international-perspectives-possibilities-tickets-673627165987
25. Gay G. Culturally Responsive Teaching: Theory, Research, and Practice. 1st Edition.
Teachers College Press; 2000.
26. Ladson-Billings G. Three Decades of Culturally Relevant, Responsive, & Sustaining
Pedagogy: What Lies Ahead? Educ Forum. 2021;85(4):351–354. doi:10.1080/
00131725.2021.1957632
27. Klingner J, Artiles AJ, Kozleski E, et al. Educ Policy Anal Arch Analíticos Políticas
Educ. 2005;13:1–40. doi:10.14507/epaa.v13n38.2005
28. Ko D, Bal A, Artiles AJ. Racial equity by design: Forming transformative agency to
address the racialization of school discipline. Urban Educ. 2024;59(3):660–693.
doi:10.1177/00420859221081774
29. Kozleski EB, González T, Atkinson L, Mruczek C, Lacy L. Teacher education in
practice: Reconciling practices and theories in the United States context. Eur J
Spec Needs Educ. 2013;28(2):156–172. doi:10.1080/08856257.2013.778114
30. Bernstein B. Class and pedagogies: Visible and invisible. Educ Stud.
1975;1(1):23–41.
31. Young M. Bringing Knowledge Back In: From Social Constructivism to Social
Realism in the Sociology of Education. Routledge; 2008.
32. Paris D, Alim HS. Culturally Sustaining Pedagogies: Teaching and Learning for
Justice in a Changing World. Teachers College Press; 2017.
33. Banks JA. Educating Citizens in a Multicultural Society. Teachers College
Press; 1997.
34. Newton PM, Salvi A. How common is belief in the learning styles neuromyth, and
does it matter? A pragmatic systematic review. Front Educ. 2020;5. doi:10.3389/
feduc.2020.602451
35. Papadatou-Pastou M, Touloumakos AK, Koutouveli C, Barrable A. The learning
styles neuromyth: When the same term means different things to different teachers.
Eur J Psychol Educ. 2021;36:511–531. doi:10.1007/s10212-020-00485-2
36. Smith LV, Wang MT, Hill DJ. Black Youths’ perceptions of school cultural
pluralism, school climate and the mediating role of racial identity. J Sch Psychol.
2020;83:50–65. doi:10.1016/j.jsp.2020.09.002
37. Tyson K, Lewis AE. The “burden” of oppositional culture among Black
youth in America. Annu Rev Sociol. 2021;47:459– 477. doi:10.1146/
annurev-soc-090420-092123
Wider Aspects of Education and Inclusion 107
38. Heath SB. Oral and literate traditions among Black Americans living in poverty.
Am Psychol. 1989;44(2):367–373. doi:10.1037/0003-066X.44.2.367
39. Phillippo K. “You’re Trying to Know Me”: Students from Nondominant Groups
Respond to Teacher Personalism. Urban Rev. 2012;44(4):441–467. doi:10.1007/
s11256-011-0195-9
40. Banks JA. Failed Citizenship and Transformative Civic Education. Educ Res.
2017;46(7):366–377. doi:10.3102/0013189X17726741
41. Loury GC. The Anatomy of Racial Inequality: With a New Preface. Harvard
University Press; 2021.
42. Loury GC. The Double Life. Glenn Loury Substack. Published 2021. Accessed
February 15, 2024. https://glennloury.substack.com/p/the-double-life
43. US Constitution Amendment XIV.; 1868. Accessed March 3, 2024. www.govinfo.
gov/content/pkg/GPO-CONAN-2002/pdf/GPO-CONAN-2002-9-15.pdf
44. Loury GC. Get your hands off my dignity. Glenn Loury Substack. Published
2024. Accessed March 3, 2024. https://twitter.com/GlennLoury/status/1752
790419262312628
45. Olssen M. Liberalism, Neoliberalism, Social Democracy: Thin Communitarian
Perspectives on Political Philosophy and Education. Routledge; 2010.
46. Ladson-Billings Guest Editor G. This Issue: Culturally relevant teaching. Theory
Pract. 1995;34(3):150–151. doi:10.1080/00405849509543673
47. Stone-MacDonald A. Learning daily life and vocational skills in natural settings: A
Tanzanian model. J Int Assoc Spec Educ. 2012;13(1):28–40.
48. Moll L, Amanti C, Neff D, González N. Funds of Knowledge for Teaching: Using a
Qualitative Approach to Connect Homes and Classrooms. Theory Pract. 1992;31(2).
49. Wolf ER. Peasants. Prentice Hall; 1966.
50. González N, Moll LC, Amanti C. Funds of Knowledge: Theorizing Practices in
Households, Communities, and Classrooms. Routledge; 2006.
51. Zipin L, Fataar A, Brennan M. Can social realism do social justice? Debating the
warrants for curriculum knowledge selection. Educ Change. 2015;19(2):9–36.
doi:10.1080/16823206.2015.1085610
52. Llopart M, Esteban- Guitart M. Funds of knowledge in 21st century soci-
eties: Inclusive educational practices for under- represented students.
A literature review. J Curric Stud. 2018;50(2):145– 161. doi:10.1080/
00220272.2016.1247913
53. Yosso TJ. Whose culture has capital? A critical race theory discussion of com-
munity cultural wealth. Race Ethn Educ. 2005;8(1):69– 91. doi:10.1080/
1361332052000341006
54. Britzman DP. If the story cannot end: Deferred action, ambivalence, and diffi-
cult knowledge. In: Simon RI, Rosenberg S, Eppert C, eds. Between Hope and
Despair: Pedagogy and the Remembrance of Historical Trauma. Rowman &
Littlefield; 2000:27–57.
55. Burns KE. Marginalization of local varieties in the L2 classroom: The case of US
Spanish. L2 J. 2018;10(1). doi:10.5070/L210135863
56. Leeman J. Engaging critical pedagogy: Spanish for native speakers. Foreign Lang
Ann. 2005;38(1):35–45. doi:10.1111/j.1944-9720.2005.tb02451.x
57. Chang H. Stress and Burnout in EFL Teachers: The Mediator Role of Self-Efficacy.
Front Psychol. 2022;13:880281. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2022.880281
58. Cummins J. Rethinking the Education of Multilingual Learners: A Critical
Analysis of Theoretical Concepts. Multilingual Matters; 2021.
108 Wider Aspects of Education and Inclusion
In higher education, it is of course the case that the issues I have highlighted
about education and inclusion both in terms of a narrow view of inclusion
focused on special educational needs and a broader view focused on aspects of
difference, such as culture, class, language, sexuality etc., are present in many
forms. For example, issues of equality of outcome versus equality of oppor-
tunity in terms of the effective inclusion of autistic students in universities are
also sites of significant tension and debate. There is also a recognition in the
literature and in practice that particularly in relation to special educational
needs, there has been much less attention paid to post-18 settings, although it
has been an area of increasing attention in the last ten years.1,2
In terms of the theoretical considerations about values and value tensions,
the questions posed in higher education are also often similar to those in
schools. A key difference is, however, that particular contextual elements
present in compulsory phase education are not present in the university.
Protection as an imperative (or a value) is not present in the same way within
universities and, crucially as adults, issues of autonomy and agency and how
if at all these are aspects for development rather than exercise are much less
clear. To illuminate the specificity of issues related to education and inclusion
in higher education, I will focus on decolonization as a movement3 and the
wider implications of this for value tensions both within the university and
more widely. In doing so, I will attempt to set education and inclusion within
the context of the rationale and aims of the modern university, both in terms
of what universities themselves (their leaders, their faculty) and society (for
example taxpayers) more widely might consider those aims to be. As I noted
in the introduction, my thinking on this has been significantly influenced by
the rise of antisemitism on campus in the wake of the October 7th atroci-
ties. This rise in antisemitism has clear points of articulation to the imple-
mentation of decolonization and Diversity Equity and Inclusion (DEI) on
campus, and I contend for the broader programme for education and inclu-
sion. Later in the chapter, I reflect on what the implications of this discussion
on higher education have for how we conceive of education and inclusion
DOI: 10.4324/9781003294894-7
110 Inclusion and Higher Education
across the educational phases including schools, also linking this back to the
prior discussions on value tensions.
point rather towards a dialogue with the liberal canon, not its relativization,
a point which seems often absent in day-to-day discussions of decolonization
on campus.
Postcolonial Theory
Postcolonial theory has its roots in literary and cultural studies and focuses on
the legacy of colonialism and imperialism and their influence on society in the
past and today. Perhaps its most seminal writer was Frantz Fanon. Fanon was
born in 1925 in Martinique and experienced the discrimination and racism of
colonial society.15 He joined the Free French forces during the Second World
War and then trained as a psychiatrist and worked in Algeria, also playing a
key role as a spokesman for the National Liberation Front –Algeria’s inde-
pendence movement. He died from leukaemia in 1961, but before that sad
untimely death wrote a number of influential texts, most particularly The
Wretched of the Earth.16 It is true that much of Fanon’s writing dazzles par
ticularly for its brilliant rhetoric and for the visceral sense of the experience of
oppression that it conveys.17 In one sense, the argument of postcolonial theory
as put forward by Fanon is straightforward –certain societies have colonized
others and used their power of arms to subdue those colonized societies for
their own economic gain. In doing so, they have misused liberalism’s supposed
commitment to individual rights and pluralism by positing either deliberately
or unconsciously that some societies are better than others, thus giving them
rights both of exploitation and of rectification. This produces a skewed lens
through which non-Western cultures are viewed, and even with the fall of
actual colonial rule, this lens continues to influence how non-Western cultures
are considered in the West and within the societies subject to colonialism
themselves.
There is and always has been interest in the role of violence in postcolonial
theory and in the writings of Fanon in particular. Fanon was clearly, at the very
least in the Algerian context, a supporter of armed struggle against colonial
powers.18 There is disparity in the field on his views on violence, and some19
have interpreted his writing to suggest that he was a strong advocate of vio-
lence. Others such as Shatz17 argue that his views on violence are nuanced.
Certainly, as a psychiatrist he recognized the corrosive impact of violence,
when undertaken, on the perpetrator. He also viewed violence as having both
redemptive and undermining consequences, in a cycle within the oppressor/
oppressed dynamic –the colonized man he wrote16(p.16) was “the persecuted
man who constantly dreams of being the persecutor”. This ambivalence,
argues Shultz,17 also transcends simplistic binaries, arguing that these were
the narrative of the colonizer and that only a more nuanced understanding of
identity would allow for peace both for those who had colonized and for those
112 Inclusion and Higher Education
who had been colonized. Shulz argues that Fanon felt, somewhat in parallel
to what Arendt20 called natality, i.e. the inherent innovation and creativity
inherent in us all (as “natal” new beginnings), that only through such new
beginnings can we overcome the accretions of history. Thus, Shultz17 positions
Fanon’s revolutionary thinking as both dialectical and redemptive, illustrating
postcolonial theory’s Marxist underpinnings. As Robert Young18 notes in his
overview of postcolonialism, postcolonial thought has been fundamentally
based on the idea of economic oppression of “North” over “South” and the
historical processes of reclamation of the economic power writ large. However,
postcolonial thinking transcends just economic considerations and recasts the
basis for how that process may occur in terms of its subjective affects, i.e. its
particular cultural expression, in what Abdel-Malek21 called the tricontinental
context of Africa, Asia and Latin America. It is perhaps in the emphasis on
this localized cultural expression, such as local knowledge and practices of
indigenous people, which both Fanon16 and the other foundational and sem
inal writer on postcolonialism, Edward Said,22 illustrate in their writings, that
postcolonialism can be distinguished from both “Western” Marxism and crit-
ical theory. Thus, in a sense, postcolonialism notes that Marxism’s strength
as a universalist (indeed fundamentally idealist) framework has a tendency to
underplay local culture, and postcolonialism, whilst accepting Marxism’s fun-
damental tenet about economic power and historical processes, and indeed
international struggle, aims to reintroduce the “local”, as it is the loss of the
local, in terms of identity, that lies at the heart of revolution, albeit dialectic-
ally, against colonial oppression.
Young18 proposes that postcolonialism is thus inherently a form of activism,
whose focus on the local means that different political foci (gender, race,
for example as well as class) can come within its orbit. Postcolonial theory
contends18 that the imperialist project of the West, post 1492, was in form
qualitatively different from prior imperial projects, due to its size, and the
extent of its dominance, partly facilitated by its technological superiority, such
as in terms of sailing ships that could extend geographical reach far beyond
that of the empires of the ancient world. The imposition of the colonial (by
implication liberal) lens on subjected peoples and their cultures, whether in a
homogenous fashion as under the French empire or a looser form as under
the British created, for both the colonized and the colonized, in postcolonial
theory, a false account. Edward Said’s important contribution was to provide,
in a similar way to some postmodern accounts, a framework for conceptually
and discursively analysing that false account, and thus uncovering other ways
of conceiving of local culture and society, which similarly allowed them to
be freed from colonial oppression. Thus, Said posited colonialism not just as
acts of conquest but, in his seminal text Orientalism,22 as a discourse of forms
of domination. This focused particularly on a linguistic deconstruction of
concepts used to describe the East by its conquerors from the West, although,
as Young18 notes, significantly, the connections to postmodern forms of
deconstruction and specifically Foucault’s analysis were not at all fully worked
Inclusion and Higher Education 113
after the years of implementation of equal rights legislation such as Title VII
in the US and the Equality Act38 in the UK, and the significant growth in
DEI programmes after the rise of Black Lives Matter in 2020,9,39 and the
added impetus this gave to decolonization, interpenetrated as it is at with
DEI, within the academy.6 This question is, I believe, important, not only in
its local sense (i.e. how can we address and counter campus antisemitism),
but also, crucially, because it illuminates wider concerns about education and
inclusion, which are relevant not just in higher education. I will consider the
links between inclusion and the Jews, its intercalation with value tensions in
public policy and education, and what this tells us about the models we cur-
rently have for education and inclusion more widely, particularly in terms of
postcolonial theory.
British writer David Baddiel has noted, with respect to the positioning
of Jews in relation to notions of equal treatment in society, that Jews Don’t
Count.40 By this, Baddiel means that as a minority, the cultural modes of
respect and consideration, which seem to apply to other minority groups, do
not apply to Jews, which he traces to the embedded nature of antisemitism in
society. There is a (albeit not overly extensive) contemporary body of scholars
worldwide interested in antisemitism, who write about how to account specif-
ically for modern forms of antisemitism.41,42 These have partly focused on what
has been termed the new left antisemitism,43 and the points of connection
between antizionism and antisemitism. Broadly theorists advocating this per-
spective note several points:
For some time there has been concern about how, if at all, DEI programmes
and the DEI culture within universities can account for the new left anti-
semitism, most notably because either the antizionist /antisemitic conspiracy
theories underpinning them have come from, and are often promoted, by fac-
ulty directly or indirectly involved in DEI programmes, and/or because they
Inclusion and Higher Education 115
It is in the very way in which new nations were born that differences became
clear…It is in the way that Tunisia became a nation like other nations that we
[Jews] became, as we were everywhere else, a civic and national negativity.
Value Tensions
This is a question of values. Although postcolonial theorists who have been crit-
ical of the tensions inherent in postcolonial theory, such as Dirlik and Memmi,
might not wish to admit it, but the logic of their critique, and the way these
tensions can be resolved, is by recognizing that as well as the sociological cri-
tique, other value systems including liberalism and conservatism have a point
to make here and that value tensions need to be recognized and explored.
Thus, Memmi61 and many others including Fanon argue for postcolonial soci
eties that value individual liberty and democracy –that follow the intentions
of the classical liberal thinkers and the Enlightenment, and to varying extent
ideas of strict justice, including those of private property, and the associated
respect for the rule of law that a notion of such justice requires. They also
thus inescapably have to recognize that these values came from the West and
from the Enlightenment, and that a Manichean binary between North and
South or between Orient and Occident, or between oppressor and oppressed,
is not, particularly as Dirlik24 notes, in the context of globalization, either pos
sible or meaningful. I also contend that these perspectives need to give much
more value to a political settlement that balances liberal and communitarian
perspectives on minority and majority, whilst fundamentally recognizing that
the limits of such a settlement are set by the bounds of liberal democratic
principles which grant minorities the negative liberty to maintain their local
culture, their faith and their languages, at the same time as trying to solve the
conflicts of the nation state inherent in colonialism’s complex legacy. As Berlin
has noted, there are no idealist solutions to such conflicts and tensions that
will not involve greater oppression than that which they supposedly seek to
solve. I would contend that DEI and inclusion in education on campus have
been examples of just such an attempted idealist solution. What history has
shown us is that it is the Jews who most often tend to end up as the targets of
that oppression, particularly when such idealist solutions try to paper over the
conflicts inherent in human activity. It is not by accident that the idealism of
Marx, when put into practice, led to the persecution of the Jews, and then led
the crusade to extend that persecution to the nation state of the Jews. None
of this is to say that postcolonial theory does not have anything to teach us in
terms of education and inclusion. However, if it is to avoid these dangers, as
before, it may be necessary to distinguish, as per a Durkheimian social realist
position, between internal and external aspects.68
and Ahluwalia,69 in their analysis of Said’s thought, argue that Said was nego
tiating between a classical realist view that sees the text as simply representing
the outside world and a structuralist position in which language mediates both
what is said and the way it is talked about. Said adopts an intermediate pos-
ition, rejecting the endless of the chains of signification of Derrida, and rather
positing that the text simultaneously reflects the world of which it speaks at
the same time as being inextricably influenced by the contingencies of the
world in its formation.69(p.22) Dirlik goes further and proposes that we can look
at colonialism as a whole as a distorted representation, which has accretions
of bias, and that there is scope in postcolonialism for these can be illuminated
and corrected through critique, thus adding to the accuracy and the quality
of the “hybrid”24 engagement between cultures. Such a stance implies
at least to some extent a realist position on the knowledge, and associated
values, of the West, deriving from both rational and empirical enquiry. At
the same time, there is a recognition that knowledge can come from mul-
tiple sources, not just from the Western cannon, and that there can be bias
about the relative positioning of sources of knowledge as well, which also
needs to be recognized. When associated with the idea of negotiation –i.e.
an understanding that there are multiple perspectives and multiple values and
value conflicts between perspectives, and between nations and faiths, and that
talking about and understanding these conflicts is necessary for us to under-
stand them–it can lead us to a space that avoids the binary thinking into which
postcolonial thinking has fallen. Such a space also recognizes, through nego-
tiation, that value pluralism still places boundaries and recognizes a common
human horizon. It also recognizes the limitations and dangers of oppositional
binaries, and their particular risks for how Jews might be conceived of in such
contexts.
Note
1 For a more detailed account of (2) and (3) see Hirsh.43
References
1. Davis MT, Watts GW, López EJ. A systematic review of firsthand experiences
and supports for students with autism spectrum disorder in higher education. Res
Autism Spectr Disord. 2021;84:101769. doi:10.1016/j.rasd.2021.101769
2. Sarrett JC. Autism and accommodations in higher education: Insights from
the autism community. J Autism Dev Disord. 2018;48:679–693. doi:10.1007/
s10803-017-3353-4
3. Tight M. Decolonization and Higher Education: A Critical Review of a
Contemporary Concern, Policy and Theory. High Educ Policy. 2024;37(1):59–
72. doi:10.1057/s41307-022-00296-8
4. Day A, Lee L, Thomas DSP, Spickard J. Diversity, Inclusion, and
Decolonization: Practical Tools for Improving Teaching, Research, and Scholarship.
Policy Press; 2022.
5. Shahjahan RA, Estera AL, Surla KL, Edwards KT. “Decolonizing” curriculum and
pedagogy: A comparative review across disciplines and global higher education
contexts. Rev Educ Res. 2022;92(1):73–113. doi:10.3102/003465432110424
6. Eaton SE. New priorities for academic integrity: equity, diversity, inclusion, decol-
onization and Indigenization. Int J Educ Integr. 2022;18(1):22. doi:10.1007/
s40979-022-00105-0
7. Gopal P. On Decolonisation and the University. Textual Pract. 2021;35(6):873–
899. doi:10.1080/0950236X.2021.1929561
8. Tuck E, Yang KW. Decolonization is not a metaphor. Decolonization Indig Educ
Soc. 2012;1(1):1–40.
9. Stokes D. Against Decolonisation: Campus Culture Wars and the Decline of the
West. Polity Press; 2023.
10. Pace I. Is Classical Colonial? The Critic. https://thecritic.co.uk/issues/july-
2022/is-classical-colonial/ Published 2022. Accessed February 23, 2024.
11. Ganek E, Sazon RAP, Gray L, Sherry D. An Introduction to Faculty Diversity,
Equity, and Inclusion for Excellence in Nurse Education: Literature Review.
AsianPacific Isl Nurs J. 2023;7:e49231. doi:10.2196/49231
12. Freebody K, Goodwin S, Proctor H, eds. Higher Education, Pedagogy and Social
Justice: Politics and Practice. Springer; 2019.
13. Moore R, Muller J. The discourse of ’voice’ and the problem of knowledge and
identity in the sociology of education. Br J Sociol Educ. 1999;20(2):189–206.
14. Bhambra GK, Gebrial D, Nişancıoğlu K. Decolonising the University. Pluto
Press; 2018.
122 Inclusion and Higher Education
15. Drabinski J, Fanon F. In: Zalta E, ed. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
(Spring 2019 Edition). Stanford University; 2019. Accessed March 6, 2024.
https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2019/entries/frantz-fanon
16. Fanon F. The Wretched of the Earth. Grove Press; 1968.
17. Shatz A. The Rebel’s Clinic: The Revolutionary Lives of Frantz Fanon. Farrar, Straus
and Giroux; 2024.
18. Young RJC. Postcolonialism: An Historical Introduction. Anniversary Edition.
John Wiley & Sons; 2016.
19. Linfield S. The Lions’ Den. Yale University Press; 2019.
20. Arendt H. The Human Condition. The University of Chicago Press; 1958.
21. Abdel-Malek A. Social Dialectics. State University of New York Press; 1981.
22. Said E. Orientalism. Pantheon Books; 1978.
23. Chakrabarti S. Moving beyond Edward Said: Homi Bhabha and the problem of
postcolonial representation. Int Stud: Interdiscip Polit Cult J (IS). 2012;14(1):5–
21. doi:10.2478/v10223-012-0051-3
24. Dirlik A. Rethinking colonialism: Globalization, postcolonialism, and the nation.
Interventions. 2002;4(3):428–448. doi:10.1080/1369801022000013833
25. Matin K. Deciphering the modern Janus: societal multiplicity and nation-
formation. Globalizations. 2020;17(3):436–451. doi:10.1080/14747731.2019.
1673615
26. Parry B. Problems in current theories of colonial discourse. Oxf Lit Rev.
1987;9(1):27–58.
27. Hirsh D, Freedman R. Responses to 7 October: Antisemitic Discourse.
Routledge; 2024.
28. Mintz J. HE leaders must exercise free speech to oppose the justification of murder.
Times Higher Education. www.timeshighereducation.com/opinion/he-leaders-
must-exercise-free-speech-oppose-justifi cation-murder (Published November 22,
2023). Accessed March 6, 2024.
29. Anti- Israel Activists Celebrate Hamas Attacks that Have Killed Hundreds of
Israelis | ADL. Anti- Defamation League Blog. Published October 14, 2023.
Accessed March 6, 2024. www.adl.org/resources/blog/anti-israel-activists-celebr
ate-hamas-attacks-have-killed-hundreds-israelis
30. Freedland J, Somerville E, Clarence- Smith L. Cambridge academic co- wrote
booklet featuring pro- Hamas article. The Telegraph. www.telegraph.co.uk/
news/2023/11/03/cambridge-academic-co-wrote-booklet-pro-hamas-article/
(Published November 3, 2023). Accessed March 6, 2024.
31. Rose D. Academics claim Hamas atrocities are part of ‘legitimate struggle’ against
Israel. Jewish Chronicle. www.thejc.com/news/academics-claim-hamas-atrocit
ies-are-part-of-legitimate-struggle-against-israel-csnfvhrj (Published October 19,
2023). Accessed March 6, 2024.
32. Reynolds J. Outrage as “UPenn Junior” endorses Hamas’ October 7 attack on
Israel. Mail Online. www.dailymail.co.uk/news/article-12719839/UPenn-Jun
ior-endorses-Hamas-Oct-7-terror-attack-Israel-Philadelphia-rally.html (Published
November 7, 2023). Accessed March 6, 2024.
33. Feldman J. Dead Jews and live antisemites. Australian Jewish News. www.australia
njewishnews.com/dead-jews-and-live-antisemites/ (Published March 21, 2024).
Accessed March 21, 2024.
34. Horn D. People Love Dead Jews: Reports from a Haunted Present. W.W.
Norton; 2021.
Inclusion and Higher Education 123
52. C. I. E. The French National Assembly Debates Citizenship for Jews. Center for
Israel Education. Published n.d. Accessed March 6, 2024. https://israeled.org/
french-national-assembly/
53. Biale D, Galchinsky M, Heschel S. Insider/ Outsider: American Jews and
Multiculturalism. University of California Press; 1998.
54. Feldman LH. Jew and Gentile in the Ancient World: Attitudes and Interactions
from Alexander to Justinian. Princeton University Press; 2021.
55. Berlin I. Two Concepts of Liberty. Clarendon Press; 1958.
56. Freeman BM. Jewish Pride: Rebuilding a People. No Pasaran Media; 2021.
57. Garelick A. The Fight for the Sabbath. Jew Curr. 2022;(Winter). Accessed March
6, 2024. https://jewishcurrents.org/the-fight-for-the-sabbath
58. Stephens B. Opinion | Why I Can’t Stop Writing About Oct. 7. The New York
Times. www.nytimes.com/2023/12/19/opinion/october-7-jews-hamas.html
(Published December 20, 2023). Accessed March 6, 2024.
59. Biale D, Galchinsky M, Heschel S. Introduction. In: Biale D, Galchinsky M,
Heschel S, eds. Insider/Outsider: American Jews and Multiculturalism. University
of California Press; 1998:1–14.
60. Fuchs C. Foundations of Critical Theory. Routledge; 2021.
61. Memmi A. The Colonizer and the Colonized. Beacon Press; 1967.
62. Cocks J. On Sovereignty and Other Political Delusions. Bloomsbury; 2014.
63. Sajed A, Seidel T. Introduction: Escaping the Nation? National Consciousness
and the Horizons of Decolonization. Interventions. 2019;21(5):583–591.
doi:10.1080/1369801X.2019.1581643
64. Levinas E. Philosophical Essays. Martinus Nijhoff; 1990.
65. Slabodsky SE. De- colonial Jewish Thought and the Americas. In: Bilimoria
P, Irvine AB, eds. Postcolonial Philosophy of Religion. Springer Netherlands;
2009:251–272. doi:10.1007/978-90-481-2538-8_14
66. Memmi A. Portrait of a Jew. The Viking Press; 1971.
67. Memmi A. Decolonization and the Decolonized. University of Minnesota
Press; 2004.
68. Young M. Bringing Knowledge Back In: From Social Constructivism to Social
Realism in the Sociology of Education. Routledge; 2008.
69. Aschroft B, Ahluwalia P. Edward Said. 2nd Edition. Routledge; 2008.
7 Conclusions
ISIS caliphate did not extend it to the Yazidis and the Chinese Communist
Party did and does not extend it to the Uighurs, to Tibet, or to Hong Kong. If
the decolonization and DEI movements cannot identify that antisemitism and
the justification of the burning Jewish families together by Hamas as resist-
ance are similarly not liberal values or part of a common human horizon, then
they cannot fall back vacuously on a mixture of activism and free speech as a
justification. Particularly not at the same time as promoting notions of diver-
sity, equity and inclusion that exclude Jews. This is an incoherent position that
implies that there is no link between wider societal values and education. If
that is so, then there is no possibility of any meaningful content for the term
inclusion in relation to education, in universities or elsewhere.
Further, universities and the school system are also embedded within a
liberal perspective on what knowledge is and what its function should be.
Value pluralism is also a liberal value and as we have seen, there is significant
debate as to the extent to which and how the state should impose values via
the education system. This question, sitting squarely in the middle between
Berlin’s7 positive and negative liberty, is not one that it can be suggested, in
a liberal democratic society, is not up for debate. Even if we take a (in my
view wrongheaded) view of democracy, as say Olssen8 or Marion Young9
does, as primarily about being deliberative (i.e. about coming to consensus
on such matters), that would put the locus for such decision-making in the
hands of the democratic apparatus of the state, not of universities them-
selves. Yet if we take DEI and decolonization, there is manifestly no or at
most very limited debate. There is no recognition that the state and wider
society in creating and funding universities still expect them to adhere in
some sense to the idea of knowledge production that is both systematic and
useful.5 Rather, there is just a one-dimensional deracinated view of post
colonial theory, which replaces a complex contested field of study with a
Manichean binary of some groups good, other groups bad. There is no rec-
ognition of viewpoint diversity such that liberal, conservative, traditional or
even communitarian political perspectives and values, and their implications
for public policy, are considered. This is the case even when certain key clas-
sical and neoliberal values are to a greater or lesser extent at the heart of
the societies who pay for them through their taxes or through fees. There is
no recognition that there are debates possible in liberal societies about the
extent to which the state, and thus universities, should direct particular value
sets in education. There is no longer any sense that the teacher as activist is
an idea open to critique. An idea of inclusion in education that is based on
the debate-free thinking presented in decolonization and DEI programmes
in universities opens up all the risks of idealist overreach that Berlin warns us
about. As he wrote:10(p.i) 1
life, liberty, and human rights of millions because their eyes were fixed upon
some ultimate golden future?
I am afraid I have no dramatic answer to offer: only that if these ultimate
human values by which we live are to be pursued, then compromises, trade-
offs, [and] arrangements have to be made if the worst is not to happen. So
much liberty for so much equality, so much individual self-expression for so
much security, so much justice for so much compassion. My point is that
some values clash: the ends pursued by human beings are all generated by
our common nature, but their pursuit has to be to some degree controlled—
liberty and the pursuit of happiness, I repeat, may not be fully compatible
with each other, nor are liberty, equality, and fraternity.
So we must weigh and measure, bargain, compromise, and prevent the
crushing of one form of life by its rivals. I know only too well that this is not
a flag under which idealistic and enthusiastic young men and women may
wish to march—it seems too tame, too reasonable, too bourgeois, it does
not engage the generous emotions. But you must believe me, one cannot
have everything one wants—not only in practice, but even in theory. The
denial of this, the search for a single, overarching ideal because it is the one
and only true one for humanity, invariably leads to coercion. And then to
destruction [and] blood…
It leads to crowds who cannot reconcile how equality for all can encompass
the individual liberty of the Jews to always, always be different. Crowds who
cannot abide the tension between universalism and particularism inherent in
the idea of the nation, and can abide it even less when it comes to the idea of
the nation state of the Jews, chanting “Death to the Jew” in Paris in 1894,11
and awful chants about Jews outside the Sydney Opera House in 2023.12
It leads to Jewish students being abused by their teachers in England13 and
hiding in fear in libraries from marauding crowds of their fellow students in
New York.14 This is the ultimate risk of treating inclusion as any empty con
cept. Promoting antisemitism is not the function of universities in society. In
particular, there is no possible sense of justice in spending our tax dollars on it.
position those who promote these as good, and those who oppose them,
or dare to point out their impracticality, or the tensions inherent between
different values when making decisions based on limitations, as bad. Good
versus bad, in which all the bother of having to deal with tensions, and hard
decisions, and compromise and complexity is deposited in the bad, is a heady
political vision. It always has been, and as Berlin noted, it has a particular
attraction to the young. In one sense this may be not altogether a bad idea,
as the idealism of youth is a potent thing. However, youth’s idealism does
not rob those of us who have been around a while longer of our responsibil-
ities for discernment. I am reminded, in thinking about Scruton and Hayek’s
question, of Melanie Klein’s ideas on splitting in object relations theory.17 In
Kleinian theory, splitting refers to a defence mechanism in which a person
unconsciously separates aspects of the self or others into polarized, extreme
categories of good or bad. This splitting often originates in infancy and early
childhood as a way to manage overwhelming emotions and experiences.
According to Klein, the process of splitting serves to protect the ego from
anxiety and conflict by simplifying complex emotional experiences into more
manageable components.18 Maturity comes when as the infant develops, they
come to understand that the hate and envy that through splitting they have
projected onto others is just that, and they develop the capacity for reparation
and gratitude, a process which inevitably involves recognizing the good and
bad that resides both in ourselves and others. There is no zero sum game, as
Marx might have us believe, in human relations and human activity. As I have
traced, postcolonial theory in potential and actuality can move past simplistic
oppressor-oppressed binaries to a more complex view of the development of
nation and identity. Yet as it is instantiated in DEI, as an element of education
and inclusion, it has become denuded of this complexity.
In a sense, we could characterize inclusion as a concept within education, as
too early on in the process of redemption that Klein outlines, as too prone to
the simplistic solutions that come from splitting the world into good and bad.
This is not something that we can easily lay at the door of Fanon or Said. It is
the responsibility of the faculty and leaders of today. That in universities, and
schools, antisemitism has so easily have reared its ugly head since October 7th
is, I think, all the proof that is needed for this contention.
today, simply noting that the academy has some form on this. As Benda notes,
the distinction between critical scholarship and activism is crucial if the space
for the critical exchange of liberal ideas is to be maintained. Of course, there
is a tension here that Berlin was too well aware of –as Popper put it –the
paradox of toleration,22 but it is our responsibility in liberal democratic states
to navigate between pluralism and liberty. The core of the idea of liberal dem-
ocracy is that we need to have both; the lesson of totalitarianism, so lost on
the academy of today, is both that there are no idealist solutions and that we
need to have the courage to accept that. Popper argued that free expression in
free societies crucially allow bad and simplistic ideas to be exposed to critique;
however, this puts a responsibility on people to speak up, a responsibility so
often avoided by the academy. Yet the academy cannot easily ignore its respon-
sibilities given its huge influence on wider society.
Both during World War II and during the rise of fascism in Europe, the
failures of the academy were closely intertwined with what went on in the
schools.23 In modern times, particularly with the growth of the influence
of the universities internationally on professional training, both pre-and
in-service teacher education and teacher leadership,24,25 it is perhaps not sur
prising that confusion about the role of schools and teachers in promoting a
thin as opposed to thick perspective on civics and a conception of the good
life has arisen.26–28 Thus, for example, in England, even where legislative
guidance has been explicit about limiting the role of teachers in promoting
partisan political perspectives,29 frequently teachers and school leaders are
positioned as agents of change in respect of social justice.30,31 The debates on
the role of the state and education based on debates between liberal, com-
munitarian and postmodernist perspectives are, for much of the teaching
profession lost, particularly given how heavily influenced they are in their
training by the mindset of the academy. The idea of the activist teacher
committed to social justice has become something like a given in teacher
education,32,33 with much of the complexity and value tensions inherent in
such a stance unaddressed. At my workplace, The Institute of Education
(the name it is best known by), since 2014 a faculty of University College,
in London, has led the field of education internationally on the Quacquarelli
Symonds World University Rankings for years at the time of writing.34 It says
in its mission statement:
Since October 7th, we have seen not just in England, the UK and the US,
but across the world, an explosion in antisemitism in the common school, just
as we have in academia.36(p.24),37,38 This raises the same question as before –how
can those committed to creating a future that is inclusive and just, who have
been trained in just this, have somehow allowed antisemitism to rear its ugly
head, so often without restraint? What meaning then can inclusion in the con-
text of education have?
But if we are not armed with an a priori guarantee of the proposition that
a total harmony of true values is somewhere to be found –perhaps in
some ideal realm the characteristics of which we can, in our finite state,
not so much as conceive –we must fall back on the ordinary resources of
empirical observation and ordinary human knowledge…The world that we
encounter in ordinary experience is one in which we are faced with choices
between ends equally ultimate, and claims equally absolute, the realisation
of some of which must inevitably involve the sacrifice of others. Indeed, it
is because this is their situation that men place such immense value upon
the freedom to choose; for if they had assurance that in some perfect state,
realisable by men on earth, no ends pursued by them would ever be in
conflict, the necessity and agony of choice would disappear, and with it
the central importance of the freedom to choose. Any method of bringing
this final state nearer would then seem fully justified, no matter how much
freedom were sacrificed to forward its advance…The necessity of choosing
between absolute claims is then an inescapable characteristic of the human
condition.
incommensurable, and that all we can do is grapple with them using our critical
faculties and our understanding of local contexts. Liberalism also highlights
for us the crucial role of resource constraints. Many of these tensions could be
dissolved, if resources were unlimited. But as Scruton16 notes, for idealism in
its progressivist versions, this point is often not recognized, and perhaps this
is partly why progressive idealism is so attractive. I am not, though, proposing
that in relation to education and inclusion, it is not legitimate to call for more
allocation of resources. It very much is, and often allocating more resources to
marginalized groups is very much what we should do. But at the same time,
resources have limits, and the value tensions that flow from those limits need
to be recognized. In particular, the limits of time and energy that teachers have
need to be given more weight in debates on education and inclusion.
answered. At the very least, by bringing these questions out into the open,
it will give teachers the space to explore them, and as Berlin argues,7 these
questions cannot be glossed over however much we might wish for that, but
can only be resolved by the hard work of weighing up what will be gained and
what will be lost. Much of the impetus for my academic interest in education
and inclusion stems from my experiences as a class teacher. I was often preoccu-
pied with the question of how to deal with difference in the classroom, and the
feeling that I was failing at it. I guess looking back at my younger teaching self,
the realization I have come to, which I think is an important one, is that there
is no easy answer to what we should do in any given classroom with any given
child. There is only the moral responsibility to respond to the question, and to
respond to it as best we can for all the children that we work with as teachers.
Note
1 From a speech composed for a ceremony commemorating his acceptance of an hon
orary degree at the University of Toronto in 1994. This was presented on Berlin’s
behalf and then published under the title “A Message to the 21st Century”.
References
1. Moore JC. A Brief History of Universities. Springer; 2018.
2. Frank DJ, Meyer JW. University expansion and the knowledge society. Theory Soc.
2007;36(4):287–311. doi:10.1007/s11186-007-9035-z
3. Wittrock B. The modern university in its historical context; rethinking three trans-
formations. In: Randeria S, Wittrock B, eds. Social Science at the Crossroads. Brill;
2019:279–301. Accessed March 6, 2024. https://brill.com/display/title/16739
4. Checkoway B. Renewing the Civic Mission of the American Research University. J
High Educ. Published online March 1, 2001. Accessed March 6, 2024. www.tand
fonline.com/doi/abs/10.1080/00221546.2001.11778875
5. Lukianoff G, Haidt J. The Coddling of the American Mind: How Good Intentions
and Bad Ideas Are Setting Up a Generation for Failure. Penguin; 2018.
6. Clark W. Academic Charisma and the Origins of the Research University. University
of Chicago Press; 2008.
7. Berlin I. Two Concepts of Liberty. Clarendon Press; 1958.
8. Olssen M. Liberalism, Neoliberalism, Social Democracy: Thin Communitarian
Perspectives on Political Philosophy and Education. Routledge; 2010.
9. Young IM. Inclusion and Democracy. Oxford University Press, USA; 2002.
10. Berlin I. A Message to the Twenty-First Century. Presented at: Ceremony for
acceptance honorary degree; November 26, 1994; Toronto. Accessed March 3,
2024. https://isaiah-berlin.wolfson.ox.ac.uk/node/4045
11. Mouhou M. Affaire Dreyfus: conspiration dans la république (The Dreyfus Affair: a
conspiracy against the state). Harmattan; 2012.
12. Hannam P. NSW police say analysis shows pro-Palestine chant in viral Sydney
Opera House video was ‘where’s the Jews?’ The Guardian. www.theguardian.
com/australia-news/2024/feb/02/sydney-opera-house-palestine-protest-nsw-
police-antisemitic-chant-no-evidence (Published February 2, 2024). Accessed
March 6, 2024.
Conclusions 135
13. Hirsh D. Fathom Long Read | The Meaning of David Miller. Fathom.
2021;(March). Accessed March 6, 2024. https://fathomjournal.org/fathom-
long-read-the-meaning-of-david-miller/
14. Miller J. Jewish students reveal what happened at Cooper Union protest. The
New York Post. https://nypost.com/2023/10/26/metro/jewish-students-rev
eal-what-happened-at-cooper-union-protest/ (Published October 26, 2023).
Accessed March 6, 2024.
15. Stokes D. Against Decolonisation: Campus Culture Wars and the Decline of the
West. Polity Press; 2023.
16. Scruton R. Hayek and conservatism. In: Feser E, ed. The Cambridge Companion
to Hayek. Cambridge Companions to Philosophy. Cambridge University Press;
2007:208–231. doi:10.1017/CCOL0521849772.012
17. Klein M. Envy and Gratitude. Hogarth Press; 1957.
18. Klein M. The importance of symbol-formation in the development of the ego. Int
J Psychoanal. 1930;(11):24–39.
19. Benda J. The Treason of the Intellectuals (La Trahison Des Clercs). Transaction
Publishers; 2014.
20. Arendt H. The Origins of Totalitarianism. HarperCollins; 1973.
21. Ferguson N. The Treason of the Intellectuals. Free Press. Published online
December 11, 2023. Accessed March 6, 2024. www.thefp.com/p/niall-ferguson-
treason-intellectuals-third-reich
22. Popper KR. The Open Society and Its Enemies. Fifth edition, revised. Princeton
University Press; 1971.
23. Wegner G. Anti-Semitism and Schooling Under the Third Reich. Routledge; 2014.
24. Mintz J. The role of universities and knowledge in teacher education for
inclusion. Int J Incl Educ. Published online 2022:1– 11. doi:10.1080/
13603116.2022.2081877
25. Zeichner KM. The Struggle for the Soul of Teacher Education. Routledge New York,
NY; 2017.
26. Biesta G. Education and the Democratic Person: Towards a Political Conception
of Democratic Education. Teach Coll Rec. 2007;109(3):740–769. doi:10.1177/
016146810710900302
27. Darling-Hammond L. Powerful Teacher Education: Lessons from Exemplary
Programs. John Wiley & Sons; 2012.
28. Hirsch ED. The Making of Americans: Democracy and Our Schools. Yale University
Press; 2009.
29. Political impartiality in schools. Published online February 17, 2022. Accessed
March 7, 2024. www.gov.uk/government/publications/political-impartiality-in-
schools/political-impartiality-in-schools
30. Charney M, Hagopian J, Peterson B. Teacher Unions and Social Justice: Organizing
for the Schools and Communities Our Students Deserve. Rethinking Schools; 2021.
31. White TC. Teacher dissent in neoliberal times: Counter-publics and alternative-
publics in teacher activism. Educ Theory. 2020;70(3):297– 316. doi:10.1111/
edth.12434
32. Cochran-Smith M. Teacher education for justice and equity: 40 years of advo-
cacy. Action Teach Educ. 2020;42(1):49–59. doi:10.1080/01626620.2019.
1702120
33. Zeichner KM. Teacher Education and the Struggle for Social Justice. Routledge;
2009.
136 Conclusions
34. QS World University Rankings for Education & Training 2022. Top
Universities: Education Subject Ranking. Published 2024. Accessed March 7,
2024. www.topuniversities.com/university-subject-rankings/education-training
35. About IOE –IOE –Faculty of Education and Society –UCL –University College
London. IOE Website. Accessed March 21, 2024. www.ucl.ac.uk/ioe/about-ioe
36. Anti-Semitic acts nearly quadrupled last year in France, says Jewish organisation.
France 24. www.france24.com/en/europe/20240125-anti-semitic-acts-nearly-
quadrupled-last-year-in-france-says-jewish-organisation Published January 25,
2024. Accessed March 7, 2024.
37. Ranking Member Cassidy, Ernst, Colleagues Urge Biden Administration to
Address Rising Rates of Antisemitism in K-12 Schools. US Senate Committee
on Health, Education, Labour and Pensions. Published November 30, 2023.
Accessed March 7, 2024. www.help.senate.gov/ranking/newsroom/press/rank
ing-member-cassidy-ernst-colleagues-urge-biden-administration-to-address-ris
ing-rates-of-antisemitism-in-k-12-schools
38. Sherwood H, Ofori M. Antisemitic incidents in UK schools soared in 2023, charity
reports. The Guardian. www.theguardian.com/news/2024/feb/15/antisemitic-
incidents-in-uk-schools-soared-in-2023-charity-repor ts Published February 15,
2024. Accessed March 7, 2024.
39. Orwell G. Notes on Nationalism. Penguin UK; 2018.
40. Mintz J, Hick P, Solomon Y, et al. The reality of reality shock for inclusion: How
does teacher attitude, perceived knowledge and self-efficacy in relation to effective
inclusion in the classroom change from the pre-service to novice teacher year?
Teach Educ. 2020;91:103042. doi: 10.1016/j.tate.2020.103042
41. Buckland R. The Buckland Review of Autism Employment: Report and
Recommendations. Department for Work and Pensions; 2024. Accessed March
7, 2024. www.gov.uk/government/publications/the-buckland-review-of-autism-
employment-report-and-recommendations
42. Hick P, Matziari A, Mintz J, et al. Initial Teacher Education for Inclusion: Final
Report to the National Council for Special Education. National Council for Special
Education; 2019:1– 220. Accessed March 5, 2024. https://ncse.ie/research-
repor ts
43. Norwich B, Jones J. Lesson Study: Making a Difference to Teaching Pupils with
Learning Difficulties. A&C Black; 2014.
44. Seleznyov S, Roberts A, Walker R, Watson S, Hogan M. Is there anything special
about lesson study in special schools? Int J Lesson Learn Stud. 2020;9(4):301–
316. doi:10.1108/IJLLS-12-2019-0084
Index
ability vs. effort, teacher differentiation autism and autism education, 59,
of, 41, 43–44, 70 69–71, 79–80; Asperger’s Syndrome,
activism, 2–4; critique of DEI and 86; autistic identity, 50, 82–83, 93;
decolonization in higher education autonomy and, 51, 82; case study
and, 126–127; disability as identity of, 80–84; in higher education, 109;
and, 50; idealism and idealizing social communication development,
tendency in inclusion in education/ 71, 82–86; video modelling and,
SEN and, 8–9, 35, 45–48, 126–127, 71. See also inclusion in educational
130–131; postcolonialism as form of, settings/SEN
110, 112, 126; social justice, 3, 14, autonomy: in autism/SEN education
46, 70, 98, 110, 129; student voice and students, 51, 82; disability as
movement, 51; teacher as activists, identity and, 50; implications of in
125–126, 129, 133; as unopen to school, 42–44; Kant and, 65–66; as
critique in higher education, liberal state value and, 35–37, 41–42,
125–126, 129, 132; voice-based 51, 115; as liberal state value vs.
discourse on knowledge and, 51, 61, duty and tradition, 36–37, 39, 93;
67–68, 86, 102, 104, 110, 113 objections to liberal position on,
agency: moral agency, 61, 67–68; 26–27, 30, 41; teacher differentiation
objections to liberal position on, of ability vs. effort and, 41, 43–44, 70
26–27, 30. See also autonomy
antisemitism: DEI and postcolonialism in Benda, J., 128–129
higher education and, 109–110, Berlin, I., 3, 12, 22, 94, 126–127;
114–121, 126–127; marginalization critique of idealist universality/positive
of, 114–115; negotiation in liberty and, 22, 24, 29, 47, 126–127;
value conflicts for, 120–121; new critique of value pluralism/relativism
left antisemitism and, 114–115; of, 47–48; focus on liberty over state
postcolonialist binary thinking and, power of, 22–24, 29; Historical
117–119, 126–128, 132–133; rise in Inevitability, 29, 49, 67; on justice,
in higher education post-October 7th 26; on knowing moral agency, 67;
and, 109, 113–117, 119, 130, 133; on oppression in revolutions, 115;
rise in in schools post-October 7th Two Concepts of Liberty, 29, 130;
and, 130. See also Judaism and Jewish on utopian movements, 8; value
identity incommensurability and, 45–47.
Asperger’s Syndrome, 86. See also autism See also negative liberty (freedom)
and autism education bias in knowledge producers, 63–65,
assessment and inclusion, 49–50, 52; IQ 68–70, 86–87; need to challenge,
tests and, 1, 49, 62 131
138 Index
binary thinking, 127; negotiation for and, 49, 59, 65–67; sociological
avoiding, 120; as oversimplistic and critique of difference and, 2; traditional
oppressive, 117–119, 126, 132–133 natural law arguments for children/
Bion, W., 2–3 families, 37, 39, 48, 64, 66; traditional
biopsychosocial perspective on difference, values/duty in, 27; as underplayed
5, 8, 41, 50 in inclusion literature, 9; universalist
Black Caribbean identity in England, vs. particularist, 24, 27; universities
educational disparities and, 1 and maintaining liberal values
Booth, T., list of inclusive values of, and, 128–129; value tensions with
16–17 communitarian perspectives and, 46;
values of in public vs. private sphere,
capability approach, 5, 40–41, 44, 85 28–29, 35–36. See also neoliberalism
children and children with SEN, 46; common-sense view of knowledge, 61,
children/parents and state education, 67–69
33–34, 46; critical thinking skills and, communitarian perspectives, 48; critique
35–37; development of autonomy, of agency/autonomy and, 26–27,
35–36, 39, 41, 51; equal 36, 41; critique of Rawls and, 30; as
representation and protections and, underplayed in inclusion literature, 9;
41, 75; new sociology of childhood/ value tensions between liberal and, 46
student voice movement and, 51; community action/empowerment, 1;
parent-child relationship, 38–39, “Community Cultural Wealth” model,
50–51, 101; traditional natural law 98
arguments for children/families and, compulsory state schooling, 34–35
37, 39, 48, 64, 66 “conception of the good”, 8, 25, 29, 31,
choice, as liberal value, 23, 26. See also 36, 47, 94, 129
educational decision-making; value critical theory, 2; “Community Cultural
tensions in inclusion in education/ Wealth” model, 98; antisemitism and,
SEN 116; culturally responsive pedagogy
civics curriculum, 28–29, 33, 36, and, 92; decolonization and nation
47; critical thinking skills for and, 117; identitarian position of, 63;
democratic engagement skills inclusion and democracy and, 15; vs.
and, 35, 37, 42 postcolonial theory, 112; sociological
classical liberalism, 3; autonomy as liberal critique of difference and, 2
state value and, 35–37, 41–42, 115; critical thinking skills, teaching of,
critique of idealist universality and, 35–37, 42
22, 24, 29; critique of liberal position Crowder, G., 24, 45–48, 94; on tradition
on agency and, 26–27, 30; critique of in liberalism, 27
resource allocation/economics and, cultural diversity: “Community Cultural
50; education and education policy Wealth” model, 98; cultural disparities
issues and, 33, 40–42, 44; educational and, 1–2; cultural norms and, 84–85,
decision-making and, 49–50; equal 93–94; culture and values, 48; Funds
representation and protections and, of Knowledge approach and, 97–104;
41, 75, 115; equality in, 2, 115; forms need for understanding social/cultural
of, 24; good life in, 8, 25, 29, 31, contexts of knowledge, 63, 69–70,
36, 47, 94, 129; justice values, 26; 126; Spanish speakers in US, 99–100;
justice/social liberalism of Rawls and, value tensions in response to, 95–97.
24–27, 30, 41; knowledge and, 52, See also “Diversity, Equity
59; limits of liberalism/society, 85–86, and Inclusion” (DEI);
130–131, 133; Marxist critique of, 27, multiculturalism
29; multiculturalism and, 115–116; as culturally responsive pedagogy, 92–93,
non-solution to value tensions, 132; critiques of, 93; oppositional
130–131; postcolonial theory critique culture/identities and, 93–94, 117,
of in academics, 113; scientific realism 120; value tensions and, 93–94
Index 139
assessments and, 51–52; in autism and 49–52, 68, 70, 84–86, 91, 93–94;
autism education, 79–84, 93, 109; perspectives on values, 16; professional
autonomy vs. duty and tradition and, judgement in the classroom and, 47;
36–37; binary thinking and, 127–128; in public vs. private spheres, 28–29,
Booth’s list of inclusive values, 16–17; 35–36; realist vs. postmodernist
cultural diversity and, 95–97; cultural positions on knowledge and, 59;
diversity and Funds of Knowledge resource allocations and resource
approach and, 97–104, 132; culturally limitations and, 12–13, 74, 76–80,
responsive pedagogy and, 93–94; 84–85, 127–128, 131–133; study of
decision-making/educational decision- kindergarteners with SEN in Hong
making and, 16, 23, 26, 47, 74; Kong and, 74, 76; team teaching as
decolonization in higher education as, solution to, 80, 86; value choices case
109, 118–121, 126–127; disciplinary studies, 76–86; value differentiation
knowledge and, 68–70, 99; economic and knowledge and, 68; voice-based
(resource allocation) vs. other, 16, discourse on knowledge and, 61,
23–24; in educational decision- 68, 86, 102, 104, 110, 113. See also
making, 16, 47–48, 74–76; excellence autonomy; duty/traditional values;
as value and, 44, 52, 60, 93–94; in equality of opportunity/outcome;
higher education, 114, 117–120, 128; inclusion in educational settings/SEN;
idealism and idealizing tendency and, representation
8–9, 35, 45–46, 126–127, 130–131; video modelling, 71
between liberal and communitarian violence, in postcolonial theory, 111,
perspectives, 46; limits of liberalism/ 117
society and, 85–86, 131–132; local “voice discourses”, 61, 68, 86, 104;
positioning of teaching/relativism decolonization as, 110, 113
and, 48; nationality and identity in
postcolonialism and, 117–120, 128; welfare state, education and, 17, 22,
need for awareness of in teacher 31–33, 45, 78
education, 133; need for teacher West Indian community (London), 1
discussion/collaboration on, 94–95; West, E. G., 33–35, 131–132
negotiation for resolving, 103,
120–121, 132–133; neoliberalism/ Young, Marion, 15, 126
welfare state and education, 17, Young, Michael, 60, 62–64, 68–69, 86,
22, 31–33, 45, 78; normativity 102
and normative values and, 40, Young, R., 112–113