Lemche - Biblical Studies and The Failure of History
Lemche - Biblical Studies and The Failure of History
Published
Argonauts of the Desert: Structural Analysis of the Hebrew Bible
Philippe Wajdenbaum
www.equinoxpub.com
Acknowledgements vii
Introduction 1
John Van Seters
12. Kings and clients: on loyalty between the ruler and the ruled
in ancient ‘Israel’ 201
vi Contents
16. History writing in the ancient Near East and Greece 253
19. How does one date an expression of mental history? The Old
Testament and Hellenism 289
20. Chronology and archives: when does the history of Israel and
Judah begin? 307
21. ‘Because they have cast away the law of the Lord of Hosts’,
or ‘We and the rest of the world’: the authors who ‘wrote’
the Old Testament 317
The works in this volume appeared originally in the following journals and col-
lections of scholarly papers and are republished here by the kind permission of
the respective publishers and editors. They are listed below in the order of their
appearance in this volume.
Chapter 12: Kings and Clients: On Loyalty Between the Ruler and the Ruled
in Ancient ‘Israel’, Semeia 66 (1995), 119–32.
Chapter 13: Justice in Western Asia in Antiquity, Or Why No Laws Were
Needed!, The Kent Law Review 70 (1995), 1695–716.
Chapter 14: From Patronage Society to Patronage Society, in V. Fritz and P. R.
Davies (eds) The Origins of the Israelite States, JSOT Supplement
Series 228 (Sheffield: Sheffield Academic Press, 1996), 106–20.
Chapter 15: Are We Europeans Really Good Readers of Biblical Texts and
Interpreters of Biblical History?, Journal for the Study of North-
West Semitic Languages (Studies Hannes Olivier) 25 (1999),
185–99.
Chapter 16: History Writing in the Ancient Near East and Greece (1999:
unpublished).
Chapter 17: Good and Bad in History: The Greek Connection, in S. L. McKenzie
and T. Römer (ed) Rethinking the Foundations: Historiography in
the Ancient World and in the Bible. Essays in Honour of John Van
Seters, BZAW 294 (Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 2000), 127–40.
Chapter 18: On the Problems of Reconstructing Pre-Hellenistic Israelite
(Palestinian) History, Journal of Hebrew Scriptures 3/1 (2000).
Chapter 19: How Does One Date an Expression of Mental History? The Old
Testament and Hellenism, in L. L. Grabbe, Did Moses Speak
Attic? Jewish Historiography and Scripture in the Hellenistic
Period, Journal for the Study of the Old Testament Supplement
Series 317 (Sheffield: Sheffield Academic Press, 2001), 200–24.
Chapter 20: Chronology and Archives: When Does the History of Israel and
Judah Begin?, in D. M. Gunn and P. McNutt (eds) Imagining
Biblical Worlds: Spatial, Social, and Historical Constructs.
Essays in Honor of James W. Flanagan. Journal for the Study
of the Old Testament Supplement Series 359 (Sheffield: Sheffield
Academic Press, 2002), 264–76.
Chapter 21: ‘Because They Have Cast Away the Law of the Lord of Hosts’,
Or ‘We and the Rest of The World’: The Authors Who ‘Wrote’ the
Old Testament, SJOT 17 (2003), 268–90.
Introduction
John Van Seters
The author of the collection of essays in this third volume of the Changing
Perspectives series is widely known as the founder of the ‘Copenhagen
School,’ a term that has become synonymous with rather radical and ‘mini-
malist’ views to many in biblical scholarship, especially in North America,
and often without any clear idea about Lemche’s contributions to scholarship.
Niels Peter Lemche conducted his theological studies and graduate research
at the University of Copenhagen during the period of 1964 to 1978, and from
there he had his first teaching appointment at the University of Aarhus, dur-
ing 1978 to 1986. It was there that he published his very important doctoral
thesis, Early Israel: Anthropological and Historical Studies on the Israelite
Society before the Monarchy (in Danish, 1984, and English, 1985), and shortly
thereafter became Professor of Theology at the University of Copenhagen
(1987), where he has remained even since. It was primarily through this work,
Early Israel, with its strong emphasis on anthropological and sociological
approaches to Israelite history, that he became known to the English-speaking
world of scholarship.
I wish to call special attention to this period of the mid-1980s because in
the chapters that follow in this collection, this time period constitutes a sig-
nificant divide between the first six, which would appear to most scholars as
rather conservative in method and conclusions, and the rest, which reflect the
various themes for which he is now famous. In this way this division reflects
Lemche’s own ‘change in perspective’ and the fact that during this early period
in his career he was fully conversant with all of the biblical scholarship that
was associated with the pre-monarchical origins of ‘early Israel’ and the pos-
sibility of Late Bronze Age traditions being reflected in biblical texts. The fact
is that because of the prevailing trend in biblical scholarship during the 1960s
and 1970s, it was expected that one have expertise in Akkadian and Ugaritic,
in addition to the biblical languages, as well as a command of the history and
civilization of the Near East back to the third millennium, and this is reflected
very well in these opening articles, in which he is a master of this material. It is
to this first group of articles that we will now turn.
Chapters 1 to 3 have to do with the antiquity of the Covenant Code in rela-
tionship to the parallel laws in Deuteronomy and the Holiness Code, and specifi-
cally with the law of the Hebrew Slave and related laws and edicts regarding
2 Biblical studies and the failure of history
time of the monarchy and to focus instead on clues in the tradition regarding
the gradual settlement of tribal groups associated with two groups of the sons of
Jacob: the Leah tribes and the Rachel tribes. The other tendency among histori-
ans was to look in the narratives of the patriarchs and the exodus and conquest
traditions for ‘historical’ clues regarding this early history. The exception was
Eduard Meyer’s Die Israeliten und ihre Nachbarstämme; Meyer was rather crit-
ical of both methods as merely the rationalization of biblical traditions, instead
of real historical studies.
Lemche carries through his careful analysis of all the significant biblical his-
torians right down to the primary exponents of both tendencies in Martin Noth
and John Bright, with Noth as the heir of the German methodology in his treat-
ment of the tribes of Jacob for his early history, and Bright making use of a great
mass of studies to support the historicity of early historical events. He concludes
by stating that we must accept two ‘common-place axioms: (1) Our most impor
tant duty is to acknowledge our ignorance, and (2) once we have acknowledged
the state of our ignorance we are in a position to acknowledge what we really
do know.’ This means that for Lemche ‘the real task for the historian is to find
the Sitz im Leben of a systematic thinking of this kind’. Thus, the primary focus
of the modern historian should be to understand the narratives about the early
history of Israel within the historical context of the biblical writers themselves
(i.e. why they write about their origins in the way that they do).
It should be noted that at this point during the mid-1980s when Lemche
wrote his Early Israel and this historical survey, his primary focus was still on
the pre-monarchy period and scholars’ treatment of this period using ‘ration-
alistic paraphrase’ and had not yet extended this critique to the history of the
monarchy and beyond. Thus, in Ancient Israel (1988), Lemche was still able to
write a chapter of over fifty pages on the period of the monarchy from David
and Saul to the exile, although with many an appropriate caution about the bias
of the Deuteronomist. In time he would become much more sceptical of such
an endeavour.
After another lapse of five years, Lemche’s views on the history of Israel
had changed significantly, as reflected in: ‘The Old Testament: A Hellenistic
Book?’ (Chapter 8). Rather than accepting an exilic dating for the historical
narrative from Genesis to 2 Kings (J + Dtr), as a number of scholars, includ-
ing myself, had done, Lemche now raised the possibility of a much later date
in the Hellenistic period. Instead of starting with conjectures about the earli-
est traditions reflected in the Pentateuch and reconstructing a tradition-history
(Überlieferungsgeschichte) to their later historiographic formation, Lemche
begins with the manuscript evidence for the Greek Old Testament and the
Hebrew Bible as a whole and works back to earlier stages of its major compo-
nents, such as the Pentateuch and historical books, the collection of Prophets,
and the Writings. Lemche tries to establish clear and datable evidence for each
step back to an older level in the text before he moves to an earlier stage for its
individual components. His conclusion is that except for bits and pieces within
the major divisions, the Hebrew Bible is a collection of Hellenistic literary
works. In this approach he was strongly influenced by the Heidelberg scholar
Introduction 5
Bernd Jørg Diebner, who published his views in a private journal of limited
circulation of which he was the editor.
Lemche, in this article, supports his late dating by a critique for the early
dating of texts, using a broad range of examples. He also acknowledges that
in my earlier studies I had called attention to similarities between Greek and
Hebrew historiography, especially in the case of the Yahwist; but he rejects my
suggestion that this similarity can be accounted for by regarding the advanced
literary culture of the Phoenicians as the source for such literary forms in both
the Greeks, with whom they had a long history of contact, and the Israelites,
their neighbours. Instead, he prefers to see this similarity as the result of direct
contact in the Hellenistic period. Lemche likewise discredits the Persian period
as a likely setting for the biblical text because of the small and rather impover-
ished state of Jerusalem during this period.
In several of the articles that follow Lemche returns to the issue of the
Hellenistic dating of the Hebrew Bible, particularly its historical tradition, and
the closely related questions of whether it is possible to reconstruct a history of
‘Israel’ and what sort of history it would be, and the closely related problem of
the history of ‘Israelite’ religion.
This re-evaluation of the political and religious history of Israel was reflected
in two essays published in 1994. The first of these was ‘Is It Still Possible to
Write a History of Ancient Israel?’ (Chapter 10). For most histories of Israel of
this period, including Lemche’s earlier history Ancient Israel (1988), the history
of Israel proper arises from ‘the changes that have occurred at the beginning of
this history, that is, before 1000 bce’ (i.e. the rise of David). Now Lemche in this
chapter seeks to push this change to include a critical re-evaluation of virtually
all of the monarchic period that follows it as well, as a continuation of his criti-
cism in Early Israel (1985). Lemche acknowledges that he is building on the
work of Gösta Ahlström and Philip Davies, who argued that ‘the Israelites’ were
an ideological construct invented by Old Testament writers. In a monograph on
the subject, The Canaanites and their Land: The Tradition of the Canaanites
(1991), Lemche had suggested that the designation of Canaanites was likewise
an ideological construct of whatever was evil and non-‘Israelite’.
In this 1994 article he reviews some attempts to deal with the nature of bibli-
cal historiography – is it history at all? How much historical information actu-
ally survived in the Old Testament? Lemche uses three examples:
1. the city of Pithom mentioned in the story of the exodus (Exod. 1:11), but
which did not exist before c.600bce;
2. the possible migration of the Benjaminites into their homeland in the story
of Joshua; and
3. the relationship between David and Omri in tradition and history.
According to Lemche:
the first example shows how late information is referred back to earliest
times in order to create a picture of the Israelite sojourn in Egypt; the second
6 Biblical studies and the failure of history
This ancient method of writing history is hardly that of the modern historian,
and makes all biblical history suspect.
In the next complementary chapter, ‘Is It Still Possible to Speak about
an “Israelite Religion”? From the Perspective of an Historian’ (Chapter 11),
Lemche addresses the problem of a biblical history of religions. He begins this
discussion by noting that the revolutionary historical views of Mendenhall and
Gottwald were intended to give up the biblical history of the conquest in favour
of salvaging the religion of Israel, although in the Old Testament history and
religion are inseparable. This biblical religion is presented as the story of the
people of God from its beginning. Therefore, to reconstruct the history of Israel
by modern standards is also to reconstruct the history of their religion. Lemche
then proceeds to give a critical appraisal of this early biblical history (e.g. Noth’s
presentation of the settlement and the amphictyony). For Lemche, the entire
biblical history from the patriarchs to, and including, David and Solomon is all
‘fictive’. He spends a lot of time on the history of the Davidic–Solomonic period
because so much of biblical religion depends upon it. He concludes from this
historical review: ‘The biblical and real history form two independent universes.
It needs to be understood that the universe created by biblical writers was cre-
ated entirely on the basis of their situation and time.’ Lemche again expresses
the view that the universe of biblical historiography is Hellenistic (see Chapter
10), and in contrast to the contemporary historical uses of Israel, the biblical
use is entirely ideological. Building on this distinction, Lemche turns to a dis-
cussion of ‘Israelite’ religion in comparison with historical and archaeological
remnants of that religion. Can the Old Testament’s Israelite religion be made to
correspond in any way with the religion of the Northern Kingdom? The distinc-
tion between the biblical religion and the archaeological evidence of religious
practice in the time of the monarchies makes obvious the transformation of this
religion of Yahweh over time. Lemche warns that this is not a minor adjustment
of the older paradigm but a radical change to an entirely new paradigm for
understanding biblical religion.
As if to illustrate this point about a new paradigm, Lemche includes, ‘Are We
Europeans Really Good Readers of Biblical Texts and Interpreters of Biblical
History?’ (Chapter 15), which begins by offering a reading of the Flood story,
as compared with its Mesopotamian counterparts, the story of the destruction
of Sodom and Gomorrah, and the story of David’s Rise in 1–2 Samuel, com-
pared with the rise of King Idrimi of Alalah. Each story has its own particular
moral, whether it is biblical, Mesopotamian�or North Syrian, and in this respect
the myth of the Flood is no different from the story of David, which is in the
nature of a fairy tale and therefore is not intended as an account of what actu-
ally happened. Reading the story as if it were a piece of modern historiography
Introduction 7
is entirely misleading because as such it would have had no meaning for the
ancient. Europeans come to these stories with the wrong anachronistic per-
spective and misread the point of the stories. Lemche also argues, with several
examples, that the ancients, including Israel, had a quite different conception
of space, time and what we mistakenly regard as history, and he proceeds to
lay out some of the problems of modern Western readings of ancient texts. So
many of the new methods and fads of reading the Bible, both historical and
non-historical, fail to ‘distance themselves from their own tradition and are
willing to read ancient texts within the context of ancient societies as products
of a mythic and magic culture’.
In 1999 Lemche wrote two essays in response to my own studies on bibli-
cal historiography. His point of departure for the first one, ‘History Writing in
the Ancient Near East and Greece’ (Chapter 16), was my comparative study of
biblical historiography In Search of History (1983) within the context of his-
tory writing in the ancient Near East and Greece. While Lemche accepts the
broad implications of that study, he places far greater emphasis on the impact of
Greek historiography upon the Near East, including the Jews in Palestine, dur-
ing the Hellenistic period. As Bertil Albrektson already pointed out in History
and the Gods (1967), in all these ancient histories the gods play an active role
in the affairs of humans, and Lemche takes time to spell out the ideological and
propagandistic nature of Near Eastern history with little regard for historical
accuracy. He then engages in a form-critical analysis of both Near Eastern and
Greek styles of writing about the past and concludes that only the Greek style
of history writing fits the biblical model from Genesis to 2 Kings.
A second essay on the Bible’s Greek connection – ‘Good and Bad in History:
The Greek Connection’ (Chapter 17), written for my Festschrift in 1999 – takes
up in greater detail the stylistic arguments for favouring the later Hellenistic
connection with biblical historiography than the earlier dating (sixth century
bce), which I preferred. Lemche first dismisses, as a very late invention, the
complete biblical history of Israel, which therefore cannot be used as a context
for dating anything within it, including not only the early history of the patri-
archs down to the conquest and settlement, but the whole of the monarchies
from David down to, and including, the exile. This immediately makes dating
anything to the exilic period problematic. The ‘myths’ associated with the exile
are products of the Hellenistic era. Such a point of departure can only result in
the negation of any interpretation of the biblical history (i.e. stories) within this
historical period. For purposes of comparison, Lemche uses the Roman histo-
rian Livy in the time of Augustus and its role in Roman education as a model for
understanding the nature and purpose of biblical historiography. My own model
of comparison in Prologue to History (1992) had been the history of Dionysius,
The Antiquities of Rome, which was also used by Josephus for his Antiquities of
the Jews. In comparable fashion with classical education, Lemche views bibli-
cal historiography as works that were for the intension of educating the elite in
the basic Jewish way of life and its understanding of good and evil in the world.
Both this piece and the previous one present a serious challenge to an exilic dat-
ing, which needs to be engaged and not merely to be dismissed as ‘minimalist’.
8 Biblical studies and the failure of history
If one accepts the view that biblical history is largely a fantasy of the
Hellenistic period and of little value as a history for the modern historian, then
how can one make use of any possible historical references in this biblical
history for the reconstruction of a Palestinian history of this period? In ‘On
the Problems of Reconstructing Pre-Hellenistic Israelite (Palestinian) History’
(Chapter 18), Lemche attempts to deal with this question. In order to discuss
the distinction between fact and fiction in biblical historiography, Lemche
takes up two examples of historical events mentioned in 2 Kings: the story of
Sennacherib’s campaign against Judah and Jerusalem in 2 Kings 18–19 and
its parallels in the Assyrian annals, and, as a second example, the war against
Mesha in 2 Kings 3 and its parallel in the Mesha inscription. These are used
to illustrate the difficulty of reconstructing the historical and distinguishing it
from the story element, and labelling the resulting accounts as history. Historical
criticism of this kind is inevitably circular, which leads to the admission that a
history of Israel cannot be produced by this method. The extra-biblical confir-
mation of the names of Israel and Judah and the names of a few kings does not
constitute much of a basis for any historical reconstruction of the monarchies.
These royal names may suggest king lists of the two states with a few very brief
remarks about a significant event during a particular reign, and little else. This
shifts the discussion to the author’s particular uses of the past for his own time.
A survey of the biblical history from the patriarchs to the post-exilic period, as
compared with extra-biblical historical and archaeological evidence, confirms
its story-like and invented character.
A closely related issue concerning historical sources within biblical history
has to do with the possibility of archival sources for the history of the kings
of Israel and Judah, and this is addressed in ‘Chronology and Archives: When
Does the History of Israel and Judah Begin?’ (Chapter 20). In this chapter,
Lemche focuses on the problem of the so-called ‘chronicles of the kings of
Israel/Judah’, which list a few of the deeds of kings and length of their reign,
similar to Mesopotamian king lists. His examination of the lengths of reign
seems to reveal a distinct pattern in which certain reigns or combinations of
reigns yield the ‘pregnant’ number of forty, especially in the early part of the list,
whereas after Jehu in the north and Amaziah in the south there is no such pattern
evident. Lemche concludes from this that it would appear that only after these
two kings was any accurate record-keeping possible. Prior to this the numbers
for the length of each king’s reign were artificially constructed, and the chro-
nology of the monarchy for this earlier period quite useless. This would also
suggest that the time of Jehu and Amaziah was the beginning of administrative
literacy in these kingdoms and that there were no written records or archives of
the earlier period.
The last two chapters that deal with the Hellenistic dating of the Old Testa
ment (Chapters 19 and 21) address two issues that have been rather over-
looked before. The first of these issues is the neglect of due consideration of
the Mesopotamian element within the biblical histories. This he does in ‘How
Does One Date an Expression of Mental History? The Old Testament and
Hellenism’ (Chapter 19) by defining more precisely the Sitz im Leben of the
Introduction 9
This would also summarize much of the argumentation in the previous arti-
cles on this subject.
Another major concern of Lemche’s scholarship that is reflected in the
remaining four chapters that we need to look at (Chapters 9 and 12–14) has to do
with the basic sociological structure of early Israelite society – the patron–client
relationship. This attempts to go beyond his earlier discussion of family, lineage
and tribe in his treatment of pre-monarchic Israel, in Ancient Israel (1988), by
building on the work of Mario Liverani on Late Bronze Age vassal treaties and
the relationship between the vassal kings and the great king. Liverani sees this
as corresponding to the Roman system of wealthy and powerful patrons and
their clients. In ‘Power and Social Organization: Some Misunderstandings and
Some Proposals, Or Is It All a Question of Patrons and Clients?’ (Chapter 9),
Lemche explains this basic structure and relationship between patron and client
10 Biblical studies and the failure of history
by using its modern counterpart, the godfather and his clients in the mafia as
a persistent Mediterranean tradition since the second millennium bce. Lemche
uses this comparison of the patron–client relationship to explain the covenant
relationship between the deity and his people in the Old Testament, and this
becomes a major theme of his sociological research. In this relationship, God
as patron demands a pledge of absolute loyalty from his people as client and in
return promises to be guardian and defender of the client.
In ‘Kings and Clients: On Loyalty between the Ruler and the Ruled in
Ancient “Israel”’ (Chapter 12), Lemche expands on how this understanding of
God as patron is reflected in the covenant language of the Hebrew Bible. This
patronage model is also applied to the relationship between king and subjects,
and to the covenant relationship between God and king in the Davidic cov-
enant. In accordance with his patronage model, Lemche endeavours to make the
case, in ‘Justice in Western Asia in Antiquity, Or Why No Laws Were Needed!’
(Chapter 13), that laws were not used in Western Asia in spite of their presence
in the Pentateuch, as indicated by the fact that no law codes have turned up in
archaeological finds of Alalah or Ugarit. Lemche then discusses the problem of
understanding the purpose of�Mesopotamian law codes in the training of jurors
rather than a fixed standard for all situations. Law is regarded as divine law
given by God to the king to administer, not in written form. In terms of how the
judicial system would have actually worked, his answer is to appeal again to
the institution of patronage and how justice is administered in such a system.
The result is a very persuasive thesis, although it perhaps raises as many ques-
tions as it answers. It is noteworthy that his new dating of the Covenant Code
in the late Babylonian period reflects a major ‘change in perspective’ from that
of his earlier treatment of this Hebrew slave law (see Chapter 1). Finally, in
‘From Patronage Society to Patronage Society’ (Chapter 14), Lemche begins
by reviewing the problem of the historicity of David and the rise of Judah as a
state by applying Jamieson-Drake’s population study. He concludes that there
was no United Kingdom of David and Solomon. Instead, he suggests that the
society of the LB period was a patronage system, which survived down to the
time of the Hebrew kings. From a detailed review of patronage in LB Palestine,
Lemche moves to a proposed reconstruction of the transition of patronage to
Iron I or II. However, since we are left with only sparse archaeological remains
of villages for most of this period, their political or social nature must remain
guesswork. Consequently, Lemche guesses that there were rudimentary patron-
ages of the lineage type and from these village patrons the system developed
towards regional patronage ‘kings’, as reflected in the ‘house of David’.
1
It is widely accepted that there is a direct connection between the law of the
Hebrew slave in Exodus 21:2ff., Deuteronomy 15:12ff. and Jeremiah 34:8ff.
because the word עבריhas been used in all three passages.1 As a matter of fact,
it would be more reasonable to focus on the use of חפשיin those passages. This
word very clearly implies a dependence of Deuteronomy 15:12ff. and Jeremiah
34:8ff. on Exodus 21:2ff., since in Deuteronomistic literature the use of חפשי
is limited to Deuteronomy 15:12, 13, 18 and the Deuteronomistically coloured
Jeremiah 34:9, 10, 11, 14 and 16. Apart from the passages mentioned, חפשיis
used elsewhere only once in the Deuteronomistic historical work – namely, in
1 Samuel 17:25. This has, however, a non-Deuteronomistic setting and the way
in which the word is used is often misinterpreted.2 The use of the words עברי
and חפשיthus suggests links between Exodus 21:2ff. and the aforementioned
passages, though they are also of the utmost importance for an understanding of
Exodus 21:2ff. and its ‘Sitz im Leben’. How עבריand חפשיhave been used also
allows us to draw conclusions about the historical construction of the first part
of the Book of the Covenant, Exodus 21:2–23:16.
It falls outside the scope of this chapter to discuss precisely when the first part
of the Book of the Covenant was amplified by the second part, Exodus 22:17–
23:16, and by the apodictic passages of the first part. Most modern Old Testament
1. Cf., among others, G. Beer and K. Galling, Exodus (HAT I 3; Tübingen: Mohr, 1939),
107, and especially M. David, ‘The Manumission of Slaves under Zedekiah’, OTS 5
(1948), 63–79.
2. This is usually interpreted to mean that David’s family was promised a special tax
exemption. For literature, see H. J. Stoebe, ‘Die Goliathperikope 1 Sam. xvii 1-xviii
5 und die Textform der Septuaginta’, VT 6 (1956), 397–413, 403, and Das erste Buch
Samuelis (KAT VIII 1; Gütersloh: Gütersloher Verlagshaus, 1973), 324. Cf. my note
‘ חפשיin 1 Sam. xvii 25’, VT 24 (1974), 373–4.
12 Biblical studies and the failure of history
scholars date the amalgamation of the two parts to the Period of the Judges.3 It is
generally agreed that the first part of the Book of the Covenant is older and that
so-called casuistic laws are related to Near Eastern legal traditions.4
It seems appropriate to refer to the recent study of S. M. Paul, which, I think,
represents the most comprehensive commentary on the Book of the Covenant
based on Near Eastern source material.5 Hardly a single section in the older part
of the Book of the Covenant (Exodus 21:1–22:16, apart from secondary addi-
tions in Exodus 21:12-17, 23-25) is without parallel in the extra-biblical legal
literature of the second millennium. Paul endeavours to prove with his analysis
that the Book of the Covenant, as a whole, was part of a code of laws, which
extended from Exodus 19 to 24, where Exodus 19:3b‑6 (plus the Decalogue)
functioned as prologue to Exodus 23:20‑33’s epilogue. Paul dates the material
to a period just prior to the settlement of the Israelite tribes6 and refuses to accept
3. E.g. F. Horst, ‘Bundesbuch’, RGG I, col. 1524; M. Noth, Die Gesetze im Pentateuch,
(1940), in Ges. St. I (Munich: Chr. Kaiser, 1957), 9–141, 17, 31, and Das zweite Buch
Mose, Exodus (ATD 5, 3rd edn; Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprect, 1965), 140–41; G.
von Rad, Theologie des Alten Testaments, I (4th edn; Munich: Chr. Kaiser, 1966), 44; E.
Nielsen, The Ten Commandments in New Perspective (SBT SS 7; London: SCM, 1968),
77. In disagreement are A. Philips, Ancient Israel’s Criminal Law (London: Blackwell,
1971) 159, who dates the collection to the time of David and Solomon; also G. Fohrer (in
E. Sellin and G. Fohrer, Einleitung in das Alte Testament, 10th edn; Heidelberg: Quelle
& Meyer, 1965, 149–50, and G. Fohrer, Geschichte des israelitischen Religions, Berlin:
Walter de Gruyter, 1969, 131), who places it in the time of Jehu. Cf., already, A. Menes,
Die vorexilischen Gesetze Israels (BZAW 50; Berlin: Töpelmann, 1928), 43, but also M.
Noth’s decisive objections in Ges. St. I, 30–31. Fohrer discusses the question from the
assumption that the Book of the Covenant was a reform pamphlet and, in this connec-
tion, refers to Mesopotamian codices. These can hardly be called reforms, which were
contained in the mišarum-acts, the royal edicts. Cf., in this regard, F. R. Kraus, Ein Edikt
des Königs Ammi-úaduqa von Babylon (SD 5; Leiden: E. J. Brill, 1958), 182–247; J. J.
Finkelstein, ‘Ammi-úaduqa’s Edict and the Babylonian “Law Codes”’, JCS 15 (1961),
91–104, and ‘Some New Misharum Material and its Implications’, Assyriological
Studies 16 (1965), 233–46; J. Bottéro, ‘Désordre économique et annullation des dettes
en Mésopotamie á l’époque Paléo-Babylonienne’, JESHO 4 (1961), 113–64. Cf. also,
in general, C. J. Gadd in CAH, II/1 (3rd edn; Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1973), 187ff.
4. Departures from the general opinion are M. David, ‘The Codex Hammurabi and its
�
Relations to the Provision of Law in Exodus’, OTS 7 (1950), 149–78; Z. W. Falk, Hebrew
Laws in Biblical Times (Jerusalem: Wahrmann,1964), 33f.; and W. Preiser, ‘Vergeltung
und Sühne im altisraelitischen Strafrecht’ (Festschrift für Eberhard Schmidt, 1961), 7–38,
reprinted in K. Koch, Um das Prinzip der Vergeltung in Religion und Recht des Alten
Testaments (Wege der Forschung 125; Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft,
1972), 236–77, 240ff. The parallels from the Ancient Near East, however, far exceed
‘general conditions’ and possibly include the construction of the law material; cf. V.
Wagner, ‘Zur Systematik in dem Codex Ex 21.2‑22.26’, ZAW 81 (1969), 176–82.
5. S. M. Paul, Studies in the Book of the Covenant in the Light of Cuneiform and Biblical
Law (VT supplement, 18; Leiden: E. J. Brill, 1970).
6. Ibid., 101–2. The author here tries to prove the existence of a codex modelled on the
prologue primary corpus by analogy to the Codex Hammurabi (hereafter, CH ).
� �
The ‘Hebrew slave’ 13
the possibility that casuistic laws had been taken over from the Canaanites,
though he does admit that, as far as investigations have shown, Canaanite law
seems to betray a strong dependence on cuneiform law.7 Even though Paul’s
thesis finally must be rejected, as he apparently fails to follow up on his analy-
ses and is not fully aware of the value of modern literary criticism or history of
tradition, his conclusion is that very little – if any – material in the casuistic laws
of Exodus 21:2–22:16 suggests that Israelite law-givers inspired this collection.8
It is, indeed, quite possible to place the origin of the first part of the Book of the
Covenant in any Canaanite city state of the second half of the second millen-
nium and assume that it was later (in extenso?) drawn into the Israelite tradition.9
The consequence of this is that undocumented assertions such as those that G.
E. Mendenhall has brought forward need to be rejected. Mendenhall maintains
that the Book of the Covenant cannot have belonged to a Canaanite background
because of a reputed low moral development of Canaanite communities and
their strict social stratification.10 Such an argument is obviously based on an
insufficient knowledge of Canaanite social stratification in Canaanite city states.
7. Ibid., 104–5, 116ff.; Cf. to this Alt, ‘Eine neue Provinz des Keilschriftsrechts’, (Kl.
Schr., III; Munich: Beck, 1959), 141–57 and R. de Vaux, Les institutions de l’Ancien
Testament, I (2nd edn; Paris: Les éditions du Cerf, 1961), 226–7.
8. It is a fact, however, that this part of the Book of the Covenant has been enlarged by cer-
tain apodictically formed rules: Exodus 21:12‑17, 23‑25. Cf. also G. Liedke, Gestalt und
Bezeichnung alttestamentlicher Rechtsätze (WMANT, 39; Neukirchen: Neukirchener
Verlag, 1971), 130ff. Apart from vv. 23‑25, the talion formula, there is, in every case, an
unmistakable connection to the decalogue: Exod. 21:12 ↔ 20:13; 21:16 ↔ 20:15; 21:15,
17 ↔ 20:12 (cf. to the original content of 20:15. E. Nielsen, Ten Commandments, 85, 91,
who follows Alt, ‘Das Verbot des Diebstahls im Dekalog’ (1949, in Kl. Schr., I; Munich:
Beck, 1953, 333–40). R. Hentschke (‘Erwägungen zur israelitischen Rechtsgeschichte’,
Theologia Viatorum 10, 1965/66, 108–33) suggests that this alteration of casuistic and
apodictic segments should be compared to a corresponding variation in Ammiùaduqa’s
edict (about 1645), which has been published by Kraus, Ein Edikt, and provided with a
substantial supplement by J. J. Finkelstein, ‘The Edict of Ammiùaduqa: a New Text’, RA
63 (1969), 45–64. Hentschke’s argument has been emphatically opposed by S. Herrmann,
‘Das “apodiktische Recht”. Erwägungen zur Klärung dieses Begriffs’, MIO 15 (1969),
249–61, 255f. Cf. also apodictic law outside Israel: Liedke, Gestalt, 115–16, 126–7.
9. Most recently, L. Rost, ‘Das Bundesbuch’, ZAW 77 (1965), 255–9; cf. also O. Eissfeldt,
The Old Testament: An Introduction (Oxford: Blackwell, 1965), 26ff. Eissfeldt is
inclined to think that a continuous series of laws was adopted: The Old Testament, 29;
cf. also to this L. Watermann, ‘Pre-Israelite Laws in the Book of the Covenant’, AJSL 38
(1922), 36–54, and A. T. Olmstead, History of Palestine and Syria to the Macedonian
Conquest (New York: C. Scribner’s Sons 1931), 104ff. Alt thought that the casuistic
laws in the Book of the Covenant were originally Canaanite (see his Die Ursprünge des
israelitischen Rechts, 1934, in Kl. Schr., I, 278–332, 295ff.). A. Jepsen, Untersuchungen
zum Bundesbuch (BWANT, III 5; Stuttgart: Kohlhammer, 1927), 76ff., 97ff., admits that
they were of ‘Palestinian’ origin but he introduces the idea of a ‘Hebräergesetz’ based
on an understanding of the ‘Hebrews’ that is now obsolete. Neither Jepsen’s nor Alt’s
interpretations exclude the possibility that the collection was developed by Israelites.
10. G. E. Mendenhall, ‘Ancient Oriental and Biblical Law’, BA 17 (1954), 26–46, now in
BARe III (New York: Doubleday, 1970), 3–24, 15.
14 Biblical studies and the failure of history
Mesopotamian kings, like their West Asiatic colleagues, formed a supreme court
of appeal.15
It is impossible to say whether the first part of the Book of the Covenant
came into existence without Canaanite influence, merely because no written
evidence of judicial rules has been found in Syria–Palestine. The appearance of
a code of laws or legal decisions16 undoubtedly goes back to the influence of the
Babylonian ‘Weltanschauung’.17
Other scholars have written against the thesis of a non-Israelite origin of the
first part of the Book of the Covenant, suggesting instead that although it does
show a relationship to Mesopotamian (and Canaanite) law, it is more primitive,
presupposing (under the influence of blood feuds) more severe punishments.18
However, this objection does not take into consideration that there are also vari-
ations in Mesopotamia from one code to another regarding the character of pun-
ishments (especially concerning the use of fines as opposed to death penalties),19
nor that it is only to be expected that the more complicated Babylonian com-
munity needed other rules than a Canaanite polity. In Mesopotamia, differences
existed from state to state, as can be seen when comparing the CH to other
codices.20 It is unreasonable, moreover, to look to the development �of laws in
other sources, were followed.’ To the Babylonian codices: cf. Finkelstein, JCS 15, 103f.
(‘royal apologies and testaments’ which were to prove to the gods, whose vicar the king
was, that the king was a šar mišarim).
15. To this, particularly W. F. Leeman’s ‘King Hammurapi as judge’, (Symbolae Martino
�
David, 2; Leiden: E. J. Brill, 1968), 107–29 (with ample documentation). Cf. also
R. Haase, Einführung in das Studium keilschriftlicher Rechtsquellen (Wiesbaden:
Harrassowitz, 1965), 36ff.
16. On the interpretation of C as a codex of ‘judgements’, see F. R. Kraus, ‘Ein zentrales
Problem des altmesopotamischen Rechtes: was ist der Codex Hammurabi?’, Genava
�
NS 8 (1960), 283–96.
17. Cf. Nougayrol, Syria 39, 32.
18. Among others, von Rad, Theologie, 44ff.
19. Jepsen gives an example of a Mesopotamian law that demands capital punishment
in cases where the Book of the Covenant only imposes fines: Exod. 22:15-16, cf.
Bundesbuch, 69. This shows that it cannot be consistently maintained that the Book
of the Covenant is more primitive. Jepsen depends on an obsolete translation of Yale
Babylonian Collection 2177 (publ. by A. T. Clay, Yale Oriental Series, Babylonian Texts,
vol I, no 28) §8 in B. Meißner, Babylonien und Assyrien, I (Heidelberg: Carl Winters
Universitätsbuchhandlung, 1920), 151; cf. A. Jirku, Altorientalischer Kommentar zum
Alten Testament (Leipzig: A. Deichertsche Verlagsbuchhandlung Dr. Werner Scholl,
1923), 98 (‘Wenn jemand die Tochter eines Mannes gewaltsam fortführt gegen den
Willen (?) ihres Vaters und ihrer Mutter und sie erkennt, so soll der Mann, der sie wider
Willen (?) erkannt und vergewaltigt hat, auf Befehl der Götter getötet werden’); cf. also
Finkelstein’s translation in ANET 3 (1969), 526: ‘If [a man] deflowered the daughter of
a free citizen in the street, her father and her mother having known [that she was in the
street], but the man who deflowered her denied that he knew [her to be of the free citizen
class] and, standing at the temple gate, swore an oath [to this effect, he shall be freed].’
20. Cf. M. San Nicólo, Beiträge zur Rechtsgeschichte im Bereiche der keilschriftlichen
Rechtsquellen (Oslo: H. Aschehoug 1931), 63ff.; cf. also David, OTS 7, 149ff. David
arrives at the negative conclusion that there is no connection.
16 Biblical studies and the failure of history
Mesopotamia for special West Semitic traits.21 Many laws, and among them at
least one codex, have been handed down from the Sumerians and it seems that
West Semites followed the same path as the earliest inhabitants of Mesopotamia.
Nevertheless, the possibility that the increase in CH of certain penalties in rela-
tion to former codices may be due to West Semitic� influence still exists.22
According to the Masoretic Text (MT), Exodus 21:2 ff. is an account of a pur-
chase of a slave, which was cancelled after six years. Alt thought – in partial
agreement with A. Jepsen – that v. 2 originally related how a ‘Hebrew’ sold him-
self.23 For form-critical reasons, Jepsen corrected תקנהto יקנה, and Alt went even
further and read ימכרin correspondence with Deuteronomy 15:12. When Paul
rebuts Alt’s emendation on the grounds that תקנהin v. 2 is dependent on תשיםin
v. 1, and thus original, he disregards form-critical as well as tradition-historical
criteria.24 Supposing Paul correct, v. 1 was from the beginning an introduction
to an important code of laws whose first units were vv. 2‑6. This, however, is
unreasonable. Moreover, Jepsen’s objection against the second person singular
is valid since it encroaches on the casuistic legal phrase as such.25 More objec-
tions have been raised against the assertion that v. 2 should have been preserved
in its original form. Paul’s arguments are also inseparably bound up with his
(Mosaic?) dating of the Book of the Covenant as a whole.26 There can be no
doubt, however, that, isolated, Exodus 21:1 shows a tension between the Book
of the Covenant and its setting and that it disrupts the coherence of the text.27
In maintaining his correction of the verbal form, Alt wanted to replace the
difficult עבדby the neutral איש, by analogy with vv. 7, 14, 18 (pl.), 20, and
so on.28 עבדis most troublesome where it stands now, and, if the MT is to be
retained, it can best be understood as a proleptic expression.29 Not until he is
bought or sold, does an עבריbecome a slave.
21. Against Jepsen, ‘Die “Hebräer” und ihr Recht’, AfO 15 (1945–51), 55–68.
22. Cf. Codex Ur-Nammu (about 2112–2095bce), Ur III, translated by Finkelstein in ANET
3, 523ff. and Yale Babylonian Collection 2177 (cf. n. 19), same place, 525–6. The theory
of a West Semitic origin of the regularly recurrent royal edicts cannot be upheld inas-
much as the oldest testimony of this is Sumerian and dates back to c. 2350 (‘Urukagina’s
reform’); see also Finkelstein, JCS 15, 103–4.
23. Alt, Kl. Schr. I, 291 and n. 2; Jepsen, Bundesbuch, 56.
24. Paul, Studies, 46, n. 7.
25. To the casuistic law, compare in particular the very exhaustive study by Liedke, Gestalt,
19–61. Liedke also looks upon the ‘when-you’ wording in casuistic legal rules as the
product of a later development.
26. Paul, Studies, 101f.
27. Cf. further E. Nielsen, The Ten Commandments, 51; Alt, Kl. Schr., I, 286 n. 1.
28. Alt, Kl. Schr. I, 291 n. 2; Cf. also Jepsen, Bundesbuch, 56: כי יקנה איש.
29. Alt, Kl. Schr. I, 291 n. 2; cf. Noth, ATD, 143.
The ‘Hebrew slave’ 17
עבריand חפשי
30. J. P. M. van der Ploeg, ‘Studies in Hebrew Law’, II, CBQ 12, (1950), 416–27, see 425f.,
and III, CBQ 13 (1951), 28–43, 28f.; and, most recently ‘Slavery in the Old Testament’,
VT 22, (1972), 72–87, see 78, 81.
31. E.g. F. Horst, Das Privilegrecht Jahwes (FRLANT 45; Göttingen: Vandenhoeck &
Ruprecht, 1930), now in Gottes Recht (Munich: Chr. Kaiser, 1961), 17–154, 97; R. de
Vaux, Les institutions de l’Ancien Testament, I (Paris: Les éditions du Cerf, 1961), 129
(cf. 136, 265); this also applies partly to Beer and Galling, Exodus, 107, though they
realize that vv. 2‑6 did not originally refer to the Israelites, but to the ‘Hebrews’.
32. R. North, Sociology of the Biblical Jubilee (AnBi 4; Rome: Ponteficial Biblical Institute,
1954), 148; this point of view is shared by Paul, Studies, 46.
18 Biblical studies and the failure of history
and Old Babylonian period, including Nuzi, and, apart from the Amarna letters,
even later in Western Asia in documents from Alalah and Ugarit.51 A closer
definition of this social group is, however, still a matter�of debate. The choice is
between defining them as ‘independent’ – that is, free in the modern sense of the
word (‘free proletarians’) – or as ‘half-free’ – that is, dependent on private per-
sons or on the government (the king). To look upon them as ‘free proletarians’ or
‘Bauern’52 is incompatible with the sources from Byblus, Ugarit and Alalah, as
�
well as with the use of hupšu in Assyrian texts. Heltzer has shown that at Ugarit
�
hupšu belonged to the bnš mlk, ‘the king’s men’. At Ugarit as well as Alalah,
�hupšu had a predominantly military function and received the supplies neces- �
�sary for their subsistence in the form of plots and provisions from the palace
administration.53 This is in agreement with the mention of hupšu in Rib‑Adda’s
letters.54 It has not been possible to trace a direct connection� between habiru and
�
hupšu. Even so, it has been assumed that the political propaganda of Abdi-Aširta
�of Amurru was directed at the hupšu class at Byblus, and that, accordingly,
Rib-Adda had reason to fear that� his hupšu would either revolt against him or
�
51. Literature: cf. Weippert, Die Landnahme, 74 n. 9. To this, may be added W. von Soden,
AHw, I, 357a; CAD 6 (Chicago, IL: Oriental Institute, 1956), 241–2.; J. Gray, The
Legacy of Canaan (VT supplement, 5; Leiden: E. J. Brill, 1957), 100 n. 6; A. F. Rainey,
The Social Stratification of Ugarit, 144; M. Heltzer, ‘Klassovaja i političeskaja borb’a v
Bible amarnskogo vremeni’ (‘Class Struggle and Political Conflicts at Byblus During the
Amarna Period’), VDI 1954/1, 33–9, 36ff., ‘Vojsko ugarita i ego organizacija’ (‘The Army
of Ugarit and its Organization’), VDI 1969/3, 21–38, 33; his results have been summa-
rized in Liverani (ed.) La Siria, 31ff., and in ‘Soziale Aspekte des Heerwesens in Ugarit’,
in H. Klengel (ed.) Beiträge zur sozialen Struktur des Alten Vorderasien, = Schriften zur
Geschichte und Kultur des Alten Orients 1 (Berlin: Akademie Verlag, 1971), 125–31;
H. Klengel, Geschichte Syriens im 2. Jahrtausend v.u.Z. Teil 2. Mittel- und Südsyrien
(Berlin: Akademie Verlag, 1969), 250, 255; M. Dietrich and O. Loretz, ‘Die soziale
Struktur von Alalah und Ugarit (II)’, WO V 1 (1969), 59–93. To the etymology of hupšu,
� �
L. Kopf, ‘Das arabische Wörterbuch als Hilfsmittel für die hebräische Lexicographie’,
VT 6 (1956), 286–302, 300ff.; cf. already W. F. Albright, ‘The North-Canaanite Poems
of Al’âyân Ba’al and the “Gracious Gods”’, JPOS 14 (1934), 101–40, 131 n. 102, and
From the Stone Age to Christianity (2nd edn; Garden City, NY: Doubleday, 1957), 285
n. 12.
52. ‘Bauern’: thus after Knudtzon, Die El-Amarna Tafeln, VAB II (Leipzig: J. C. Hinrichs
1915), 1417. ‘Free Proletarians’: according to I. Mendelsohn, ‘The Canaanite Term for
“Free Proletarian”’, BASOR 83 (1941), 36–9.
53. Heltzer, VDI 1969/3, 33, Cf. his ‘Carskie ljudi’ (bnš mlk) i carskie xozjaststvennye cen-
try (gt) v Ugarite’ (‘Royal Dependents [bnš mlk] and Units of the Royal Estate [gt] in
Ugarit’), VDI 1967/2, 32–47, and the same in Liverani, La Siria, 34, and in Klengel,
Beiträge, 129. The testimonies of hupšu in Ugarit are few. They are mentioned, however,
�
together with the military group šananu/tnn in PRU 5, 15 (cf. also I Krt 90–91: hpt.dbl.
�
spr / �nn.dbl.hg, ‘h. without numeral, �. without number’). Important in this connection is
�
also the RŠ 24.247 (KTU 1.103 (+ KTU 1.145) mlkn.j ’zz. ’l.hp�h, ‘Our king shall prevail
�
over his hupšu’, cited by Gordon, UT, 404, no 915. The greater part of the material relat-
�
ing to hupšu in Alalah has been treated by Dietrich and Loretz, ‘Die soziale Struktur’.
� �
54. Rib-Adda’s failing confidence in the loyalty of his hupšu was a result of his inability to
�
provide them with the mentioned supplies; cf. EA 118: 23–4; 125: 25ff.; 85: 10ff.
22 Biblical studies and the failure of history
they would bolt and join Abdi-Aširta.55 The social standing of hupšu in Assyria
�
seems to have been very much the same as in western Asia. There, they were
also soldiers (mercenaries) with specific corvée obligations.56 The mention of
hupšu, however, is not restricted to the military profession. From Nuzi, we know
�of three cases in which persons, characterized as hupšu, are weavers.57 From
� artisans, shepherds, one
Alalah (stratum IV, fifteenth century) we have various
�
courier and one doctor (all exceptions)58 who belong to the hupšu (= name in
�
Alalah).
�
From this material, it is possible to define חפשיin Exodus 21:2 in two ways.
A Hebrew has become a חפשיby being released from slavery and, in turn, has
entered into a private relationship with his former master. Alternatively, the
hitherto privately owned עבריhas passed into a form of collective dependency
on the city-state to which his former master belonged. For this reason, it is inac-
curate to define his social position merely as a freedman. A חפשיshould also
be placed socially, somewhere between a slave and a freedman. Accordingly
there is a difference between Exodus 21:2ff. and its secondary development in
Deuteronomy 15:12ff. and Leviticus 25:39ff. The last two passages treat the
manumission as a complete restitution, whereas Exodus 21:2ff. only allows the
slave to advance to a subordinate class.
Such promotion was not always looked upon as desirable, as is apparent
from Exodus 21:4‑6, which confirms the Hebrew’s right to choose for himself
whether he will remain a slave.59 It is not quite clear what his position as an עבד
in Exodus 21:2ff. really means. The parallels from Nuzi define the social stan
ding of a male habiru slave as wardatum ‘slavery’60 and of a female as amtum.
� latter, the punishment for breach of contract on the part of
In the case of the
the slave was severe corporal mutilation and resale, which might be taken to
mean that it was not normally permissible to sell a slave in Nuzi. Whether a
similar measure existed in the Book of the Covenant is uncertain, but probable.
Nowhere in the Old Testament is the resale of Hebrew slaves mentioned.
Nothing can be said about the rights and obligations of a Hebrew slave in
the situation of prolonged slavery. The term עבדו לעלםin Exodus 21:6 seems to
indicate that the slave was to remain in the service of his master indefinitely;
55. Klengel, Geschichte II, 250, and Liverani, ‘Implicazioni sociali nella politica di Abdi-
Ashirta di Amurru’, RSO 40, 1965, 267–77, 272f. Cf. also EA 118: 36–9: al-lu / pa-ñá-ri-
ma LÚ.MEŠ hu-up-ši ù / ùa-ab-tu LÚ.MEŠ.GAZ. MEŠ/URU, ‘it is a fact that the Hupši
� �
have run away, and the habiri have (consequently) captured the town’.
�
56. The material has been summed up in CAD 6; cf. most recently G. Cardascia, Les lois
assyriennes (Littératures Anciennes du Proche-Orient 2; Paris: Les Éditions du Cerf,
1969), 220–21. (to MAL A 45, dating from the twelfth century though the law may be
older; cf. Meek, ANET3 180).
57. Cf. E. R. Lacheman, ‘Note on the Word hupšu at Nuzi’, BASOR 86 (1942), 36–7.
�
58. Cf. Dietrich and Loretz, ‘Die soziale Struktur’, 87. Only in the case of 18 out of 542
persons has an occupation been mentioned.
59. Further details to vv. 3‑6 in Paul, Studies, 47ff.
60. One exception: Bottéro, 4e RAI, no. 54:3 [a-na gi]-el-lu-uh-ti. The reading and the con-
�
tent of the word is not quite certain. Cf. von Soden, AHw, I, 284, s.v. gelduhlu, gelzu(h)lu.
� �
The ‘Hebrew slave’ 23
but whether this meant that the owner could not get rid of his slave by selling
him or setting him free at a later date must be left an open question at present.61
Exodus 21:7‑11
With regard to vv. 7-11, which, in their present context state the rules a Hebrew
must follow in the case of wanting to sell a daughter, it is necessary to obviate
some misunderstandings. It is expressly stated that the issue is the sale of a
daughter, who is apparently a virgin, not the sale of a Hebrew woman, an עבריה.
Thus, the law described in vv. 7‑11 cannot be taken to apply to Hebrew women
in general and to mean that these could not be set free on the same conditions as
male slaves.62 Either there are no rules for a Hebrew selling his wife (or his sons,
for that matter) or these two categories are incorporated in the law of vv. 2‑6 in
a way that it was considered impossible that a man sell his wife and remain free
himself and, further, that a son sold into bondage had the same possibilities of
manumission as his father.
Conclusion
The traditional point of view that the Book of the Covenant is of Israelite ori-
gin has supported many absurdities and distortions in the interpretation of the
Hebrew slave and his social standing. This chapter attempts to shed new light
on a number of obscurities in Exodus 21:2‑11:
1. The first part of the Book of the Covenant fits in very well with a context
that is Canaanite, not Israelite.
61. Paul, Studies, 50, thinks that האלהים, Exodus 21:6 refers to the household god (elsewhere
in the Old Testament תרפים. In this case, the slave was accepted as a permanent mem-
ber of the household in the presence of the god (whose protection was thus extended
to him). This would also explain Rachel’s theft of Laban’s תרפיםas enabling Jacob to
break his contract of service to Laban as a person without his having to break away
from the protective penates. Cf. M. Greenberg, ‘Another Look at Rachel’s Theft of the
Teraphim’, JBL 81 (1962). The rather fanciful interpretation of Rachel’s psychology may
be neglected in this connection. It is, however, more probable that האלהיםindicates that
the ceremony took place in the local sanctuary; cf. to this, most recently, M. Weinfeld,
Deuteronomy and the Deuteronomic School (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1972),
233.
62. In opposition to Beer and Galling, Exodus, 108; Noth, ATD, 5, 144, and P. A. H. de
Boer, ‘Some Remarks on Exodus xxi 7‑11’, Orientalia Neerlandica 1948, 162–6. Cf.
Jepsen, Bundesbuch, 27–8, who is probably right when stating partly that she is not set
free because of the status she obtains with her owner. Both Jepsen, Bundesbuch, 28, and
de Boer, ‘Some Remarks’, 162, are right when interpreting עםin v. 8a as ‘family’, thus
indicating that the slave girl cannot be sold to another family. I. Mendelsohn, Slavery,
12f. takes vv.7‑11 as parallels to the ‘sale-adoption’ contacts from Nuzi; but it is doubtful
whether this is actually a parallel; cf. also Paul’s hesitations, Studies, 53.
24 Biblical studies and the failure of history
2. This also applies to the first law in the Book of the Covenant, the law of
the Hebrew slave. The placing of this law within the first part of the Book
of the Covenant cannot really be challenged, but several objections may
be raised against the wording of v. 2. The beginning of v. 2 should be cor-
rected in accordance with Alt’s views.
3. The interpretation of this law must necessarily include the general debate
on habiru and hupšu. I have tried to explain the words עבריand חפשיin
� agreement� with the modern view on habiru and hupšu as sociologi-
close
� �
cal denominations.
According to this a habiru should be taken to mean an outlaw and hupšu some-
one dependent on a �city-state or on a citizen of the same.63 The thought
� that the
Hebrew of Exodus 21:2 was necessarily an Israelite must be ruled out; but this
does not exclude the possibility that he might have been. It is quite probable that
impoverished Israelites or groups from the now resident Israelite tribes joined
the habiru and it must have been difficult, at times, for the original inhabitants
�
to distinguish between Hebrews and Israelites among the roaming gangs of
robbers.
The results reached do not, however, solve all problems. There is still the
question of how the transformation of the Hebrew from an antisocial straggler to
an Israelite citizen took place, and of how the traditional synthesis of the laws of
the manumission of slaves with the law of the fallow year, transforming it into
first a ‘Sabbath year’ and later a ‘Year of Jubilee’, was effected.64
Appendix
In general, it is held that חפשיmeans ‘free’ from something – for example, from
paying tax or other duties65 or, alternatively, free from corvée obligations66 or
63. It is not improbable that hupšu/ חפשיis the West Semitic word for Akkadian muškênum,
�
who were also a client-class. Cf. W. von Soden, ‘Muškênum und die Mawali des frühen
Islam’, ZA 56 (1964), 133–41, who finds similarities between the Arabic mawali and
the muškênum class in the Old Babylonian period; cf. too B. Kienast, ‘Zu muškênum =
Maula’, XVIII Rencontre assyriologique internationale, 1970 (Bayerische Akad. d. Wiss.
Phil. Hist. Kl. Abh., N.F. 75; Munich: Bayerische Akademie der Wissenschaftten, 1972),
99–103.
64. I refer to these problems (including Jer. 34:8ff.) in Chapter 2, this volume.
65. Thus K. Budde, KHAT V11I, 126; W. Nowack, HKAT 1 4, 88; H. Gressmann, SATA II/1,
67; W. Hertzberg, ATD 10, 114.
66. H. P. Smith, ICC, 158.
The ‘Hebrew slave’ 25
possibly both.67 Other suggestions have been put forward by W. Caspari68 who
thinks that Saul offered to annul whatever debt might have been incurred by
David’s family, and by H. J. Stoebe69 who would prefer to write off the whole
passage as secondary, partly because it is not included in the LXX and partly
because it makes no sense in view of the fact that David was a free landowner.
This last argument is irrelevant, however, since Saul could not know beforehand
who was going to accept his offer. Nor would it offer any solution to look upon
Saul’s pledge to grant tax exemption as insignificant since David’s family, as
Judeans, could not have been tributaries of the Israelite king. In this connection,
I think it most probable that no political union existed between Israel and Judah
before David became king of both countries.70
Another way of understanding v. 25 is by way of a closer definition of the
word חפשי. I have tried above to prove that in Exodus 21:2 חפשיshould be inter
preted in light of the source material on the hupšu from the Near Orient.
Hupšu/ חפשיwere a class of clients in the �city-state, supported by the alloca-
tion� of plots for cultivation or by supplies of provisions from the royal stores.
It seems to me clearly relevant to take this understanding of the hupšu/חפשי
� meant in
into consideration when trying to penetrate into what Saul actually
promising the status of a חפשי. Probably there is no question of tax exemption
or the like (a typically modern thought), but rather of an offer to grant supplies
from the royal household. It is well known from 1 Samuel 17:7 that Saul had the
means to support a private guard of mercenaries, and it may be deduced from
this that he also had the means to attract influential families as his clients. In
this particular case, the intention may have been to procure adherents in Judean
circles just as later on David bought himself support from leading Judeans.
Introduction
On several occasions during the last few years the royal edicts known from the
Old Babylonian period have been associated, because of their social tenden-
cies, with the Israelite laws of manumission, land regulation and transactions
etc.1 The Israelite laws are, for the most part, to be found in the legislation
related to the Sabbatical Year in Deuteronomy 15:1‑18, and to the Jubilee Year
in Leviticus 25. According to the Old Testament, these particular years occurred
every seventh or every fiftieth year. In the absence of any proof, however, that
the Babylonian edicts should have been issued at regular intervals, F. R. Kraus
and J. J. Finkelstein are rather unwilling to accept that the Babylonian institu-
tion is parallel to the Israelite one. J. Lewy, on the other hand, goes further and
attempts to prove from the cuneiform literature that the Mesopotamian decree
on the remission of debt, manumission, etc. and the Israelite Jubilee Year leg-
islation had mutual origins in the Amorite population which was spread over a
large part of Mesopotamia, as well as Palestine and Syria. In pre-monarchical
Israel the institution was supposed to recur at regular intervals due to the lack
of governmental authorities, whereas in Mesopotamia the various kings were
free to regulate the dates freely.
M. Weinfeld has recently gone further in his comparisons and tries to show
that the Israelite Sabbath and Jubilee Year institutions survived all through the
period of the Israelite monarchy in the form of royal reform laws, issued at regu-
lar intervals.2 The most important evidence for this is the description in Jeremiah
1. Thus, J. Lewy, ‘The Biblical Institution of derôr in the Light of Akkadian Documents’,
EI 5 (1958), 21–31, 29ff; J. Bottéro, ‘Désordre économique et annullation des dettes en
Mésopotamie à l’époque paléo-babylonienne’, JESHO 4 (1961), 113–64, 164; cf. also,
but with reservations, F. R. Kraus, ‘Ein Edikt des Königs Samsu-Iluna von Babylon’,
Assyriological Studies 16 (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 1965), 225–31,
230–31; and J. J. Finkelstein, ‘Some New Misharum Material and Its Implications’,
Assyriological Studies 16 (1965), 233–46, 245.
2. M. Weinfeld, Deuteronomy and the Deuteronomic School (Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 1972), 152ff. To some extent also the same author’s זרמים תיאולוגיים בספרות התורה,
Beth Miqra 44 (1970), 10–22, 15 and n. 19.
The manumission of slaves 27
In other words, it may be asserted that royal edicts, if such existed in Israel,
were not called מישריםacts, and it is hardly possible to take for granted a direct
Mesopotamian impact upon the use of Hebrew מישריםin the Old Testament. In
fact, the use of מישריםin connection with the Enthronement Feast of Yahweh to
some extent indicates that the connection is indirect and that the special inter-
pretation of the word as related to social reforms has been lost in the same way
as the use of mišarum in Mesopotamia, the technical sense of the word appar-
ently having fallen out of use after the Old Babylonian period.
Although I find it necessary to disagree with Weinfeld’s argument, I admit
that his theory of an Israelite institution corresponding to the Babylonian decrees
of ‘freedom’ and ‘justice’ may be correct. It is obvious from the Old Babylonian
edicts that these were issued primarily in connection with a new king’s accession
to the throne, usually in the second year of his reign7 (and at times later in his
reign).8 Since the intention behind these edicts was to re-establish social balance
(as is apparent from their designations), they cannot be separated from the obli-
gation which bound oriental rulers to protect the lives and welfare of the poor,
an obligation, imposed upon kings by their divine overlord.9 The possibility that
a similar institution had served as the background of hopes attached to the new
king (or his designated successor), which finds expression in several passages
from the Old Testament, cannot be dismissed without further explanation.10
The discussion of the Old Testament Sabbath and Jubilee years should, nev-
ertheless, not rely uncritically on so-called parallels in cuneiform literature. The
results of a closer investigation of the Babylonian material require that one
not unhesitatingly compare Akkadian mišarum of the Old Babylonian era with
Hebrew מישרים, as M. Weinfeld has done, since mišarum was apparently not
used for social edicts after the Old Babylonian period. Consequently, – מישרים
if we try to follow Weinfeld – must have been borrowed from Akkadian long
before the Israelite immigration and survived in this meaning in Palestine alone
for about 1000 years. This is not possible. On the other hand, andurārum, in
Hebrew ( דרורcorresponding to Neo-Assyrian durārum), may have been bor-
rowed at any time in its 1000-year history, bearing the meaning of a social edict
or royal favour. Therefore, to more precisely arrive at the exact time of the bor-
rowing and to obtain a better understanding of the problem of the origin of the
7. See Finkelstein, ‘Some New Misharum Material’, 243ff., and his ‘Ammiùaduqa’s Edict
and the Babylonian “Law Codes”’, JCS 15 (1961), 91–104, 102; see also F. R. Kraus,
Ein Edikt des Königs Ammi-úaduqa von Babylonien (Studia et Documenta ad Iure
Orientis Antiqui Pertinentia; Leiden: E. J. Brill,1958), 224ff.: nos 33 (Hammurabi), 36
�
(Samsuiluna), 38 (Abiešuh), 41 (Ammiditana), 43 and 44 (Ammiùaduqa).
�
8. Cf. to this Finkelstein, Assyriological Studies 16, 243ff.
9. Cf. C. Fensham, ‘Widow, Orphan and the Poor in Ancient Near Eastern Legal and
Wisdom Literature’, JNES 21 (1962), 129–39.
10. Cf. Ps. 72:1ff; Isa. 11:1ff. See also M. Noth, ‘Amt und Berufung im Alten Testament’,
1958, in Gesammelte Studien I, 2nd edn (Munich: Chr. Kaiser, 1960), 309–33, 332 n. 49.
Noth thinks that a royal institution may have formed the background of Isa. 61:1ff.
The manumission of slaves 29
Old Testament Sabbatical and Jubilee Years, one needs first of all to analyse the
Old Testament material.11
The laws
11. Cf. Chapter 3, this volume. The necessary technical information will be found there. The
two principal theses are:
1. Mišarum was not used of social edicts after the Old Babylonian period, whereas
andurārum could be used in this sense from Old Babylonian to Neo-Assyrian times
(the last evidence known perhaps dates to the reign of Assurbanipal.
2. Some references to mišarum (and also to andurārum) later than the Old Babylonian
period should not be understood uncritically as references to royal edicts with more
general consequences. They are perhaps, rather, only referring to acts concerning
individuals.
12. As to Exodus 21:2ff., I would like to refer to Chapter 1, this volume.
13. Cf. Chapter 1, this volume, n. 12.
30 Biblical studies and the failure of history
Deuteronomy 15:1‑18
In Deuteronomy 15:2‑18 we seem to find the same two sections from the Book
of the Covenant joined together in the law of the Sabbatical Year.
Deuteronomy 15:1: מקץ שבע־שנים תעשה שמטה. This does not necessarily
imply that Deuteronomy 15:1 refers to a general observation every seventh
year. The range of the שמטהhas not been stated, and besides it is a question of
whether agrarian conditions are included in the use of שמטהin Deuteronomy at
all. In the ‘commentary’ on Deuteronomy 15:1‑11, there are conditions related
to landed property that have been allowed for. However, it seems that from the
‘commentary’ in vv. 2-3 and also from the added regulations on loans in vv.7ff.,
the Deuteronomists in Deuteronomy 15:1‑11 refer to a שמטהregularly recur-
ring, which is analogous to the annulment of liabilities in a Deuteronomistic
context.17
14. It may be maintained against Noth (Das zweite Buch Mose, Exodus, ATD, 5; Göttingen:
Vandenhoeck and Ruprecht, 1958, 154) that even though the practical importance of the
fallow year for soil fertility is not explicitly mentioned in Exod. 23:10‑11, this may well
be implicitly understood according to the understanding of the period. Cultivation of the
soil and the harvesting of its products have always been subject to religious perceptions
and it is wrong, based on modern farming and its particular working morale, to draw
conclusions regarding farming conditions of the past.
15. In opposition to e.g. Beer and Galling (Exodus, HAT I 3; Tübingen: Mohr, 1939, 119),
who think that Exod. 23:10‑11 prescribes the observance of a generally valid Sabbatical
Year and who argue on the basis of, first, an analogy to v. 12, and, second, a parallel
to Lev. 25:2‑7 and Exod. 23:12, which demand the observance of the weekly Sabbath
is irrelevant, in view of the fact that the two parts, vv. 10‑11 and v. 12, have evidently
been joined together because of the analogy between the seven years in vv. 10‑11 and
the seven days in v. 12. This does imply, however, that it becomes possible to draw
conclusions regarding the actual contents of vv. 10‑11 from v. 12. As regards Lev. 25:2‑7,
this is probably a late and secondary interpretation of Exod. 23:10f. Cf. also Noth’s less
categorical treatment of Exod. 23:10‑11, ATD 5, 153–4.
16. E.g. F. Horst, Das Privilegrecht Jahwes (FRLANT 45; Göttingen: Vandenhoeck and
Ruprecht, 1930), now in Gottes Recht (Munich: Chr. Kaiser, 1961), 17–154, see 80;
see also G. Seitz, Redaktionsgeschichtliche Studien zum Deuteronomium (BWANT 93;
Stuttgart: Kohlhammer, 1971), 167.
17. Even though there is no complete agreement with regard to the details of Deut. 15:1‑11,
it seems a fact that several layers of commentaries and warnings have been added to the
older law, cited in v. 1 on the basis of the שמטהordinance of v. 1. Cf. e.g. Horst, Das
The manumission of slaves 31
Privilegrecht, 79ff., and G. von Rad, Das fünfte Buch Mose. Deuteronomium (ATD,
8; Göttingen: Vandenhoeck and Ruprecht, 1964), 74. See also R. P. Merendino, Das
deuteronomistische Gesetz (BBB, 31; Bonn: Peter Hanstein, 1969), 106ff., and Seitz,
Redaktionsgeschichtliche, 167ff.
18. A. Jepsen, Untersuchungen zum Bundesbuch (BWANT, III 5; Stuttgart: Kohlhammer,
1927), 56.
19. Alt, Kl. Schr. I, 291. See also Chapter 1, this volume.
20. Note the use of ‘ מרצעpricker’, which in the Old Testament is only used in these two
passages. Although the quotation does not follow Exod. 21 word by word, the majority
of the words in Deut. 15:16f. have been taken from the Book of the Covenant.
21. Merendino, Das deuteronomistische Gesetz, 113.
22. The adaptation of Jeremiah 34 apparently has not understood יin חפשיas a gentilic end-
ing. Cf. below.
32 Biblical studies and the failure of history
Leviticus 25
In its present shape, the legislation of the Jubilee Year, Leviticus 25, forms part
of the Holiness Code, Leviticus 17–26. The first half of Leviticus 25 is devoted
to the Sabbatical Year, taken to mean a fallow year with a religious founda-
tion (vv. 1‑7). The second part of Leviticus 25 defines the intention of the spe-
cial Sabbatical Year, which, supposedly every fiftieth year, coincides with the
o rdinary Sabbatical Year recurring every seventh year. This year is described
as ( יובלthe precise meaning of this word has probably been forgotten),25 and
the celebration of it follows upon a declaration of ‘freedom’ ()דרור. The real
intention of the Jubilee Year legislation follows in v. 10b: ושבת איש אל־משפחתו
ואיש אל־אחזתו. All details must be considered in view of this. V. 10bα refers to
the גאלהregulations in the following verses – in particular, vv. 25ff. and v.10bβ
to the slave law in vv. 39ff. Apart from this, the legislation maintains rules for
the observance of the fallow year in the same way as it does for the normal
Sabbatical Year and also for loan activity.
Traditio-historically, Leviticus 25 is far from being a unified whole, but
presents many problems. The most conspicuous difficulty is the date for the
Jubilee Year in v. 11 – namely, every fiftieth year. This coincides with the
Sabbatical Year, which recurs every seventh year. Literally, this suggests that
two Sabbatical Years be observed in a row, a most damaging prescription if
carried out in reality.26 Several solutions have been suggested: one that the
number fifty of v. 11 rounds off forty-nine to fifty.27 Another proposes that the
forty-ninth year is reckoned as the fiftieth because the former Jubilee Year is
included in defining the entire Jubilee period.28 If E. Kutsch was correct in say-
ing that the tenth day of the seventh month was not understood as an ancient
New Year’s date, then the Jubilee Year would stretch from the forty-ninth year
into the fiftieth. This might offer a third explanation for the chronology.29 It is
worth mentioning, though, that if the date of v. 9 may reasonably be understood
as dependent on the introduction of a new calendar shortly before the exile,30 the
fiftieth year in v. 11 cannot be explained with Kutsch. As to the first suggestion,
25. Cf. R. North, Sociology of the Biblical Jubilee (AnBi 4; Rome: Pontificium Institutum
Biblicum, 1954), 96ff.
26. Cf. R. de Vaux, Les institutions de l’Ancien Testament, I (Paris: Les éditions du cerf,
1961), 268.
27. E.g. North, Sociology, 129ff., who makes a comparison to Pentecost πεντεκοστή origi-
nally ‘fifty (day)’, though Deut. 15:9 says ‘seven weeks’, and Lev. 23:16 ‘Seven weeks’
from the day after the Sabbath until the day after the Sabbath = fifty days, but in reality
it is only = forty-nine.
28. A. Jirku, ‘Das israelitische Jubileejahr’ (1929), in Von Jerusalem nach Ugarit (Graz:
Akademische Druck- und Verlagsanstalt, 1966), 320, follows the suggestion made by
Kugler. The number fifty has been reached through the Hebrew practice of counting
both terminus a quo and terminus ad quem. In the case of Lev. 25, this implies that both
old and new Jubilee Years are included in a Jubilee Year period of fifty years; cf. also
K. Elliger, HAT, I 4, 352, and H. Graf Reventlow, Das Heiligkeitsgesetz formgeschich-
tlich untersucht (WMANT 6; Neukirchen: Neukirchener Verlag, 1961), 125.
29. Cf. E. Kutsch, Das Herbstfest in Israel (Masch. Schr. Diss.; Mainz 1955; not avai-
lable), and R. Kilian, Literarkritische und formgeschichtliche Untersuchung des
Heiligkeitsgesetzes (BBB 19; Bonn: Peter Hanstein, 1963), 123–4.
30. See Noth, ATD 6, 162, and Reventlow, Das Heiligkeitsgesetz, 129, who follows J.
Begrich, Die Chronologie der Könige von Israel und Juda (Beiträge z. hist. Theol., 3;
Tübingen: Mohr, 1929), 156ff. Cf. also Zimmerli, ‘Das Gnadenjahr des Herrn’, in Arnulf
Kutschke and Ernst Kutsch (eds) Festschrift für Galling, Kurt: Archäologie und Altes
Testament (Tübingen: Mohr, 1970), 325.
34 Biblical studies and the failure of history
it is a question of whether seven times seven years was not, to the Israelites, in
fact, a round figure, represented as fifty years.
Concerning recent tradition-research dealing with this chapter, there is lit-
tle or no agreement on details. H. Graf Reventlow suggests three originally
independent segments. The first, ending with v. 24, retains two older tradition
units which are opposed to each other: a Sabbatical Year legislation, which
originally offered agrarian ordinances, and a legislation of the Jubilee Year,
which contained regulations for the גאלה. In the last part of Leviticus 25 (vv.
25ff.), Reventlow demonstrates a complex of so-called מוךrules which were
social ordinances for the benefit of the impoverished segment of the population.
These elements were, according to Reventlow, secondarily joined together in
Leviticus 25, and a ‘Prediger’ has added his partly parenetic commentaries.31
R. Kilian assumes at least four stages of tradition. He mentions one redactor
for the archetype, another for the inclusion of the Holiness Code, a third who
is identical with the compiler of the P-source, and a fourth who created the
legislation of the Jubilee Year. Originally there was only the legislation of the
Sabbatical Year, which Kilian thinks can be separated from Leviticus 25 through
literary criticism. Not until late, probably after Nehemiah, was this legislation
on the Sabbatical Year amplified and reinterpreted to accord with the law of the
Jubilee Year. The latter legislation is in itself expressive of a late Utopia.32
The scholar who has gone farthest in the direction of splitting Leviticus 25
into discrete sources is K. Elliger, who traces up to eight stages of tradition in
this chapter.33 Elliger assumes the existence of an older written law dealing
with land transactions, which was converted into the Jubilee Year law no later
than the seventh century bce, partly through the addition of social ordinances to
relieve poverty. An even later redaction has combined the Jubilee Year legisla-
tion with that of the Sabbatical Year and, finally, the laws regarding enslaved
debtors have been added.
The following laws in Leviticus 25 are mentioned in detail:
In this chapter, the Sabbatical Year is understood as a fallow year comprising both
fields and vineyards, but given a religious context. The wording of Leviticus 25
is undoubtedly literarily dependent on the wording of Exodus 23:10. Compare
Leviticus 25:3: שש שנים … תזרע שדך ואספת את תבואתהwith Exodus 23:10: שש שנים
תזרע את ארצך ואספת את תבואתה. The technical use of the root שמט, either verbally
תשמטנה, Exodus 23:11, or as a noun שמטה, Deuteronomy 15:1, has been avoided
in Leviticus 25:2ff. However, the close relationship between Leviticus 25:2ff.
and Exodus 23:10‑11 is obvious for two additional reasons. First, in Leviticus
25:3ff, the vineyards are included from the Sabbatical Year law. They are also
included in the fallow year legislation of Exodus 23:10-11. However, as men-
tioned above, they have been inserted secondarily. There is no economic reason
to include the vineyards in Leviticus 25:3ff. or in Exodus 23:10-11 and eco-
nomic reasons are most likely to have provided the actual background of the
fallow year.34 The inclusion of vineyards in Leviticus 25 also breaks the literary
connection between Leviticus 25:3a and 25:3c (cf. Exod. 23:10!). Second, it is
remarkable that ‘the wild animals of the country’ (Lev. 25:7) are the consum-
ers of the products of the soil during the Sabbatical Year. In vv. 4‑5, mem-
bers of Israelite households, including גריםand domestic animals, receive their
food from the fields, not the poor whom Exodus 23:11 expressly mentions as
those who benefit from the law. The wild animals have been included both in
Leviticus 25:7 חית אשר בארצךand in Exodus 23:11 חית השדה.
Verses 1‑7 emphasize that the Sabbatical Year was generally valid, inasmuch
as v. 2 demands observance of the Sabbath in the ‘country’, ארץ, which expres-
sion can only refer to the whole of the Israelite territory. In contrast, we have
a practical formulation of the law of the Sabbatical Year in v. 3 (4b), which
has שדהabout the fields instead of ארץ. In v. 4a, however, ארץappears once
again, with the meaning ‘the national area’. In comparison, it may be mentioned
that the fallow-year regulation of Exodus 23:10 ארץis not used in regard to
‘the country’, but instead refers to ‘the fields’. This may be taken as proof that
the older fallow year regulation, Leviticus 25:3 (4b), has been interpreted and
generalized by this later adaption. The final commentary in v. 6 also would be
meaningless if not for the fact that, in vv. 2ff., arrangements of general value
were referenced. Sabbatical Year legislation is, finally, accessed and concluded
in vv. 20‑22. This commentary may well be more recent (in traditio-historical
terms); but it firmly establishes the fact that in the fallow year had not actually
been put in practice before the time of the commentator.
With regard to contents, the first part of the Jubilee Year law, vv. 11‑12, corre
sponds to the Sabbatical Year. V. 13 introduces the גאלהinstitution, underlying
the annulment of land purchase, the redemption of lands and manumission. The
rules of vv. 14‑16 and 27‑28, which deal with how the price of land is fixed,
correspond to similar rules for the manumission of enslaved debtors (vv. 50‑52).
In both cases, payment is fixed on the basis of the remaining length of time of
an arrangement within a given Jubilee Year. The main segment, dealing with
גאלה, in relation to landed property, is undoubtedly modelled on older sources,
as it appears from the different ways in which landed property is treated in town
34. It is useless for a vintner to let his vineyard lie fallow every seventh year. It is normal,
today, for a vine to have uninterrupted production for thirty years, after which it is cleared
and new vines, which take five years to reach a reasonable standard of production, are
planted. This applies to vineyards of good quality. Those of lesser quality require a
longer period of development.
36 Biblical studies and the failure of history
and in country (including the unfortified towns). With literary criticism alone,
it cannot be determined whether the גאלהinstitution has always built on Jubilee
Year legislation.
Reventlow has suggested that vv. 25‑54 represent an originally independent
social codex, characterized by the use of the formula אחיך כי־ימוך, vv. 25, 35, 39,
(47). One part of this codex (vv. 35ff.) does not mention the Jubilee Year at all,
which is all the more remarkable as it was supposed that debts were remitted in
accord with the Jubilee Year, particularly insofar as this was analogous to Old
Babylonian mišarum acts. The fact that the Jubilee Year is not mentioned in vv.
35-36 could indicate that a reinterpretation of the original intention of the מוך
laws has led to the incorporation of verses 25‑54 within Jubilee Year legislation.
Assuming that the importance attached to the absence of the Jubilee Year
in vv. 35ff. has been exaggerated, it seems worthwhile to consider whether
reference to the Jubilee Year in the מוךlaws belongs among their principal
components, even though missing in vv. 35ff. If so, a reference to a Jubilee
Year should not be taken as a reference to a Sabbatical Year. In vv. 39ff., we
have legislation relating to slaves who were to be set free at the beginning of
the Jubilee Year. Even though one must keep in mind that an indebted Israelite
was not to be exploited as a slave but treated as a paid worker, – שכירa service
period lasting up to fifty years – could potentially imply lifelong slavery, and
any offer of manumission would accordingly be illusory.35 A fifty-year period
is not, however, emphasized anywhere in the מוךlaws as a fixed Jubilee Year
term, and I suggest that vv. 39‑54 (in which passage, many verses are probably
secondary) be interpreted by analogy with the slave laws of Exodus 21:2ff.
and Deuteronomy 15:12ff., both of which insist that six years of service is suf-
ficient for persons who have been forced to sell themselves because of debt. If
the interpretation of יובלas deriving from the verbal root √ jbl, as suggested by
R. North, is correct,36 the Jubilee Year may be taken to mean the ‘manumission
year’, ‘the year of release’ or the like. In accordance with Exodus 21:2ff. and
Deuteronomy 15:12ff., this was probably identical with the seventh year of
service. It thus becomes possible to suppose that the connection between the
celebration of the Sabbatical Year every seventh year, understanding the Jubilee
Year as a seven-year term, was fixed individually for slaves and for various
cases of land purchase, which has led to a secondary collection of the fallow
year and social laws of Leviticus 25. That the Jubilee Year occurs at intervals
of forty-nine years, in accord with Leviticus 25, may be due to the fact that it
has been interpreted as a countrywide arrangement, and practical and economic
motives inspired the redactor to place the Jubilee Year as the seventh Sabbatical
Year.
35. This has been acknowledged by, e.g., de Vaux, Institutions, I, 327, Noth, ATD 6, 168, and
Kilian, Literarkritische, 129.
36. North, Sociology, 102ff. North also compares this with the Akkadian biltu (from wabālu,
‘to bring’) meaning ‘tribute.’ Biltu is, however, used particularly in regard to duties
imposed on tenants (‘the so-called nāšî bilti’), as well as in regard to yields of the soil,
in general.
The manumission of slaves 37
Whether the law of the Jubilee Year was ever put into practice along the
lines described in Leviticus 25 cannot be decided here. We must first investi
gate whether there are references to this or similar arrangements elsewhere in
the Old Testament.
Practical examples
Jeremiah 21:8‑20
Zedekiah’s law relating to the manumission of Hebrew slaves, Jeremiah 34:8ff.,
is the only example we know from the Old Testament of a royal edict issued
with an apparently social intention. It is generally considered to be a unique
provision aiming at the replenishment of the ranks after the war against the
Babylonian enemy. Alternatively, by manumitting the slaves, the authorities
hoped they would not have to feed them during a possible Babylonian siege.37
No matter what the intention, the royal edict was repealed the moment there was
no longer a danger of siege.
Viewed traditio-historically, the basic elements of Jeremiah 34:8ff. have
been incorporated into the so-called ‘Book of Baruch’; but it is, in general,
acknowledged that the passage has been mutilated in the process.38 The most
conspicuous difficulty is that the quotation from the law referred to in v. 14 does
not correspond to the contents of the royal edict. Zedekiah’s law concerned
all enslaved debtors of Judean birth (v. 9). In v. 14, the question centres on
individual manumission after six years of service. M. David is probably cor-
rect in maintaining that the additions to Jeremiah 34:8ff. and their subsequent
37. B. Duhm, Das Buch Jeremia (KHAT, XI; Tübingen Mohr, 1901), 279ff., and P. Volz.
Prophet Jeremia (KAT, 10; Leipzig and Erlangen, A. Deichert’sche Verlagsbuchhandlung,
1922), 317f., both suggest the last possibility, whereas W. Rudolph, Jeremia (HAT,
I 12, 2nd edn; Tübingen: Mohr, 1958), 203ff., and M. David, ‘The Manumission of
Slaves under Zedekiah’, OTS 5 (1948), 63–79, 63 think that military considerations
were responsible. A. Weiser, Das Buch Jeremia (ATD, 20/21, 5. Aufl.; Göttingen:
Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 1966), 311–12 thinks that the king wanted to do penance to
Yahweh. It is probable that military considerations were the underlying reason for the
proposal. However, I have found no parallels to such manumission in the ancient Near
East. In classical antiquity, it was not an unknown phenomenon; cf., e.g., the fact that the
Spartans released a contingent of Helots in the Peloponesian war, who had been at war
in Thrace under Brasidas. This was, no doubt, the consequence of a previous promise of
manumission (Thucydides, V: 34), similar to what occurred when the Thebans and their
allies threatened to invade Laconia in 371/370bce. (Xenophon, Hellenica, VI: 5.28).
After the battle of Chaironeia in 338bce, Hyperides proposed that the slaves should be
set free and armed against the Macedonians (Hyperides Orationes sex cum ceterarum
fragmentis edidit Christianus Jensen; TB; Leipzig: Teubner, 1917, 118–19). After the
defeat at Cannae, 216bce, the Roman state bought 8000 slaves from private persons and
armed them; but it is not stated whether they were manumitted (Livy, 211: 57.11). I owe
these references to Dr Sten Ebbesen, professor in classical philology at the University of
Copenhagen.
38. Thus Duhm, Das Buch Jeremiah, Weiser, Das Buch Jeremiah, and of Rudolph, Jeremiah,
the C-source.
38 Biblical studies and the failure of history
were unable to refer to precedents, let alone a regular practice, resulting in the
issuance at regular intervals of royal laws with such an intention.
Nehemiah 5:1‑13
In the Old Testament, there is another example of a social reform of more gen-
eral character – namely, Nehemiah 5:1‑13 (from about 445bce).43 Due to com-
plaints from the poorest that in order to buy corn or pay their duties they were
forced to sell their children and property, Nehemiah called for a general amnesty
for enslaved debtors and the annulment of every land mortgage.
Nowhere in Nehemiah 5:1‑13 are older laws referred to as normative in this
matter and nowhere is it implied that this is a description of a recurrent phe-
nomenon. Nevertheless, there are some affinities with the Jubilee Year legisla-
tion. In Leviticus 25:39ff., it is emphasized that it was not permissible to sell
compatriots who had been enslaved because of debt; furthermore, Jews, who
had pledged themselves to people of other nationalities, should be redeemed as
soon as possible.44 In Nehemiah 5:1‑13, transactions of land are cancelled in
cases where debt has been incurred.
I would like to add the following comments. In Leviticus 25, it seems self-
evident that the last part of the chapter consists of an originally independent
codex of so-called מוךrules, which may never have been looked upon as general
amnesties before their incorporation within the legislation on the Sabbatical
Year, but were rather understood as rules relating to individual transactions.
Links between Nehemiah 5:1‑13 and Leviticus 25 all concern such מוךrules;
and, since Nehemiah 5:1‑13 does not refer to set dates for the annulment of all
obligations, the Jubilee Year legislation, as expressed in Leviticus 25, was not
normative in the eyes of Nehemiah’s contemporaries. This does not necessarily
mean that it never existed. Rather, it should be taken as a confirmation of the
hypothesis that Leviticus 25 merely expresses pious theory.45
In either case, the reform mentioned in Nehemiah 5:1‑13 should be arranged
on the same line as Zedekiah’s law – namely, as a singular measure, which was
not repeated, as is in accord with the Old Testament evidence.
43. It is of no consequence whether this ‘reform’ is dated to the time when Nehemiah rebuilt
the walls of Jerusalem, as a majority of modern commentators think, or to the time after
the walls were built, as suggested by L. W. Batten, The Books of Ezra and Nehemiah
(ICC; Edinburgh: T. & T. Clark, 1913), 237, and F. Michaeli, Les livres des Chroniques,
d’Esdras et de Néhémie (CAT, 15 I; Neuchatel: Delachaux & Niestlé, 1967), 327.
44. Apparently this referred to conditions in Palestine after the time of the exile: thus the
majority of commentators. K. Galling, however, thinks that the reference is to condi-
tions in the Babylonian diaspora; Die Bücher der Chronik, Ezra, Nehemia (ATD, 12;
Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 1954), 227.
45. W. Rudolph, Ezra und Nehemia (HAT, I 20; Tübingen: Mohr, 1949), 129, thinks that
Nehemiah does not intentionally refer to Deut. 15 since to him the important issue was
to have a reform carried through immediately. There was no time to wait for the next
Sabbatical Year. Accordingly, it cannot be deduced from Neh. 5:1‑13 that the laws of the
Sabbath Year were out of force. On the other hand, it cannot be maintained, e silentio,
that these laws were in force at the time of Nehemiah.
40 Biblical studies and the failure of history
Conclusion
the social importance attached to the fallow year. Second, there was the ancient
law of habiru slaves in Exodus 21:2‑6. However, none of the passages from
� of the Covenant can be compared directly with the Deuteronomistic
the Book
legislation on the Sabbatical or Jubilee Years in the Holiness Code. This is partly
due to the secondary expansion of the originally strictly limited slave law in
Exodus 21:2‑6 to all indebted slaves of Israelite birth and partly due to Leviticus
25’s regulation that every seventh fallow year involve the cancellation of land
sales forced by debt. Finally, the whole complex of problems involved in the
contracting of debts, as expressed in both Deuteronomy 15 and Leviticus 25,
represents a completely new element in relation to the regulations of the Book
of the Covenant. This does not mean that rules concerning the remission of debt
may not be older than the Deuteronomistic or priestly legislation. The rules of
the remission of debt may well be related to regulations such as the מוךrules in
Leviticus 25:25ff. These may have had a validity of their own before they were
joined together with legislation on the Sabbatical Year and the Jubilee Year,
which the author of Leviticus 25 has taken over, partly from the Book of the
Covenant and partly from the Deuteronomistic Sabbath Year.
The fact that the two parts of Deuteronomy 15 are self-evidently secondarily
linked together, as the contradictory contents of Deuteronomy 15:1‑11 and vv.
12‑18 clearly show, is of decisive importance when one tries to estimate the time
in which the idea arose that the Sabbatical and the Jubilee Years reflected the
time in which ownership of the land was regulated. But if the Sabbatical Year
was a secondary construction for the Deuteronomists, this must also apply to the
legislation of the Jubilee Year in Leviticus 25 given that the generally acknowl-
edged Sabbatical Year every seventh year was invented by the Deuteronomists.
If the historical foundation of the seven-year cycle is allowed to lapse, the fifty-
year cycle of Leviticus 25 also collapses, inasmuch as it is only an amplified
seven-year cycle.
Finally, it appears that the two well-known general amnesties mentioned in
the Old Testament, Jeremiah 34:8‑20 and Nehemiah 5:1‑13, were put into effect
without any reference or allusion to a Sabbatical or a Jubilee Year. Zedekiah’s and
Nehemiah’s laws should be judged as unique phenomena, a standpoint which is
also shared by the majority of Old Testament scholars. One thing may, however,
assist us in tracing the origin of the idea of the Sabbatical and Jubilee Year. The
technical name of Zedekiah’s reform is דרור, which corresponds to the Akkadian
andurārum. As becomes clear from Mesopotamian practice, when governments
issued social edicts, andurārum was the Neo-Assyrian word usually applied.
In several places, even in the Neo-Assyrian period, we find andurārum with-
out the prefix, durārum, which is quite analogous to דרור. I think the corre
spondence between Zedekiah’s law and the Neo-Assyrian edicts means that
Zedekiah was dependent on the Neo-Assyrian practice. This is not surprising in
that, at the time of Zedekiah, Judah had been a vassal to the Assyrians for more
than a century, and to the Chaldeans thereafter. It is to be supposed that various
Assyrian edicts, which may have been intended as favours to the Judeans, were
called (an)durārum decrees or that social reforms were, in accordance with
Mesopotamian traditions, called so in the former Northern Kingdom.
42 Biblical studies and the failure of history
Appendix
of the development of the concept of mišarum. On the one hand, we have the
secondary use referred to by Wildberger,52 where the reference to mišarum
merely suggests, in general, that the king tries to rule ‘justly’. On the other
hand, we have the mišarum acts from the end of the third millennium bce and
down through the first 500 or 600 years of the second millennium, which aim
to diminish abuse. That the origin of the more general use of mišarum (placed
side by side with kittum as an elliptical expression, comprising ‘justice’ in its
totality) is to be looked for in these edicts is clear both from the Lipit-Ištar hymn
quoted by Wildberger53 and, even more clearly, from the documents treated by
Kraus (UM 5, no. 74: v. 11ff.:54
In Nippur stellte ich Gerechtigkeit (níg.si.sá) her, ließ Ehrlichkeit (níg.gi) sich
zeigen. Wie Schäfe … ließ ich sie … Grass fressen. Das schwere Joch nahm
ich von ihren Nacken. Dauernde Wohnung ließ ich sie beziehen. Nachdem
habe ich in Nippur Ehrlichkeit (und) Gerechtigkeit hergestellt das Land
zufriedengestellt.55
Neither this text nor the Lipit-Ištar hymn are expressions of vaticinia ex
eventu, nor are they oracles aimed at the succeeding king. They refer to the
actual introduction of social reforms in the reign of the said king.56 In this con-
nection, the prologue of the Codex Hammurabi (CH), V 14ff. might be included:
� the people and� instruct high principles, I
‘When Marduk ordered me to guide
decided that order and justice be proclaimed in the country. I brought the people
happiness.’57 Likewise, the prologue of the Codex Lipit Ištar (CL): ‘According
to Enlil’s orders I established “social justice” in Sumer and Akkad.’58 The expec-
tations regarding the Davidic descendant in Isaiah 11:1ff. should be understood
on the basis of the reform practice: not so much as a complete parallel, but rather
as a late literary reminiscence of it. In this way, Isaiah 11:1ff. reflects a stage
of development within the framework of Israelite royal ideology which was
in line with the Neo-Babylonian application of the concept of ‘social justice’
(mišarum).
Additional note
Only after I had finished this chapter did I have the opportunity to read N. Sarna’s,
‘Zedekiah’s Emancipation of Slaves and the Sabbatical Year’.59 However, our
conclusions are so divergent that I shall not dwell on it in detail. Sarna thinks
that Zedekiah’s manumission took place in connection with the celebration of
a Sabbatical Year in 599–587bce. He realizes the connection between Jeremiah
34:8ff. and Deuteronomy 15:12ff., but he thinks that Jeremiah 34:8ff. represents
an ancient interpretation of Deuteronomy 15:12ff., evidently stemming from
Jeremiah himself. Sarna may be counted among the scholars who ignore, or at
any rate only superficially touch upon, the literary critical and traditio-historical
difficulties related to the interpretation of the Old Testament laws of manu-
mission, etc. Thus, he takes for granted that the Sabbatical Year cycle was an
ancient institution in Israel, based on the Babylonian material of mišarum (and
andurārum), the meaning of which he has not investigated.
59. In Orient and Occident: Essays Presented to Cyrus H. Gordon (AOAT 22; 1973), 143–9.
3
1. See Chapter 2, this volume. The confinement here to the terms andurārum and mišarum
is explained by the fact that, among the different terms used in connection with the royal
decrees in Mesopotamia, only these two appear as loanwords from Akkadian in the Old
Testament: mišarum as mîšarîm or mîšôr, most pregnantly in Pss. 96:10; 98:9; 99:4,
and Isa. 11:4; andurārum as derôr in Lev. 25:10 (the law of the Jubilee Year); Jer. 34:8
(Zedekiah’s decree of manumission of slaves); Isa. 61:1 (freeing of prisoners); Ezek.
46:17 (regulations of real estate).
46 Biblical studies and the failure of history
Any discussion on the subject of the Mesopotamian royal edicts which were
issued to initiate social reforms must start with the Edict of Ammiùaduqa (1646–
1626bce), which dates from c.1646–1645bce, since this is the most complete
extant example.2 The decree begins with a short introduction: ‘The tablet which
contains the decree imposed upon the country to be heard at the time when
the king established a mišarum for the country.’3 It contains two principal sec-
tions: one concerning public affairs, which occupies the main part of the decree,
§§2–3, 10–19; and another concerning private debts, §4 and §§5–9. The decree
is concluded by a supplement, §§20–22; §§2–4 mention the general provisions;
§2 provides relief from some duties imposed on groups of crown tenants; §3
outlines the regulations for ‘the stock exchanges’ of Babylon (kārum) and for
KAR.H I.A ša ma-tim (literally, the ‘harbours of the country’). These rules are
�
exclusively concerned with duties payable to the royal administration. In §§10–
11 particulars are given for the general provisions of §3, and §§12–19 explain
the precise contents of §2. According to §4, claims of debt against LÚak-ka-
di-i ù LÚa-mu-ur-ri-i, ‘the Akkadians and the Amorites’ (this implies the whole
population), are cancelled.4 In this connection, there appear a series of condi
tions concerning transgressions of this section for which capital punishment is
ordered; §§8–9 state the exceptions to §4 in case of a debt incurred to obtain
a profit or in the course of commercial travel. In the supplement, §§20–22,
§20 orders the freeing of people enslaved because of debt from the towns of
Numhia, Emutbalum, Idamaras, Uruk, Isin, Kisurra and Malgum if the slave in
� is a (former) freeman (DUMU [mār], plus city name). The manumis-
question
sion includes his family; §21, however, says that the manumission is not to be
carried out if the debtor is a (former) ordinary slave (GEMÉ ARAD wi-li-[i]d É
[ša DUMU nu-u]m-hi-a, etc.). The decree of Ammiùaduqa ends with §22. This
� the provincial governors who subject military groups to
final article concerns
corvée in return for payment in kind.
The recurring formula, justifying the measures taken in this decree, is:
‘Because the king has established a mišarum for the country’ (aš-šum šar-rum
2. This document has been published by F. R. Kraus, Ein Edikt des Königs Ammi-úaduqa
von Babylon (SD 5; Leiden: E. J. Brill, 1958), 17–43, the most important copy Ni 632.
The very fragmentary text B (BM 78259) was published by S. Langdon in 1914 and
again in a revised edition by C. J. Gadd, in Symbolae Koschaker (SD 2; Leiden: E. J.
Brill, 1939), 102–5, and most recently by G. R. Driver and J. C. Miles, The Babylonian
Laws, vol 2 (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1955), 320ff. The introduction to the
decree, text C (BM 80209), is published by J. J. Finkelstein, ‘The Edict of Ammiùaduqa:
A New Text’, RA 63 (1969), 45–64. The supplement brought to light by Finkelstein
means that the number of each article according to Kraus’s original publication should
be raised by two.
3. §1: ñup-pí … / ša-mi-am [qá-bi] / i-nu-ma [šar-ru-um mi-ša-ra-am] / a-na ma-tim
iš-[ku-nu], according to the reconstruction by Finkelstein, ‘Edict of Ammiùaduqa’, 47.
4. Ibid., 53 and n. 1.
Andurārum and Mišarum 47
5. See here Kraus, Edikt, 183ff.; see also R. Hentschke, ‘Erwägungen zur israelitischen
Rechtsgeschichte’, Theologia Viatorum 10 (1965–6), 117ff., from an Old Testament
scholar’s point of view. Some of Hentschke’s theses as regards apodictically formulated
provisions versus casuistically formulated in this edict are excluded by the recent publica-
tion of the introduction to the decree. See, however, Finkelstein’s study, ‘Ammiùaduqa’s
Edict and the Babylonian “Law Codes”’, JCS 15 (1961), 91–104, especially 100.
6. For the chiastic arrangement, compare §§2 and 3 to §§10–19; §4 to §§5–9; §2 to §§12–
19; and §3 to §§10–11.
7. Finkelstein, ANET, 3rd edn, 528 n. 9.
8. See Finkelstein, ‘Ammiùaduqa’s Edict and the Babylonian “Law Codes”’, 100.
9. Text C 44f.: ša a-na ùe-em-da-at šar-rum(!) / la uá-ta-ar-ru i-ma-at.
10. Text A v 34f.: an-d[u-ra-a]r-šu / [ša]-ki-[i]n, ‘his freedom has been established’; A vi 8f.:
[an]-du-ra-ar-[š]u / [ú-u]l iš-ša-a[k-k]a-an, ‘his freedom shall not be established’.
11. Text A i 13ff.: aš-šum šar-rum [mi-š]a-ra-am / a-na ma-tim iš-ku-nu / tup-pa-šu he-pí,
�
‘because the king has effectuated a mîshārum for the country, his tablet is smashed’;
C 54: aš-šum ka-ni-ik-šu uá-wa-uá ka-ni-[ik-šu ih-hepé], ‘since he has altered his docu-
� �
ment, his document shall be smashed’.
12. Kraus, ‘Ein Edikt des Königs Samsu-Iluna von Babylon’, Studies in Honour of Benno
Landsberger (AS 16; Chicago, IL: Chicago University Press, 1965), 225–31 (Museum
of Istanbul Si. 507, from Sippar).
48 Biblical studies and the failure of history
obv. 11–17, and the last, rev. 1–7. It is very interesting to note that both articles
correspond almost exactly to stipulations in Ammiùaduqa’s decree: obv. 11–17
to Ammiùaduqa’s §2 and rev. 1–7 to §21. This correspondence applies to the
actual wording as well as to the order of the wording within the decree. The sim-
ilarity also includes the technical terms andurārum and mišarum. Andurārum
is used as an expression for the manumission of slaves (there remains only the
parallel to the negative part of the slave stipulations in Ammiùaduqa’s decree).13
In the parallel to Ammiùaduqa’s edict in §2, we find reference to ‘because the
king has established a mišarum’.14
Mišarum
The two technical terms andurārum and mišarum are extremely important for the
subject of this study. Nonetheless, we may omit consideration of the references
to ùimdat šarrim, which is supposed to have been the designation of the royal
decree itself as an official proclamation,15 though in the Edict of Ammiùaduqa
it is only used in §5. According to M. de J. Ellis, the use of ùimdatum was not,
however, confined to social decrees, but had a wider juridical application, since
ùimdatum could also be understood as a designation for a juridical corpus, as,
for instance, in the Code of Hammurabi.16 Thus, ùimdat šarrim is, indeed, used
in other texts to announce a �king’s implementation of provisions purported to
be of the same social purpose as the Edict of Ammiùaduqa; but examples of the
use of ùimdat šarrim in this specific context are not found later than the end of
the first Babylonian Dynasty at the beginning of the sixteenth century bce. The
decrees, themselves, seem nevertheless to have preferred mišarum to ùimdatum,
presumably because of the social ideology inherent in the word mišarum, which
means ‘justice’ (from the verb ešērum). The Edict of Ammiùaduqa also uses
mišarum several times, and the only example of ùimdatum, in §5, certainly does
not refer to the decree itself, but to some other specific royal decision or general
legal custom authorized by the king.17 In using mišarum, the Amorite kings of
13. Si. 507 obv. 6f.: an-du-ra-ar-šu / ú-ul iš-ša-ka-a[n], compare with the Edict of
Ammiùaduqa A vi 8f. (see note 8 above).
14. Si. 507 obv. 13f.: aš-šum LUGAL mi-[ša-ra-am] / iš-ku-nu. This formula is not used in
the Edict of Ammiùaduqa §2, which speaks against the proposal made by Hentschke,
Theologia Viatorum 10, 120, to see a special connection between the use of mišaram
šakānum and the articles in the apodictic style of the decree of Ammiùaduqa (§§3, 4,
12, 15, 16, 19, and 20). On the other hand, it is possible to argue so far as it can be read
from the decree itself that it was necessary for the validity of the decree that the mišaram
šakānum formula be used once in connection with each provision, whether in the general
part or in the more detailed description of its contents following later in the edict.
15. For literature to ùimdatum, see: CAD 17, S, 194ff.; B. Landsberger, Symbolae Koschaker
(SD, 2; Leiden: E. J. Brill, 1938), 219–34 and recently M. de J. Ellis, ‘úimdatu in the Old
Babylonian Sources’, JCS 24 (1972), 74–82.
16. Ellis, ‘úimdatu’, 82.
17. Ibid, 78. Ellis mentions that it may have been either a written or an unwritten rule.
Andurārum and Mišarum 49
Babylon established connections dating back via the traditions from Isin, where
an Amorite dynasty had ruled between 2000 and 1800bce, to the Third Dynasty
of Ur (Sumerian), c.2100–2000bce.18
The particular use of the Sumerian term níg.si.sá, which is equivalent to
Akkadian mišarum, used to express the promulgation of royal reforms, is first
found in sources concerning Ur-nammu of the Third Dynasty of Ur (2113–2096
bce). Lipit-Ištar of Isin (1934–1924bce) adopted this usage.19 Apart from the doc-
uments of Lipit-Ištar, other references are known dating from the period of the
Dynasty of Isin, which apply to similar occasions (e.g. a year date from the reign
of Irra-Imitti, 1869–1862bce).20 In Babylon, the kings Sumulael, Hammurabi,
� for their
Samsuiluna and Ammiùaduqa made use of mišarum as a designation
acts of reform. At Ešnunna, in the eighteenth century, mišarum was also used.21
Other examples come from the Kingdom of H ana, with its administrative cen-
tre at Terqa, the former provincial capital of� the Kingdom of Mari. This evi-
dence dates from the end of the Old Babylonian period.22 Thereafter we have
no evidence of mišarum used in the special sense of royal decree, but only in
a general one, ‘justice’ or ‘equity’, without reference to a specific occasion.
The only exception could have been a Neo-Babylonian dating from the reign
of Neriglassar (559–555bce), the fourth king of the Chaldean dynasty: mi-ša-ri
i-na ma-tim aš-ta-ak-ka-an / ni-ši-ia ra-ap-ša-a-tim i-na šu-ul-mi ar-ta-né-e’-e:
‘I permanently established mišarum for the country (and) I let graze perma-
nently in peace my far-extended people.’23 This reference to a mišarum act is
unique in the Neo-Babylonian period, and it is hardly more than an expression
of the ‘renaissance’ tendencies which played a prominent part at the time in the
18. Apparently mišarum was not used as a technical term by the Amorite dynasty of Larsa,
c.2025–1760bce.
19. Ur-Nammu: see H. de Genouillac, Textes religieux sumériens du Louvre (TCL, vol 15;
Paris: P. Geuthner, 1930), no 12, l.38 (pl. 35), ed. and trans. by G. Castellino, ‘Urnammu:
Three Religious Texts’, ZA 53 (1959), 106–32; see especially 119 and 122. Refer also
to the Codex Ur-Nammu; see S. N. Kramer, ‘Ur-Nammu Law Code’, Orientalia n.s. 23
(1954), 40–51, II. 112–13: [níg.si].sá … mu.ni.gar. Lipit-Ishtar: see Kraus, Edikt, 198
n. 4: mu dli-pí-it-ištar lugal.e níg.si.sá ki.en.gi ki.uri.a mu.ni.in.gar, ‘the year in which
the king Lipit-Ištar established equality (níg.si.sá) in Sumer and Akkad’. Refer to Kraus,
Edikt, 198, for other examples from the reign of Lipit-Ištar.
20. Kraus, Edikt, 200 n. 7. Kraus mentions another reference to mišarum / níg.si.sá from
Isin; see Ibid, 201 n. 9. He has published this in ‘Nippur und Isin nach altbabylonischen
Rechtsurkunden’, JCS 3 (1951), 30f. Unfortunately, it is not possible to decide precisely
who the king responsible for this document was.
21. Kraus, Edikt, 230ff., nos. 49, 50 and 52.
22. Ibid, 232f. The kings of Hana were contemporaries of Hammurabi of Babylon. See, in
� �
reference to Hana, J. R. Kupper in CAH, 3rd edn, vol 2, pt 1 (Cambridge: Cambridge
�
University Press, 1973), 29ff.
23. For text, see C. J. Gadd, Cuneiform Texts, vol. 36 (London, 1921), pl. 19, col. ii: 2, trans.
by S. Langdon, Die neubabylonischen Königsinschriften (VAB, vol 4; Leipzig: J. C.
Hinrichs, 1912), 216; see also C. Bezold, in E. Schraeder (ed.) Historische Texte des
neubabylonischen Reiches (KB, 3/2; Berlin: Reuther, 1892), 78f.
50 Biblical studies and the failure of history
whole Near East. Therefore this is not a reference to an actual reform, but is
a literary cliché taken over from earlier royal inscriptions as is the case of the
greater part of this document of Neriglissar. In addition, the Gtn verbal form
used in the section of the inscription cited also points to the same interpretation
of this document.
From the Middle Babylonian Period, the kings might title themselves šar
mišarim, ‘king of justice’, in the same manner Hammurabi had earlier.24 A king
could also designate himself ‘the one who loves �justice’.25 Moreover, they might
say that mišarum prevails in the country and periods might be called šanat
mišarim, ‘year of justice’, etc.26 In the documents from Alalah , we find a ‘month
of justice’, arah mišari, which could perhaps be understood� as a reference to
the issuance of �a mišarum act; but, of course, this example is rather ambiguous
since it does not furnish further information.27
Andurārum
28. The most important older inventory of the evidence is E. F. Weidner, ‘Ilushumas Zug
nach Babylonien’, ZA 43 (1936), 114–23. Now it is better to refer to CAD, A/2, 115ff.,
though I am not quite satisfied with the description of andurārum. I think it is too simpli-
fied. In this connection I should like to draw attention to M. T. Larsen, The Old Assyrian
City-State and Its Colonies (Mesopotamia, vol. 4; Copenhagen: Akademisk Forlag,
1976), 63–80.
29. J. Lewy, ‘The Biblical Institution of Derôr in the Light of Akkadian Documents’, Eretz
Israel 5 (1958), 21, with references.
30. For text, see E. Sollberger, Corpus des inscriptions ‘royales’ présargoniques de Lagash
(Geneva: E. Droz, 1956), 48ff., edited and translated by Lambert, ‘Les ‘réformes’ d’Uru
kagina’, RA 50 (1956), 169–84; see esp. cone B+C, 183. German translation by J. Klíma,
‘Urukagina, der große Reformer in mesopotamischen Frühgeschichte’, Das Altertum 3
(1957), 72ff.
31. In addition to the titles mentioned in the previous note, we may refer to the reply by I.
M. Diakonoff. to Lambert in ‘Some Remarks on the “Reforms” of Urukagina’, RA 52
(1958), 1–15. See also C. J. Gadd in CAH, 3rd edn, vol. 1, pt. 2 (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1971), 140ff.
32. Transcription and translation by Lambert, ‘Les “reformes”’, 182f. (cone A).
52 Biblical studies and the failure of history
33. See Lambert, ‘L’Expansion de Lagash au temps d’Entéména’, RSO 47 (1972), 1–22. A
preliminary study of the text was given by the same author in ‘Une inscription nouvelle
d’Entéména prince de Lagash’, Revue de Louvre 21 (1971), 231–6; iii 10–iv 5: technical
term: ama.gi4 (lagaški) e.gar.
34. See Falkenstein’s translation, Die neusumerischen Gerichtsurkunden (Bayerische
Akademie der Wissenschaften. Philosophisch-historische Klasse. Abhandlungen. Neue
Folge Heft), 39, 40 and 44. Veröffentlichungen der Kommission zur Erschließung
von Keilschrifttexten, Serie A/2. Stück, 1–3 Teil; Munich: Bayrische Akademie der
Wissenschaften, 1956–7), vol 3, 91: ‘Der zur Mutter zurückkehren’; ama.ar.gi4 =
andurārum; see CAD, A/2, 115.
35. ama.gi4 še.har.ka e.gar; see Lambert, ‘L’Expansion de Lagash’, 6.
�
36. See esp. Falkenstein, Neusumerischem Gerichtsurkunden, vol. 1, 92ff. In this con-
nection, it is important to distinguish between the terms ama.ar.gi4 and šu.bar during
the Ur III period; ama.ar.gi4 seems to be a specialized term for particular occasions of
manumission (from slavery because of debt?), whereas shu.bar (literally ‘to open the
hand’) is a common word for release and manumission in general. The use of shu.bar
is not confined to human beings but includes domestic animals as well as objects. See
examples cited by Sollberger, The Business and Administrative Correspondence under
the Kings of Ur (TCS, vol 1; Locust Valley, NY: J. J. Augustin, 1966); see glossary, 104,
s.v. šu.ba(r).
37. See below referring to the Code of Hammurabi §§117, 171, and 280. The fragments of
�
the Ur-Nammu Code were edited by O. R. Gurney and S. N. Kramer in ‘Two Fragments
of Sumerian Laws’ (AS 16; Chicago, IL, University of Chicago Press, 1965), 13–19; see
esp. 13, §1.
Andurārum and Mišarum 53
of Ur, the sons and daughters of [I]sin, the [so]ns and daughters of [Sum]er
(and) Akkad upon whom … slaveship … had been imposed ( … nam.arad
[hu.m]u.ni.íb.aka).’38
�
In this case, the direct connection between the use of ama.ar.gi4 and the men-
tion of slavery (nam.arad) is still retained, but the word ‘slavery’ is perhaps not
meant literally.39 This means that the prologue to the Code of Lipit-Ištar repre-
sents a stage between the use of ama.ar.gi4 as a designation for manumission
and the general sense of a decree, issued to render assistance to the poorer part
of the population.
Turning from the Sumerian term ama.ar.gi4 to the Akkadian equivalent,
andurārum, we see that the proper connection between andurārum and manu-
mission is still present in the Hammurabi Code (§§117, 171, 280) and in the
�
Edicts of Samsuiluna and Ammi-úaduqa. In the last case, at any rate, andurāram
šakānum only concerns §§20–21 and is not used in a general sense as a designa-
tion for this social decree. However, one example is known and dates from the
reign of Samsuiluna, where andurārum is used rather generally of the promul-
gation of a royal decree in a date formula from year two: ‘The year in which he
established freedom for Sumer and Akkad.’40
On the other hand, Kraus’s no. 47 does fall outside the use of andurārum
hitherto mentioned, since it designates here a local introduction of exemptions
from taxes imposed upon the fruit of date palms. Unfortunately, it is not possible
to date this document more precisely than the first Babylonian Dynasty.41 We
may also include the so-called andurārum established by the king of Assyria,
Ilušuma (c.1930bce), as a favour to the Akkadians42 and the decree of Irišum
I (c.1906–1867bce), concerning an andurārum applying to silver, gold, cop-
per, tin, etc.43 Among the documents from Mari, one example is known which
38. Thus, Kramer’s translation in ANET 3, 159; the Lipit-Ishtar Code, iii 56–70.
39. See further, É. Szlechter, ‘Le Code de Lipit-Ishtar (II)’, RA 51 (1957), 177–96, especially
178.
40. Kraus, Edikt, 227, no. 36, mu … ama.ar.gi4 ki.en.gi ki.uri in.ni.gar.ra.
41. Ibid., 230, no. 47; for text, see G. Dossin, Lettres de la première dynastie babylonienne
(TCL 17; Paris, 1933), no. 14, translated by E. Ebeling, Altbabylonische Briefe der
Louvre-Sammlung aus Larsa (MAOG, vol. 15, no. 1/2; Leipzig: Harrassowitz, 1942, 16;
(AO 6322), an-du-ra-ar ZÚ.LUM i-na KA.KA.SI.KI-ma / ša-ki-in i-na KÁ.DINGIR.
RA.KI / ú-ul ša-ki-in, ‘freedom for dates is established in KA.KA.SIki, but not estab-
lished in Babylon.’
42. See Weidner, ‘Ilushumas Zug’, pl. 7 (on 120), transcription, 115:49ff. and Kraus, Edikt,
233, no 58, a-du-ra-ar / a-ga-ti / ù ma-ri-šu-nu / aš-ku-un. M. T. Larsen, Old Assyrian
City-State, 78ff., most convincingly refutes the idea of seeing any reference to a ‘politi-
cal’ liberation in Ilushuma’s text (i.e. that Ilushuma conquered Babylonia). Ilushuma
allows the Akkadians to trade freely in Assur.
43. Kraus, Edikt, 233, no. 59; see O. Schroeder, Keilschriftexte aus Assur historisches
Inhalts, vol. 2 (WVDOG, vol. 37; Leipzig: Hinrichs, 1922), no. 11, ed. and trans. by
Ebeling, B. Meissner and Weidner, Die Inschriften der altassyrischen Könige (AOB,
vol. 1; Leipzig: Quelle and Meyer, 1926), 12, no. 7:20–25.
54 Biblical studies and the failure of history
48. In regard to the evidence from Nuzi/Arrapkha, see Müller, I. H. Klengel (ed.) Beiträge zur
sozialen Struktur des alten Vorderasien: Schriften zur Geschichte und Kultur des alten
Orients, vol. 1 (Berlin: Akademie Verlag, 1971), 53–60. I have had no access to Müller’s
unpublished dissertation, Die Erlässe und Instruktionen aus dem Lande Arrapkha
(Leipzig, 1968). See also, referring to šūdūtum = ‘proclamation’, E. R. Lacheman,
‘The Word šudutu in the Nuzi Tablets’, in Trudy dvadzata pjatogo Mezdunarodnogo
Kongressa Vostokovedov, vol. 1 (Moscow, 1962), 233–8.
49. R. H. Pfeiffer, The Archive of Shilwateshub Son of the Kings (HSS, vol 9; Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press, 1932), no. 102:30ff., tup-pu i-na EGIR.KI šu-du-ti / i-na
EGIR.KI an-du-ra-ri / i-na URU Nu-zi ša10-ti-ir.
50. The normal formula: ñup-pu i-na EGIR.KI šu-dû-ti (eš-ši) … ša10-ti-ir, ‘the tablet has
been written down after the (new) šūdūtum’.
51. E. Chiera, Texts of Varied Contents, Excavations at Nuzi (HSS vol 5; Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press, 1929), no 25:23ff., … ñuppu / ina EGIR an-du-ra-ri / i-na
ba-ab a-bu-ul-li / ša URU ma-ti-ha ša10-tir.
�
52. Müller, Beiträge zur sozialen Struktur, 58.
53. SMN 2684:47ff.: tup-pí arki šu-du-ti eš-ši ki-i-me qí-bi-i-ti ša šar-ri … a-na âli Nu-zi
ki
at this point that the establishment of a šūdūtum at Nuzi depended on the Old
Babylonian decrees.54
Two documents from Nuzi mention the setting free of persons kept as pledg-
es.55 Perhaps these cases concern slaves (of debt?) manumitted according to
the execution of an andurārum/ šūdūtum act.56 On the other hand, it is cer-
tainly not impossible that they owe their new state of ‘freedom’ to a separate
manumission.57
In Western Asia, evidence for andurārum appears in the documents from
the second millennium, but so far only at Alalah and there, exclusively in the
� ), which chronologically cor-
documents from level VII (eighteenth century bce
responds to the Old Babylonian period in Mesopotamia. Yet, in these cases,
no proof has been found that they were more than separate manumissions.
Therefore, they cannot be explained as evidence for the promulgation of social
decrees of a more general character.58
As far as the last mentioned two references to andurārum/ šūdūtum at Nuzi
and the evidence from Alalah are concerned, it is not certain that manumission
originates in the issuance of �a royal decree of general validity on analogy with
54. R. H. Pfeiffer and E. A. Speiser, One Hundred New Selected Nuzi Texts (AASOR, vol.
16; New Haven, CT: American Schools of Oriental Research under the Jane Dows
Nies Publication Fund, 1936), no 51. The document opens thus: ša-du-du an-nu-ú ša
awelutiMEŠ warad ékallimlim, ‘this is the decree concerning the slaves of the palace’. The
other documents to which Müller has drawn attention in this connection are Lacheman,
Miscellaneous Texts from Nuzi, vol. 2 (HSS, vol. 14; Cambridge MA: Harvard University
Press, 1950), no. 9, and Chiera, Joint Expedition with the Iraq Museum at Nuzi, vol. 2
(Paris: Paul Geuthner, 1930), no. 195. See also A. Saarisalo, New Kirkuk Documents
Relating to Slaves (StOr Fennicae, 5/3; Helsingfors: Societas Orientalis Fennica, 1934),
49.
55. Lacheman, Economic and Social Documents (HSS, 16; Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press, 1958), no. 354:7 and Pfeiffer and Lacheman, Miscellaneous Texts from
Nuzi, vol. 1 (HSS, 13; Cambridge, MA; Harvard University Press, 1942), 149:34f. The
first one runs: (names) 5 SAL.MEŠ an-nu-tu4 i-na an-du-ra-ri i-te-lu (names) 8 SAL.
MEŠ an-nu-tu4 mi-du-ú, ‘these five women have been taken away because of a liberation
…; these eight women have died’. The other: i-na-an-na SAL i-na in(!)-du-ra-ri i-te-
e-li(!) ù ša-a-na-am-ma SAL.MEŠ mqa-i-te i-ri-iš-mi, ‘now the woman has been taken
away because of a liberation, and Qaite claims other women’.
56. Thus CAD, A/2, 116.
57. Müller and B. K. Ismail, ‘Einige bemerkenswerte Urkunden aus Tell al-Fakhkhâr zur
altmesopotamischen Rechts-, Sozial- und Wirtschaftsgeschichte’, WO 9 (1977), 14–34.
They edit two new documents with references to šûdûtum. Both documents were exca-
vated at Tell al-Fakhkhar and belong to the same period and cultural environment as
the Nuzi evidence. The first (IM 70872; ibid, 15f.) concerns the redeeming of a former
freeman, now a slave, and the second (IM 70825; ibid, 26f.) deals with a case of a
pledge. Both documents refer to the fact that the documents were written after the
šūdūtum. Neither document, however, elucidates the actual form of the šūdūtum act and
its implications.
58. See Alalakh Tablets 65:6f., … i-na an-da-ra-ri-im / ú-ul i-na-an-da-ar see also CAD,
D, 109, and refer also to AT 29:9ff., KU.BABBAR ú-ul / us-sa-ab / ú-ul it-ta-ra-ar, and
nos 30:9; 31:9; 38:10; 42:6.
Andurārum and Mišarum 57
Ammiùaduqa’s decree. I referred above to the fact that andurārum in the Old
Babylonian period could be used of individual manumission. It is applied in just
this manner, for instance, in the Hammurabi Code §117: ‘If a claim has “caught”
� son, and daughter or has been handed over to
a man, (and) he has sold his wife,
slavery, they shall serve for three years in the house of their purchaser or their
creditor, (but) in the fourth year their freedom shall be established.’59 Other
examples are known which have their origins in the Old Babylonian administra-
tion of justice: ‘Nin-šubur-tâjar is Apil-ilišu’s slave. Before Šamaš he set him
free.’60 In this case, as in some others, we find the contribution of the Sumerian
usage of ama.ar.gi4 (i.e. individual manumissions). From the Old Babylonian
period, another example is worth mentioning: ‘Ištar-rîti … is a slave of Wedum-
libur and Nin-utu-mu, his wife. Wedum-libur, her master, and Nin-utu-mu, her
mistress, set her free.’61
In this study, we must attach more importance to the fact that andurārum
was also used as a term describing royal decrees later than Old Babylonian
times.62 Thus, the Kassite King Kurigalzu II (c.1345–1324bce) prides himself
on the title, ‘the one who established andurārum for the inhabitants of Babylon’,
though this may only be a literary cliché.63 In Neo-Assyrian times both Sargon
(II) and Esarhaddon boast of their promulgation of andurārum in favour of some
parts of their empire. For instance, Sargon in his great ‘ornamental inscription’
asserts: ‘I established freedom for Ur, Uruk, Eridu, Larsa, Kullab, Kisik (and)
Nimidlaguda, and their stolen deities I returned to their place.’64 More than once
Esarhaddon mentions andurārum acts:
59. Col. iii: 54‑67. See also in the same sense §§171 and 280.
60. (From Nippur) mdNIN.ŠUBUR-ta-a-ar / ÍR ma-pil-ì-lí-šu / i-na ma-kha-ar dUTU a-du-
ra-ar-šu iš-ku-nu; C. F. Keiser and J. B. Nies, Historical, Religious and Economic
Texts and Antiquities (BIN, vol. 2; New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1920), no.
76:4. The text has been translated in P. Koschaker and Ungnad, Hammurabi’s Gesetz, 6
(Leipzig: E. Pfeiffer, 1923), no. 1428.
61. mišdar-ri-i-ti … / gemé we-du-um-li-gar (!) / ù nin.dutu.mu nin.a.ni / mwe-du-um-li-bur
lugal.a.ni ù nin-ditu.mu nin.a.ni / ama.ar.gi4 .a.ni / in.gar.re.eš, published in M. Çig, H.
Kizilyay, and F. R. Kraus, Altbabylonische Rechtsurkunden aus Nippur (Istanbul: Milli
E�itim Basimevi, 1952), no. 7; see also as the first V. Scheil, ‘Notules’, RA 14 (1917),
139–63, here 151, no. 30. The document has been translated in Koschaker and Ungnad,
Hammurabi’s Gesetz, 6, no. 1427.
62. See esp. Weidner, ‘Ilushumas Zug’, 120ff., with references, and Lewy, ‘Biblical Instit
ution of Derôr’, 30ff.
63. See A. Boissier, ‘Document cassite’, RA 29 (1932): 96, obv. 13, ša-ki-in an-du-ra-ar ni-ši
KÁ.DINGIR.RA.KI.
64. For text, see H. Winckler, Die Keilschrifttexte Sargons, vol. 2 (Leipzig: E. Pfeiffer,
1889), pl. 35, no. 74: 136f., … pa-nu-uš-šú-un ša ŠEŠ.UNUG.KI UNUG.KI NUN.KI /
UD.UNUG.KI KUL.UNUG.KI ki-sikKI URUni-mid-dla-gu-da áš-ku-na an-du-ra-ar-šú-un
ù DINGIR.MEŠ-šú-nu šal-lu-ti a-na ma-ha-zi-šú-nu ú-tir-ma, translated in E. Schrader,
�
Sammlung von assyrischen und babylonischen Texten (KB, vol 2; Berlin, 1890), 72, and
in Luckenbill, Ancient Records of Assyria and Babylonia (Chicago, IL: University of
Chicago Press, 1927), 35, §69.
58 Biblical studies and the failure of history
To improve the position of their šubaru much more than before I had in mind
and was my intention. Their tablets of freedom I wrote once more. More than
before, I made them great, important, exalted, and glorified. From the duties
on grain, on tenancy, on exploits, on the quay, and the passage in my country
I freed them, and I established their freedom.65
Compare:
Again I established freedom for the subdued Babylonians, for the privileged
persons (and) for the released ones of Anum and Enlil. People that have been
sold, who found themselves as slaves who were distributed among the foreign
riffraff I gathered together, I looked upon the as Babylonians, (and) their sto-
len belongings I caused to be returned.66
65. See R. Borger, Die Inschriften Asarhaddons Königs von Assyrien (AfO, Beih. 9; Graz:
Im Selbstverlage des Herausgebers, 1956), 3, II:42ff. (III:12f: … an-du-ra-ar-šú-nu /
a-áš-kun); see also J. N. Postgate, Taxation and Conscription in the Assyrian Empire
(Studia Pohl, Ser. Maior, 3; Rome: Pontificium Institutum Biblicum, 1974), 132, §1.4.1.
66. Thus, Borger, Inscriften Asarhaddons, 25, episode 37:12ff. = VII: 12‑25 (ll. 16‑17:
an-du-ra-ar-šú-nu / eš-šiš a-áš-kun); see also Ibid, 94, ll. 34f. (Sammeltext): ‘[The
Babylonians] … I gathered together / … [to the naked (thus Borger)] I gave clothes
[and] I established their andurārum’: … ki-i iš-ten ú-pa-hir-ma / […u]-lab-biš an-du-
�
ra-ar-šú-nu áš-kun ….
67. R. F. Harper, Assyrian and Babylonian Letters, vol. 7 (London: Luzac, 1902), no. 702,
obv. 9f., from Zakir to Assurbanipal, c.650bce, URU he-pu-ú / [ … ] a-na-ku ul-te-šib u
�
du-ra-aár-šú al-ta-kan. The letter has been transcribed and translated in L. Waterman,
Royal Correspondence of the Assyrian Empire, vol. 1 (Ann Arbor, MI: University of
Michigan Press, 1930), 480f. Weidner, ‘Ilushumas Zug’, 122, dates this document to the
reign of Esarhaddon.
Andurārum and Mišarum 59
Conclusion
Besides mišarum and andurārum, several other terms occur which can be
summed up by the conception ‘royal grant of favour’.70 I have chosen to disre-
gard this evidence here, since it does not illuminate the connection between the
Old Babylonian edicts and the biblical laws of the Jubilee and Sabbath Year.
On the other hand, it is very important, when establishing relations between
the biblical evidence and the documents from Western Asia and Mesopotamia,
that only mišarum and andurārum are used as loanwords in Hebrew. This much
we may conclude: mišarum was not accepted as a term for the royal social edicts
later than the fall of the First Babylonian Dynasty, whereas the earliest evi-
dence for andurārum with this meaning presumably dates back to Samsuiluna,
c.1700bce, and the last known occurrence belongs, it seems, to the reign of
Assurbanipal, c.650bce. Since Hebrew mîšarîm is evidently a loanword from
Akkadian, this borrowing must have taken place several hundred years before
the Israelite immigration into Palestine, if it is to be understood as a desig-
nation of royal edicts in Palestine comparable to, for example, the Edict of
Ammiùaduqa. I think it is not worth the effort, however, to insist on this. It is
another matter with andurārum since this word has developed differently as
a designation for royal decrees. The evidence from Nuzi includes the latest
occurrences from the second millennium of andurārum, no doubt referring to
a form of royal decree, the contents of which were to some extent comparable
to the mišarum acts. Thereafter, there is no evidence which conclusively points
to a continuation of a similar practice before the Neo-Assyrian Empire. When
Sargon, Esarhaddon or Assurbanipal, during the later history of this empire,
mention andurārum decrees or decrees including andurārum provisions, they
68. See Postgate, The Governor’s Palace Archive (London: British School of Archaeology
in Iraq, 1973), 230f., no. 248 (ND 487/BM 13001) rev. 13á–16á (in Postgate’s tran-
scription): šúm-mu U[N].MEŠ ša-tu-nu ina du-ra-ri ú-su-ú / mEN.URU kás-pu a-na
EN.MEŠ-šú / ú-ta-a-ra. See also the broken text, cited in ibid., 38, no. 10 (ND 243/IM
56826), obv. 8áff., [šum-m]u LUGAL (!) an-dura-ru / [i]-ša-kan mla-mar-ia-a-nu … (rest
more or less broken).
69. šum-ma du-ra-ru šá-kin ms[i-lim-Aššur] / KU.BABBAR-šú i-da-gal; see C. H. W. Johns,
Assyrian Deeds and Documents, vol 1 (London: George Bell and Sons, 1898), no.
629, rev. 13f., translated in Kohler and Ungnad, Assyrische Rechtsurkunden (Leipzig:
E. Pfeiffer, 1913), no. 146; this document goes back to the reign of Esarhaddon
(c.680bce).
70. Here we may include zakûtum; see Kraus, in Symbolae M. David, 2 (Leiden: E. J. Brill,
1968), 9–40; šubarum, see Böhl, Der babylonische Fürstenspiegel (MAOG, 11, pt. 3;
Leipzig, 1937), 18; and see the note above concerning Sumerian šu.bar during the Ur III
period; awāt šarrim, uššurum, šuddunum, šasūm, see Kraus, Edikt, esp. 45ff. and passim.
60 Biblical studies and the failure of history
may have deliberately chosen to use the old term andurārum – perhaps only as
an expression of the ‘renaissance’ during the seventh and sixth centuries bce.
Turning to the Old Testament evidence, Hebrew derôr is likely to be a loan-
word from Akkadian, since no independent West Semitic tradition of andurārum
can be traced and the only examples date from Alalah, from the eighteenth cen-
tury bce. The borrowing may have taken place in the� course of the first half of
the second millennium bce or in the seventh or sixth century bce. It is, however,
methodologically improper to date the borrowing according to the oldest evi
dence alone, as J. Lewy does. Seemingly, this scholar confuses the principles
of the terminus a quo with the terminus ante quem. The conclusive argument
in this case must be the terminus ante quem, which, according to the evidence
currently available, is 650bce.
The investigation of the evidence of the Old Testament makes it rather dif-
ficult to imagine that the laws of the Sabbatical Year and the Jubilee Year rely
on an early institution in Israel and Palestine. Everything points to the fact that
these laws depend on social theory which originated late in Israel, but which
also had its background in such very old laws as Exodus 21:2‑6 and 23:10‑11.71
The technical term for the Jubilee Year, derôr, is borrowed from Akkadian in the
Neo-Assyrian period (which may also be the correct explanation of the missing
prefix an- in the Hebrew word). The Edict of Zedekiah bears evidence to this
fact (Jer. 34:8). This is not exceptional, since the Assyrians used andurārum
(durārum) as a designation for royal decrees at the same time as the kingdom of
Judah was a vassal of Assyria, and it was only a few years after the termination
of this period of vassalage that Zedekiah established his derôr.
Thus, it is wrong in a study of the Babylonian decrees to refer uncritically to
the so-called parallels in the Old Testament. Positively, we can only stress the
ideological resemblance between the Babylonian social decrees and social laws
in the Old Testament. Here we touch on a common characteristic of the ancient
Near Eastern view of the duties of kings.
71. See Chapter 2, this volume; and for the details of Exod. 21:2‑6, see Chapter 1, this
volume.
4
world, drawn on by Martin Noth.11 In this section, I shall try to give a short sum-
mary of what may be said about the Greek amphictyonies as far as it may be of
interest to Old Testament scholarship. I do not, however, claim to be exhaustive.
Αμφικτυονία is an often used designation for the sacral leagues between the
Greek states, and differs in its basic structure and purposes from other politi-
cal alliances, termed συμπολιτεία and συμμαχία. According to J. A. O. Larsen,
συμπολιτεία refers to a federal state built up on nominally independent city
states, and this political system has evolved from a more primitive and more
loosely organized tribal state.12 It is characteristic of a federation that all its
members belong to one of the Greek tribes.13 συμμαχία is, as the designation
indicates, an alliance of city states for military purposes. Alliances of such a kind
were very often agreed upon for longer periods. As examples of symmachies,
the Peloponnesian, Delian League and Second Athenian Leagues might be men-
tioned, as well as the Hellenic League created by Philip II of Macedonia.14
Αμφικτυονία was used for the first time by Demosthenes (fourth century
bce) and, on that occasion, was used as a nomen proprius for the sacral league,
which had as its centre the shrine of Apollo at Delphi.15 The designation for the
individual members, α᾽ μφικτύονες, was, however, used already by Herodotus
and Pindar (fifth century bce). Herodotus always uses this word to designate a
11. The literature concerning the amphictyonies in Greece is mostly confined to the stud-
ies used by Noth: G. Cauer, ‘Amphiktyonia’, in Pauly-Wissowa, Realencyclopädie
der classischen Altertumswissenschaft, I, 2 (Stuttgart: J. B. Metzler, 1894), 1904–35,
and G. Busolt, Griechische Staatskunde, 2, 3rd edn (ed. by H. Swoboda, Handbuch
zum Altertumswissenschaft, IV:i:1 (Munich: Beck, 1926), 1280–310. The most recent
critical studies on the question of the amphictyony in Israel do not alter the situation in
general; see G. W. Anderson, ‘Israel: Amphictyony: ‘am: Kāhāl: Edāh’, in Translating
and Understanding the Old Testament. Studies in Honour of H. G. May (Nashville,
TN: Abingdon, 1970), and C. H. J. de Geus, The Tribes of Israel (Assen: Van Gorcum,
1976). In his otherwise excellent study, de Geus follows the views put forward by F. R.
Wüst, ‘Amphiktyonie, Eidgenossenschaft, Symmachie’, Historia III (1954/5), 129–53.
According to Wüst, the Delphic amphictyony must have been founded in the sixteenth
century bce, and the name α᾽ μφικτυονία, with -υ- must have been the original, going
back to a possible tribal name. Wüst also considers the Delphic amphictyony to be an
organization at first established by a single tribe only. The attitude of the present writer
regarding Noth’s thesis of an Israelite amphictyony in the period of the judges is very
critical. See my book (in Danish) Israel i Dommertiden (Israel in the Period of the
Judges), Tekst og Tolkning 4 (Copenhagen: CEG Gad, 1972).
12. J. A. O. Larsen, Representative Government in Greek and Roman History (Berkeley, CA:
University of California Press 1955), 22–3. Continuity is secured since ε’΄θνος is used as
the designation for the members of both categories of leagues. Another point of view
has been put forward by Ida Calabi, Ricerche sui rapporti tra le poleis (Florence: Nuova
Italia, 1953), 11ff. She does not accept the strict discrimination between the religious and
the political alliances.
13. J. A. O. Larsen has given an excellent survey of the history and institution of this federa-
tion in his Greek Federal States (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1968).
14. J. A. O. Larsen uses the term permanent alliances for these leagues. See his discussion
in Representative Government, 47ff.
15. Demosthenes XI:4; V:19.
The Greek ‘amphictyony’ 65
16. Herodotus VI:58, IX:11; Pindar Pyth IV:66, Nem VI:40, Isthm IV:8. See, referring to
περικτίονες, Nem XI:19, Isthm VIII:64, X:8‑9.
17. Strabo VIII:C374.
18. Strabo IX:C412.
19. Pausanias IV:5:2; see Calabi, Ricerche, 20f. Nevertheless, it seems probable that the
passage in Pausanias refers to the Delphic amphictyony.
20. See, accordingly, Calabi, Ricerche, 13, and Liddell and Scott, Greek–English Lexicon
(9th edn; Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1925), 92 s.v.
21. See Kleine Pauly Lexikon I, 311.
22. Busolt, Griech. Staatskunde, 1280 n. 1. Busolt is not able to put forward an etymo-
logical explanation of the form including the -υ-. Ernst Meyer proposes to understand
α᾽ μφικτυονία as an Attic (i.e. a literary form) and he calls α᾽ μφικτυονία for the original
but local form (evidently without any attestation in literature, though an example of the
derivation, α᾽ μφικτίονες, is known according to Liddell and Scott, s.v.); see Meyer’s
edition of Pausanias, Beschreibung Griechenlands (Stuttgart: Artemis Verlag,1954), 686
n. 486.
66 Biblical studies and the failure of history
domain.23 Until Roman times, there were twelve members of the amphictyony,
but the identity of the various participants might alter according to political
events. The fact that the members are termed ε’΄θνη is very often enlisted as
proof of the antiquity of the league, since the designation πόλεις for the mem-
bers would have been more natural if the Delphic league had been a compara
tively recent creation.24 J. A. O. Larsen, in his study on the subject, referred to
above, did draw attention to the use of ε’΄θνη as a designation for the individual
members of Greek federal states and also for their predecessors through most of
the classical period. The members of the Delphic amphictyony, called by their
tribal names (e.g. the Thessalians, the Boeotians, the Dorians, the Ionians, etc.)
may have been federal states themselves. After his victory at Actium, Augustus
extended the membership of the Delphic amphictyony to include Nicopolis,
the city recently founded by him; but, against all the rules, he gave it threefold
representation.
Normally, each member chose two delegates. ’ιερομνήμονες and the twenty-
four ’ιερομνήμονες formed an assembly together, whose main purposes were to
supervise the sacral area at Delphi and arrange the Pythian games every four
years. On the other hand, we have no information of any ‘amphictyonic legisla-
tion’ administered by the assembly of ’ιερομνήμονες; but one of their functions
was to manage the amphictyonic treasure and, if possible, to act as arbiters
between the member states. Another group of amphictyonic officers was the
πυλαγόροι, but no information has survived as to their function. The exact
number of πυλαγόροι is unknown.25 Ιερομνήμονες, together with the πυλαγόροι,
formed the συνέδριον of the amphictyony. The duty imparted on the member
states was to protect the integrity of the central shrine and, if necessary, make
preparations for retaliatory measures – that is, holy war against transgressors
of the privileges of the shrine. Accordingly, in 356/355bce, the Phocians, the
tribe in whose territory Delphi was situated, seized the shrine by force but were
utterly defeated and, together with the Spartans, their allies, were expelled from
the amphictyonic assembly. The Phocian mandate was transferred to King
Philip II of Macedonia, the man who made the total defeat of the Phocians
possible.26 On the other hand, the amphictyony does not seem to have played
any part in the wars between the member states. Moreover, membership in the
Delphic amphictyony did not exclude hostilities between members. Neither was
it expected that the amphictyony should be the chief organizer of the common
defence against foreign invaders, such as, for instance, the Persians. In times of
distress, the shrine of Apollo was first of all the oracles to which people resorted
for comfort.
23. Strabo IX:C418; Pausanias C:37:5. This is the First Holy War.
24. Nobody thinks that the league should be more recent than the eighth century bce, and the
date for the foundation is normally fixed to the early eighth century bce.
25. See Busolt, Griech. Staatskunde, 1307.
26. Busolt, Griech. Staatskunde, 1296; see Diodorus Siculus XVI:60; Demosthenes
XIX:65.66.123.275.325; XVIII 36.42; Aeschines II:9; III:80.
The Greek ‘amphictyony’ 67
Conclusion
The fragmentary state of the J sections in Genesis 6–8 is well known and needs
no comment here. Below I shall mention some consequences of the defective-
ness of the J version.
The dates in the fragments of J are:
The fragments of J give a total of merely 61 days for the whole story.
Some scholars claim, however, that because J is only partially preserved,
the original chronology of J included a span of time much longer than that
indicated by the fragments left to us. Let me quote, for example, E. Nielsen,
who suggests a total other than the 61 days preserved in J in Genesis 6:8.1 He
This system apparently presents a totally different chronology than that pre-
served in J. Only one period of time is expressly mentioned, in 7:24, according
to which the flood lasted not 40 days but also a rise of water that alone lasted
for as much as 150 days.4 Otherwise, P emphasizes the importance of placing
the individual events in the story on fixed dates of the year.
Attempts at a solution
Most scholars agree that we have two different chronological systems combined
by a redactor, who has tried – we suppose – to minimize the differences between
J and P without much success.5
Only a few favour another view of the chronological systems, including
Nielsen in his Oral Tradition. Nielsen tries to demonstrate the inner coherence
of all the dates preserved in Genesis 6–8. His starting point is the chronological
system of P, which, according to him, is not really a coherent system since it falls
apart in places. Evidence of this is the seeming lack of correspondence between
17.2.600 and 27.2.601. The explanation offered is that during the transmission
of the text, a shift from a reckoning in lunar years to a reckoning in solar years
had taken place. This implies that the chronology of P was adjusted according to
the new reckoning in solar years. If so, Nielsen argues, then the interval between
17.2.600 and 17.7.600 described in Genesis 7:24 as a period of 150 days is, in
fact, according to the reckoning in lunar months, only 147 days (or, to be exact,
147.5 days, a lunar month being only 29.5 days). The 150 days must therefore
be understood as a round number, as proposed by Gunkel.6
4. Gen. 7:17 (in the style of P), claiming the Flood to have lasted only forty days, is a gloss
trying to harmonize the difference between the chronologies of J and P. Cf. also Wester
mann, Genesis, 588, following J. Skinner, ICC (Edinburgh: T & T Clark, 1910), 165.
5. I have no intention of reviewing the various theses on the chronological system in the
Flood story. Nobody has achieved a coherent review and for very good reasons, since
most of the debate has been highly speculative and, strictly speaking, not very useful.
A list of relevant (and irrelevant) literature is given by Westermann, Genesis, 580–81,
and a short summary of some of the various theses may be found in S. McEvenue, The
Narrative Style of the Priestly Writer (AnBi, 50; Rome: Pontefical Biblical Institute,
1971), 54ff.
6. H. Gunkel, Genesis (HCAT, 4. Aufl.; Göttingen, Vandenhoeck and Ruprecht, 1917), 147.
72 Biblical studies and the failure of history
7. The reason for the rather schematic time-reckoning of P is likely to be that the chronol-
ogy of P did not represent any cultic reality, but was only a theological construction. As
to the cultic dependence of J, see below.
8. Gunkel, Genesis, 145.
9. Nielsen, Oral Tradition, 99.
10. Ibid.
The chronology in the story of the Flood 73
8:13 and 8:14; nor does it offer any reason why two sentences saying very much
the same thing could be allowed to stand.
The rest of Nielsen’s argument is more traditional in its methods.11 He makes
calculations on the period from the moment the mountains appear above the
waters, 1.10.600, to the date of the sending out of the dove the third time and
on the period going back from the 17.2.600 to the day of the appearance of God
to Noah:
Ultimately, he argues, it is possible to place all dates in the course of one year
presupposing that 1.1.600 is both Noah’s birthday and New Year’s Day. Then we
have to believe that the Flood story presupposes that the old calendar, accord-
ing to which the New Year commenced in autumn, was still in use.12 Thus, the
Flood begins in the month of December and lasts for the rest of that month and
also covers the whole of January (i.e. the two months receiving the heaviest
precipitation in Palestine).
Nielsen’s conclusions are threefold:
1. The author of the story of the Flood, Genesis 6–8, has tried to fit it into a
definite chronological scheme.
2. If this author is P, it appears that P was never an independent written
source, at least in the Flood narrative, since the coherence between J and
P demonstrates that the P dates cannot fully be understood except in cor-
relation with J dates.
3. P is not a traditional redactor, but is virtually writing a new narrative.
I do not, however, find this solution satisfactory. First of all, and contrary to
his opinion, the P dates may be understood without recourse to the dates in
J, since they are not contradictory apart from the J dates as argued by Niel
sen; I refer to his argument for an interval of 150 days between 17.2.600 and
17.7.600. Second, the calculation from 1.10.600 to 1.12.600 is irrelevant, since
the last date is neither mentioned nor alluded to in the narrative; it is a scholarly
invention. Finally, I must stress that Nielsen does not reconcile the difficulties
presented by the conflicting dates in Genesis 8:13 (1.1.601) and 8:14 (27.2.601).
His supposition of an anticipatory date is gratuitous even though it might make
sense when dealing with the differences between Genesis 7:24 (150 days) and
7:4 (40 days). Both dates, 1.1.601 and 27.2.601, are in P. No serious scholar
has ever disputed this. We therefore have to find another explanation for the
discrepancy.
Two different methods of dating are used in the story of the Flood, one of which
uses precise dates and the other periods of time. The first of these shows some
inconsistency since there seems to be two kinds of dates:
The fundamental point is whether P would want to retain both dates in Genesis
8:13‑14. What kind of redactional principle lies behind the juxtaposition of
those dates?13
The solution must, in fact, reintroduce one of the main conclusions of literary
criticism: that the story of the Flood is compiled by a redactor on the basis of
two independent written sources. In this context, we have to forget the ques-
tion of oral tradition. The kind of dating preserved in the story, especially in
P, clearly indicates written sources as the form of transmission. The redactor
worked in the style of P, which has made it difficult to demonstrate convincingly
which part of the story belongs to P and which belongs to the redactor. We may
provisionally designate the redactor as RJP. I find the presence of this redactor
evident because of Genesis 8:13‑14, where both verses are written in the style
of P. Furthermore, the correlation between the dates 27.2.601 and 17.2.600 is
clearly presupposed in Genesis 8:14. Yet, another date is dependent on 17.2.600
– namely, 17.7.600, which is the result of a simple calculation: 17.2.600 + 150
days = 17.7.600. An inner coherence between 17.2.600, 17.7.600 and 27.2.601
seems obvious, but this alone does not indicate whether the three dates in ques-
tion owe their existence to P or to RJP.
13. No scholar has ever succeeded in bringing forward a reasonable explanation of this
obvious duplicate. The nearest is perhaps Westermann, Genesis, 603–4, who argues that
the two dates duplicate each other. According to Westermann, the many, highly specula-
tive comments on these two verses owe their existence to the fact that the two verses
have been secondarily joined. Isolated from each other, they say exactly the same. The
two dates, claims Westermann, depend on different layers in the school of P. However,
thereafter Westermann’s remarks on this problem leave us in the dark. How the normal
explanation works may be seen, for example, from a modern translation such as the New
English Bible: ‘And so it came about that, on the first month of his six hundred and first
year, the waters had dried up on the earth … the surface of the ground was dry. By the
twenty-seventh day of the second month the whole [sic!] earth was dry.’ This is simply
not a correct translation, but a crassly harmonizing interpretation.
The chronology in the story of the Flood 75
What, then, is the reason for the strange date for the commencement of the
Flood: 17.2.600? One strand in the P material points to 1.1.601 as the last day
in the story. Accordingly, we would expect to find 1.1.600 as the starting point:
in fact, we have 17.2.600. In this case, the solution is obviously nearly the same
as that proposed by Cassuto. 17.2.600 depends on other dates in the story, one
preserved, one not. The one preserved is the seven days of respite, Genesis 7:4;
the one lost is the forty days during which Noah constructed the ark: all in all,
forty-seven days. As mentioned above, both dates clearly belong to the J tradi-
tion and the conclusion must be that the date in P-style, 17.2.600 (Gen. 7:11),
is dependent on the presence of the J tradition (as pointed out by Nielsen). The
second conclusion is that all three dates, 17.2.600, 17.7.600 and 27.2.601, are
dependent on the presence of J (i.e. they all presuppose the joining of J and P).
Or, expressed otherwise, the three dates are the results of putting together J and
P and they represent the chronological system or framework of RJP.
As a control of this hypothesis, I point to the fact that we have dates in the
Flood story which do not presuppose the union of J and P (i.e. 1.10.600 and
1.1.601)! It is impossible to deduce 1.10.600 from the other dates in the rest
of the narrative. Instead of 1.10.600 (Gen. 8:5), we should, by analogy with
Genesis 8:4, expect 17.10.600. This date, however, is not present in the narra-
tive. To understand its absence we must refer again to the case of 17.2.600 and
17.7.600. 17.2.600 is dependent on the chronological system of J, now only
partially preserved. This means 17.7.600 owes its presence to 17.2.600, or rather
to the mention in Genesis 7:24 of the 150 days as the period in which the waters
increased. No information is given regarding the period between the grounding
of the ark and the appearance of the tops of the mountains except the fixed dates
of 17.7.600 and 1.10.600. No necessary connection exists which forces the date
1.10.600. Therefore, the redactor did not need to deal with such an interval. He
retained the date 1.10.600 because it was already in his source material.
We have three dates, therefore, which owe their existence to the union of
J and P: 17.2.600, 17.7.600 and 27.2.601. Independently, there is a third sys-
tem present in which the Flood ends on 1.1.601, after the mountains appeared
on 1.10.600. We have dealt with the preservation of the date in Genesis 8:5,
1.10.600, and now turn our attention to Genesis 8:13. The date 1.1.601 is obvi-
ously a variant of the one in Genesis 8:14 and is not connected in any way to
J’s chronology. We saw that the reason for keeping 1.10.600 was the redactor’s
intention of including the dates in his source material. I think the same reason-
ing is responsible for the presence of 1.1.601. The redactor preferred to keep
the information already in P. On the other hand, he tried (without real success)
to reconcile the intention of the chronological system of P with the J material.
In maintaining this, I draw attention to the fact that the flood takes place in one
year according to the present framing of the story, starting on 17.2.600 and com-
ing to an end on 27.2.601. This frame owes its existence to RJP. Alternatively,
we have another date for the last event in the story – namely, 1.1.601. That R
evidently wrote in the traditional style of P indicates that we should expect the
P Flood story also to have lasted one year. Since it comes to an end at 1.1.601,
it presumably started on 1.1.600, not on 17.2.600. Perhaps we must admit that
76 Biblical studies and the failure of history
the date 1.1.600 is missing altogether. If so, this date was not in the P source,
since the redactor does include the other dates from his source, even when they
contradict his own system. There is, however, another possibility of finding the
missing date elsewhere in the narrative. I am hinting at the statement in Genesis
7:6: ‘He (Noah) was six hundred years old, when the waters of the flood came
upon the earth’ (P). The meaning could, of course, be simply that the Flood
started on a certain day during the 600th year of Noah’s life. However, this is
not likely. It is more reasonable to consider the date in Genesis 7:6 as suggesting
that the Flood started in 1.1.600. The chronological system of the P source may
therefore be reconstructed as follows:
• (1.1.600.) Noah is 600 years old. He is told to enter the ark. The Flood
starts.
• 150 days. The waters increase.
• (1.6.600.) The ark is grounded (this date might not have been present in
P, since it is not preserved).
• 1.10.600. The tops of the mountains appear.
• 1.1.601. The Flood ends, etc.
(1.1.600) – [47 days (from J)] – 17.2.600 – [150 days (from P)] –
17.7.60014 – (1.10.600 [from P] – 1.1.601 [from P]) – 27.2.601.15
This solution may also have implications for our understanding of the chrono-
logical system in J. If we go back forty-seven days from 17.2.600, we reach
(in J) not the birth of Noah in year 600, but the cultic New Year (placed, with
Nielsen, in the autumn). Beginning with the New Year, the Flood events unfold
over the next 148 days, including – unlike P – the construction of the ark and
a period of seven days thereafter. It is impossible to stretch the duration of the
Flood according to J in order to cover the period until the next New Year, but it
is more likely, as indicated by Nielsen.
In an article a few years ago I tried to place the first law of the ‘Book of the
Covenant’ (Exod. 21:2ff.) in a cultural and sociological setting, belonging to
the second half of the second millennium bce.1 The argument in that article
depended on the assumption that the sociological designation Hab/piru, known
�
from Near Eastern sources, is etymologically identical with Hebrew עברי. This
assumption has often been contested on the basis of philological considerations
by a number of scholars (‘-p-,’ not ‘-b-’), most recently E. Lipińsky in a response
to my article. However, the arguments do not carry enough weight to alter the
fact that the evidence now favours the reading of the word as habiru, equally
with hapiru.2 I will therefore maintain the reading habiru and� strive to offer
� � most likely explanation
an adequate etymology for the term עברי/habiru. The
�
rests, of course, on an association with עבר, meaning ‘to transgress’ (a border or
the like). The etymology thus suits the modern view of the habiru as referring
� environmental
to fugitives, as proposed by, among others, M. Liverani.3 The
setting of the law on the Hebrew slave, Exodus 21:2ff., is further supported
by the connection with the term חפשי/hupšu. There is no doubt that חפשי/hupšu
� group in Western Asia during the� Late
was a designation for a specific social
1. See Chapter 1 of this volume. This was followed up by two other articles, reprinted as
Chapters 2–3 of this volume.
2. Cf. E. Lipińsky, ‘L‘Esclave Hébreu’, VT 26 (1976), 120–23. Lipińsky seems to have
passed too lightly over my notes in VT 25, 138 [n. 41], referring to the argument of
Bottéro, in RLA IV, 14–27, especially §3, 22–3, in which he argues that the rendering
of the second syllable by -BI- is from an Assyriological point of view by far the most
probable. The identification of habiru and Hebrew is now also supported by H. Cazelles,
�
‘The Hebrews’, in D. J. Wiseman, Peoples of Old Testament Times (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1973), 1–28 [21ff.].
3. This implies, of course, that any consideration of a connotation with ‘ עפרdust’, as has
been recently repeated by M. C. Astour, in IDB supplemental vol (1976), 384, must
be ruled out. It will hardly be necessary to resort to any other equivalent, such as the
Hurrian ewri, epri or ibri (thus, Cazelles, in Wiseman, 19; cf. also J. Lewy, ‘Origin and
�
Signification of the Biblical Term “Hebrew”‘, HUCA 28, 1957, 1–13, 8ff.). For habiru as
�
fugitives, cf. M. Liverani, ‘Il fuoruscitismo in Siria nella Tarda età del Bronzo’, Rivista
Storica Italiana 77 (1965), 315–36, but cf. also the discussion in J. Bottéro, Le problème
des habiru (RAI IV; Paris: Imprimerie nationale, 1954), 191ff.
�
78 Biblical studies and the failure of history
Bronze Age.4 The interesting point is that legislation, most likely originating
in the Canaanite world, has been adopted by the Old Testament and, as pre
served in Exodus 21:2ff., in a nearly unchanged form. Similarly, we have clear
evidence that this law was accepted by the Israelite tradition during the seventh
or sixth century bce at the latest, since the law in Exodus 21:2ff. is cited and
has been interpreted elsewhere in the Old Testament, in Deuteronomy 15 and
Jeremiah 34.5 The same law also most likely supports the law dealing with the
Jubilee Year in Leviticus 25,6 though it is noteworthy that in Leviticus 25 the
term ‘Hebrew’ is absent. We may ask whether the reason for this omission was
that ‘Hebrew’ was still not a generally accepted national self-designation for the
Israelites at the time of the priestly redactor. If this is the case, we may assume
that the term ‘Hebrew’ is only mentioned in Deuteronomy 15 and Jeremiah 34,
because these passages quote Exodus 21:2ff. and not because the term had come
into widespread use as a national name by the time of King Zedekiah.
This preliminary treatment of the use of ‘Hebrew’ in the Old Testament goes
to show that we are obliged to find other means if we are to define when and how
‘Hebrew’ became an Israelite national name in a more precise manner, if it is at
all possible to do so on the basis of the Old Testament material.
4. Cf. VT 25, 139ff. The criticism put forward by T. Willi, Die Freiheit Israels. Philologische
Notizen zu den Wurzeln þpš, ’zb und drr, in Beiträge zur alttestamentlichen Theologie,
Festschrift W. Zimmerli (Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 1977), 531–46, 534 n.
13, surprises me a little. Willi’s argument is that my understanding of hupšu/þofšî ‘setzt
�
eine kaum zulässige Gegenstellung israelitischer sozialer Verhältnisse mit demjenigen
mesopotamischen Stadtstaaten [!] voraus …’. I am somewhat confused as to Willi’s con-
ception of Mesopotamia since most of my evidence belongs to the Cana’anite/Amorite
world (primarily Ugarit, Alalah and El Amarna letters).
�
5. See Lemche, VT 26, 43ff., 51ff.
6. Ibid., 46ff.
7. See especially Bottéro, in RLA IV, 23ff. Further sources are mentioned in my article
in VT 25, primarily on 138–9. Apart from Bottéro’s contribution to the RLA, the best
general treatment of the problem may still be that of M. Weippert, Die Landnahme
der israelitischen Stämme (FRLANT 92; Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 1967),
66–102. Some interesting points of view have also been put forward by M. Rowton in
his series of articles on the subject of nomadism in the ancient Near East, especially:
‘The Topographical Factor in the abiru Problem’, AS 16 (1965), 375–87; ‘Dimorphic
Structure and the Problem of the ‘Apiru-‘Ibrîm’, JNES 35 (1976), 13–20; but also
‘Dimorphic Structure and the Parasocial Element’, JNES 36 (1977), 181–98.
‘Hebrew’ as a national name for Israel 79
this is perhaps not precise, as they are at times under the sway of the law within
a state, not outside it.8 The designation ‘fugitive’ may be more correct since it
covers habiru, who live within the society, as well as habiru living as outlaws,
beyond�the control of the establishment. If we accept the� translation ‘refugee’ as
the one which most satisfactorily describes the concept of habiru, it also points
� (i.e. an alien in the
to the fact that a habiru normally was of foreign extraction
�
state where he had found a place). Because of that status, his juridical posi-
tion differed from that of normal residents in the state in question.9 The law in
Exodus 21:2ff. may be an example of a method used by the Canaanite city-states
to reintegrate the foreign habiru within the social system of the state and thus
give them a better juridical� position.10 When a habiru was manumitted from the
status of slave into the status of hupšu, he had� to some extent a better defined
� opened up a way to full integration within
place in society which may have
the society. I have argued elsewhere for understanding hupšu/ חפשיas origi-
� the translation of
nally meaning ‘clients’.11 This does not imply, however, that
Hebrew חפשיwith ‘free’, in other parts of the Old Testament other than Exodus
21:2ff., need be incorrect. There is much to be said in favour of the assertion that
during the first part of the first millennium bce the word had a more imprecise
meaning, since, after all, the specific social conditions of the Late Bronze Age
no longer existed.12
Turning again to the Near Eastern sources from the second millennium,
when Rib-Adda complains bitterly of the deception of his hupšu in his reports
to Egypt, there is implied, according to my interpretation,� a strike among the
8. Among others, Weippert, Landnahme, 62. As to habiru living under the law, we may
�
refer to texts from Alalah, Ugarit, Boghazköy and, especially, the contracts from Nuzi
�
(Bottéro, habiru, no. 49ff.).
�
9. See Liverani, ‘Il fuoruscitismo’, 317. Cf. also M. Heltzer, ‘Problems of the Social
History of Syria in the Late Bronze Age’, in Liverani, La Siria nel Tardo Bronzo (Rome:
Centro per le Antichità e la Storia dell’Arte del Vicino Oriente, 1969), 31–46, 34. Lewy,
in HUCA 27, 8ff., argues that the term denotes an alien – more specifically, a resident
alien. This is a far too narrow definition since, in many occurrences, the habiru was not
�
just a resident, but living outside the state territory, and a rendering like Lewy’s does not
pay due attention to the ideogrammatical rendering of the term as SA(G).GAZ and its
connotation with šaggašum, ‘murderer’, and habbātum, ‘robber’.
�
10. This was my argument in VT 25, 129ff.
11. Ibid., 139ff., with documentation.
12. So far, I follow T. Willi in that þofšî at first denoted a special status of the ex-slave, but
I see no reason to accept the thesis that this term should have its ‘Sitz im Leben’ in the
‘Obligationsrechts’!, a theory which is not supported by the Old Testament evidence. It
is hardly necessary to presume any financial reason as the primary motive of the Hebrew,
who sold himself as a slave. More likely, it was prompted by a wish to obtain social
security. However, later on, þofšî evidently lost some of its original meaning, as may be
seen from the rather ‘neutral’ examples in, for example, Job 3:19; 39:5; Ps. 88:6 and Jes.
58:6. As already pointed out in my article in VT 26, 45, it was not a perfect situation for
a slave to be set free, if he was not provided with the means of self-support in connection
with such manumission. Amendments to this situation, which also testify to the later
neutral understanding of þofšî as ‘free’, are provided by the application of Exod. 21:2ff.
in Deut. 15:13, 18.
80 Biblical studies and the failure of history
c lients of the state who are in charge of the tillage of the public estates or, more
precisely, such clients had now decided to return to their former life as habiru.13
Because of this deception, the state and kingdom in casu Byblos are now � faced
with disaster. The propaganda offensive, which the kings of Amurru directed
against the habiru (including the members of this social group in Rib-Adda’s
�
own state), gives us a fairly good impression of the general conditions in Byblos
during the Amarna period.14 The habiru are seduced by the clarion call from
�
the kings of Amurru to run away again, and these kings also direct their activ-
ity against the former habiru, now called hupšu, whose status as clients to the
� persuaded to abandon
�
King of Byblos they are and, thus, revert to their former
position as habiru. It is possible to speak of a social revolt in Byblos against the
� although the revolutionary party was not yet an integrated part
local dynasty,
of society.
In accord with this, we now need to deal with current discussions of the
supposed transition from a system of city-states during the Late Bronze Age in
Palestine to another quite different social pattern emerging at the very beginning
of the Iron Age (i.e. the origin of Israel and, more specifically, the role of habiru
�
in this process). It is well known that supporters of the so-called sociological
explanation of Israel’s settlement in Palestine assume that the process described
in the Old Testament was, in fact, an internal process, as an immigration of a
group originating outside Palestine lead to a radical transformation of the soci-
ety within Palestine.15 According to Mendenhall and other scholars, there might
have been only a single group from outside the land, a ‘Moses group’. This
group, nevertheless, was the foundation of the later Israelite understanding of
the nation’s origin.16 What actually happened during the ‘Israelite settlement’,
Mendenhall will explain, is an internal social revolt directed against oppression
in the city states in Palestine during the Late Bronze Age. The subdued peasants,
according to Mendenhall the habiru/Hebrews, reacted to oppression and created
a new kind of society, Israel, �which had as its basic ideology the ideas of liberty,
equality and fraternity, quite different from the Canaanite states.17
13. EA 77, 36–7 (the context is rather broken); 81, 33 (if you accept Knudtzon’s reconstruc-
tion); 118, 23–4 (broken); 118, 37–8; 125, 27–8; but cf. also 85, 12 (LU.MEŠ hu-up-
�
ši-ja); 112, 12; 114, 57; 117, 90; 130, 42.
14. Cf. further M. Liverani, ‘Implicazioni sociali nella politica di Abdi-Ashirta di Amurru’,
RSO 60 (1965), 267–77, and P. Artzi, ‘“Vox Populi” in the El-Amarna Tablets’, RA 58
(1964), 159–66; cf. also H. Klengel, Geschichte Syriens im 2. Jahrtausend v.u.Z., II
(Berlin: Akademie Verlag, 1969), 253ff., 276ff.
15. As originally put forward by G. E. Mendenhall, ‘The Hebrew Conquest of Palestine’,
BA 25 (1962), 66–87; cf. also BARe III (1970) 100–20; cf. also the same author’s The
Tenth Generation (Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1973), especially
ch. 5: ‘The ‘apiru Movements in the Late Bronze Age’, 122–41, and the lecture of N. K.
Gottwald in Edinburgh 1974, ‘Domain Assumptions and Societal Models in the Study
of Premonarchic Israel’, VT supplement 28 (Leiden: E. J. Brill, 1975), 89–100.
16. BA 25, 73f.
17. BA 25, 79ff. The Tenth Generation, 127ff. As to the revolt as the peasants’ revolt, see BA
25, 73.
‘Hebrew’ as a national name for Israel 81
This is not the right place to deal with Mendenhall’s thesis in detail, but
I would like to stress some points. The idea of a peasant’s revolt, within the
context of the city-states of the Late Bronze Age, is highly questionable and evi-
dence of it can only be found in a few instances related to the development of the
society in the central highlands of Palestine.18 First and foremost a superficial
reading of the sources from the Late Bronze (i.e. the Amarna letters) and Early
Iron Ages or, better, the sources which deal with that period – namely, the Old
Testament’s historical books (including the books from Joshua to 2 Samuel) –
demonstrates that the same general system of city-states existed in the Iron Age
as in the Late Bronze Age and, by and large, the same social structures survived
in those city-states during the Iron Age.
Normally, these city-states were still ruled by kings, evidently supported by
an oligarchy consisting of well-to-do merchants and landowners.19 In Palestine
proper, some of the city-states which existed during the Iron Age came into
the hands of a new element of the population, without doubt the newly arrived
Sea Peoples, among whom the Philistines surely played a leading role. They
brought with them a new material culture, which is clearly discernible from an
archaeological point of view.20 In the beginning, the domain of the Sea Peoples
in Palestine seems to have been confined to the coastal plain, south of Mount
Carmel, but, during the so-called period of the judges, they established strong-
holds north of Mount Carmel and eastwards in Beth-Shean and the Jordan Valley.
In the end, they also tried to gain control of the central Palestinian highlands.21
18. Around Shechem, as referred to in ìR-Hepa’s letters from Jerusalem, EA 289, 21ff. But
�
this example of habiru movements may also be understood quite ordinarily as a descrip-
�
tion of para-social elements strangling a city, or of a city crumpling under the pressure
of para-social elements.
19. This holds good for the general situation on the plain. In the mountains, the situation
may have altered to some degree due to the establishment of an Israelite confederation.
Even in this part of Palestine, however, city-states known from the el-Amarna letters
continued their existence. First of all, of course, Jerusalem, which was only conquered
by David, but even Shechem during this period as it is reflected by Judges 9’s Abimelek
story, may be considered a Canaanite city-state ruled by a king. On the plain, many city-
states, as, for example, Lachish and Eglon (Josh. 10:5), seem to have been in existence
around 1200bce, as reflected by the Book of Joshua, though leaders are summed up in
v. 6 as ‘all the Amorite kings in the Mountains’ ()כל מלכי האמרי ישבו ההר. We may also
mention Gezer (Josh. 10:33) and, in regard to the situation in the North, we may refer
to Joshua 11: Hazor, even though the narrative in Josh. 10–11 is considered rather late
and consisting of various independent traditions, put together at a rather late date (cf. M.
Noth, Joshua, 60–61). Nevertheless, it shows that it was common knowledge among the
Israelites that the Canaanites were organized in a system of city-states ruled by kings.
20. I am, of course, hinting at the so-called Philistine pottery, even if this designation is
imprecise; cf. N. K. Sandars, The Sea Peoples (London: Thames and Hudson, 1978),
166ff.
21. For example, the general view, as put forward by M. Noth, Geschichte Israels (2nd edn;
Göttingen: Vandenhoeck and Ruprecht, 1955), 150–51. This may be supported by the
fact that not much Philistine pottery has been found (as, e.g., at Beth-Shan). What is
actually found there is very late; see Sandars, The Sea Peoples, 172.
82 Biblical studies and the failure of history
22. In the mountains, topological conditions allowed the establishment of only a few city-
states such as Jerusalem and Shechem. Even a small town must have at least some addi
tional agricultural land to survive. In central Palestine, the mountains are interspersed
with several small valleys but only in a few instances does the terrain leave enough space
for bigger cities to grow up, as in the case of Shechem. The topological factor, on the
other hand, does not allow for larger city-states because of difficulties in communication.
We rather need to assume the existence of a territory known as habiru land around the
�
city-states in the mountains, but outside their control. So even if a city-state may claim
a large territory, in reality, it has control only over a part of it. The first entity to create a
large, coherent state in the central mountains was Israel, since it was not a city-state but
a ‘national state’, which differentiation G. Buccellati has done a lot to elucidate (Cities
and Nations of Ancient Syria; Studi Semitici 26; Rome: Istituto di Studi del Vicino
Oriente, 1967). Some of the most informative recent contributions to understanding the
importance of the topological factor have come from M. Rowton, in AS 16 (1965),
375ff., but cf. also ‘The Woodlands of Ancient Western Asia’, JNES 26 (1967), 261–77,
and ‘The Physical Environment and the Problem of the Nomads’, in J.-R. Kupper (ed.)
La Civilisation de Mari (RAI, 15; Paris: Société d’édition Les Belles lettres, 1967),
109–21. How the process of amalgamation of the different habiru elements into tribes
�
may have taken place can be illustrated by examples cited in Rowton, JNES 36, 183ff. It
is also very interesting to compare this with the rise of the medieval Arabic tribe Mawali,
cf. Rowton, JNES 36, 194.
23. The most recent summary of evidence may be by J. Maxwell Miller, in Hayes and Miller,
Israelite and Judaean History (London: SCM, 1977), 252–62. Cf. also K. M. Kenyon,
Archaeology in the Holy Land (3rd edn; London: Thomas Nelson, 1970), 209. She points
to the fact that a change in material culture occurs at the transition from LB I to LB
II rather than later in the shift from LB to EI; but, even so, it is still the same culture,
showing merely a ‘marked deterioration’. Cf. also R. Amiran, Ancient Pottery of the
Holy Land (New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press, 1969), 191f. She refers to the
fact that ‘from MB I onwards, the development of the material culture … is continuous,
gradual, and evolutionary until the end of the Iron Age or even later’, even as she also
points to a shift in fabrication techniques during the Early Iron Age and the formation
of a new ‘set of ceramic Ideas’ which she ascribes to the appearance of Israelites in
Palestine, but which might just as well be attributed to an evolutionary process of new
‘Hebrew’ as a national name for Israel 83
It is an extraordinary fact that the use of the term Hebrew in the Old Testament,
except for a few instances, is confined to a fraction of literary compositions. It
is not widespread in the historical sections in the Old Testament. We must deal
with the exceptions. The first is Genesis 14:13. Here Abraham is titled העברי.
We may assume that the term is used here with a national significance, but the
section as a whole is undoubtedly very late, post-exilic and inapplicable as a
source of historical information about conditions during the second millennium
bce.28 The second exception is Jonah 1:9. Here the prophet calls himself an עברי.
techniques.
24. It was, of course, not an ‘amphictyony’, in the sense of M. Noth, as recent criticism
has clearly demonstrated. See, among others, A. D. H. Mayes, Israel in the Period of
the Judges (SBT SS, 29; London: SCM, 1974), and in Hayes and Miller, Israelite and
Judaean History, 299–308. I have tried to demonstrate the impossibility of using the
Greek amphictyony as a prototype in Chapter 4, this volume.
25. As demonstrated by the inclusion of the Canaanite city-territories in Solomon’s admin-
istrative division of his kingdom in 1 Kings 4.
26. To cite only the references which doubtlessly deal with the situation in the mountains:
EA 246; 254; 272; 286–90.
27. We need only refer to the study of E. Nielsen, Shechem (Copenhagen: CEG Gad, 1955).
28. Cf. the recent review of the older discussion of the historicity and date of Gen. 14 by J. A.
Emerton, ‘Some False Clues in the Study of Genesis XIV’, VT 21 (1971), 403–39. Cf.
84 Biblical studies and the failure of history
Again, this bears a national meaning; but, once more, the evidence belongs to
the post-exilic period.29
I have already dealt with the first body of pre-exilic evidence in Exodus
21:2ff., the law concerning the question of Hebrew slaves and the citations
from that law in Deuteronomy 15 and Jeremiah 34. In the first place, the term
Hebrew is used as a sociological designation and, in the other examples, the
word is dependent on Exodus 21:2ff. It is not, therefore, possible (on the basis
of these examples) to date a shift in the understanding of the term Hebrew.
Finally, three groups of occurrences are discernible in the historical books of
the Old Testament. The first group belongs to the Joseph Story,30 the second to
the so-called ‘Paschal Legend’ of Exodus 1–1531 and the third is confined to the
first Book of Samuel.32
also the treatment of this chapter by T. L. Thompson, The Historicity of the Patriarchal
Narratives (BZAW 133; Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1974), 187–95. and J. Van Seters,
Abraham in History and Tradition (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1975),
196–308, both of whom consider the chapter a very late addition to the patriarchal nar-
ratives. C. Westermann in his Die Verheißungen an die Väter (FRLANT 116; Göttingen:
Vandenhoeck and Ruprecht, 1976), 60, points to an affinity to the proto-history, Gen.
1–11, rather than to the rest of the patriarchal narratives. Lewy, in HUCA 28 (1957),
6–7, seems to use Gen. 14:13 as a point of departure or as the origin to the later Jewish
understanding of ‘Hebrew’ because of the LXX translation: ο῾ περάτης. This holds true
as regards the main manuscripts, though some late Greek minuscles vary, but they are of
no consequence here. This indicates that even in the Hellenistic period it was not obvi-
ous that the term Hebrew was not an ethnic name, but an appellative noun. This opens
up the possibility of understanding the term ‘Hebrew’ in Gen. 14:13 in line with other
occurrences, denoting ‘foreigners’. Abraham may have been called thus, because he was
a fugitive from Mesopotamia, foreign to the people of the land. We should not, however,
stress this point too far.
29. Jonah 1:9 ואנכי עבריis the only example in the Old Testament, where an Israelite (or
Judaean) calls himself a ‘Hebrew’. Even in this case, there is a hint of the ancient under-
standing of Hebrew as ‘fugitive’, since Jonah may declare himself a refugee from his
own country in accord with the fictitious setting of the scene. Otherwise, K. Koch, ‘Die
Hebräer von Auszug aus Ägypten bis zum Großreich Davids’, VT 19 (1969), 37–81,
43–44. Koch thinks that Hebrew is used in Jonah 1:9 as a reminiscence of the old
Philistine designation of the Israelite population in the mountains, as testified in the first
book of Samuel. However, he stretches the continuity in usage a bit too far when he sup-
poses that the sailors from Jaffa were Philistines by descent and that the old tradition from
the great old days of the Philistine sway over most of Palestine was still alive. We must
note, however, that there is simply not enough evidence in the Old Testament to support
his thesis. To draw any conclusion on the basis of such scanty material is, at best, rash.
30. Gen. 39:14, 17; 40:15; 41:12; 43:32.
31. Exod. 1:15, 19; 2:7, 13; 3:18; 5:3; 7:16; 9:1, 13; 10:3. Cf. also Exod. 2:6.
32. 1 Sam 4.6, 9; 13.3, 7(?), 19; 14.11, 21; 29.3. An additional example is found in 1 Chron.
24:27, but as a personal name. This occurrence is of no use in this argument. The use
of the personification עברfor ( עבריas used in the genealogies of Genesis 10:21, 25,
normally ascribed to J; but cf. also Num. 24:24, evidently a ‘Zusatz’ to the Bileam texts)
is treated by Koch, in VT 19, especially in regard to Gen. 10:21, 71ff. However, these
genealogies should be let out of consideration from the start, since they cannot be taken
as evidence for real knowledge of the origin of the Semitic peoples, but only as expres-
‘Hebrew’ as a national name for Israel 85
It is striking that ‘Hebrew’ in the Joseph Story is never used by the Israelites
as a description of themselves, either of a group characterized as the sons of
Jacob or of individual persons such as Joseph. Egyptians describe Joseph as a
Hebrew three times. In Genesis 39:14, 17, Potiphar’s wife applies the designa-
tion to Joseph, implying a clearly derogatory understanding of the term: a person
so base as a Hebrew has dared violate her. In Genesis 41:12, Pharaoh’s cupbearer
calls Joseph a נער עברי. On the basis of these examples, we cannot decide with
any certainty whether Hebrew is used in a national (i.e. ethnic) or sociological
sense. If the three examples are isolated as single occurrences and placed in the
fictitious setting of the Joseph Story (i.e. Egypt) during the middle part of the
second millennium bce, there is no doubt that Hebrew is understood as a social
designation. The same argument is valid when we deal with the other examples
in the Joseph story. In Genesis 40:15, Joseph, who does not declare himself
a Hebrew, describes how he was kidnapped from the country of the Hebrews
=( מארץ העבריםPalestine, from an Egyptian perspective). Therefore, the com-
pound ארץ העבריםis used only in a geographical sense. It is not to be considered
a national name, but it may be a description of the area in question as a more or
less lawless territory, compared to Egypt.33 Finally, in Genesis 43:32, the reason
for Joseph’s reluctance to communicate on more friendly terms with his family
is presented in a general way as the normal Egyptian disapproval of intercourse
with Hebrews at table. The application of Hebrew in this context could be ethnic
as well as sociological, but it primarily speaks to Egyptian xenophobia.
sions of rather late compilers’ reflections on the problem of the relationship between
various Semitic peoples of only limited historical value. Altogether, the use of the name
עבריin the Old Testament is not a clue to understanding עבריbut, vice versa, the evolu-
tion of the concept עבריmay be answerable for the introduction of the personification
עבריand, for that reason, the best we can do is exclude the personification עבריfrom the
discussion.
33. Accordingly, it is possible to compare the use of ארץ־העבריםin Gen. 40:15 with refer-
ences to habiru territories in the second millennium, even though evidence is scanty; cf.
�
Bottéro, habiru, no. 161 (RS 17238): … eqli (LÚ) SA.GAZ (il) šamši …. Cf. to this H.
�
Schmökel, Geschichte des alten Vorderasien (HO; Leiden: E. J. Brill, 1957), 232–34,
and to the problem of the identification of the habiru territories Rowton, AS 16, 382ff.
�
Another view of Gen. 40:15 has been put forward by D. B. Redford, ‘The “Land of the
Hebrews” in Gen. XL 15’, VT 15 (1965), 529–32; see also the same author, The Biblical
Story of Joseph (VT supplement 20; Leiden: E. J. Brill, 1970), 201ff. He compares Gen.
40:15 with very late Egyptian evidence (a demotic papyrus in Vienna), quoting the term
‘ybr’ to mean ‘(the land of the) Hebrews’. Therefore, ארץ־העבריםis simply an anachro-
nistic insertion into the context. Koch (VT 19, 51–2) uses the reference brought to light
by Redford without considering that this is, in fact, a very late first millennium datum,
which is hardly allowable to use as evidence for anything in the late second millennium.
This is a striking example of the type of historical argumentation which mars Koch’s
otherwise excellent article, but which, on the other hand, demonstrates the difficulties
of equating biblical data with ancient Near Eastern documents. Evidently the ebr land
in the Egyptian text can only be used in support of a late dating of the Joseph Story, or
this part of it, not of an early date, and so far Redford’s own application of the datum is
correct from a methodological point of view.
86 Biblical studies and the failure of history
It seems that it is not possible, on the basis of the five occurrences of the
term Hebrew in the Joseph Story, to point to a single use which can definitely be
termed ‘national’. It is similarly very characteristic that the designation is only
used in the case of a confrontation with Joseph or the other sons of Jacob with
the Egyptians in order to describe these people from the Egyptians’ perspective
or as the name by which they are known to the Egyptians. It is interesting that
it is possible to reach a provisional conclusion of this kind without recourse to a
discussion on the subject of dating the Joseph Story or of establishing a division
of sources within the story. If we were to suppose that the fictitious setting of the
Joseph Story in the middle of the second millennium bce was correct, the appli-
cation of the term ‘Hebrew’ does not differ much from the use of habiru/‘pr.w
�
in ‘contemporary’ Egyptian sources.34 If it is, however, more reasonable to date
the story to the time of David or Solomon,35 or even later (e.g. the exilic or
late pre-exilic period),36 we cannot draw a conclusion regarding the ‘national’
application or ‘sociological’ understanding on the basis of material in the Joseph
Story. On the other hand, there does not seem to be any reasonable possibility
of a solution to the question of a correct dating by using the traditional analyses
of literary criticism, which trace the presence of the traditional Pentateuchal
sources J, E and P in the Joseph Story, since this would imply that both J (Gen.
39:14, 17; 43:32) and E (Gen. 40:15; 41:12) made use of the term Hebrew.37
In the second composition, dealing with the sojourn of the Israelites in Egypt,
the so-called ‘Paschal Legend’ in Exodus 1–15, it is possible to discern three
different applications of the designation ‘Hebrew’.38 In Exodus 1:15, 19; 2:7 we
34. Bottéro, habiru, no. 181–93. The oldest reference dates from the beginning of the fif-
�
teenth century bce. Cf. also the survey of the evidence by S. Herrmann, Israels Aufenhalt
in Ägypten (SBS, 40; Stuttgart: Katholisches Bibelwerk, 1970), 55ff. To some degree,
Herrmann puts his questions to the evidence a little differently since he, correctly, notes
that it is an astonishing fact that, apart from Gen. 14:13 and Exod. 21:2, all references to
the Hebrews in Genesis and Exodus apply to Israelites in Egypt. He disregards, however,
the fact that all evidence is collected in two separate narratives: the ‘Joseph Story’ and
the ‘Paschal Legend’ and is not distributed here and there in the Tetrateuch, where we
find references to the Israelite sojourn in Egypt.
35. Among other scholars, G. von Rad, ‘Josephgeschichte und ältere Chokma’, VT supple-
ment 1 (Leiden: E. J. Brill, 1953), 120–27, and Das erste Buch Mose. Genesis (ATD, 2/4,
9th edn: Göttingen: Vandenhoeck and Ruprecht, 1972), 359f.
36. This is the argument in Redford’s study in VT supplement 20. Redford stresses the point
that no reminiscence of the Egyptian society in the second millennium is extant in the
Joseph Story, but what there is dates from the Saitic period or even later and, therefore,
the termini for the composition of the story are between the conclusion of the seventh
century and the third quarter of the fifth century bce (242).
37. Cf. also the conclusion of Redford’s study on the Joseph story. Redford claims the exist-
ence of different layers in the Joseph story, a ‘Reuben-version’ and a ‘Judah-version’, but
none of them are comparable to the traditional Pentateuchal sources, J, and E, and they
are only present in the Joseph story (252).
38. I am not going to involve myself in the discussion of the coherence of Exodus 1–15.
As to the designation of Exodus 1–15, see J. Pedersen, ‘Passahfest und Passahlegende’,
ZAW 52 (1934), 161–75 (cf. also Noth, Überlieferungsgeschichte des Pentateuch,
‘Hebrew’ as a national name for Israel 87
Stuttgart: Kohlhammer,1948, 71ff.). We find criticism from a literary point of view in,
for example, G. Fohrer, Überlieferung und Geschichte des Exodus (BZAW 91; Berlin:
Walter de Gruyter, 1964); see also Fohrer, in Sellin and Fohrer, Einleitung in das Alte
Testament (Heidelberg: Quelle and Meyer, 1965), 128–9. He ascribes the references
to Passover, the Massot festival and the ‘Weihung’ of the first-born in Exod. 12:1‑20,
24‑27a; 13:3‑16 to the presence of the sources D and P.
39. I do not think that this designation has anything to do with the reference to ‘the gods
of the habiru’ in the Near Eastern sources, in this case mostly from the archives of
�
Boghazköy (Bottéro, habiru, no. 75–86). Cf. also the discussion in Bottéro, habiru, 81ff.
� �
It is evident that the אלהי העברים, even if it is formally a parallel to the DINGIR.MES
SA.GAZ = DINGIR MEŠ habi-re-e-eš, is only a presentation of Yahweh as the God of
�
Israel, known to the Egyptians as the God of the Hebrews. Compare with the sequence
in Exod. 5:1ff. Moses presents Yahweh to the Egyptians as the God of Israel, leading
to the question from Pharaoh: ‘Who is that Yahweh’ and then we get the definition of
Yahweh as the ‘God of the Hebrews’. Other scholars including Koch, VT 19, 53, attribute
the different titles of Yahweh to the presence of different sources so that Yahweh, the
God of the Hebrews, is used exclusively by J, whereas E uses other designations. While
this is a generally accepted argument in Pentateuchal criticism, as such, the case may
nevertheless be otherwise if one reckons with a coherent strain of traditions, collected
in the more or less independent work of the ‘Paschal Legend’. Therefore, there may be
good reasons for interpreting the use of ‘God of the Hebrews’ versus ‘God of Israel’,
etc., on line with the usage of different designations, Israel and Hebrews, in 1 Samuel
(see below). If the composition of J can be fixed to the time of the united monarchy, J has
probably preserved or kept in mind an old designation for Yahweh, even if that cannot be
proven. If J or the so-called J , to quote H. H. Schmid, Der sogenannte Jahwist (Zürich:
TVZ Verlag, 1976) on this section of Exodus, 44ff., belongs to the seventh century bce or
even later it is still possible to suppose the preservation of old usage, but after all much
more likely that the difference of usages is due to the compiler’s deliberate literary work.
40. העברי. The feminine is in the Old Testament only used in Exod. 1–2 and in Jer. 34:9, in
the reflection on the law from Exod. 21:2ff., cited in Jer. 34:14.
88 Biblical studies and the failure of history
41. Accordingly, a naive comparison with habiru gods (see note 39) is ruled out. The desig-
�
nation of Yahweh in this section at times varies – for example, in Exod. 3:15: יהוה אלהי
אבתיכם, whereas in 5:15 יהוה אלהי ישראל, both places are traditionally ascribed to E; but
see note 39.
42. As reflected in the so-called ‘Kleine Credo’ of Deut. 26:5ff. and elsewhere in the his-
torical and prophetic literature as in Deut. 5:15, Jer. 34:13, etc. It should be noted that
‘Hebrew’ is not used in any of these connections with Egypt, not even in Jer. 34:13.
43. Depending on the date of this section of Exodus. Nevertheless, this is a much debated
question. The dating of the composition of the Pentateuchal sources varies from the tra-
ditional tenth to ninth century bce (the perhaps latest investigation leading to this result
is that of P. Weimar, Untersuchungen zur Redaktionsgeschichte des Pentateuch, BZAW,
146; Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1977, especially 164), to the seventh century bce (H. H.
Schmid, Der sogenannte Jahwist) or even later. I am not going to engage this discussion
here, but the uncertainty shows that it is risky to decide on an absolute date of an ethnic
‘Hebrew’ as a national name for Israel 89
In many respects the use of Hebrew in the first Book of Samuel demonstrates
a striking similarity to the use in the Joseph Story and the ‘Paschal Legend’.
As opponents of Israel, the Philistines have the same role as the Egyptians. In
1 Samuel 4, the introduction to the Ark narrative, Hebrew is used twice to des-
ignate the enemies of the Philistines (1 Sam. 4:6, 9) in quoting Philistine refer-
ences to their adversaries. Precisely the same usage also appears in 1 Samuel
13–14. In these chapters, as well, Hebrew is used in opposition to the Philistines,
13:3(?), 19; 14:11, 21. On the other hand, we have clear evidence that these
adversaries of the Philistines called themselves either Israel or Israelites. Thus,
1 Samuel, without doubt, points to an identification of the terms Israel and
Hebrew by the Philistines.44 The problem is whether they used the designation
in a national sense rather than Israel and as something different from Israel, or
whether the designation still had some sociological meaning.
Some references are what we may characterize as neutral applications, which
tell us nothing that will enable us to solve the problem of distinguishing an
ethnic from a sociologically based designation. This applies to 1 Samuel 4:6,
where the Philistines call the camp of their opponents מחנה העברים. Another
passage in this group of neutral usages is 1 Samuel 13:19. In Israel, weapons
are in short supply because the Philistines would not consent to allow smiths
to deliver them to the Hebrews. Again, in 1 Samuel 14:11, a Philistine out-
post identifies individual foes coming against it as Hebrews. In each instance,
1 Samuel proceeds to inform us that all such Hebrews are, in fact, Israelites.
Thus, in 1 Samuel 4:1‑5, the Israelite camp is just the same as the one called
understanding of Hebrew from the material in Exodus 1–15. The possibilities confine us
to the period of the Israelite monarchy. It is also dangerous to rely on so-called historical
remembrance in these sections even if the resemblances to Egyptian sources mentioning
‘aprw are striking. On the other hand, it is impossible to accept the remarks put forward
by Koch, VT 19, 63, that the Egyptian use of ‘aprw during the nineteenth dynasty altered
very much from older Egyptian usage. As his only really positive argument, Koch men-
tions an interval of 130 years. This is not very convincing, since among the very different
Near Eastern sources dealing with the habiru, the designation seems to vary very little
�
during a period of nearly 1000 years and the term seems to be used as a description of
essentially the same phenomenon, independent of place or time.
44. J. Weingreen (‘Saul and the habiru’, IV WCJS, 1967, 63–6) tries to separate the terms
�
Hebrew and Israelites. The Hebrews are foreigners, trying to help Israel to defeat the
Philistine onslaught. Possibly they were used as mercenaries or professional soldiers
by Saul. Weingreen’s point of departure is 1 Sam. 13:7: ְו ִע ְבִרים ָע ְברוּ ֶאת ֵהֵיְּרֵדּן, but only
after a small textual correction, which is quite likely (supported, e.g., by H. J. Stoebe,
Das erste Buch Samuelis, KAT, VIII/1; Gütersloh: Gütersloher Verlagshaus Gerd Mohn,
1973, 255); but, nonetheless, he builds his thesis on insecure ground. No other example
in 1 Sam supports this thesis since, in all other examples, it is more reasonable to look
on the Hebrews as properly Israelite. Weingreen did not acknowledge the special use of
‘Hebrew’ in the Old Testament’s historical parts, as used by foreigners of Israel and not
by the Israelites themselves (regarding 1 Sam. 13:3; cf. note 45 below). In conclusion of
the argument, it needs to be asked why David should be called a Hebrew in 1 Sam. 29:3.
Even if Judean by birth, he, nevertheless, represents Israel as a fugitive from Saul, the
King of Israel.
90 Biblical studies and the failure of history
by the Philistines ‘the camp of the Hebrews’. In the same manner, in 1 Samuel
4:9‑10, the Hebrews, beaten at Aphek, are Israelites. The problems of 1 Samuel
13:3-4 are, however, much more intricate. If we follow older commentaries and
translations and adopt the Masoretic Text: וישמעו פלשתים ושאול תקע בשופר לאמר
ישמעו העברים, it should be amended to וישמעו פלשתים פשעו העברים ושאול תקע
בשופר בכל־הארץ ולאמר, partly on the basis of the Septuagint.45 According to
the Masoretic version, Saul addresses the Hebrews, urging them to support
the uprising against the Philistines, but in the verse immediately following 1
Samuel 13:4, such Hebrews are termed כל ישראל. We have the same phenom-
enon in 1 Samuel 13:3‑4 as in 1 Samuel 4:1‑5 and 4:9‑10, even though some
scholars assume that כל ישראלin 1 Samuel 13:4 must be added to the reference
to Hebrews in v. 3. I find it impossible to agree with Koch that 1 Samuel 13:3‑4
proves that the designations Hebrews and Israelites are not used to refer to the
same political entity in 1 Samuel.46 Finally, the problem of the correct reading
of 1 Samuel 13:3 remains, and, for that reason alone, we should not build too
many hypotheses on the basis of this single verse.47
There still seems to be other occurrences in 1 Samuel, which give us better
information for solving this problem. According to 1 Samuel 4:9, the Philistines
pulled themselves together before the battle, thanks to the admonition that they
not become slaves to Hebrews, much as the Hebrews had been formerly slaves
to Philistines פן תעברו לעבדים כאשר עבדו לכם. It is, however, not entirely certain
that the designation is a sociological expression, since it could refer to a former
Israelite state of dependence on Philistines. Additionally, we need to reckon
with the possibility that the wording of v. 9 could be dependent on v. 8, refer-
ring to wonders achieved by God in Egypt for the sake of Israel (with the tacit
implication that Israelites were slaves there). On the other hand, it is more likely
that v. 8 is, in fact, redactional and a reason for its inclusion in this may be the
reference to the Ark of the Covenant and the God of Israel in v. 6-7.48 In this
45. See J. Wellhausen, Der Text der Bücher Samuelis (Göttingen: Vandenhoeck and Ruprecht,
1871), 80–81, and the older commentaries by K. Budde, Die Bücher Samuel (KHCAT,
VIII; Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 1902), 84f., W. Caspari, Die Samuelbücher
(KAT, VII; Leipzig: Deichertsche, 1926), 154, and S. R. Driver, Notes on the Hebrew
Text and the Topography of the Books of Samuel (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1913), 98.
The actual emendation may alter from author to author; but, essentially, all come to the
same result.
46. See Koch, VT 19, 46–7.
47. As stressed by the older commentators (cf. note 45). The Masoretic Text tradition seems
rather stable. The MT is furthermore supported by the targum, and the Vulgate, and to
some extent also by the Peshitta, though the Peshitta places both העבריםand כל ישראל
on a line making both subjects to the verb ישמעו, and leaving out שמעו לאמרin v. 4. It
is still problematic to explain the Greek η
῾ θετήκασιν as a mere scribal corruption of an
originally Hebrew ישמעוand to some extent the lectio difficilior. Whether the Greek
text represents an independent Hebrew tradition as its ‘Vorlage’ or is dependent on a
corrupted Hebrew version is not clear.
48. Cf. also H. Timm, ‘Die Ladeerzählung (1 Sam. 4‑6; 2 Sam. 6) und das Kerygma des
deuteronomistischen Geschichtswerks’, EvTH 26 (1966), 509–26, 521.
‘Hebrew’ as a national name for Israel 91
come to an end to this very preliminary discussion of the designation in the Old
Testament.
Conclusion
history of Israel during the period of the judges, both biblical and extra-biblical.
The extra-biblical material consists, first and foremost, of the stele of Merenptah
dating from the very beginning of the so-called period of the judges (or perhaps
from the last days of the period of the settlement).54 However, evidence from
the Amarna letters from the Late Bronze Age should also be included. I have
made some use of that evidence above. I simply note here that in 1 Samuel
the Philistines define the inhabitants of the central Palestinian mountains as
Hebrews. This must be considered both a sociological and a national designa-
tion because these inhabitants of the mountains had an identity coherent enough
to allow them to present themselves as a society with its own name, Israel. The
stele of Merenptah seems to confirm this view. According to the inscription on
the stele, Israel is reckoned among the enemies of Pharaoh and it is the name
of the society which is used, not the designation habiru-land or the like. In this
� of Seti I from Beth-Shean.
connection, we may compare it with the earlier stele
In that inscription, the Egyptians do not make use of the name Israel, but the
possibility exists that it was already a political reality. On the other hand, the
inscription speaks of a punitive expedition directed against groups of habiru in
� either
Palestine. Without further proof, we cannot identify these habiru with
�
Israel or the predecessors of Israel, even if they perhaps did inhabit the same
area, or part of it, as the Israelites did in later days, since we still have to reckon
with the possibility of changes in the composition of the population during the
interval of almost eighty years between the erection of the stele of Seti I and
Merenptah’s inscription. The stele of Seti I may bear evidence of alterations
in the population because it tells us of some tribal entities no longer extant in
Old Testament days.55 The stele of Merenptah also seems to testify to the fact
that Israel had a society different from the city states on the plain because the
inscription uses the foreign people determinative for Israel and not, as in the
other cases in this section of the stele, the foreign nation determinative.56 Com
pared with 1 Samuel, it demonstrates that the Philistines did not see Israel as
a regular state, but rather considered it another and more loosely organized
kind of society different from their own. Therefore the designation ‘Hebrews’
is used of the Israelites, although it is not certain that Israel at its origin was a
regular society of habiru. We should emphasize, however, that, as it appeared
�
to foreigners, the designation was comparable to the habiru who played a very
active role during the Amarna age in Palestine in the� same area as later Israel.
This territorial coincidence could be the reason for the designation ‘Hebrew’
being attached to Israel by neighbouring peoples such as the Philistines. What
kind of society Israel actually was is unknown, but it was not an amphictyony
57. M. Noth, System der Zwölf Stämme Israels (Stuttgart: Kohlhammer, 1930). As to the
present writer’s views, see the résumé of my book in Danish, Israel i Dommertiden
(Copenhagen: CEG Gad, 1972), in O. Bächli, Amphiktyonie im Alten Testament
(TZ Sonderband VI; Basel: Friedrich Reinhardt Verlag, 1977), 4f. and passim.
7
assessments of Israel’s early history, which, from a religious point of view, are
generally very conservative.
Any review of previous scholarship must be selective and arbitrary if we
do not go back to Richard Simon or Jean Astruc. Nevertheless, the admittedly
arbitrary point of departure of 1878 and the publication of Julius Wellhausen’s
Prolegomena3 is motivated by the general acknowledgement that this work
initiated a new era in biblical studies, the repercussions of which are still acutely
felt. Of course, earlier scholars of the calibre of Heinrich Ewald and Abraham
Kuenen must be left out of consideration, since they have only little to contrib-
ute to the on-going debate on the origin of Israel and, I may add, have had hardly
any serious influence on this discussion during the last fifty years.4
Julius Wellhausen
Lothar Perlitt, published in 1965, has, on the other hand, made it clear that this
traditional evaluation of Wellhausen’s roots in the philosophy of his own time
is totally misconceived.6 Perlitt explains that Wellhausen was not a partisan of
the Hegelian philosophy. To the contrary, he was opposed to Hegel’s schematic
philosophy of history and, although Perlitt warns against a hasty identification
of Wellhausen as a romanticist, it is obvious that his place among scholars was
rather with such as Herder than among the adherents of the Enlightenment’s
optimistic view of history, an understanding which found its ultimate manifesta
tion in the historical-philosophical writings of Hegel.7
A thorough assessment of the published works of Wellhausen on ancient
Israel and the Old Testament will likely show that Wellhausen was not continu-
ing a direction going back to the Enlightenment, with its optimistic idea of the
development of man. On the contrary, he adhered to the classical conception,
according to which man is originally placed in a golden era and later becomes
entangled in inferior situations. It, of course, never interested Wellhausen to
write general works with a historical-philosophical content since he was ever
concerned with a particular culture – in this regard, Israelite culture and, oth-
erwise, Arab civilization. It was, however, characteristic of this great scholar
that he did not base his work in preconceived ideas of the development of the
Israelite nation without having a textual basis. Before the appearance of his
Prolegomena and his later Israelitische und jüdische Geschichte, he started with
extensive analyses of the history of the transmission of the Old Testament text,
particularly the sources of the Hexateuch.8 If the more comprehensive charac-
ter of the work of Wellhausen is not acknowledged, it is impossible to reach a
proper assessment of his scientific importance.
Wellhausen subdivides the history of the Israelite tradition into three succes-
sive phases, which he defines respectively as the Jehovistic, Deuteronomistic
6. L. Perlitt, Vatke und Wellhausen (BZAW, 94; Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1965). The study
of Perlitt forms the background of the changed view on Wellhausen in Kraus’s Hist
-Krit. Erforschung (2nd edn), although Kraus only reluctantly acknowledges the fact. It
is also Perlitt who is cited by Albright in Yahweh and the Gods, 230. Albright expresses
an opinion which, had he had the time, would have induced him to change his opinion
of Wellhausen’s philosophical standing.
7. Vatke und Wellhausen, 178. Here Perlitt presents the following pedigree of Wellhausen’s
understanding of the Israelite development: Lessing, Herder, Goethe, Schleiermacher, the
Idealistic philosophy, de Wette and Ranke. He offers a circumstantial account of the rel-
evance of this list of names in the section devoted to Wellhausen (Vatke und Wellhausen,
153–243, passim). His including Wellhausen among ‘die historischen Romantiker’ is on
212ff. According to Perlitt, Wellhausen considered himself congenial to scholars such as
Theodor Mommsen and especially his personal friend Ulrich Wilamowitz-Moellendorf,
to whom he dedicated his Israelitische und jüdische Geschichte (Berlin: Georg Reimer,
1894; here cited after the 9th edn, Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1958).
8. Cf. Wellhausen, Die Composition des Hexateuchs und der historischen Büchern des
Alten Testaments (4th edn; Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1963), which originally appeared
as a series of articles in 1876–7; cf. Composition, 1.
98 Biblical studies and the failure of history
as a very special religion, which was not comparable to others. The appearance
of Israelite monotheism was attributed rather to later developments in Israel as
a whole, with special emphasis on the imprint of the Exile.
I have no intention to comment on all of Wellhausen’s ideas. If we turn our
attention, however, to his description of Israel before the monarchy, we are in
for a surprise – if our starting point is with his analyses of the history of Israelite
literary traditions and Israelite religion. Wellhausen’s reconstruction of the early
history of Israel is not at all revolutionary. For scholars, a century after the
appearance of his Prolegomena, it is rather dull and uninspiring. His historical
reconstruction does not try to deconstruct early Israelite history. Rather, his
description is best described as a critical or rationalistic paraphrase of the Old
Testament tradition, with occasional modifying remarks. Sometimes, he touches
up some stories in a harmonizing fashion, much as may be found in homiletic
books. Wellhausen’s paraphrase of the episode of Abimelech offers an obvious
example.16 On the other hand, it is quite characteristic of his view of tradition
that he accords no historical value to the patriarchal stories. He merely reckons
them to be the product of a much later period and transposed into the early days
of the nation.17 Nevertheless, the division of the tribes of Israel in the patriarchal
narratives still forms the basis of his historical reconstruction of the process of
settlement in his history in the period of the judges.18
According to Wellhausen, the origin of Israel as a nation preceded its settle-
ment in Palestine. Israel was the conglomerate of three different groups. The
first group consisted of Israelites who formerly lived in Goshen on the border
of Egypt. The other group inhabited the desert of Sinai in the environs of the so-
called place of revelation. These two groups integrated with each other before
meeting the third group, which had migrated to Transjordan many years before.19
Wellhausen considered all of them to be nomadic.20 Nevertheless, he clearly
distinguished between them and, for example, the Midianites. The Midianites
were camel-nomads, true children of the desert, real predatory camel-nomads,
whereas the Israelites were small-cattle nomads.21 The conquest of Cisjordan,
according to Wellhausen, followed a course very much the same as is deline-
ated in later scholarly literature devoted to the settlement of Israel. Wellhausen
accounted for several attempts to conquer the area and followed the subdivision
of the Israelite tribes in the Old Testament into Leah and Rachel tribes, although
he also considered the existence of the so-called co-wives to be important as
indicators of other tribes in Palestine.22 However, only the conquest of Palestine
by the Rachel tribes under the command of Joshua is considered the proper
my book Early Israel, this idea is not far from modern socio-anthropological
notions of ethnicity.27
Wellhausen was, however, wrong on one point – namely, that this system
of social organization was favourable to individualism. This is not the case; it
rather points to collectivism, though at a local level. The difference between
Wellhausen’s understanding of individualism and the modern discussion of col-
lectivism is, nevertheless, not a fundamental one. It merely delimits the system
of social references among so-called primitive peoples. We may conclude that
Wellhausen was basically correct. Primitive cult is individualistic. However, it
is not the concern of a single person, but a group of peoples.
Bernhard Stade
idé fixee, which went back to the monarchy; but it is his intention to emphasize
(in accordance with Wellhausen) that Israel, as a national entity, was no older
than the monarchy. Therefore, the Old Testament picture of pre-monarchical
Israel is not to be dated before the monarchy.32 No unity existed before that date,
especially no system of twelve tribes. Such a system has, according to Stade and
Wellhausen, played any practical political role, as it is impossible to describe
any moment in Israel’s history where all twelve tribes existed simultaneously.33
I am not going to deal with Stade in extenso, and therefore I do not comment
on his second main work, his Old Testament theology,34 and shall confine my
remarks to his Geschichte des Volkes Israel. The general outlook of this exhaus-
tive work is easily appreciated since Stade accords, on most points, with the
views of Wellhausen and draws on the same corpus of sources as Wellhausen
had. Questions of detail are immaterial since most of his arguments are dated.
The fundamental disagreement between Stade and Wellhausen regarding the ori-
gin of Israel is that Stade speaks of a prolonged Israelite sojourn in Transjordan
before settlement in the Cisjordan. During their stay east of the Jordan, Israelites
changed occupations from nomads to farmers.35 Even such a difference of opin-
ion is apparent only because the brevity of Wellhausen’s description disguises
his proper sociological evaluation of the period.
Stade is, however, totally in agreement with Wellhausen when he argues that
the Israelites, or the Hebrews – as he also calls them, though without any idea of
the sense of this term (his history was published the year before the discovery of
the Amarna letters) – were originally nomads who wandered the steppe between
the desert and the sown.
More important is the difference of opinion between Stade and Wellhausen
in regard to the character of Israelite settlement in Cisjordan. Stade claimed
that Israelite settlement should not be viewed as a single mass invasion into
Cisjordan or even as a sequence of conquests, reflected by the existence of
such tribal groups as Leah and Rachel tribes. He is much more on the wave-
length of Albrecht Alt when he argued that we speak of a process of settlement
described as an infiltration from Transjordan into Cisjordan, a process of long
duration. Stade, however, did not consider these invaders to have been small-
cattle nomads. According to him, they were farmers or, better, surplus members
of the Transjordanian agricultural community. Such surplus was the result of
an Israelite transition to agriculture, including the establishment of permanent
settlements in the Transjordan. Settlement in the Cisjordan was, accordingly, the
outcome of an emigration, provoked by a growing population, regulated by the
emigration of the surplus population.36
Hermann Guthe
several stages. Guthe was able to draw on information from the Amarna let-
ters and considered the Hebrews mentioned there to be identical with the Leah
tribes. He placed the settlement of this tribal group just after the turn of the four-
teenth century bce. The decisive conquest occurred 100 years later, carried out
by the Rachel tribes or, more precisely, the tribe of Joseph under the command
of Moses and Joshua. The Joseph tribe penetrated the area from a point in the
Sinai Peninsula after having been converted to Yahwism at the ancient Yahweh
sanctuary at Kadesh.41
It is characteristic of Guthe that he tries to reconcile Wellhausen’s under-
standing of the development of Israel with information contained in the Old
Testament itself, and, in doing so, he weakens the ideas of Wellhausen because
under the influence of the rapidly growing external evidence, he is inclined
to retain more and more of the Old Testament tradition as historical. He was
thereby confronted with another problem: that he did not possess a satisfying
understanding which would enable him to distinguish between sources with
useful information and secondary sources. Consequently, Guthe’s approach to
his sources must necessarily be arbitrary. He chose texts which gave sense to
his theories and tacitly bypassed other passages in the Old Testament which did
not suit this picture of historical development. The result is that he presented
a historical reconstruction of the early history of Israel which does not derive
from either Wellhausen or the Old Testament. Guthe was trapped by a dilemma
which made its impact upon all studies of the history of Israel from the begin-
ning of historical-critical scholarship (i.e. the dilemma of how to define criteria
for the source material for the investigation).
Carl Steuernagel
The name of Carl Steuernagel has already been mentioned in this survey. If we
look at the study of Steuernagel on the Israelite settlement,42 it is obvious that
we are presented with the literary-critical method in its purest form. On the one
hand, Steuernagel builds on previous literary-critical analyses, including his
own studies on the Pentateuch and the Book of Joshua, on the basis of which he
believed it possible to distinguish Jahwistic and Elohistic sources.43 On the other
hand, his handling of these strata conforms to his era and he does not possess
any presuppositions which might enable him to evaluate the textual evidence as
41. §16–17 and 56–63, respectively, called ‘Der erste Angriff auf der Westjordanland’, and
‘der zweite Angriff auf das Westjordaniand’. On Moses and the place of revelation, cf.
§7: Moses (an Egyptian personal name), 27–30, and on the Sinai event, which Guthe
placed at Kadesh Barnea, §9: ‘Bedeutung des Aufenhaltes bei Kadesh’, 36.
42. Carl Steuernagel, Einwanderungen (1901).
43. These analyses were followed up in his commentaries Das Deuteronomium (HKAT,
1,3,1; Göttingen: Vandenhoeck and Ruprecht, 1898; 2nd edn, 1923), and Das Buch
Joshua (HKAT, 1,3,2; 2nd edn, Göttingen: Vandenhoeck and Ruprecht, 1921). Cf.
also his account in his introduction, Lehrbuch der Einleitung in das Alte Testament
(Tübingen: Mohr, 1912).
Rachel and Leah 105
historical sources. This is apparent in the first section of his study on the settle
ment. Even though he admits that the tradition about the earliest Israel is legend,
he nevertheless argues that it is possible through critical analysis to distinguish
primary themes from secondary elaborations, and use the former as historical
information.44
Steuernagel began his investigation with an analysis of the genealogical sys-
tem in the Old Testament. He presented a model for interpretation which has
been important to many scholars working on this theme since.45 Steuernagel
unhesitatingly postulates that the existence in the Pentateuch of three differ-
ent kinds of genealogical lists is to be taken as proof of the existence of three
different stages in Israel’s development.46 Dealing with the genealogies, he
also applied a model for his interpretation, borrowed from Guthe, according to
which he saw it possible to combine the genealogical information in the form
of a trustworthy history. He began with the existence of four tribes, named after
the four apical mothers: Leah, Rachel, Bilha and Zilpa. The names of these
represented more than merely four main groups of tribes; they were also the
names of four primary Israelite tribes, from which twelve tribes sprang after the
settlement.47 It was, however, not these four primary tribes, but a fifth, the tribe
of Jacob, which was the real tradent of the tradition. The tribe of Jacob alone had
been in Egypt and had fled from Egypt under the command of Moses, later to be
united with other tribes living in the Sinai – namely, the Rachel and Leah tribes.
The centre of this union was Kadesh Barnea. Later, the tribe of Leah left the
other tribes. As time passed, the tribes of Rachel and Jacob fused and left Sinai
to travel to Mesopotamia via the Transjordan. They were eventually forced by
Arameans to leave Mesopotamia and return first to northern Gilead and later to
the Cisjordan.48 Meanwhile, Leah’s tribe penetrated the country from the south
after its departure from Jacob and Rachel.49
Steuernagel offers an exact date for these events. In doing so, he refers to
Egyptian sources, especially the Amarna letters and Merenptah’s ‘Israel-stele’,
which had been discovered and translated only a few years before the appear-
ance of Steuernagel’s study.50 The Exodus must, he suggested, be placed in
the second half of the fifteenth century bce. The settlement of the Leah tribe
took place at the beginning of the fourteenth century bce, coinciding with the
departure of the Jacob–Rachel tribe for Mesopotamia. The united Rachel–Jacob
tribe was again in Transjordan about 1860 to 1360 and crossed the Jordan River
circa 1340bce.51
There is no reason to detail the incredible amount of information in
Steuernagel’s historical reconstruction. He goes into the smallest detail in his
description of the prehistory of Israelite tribes. I have mentioned a few points of
his method but will not forget the importance of his conviction that the twelve
tribes did not emerge before the Israelite settlement in Palestine.52 More relevant
to us is his view on the relation between the patriarchal traditions and the set-
tlement narrative in Joshua. Steuernagel wrote his study during a period which
was not yet influenced by the firm conviction that the patriarchs belonged to a
period earlier than the Late Bronze Age. Therefore, according to Steuernagel,
who considered the patriarchal narratives legends, they must reflect conditions
no earlier than the Late Bronze Age and tell us the same story as the traditions
in Joshua, though the wording is different, and it is possible to extract informa-
tion from each stratum.53 The Jahwist was unaware of the later settlement of
the Rachel–Jacob tribe in central and northern Palestine, and only informs us
of the conditions – his is only a fragmentary report – of the settlement of the
Leah tribe in the southern part of the country.54 On the other hand, the narra-
tives in the Book of Joshua relate the settlement of the Jacob–Rachel tribe, and
Steuernagel considered this corpus of narratives – as most scholars then did –
Elohistic. Even in the Pentateuch, the Elohist only refers to the Jacob–Rachel
settlement.55 Accordingly, Steuernagel tried to harmonize the differences
between the conquest stories in Joshua and the Jacob traditions in Genesis.56
I see no reason to evaluate all of Steuernagel’s theories about the settlement.
They are mostly dated, though some of his central ideas, such as the division
50. Cf. W. Spiegelberg, ‘Der Siegeshymnus des Merenptah auf der Flinders Petrie-Stele’,
ZÄS 34 (1896), 1–25.
51. Steuernagel, Einwanderungen, §16, 123–5.
52. Ibid., 7f.
53. In reality, Steuernagel is only interested in the Jacob tradition. Only occasionally does
he direct a few remarks to Abraham connecting him with traditions which belong to the
southern part of Palestine. On the possibility of a historical identity between the events
contained in the Jacob tradition and conquest stories in Joshua, cf. ibid., 86ff.
54. Ibid., §11: ‘Die Erzählung des Jahwisten’, 70–83.
55. Ibid., §12: ‘Die elohistischen Überlieferung im Buche Joshua’, 83–98, §13: ‘Die elohi-
stische Überlieferung im Buche Numeri’, 98–111.
56. The problem is the direction of the immigrants. Jacob came from the north, crossed the
Jordan at Adamiye, travelled on to Shechem and thereafter to Bethel. Joshua came from
the south, crossed Jordan at Jericho and travelled via Bethel to Shechem. On the other
hand, Steuernagel maintains that Josh. 3 contains remnants of an old tradition, according
to which Joshua had crossed the Jordan at Adamiye, cf. ibid., 88.
Rachel and Leah 107
between a Leah and a Rachel group of tribes, are still very much in vogue,
as is his understanding of the temporal sequence of the stages of settlement.
Steuernagel’s study is perhaps the very best example of how a seemingly excel-
lent and logical reconstruction of the early history of Israel, based on extant
source material, tampers with the data and becomes thereby an exponent of the
arbitrary and wanton biblical research at the turn of this century. On the one
hand, we have a scrupulous endeavour to extract historical information from
Old Testament sources; but, on the other, we have these same sources brutally
dismissed whenever they vary with the governing theory of the investigator.
It is without doubt possible to demonstrate that, in this case, the outline of
Steuernagel’s settlement must have been conceived before his analysis of the
source material.57 The result is that a strange fissure appears as Steuernagel stub-
bornly retains a historical nucleus of biblical narratives including the Bible’s
chronology,58 while trying to describe a development which cannot be recon-
ciled with the Old Testament picture of the origin of Israel.
It must be stressed, finally – and it is necessary to say this bluntly – that this
kind of approach owes its existence to his particular methodology, a very rigid
literary-critical analysis, conducted in a mechanical way. This method has never
been able to exert relevant historical information from the sources because
it was never constructed to do so. It is not a historical method, but a literary
approach. Another point is – and here Steuernagel and his contemporaries are
not to be blamed – the confused knowledge of the sociological groups which
may have been active when Israel came into being.
There is one instance in which Steuernagel becomes uncertain, when he is
confronted with the problem of the habiru; but here he is able to refer to the
� Amarna letters in his possession.59
incomplete state of the edition of the He
seems to consider habiru to be simply nomads and he identifies habiru of the
Amarna letters with� the Leah tribe. It goes without saying that he considered
� the
mention of the habiru in the Amarna letters as evidence of the settlement of the
� days of Amenophis IV.60 He was very traditional in his view of
Leah tribe in the
the role of nomads in the Near East, and, as a result, he manipulated the various
nomadic tribes – which may never have existed apart from in his own mind – as
if they were chess pieces. He never demonstrated any understanding of the life
and culture of nomadic societies.
57. A couple of examples: Leah is secondary in comparison with Rachel in connection with
Jacob. For that reason, the tribes of Leah were never amalgamated with the Jacob tribe
as the Rachel tribes had been. This reconstruction pays homage to the fact than Rachel
was Jacob’s favourite spouse, but at the same time it forgets that Leah was Jacob’s first
wife! Second, in the evaluation of the Jacob tradition in Genesis 31–33 and 35, all the
passages about Esau are considered ‘freie Dichtungen’; Steuernagel, Einwanderungen,
57. Third, the geographical information in Exodus 1 has no value at all; ibid., 114.
58. Ibid., 124. Steuernagel stresses that the 480 years between the temple of Solomon and
the Exodus are historically correct, and not only 12 × 40 years.
59. Ibid., 116.
60. Ibid., 116ff.
108 Biblical studies and the failure of history
Eduard Meyer
61. E. Meyer, Die Israeliten und ihre Nachbarstämme (Halle: Max Niemeyer, 1906;
repr. Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, 1967), including a contribution
by B. Luther (especially on the Jahwist). The presentation in the second volume of
Meyer, Geschichte des Altertums II 2 (Stuttgart: J. G. Cotta, 1931; repr. Darmstadt:
Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, 1965), is mainly a short resume of the content of
Die Israeliten, but here the conclusions are perhaps more pointed. This implies that the
appearance of Alt’s study on the settlement in 1925 had no consequence for Meyer’s
historical reconstructions. Perhaps it is fairer to suppose that he did not have the time to
adopt his own account to the new viewpoint.
Rachel and Leah 109
was formed by the Jahwist. The Jahwist was not interlaced at a later stage by
a redactional process with a corresponding volume of Elohistic material. The
Elohist was more likely a redactor of the Jahwistic corpus. Thus, Meyer under-
scores the idea that the Elohist, in every respect, presupposes the existence
of the Jahwist, but also that the Elohist sometimes supplements the Jahwistic
stratum with its own reformulation of the Jahwistic tradition, and, at times, with
traditions of his own. Finally, in order to appreciate Meyer’s evaluation, it is
important to notice that he considered the Elohist of Israelite origin (c.800bce),
whereas the Jahwist, in his eyes, was a Judean (c.900bce).62
As already mentioned, Meyer’s starting point was the genealogical informa-
tion in the Old Testament in toto and not merely in the three different versions
of the twelve tribe lists. He did not, however, consider this system of the twelve
tribes to be valuable historical information. He claimed that the lists of tribal
eponyms were not earlier than the Hebrew Kingdom. He also disclaimed the
possibility of any relations of the tribal lists to historical realities which might
have triggered the appearance of the various systems. Thus, the so-called Dinah
tribe is fictitious. Dinah, the daughter of Jacob, is nothing but a literary device
invented by the author of the narrative in Genesis 34.63 In the same fashion he
denied that the tribal system in the lists of the twelve tribes is a source of very
old historical facts. This was partly due to the fact that it is impossible to name
a period in the history of Israel when all twelve tribes existed at the same time,
and partly because systematization in accord with the four apical mothers is a
product of art. It should not be harmonized to agree with historical information
about the prehistory of various tribes.
It is possible, though, because of various genealogical data (which are dis-
persed throughout the Old Testament, but especially frequent in Genesis) to
describe the general cultural situation of Israelite tribes and their relations to
neighbouring tribal entities. The central sections in the study of Meyer are
devoted to this kind of investigation and we expressly draw attention to the
chapter devoted to the ‘southern tribes’, which is very brief.64 At the same time,
Meyer is not naively arguing that the information contained in the sources is
very old and he does not disregard the importance of the literary context or the
age of this context, which is important in dating the particular information. Only
on this basis does he draw conclusions about the history of the tribes.
62. The dates of J and E are clearly marked out in Meyer, Geschichte, 200. On the question
of E’s dependence on J or on the possibility that E was, in fact, trying to amend J, cf.
several dispersed remarks in Meyer, Die Israeliten: e.g., 17, on Exodus 3–4, 43, on the
Israelites in Egypt, and cf. especially B. Luther, Die Israeliten, 169. See also Meyer,
Geschichte, 200, where the whole problem is clearly expressed.
63. Meyer, Die Israeliten, 422f. Meyer does not attribute any historical value to the narrative
in Gen. 34. Should there be a historical nucleus, this is hardly anything but a reflection
of Abimelech’s dealing with Shechem in Judges 9. Genesis 34 is also at variance with
Genesis 35, where Jacob is depicted as living peacefully at Shechem; cf. Die Israeliten,
419.
64. Ibid., 299–471.
110 Biblical studies and the failure of history
the northern tribes must therefore depart from the traditional one based on the
dividing line between the Rachel and Leah tribes. According to Meyer, it is an
indisputable fact that no northern tribe arose except in Palestine. The northern
tribes did not exist prior to the settlement itself.72
Only one tribe took part in the settlement: the tribe of Israel.73 The original
area of settlement of this tribe was the mountainous region in central Palestine
or, to be more precise, the Mountain of Ephraim. This area was the centre of
the centrifugal process during which the tribe of Israel or Joseph (Meyer was,
indeed, rather irresolute as to the true name of this tribe) dispersed to the north
and to the south, but also to the east to Transjordan. This process called the
various tribes into being; but the process itself never materialized in the estab-
lishment of a rigid system of tribes before the monarchy. The situation was
always fluid and none of the tribes stopped their formative processes. Fission
and fusion were common features of all of the tribes during the Period of the
Judges.74 The process was near its end as the Song of Deborah was composed,
although not totally closed. This is a reasonable argument in favour of a date
for the settlement itself far back in the history of Palestine. According to Meyer,
the Song of Deborah belonged to the twelfth century bce and the settlement of
the Israelites must be placed several centuries earlier.75 As a matter of fact, the
description in the Amarna letters of troublesome political conditions in central
Palestine during the fourteenth century bce bears evidence of the beginning of
this Israelite settlement.76
The socio-political condition of the pre-monarchical period was considered
by Meyer as heroic. Israel was ruled by a tribal aristocracy and thus it appears
in the sources until the emergence of the monarchy. Consequently, Meyer con-
sidered the social structure of the Israelite tribal society to have been highly
stratified. Society was governed by rich landowners, a natural result of the grad-
ual process of settlement, which in the case of Israel was closed rather early.77
To the south, Judah was still half nomadic in the Period of the Judges.78 This
social structure created problems for political coherence in an Israelite tribe
and especially in the higher levels in the hierarchy. It influenced the relation-
ship between neighbouring tribes. A common political authority was normal in
a tribe, although its importance was curtailed. However, between the various
tribes, there were no permanent political relations but only small-scale leagues
or provisional alliances.79
Meyer admitted that, at least in theory, the amount of historical information
in the Old Testament about the origin of Israel was rather scanty; but, in his
reconstruction of early history, he refused to draw on the so-called historical
narratives in the Old Testament. At any rate, the value of these historical nar-
ratives is slight or non-existent and basing a reconstruction of Israel on such
material was illusory.80 These sources express retrospectively an idea of the
emergence of Israel as a national entity which belonged to a much later period
(i.e. to the early period of the monarchy).
This evaluation is also valid for the traditions about the patriarchs. In these
narratives, source material of a very different kind is included, even demytholo-
gizations of pre-Israelite heroic narratives about persons who might once have
been gods (e.g. Jacob, Joseph, Isaac and Esau).81 The literary context of the nar-
ratives about the patriarchs which are placed at the beginning of the national his-
tory, before the settlement of Israel under Joshua, forced the later history writers
– in casu J – to move the patriarchs out of Palestine again. For that reason, J
composed the Joseph history. This story is literary fiction and nothing else, and
it draws heavily on motifs borrowed from Egyptian fairy tales.82
A similar evaluation is presented concerning the narratives about the Israelites
in Egypt and the Exodus, as well as the settlement. The settlement narratives are
nothing but a late writer’s (E) collection of traditions which originally belonged
to the same milieu as the heroic narratives in the present Book of Judges. As
historical sources for the Israelite settlement, they have no value at all, or so
Meyer thought.83 The real problem is that the narratives are much later than the
events which form their themes. Although this is generally acknowledged, we
79. Cf. ibid., 507f. The changes in this system began with the rise of the monarchy.
80. Cf. ibid., 226. The earlier historical sources in the Old Testament concern events of the
late twelfth century bce. The oldest source is the Song of Deborah. In this connection,
it is important to notice that Meyer was prepared to accept that there are traces of an
old history book, but he is very imprecise here and never defines clearly what was the
importance, the content or the extent of this work. It is reasonable to think that he only
described traditions about the Period of the Judges, among which Meyer includes the
Abimelech narrative in Judg. 9, the original version of the narrative about Gideon’s
election to be king, Judg. 8:22ff. and the report on the migration of the Danites, Judg.
17. Cf. also Meyer, Die Israeliten, 226, on Abimelech and Gideon, and cf. ibid., 478f.
81. Cf. ibid., 472: ‘Hinter den abgeblaßten Gestalten des Esau, Jakob, Laban erkennen wir
die aus Göttern hervorgegangenen riesigen Heroen der Urzeit.’ The main treatment of
this subject is ibid., 249ff.
82. As concerns the story of Joseph, Meyer refers to the analysis of Luther in ibid., 141ff.
On the Egyptian motives which are used in this story, cf. ibid., 151. On the purpose of
the Joseph Story, cf. ibid., 229.
83. This opinion is most pregnantIy expressed in Meyer, Geschichte, 213: ‘Diese ganze
Darstellung [the conquest narrative in the Book of Joshua] steht in krassen Widerspruch
zu den zustanden, die wir beim Einsetzen wirklich geschichtlicher Kunde überall finden,
und ist historisch völlig wertlos.’
Rachel and Leah 113
must stress the fact that this implies that they are of no use as historical sources
without a critical pruning. Meyer, however, argues that this procedure is, indeed,
unscholarly; it is merely an arbitrary rationalization.84
Meyer’s approach is very important even today, especially when we try to
extract historical information from the source material in the Old Testament,
although his warnings against the tendency (Meyer himself says fashion) of
rationalization land on stony ground. The majority of Old Testament scholars
have, since his day, continued in the very practice he denounced. This does
not mean that his methods were infallible. A case in point is his use of the
genealogies (although reasonable in itself and demonstrating an awareness of
the fundamental problems involved) to produce a rational reconstruction of the
earliest history of Israel. In his application of the genealogical material, Meyer
was not very different from his contemporaries, because his evaluation of these
sources was determined by his preconception of the different sociological stages
of humanity and of the theory of development from one stage to the next. Meyer
was just as convinced of the nomadic prehistory of Israel, as Wellhausen and
Stade had been, not to speak of Steuernagel. His reconstruction is determined
by the old-fashioned classical interpretation of the Semites as nomads who were
always on the point of settling down in the civilized country in order to reach the
supposed higher status of agriculture. If this general view of the social develop-
ment is wrong, Meyer’s analyses, which are based on the genealogical informa-
tion in the Old Testament, must be corrected, but this does not imply that they
are totally without value.
Franz Böhl
That Meyer’s evaluation of the sources is relevant for our discussion is demon-
strated by other contemporary reconstructions of the early history of Israel. The
general impression is, however, that scholars of this period tried to incorporate
the growing pile of sources from the ancient Near East as direct or indirect
information about the origin of Israel. It was hardly possible that the evalua-
tion and application of such sources were correct. Experience tells us that new
evidence only finds its proper reception over time. This is also true for evidence
for early Israel.
A fine demonstration of this postulate is Franz Böhl’s study Kanaanäer und
Hebräer of 1911.85 From a methodological point of view, this monograph was
a model study and counted as such by most scholars. Yet, a modern scholar will
84. Meyer returns to this problem at several occasions, most pointedly in Die Israeliten,
50. Cf. also 421 on his evaluation of the understanding of Genesis 34 among his con-
temporaries, and his contemptful remark on 424: ‘Überhaupt ziemte sich den im Alten
Testament überlieferten Sagen gegenuber eine viel großere Zurückhaltung, als sie gegen-
wartig von den theologischen Historikern geübt zu werden pflegt.’
85. F. Böhl, Kanaanäer und Hebräer. Untersuchungen zur Vorgeschichte des Volkstums und
der Religion Israels auf dem Boden Kanaans (BWAT 9; Leipzig: J. C. Hinrichs, 1911).
114 Biblical studies and the failure of history
86. On the Hittites, cf. ibid., 12–30. The main reason for his unsatisfactory treatment of
the Hittites is, of course, that in 1911 it was impossible to read Hittite inscriptions.
This explains why Böhl, for example, in Kanaanäer, 28, speaks about the presence of
a northern Arabian or south Palestinian tribe of the name Hatti, which should appear
�
in Neo-Assyrian documents. Böhl approaching the observation expressed in J. Van
Seters article, ‘The Terms “Amorite” and “Hittite” in the Old Testament’, VT 22 (1972),
64–81; namely, that the Old Testament use of the terms ‘Amorite’ and ‘Hittite’ parallels
Neo-Assyrian usage, where Hatti is the name of the northern part of Syria west of the
�
Euphrates, whereas Amurru is the name of the southern part of Syria. Cf. also Böhl on
the designation Amurru, Kanaanäer.
87. Böhl, Kanaanäer, 73. Cf. also 89.
88. Ibid., 73.
89. Ibid., 67. Böhl anticipates the conclusions in M. Weippert’s excellent review of the
habiru in his Die Landnahme der israelitichen Stämme, (FRLANT 92; Göttingen:
�
Vandenhoeck and Ruprecht, 1967), 102. As Weippert formulates it: ‘Hebräer ist ein
weiterer Begriff als Israeliten. Alle Israellten sind Hebräer, aber nicht alle Hebräer sind
Israeliten.’ In reality, it should have run thus: all Hebrews are habiru, but not all habiru
� �
are Hebrews. Cf. also my Israel i Dommertiden (Copenhagen: CEG. Gad, 1972), 118 n. 5.
Rachel and Leah 115
Hugo Gressmann
We find exactly the same pattern of explanations in other studies from this
period. It is not my intention to present a survey of everything written about
the origin of Israel. I will, however, mention some important studies to describe
what the general attitude was just before the appearance of Albrecht Alt’s 1925
study of Israelite settlement.
In this connection, it is useful to include one of the most important studies
devoted to the Mosaic tradition and its historical basis. This work is an excellent
example of the methods used in the study of the pre-monarchical traditions in
the Old Testament, as classic literary-criticism was being supplemented by new
methods (especially form criticism). The work in question is Hugo Gressmann’s
Mose und seine Zeit, published in 1913.92
The first part of Gressmann’s study is devoted to a detailed survey of the
Mosaic tradition in the Hexateuch. Thereafter, he directs his attention to a
thorough discussion of the principles which govern the incorporation of these
traditions within historical reconstructions.93 By and large, Gressmann agrees
with his elder colleagues in the general evaluation of sources. They are all leg-
endary. On the other hand, he argues that it is possible, on the basis of a meth-
odological exploitation of legendary studies, to arrive at a historical nucleus of
the legends, which is applicable in a modern historical reconstruction, whose
purpose is to inform us about Israel’s origin. The first principle of such research
is – according to Gressmann – the isolation of invariable elements in the various
traditions. Such elements are not the narrative themes connected with the liter-
ary genre of legend, but are proper and place names, as well as information
about such persons and places. The second principle is to sort out parallel mate-
rial in the legends.94 It is thus typical of legends about Moses that they contain
several double traditions. The size and shape of a tradition may be wholly unim-
portant and secondary and does not permit historical conclusions; but if certain
traditions appear in different versions and include common features, this would
indicate the presence of an older layer of tradition, which might be used in
historical reconstruction. This is but a preliminary introduction to Gressmann’s
understanding of the legends as sources, but it is enough to show that he thought
the Mosaic tradition contained a historical nucleus and that a correct analysis
of this tradition enabled us to grasp the nucleus and use it as a historical source.
It was then reasonable to maintain that the identity of results demonstrated
the usefulness of the method in question and supplied us with unfailing clues
for our own investigations. The embarrassing fact is, however, that a compari-
son of the results obtained by scholars who used Gressmann’s approach or an
approach similar to his discloses a totally different situation when it came to the
central questions about the prehistory of Israel. Moreover, even though they fol-
lowed a generally sound method, scholars often put too much weight on the Old
Testament itself. Consequently, it is often rather difficult to distinguish between
proper history writing and a paraphrase of Old Testament narrative.
Gressmann himself often reached bold results by combining the biblical
tradition with his own observations, especially in the final part of his mono-
graph about Moses.95 On the basis of the sources from the Near East, he drew
conclusions about the general character of the history of Palestine in the Late
Bronze Age. In his opinion, these sources tell us about a large migration in the
area during which the Hebrew tribes settled in Palestine around 1500bce. This
wave of newcomers submerged all of Canaan. During the thirteenth century
bce, on the other hand, we find evidence of a smaller and ‘zanftere’ invasion.
The patriarchs should be viewed in the light of this situation as semi-nomads
who arrived in the southern part of Palestine before Moses (to place them later
is impossible, Gressmann argues).96 At a later date, the Israelite emigration to
Egypt followed, which he compared to descriptions of the arrival of Bedouin
groups in Egypt, known from contemporaneous Egyptian sources.97 Gresssnann
estimates Israelite population in Goshen (i.e. Wadi Tumelat) to have been
about 5000 individuals, an evaluation he based on censuses of the local popula-
tion at the end of the last century.98 Finally, the mention of Israel on Pharaoh
criticized by B. J. Diebner, ‘Es laßt sich nicht beweisen, Tatsache aber ist … Sprachfigur
statt Methode in der kritischen Erforschung des AT’, DBAT 18 (1984), 138–46. We are
often met with emotional rather than scientific arguments, even homiletic formulations,
and the mass of words shall apparently cover rather scanty source material. Especially
R. Kittel’s Geschichte des Volkes Israel (cf. below) is ‘enriched’ by such argumentation.
95. Gressmann, Mose, 393–424, Part III: ‘Profangeschichtliche Ergebnisse’.
96. Cf. ibid., 396ff., on the patriarchs and 399 on the early settlement of the Hebrews, but
also on the second wave of settlers. Gressmann considered the habiru to be part of the
�
Aramean migrations, which he dated between 1500 and 1300bce.
97. Ibid., 403. The source cited here and elsewhere is always Pap. Anastasi VI. Cf. ANET 3,
258.
98. Gressmann, Mose, 402. Already at the beginning of the present century the living condi-
tions in the area had changed. On previously rich grazing ground, there now lived a
Rachel and Leah 117
Merenptah’s ‘Israel stele’ shows that Israel was back in Palestine before the
time of Merenptah, and, accordingly, the Exodus should be placed in the reign
of Ramesses II, circa 1260bce.99
The invariable element in the Exodus tradition is the remembrance of a deliv-
ery from Egypt at the Sea of Reeds. But the geographical locus for the crossing
of the sea must be decided on the basis of a more comprehensive investigation
of the wanderings from the sea to Mount Sinai and the interpretation of the
events at Mount Sinai, during which a volcano seems to have been erupting.
The description of volcanic activity points towards the north-western part of the
Arabian Peninsula (Midian). Thus, the crossing of the Sea of Reeds did not take
place at the Red Sea or somewhere along the line drawn by the present Suez
Canal, but at the Gulf of Aqaba.100 The main station of the Israelites during their
wanderings in the desert was, however, Kadesh Barnea or, to be more precise,
the environment of present day ‘Ain Quderat. Gressmann believed the Israel
ites to have stayed here for an entire generation.101 From Kadesh, the Israelites
penetrated Palestine to the south, a settlement process during which Judeans,
but also Calebites, Simeonites and Kenites, played a role.102 However, the most
important part of the Israelite settlement did not take place before the main body
of Israelites crossed the Jordan into Cisjordan, around 1230bce.103
Gressmann then turned to describe the consequences of these events for the
history of Israelite religion, which was far more important to him than simple
historical facts. His first point seems to contradict his theory of a crossing at
Aqaba because he also argued that the Israelites never themselves approached
the Mountain of God in Midian.104 The mention of Sinai owes its existence
to an old recollection which derived from the fact that Moses did not himself
invent the Yahwistic religion. The Hebrew tribes to the south had already, before
Moses, made their acquaintance with Yahweh from Sinai.105 Yahweh himself
was of Midianite origin, but his priest, Jethro, had brought his most important
shrine, the Ark, to Moses and Israel during their sojourn at Kadesh. This initi-
ated the instalment of Yahweh (Gressmann almost calls it the enthronement of
Yahweh) as the God of Israel for all time. Israel adopted Yahweh because Israel
recognized Yahweh to be the God who had saved them from the hands of the
Egyptians at the Sea of Reeds.106
r apidly expanding agricultural population. This development did not, however, begin
before the second half of the nineteenth century ce. When Gressmann estimates the num-
ber of Israelites, who may have lived in this region, he relied on information obtained
from geographers and travellers in the area around the middle of the last century.
99. Ibid., 404.
100. Ibid., 409ff.
101. Ibid., 419ff. On the duration of the sojourn, cf. 422.
102. Ibid., 423.
103. Ibid., 424.
104. Ibid., 438.
105. Ibid., 435.
106. Ibid., 443. In the text, I have bypassed Gressmann’s eulogy of the personality of Moses,
but it should not be forgotten because it provides us with a classical example of the
118 Biblical studies and the failure of history
Rudolph Kittel
Let us for a moment direct our attention towards the most voluminous his-
tory of Israel in those days, the one by Rudolph Kittel. In his history, we find
the same conviction expressed – that it is possible to use the legendary litera-
ture in the Old Testament for historical reconstruction – as was already main-
tained by older scholars. His results were, however, somewhat different from
Gressmann’s.107 Kittel began his reconstruction with an identification of habiru
�
with Hebrews, considering habiru to have been an ethnic group. He spoke of
�
a migration of Hebrew tribes, which began already early in the second millen-
nium bce and which resulted in a settlement in Palestine between 1570 and
1550bce,108 in which the Old Testament patriarchs took part. Although Kittel
believed that the patriarchs were originally historical persons (e.g. tribal chiefs
or the like), he also considered them to be representatives of whole tribes among
whom they were remembered as part of the history of the tribe.109 The sequence
of tribes who participated in this early settlement is the same as the sequence
of patriarchs in Genesis: first Abraham, then Isaac and finally Jacob.110 During
this early sojourn of Israelite tribes in Canaan, eight new tribes were formed:
the Leah tribes (although, according to Kittel, Leah herself was originally of
the same tribe as Levi).111 The Rachel tribes existed at this early date, but they
lived in the most southern part of Palestine and later emigrated to Egypt with
Judah and Simeon.112
Kittel’s section on the Mosaic tradition is also straightforwardly presented.
After having emphasized that at least the general pattern of the tradition is true
from a historical point of view, Kittel retained much more than the general pat-
tern. His evaluation of the various events differed, however, to some degree
from Gressmann’s. He vehemently opposed that Mount Sinai was situated in
impact which the time of the individual scholar has upon his historical reconstructions.
In his survey of Moses’s character, Gressmann mentions the following remarkable fea-
tures: ‘Energie, Arbeitskraft, Klugheit, Gerechtigkeitssinn’, and ‘Liebe zu seinem Volk’.
Perhaps it is imperial Germany’s ideal of a public servant? Cf. ibid., 479–80.
107. R. Kittel, Geschichte des Volkes Israel, I (Gotha: Friedrich Andreas Perthes, 1888), here
quoted after the sixth edn (Gotha: Leopold Klotz, 1925).
108. Ibid., I, 291ff.
109. Ibid., I, 270ff., on the patriarchs as historical persons and tribal chiefs.
110. Ibid., I, 296.
111. Ibid., I, 301. Already at an earlier point in his history, Kittel explained why the system of
twelve tribes is secondary, but nevertheless contained remembrances of the developmen-
tal history of the Israelite tribes, ibid., I, 297–8. Dinah was considered by some scholars
to be the leftover of an extinct tribe of that name. Kittel, however, justly opposed such an
idea; ibid., I, 297. On the other hand, he incorrectly used the narrative about the birth of
Jacob’s sons, Genesis 29–30, as a source of tribal history, especially of the sequence in
which the tribes came into being. This sequence is hardly anything but a literary device;
cf. my Israel i Dommertiden, 106f.
112. Kittel, Geschichte, I, 301ff.
Rachel and Leah 119
Arabia and the Sea of Reeds at Aqaba.113 Mount Sinai is to be placed at Kadesh
and was one of ‘the stately mountains around Kadesh’.114 The tradition which
is connected with Sinai concerns events which took place at Kadesh. Hereafter,
it was easy for Kittel to retain the traditions in the Old Testament about Moses
and the origin of the Yahwistic faith in Israel.115 Kittel’s date for the Exodus was
classical: the Exodus itself took place during the reign of Merenptah, circa 1220
bce, and Moses died twenty years later, circa 1200bce.116
In Kittel’s reconstruction of the Israelite settlement in Canaan we see a
characteristic combination of bold hypotheses and banal paraphrases of large
sections of the Old Testament. He considered the settlement to have been a
compact event. Israelites crossed the Jordan under the command of Joshua as a
unity. After that, the tribes dispersed to their future tribal territories, which they
conquered and settled on their own.117 The Israelite conquest was also facilitated
by the presence in Canaan of Israelite tribes, who had lived there for centu-
ries.118 If we are going to summarize the analysis by Kittel of the Israelite set-
tlement, this would point to the presence in Palestine around 1200bce of three
groups or categories of Israelites: tribes which settled in the country from the
sixteenth century bce; tribes which penetrated to the south and living in south-
ern Palestine; and the House of Joseph, which crossed the Jordan in Joshua’s
day. The union between these three groups was marked by general acceptance
of all Israelites of a Yahwistic faith, which was the outcome of a direct inven-
tion of Joshua. Joshua invited the tribes to send representatives to a diet to be
held at Shechem. The result of this was an alliance of all Israelite tribes.119 A
process of canaanization followed, which, which had serious consequences for
the Israelite mode of life, but also for religion, especially among common men.
The maintenance of a pure Yahwistic faith was hereafter a matter of religious
113. Ibid., I, 343ff. Kittel stressed that the earlier sources mentioning the place of Yahweh
are all of north Israelite origin. They do not demonstrate any precise knowledge of the
geographical localities since they just use the geographical names Seir and Edom in a
general way for the regions to the south of Palestine. On the other hand, Kittel points at
the fact, perhaps as the first, that the argument that the description of the revelation at
Sinai indicates the experience of a volcanic eruption is naive and faulty. Clearly this part
of the narrative alone owes its existence to later ideas of theophanies. There is hardly any
reason to invest much effort in the endeavour to find still active volcanoes in the region
to the south of Palestine or to the south-east in order to consider which volcano was the
place of revelation. Cf. ibid., I, 348.
114. Ibid., I, 346. This is a very revealing remark since it illustrates how important a firsthand
knowledge of topography is for a precise historical-topographical conclusion. There are,
of course, no stately mountains around the oasis of Kadesh.
115. Cf. ibid., I, 346ff., §35: ‘Der geschichtliche Hergang. Aufzug und Wüstenzug’, and
378ff., §36: ‘Mose und seine Religion’.
116. Date of the Exodus: ibid., I, 370 (cf. also 395). The death of Moses: ibid., I, 395.
117. Ibid., I, 406. Kittel’s claim that the biblical concept of the conquest followed a precon-
ceived general plan is true (i.e. the conquest followed a scheme which followed the
occupation of individual tribal territories).
118. Ibid., I, 422.
119. Ibid., I, 438.
120 Biblical studies and the failure of history
elite, which consisted of the priestly class living at religious centres, especially
the sanctuary of Shiloh.120
Ernst Sellin
about Moses was embellished in many respects in the different sources. There
is nothing, in fact, which proves that Moses was originally considered to have
been a Levite or priest. He was an ordinary shepherd like the majority of his
kinsmen. Only the priestly source contains an expressed acknowledgement of
Moses as a member of the tribe of Levi. The first meeting between Moses and
the historical Levites took place at Kadesh, but this is not evidence for the
descent of Moses.129
Only one thing is certain concerning the early life of Moses, Sellin argues:
the flight to Midian.130 Although Moses introduced Yahweh to Israelite fugi-
tives from Egypt, he did not turn Yahwism into the national religion of Israel.
Before he could achieve this, he was murdered by rebellious Israelites during
their sojourn in Transjordan, or so Sellin postulated.131 The honour of being a
true advocate of Yahweh is bestowed on Joshua, as is well recognized from
Joshua 24.132
The historical reconstruction of the settlement by Sellin is, on the other hand,
not very different from Kittel’s. Even Sellin talked about a greater united migra-
tion into central Palestine, followed by an expulsion of the Israelite population
that had lived there for many years.133 Finally, Sellin presents us with fixed dates
for most of the events during this early period. Moses died circa 1200bce, and
Joshua circa 1190bce, while Deborah quickly conquered the Canaanite coalition
circa 1170bce and Gideon fought against the Midianites just twenty years later,
followed by the acts of Abimelech after another twenty years, etc.134 Kittel’s
description of the Period of the Judges does not deviate in any important respect
from that presented by his contemporaries. Kittel also stressed the consequences
of Canaanite culture on the Israelites, the result of which was that Israelite folk
religion did not change in any important respect before the exile.135
C. F. Burney
I close this survey of the study of early Israelite history from 1878 to 1925
with a few remarks about the most important monograph on this subject by a
scholar who was not a member of the community of German biblical scholars
129. Ibid., I, 80. Also Sellin had his bet on the character of Moses. The older traditions are
supposed to tell about a man ‘von eisener Energie, Leidenschaft, ja Jähzorn’, whereas
the younger have mollified this impression by showing Moses to be meek; Geschichte,
I, 79.
130. Ibid., I, 80.
131. Ibid., 1, 77–8. Cf. 94: ‘Die Ermordung ihres Führers wurde für die Moseschar das Signal,
die Gefilde bei Sittim zu verlassen’.
132. Ibid., I, 97ff.
133. Ibid., I, 96.
134. Ibid., I, 139ff. Sellin sometimes seems rather blood thirsty. He also ‘murders’ Gideon or,
to be precise, Jerubbaal, whom he considered Gideon’s elder brother; ibid., I, 110.
135. Ibid., I, 14.
122 Biblical studies and the failure of history
136. C. F. Burney, Israel’s Settlement in Canaan: The Biblical Tradition and its Historical
Background (The Schweich Lectures, 1917; first edn, London: Oxford University Press,
1918; third edn, 1921).
137. Burney deals with the biblical chronology in Israel’s settlement, 4–5. The list runs:
Moses, Joshua, Othniel, Ehud, Barak, Gideon, Jephtah, Samson, Eli, Samuel, Saul,
David – in all, twelve names representing twelve generations, in accordance with the
notice in 1 Kgs 6:1 that the period from the Exodus to the temple of Solomon comprised
480 years (i.e. twelve generations of each forty years).
138. Burney, Israel’s Settlement, 52.
139. On the settlement and composition of Judah, cf. ibid., 30–31. The specific origin of Judah
and its prehistory also explains Judah’s and Simeon’s later isolation in comparison with
the northern tribes, reflected in the Song of Deborah, which does not contain any mention
of the southern tribes. In Burney’s time, this relationship was generally explained as the
result of the presence of a Canaanite enclave in central Palestine (Jerusalem, Beeroth
and Gibeon), which formed a barrier to the free communication between northern and
southern tribes. Only Sellin opposed the idea, in his Geschichte, I, 106. Sellin was right
– as seen from his own perspective. If the habiru were able to move freely around in
�
the whole area in the Amarna Age and if the habiru were nomads, a more than usually
�
determined effort was needed if the Canaanite city-states were to prevent the yearly
migrations of the nomads. This would also be valid in the case of Judah or Israel, if these
tribal groups were nomadic at the time. The argument is, however, invalid if the tribes
were already settled in the Period of the Judges.
140. Burney, Israel’s Settlement, 73.
Rachel and Leah 123
SA.GAZ (which, by the way, shows up much more frequently in these letters
than the phonetic spelling habiru) did not concern the habiru. The SA.GAZ
�
should be phonetically spelled habbatum, ‘brigands’, or� so he believed.141 In
�
line with German scholars, he related the patriarchs to the Arameans – he even
spoke about a small Aramean tribe with the name Rebecca.142 Finally, Burney
dated the Exodus to the reign of Merenptah, identifying the ‘oppressor of Israel’
with Ramesses II.143
1. First and foremost we may stress the amount of very detailed accounts of
the earliest history of Israel which appeared in those days and which dwarf
most of what has appeared since then.144 We are immediately tempted to
ask whether it is possible to know as much as scholars claimed? There
are, however, other reasons for the size of, for example, Rudolph Kittel’s
Geschichte des Volkes Israel, to which I shall return.
2. The extent of the discussion about the epistemological problems of histor-
ical research is negligible. Also negligible are references to such a discus-
sion in other disciplines, especially in general history. The consequence
is not any lack of methodological considerations as to the correct usage of
the biblical sources (see also points 3 and 5), but a too uncritical accept-
ance of the biblical account in its main points. Nobody was – so to speak
– discouraged by the unique character of Israelite history.
3. The lack of methodological reflection has two consequences. First, schol-
ars tried to reproduce the biblical tradition as far as possible. The result
was a ‘rationalistic paraphrase’, to use an expression coined by Mario
141. Ibid., 66–7. His evidence is EA 299:26: LÙSA.GAZ.MEŠ-tum. This example can hardly
be valid for all other instances of SA.GAZ in the Amarna letters, where this -tum is
lacking. Cf. also J. Bottéro, Le problème des habiru à la 4e rencontre assyriologique
�
internationale (Cahiers de la Société asiatique 12; Paris: Impremerie nationale, 1954),
110 n.
142. Burney, Israel’s Settlement, 85. It is tempting to cite E. Meyer’s scornful remark of how
grotesque such a naive usage of the tribal names is in the reconstruction of tribal history.
If we were supposed to do the same with the personal names in the Homeric epic, Helena
might have been a tribe, which by force had been removed from its home territory by
the cruel tribe of Trojans, followed by a tribal war between local tribes provoked by this
event; cf. Meyer, Die Israeliten, 423.
143. Burney, Israel’s Settlement, 83.
144. It is true that R. de Vaux’s Histoire ancienne d’Israël (Paris: Lecoffre, 1971–3) was
planned to surpass all earlier histories of Israel in size and thoroughness, but this opus
was never finished. De Vaux reached only the Period of the Judges, and this far only
fragmentarily.
124 Biblical studies and the failure of history
145. Cf. especially his ‘Storiografla politica hittita – II: Telipinu, ovvero: della solidarietà’,
OA 16 (1977), 105–31, especially 105–8. Cf. already M. Liverani, ‘Problemi e indirizzi
degli studi sul Vicino Oriente antico’, Cultura e Scuola 20 (1966), 72–9.
146. Cf. Diebner, ‘Es läßt sich nicht beweisen’, DBAT 18 (1984), 138ff.
Rachel and Leah 125
peoples or places mentioned by the legend.147 This does not mean that the
narrative is history, whereas the persons or places are not. In the patriar-
chal narratives, most of the localities are, of course, historical facts, with
only a few exceptions, like Sodom or Gomorrah. We are, accordingly,
entitled to suppose that most localities were in existence when the narra-
tives were composed; but whether they also existed in the remote past, in
the so-called Patriarchal Period, is a different question. The connection
between persons and places in a narrative is not a matter of course; but the
relationship between the events, the persons and the localities is casual,
which means that we must not accept that such relations are an a priori
fact.148
In modern Old Testament scholarship, the honour must go to John Van Seters
for calling attention to Olrik’s now more than 75-year-old rule for legendary
research, not because the rules themselves are the final truth, but because they
represent an alternative to the rules for legendary research on which too much
study of Israelite history has blindly relied.149
The modern idea of the historical value of biblical tradition about the pre-
history of Israel may best be illustrated by a couple of citations relevant to the
traditions of the Rachel and Leah tribes. The authors are Sigmund Mowinckel
and Martin Noth. I hereby bypass the much more conservative accounts by
William F. Albright and his disciples.
In his Festschrift article for Otto Eissfeldt, Mowinckel concludes his study:
147. The laws of Olrik were published in a German translation as ‘Epische Gesetze der
VoIksdichtung’, Zeitchiift für deutsche Altertum 51 (1909), 1–12. A short résumé in
English is present in J. Van Seters’s Abraham in History and Tradition (New Haven, CT:
Yale University Press, 1975), 160–61.
148. Cf. further my Early Israel, 379ff.
149. Van Seters, Abraham, 160–61, and passim.
150. S. Mowinckel, ‘“Rahelstamme” und “Leastamme”’, in Von Ugarit nach Qumran
(Festschrift Otto Eissfeldt; BZAW, 77; Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1958), 129–50, cf. 150.
126 Biblical studies and the failure of history
151. M. Noth, Geschichte Israels (Göttingen: Vandenhoeck and Ruprecht, 1950), 85.
152. J. Bright, A History of Israel (London: SCM, 1960), 125–6.
153. E. Nielsen, Grundrids af Israels historie (2nd edn; Copenhagen: CEG Gad, 1960);
B. Otzen, Israeliterne i Palæstina (2nd edn; Copenhagen; CEG Gad, 1982).
154. Nielsen, Grundrids, 38–43. E. Nielsen, however, notices that the Spiegelbergian hypoth-
esis in its original form was too simplistic to account for the much more complicated
historical process of settlement; ibid., 42. Cf. further Otzen, Israeliterne, 75–95 (a chap-
ter with the heading ‘The Two Waves of Settlement’).
Rachel and Leah 127
well known. Let us therefore mention only a few examples, concentrating on the
question of Rachel and Leah. Siegfried Herrmann pays no attention to the divi-
sion into Rachel and Leah tribes, and his evaluation of this question is very much
the same as Mowinckel’s. The partition has nothing to do with the conquest, but
reflects the areas in which the tribes settled in pre-monarchical Israel.155
Other scholars, however, still maintain the idea of two or more separate
Israelite settlements and think that this is reflected by the division of the land
according to apical mothers. Roland de Vaux endeavoured to connect the two
groups with two different exoduses from Egypt, but he has not been followed
in this. His theory is a vivid example of the level of rational paraphrase of his
Histoire ancienne.156 A more classic reconstruction of the process of settlement
is that of Georg Fohrer, since he, much as earlier scholars, speaks of Israel’s
four primary tribes and their respective settlements. Fohrer also maintains the
traditional idea, according to which the tribes of Levi and Simeon lived in cen-
tral Palestine only to be driven away by the arrival later of the Rachel tribes.157
Finally, Herbert Donner, in his new Geschichte des Volkes Israel and in spite
of many reservations, which try to explain the amount and purpose of the genea-
logical speculation in early Israel, argues in favour of viewpoints very much
the same as Fohrer’s. Therefore, Donner does not believe that a land division
according to apical mothers is merely a product of late speculation. In reality,
he operates with several waves of immigration.158
There is really no need to continue the specific theme of the Rachel and Leah
tribes. This subject was chosen as a single example among many of a general
problem. The problem is plainly that we want to know more than is possible. In
my Early Israel, I stressed two rather common-place axioms:
155. Cf. S. Herrmann’s excursus in his Geschichte Israels in alttestamentlicher Zeit (2nd ed.;
München: Chr. Kaiser, 1980), 137–39.
156. De Vaux, Histoire ancienne, I, 358. The most thorough and critical review of the Histoire
ancienne has been published by M. Liverani, in OA 15 (1976), 145–59. Liverani actually
stresses that the Histoire ancienne by de Vaux fails as a synthesis since it contains far too
much paraphrase and analytical argumentation.
157. G. Fohrer, Geschichte Israels (Heidelberg: Quelle and Meyer, 1977), 52.
158. H. Donner, Geschichte des Volkes Israel und seiner Nachbarn in Grundzügen, I
(Göttingen: Vandenhoeck and Ruprecht, 1984), 61.
159. Lemche, Early Israel, 414.
128 Biblical studies and the failure of history
160. De Vaux, Histoire ancienne, I; vol. II is, of course, much less thoroughgoing since it
contains only a collection of sketches and preliminary studies of the Period of the Judges.
The neo-conservative attitude of Herrmann is well known and was already present in his
Israels Aufenhalt in Ägypten (SBS, 40; Stuttgart: Katholisches Bibelwerk, 1970). As a
matter of fact, his attitude is deceptive because more than twenty years ago he published
an important contribution to a re-evaluation of the early history of Israel as ‘Das Werden
Israels’, TLZ 87 (1962), 561–74.
161. Fohrer, Geschichte; A. Lemaire, Histoire du peuple hébreu (Paris: Presses Universitaires
de France, 1981); H. Jagersma, A History of Israel to Bar Kochba (London: SCM, 1994).
162. Of course, there is evidence of some fundamental problems for the study of the history
of Israel when the treatment of the prehistory reaches a quite inappropriate size, whereas
the period of the monarchy – not to speak of the exilic and post-exilic periods – receives
scant attention. It is quite normal to see when we reach the era of David and Solomon
that more than half of a history of Israel is finished, although the known history of Israel
only begins at this point. The reason is not merely that it is easier to discuss at length
what is not known than what is well known. The attitude of the historians, rather, reflects
the modern ideology according to which the oldest is automatically the best because
it is original and genuine. Therefore, it is important to the historian that the Israelite
society, its culture and religion and, at least, the essential content of its literature had
obtained the final form before the introduction of the monarchy. The monarchy should
Rachel and Leah 129
not be allowed to have contributed to the Israelite tradition in any positive way. See this
emphatically in the general attitude of a major work in N. K. Gottwald, The Tribes of
Yahweh (Maryknoll, NY: Orbis Books, 1979). Gottwald’s entire work is permeated by
what is best described as neo-romanticism.
163. E.g. in Fohrer, Geschichte Israels, 23.
164. Herrmann, Geschichte, 54–9.
165. Donner, Geschichte, 22–7.
166. T. L. Thompson and D. Irvin, ‘The Joseph and Moses Narratives’, in J. H. Hayes and
J. M. Miller, Israelite and Judaean History (London: SCM, 1977), 149–212. It is a pity
that many of the contributions to this work are not of the same opinion with regard to
their evaluation of the application of ancient documents. It would be better to say that the
contributors are generally in agreement with, for example, Fohrer, Herrmann or Donner.
An exception to the rule is J. A. Soggin’s new A History of Israel (London: SCM, 1985).
167. Cf. M. Noth, Überlieferungsgeschichte des Pentateuch (Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche
Buchgesellschaft, 1966), 172–91, and about the burial tradition, especially 186ff. Cf.
also the short résumé in Geschichte Israels, 127–8.
130 Biblical studies and the failure of history
168. N. P. Lemche, ‘On the Problem of Studying Israelite History’, BN 24 (1984), 94–124.
169. M. Liverani, ‘Memorandum on the Approach to Historiographic Texts’, Or NS 42
(1973), 178–94.
Rachel and Leah 131
There are several alternative ways of studying the oldest history of Israel
which are more fertile and which are possible as soon as we have acknowledged
both what we know and what we do not know. The historian should not leave
it to colleagues who are specialists in biblical literature to evaluate the histori-
cal sources as literary products. They need themselves also sort out the factors
which decided the shape of the historical tradition when it was composed by
its writers – for example, why the prehistory of Israel was described as a heroic
period in the same manner as writers from other civilizations described their
past. The identity between, for instance, the view of the Greeks about their leg-
endary prehistory, of the Romans of their past, or of the Teutons, etc., is more
than just a casual resemblance. The description of the early history of such
peoples reflects the ideological point of view of their authors. The resemblance
between Greek, Roman, Teutonic or Israelite heroic periods indicates, accord-
ingly, common structures and a common mentality, though the authors belonged
to quite different cultures. They shared and produced descriptions of the past
which follow analogous lines.
The work of the historian is therefore to unveil such mental structures in
order to clarify how they worked in the composition of the historical narrative
and to use them as analytic tools. Such structuralist studies are not only inves-
tigations of narrative texts, but, as my colleague Hans Jørgen Lundager Jensen
has already demonstrated in the Scandinavian Journal of the Old Testament,
it is really historical-critical scholarship.170 Historical research which pays no
attention to such subjects is therefore neither historical nor critical because it
leaves out of consideration the level of knowledge which we already possess.
The division of the Israelite tribes according to apical mothers does not
intend to provide precise historical information. Neither is it an expression of
Israelite genealogical speculation. It is an expression of a specific Israelite way
of systematizing the knowledge of their own generation by the authors of the
narrative and by their readers. The real task of the historian is to find the Sitz im
Leben of a systematic thinking of this variety.
Any part of the Old Testament description of Israel’s prehistory may be
examined in the same fashion. The concept of the Exodus which, as is well
known, plays a considerable role in the consciousness of the Old Testament
writers should not necessarily be interpreted as historical remembrances from
the remote past, but as the expression of the period in which the Exodus narra-
tives were drafted, which is now understood to be the period of the Exile. But
why, then, an Exodus from Egypt?171
Even though the country from which the Israelites escaped may be immate-
rial or only have symbolic status, the presence of a remembrance about Egypt
and the delivery in various pre-exilic prophetical sayings, especially by Hosea,
170. Cf. especially H. J. Lundager Jensen, ‘Die Frauen der Patriarchen und der Raub der
Sabinerinnen’, SJOT 1 (1987).
171. We must, however, not forget that the ‘original’ Exodus in the Old Testament, the one by
Abraham, was from Ur in Chaldea (i.e. from Mesopotamia).
132 Biblical studies and the failure of history
indicates that the Exodus idea was not totally unknown before the Exile.172 But it
is also relevant in this case to ask whether it is a remembrance of an event which
took place perhaps more than half a millennium before Hosea’s own time, or
whether the idea originated in events or experiences of a much later date (or
even of an earlier date?).
It would be easy to add more examples. It is hardly necessary. The result
is clear. The historian whose subject is the history of Israel has to decline the
temptation to force his sources to yield illegitimate information which thereby
destroys his theme. The sources must be studied for what they are: information
about themselves.173 After that, they may potentially also be studied for what
they are not: information about events and conditions outside themselves.
If we review the fourth point mentioned above, the question of harmonizing
biblical data with extra-biblical data, this is apparently a false problem. It is a
confusion of different categories when we try to reconcile sources for the history
and culture of Palestine in the second millennium bce outside the Old Testament
and the biblical narrative about the pre-monarchical period because the Old
Testament sources are not relevant to the second millennium bce but to the first.
There are, accordingly, no common denominators between biblical information
and ancient Near Eastern evidence relevant to the second millennium bce. It is
better to investigate the possibility of a common denominator between biblical
evidence about the pre-monarchic period and external evidence about the his-
tory of Israel in the first millennium bce.
172. Cf. on the historical remembrances in the pre-exilic prophetic literature, Lemche, Early
Israel, 306–28.
173. Cf. Liverani, ‘Memorandum’, 179.
8
It may be rather imprecise to call the Old Testament a Hellenistic book – as not
all Old Testaments can be Hellenistic. It is obvious that the Septuagint must be
considered Hellenistic since it was not translated before the Hellenistic period.
The Hebrew Bible is, on the other hand, not a Hellenistic book for the simple
reason that it – in its present shape – is a Jewish rabbinic collection of writings,
no earlier than the second century ce (although the beginning of the process of
canonization can be traced further back).
It is, therefore, reasonable to connect the appearance of the Hebrew Bible
with the historical catastrophes that drastically influenced the life of Jewish
communities, especially in Palestine, at the end of the first century ce and in the
first half of the second century ce, which threatened to remove Jews from his-
tory. Also a new threat to the Jewish faith may have been important – that is, the
Christian religion, which (although originally part of the Jewish world) devel-
oped into a major opponent to Jewish religious society. Moreover, Christianity
argued that it had replaced the Jewish religion as the only legitimate faith.
According to James Barr, R. H. Lightfoot once claimed that the origin of
the New Testament should be sought in the moment early Christians, under the
impression of the first Roman persecutions, lost faith in the survival of their
religion. As a result of their fear, they decided to write down their traditions and
recollections in order that these might not be lost or deliberately perverted.1 The
canonization of the Hebrew Bible may also have been caused by such motives,
not to be separated from the fact that the Jews had seen their religious centre, the
temple, defiled and destroyed, and – probably before the process of canonization
had reached its goal – had had to evacuate their traditional religious home,
Jerusalem, to become foreigners in their own land.2
A number of differences exist between the Hellenistic Septuagint and the
later Hebrew Bible. One of them consists of the fact that a number of books in
the Septuagint are not included in the Hebrew Bible, although they are certainly
1. Cf. James Barr, The Bible in the Modern World (London: SCM, 1973), 43.
2. In 135 ce, after the insurrection against the Romans under Hadrian.
134 Biblical studies and the failure of history
3. Thus the references to the Tana(kh) in other writings – for example, in the Prologue to
Jesus Sirach and the New Testament – can hardly be considered conclusive evidence of
the originality of the order in the Hebrew Bible. This information is more likely to be an
indication of a hierarchical kind of order: first, the Law; second, the Prophets; and, third,
whatever else, without reference to the actual place of the ketubim inside the Tanakh. For
recent overviews of this problem, cf. J. A. Sandars, ‘Canon’, ABD, I, 837–58, and M. K.
H. Peters, ‘Septuagint’, ABD, V, 1093–104.
The Old Testament 135
the Septuagint was determined. Ezra’s position as the one who finally installed
the Law seems to be a creation of fairly late Jewish thinking. In favour of this,
the fact that Jesus Sirach does not know Ezra but – in his historical overview
(Sir. 42–50) – skips over the period from Nehemiah to the high priest Simon,
the son of Onias (Sir. 49:13; 50).4 The persons responsible for the selection of
5
books included in the Septuagint were thus not constrained to acknowledge
only books that could be attributed to figures of ancient Israelite history; they
were free to include whatever kind of writing – even contemporary writings –
they pleased.
However, when we compare the Septuagint to the Hebrew Bible, the impor-
tance of the author – that he must perforce be pre-Ezra – seems not always to
have been decisive, as some books in the Septuagint, such as the Psalms of
Solomon, the Wisdom of Solomon and the first book of Esdras, were not found
worthy to be included in the Hebrew Bible. In this case, other principles may
have governed the decision, perhaps only a mechanical one that no Hebrew
manuscript of these books was extant.6 It should be relatively easy to isolate
two such major principles: first, the requirement that the content of a certain
book not be in conflict with dominant Jewish-theological doctrines of the day;
and, second, the requirement that books of special interest to religious groups
such as the early Church – especially apocalyptic literature – be discarded or
represented as little as possible.7
Although these issues are interesting and, at the same time, provocative,
this is not the place to proceed further. Very little has been done from an
Old Testament point of view because of a lack of interest on the part of Old
Testament scholars, as the Hebrew Bible has obtained a position as the only
relevant version to study in Christian scholarly tradition.8 To the extent that
the already mentioned particularities of a Septuagint and Hebrew Bible may
be considered facts (insofar as we are entitled to speak about ‘facts’ in Old
Testament studies), the argument cannot be considered controversial. It is thus
time to return to the theme of this chapter: whether or not the Old Testament
was a Hellenistic book.
4. The point is well made by G. Garbini, History and Ideology in Ancient Israel (London:
SCM, 1988), 152.
5. In order not to be misunderstood, this should be stressed: it is most likely that more than
one selection of books was made and that the standardization into a single canon may
have been a phenomenon of a fairly late period.
6. Whether or not such a Hebrew ‘Vorlage’ for these books has ever existed is irrelevant to
the present argument.
7. The exception to this rule is, of course, the Book of Daniel. This is not to deny that some
earlier witnesses of the embryonic apocalyptic tradition were also accepted, say, Ezekiel
and Zechariah.
8. Pace the hard-working and learned minority of Septuagint specialists, forming the body
of the IOSCS.
136 Biblical studies and the failure of history
9. Cf. Mt. 5:17; 7:12; 22:30; Lk. 16:16; Acts 13:15; 24:14: exclusively ο῾ νόμος καὶ οι῾
προφη̃ται; cf.; however, the enigmatic Lk. 24:44: πάντα τὰ γεγραμμένα ε’ ν τω ι̃ νόμω
ι̃
Μωϋσέως καὶ τοι̃ς προφήταις καὶ ψαλμοι̃ς. Sirach, Prologue δίὰ του̃ νόμου αι᾽τω̃ν
προφητω̃ν καὶ τω̃ν α’΄λλων (cf., however, also Sir. 39:1: again only the Law and the
Prophets).
10. On this, B. Otzen, Judaism in Antiquity: Political Developments and Religious Currents
from Alexander to Hadrian (The Biblical Seminar 7; Sheffield: JSOT Press, 1990), 29.
It is the opinion of Otzen that the Samaritans deliberately broke the relationship to main-
stream Jewry, rather than being ostracized by the community of Jews in Jerusalem.
The Old Testament 137
Literary matters
The objections that can be directed against a Samaritan schism as the main wit-
ness to the existence of the Pentateuch before circa 300bce will, of course, not
make the Old Testament a Hellenistic book. It will, therefore, be necessary to
broaden the perspective of the discussion by including other aspects, literary as
well as historical
It seems obvious to most scholars that our estimate of the age of a certain
book of the Old Testament must be based on information contained in the book
itself and not on other information. Such an estimate should certainly not be
based on the existence of a historical background that may never have existed.
Although seemingly self-evident, this method is not without fault, and it may
easily become an invitation to ‘tail-chasing’, to quote Philip R. Davies.12 By
this, we mean that the scholar may become entangled in a web of circular argu-
mentation, conveniently called the ‘hermeneutical circle’ (and an inevitability
which apparently makes it more acceptable among exegetes). It is also supposed
that the reading of a piece of literature automatically persuades it to disclose its
secrets, as if no further qualifications are needed.
The first point to discuss will be the circular argumentation that is based
on a too ‘close reading’ of a biblical text. My first example is from Samuel.
Some assume that these (two books in English) must be old simply because
they say that they are old.13 The exegete who claims that the books of Samuel
11. Cf. the excellent, though rather compressed, discussion in J. A. Soggin, Einführung in die
Geschichte Israels und Judas (Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellscheft, 1991),
219–22. According to Soggin, the schism, according to later Jewish tradition, was set
back to the time of Ezra and Nehemiah, although Soggin also acknowledges that the
schism was not a decisive reality before the Hellenistic period.
12. Cf. Philip R. Davies, In Search of ‘Ancient Israel’: A Study in Biblical Origins (JSOT
supplement, 148; Sheffield: JSOT Press, 1992), 36, here used in connection with the
reconstruction of a so-called ‘ancient Israel’ based on information contained in much
later (Old Testament) literature.
13. The example is only one among many possibilities. The example might just as easily
have been the Pentateuch or any part of the Deuteronomistic History. We could easily
include also the prophetic books in the argument. Cf. N. P. Lemche, ‘The God of Hosea’,
in E. Ulrich, J. W. Wright, P. R. Davis and R. Carroll (eds) Priests, Prophets and Scribes:
138 Biblical studies and the failure of history
must perforce be old will have to accept, as his point of departure, this claim
by either rather naively assuming that Samuel was the author (as later Jewish
tradition did claim) or by a more sophisticated argumentation – for example, of
the kind often formerly used to prove narratives such as the ‘succession Story’
to be old, as only an eye-witness would have been acquainted with the particu-
lars of David’s family.14 In order to escape the trap created by such circular
argumentation and naive understanding of a biblical text, it will be necessary to
go further and find arguments not necessarily part of the biblical text itself, but
based on other sources. Such information discloses to the reader that the books
of Samuel were composed not at the very moment Israel got its first king, but
at a much later date.
The case of the books of Samuel is hardly unproblematic. Samuel cannot,
of course, be the author, since he passes away already in 1 Samuel 25, yet, to
reappear as a ghost, three chapters later. After this point, anybody could have
been the author and the only certain thing that can be said is that the composi-
tion’s terminus a quo must be at a date following the death of Samuel, which,
according to both biblical and modern scholarly tradition, would be in the late
eleventh century bce. The logical terminus ad quem for the composition must,
however, be the moment when we possess the first complete scroll or book
containing the text of Samuel as a whole. This date is not before, at the earliest,
the first half of the fourth century ce, the date of the presumably oldest Greek
manuscript (Vaticanus) of the Septuagint. As a consequence, we are involved
with a time span of no less than 1300 to 1400 years and, in principle, need to
maintain that the books of Samuel could have been written at any time between
1000bce and 350ce. It will certainly be very important to choose the right kind
of procedure to follow! Should we start at the earliest possible date, the eleventh
century bce, or at the latest possible – that is, the fourth century ce? To rephrase
the sentence: should we begin at the point where we are left with postulates
and hypotheses – that is, 1000bce – or is it preferable to start the procedure of
finding a date for the composition of the books of Samuel at the point where we
can be certain that these books existed – that is, 350ce? The simple fact is that
we do not know that the books of Samuel existed around 1000bce, but we do
know that they did in 350ce!
Although it has become standard procedure in the study of the Old Testament
to begin where we know the least and to end at the point where we have safe
Essays on the Formation and Heritage of Second Temple Judaism in Honour of Joseph
Blenkinsopp (JSOT supplement, 149; Sheffield: JSOT Press, 1992), 241–55.
14. Cf. A. Weiser, Einleitung in das Alte Testament (Göttingen: Vandenhoeck and Ruprecht,
sixth edn, 1966), 151; cf. the somewhat more interesting argument in L. Rost, Die
Überlieferung von der Thronnachfolge Davids (1926), reprinted in his Das kleine
Credo und andere Studien zum Alten Testament (Heidelberg: Quelle and Meyer, 1965),
119–253, see 234. If so, scandals in royal families may not be the subject of modern
boulevard journalists alone! It should never be forgotten who will be best acquainted
with inner thoughts of the participants of a narrative or play: the author himself who
invented its characters.
The Old Testament 139
15. Cf. also the proposal by Diana Vikander Edelman, King Saul in the Historiography of
Judah (JSOT supplement, 121; Sheffield: JSOT Press, 1991), 11–26, to read the story of
Saul and David as an ancient reader would have done it (although this is certainly a vain
hope, as Diana Edelman herself readily admits).
16. The creative activity of God in Genesis 1 is usually described by the verbs בראand
עשה. However, the light (v. 3) and the darkness (v. 9) appear not because they are his
creation, but on his direct order, (neither בראnor עשהis used in this connection). After the
appearance of the light, God makes a division (Hebrew בדל, in the hiphil) between light
and darkness (v. 4), after which, God personally makes the firmament (v. 7: )עשה. This
firmament, however, is to be considered another division, only now between different
kinds of water. The waters below the firmament are collected in one place on God’s order
and the dry land appears as a consequence. Again, it should be realized that the dry land
is not a creation of God; it just appears as a consequence of division between the water
and the land.
140 Biblical studies and the failure of history
Historical matters
At this point a shift of emphasis from literature to history is appropriate to
continue our discussion of the Old Testament as a Hellenistic book. By way of
introduction, we ask how important the historical information provided by a
biblical book is for dating the work. We should proceed in much the same way
as already indicated above, although literary issues have now been replaced by
historical. Instead of looking for the place of origin of some ideological ele-
ments, discerned in a given biblical text, we try to establish the time and place of
whatever historical information the text in question provides. In this, I shall use
two examples: the first from the book of Joshua and the second from Samuel.
The first example is easy enough to justify today as it has been long evident
that the historical ‘reality’ referred to in the book of Joshua has disappeared.
Joshua has simply nothing to tell us about the historical origins of an Israelite
nation. No prolonged discussion of Forschungsgeschichte is necessary here,
The Old Testament 141
17. Cf. N. Lemche, Early Israel: Anthropological and Historical Studies on the Israelite
Society Before the Monarchy (VT supplement, 37; Leiden: E. J. Brill, 1985), 1–79. A
much shorter résumé can be found in my Ancient Israel: A New History of Israelite
Society (The Biblical Seminar, 5; Sheffield: JSOT Press, 1988), 104–16.
18. Cf. B. J. Diebner, ‘Wider die “Offenbarungs-Archäologie” in der Wissenschaft vom
Alten Testament. Grundsätzlicher zum Sinn alttestamentlicher Forschung im Rahmen
der Theologie’, DBAT 18 (1984), 30–53.
19. The classical German description of this period is certainly Martin Noth, Geschichte
Israels (Göttingen: Vandenhoeck and Ruprecht, 1950). In more recent German histories
of Israel, such as (probably the best informed) Herbert Donner, Geschichte des Volkes
Israel und seiner Nachbarn in Grundzügen (ATD 4.1; Göttingen: Vandenhoeck and
Ruprecht, 1984) the construct has begun to crumble, and the amphictyony is no longer
part of it anymore.
142 Biblical studies and the failure of history
with their roots in the Bronze Age. Only at a much later date did ‘Israelite’
society develop characteristics of the ‘Israel’ found in the Old Testament.20 One
historical fact cannot, of course, be denied – namely, the existence of the nar-
ratives of Israel’s conquest of its land in the book of Joshua. However, these
tales have nothing to do with historical circumstances at the end of the Late
Bronze and beginning of the Iron Age. This is not a postulate, but a fact, and we
are, therefore, in the position to ask what the narratives in Joshua really tell us
about since they do not inform us of a conquest of Palestine in ancient times.
The answer is clear and obvious: the book of Joshua informs its readers of a
conquest that never happened. The next question concerns why this book of
Joshua presents information about a conquest that never happened? The answer
to this may not be as clear as the former because it is not a fact based on hard
evidence. Instead, it depends on scholarly theories and hypotheses. One pos-
sible answer could be that the tradition of Israel’s foreign origin was invented
at a later date to create a racially pure nation. An extensive number of passages
in Joshua and elsewhere in the Old Testament may be called in supporting this
answer, starting with the book of Genesis and continuing through to the book
of Ezra. If we wish to continue this line of thought, the next question will prob-
ably regard when the impetus arose which created the context, where the idea
of racial purity of an Israelite people, opposing other nations, living in its land,
could arise, as this claim cannot be supported by historical evidence. The cor-
rect answer to that question will be that such an idea arose the moment certain
individuals, who understood themselves to be Israelites, saw others whom they
did not so consider, as occupying Israel’s land. Evidently – in light of what we
know about Israel’s origins – this claim of being pure Israelites, destined to
inherit the land, must have been a late development and most probably renders
Joshua a post-exilic book, written by an author – or a number of authors – who
can scarcely have lived in the land. This suggests that Joshua is, first, post-exilic
and, second, from the Jewish diaspora. To use a Hebrew term, it originated in
the Jewish gola.
In introducing my second example, I wish to return to the books of Samuel.
The central character is David, and neither Samuel nor Saul as the narratives
about Samuel and Saul are considered a prolegomenon to the narratives about
David. It is only right to say that David is truly the great hero of Israel’s past
20. A kind of status quaestionis can be found in Diana Edelman (ed.) ‘Toward a Consensus
on the Emergence of Israel in Canaan’, SJOT 5.2 (1991), 1–116 (including contributions
by N. Lemche, G. W. Ahlström, I. Finkelstein and others), and in two comprehensive vol-
umes: T. L. Thompson, The Early History of the Israelite People (SHANE; Leiden: E. J.
Brill, 1992), and G. W. Ahlström, The History of Ancient Palestine from the Palaeolithic
Period to Alexander’s Conquest (JSOT supplement, 146; Sheffield: JSOT Press, 1992).
So far no serious reaction has come from German scholars; a book such as R. Neu, Von
der Anarchie zum Staat: Entwicklungsgeschichte Israels vom Nomadentum zur Monar
chie im Spiegel der Ethnosoziologie (Neukirchen–Vluyn: Neukirchener Verlag, 1992),
should, rather, because of its total neglect of archaeology and because of its extensive
rationalistic paraphrase of the biblical text, be understood as a clear step backwards.
The Old Testament 143
(Joshua alone might dispute that claim) and he was reckoned the creator of a
great Israelite empire, preceding the independent histories of the kingdoms of
Israel and Judah.
Laypeople as well as scholars (including the present writer21) have always
thought highly of the historicity of David and considered it an established fact.
They also believed the main part of the traditions about David and his son and
successor, Solomon, to be trustworthy information, although none of it, nei-
ther person nor event, has been confirmed or supported by external evidence,
especially by written sources from other parts of the ancient Near East. The
only written evidence about David and Solomon are from sources whose infor
mation comes from the Old Testament itself. Only a few voices of protest have
arisen that may cast doubt on the historicity of the early Israelite empire, includ-
ing the historicality of its two kings.22 Although the conclusions reached by
David Jamieson-Drake can only be considered a temporary resolution,23 it is his
opinion that we find no evidence of a united Israelite kingdom from pre-exilic
times. To the contrary, it is unlikely that a state called Judah came into existence
before the middle of the eighth century. The Jerusalem of ‘David’s time was
hardly anything but a small fortified village, occupying a territory of less than
4 hectares, inhabited by a population of hardly more than 2000 persons, includ-
ing women and children’.24 Although Jamieson-Drake’s argument will certainly
provoke other scholars to object, he presents a very strong case in favour of
abandoning the period of the United Kingdom as historic.
These two dubious cases, concerning the historicity of a conquest and a
United Kingdom, certainly point in the same direction. When we deal with the
tradition of the empire of David, we obviously have to ask why the idea of a
Davidic empire arose if it were without historical foundation. The exchange
of answers and questions that may follow will be of the same kind as the one
described in more detail above concerning Joshua’s conquest. The result of such
a discussion would probably be that a number of possible dates for the origin of
this idea of David and his empire could be proposed, either a late pre-exilic, an
21. Cf. my article, ‘David’s Rise’, JSOT 10 (1978), 2–25. Although the historical part of the
argument in that article as well as that of several other contributions by other scholars
either following in its footsteps or progressing along comparable lines may now have to
be discarded, the literary argument is still of some importance, as maintained by G. G.
Nicol, in his ‘The Death of Joab and Accession of Solomon’, SJOT 7 (1993), 134–51.
22. Cf. the outspoken mistrust of the biblical tradition in G. Garbini, History and Ideology in
Ancient Israel, (London: SCM, 1988), 21–32. Recently also D. B. Redford has presented
a negative view of the historicity of David and Solomon, in his Egypt, Canaan, and
Israel in Ancient Times (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1992), 297–311.
23. Cf. D. W. Jamieson-Drake, Scribes and Schools in Monarchic Judah: A Socio-
Archaeological Approach (JSOT supplement, 109; Sheffield: JSOT Press, 1991).
24. The calculations of the population size is, however, not presented by Jamieson-Drake but
is my own estimate, based on a calculation of population size like the one proposed in
J. M. Sasson, Jonah (AB, 24B; New York: Doubleday, 1990), 312. It should, however,
be clear that this is a very generous calculation. It would also be possible to say that the
area covered only 1 or 2 hectares, and included a population of 1000 persons or fewer.
144 Biblical studies and the failure of history
exilic or even a post-exilic one. The answer to the question why this story was
invented at all will presumably be of this type: to create an ‘Israelite’ great king
comparable to the great kings said to have ruled other nations. Biblical histori-
ans consequently turned the mythical ancestor of the Judean royal family into an
ideal king, comparable to the empire-builders of the ancient world. It might also
be argued that since this great ancestor-king never lived, it is impossible to con-
sider the stories about the Kingdom of David as historical reports concerning the
past. Rather, they present a programme for a future which will appear as soon
as the contemporaries of the historians themselves have (re-)conquered their
land. It could very well be the case that the stories about David, as well as the
conquest, aimed at creating a programme for a glorious future of Israel, rather
than a report about a past glory that never existed. Thus, these narratives could
well derive from the Persian period and the model of the great king may have
been none other than the great founder of the Persian Empire, Cyrus. It should
not be forgotten that the careers of Cyrus and David bear a number of compara-
ble traits. It is, however, also possible that the idea of the great King David only
arose in the Hellenistic period, but for comparable reasons.
More than a few scholars will be prepared to think of the books of Joshua
and Samuel as having propagandistic motives. Lately, a number of studies have
connected the composition of these books with the reign of Josiah. One such
example is provided by Magnus Ottosson who regards the book of Joshua a
product of the Josianic age with a programme for the Josianic restoration of the
Davidic kingdom.25 It should, however, be noted that while Ottosson thinks the
conquest stories in Joshua are fictional war reports and have little if anything to
do with historical facts, he still considers the Davidic kingdom to be a histori
cally established fact. Contrary to Ottosson’s opinion, his analysis (probably
correct) of the relationship between P-elements and the main D-narrative in
Joshua actually proves Joshua to be not Josianic but post-exilic, and later than
P – provided, of course, that P should be dated in the post-exilic era.26
Another scholar who thinks highly of the Josianic age as a time for the com-
position of ‘historical’ texts is Diana Vikander Edelman, who considers the
Saul–David narrative to belong to the time of Josiah, although the purpose of
writing this story at exactly this moment in Judah’s history seems more ambigu-
ous.27 It is a problem for her dating of these narratives that the Israelite people in
1 Samuel 8 demand to have a king like all other nations. Why should anybody
in the age of Josiah wish to have a king, as they already had one? As a matter
of fact, this demand can hardly be pre-exilic.28 It is therefore more likely that
the author of 1 Samuel 8 wrote during a period and for a society without a king.
Here, too, it is better to look to the exilic or post-exilic periods.29
This predilection for the time of Josiah as the creative period in the history
of Hebrew literature is, moreover, problematic. It is, after all, Deuteronomistic
historians who claim that the period of Josiah was a splendid era, a restora-
tion period and therefore an appropriate time and place for writing great litera-
ture such as Joshua and Samuel. If scholars accept the picture presented by the
Deuteronomistic circle, without examining their reasons for turning Josiah’s
period into such an age of ‘enlightenment’, they fall into the same hermeneutical
trap as, formerly, scholars such as Gerhard von Rad did, who thought highly of
the Solomonic period as background for Israelite history-writing.30 Although
this background for Hebrew history-writing now evaporates with the demise of
a Hebrew empire of the tenth century bce, scholars are tirelessly repeating the
same arguments now in connection with an era of Josiah, which they consider to
have been nearly in the same class as that of Solomon! It should not be forgot-
ten that all we know about Josiah is what Old Testament writers have told us.
No external source mentions Josiah, except those which are clearly dependent
on biblical narrative. It is primarily because the Old Testament itself says that
Josiah tried to unify all Israel in a single major state at the end of the seventh
century bce that biblical scholars believe this to be true.31 However, the Josiah
28. Unless we should choose to express a view on these narratives such as the one in
F. Crüsemann, Der Widerstand gegen das Königtum (WMANT, 49; Neukirchen–Vluyn:
Neukirchener Verlag, 1978), who maintains that they are to be considered reflections of
party politics in pre-monarchical times – not a bad idea at all if it was possible to claim
that the Deuteronomistic traditions are as old as that.
29. It may be an alternative to the idea that David became the model of later Judean kings,
especially Josiah, to transfer this honour from the presumably non-existent David to a
person whose historicity cannot be doubted, and here the obvious candidate would prob-
ably be Omri (followed by his son Ahab). The importance of the state that was governed
by these kings is certain and is also reflected by Assyrian and Moabite inscriptions. It
is also generally assumed that they reigned over a territory that included Jerusalem, if
not all of Judah. It is at least a working hypothesis that, in the period following the fall
of Samaria, the idea of a United Kingdom, which was founded on the existence in the
ninth century of the Kingdom of Omri, was transferred to Judah, and that the greatness
belonging to the old Israelite kings was at the same time bestowed on David, the mythi-
cal ancestor of the Judean kings.
30. Programmatically expressed in G. von Rad, ‘Der Anfang der Geschichtsschreibung im
alten Israel’ (1944), now in his Gesammelte Studien zum Alten Testament (TB 8; Munich:
Chr. Kauser, 1958), 148–88.
31. This reminds me of the verdict of Mario Liverani, in his ‘Storiografia politica hittita II:
Telipini, ovvero: Della Solidarieta’, OA 16 (1977), 105–31, see 105: ‘The indolence
of the historians is of great extent, and when they deal with a certain period and they
are confronting a continuous account of the course of events, which has already been
included in some sort of “ancient” documentary source (which is perforce not contem-
porary with the events themselves), then they all too happily apply this account, and
they limit their efforts to paraphrasing it or even rationalizing it’ (trans. N. P. Lemche).
146 Biblical studies and the failure of history
of 2 Kings need not be a historical character at all (though it seems likely that
shortly before the disappearance of the short-lived state of Judah, there did live
a king called Josiah in Jerusalem); he may be nothing more than the invention
of the Deuteronomistic author(s) who wrote Kings. The comparison between
David and Josiah is, of course, also a product of Deuteronomistic thinking and it
shows how the Deuteronomists worked a rather miserable king with an inglori-
ous end into a major historical figure of Israel’s history. It can also be argued that
the Deuteronomists needed a Josiah very much if they were to legitimate their
own religious programme and, in this regard, it was of no consequence whether
the Deuteronomistic History was a work of an exilic or post-exilic period.32
The discussion may pause at this point and it may be argued that the time of
Josiah, the so-called restoration period, known only from the Old Testament,
is nothing more than a product of Deuteronomistic imagination and it is not
necessarily more historical than the age of David and Solomon.33 Instead of
transferring the period of Josiah into a great time for history-writing in Israel
(or Judah), only to repeat former mistakes, it will be safer to apply the same
procedure as advocated above in connection with the dating of biblical litera-
ture – that is, to begin where we can be certain that the literature in question
really existed and, after having established that fact, proceed with our quest for
a possible earlier date. It should, however, be understood that there may be lit-
tle reason to go back to the time of Josiah, which may itself be no more than a
postulate created by Old Testament writers.
Liverani is dealing with scholarly reconstructions of the history of the ancient Hittite
empire, normally based almost exclusively on the decree of Telipinus and generally
accepting its views, and it is fairly easy for Liverani to deconstruct the content of the
edict and to show that it is a totally propagandistic and partisan view of the history of the
Hittites that is presented by the king who issued the decree.
32. It is, on the other hand, interesting to compare the description of Josiah in 2 Kings with
2 Chron. 34–35. The Chronicler seems much less enthusiastic about this king than his
Deuteronomistic source, although he duly quotes the Deuteronomistic narrative from
one end to the other. However, when he comes to the death of Josiah, the Chronicler
clearly expresses his contempt of this king who died an ignominious death because he
disobeyed a direct order from Yahweh. The Chronicler diminishes (or even ridicules:
cf. the wording of 2 Chron. 35:18, ‘No Passover like it had been kept in Israel since
the days of the prophet Samuel’, with the slightly different version in 2 Kgs 23:22!) the
importance of Josiah’s reform as described in 2 Kings by referring to Hezekiah as the
real reformer who reinstated the Passover in its former glory (cf. 2 Chron. 30). According
to the Chronicler, the reform of Josiah was no more than a copy of the one initiated by
Hezekiah (cf. 2 Chron. 31:1).
33. It should not be overlooked that some indications offered by Jamieson-Drake point at
the possibility that the decline of Judah started well before the Babylonian destruction
of Jerusalem, notably in the sector termed ‘Public Works’. Cf. Jamieson-Drake, Scribes
and Schools, 104, and charts 7 and 9, although a more comprehensive study of the period
of Josiah is badly needed, especially from an archaeological point of view.
The Old Testament 147
Other themes
study on the Canaanites – to say that ‘Israelites’ are left without any specific
ethnic affiliation at all. They simply reflect a regional selection of inhabitants
of Palestine, where they formed a late branch of the population that had been
present in Western Asia since the beginning of history. The idea of ‘Israel’ in
the Old Testament may be nothing except a very late ideological concept, as
maintained by Philip R. Davies.37
Third, the Babylonian exile: this is certainly an issue that is growing in
importance as the greater part of the Old Testament is now considered fairly
late. The whole issue of the exile could be summarized in the following fashion.
We have excellent information about the beginning of the Babylonian exile dur-
ing the first half of the sixth century bce; it is, however, far more uncertain when
it ended. The ‘official’ date of return is, of course, 538bce, when the exiles were
allowed to return as a consequence of Cyrus’s decree, or this is what is normally
assumed. However, if such a decree was ever issued, with the particular inten-
tion to send the Jewish people home, it could be maintained that the Jews of
Babylonia were offered something which they could easily refuse. Most of them
preferred to stay in Babylonia and to die there as did also their descendants for
many generations. They found little reason to leave the centre of the Persian
Empire in order to move to its fringe to one of its poorest and most desolate
provinces. It is quite ironic that the end of Jewish communities in Mesopotamia
came first in 1948ce, when the majority of the Jews in Mesopotamia were forced
to leave and to return to Palestine as a consequence of the establishment of the
modern Jewish state. I wish to stress this point, as most scholars who are prone
to date the larger part of the Old Testament to the Babylonian exile may after
all be right: this literature is really exilic. It should also be stressed at the same
time that few of the aforementioned scholars have realized that the exile con
tinued – almost forever – although its extent was self-inflicted. The sons and
daughters of deportees happily continued to live in Mesopotamia as long as the
Persian Empire existed, but also under the following empires of the Seleucids,
Sassanides and Parthians. It may even by maintained that the idea of an exile
became an obsession for the Jews of the Diaspora because it provided them
with a legitimate excuse for keeping away from a barren place called Palestine.
The following points speak in favour of a Hellenistic date for the Old Testament:
1. It is a fact that the history of Israel as narrated in the Old Testament has
little if anything to do with real historical developments in Palestine until
37. On the Canaanites, cf. N. Lemche, The Canaanites and Their Land: The Tradition of the
Canaanites (JSOT supplement, 110; Sheffield: JSOT Press, 1991). The consequences
of this are more sharply drawn by Davies, In Search of ‘Ancient Israel’. Most of this
development was, however, foreseen by the late Gösta W. Ahlström, in his Who Were the
Israelites? (Winona Lake, IN: Eisenbrauns, 1986).
The Old Testament 149
at least the latter part of the Hebrew monarchy. It cannot be denied (and
there is, as a matter of fact, no reason to deny it) that we may possess
some few genuine historical recollections; but, at the same time, it should
be argued that, from a historian’s point of view, we must consider Old
Testament literature a poor source of historical information.
2. An extensive part of this literature should be considered the creation of the
Jewish Diaspora, first and foremost, the patriarchal narratives, the story
in Exodus about Israelites in Egypt and their escape from Egypt, but also
the conquest narratives in Joshua. All of these aim at one and the same
issue – at a more or less utopian level – that a major Jewish kingdom (even
empire) should be (re-)established in Palestine, an idea that emerged in
spite of the fact that it had no grounding in an ancient Israelite empire.
3. The writers who invented the ‘history of Israel’ seem to have modelled
their history on a Greek pattern. The first in modern times to stress this
point is presumably John Van Seters,38 although his reference to Hecataeus
of Miletus may seem gratuitous, as we no longer possess Hecataeus’s
history except in the form of rather diminutive fragments. It would be
preferable to propose the history of Herodotus as the earliest point of
comparison and to indicate that there are a number of similarities between
the histories of Herodotus and the Old Testament. Both histories have as
their beginning a perspective that encompasses the world as such, and
this perspective narrows to single nations only at a later point, the Greek
and the Hebrew, respectively. I should like to stress this point without
ignoring many significant differences between Herodotus’s history and
the Old Testament historical literature.39 It is merely my intention to indi-
cate that biblical historians display knowledge of Greek tradition, and that
38. Cf. J. Van Seters, In Search of History (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1983),
and now his Prologue to History: The Yahwist as Historian in Genesis (Louisville, KY:
Westminster John Knox Press, 1992). In his book, Van Seters argues that two currents
are present in the Yahwistic parts of Genesis, one of them displaying an interest in history
proper, while the other is more of an ‘antiquarian kind’. The first current can be traced
back to the Greek historical tradition while the second is genuinely oriental, and has its
roots in Mesopotamia, in the Babylonian tradition. According to Van Seters, the meeting
place of both currents cannot be pre-exilic, but must be dated to the Babylonian exile
in the strict sense of the word. In favour of this, Van Seters discusses the possibility
that the Phoenicians were the carriers of the Greek tradition to the Orient. This sounds
like an unnecessary complication and is completely unattested. In spite of Van Seters’s
splendid defence of his exilic date, a more relevant moment can and should be proposed
for the confluence of Greek and Oriental tradition – that is, the time of the Seleucid and
Ptolemaic empires when the Greeks ruled the East. In this age, the Jews of Mesopotamia
would have had easy access to Greek as well as Babylonian traditions.
39. Other Greek historical works should, of course, be consulted as relevant to the discus-
sion, in particular Hellenistic authors, but also Livy, although Livy, being a Roman
author, can only be an elaborate example of history-writing in the Hellenistic world. The
fact, however, remains that a number of parallels can be found between Livy and the
Old Testament history, even structural ones. This may not be a coincidence but may be
a testimony of a common ‘spiritual’ (i.e. Hellenistic) background.
150 Biblical studies and the failure of history
this hardly was the case before Greek historians were became known and
read in the Near East.
4. The Persian period does not seem to meet the requirements of being the
time when the historical books of the Old Testament were composed. First
of all, it would have to be proven that Greek authors were known and
extensively read in the Persian Empire, and I doubt very much that this
was the case. Furthermore, we have to look for a suitable place where the
biblical-historical narratives may have been compiled.
One of the major problems in this connection is the fact that we have very lit-
tle information about the Persian age, at least as far as the Jewish population is
concerned. We know practically nothing about the situation in Palestine except
from the books of Ezra and Nehemiah and, although these books have generally
been highly regarded as first-hand sources of information, some critical voices
have arisen lately arguing, first, that the mission of Ezra never took place; and,
second, that the authenticity of the so-called ‘autobiography’ of Nehemiah may
also be doubted – with reference to the fact that autobiographies constituted an
acknowledged and widespread literary genre in the Greek world.40
Palestine during the Persian period hardly seems to have embraced the kind
of society in which to look for the authors of literature such as those found in the
historical parts of the Old Testament. From a material point of view, the Persian
conquest seems to have brought little positive to Palestinian society, in general.
The rebuilding of Jerusalem was evidently only on a minute scale, the Jerusalem
of Nehemiah being even smaller than the one that existed before the extensions
to the city area made by Hezekiah.41 It is certainly true that much work has to be
done in order to clarify the conditions of the Persian period, archaeologically,
if we wish to create the impression that great literature may possibly have been
composed in this age.42
40. A number of interesting viewpoints relevant to this discussion can be found in R. Davies
(ed.) Second Temple Studies: Persian Period 1 (JSOT supplement, 117; Sheffield: JSOT
Press, 1991); notably, Lester L. Grabbe, ‘Reconstructing History from the Book of Ezra’,
98–107; and R. Carroll, ‘Textual Strategies and Ideology in the Second Temple Period’,
108–24. On Nehemiah’s biography, cf. also D. J. A. Clines, ‘The Nehemiah Memoirs:
The Perils of Autography’, in his What Does Eve Do to Help? And Other Readerly
Questions to the Old Testament (JSOT supplement, 94; Sheffield: JSOT Press, 1990),
124–64. It is, as a matter of fact, an age-old position which hereby makes its re-entrance
on the scene: cf. C. C. Torrey, ‘The Exile and the Restoration’, in Ezra Studies (Chicago,
IL: University of Chicago Press, 1910), 285–340, and especially C. C. Torrey, The
Composition and Historical Value of Ezra–Nehemiah (BZAW 2; Giessen: Töpelmann,
1896). See also the discussion in Davies, In Search of Ancient ‘Israel’, 78–87, and, of
course, in Garbini, History and Ideology, 151–69.
41. It is strange to realize how uninformative even the most recent descriptions of Jerusalem
in the Persian period are. Thus J. King, in ABD, III, 757, has nothing to add to such old
books as K. M. Kenyon, Digging up Jerusalem (London: Ernest Benn, 1974), 172–87.
Both King and Kenyon merely paraphrase the books of Nehemiah and Ezra.
42. In spite of the existence of a work such as E. Stern, Material Culture of the Land of
the Bible in the Persian Period (Warminster: Aris and Phillips, 1982), a study such as
The Old Testament 151
An utterance such as the following from Philip J. King, ‘The Persian Period
was a time of peace and prosperity, when Judah was allowed a great deal of
administrative independence’, should awaken suspicion. How do we know this,
except that it is the convenient, common opinion of many scholars? Modern
examples of crumbling societies left on their own and with ‘a great deal of
administrative independence’ provide a sad picture of local incompetence, and
Jamieson-Drake’s demonstration of the total collapse of Judean society around
600bce points to socio-economic conditions in Palestine during the following
centuries that will have demanded more than the occasional visit of a Persian
emissary to settle. As a matter of fact, the often praised leniency of the Persians
towards their subject nations may have been nothing more than a display of an
absolute lack of responsibility on the part of Persia. Maybe they did not interfere
in local affairs because they did not care! A re-evaluation of Persian rule and a
realistic appraisal of the Achaemenid administrative system are much needed.
The possibility that the community in Jerusalem was organized as a ‘Tempel-
Bürger’ society, as maintained by some scholars, following a proposal made by
Joel Weinberg (e.g. Joseph Blenkinsopp and David Petersen) seems to me to be
a moot question, as very little except the idea itself speaks in favour of such a
theory.43 I have little to offer here, except that I have severe doubts about the
efficiency of Persian administration in those days, doubts caused by a report
such as Xenophon’s Anabasis. Here, in the heyday of the Persian Empire (at the
end of the fifth century bce), Xenophon, together with a minor army of Greek
mercenaries (roughly 10,000 men), participated in an expedition that brought
them to the very heart of the empire. The expedition, however, did not end here
when their Persian warlord was killed in a battle. The Greeks simply turned
around and walked home. In spite of having lost their commanding officers,
they were not only able to get rid of their Persian persecutors but to proceed
on their journey right through – at the beginning – the richest provinces of the
Persian Empire. They were met by serious opposition, first, when they crossed
the borders of Anatolia, although their opponents there were not Persian troops
proper, but local mountain tribes, seemingly the subjects of the Persian king.
Jamieson-Drake, Scribes and Schools, is most needed for this period and the available
material should be statistically analysed. The deplorable lack of material is also reflected
by the rather short description of the age from an archaeological point of view in Helga
Weippert, Palästina in Vorhellenistischer Zeit (Handbuch der Archäologie, 2.1; Munich:
C.H. Beck, 1988), 687–718. Her remarks on 697 (‘Forschungsstand’) are most revealing.
It is also the case that most of the material from this period is found in sites north of
present-day Haifa, an area that can hardly be considered part of the Persian province of
Yehud!
43. On this see J. Blenkinsopp, ‘Temple and Society in Achaemenid Judah’, in R. Davies
(ed.) Second Temple Studies 1, 22–53, and D. Petersen, ‘Israelite Prophecy: Change
Versus Continuity’, in J. A. Emerton (ed) Congress Volume: Leuven 1989 (VT supple-
ment, 45; Leiden: E. J. Brill, 1991), 190–203, see 195–203. The original formulation of
this hypothesis can be found in Joel Weinberg, ‘Demographische Notizen zur Geschichte
der nachexilischen Gemeinde in Juda’, Klio 59 (1972), 45–59, and the same author’s
‘Das beit ‘abot 6.‑4. Jh. v.u.Z.’, VT 23 (1973), 400–14.
152 Biblical studies and the failure of history
The report by Xenophon hardly indicates that the adversaries of the Greeks
were citizens in an efficiently governed state or empire! It would also certainly
be an appropriate irony – assuming a view of the origins of the Old Testament
such as that promoted by, for example, Philip Davies should be vindicated – if
most of the archaeological material of the formative period of Old Testament
literature should belong to the much neglected Persian period, as this material
has often been thrown away or placed in dumps, that archaeologists might get
down quickly to ‘true’ Israelite layers.44
It should never be forgotten that the revitalization of the ancient Near East
occurred only after the Greek takeover. It is an established fact that city life
vastly expanded after the conquests of Alexander. In this, we must realize
that innovations in Jerusalem and Palestine were comparable – although on a
smaller scale – to the cultural developments in Syria, Mesopotamia and Egypt.
This theme hardly has to be discussed further other than to point out that we
now, finally, in the Hellenistic period, get a glimpse of a society in which great
literature may have been composed, kept and loved. Scholars may nurse very
romantic ideas about what may have happened in the nooks and crannies of pre-
Hellenistic Palestine, in a society considerably poorer than the one that has been
found.45 A more sophisticated and realistic assessment of facts suggests that the
Persian period was not the time in which the Old Testament could have been
written. Hardly any parallel exists to such a development, but a lot of evidence
that suggests that the Hellenistic period was the formative period of early Jewish
thought and literature, as witnessed by the Old Testament itself.46
There is no reason to gloss over the fact that the majority of Old Testament
scholars of the present day will not readily accept new ideas such as these con-
cerning the date and ideological background of the Old Testament. A number
of reasons may be found, not all of them based on irrational, if understandable,
44. An outspoken example of the lack of interest (i.e. contempt) for the Persian Period among
Israeli archaeologists is the recent ‘standard’ archaeology by A. Mazar, Archaeology of
the Land of the Bible 586 bce (New York: Doubleday, 1990). His example is certainly
not exceptional!
45. For example, the Late Bronze Age, a society that was hardly the home of great literature,
as is clear from the Amarna letters.
46. So far, the topic under discussion has been the historical literature. That the writings
are mostly Hellenistic literature seems self-evident in the light of the present discussion
and there is no need to elaborate further on this at this point. The prophetic literature,
however, poses a special problem because this collection is normally understood to be
more recent than the Pentateuch and the Deuteronomistic History, which, according to
the Jewish tradition, is also prophetic. This is not the time to go into this here, except
to say that Julius Wellhausen’s verdict should be remembered, that the Prophets predate
the Law. The possibility that the historical literature may be late does not preclude that
the prophetic literature is yet later (the collection may be, but that is another case). The
analysis in my Early Israel, 306–36, showed that the historical tradition was unknown
to the pre-exilic prophets. My estimation of the time of composition of the so-called
pre-exilic collections may be wrong after all, but the conclusion may still be valid that
these prophetic collections predate the appearance of a larger historical narrative of the
kind found in the Pentateuch and in the Deuteronomistic History.
The Old Testament 153
d isbelief and reluctance to accept what goes against the opinio communis of
several generations. Exclamations such as ‘This is nonsense!’, ‘This cannot be
true!’ or ‘This is impossible!’ are often heard, although the argument in favour
of such ‘criticism’ will usually be of a circular kind – that is, it cannot be true
because it goes against the once generally accepted view, which is, in turn,
based on the assumption that such alternatives cannot be correct.
However, objections of a more serious kind will likely be launched against a
position like that held in this chapter:
It should be possible to answer all three questions at one and the same time
by introducing ethno-linguistic as well as socio-economic arguments, although
these need not be very sophisticated. The issues are, in fact, quite plain. The
remarkable qualitative distance between Chronicles and the Deuteronomistic
History is not merely a distance in time (the Chronicler is generally citing the
Deuteronomistic History, so this history must predate Chronicles), short or long;
it may just as well bear witness to the fact that the two histories were composed
in very different environments. It is, moreover, quite safe to assume that those
responsible for publishing the books of Chronicles were less able narrators than
the Deuteronomistic historians.
This discussion sounds much like a new version of the debate about the
respective date of J, E and P, which has lasted for more than a century. It is well
known that much of this discussion was based on arguments such as differences
of religious or political outlook, linguistic matters, etc. It was also assumed that
the Yahwist was a more simple-minded fellow (although by all means a great
narrator) than his Elohist colleague and that the persons behind P display a view
of religion (if not theology) that is quite different from that found in J and E.
Such differences were explained a long time ago by Johannes Pedersen as not
necessarily the consequence of a difference in time; they could well be the out-
come of different milieus and/or abilities and preferences of their authors.47 To
47. Cf. J. Pedersen, ‘Die Auffassung vom Alten Testament’, ZAW 49 (1931), 161–81.
154 Biblical studies and the failure of history
deny that Pedersen’s argument could be valid would be the same as maintaining
that Plato could not be a contemporary of Xenophon!
When we turn to linguistic matters, it is true that the language of Ecclesiastes
is much nearer the Middle Hebrew of the Mishna, and it is far removed from
classical Hebrew, which is the idiom of the Pentateuch and Deuteronomistic
History. Nevertheless, it should be realized that it is impossible to say whether
such differences reflect differences of time or milieu (or context). Where should
we look for the author of Ecclesiastes, and who wrote the Deuteronomistic
books, are relevant questions. Although I will not deny that such differences
may reflect different times of composition, I will also stress the fact that Hebrew
was known (if not spoken) in post-exilic times among Jews living in places as
different as Mesopotamia, Egypt and Palestine. Dialect differences, which must
have existed between these places, have been poorly studied. We must also con-
sider that it may be impossible to find evidence of such differences, as linguistic
differences have been harmonized, though certainly not totally eradicated.
Finally, in order to counter the argumentation that refers to differences
between the Septuagint and Hebrew books of the Old Testament, it should be
remembered that it is safe to assume that the Septuagint came into being in
Egypt. There is, on the other hand, no certainty that the Hebrew writings also
originated there. It is not unreasonable to think of a mixture in the Hebrew Bible
of writings which came from Mesopotamia (especially the major part of the
historical literature) and from Palestine (perhaps Ecclesiastes, certainly Daniel
and others). Neither can we totally exclude the possibility that Hebrew – as
represented by the Hebrew Scriptures – was no longer a living language. In this
period, Hebrew may have been what Ernst Axel Knauf has termed an artificial
language, a kind of ‘Latin’, perhaps ‘invented’ as the idiom of sacred litera-
ture.48 It is likely that the original Hebrew manuscripts, which were incorporated
within the Septuagint, were simply translated after having been transferred to
Egypt because of the less than inadequate knowledge of Hebrew among ordi
nary Jews living in a city such as Alexandria. There is really no reason to believe
that the Hebrew versions must perforce have been much older than their Greek
translations. To discuss an interval of 100 years or a decade, or even a single
year, is hopeless, as no hard evidence for the interval between the appearance
of a Hebrew original and Greek translations can be found in support of any of
these positions.
Theses
It is my intention at the end of this chapter to present some ‘theses’ to show that
the view of the Old Testament presented here may lead to a renewed appraisal
of its status as sacred literature for both Jews and Christians in ancient times.
These theses are all to be considered for future discussion. Here, they are only
listed. First, four theses concerning the relationship between the Septuagint and
the Hebrew Bible:49
Finally, four theses concerning the relationship between the two Testaments:
1. The lapse of time between the composition of the major part of the Old
Testament and of the New Testament must be considered minimal in light
49. Some preparatory work on this has already been published by my colleague Mogens
Müller; see his ‘Graeca sive Hebraica veritas? The Defense of the Septuagint in the Early
Church’, SJOT 3.1 (1989), 103–124, and his ‘Hebraica sive graeca veritas: The Jewish
Bible at the Time of the New Testament and the Christian Bible’, SJOT 3.2 (1989),
55–71.
156 Biblical studies and the failure of history
These theses may eventually lead to a renewed interest in the Old Testament and
save it from becoming a theological and intellectual cul de sac among Christian
believers. Traditional historical-critical research has, in spite of its many merits,
made the Old Testament a book that merely provides information about the past,
and which has little to say to modern (Christian) people. In connection with the
New Testament, the Old Testament must be considered a main topic of interest
50. This is not to deny that extraordinary intellectual achievements have been accomplished
in this field, as, for example, perhaps the most important Old Testament theology of
this century, Gerhard von Rad’s Theologie des Alten Testaments (2 vols; Munich: Chr.
Kaiser, 1957–1960). At the same time, it should be realized, however, that because of his
defining historical and redaction-historical approach, von Rad wrote a mental history of
the ancient Jews, which is legitimate in a Christian environment. A fine dissection of the
problems involved in writing Old Testament theologies in the present century has been
written by J. Høgenhaven, Problems and Prospects of Old Testament Theology (The
Biblical Seminar, 6; Sheffield: JSOT Press, 1988).
51. The opposite could be said of specialized theologies of the New Testament, as it was
never intended to be an independent part of the Bible, but certainly presupposes the
existence of the Old Testament.
The Old Testament 157
for all Christians, laypersons and theologians alike. This approach should cer-
tainly not be considered an attack on the integrity of the Old Testament in a
Christian environment and it does not prevent historical studies from continuing
to be based on the Old Testament.52 To the contrary, the Old Testament should be
acknowledged as part of the Christian canon and, as such, important to Christian
believers on a level with the New Testament. Nor should it be forgotten that
the New Testament is such a small book with a comparably narrow theme only
because of the presence of the Old Testament within a Christian canon.
Acknowledgements
52. It is not for me to judge whether a change of approach to Old Testament studies will
bring any benefit to modern Jewry. I imagine that the majority of modern Jews will
consider these to be irrelevant, but it is my hope that they will also in time appreciate
their importance for the relationship between Christians and Jews, if the Christian com-
munities will understand that the origin of the Old Testament as well as the cradle of
Christianity should not be sought among ancient Israelites, but in the Jewish society of
the Hellenistic and Roman periods.
9
Let me start this lecture by quoting the admonition of God in Exodus 23:20-33
extensively:
And now I am sending an angel before you to guard you on your way and to
bring you to the place I have prepared. / Heed him and listen to his voice. Do
not defy him; he will not pardon your rebelliousness, for my authority rests in
him. / If you will only listen to his voice and do all I tell you, then I shall be an
enemy to your enemies, and I shall harass those who harass you. / My angel
will go before you and bring you the Amorites, the Hittites, the Perizzites, the
Canaanites, the Hivites and the Jebusites and I will make an end of them. /
You are not to bow down to their gods; you are not to worship them or observe
their rites. Rather, you must tear down all their images and smash their sacred
pillars. / You are to worship the Lord your God and he will bless your bread
and your water. I shall take away all sickness out of your mist. / No woman
will miscarry or be barren in your land. I shall grant you a full span of life. /
I shall send terror of me ahead of you and throw into panic every people you
find in your path. I shall make all your enemies turn their backs toward you.
/ I shall spread panic before you to drive out the Hivites, the Canaanites, and
the Hittites in front of you. / I shall not drive them out all in one year, or the
land would become waste and the wild beast too many for you, / but I shall
drive them out little by little until you have grown numerous enough to take
possession of the country. / I shall establish your frontiers from the Red Sea
to the Sea of the Philistines, and from the wilderness to the River Euphrates, I
shall give the inhabitants of the land into your power, and you will drive them
out before you. / You are not to make any alliance with them and their gods.
/ They must not stay in your land, for fear they make you sin against me by
ensnaring you into the worship of their gods. (New English Bible)
Power and social organization 159
And I continue with another quotation, this time from Mario Puzo’s novel The
Godfather.1 The following dialogue – if not monologue – can be found at the
beginning of the book when a despairing father of a girl, who had been mis
treated by some youngsters, who had only received a mild sentence from the
court, appeals to the Godfather – the head of the Corleone family – in an effort
to obtain justice. However, the father, a caretaker, has offended the Godfather
by never calling him ‘Godfather’, and – worse – he offers to pay for the service.
What was expected in the first instance was that, before he had gone to the court
with his case, he should have involved the Godfather in seeking his revenge.
Instead, he played with ‘other gods’ (as it were), and disregarded the honour of
his own, the Godfather, who, nevertheless, forgives these offenses. Yet, before
he agrees to do what is asked he delivers a speech:
But if you had come to me, my purse would have been yours. If you had
come to me for justice those scum who ruined your daughter would be weep-
ing bitter tears this day. If by some misfortune an honest man like yourself
made enemies they would become my enemies … and then, believe me, they
would fear you.
The scene ends with the following dialogue between the applicant and the
Godfather. The caretaker: ‘Be my friend. I accept.’ The Godfather: ‘Good, you
shall have your justice. Some day, and that day may never come, I will call upon
you to do me a service in return. Until that day, consider this justice a gift from
my wife, your daughter’s godmother.’
In both places the important points are:
Many passages in the Old Testament – if not most of the Bible – follow this line.
The Deuteronomistic History contains one long tale of disobedience against the
superior being to whom Israel had sworn allegiance, and although we some-
times find expressions of the opposite – for example, in Psalm 89, where the
God is rebuked for having forsaken the faithful king of his chosen dynasty, or
in Psalm 44, in which the people of Israel have never broken the covenant – the
tone of unfaithfulness runs through the historical narratives and greater part of
prophetic literature – to the destruction of Jerusalem and its temple and the exile
of the unfaithful people of God.
It has long been recognized that Old Testament authors were not entirely
original. They made use of the relationship between superior and vassal,
known from innumerable ancient Near Eastern texts, among which the Hittite
suzerain-treaties might well offer the clearest – but certainly not the only –
examples.2 One could quote extensive passages in example from the treaty
between Šuppiluliumaš I of H atti (fourteenth century bce) and Šattiwazza (if not
Mattiwaza or Kurwazza) of �Mitanni.3 Šattiwaza is obviously the inferior part-
ner in the agreement. It is, therefore, forbidden him to entertain relations with
foreign parties not accepted by the king of H atti. Should one arise as ‘an enemy
� king of H atti’. Mutual friends are
of the state of Mitanni, he is an enemy of the
also good to have, so if a foreigner ‘is a friend of the� king of H atti, he is also
� contain rules
the friend of the king of Mitanni’. Large parts of such treaties
for exchanges between suzerain and vassal, as if between two people of equal
standing, which, when the stipulations are read closely, is, in fact, not the case.4
Normally, weightier duties are placed on the vassal. However, a treaty like this
guarantees the vassal help from his suzerain when he or his family is in danger.
In a series of studies, the well-known Italian Assyriologist Mario Liverani
has shown how the political scene in western Asia was dominated by a system
according to which petty kings were always subordinate to a mightier king:
either the king of Mitanni or the king of H atti.5 On the other hand, it was never
�
imagined that a petty king could survive alone for any longer period. Sometimes
there were reactions against this system – for example, in the short history of
the independent state of Amurru during the fourteenth century bce. Here, the
kings, because they ruled a state on the border between the Hittite and Egyptian
empires – tried to play the two great kings against each other and thereby obtain
a temporary situation of independence, which was, however, soon abandoned
as the king of Amurru had to submit to the one mighty lord, the king of H atti, to
�
escape the yoke of the other, who was Pharaoh.6
2. In general on this discussion, see D. J. McCarthy, Treaty and Covenant: A Study in Form
in the Ancient Oriental Documents and in the Old Testament (Analecta Biblica, 21;
Rome: Biblical Institute Press, 1978).
3. Translated in E. F. Weidner, Politische Dokumente aus Kleinasien: die Staatsverträge
in akkadischer Sprache aus dem Archiv von Boghazköi (Bohazköi-Studien, 8 and 9;
Leipzig: J.C. Hinrichs, 1923), 2–57.
4. On how a Hittite suzerain treaty may be structured to hide the inequality between great
king and vassal, M. Liverani, ‘Storiografia politica hittita – I: Shunashshura, ovvero:
Della reciprocità’, Oriens Antiquus 12 (1973), 267–97.
5. Beginning with his article ‘Contrasti e confluenze di concezioni politiche nell’età di
El-Amarna’, Revue Assyriologique 61 (1967), 1–18, and reaching a temporary climax
in his ‘Prestige and Interest: International Relations in the Near East c.1600–1100bc’
(History of the Ancient Near East/Studies I, Padova, 1990).
6. Cf. on the short history of Amurru, especially Horst Klengel, Geschichte Syriens im 2.
Jahrtausend v.u.Z. Teil 2: Mittel- und Südsyrien (Deutsche Akademie der Wissenschaften
zu Berlin. Institut für Orientfirschung, Veröffentlichung Nr. 70; Berlin: Akademie-
Verlag, 1969), 6. Abschnitt: ‘Amurru’, 178–325.
Power and social organization 161
7. Text and translation George Dossin, ‘Les archives épistolaires du Palais du Mari’, Syria
19 (1938), 105–26, 117.
8. M. Liverani, ‘Le lettere del Faraone a Rib-Adda’, Oriens Antiquus 10 (1971), 253–68,
‘Rib-Adda, giusto sofferente’, Altorientalische Forschungen 1 (1974), 175–205.
162 Biblical studies and the failure of history
god in the land of blessing on the other side of the grave, whereas, in Western
Asia, such promises would hardly pay your mortgage.
Two different political ideologies existed at the same time, both tracing their
history back to the hidden past, and both destined to survive centuries after the
close of the Amarna period and the Late Bronze. We should, however, expect
such ideologies to reflect different socio-political usage – which was the main
reason I introduced the quotation from The Godfather early in the discussion.
Let me be clear that my thesis is that the political ideology of the kings of
Western Asia in the Amarna Age was under the influence of a societal system,
which was structured similarly to Sicilian society of the twentieth century ce,
dominated by Mafiosi. In order not to be misunderstood, Western Asia was
politically structured as a society consisting of two types of persons: patrons
and their clients. It was a system of patronage (from a different perspective also
called clientelism). Such a political system moulded political-ideological termi-
nology and controlled the behaviour of people living in that society. This is not
a joke. Some call this the Mediterranean political system, suggesting that it was
the standard political system of the Mediterranean region, given that other polit-
ical forces not intrude on the traditional (i.e. local society). It is also a system
which is still largely operative in the Mediterranean world. On the other hand,
it is also very different (or should be) from the system we find in Central and
Northern Europe, where patronage as a system has been abolished for at least
a couple of centuries. A near classic selection of studies published by Ernest
Gellner and John Waterbury9 demonstrates the presence of patronage in Italy
(the basic terminology is, or is influenced by, Italian), Malta, Turkey, Cyprus,
Iraq, Lebanon, Jordan, Egypt (i.e. the modern state), Tunisia, Libya, Algeria and
Morocco. It also exists in Corsica and in France before the revolution.
This system seems to blossom nearly everywhere in what anthropologists
have identified as pre-industrial societies (though to some degree stratified).10
It is not found in most simple family-oriented societies, but in complex socie-
ties that have reached a degree of work differentiation. The principal enemy of
this system seems to be bureaucracy, as when bureaucracy functions well (with
limited corruption, as prevails today in most Protestant countries of Europe),
there is no room for the patron–client system to function.
The basic structure of the system consists of the existence of the afore-
mentioned two categories, patrons and their clients, the patrons being the
more powerful, as well as wealthy leaders of parties and clans. A patron is, in
theory, not bound by bonds of allegiance to other parties, although this may
be blurred because the actual development of the system is hardly simple.
Clients, for their part, are defined as persons who are not slaves in a technical
sense, but free citizens who have entered a contractual relationship with one
9. E. Gellner and J. Waterbury, Patrons and Clients in Mediterranean Societies (New York
and London: Duckworth, 1977).
10. Cf. S. N. Eisenstadt and Luis Roniger, Patrons, Clients and Friends: Interpersonal
Relations and the Structure of Trust in Society (Themes in the Social Sciences;
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1984).
Power and social organization 163
to whom they owe allegiance and loyalty and whom they serve, should their
patron so wish.
Why does such a system arise? First of all, the state apparatus of simple or
embryonic states is often not effective. We all recognize in the Bible that the
great men of society must care for the widow and the orphan, the poor and the
destitute. It is a central theme in the prophetic message that wealthy Israelites
did not do that, but deserted their obligations for their own interests. If neces-
sary, they bribed judges and officers of the court. It is also well recognized that
this happened because the state generally did not possess the means to enact
justice. There was no significant police force. If a person had a case against
another, he need himself drag that person before a judge and hope for the judge-
ment to go his way. Even this was a privilege that was not bestowed on all, but
only on wealthy landowners, so-called full citizens. Women, children and the
landless did not share such privilege. They were not citizens, but relied on the
mercy or good humour of the wealthy. The choice at hand for the poor was a
rich man who could secure their rights – not far different from The Godfather’s
caretaker, who, unable to obtain justice in court, needed to refer back to the
Godfather to carry his case. Those who know the novel well might also remem-
ber that the caretaker started with a request that the scoundrels should be killed.
The Godfather, who weighed the case, simply decided that this was too much
and not according to the rules. It would be enough to break all their bones – and
so it happened.
In the embryonic state of this system there was but a single patron, who
presided over all other patrons: the king (who owed only his god allegiance).
Therefore, the notion of the just king sitting on his throne creating law and
justice is a prevalent theme, not only in the Old Testament but in the Near East
as a whole.
It is a remarkable fact that until now no laws have ever appeared in any docu-
ment from Western Asia – the Old Testament laws including the so-called Book
of the Covenant (Exod. 21–23) being a special case, but eventually reflecting a
Babylonian understanding of justice and law. No patron and especially no king
would have cared being told how to judge and how to decide a specific case.
It was their sovereign right to act as judges as well as lawgivers at one and the
same time.
Was it a bad system, as the similarity to Mafia rule seems to demonstrate?
No, not in itself. From the viewpoint of the common man, the patron was a fear-
ful creature whom you were obliged to follow, and against whom you certainly
were not expected to react – and, if you did, you broke the bond to your patron
and had the worse to expect from his hand, including death. On the other hand,
it must be remembered that the patron is a powerful man who almost ‘owns’
you, although in a respectful way (Mafiosi are always ‘Uomini d’onore’, ‘men
of honour’), so that your feelings are not hurt (too much). He must be feared
and respected, but he also has to treat you with respect. In practice, your life
is safe as long as you keep your part of the bargain. That is the most important
aspect of the system. The patron cannot refuse a rightful wish formulated by
a loyal client because, if he does so, he has broken his oath, a thing that may
164 Biblical studies and the failure of history
endanger the client’s existence in the short run – but also the patron’s survival.
The bond between client and patron is broken if either party does not fulfil its
duties towards the other.
How does such a system function in practice? We have already heard of cases
brought before the court where the client must hope for his patron to rescue him.
Other instances may relate to times of distress and hunger, where the superior
resources of the patron may help the client to survive, or, failing such help, the
client would die. The patron simply must provide for the survival of his clients.
On the other hand, the patron, of course, benefits from the contributions which
the clients offer their patron: tilling fields, paying rent, providing manpower
in conflicts between patrons and the like. Many instances can be considered
where the patron benefits from his clients. The system is, however, not as such
exploitative (it may, of course, be, but only when abuses substitute the correct
application of the system, as in present-day mafia systems), for the costs of
holding the patronage when clients are under distress may well supersede any
income from such clients. If he wishes to keep his clients together, the patron
must support them and provide them with means of survival – or they will desert
him. This obligation for support may not seem as critical as it is because it could
be argued that such desertion, at a time when the country is hit by hunger and
draught, for example, in fact, could help the patron to keep his possessions.
However, this is hardly a valid explanation, as, within this Mediterranean sys-
tem, the most important aspect of clientelism consists of the prestige, which the
adherence of a large number of clients bestows on the patron, and prestige is
the all important factor at play in regard to political power between patrons. If
one patron does not give such care to his clients, his clients may choose another
patron, who better deserves their gratitude. The status of the new patron will
grow just as the power of the former diminishes. In the end, he runs the risk
of losing his position altogether. Therefore, the order of the day for the good
(i.e. clever) patron is to hold his clients under his benevolent hand at all cost.
It has been maintained that the patronage system is, indeed, a very effective
way of ensuring the redistribution of wealth in society. It is not just a system of
tyrannical economic exploitation; under certain circumstances, it can be a well-
functioning economic system.
How is it that this notion of patronage, which, in my eyes, formed the
single most important social factor in most of the ancient and many modern
Mediterranean societies, among which, also, ancient Palestinian society, includ-
ing the states of Israel and Judah, belonged, has been so little recognized? If
we read, for example, Gottwald’s The Tribes of Yahweh and other works by
the same school of thought,11 it becomes obvious that they have no idea that
political power is invested in patronage. They rather assume that power and
11. N. K. Gottwald, The Tribes of Yahweh (Maryknoll, NY: Orbis, 1979); M. Chaney,
‘Ancient Palestinian Peasants Movements and the Formation of Premonarchic Israel’, in
D. N. Freedman and D. F. Graf (eds) Palestine in Transition. The Emergence of Ancient
Israel (The Social World of Biblical Antiquity Series, 2; Sheffield: Almond Press, 1983),
39–90.
Power and social organization 165
First comment
The notion of class societies comes from Gottwald’s Marxist perspective. Not
that, in principle, I have anything against Marxism as a scholarly theory (as a
political system, it has demonstrated its impossibility – although every politi-
cal system, good or bad, would probably break down in Russia); but the theory
developed on the basis of Central European society as found in nineteenth-cen-
tury Germany, France and England. It was believed that we only need to have
two different groups to have a class society. In fact, however, in these countries
150 years ago, we find at least three classes: peasant, noblemen and the liberal
third class, which assumed power in the wake of the French Revolution of 1789.
It is my thesis that this third ‘class’ created all the trouble because it was new
(although it developed in Central Europe over a period of, say, 500 years), it was
wealthy and it was independent – owing nothing to the state nor the nobility. It
created its own fortune, and now – in 1789 – demanded its right to power, as the
most dynamic part of the society.
Pre-revolution France was dominated by the relation between nobility and
peasants, who, in fact, were clients of the nobility. So it was everywhere in the
pre-industrialized world. The phenomenon is well known from my own country
– and part of the curriculum as early as primary school. The ties which bound the
nobility to the peasants and vice versa are important for all the reasons described
earlier in this lecture. In Denmark, it was not against the rules that those who
liberated the peasants at the end of the eighteenth century (in 1787) were among
the highest-ranking noblemen of the country:12 good patrons, caring for their
clients! It is interesting that one of the slogans of the French Revolution was
that ‘power belongs to the people!’ The new group, the independents, really
believed themselves identical with the people. Again, it is hardly coincidence
that we soon find the first pronounced ideas of nationality and nation, and of a
people identified with the nation, belonging to a specific territory with a national
heritage and, finally, a history. These new rulers misunderstood themselves to be
the world and they formed their impression of the world according to their own
perceptions, especially of themselves as standing between two groups: between
the peasants and the old nobility. As a result, the idea of a class-society appears,
an idea that for all practical purposes was false as originally formulated, but one
which was taken up by the new ‘class’ that had begun to appear in England at
the end of the eighteenth century. It was, however, during the nineteenth and the
beginning of the twentieth that the victors from 1789 (i.e. the class of workers)
were led to fight cruel wars against the bourgeois. Although employing them,
without, however, any understanding of the old bond between patrons and cli-
ents, the bourgeois factory owners had not cared for their workers’ needs.
Modern European society is horizontally arranged – that is, it is today a
class society, in every sense. Ancient society, however, was not. I sometimes
describe its social structure as vertical, consisting of a vertical polarity, associ-
ating wealthy patrons with their poor clients. There was no politically common
ground among peasants who belonged to different patrons and any such form
of political communication was forbidden – as it was forbidden for a vassal of
the great king to associate with others not belonging to the same system – ‘fam-
ily’ – or patronage. Only once do we find examples from the ancient Orient of
a different type of society, during the Hellenistic period. This society, however,
strongly differed from the older Orient, as well as the later Muslim one. An
independent third class also emerged, consisting of well-to-do people who lived
in huge Hellenistic cities. To understand the difference between the Hellenistic
and the previous oriental worlds, we need to study the structure of a Hellenistic
oriental city and compare it to older types of cities. The desert city of Palmyra,
for example, with a 4 or 5 kilometre long central road (Cardo), with open spaces
and many great houses, over an area which needs to be measured in square
kilometres, can be contrasted to a large city in Western Asia of the late Bronze
Age, such as Ugarit, which covered an area of about 160 hectares, where, apart
from the temples, only a single house – the royal palace – was well built. In
Hellenistic cities, we find a third class, standing apart from rulers and peasants,
living on its own means and independent of other groups. This may well be the
reason we also see notions of nations and nationality appearing in this period,
quite comparable to ideas of the embryonic Romantic Age 2000 years later.
Second comment
Was power not invested in the family, as we find an extensive use of terms such
as ‘father’, ‘son’ and ‘brother’ in the Old Testament? Although this is true, it
has been known for many years that such terms are used in different ways in
Ancient Near Eastern writings. On the one hand, a father may be the physical
progenitor of his son. On the other, he may be a superior person deserving of
respect. At the highest level of the patronage system, this is obvious when kings
address each other as ‘brothers’ or ‘fathers and sons’. In a letter from around
1250bce, for example, the Assyrian king is the ‘brother’ of the ‘Hittite’ king,
who, however, knows of no such ‘brotherhood’.13 Evidently, the Assyrian king
tried to explain to his colleague in H attusas that he himself belonged in the same
� colleague in Egypt (who was given respect
class as both the Hittite king and his
as the ‘brother’ of the king of H atti). The Hittite king, for his part, refused to
�
13. Translated in G. Beckman, Hittite Diplomatic Texts (SBL Writings from the Ancient
World Series, 7; Atlanta, GA: Scholars Press, 1996, no 24A), 138.
Power and social organization 167
author and title) explained how Napoleon turned Europe into one big Corsican
mafia/patronage system, placing his family, his brothers and sisters with their
husbands on the different thrones of occupied countries, and keeping one
brother as his private consigliore – that is, ‘family adviser’. Napoleon, who was
brought up in a Corsican patronage system, could not imagine that any other
system would work.
Third comment
Nothing speaks against the reconstruction of ancient society proposed here,
not even the existence of tribes, that single most impossible notion of social
anthropology. Tribes are no substitute for a patronage system. They have little
political power in themselves and they possess no means for handling more
complicated matters as appear in complex societies. On a more basic societal
level, tribes may well have such importance, but in a complicated – yet not
fully developed – socio-economic system; as is typical in Bronze and Iron Age
Palestine and Syria, tribes played no role – except in the ideology of a patron-
age system (because that ideology maintains that people, belonging to the same
tribe, must side with members of their tribe). Tribes disappear because they are
superseded by the patronage system. We must remember that, in early states,
kings are reckoned the first and most important patron: as in Rome, he is Primus
inter pares. When a true bureaucracy arises with civil servants or a third class
between patrons and their clients, the patronage system will likely break down,
as has happened in a limited number of countries in modern times, such as
Scandinavia (remnants of the old system do, of course, still exist), Holland and
parts of Germany, and, in antiquity, in Egypt, where the notion of being the serv-
ant of the god (i.e. Pharaoh) prevented civil officers from deserting their master:
who could resist the offer of eternal life together with your god and master? It is
obvious that the Egyptians, as already explained, did not understand the system
of patronage as it existed in Western Asia simply because they did not have such
a system of their own.
Acknowledgements
1. Published in W. Dietrich (ed.) Jahwe unter den Göttern und Göttinnen des Alten Orients
(OBO; Freiburg: Universitätsverlag/Göttingen: Vandenhoeck and Ruprecht, 1994),
59–75.
170 Biblical studies and the failure of history
to face the fact that the greater part of biblical literature belongs to the so-called
exilic or post-exilic periods.2
I am not going to discuss Israelite religion here. Instead, the theme of this
chapter will be the history of ancient Israel and I intend to present how I think
we should continue our study of this history in the future, whether or not it is
legitimate to speak of such a history at all. In order to introduce my subject,
I briefly mention some of the new elements that have changed the course of
the study of ancient Israel. It cannot be ignored that most of the changes have
occurred at the beginning of this history – that is, before 1000bce – while the
following periods have until recently been left almost untouched by modern
developments. There is, however, reason to believe that the period after 1000bce
will be the focus of our interest in the future and that dramatic changes are also
about to take place during this period. Be this as it may, I beg your indulgence
for starting this section by referring to my study, Early Israel,3 although I still
believe that this can be justified because the idea of the history of ancient Israel
presented there played an essential role in promoting the present situation, char-
acterized by rapidly changing views concerning historical matters.
It could be maintained and it should not be forgotten that George Mendenhall
(since 19624) and Norman Gottwald (since 19745) started their deconstruction
of Old Testament history, which certainly contributed to the change of para-
digm that has occurred in Old Testament studies. At the same time, it should
not be forgotten that their theories have their fair share of problems, since
Mendenhall’s and Gottwald’s major contributions are idiosyncratic and often
misleading. Mendenhall, for example, seems prepared to sacrifice the history
of Israel to preserve the history of Israelite religion, whereas Gottwald is only
‘revolutionary’ in the sense that he applies a revolutionary model to the study
of Israel’s origins. Aside from this, Gottwald’s methodology is rather conven-
tional; the number of new ideas is quite limited. If anyone is in doubt on this
issue, he should consult Gottwald’s introduction to the Old Testament,6 which
makes it obvious that, apart from a certain ‘sociological’ flavour imposed on
2. ‘So-called’ because the term ‘the Exilic Period’ presupposes that it ended in 538bce.
This was, however, only partially true, as most ‘exiled’ Jews remained in Babylonia
for the rest of their lives. I sometimes maintain that the real end to the Babylonian exile
only came in 1948ce, when the proclamation of the modern state of Israel triggered the
second Alia, the one from modern Iraq to Palestine/Israel, leaving only a tiny remnant of
Jews in their age-old home in Mesopotamia. This is, of course, intended to be understood
as a joke – a joke, however which has some reality behind it. The presuppositions for
speaking of an exile certainly did not end in 538bce.
3. VT supplement 37 (Leiden: E. J. Brill, 1985).
4. The year of publications of his ‘The Hebrew Conquest of Palestine’, in BA 25 (1962),
66–87.
5. See his lecture at the IOSOT meeting in Edinburgh, 1974, ‘Domain Assumptions and
Societal Models in the Study of Pre-Monarchic Israel’, VT supplement 28 (1975),
89–100.
6. N. K. Gottwald, The Hebrew Bible: A Socio-Literary Introduction (Philadelphia, PA:
Fortress, 1985).
Is it still possible to write a history of ancient Israel? 171
his textual analysis, the main view of scripture is most traditional and not
inspiring.
The main reason for quoting my own study is to refer to the ‘maxims’ for-
mulated at the end of the book: first, our most important duty is to acknowledge
our ignorance; second, once we have acknowledged the state of our ignorance,
we are in a position to acknowledge what we really do know. These statements
could be understood as mottos underlying many studies that have appeared
since 1985, not least the recent monograph by Thomas L. Thompson.7
When I finished writing Early Israel (now more than ten years ago), it
seemed clear to me that a literary theory was missing which might provide an
answer to the obvious discrepancies between the Old Testament description
of the early history of Israel and the history of Palestine during the transition
from the Late Bronze to the Early Iron Age. This writer, like most of his con-
temporaries, was entangled in the historical network laid out by Old Testament
writers, according to whom the history of Israel was divided into fixed periods:
the periods of the settlement, the judges, the united and the divided monarchies,
the exilic and the post-exilic periods. During the middle 1980s, we were pre-
pared merely to scratch or adjust the portrait, which had been painted by Old
Testament narrators.
In his Who Were the Israelites?, the late Gösta W. Ahlström went further8 as
he correctly questioned the identity of so-called early Israelites. Very few really
understood what Ahlström’s intention was and this writer, himself, had to write
two more books before he understood what changes were developing. When
he admitted to Gösta Ahlström that he must be slow-witted, Ahlström replied:
‘Yes, since you say so yourself!’ Indeed, Ahlström preceded Philip R. Davies in
demonstrating that the ancient Israelites represented a phenomenon which had
been invented by Old Testament historians: the Israelites were never a historical
reality. Philip Davies has, nevertheless, discussed this in a highly directed man-
ner in his recent polemical contribution to the discussion, ‘In Search of Ancient
Israel’.9 According to Davies, Old Testament scholars have tried to grasp for
more than 200 years the historical truth behind the Old Testament narratives, as
if this truth were a holy grail and biblical scholars, modern knights of that grail.
However, they have been no more successful than their colleagues had been,
gathered about King Arthur’s round table.
Ahlström and Davies are correct in maintaining that the ancient Israelites
were invented by Old Testament writers. They play the role of ‘good guys’. On
the other hand, once we have identified the heroes of the tale, we also need to
find the ‘bad guys’, for without a conflict between good and evil there is hardly a
narrative. ‘The bad guys’ of the Old Testament narratives are surely identified as
10. N. P. Lemche, The Canaanites and Their Land: The Tradition of the Canaanites (JSOT
supplement, 110; Sheffield: Academic Press, 1991).
11. Cf. The Canaanites, 56–57.
12. In Shalmanaser III’s version of the battle at Qarqar in 853bce, ANET 3, 279.
Is it still possible to write a history of ancient Israel? 173
and the people of Old Testament narrative. The only thing the two entities may
have had in common is the name. However, even a modern state in this region is
called ‘Israel’, although the relation of this modern Israel to ancient Israel – that
is, to the Northern Kingdom – is principally a matter of ideology. Whether the
inhabitants of central Palestine during the time of Omri and Ahab ever under-
stood themselves as ‘Israelites’, in an ethnic and national sense, is unknown.
They may merely have seen themselves as human beings who happened to
pay taxes to a king of a state called ‘Israel’. It was equally possible to call it
‘Samaria’ or ‘the House of Omri’ (Bît H umriya). The only thing we can safely
�
assume is that Old Testament writers considered this population to be Israelite
in an ethnic sense of the word.
At the centre of the debate stands the question as to whether we should fol-
low Old Testament historians here. Should modern scholars allow these writers
to decide the course of research? Would it not be preferable if the modern his-
torian simply skipped over the biblical construction and made his own recon-
struction of what he thought to be the history of ancient Palestine?13 The Old
Testament would be but one source of knowledge (albeit a rather comprehensive
one) among others, and there would be no reason to pay special attention to
the Old Testament version. I must draw attention to a number of related ques-
tions that should also be discussed. We have questions of definition, the most
important of which being the use of the name ‘Israel’. The importance of this
and other matters become obvious in reading the contributions to the volume
published by Diana Edelman, The Fabric of History.14 In this volume, there are
studies that are indistinct and evasive in their terminology: for example, the
articles by William B. Dever15 and especially that by J. Maxwell Miller,16 and
there are contributions, which seem to have overcome this problem, especially
the ones by Thomas L. Thompson17 and Ernst Axel Knauf.18 On the other hand,
it is obvious that, in the event that problems of definition and terminology are
13. Allowing for the fact that any reconstruction of history can only be a reconstruction; it
is certainly not to be mistaken for history. I have sometimes been unjustly accused of
having, much like ancient Deuteronomists, created nothing but my own personal version
of the history of Israel (cf., e.g., S. Herrmann, ‘Die Abwertung des Alten Testaments
als Geschichtsquelle. Bemerkungen zu einem geistesgeschictliches Problem’, in H. H.
Schmid und J. Mehlhausen (eds) Sola Scriptura. VII. Europäischer Theologen-Kongreß
Dresden, 1990 (Gütersloh, Gütersloher Verlagshaus Gerd Mohn, 1993), 156–65. This
may be true, but at least it is my version, not just a new paraphrase of a Deuteronomistic
one.
14. D. V. Edelman (ed.) The Fabric of History. Text, Artifact and Israel’s Past (JSOT supple-
ment, 127; Sheffield: Academic Press, 1991).
15. W. B. Dever, ‘Archaeology, Material Culture and the Early Monarchical Period’, in
Edelman, The Fabric, 103–15.
16. J. M. Miller, ‘Is It Possible to Write a History of Israel Without Relying on the Hebrew
Bible?’, in Edelman, The Fabric, 93–102.
17. T. L. Thompson, ‘Text, Context and Referent in Israelite Historiography’, in Edelman,
The Fabric, 65–92.
18. E. A. Knauf, ‘From History to Interpretation’, in Edelman, The Fabric, 26–64.
174 Biblical studies and the failure of history
not solved, the discussion will end in a morass and issues blurred. Another mat-
ter that needs to be discussed deals with the historical interest present in ancient
times. Did Old Testament historians really want to write history? How would
they have understood such a project? During the last decade, several scholars,
including this writer, have given such problems considerable attention and it is
now clear that a history writing that has anything in common with the modern
concept of history cannot be expected from the hands of Old Testament ‘histori-
ans’; this kind of writing was certainly not on their agenda when they presented
their version of a history of Israel. Although Baruch Halpern has tried to argue
that Old Testament historians were true historians,19 it would be misleading to
maintain that he has presented a strong argument in favour of this thesis. I have
only to refer to his very extensive discussion of Ehud’s killing of Eglon, which
obviously works against his own interests.20
The third question to be addressed concerns the problem of the survival of
historical information in Old Testament historical literature. Excluded from this
discussion, is the clearly historical information about Sennacherib’s siege of
Jerusalem in 701bce and that pertaining to Nebuchadnezzar’s conquest of the
same city in 597bce. The fact that the authors of the stories of Sennacherib’s
siege have embellished their narrative by introducing legend does not imply
that this siege must be considered unhistorical. Rather, it tells us something
of the methods used by Old Testament history writers when constructing their
histories.
I have finally reached the theme of this chapter: the possibility that there may
be some historical information contained in Old Testament writings after all,
even in those parts which concern the early history of Israel. However, though
it cannot be excluded that such information is present, it is far from safe that
they are in a context, which is correct from a historian’s point of view. I intend
to present three examples of possible historical information handled by Old
Testament historians. My first example relates to the sojourn of the Israelites in
Egypt. The second deals with the Benjaminite immigration into Palestine, and
the third concerns the relations between David and Omri. It goes without saying
that, as far as the early history of Israel is concerned, the discussion is prelimi-
nary; it certainly does not intend to provide a final argument on these matters. I
present only proposals and ideas which may or may not become part of a more
comprehensive discussion.
The note in Exodus 1:11 that Israelites in Egypt were forced to build the stor-
age cities of Pharaoh, Pithom and Ramses has often been considered evidence
19. B. Halpern, The First Historians: The Hebrew Bible and History (San Francisco, CA:
Harper & Row, 1988).
20. Ibid., 39–75.
Is it still possible to write a history of ancient Israel? 175
that there was a historical background to the Exodus narrative. In this, scholars
usually refer to the mention of hapiru in an Egyptian document in the days of
� participated in the construction of the great
Ramses II (1279–1212bce), who
pylon gate tower – namely, Ramses Miamon.21 The note in Exodus 1:11 is
accordingly assumed to be historically correct, as, from a linguistic point of
view, the hapiru of the Egyptian documents are supposed to be identical with
�
biblical Hebrews and it certainly has not escaped the attention of modern schol-
ars that Israelites are often referred to as ‘Hebrews’ in the Joseph and Exodus
narratives. Both Pithom and Ramses are place names known from the history of
Egypt. The city of Ramses, without doubt, should be identified with the ruins of
Khatana-Qantir in north-eastern Egypt. During the late New Kingdom, this site
was called Pi-Ramesses (taking its name from the famous Ramses II, the great
builder of this city) and was the residence of the Pharaohs of the nineteenth and
twentieth dynasties. After that period, the place was forsaken by its inhabitants
and the residence moved to nearby Tanis, the Zo’an of the Old Testament, the
city that was to become the new capital of Egypt in the days of the twenty-first
dynasty. In light of this fact, it would be reasonable to consider the information
of Exodus 1:11 to be historical and connected to conditions which occurred in
Egypt at the end of the second millennium bce and only then. Although this may
seem unproblematic and beyond doubt, some problems arise as soon as we turn
our attention to the identity of the second storage city: Pithom.
According to Exodus 1:11, Pithom should be regarded as a city comparable
to Ramses. This is, however, historically impossible, as ‘Pithom’ was only used
as the name of a city in the Saite period, from the seventh century onwards.
Pithom means ‘the House of (the god) Atum’, and was also known prior to the
Saite period as the name of temples and temple estates belonging to this god (or,
better, to the priests of Atum). The name was, however, never connected with
cities. Moreover, archaeologists working at tell el-Maskhuta in north-eastern
Egypt have found clear evidence that this was the ancient city of Pithom and
that it was founded by Pharaoh Necho II between 609 and 606bce.22 Hence,
information that Israelites worked as forced labourers before the Exodus at the
site of Pithom is anachronistic. On the other hand, it cannot be denied that
prisoners of war from the territory of the former state of Israel or from Judah
may have been employed by Necho in his building activities in northern Egypt.
Such prisoners may have been transported to Egypt by Necho in the wake of his
609bce campaign, during which King Josiah of Judah lost his life at Megiddo.
It is also possible that immigrants from Palestine, who already lived in Egypt,
had been conscripted for building purposes. It may not be possible to point to
a moment in the history of Egypt when both cities mentioned in Exodus 1:11
existed simultaneously and it may be difficult to say anything about the time
when the Israelites are supposed to have worked at the storage cities of Pharaoh.
21. J. Bottéro, Le problème des habiru (Paris: Imprimerie nationale, 1954), no 188, 169–70.
�
22. Cf. J. S. Holladay, The Wadi Tumilat Project. The Excavations of Tell el-Makhuta
(Malibu, CA: The American Research Center in Egypt, 1982).
176 Biblical studies and the failure of history
Part of the content of Exodus 1:11 does seem to belong to the second millen-
nium, another to the middle of the first millennium. It may, nevertheless, be
possible to create some coherence if the Egyptologist Edward F. Went should
happen to be right in maintaining that the name of ‘Ramses’ in Exodus 1:11 need
not be directly connected to the city of Ramses, going back to Ramses II. The
Ramses of Exodus 1:11 may refer to Tanis, which had been built by recycling
stones from nearby Ramses. The colossal statues of Ramses II were also moved
from Ramses to Tanis and traces of a cult of Ramses II can be found at Tanis
until the Hellenistic Period. Accordingly, Went maintains that Old Testament
writers transferred the name of Ramses (never lost to Egyptian traditionalists)
to another place – namely, Tanis, which was still in existence when they wrote
their history. At the same time, they transferred their information about pos-
sible building activities of ‘Israelites’ in the days of Pharaoh Necho back to an
assumed stay of Israel in Egypt in ancient times.23
If this explanation is plausible, the main argument in favour of the historical
context of the Exodus narrative has lost its foundation. Instead of being able to
prove that Israelites were once in Egypt, Exodus 1:11 can be taken as evidence
of the ways and manners of Old Testament historians, who, in this case, obvi-
ously manipulated their sources to create an impression of Israelites working as
slaves in Egypt at an early point in the history of Israel. The note in Exodus 1:11
about the building of Pithom and Ramses may be historical after all; but this
history has nothing to do with the history of ancient Israel. Instead, it should be
understood in relation to later conditions that were used by the authors to create
their own fictitious picture of the sojourn in Egypt. In its present context, the
note is certainly anachronistic. While this example may seem obvious, the next
case, which deals with the settlement tradition in the book of Joshua, however,
will demand more patience from the reader.
When it was first formulated, the classic German explanation of the settlement
of the Israelites was hailed as an important breakthrough in the history of schol-
arship because the two main figures associated with this explanation, Albrecht
Alt and Martin Noth, ignored the information in the book of Joshua insofar as
it concerned an Israelite conquest of Canaan. There is no reason to review their
research here or to deal with alternative ideas about the conquest, which pre-
vailed in other quarters of biblical scholarship.24 Only a single interesting obser-
vation which was made by these scholars will give focus to our interest. This is
the observation that all specific conquest narratives in Joshua concern localities
in the territory of Benjamin (although the hero of the conquest, Joshua, was
himself from Ephraim). Alt and Noth considered these conquest narratives to
25. A. Alt, in his article ‘Josua’ (1936), Kleine Schriften zur Geschichte Israels I (Munich:
Beck, 1953), 176–92; M. Noth, thus in his introduction to his commentary on Joshua,
Das Buch Josua (HAT, I 7; Tübingen: Mohr, 1953), 11–13.
26. Cf. Judg. 3:15, 17, 21, and especially 20.16. Cf. among the more recent, Halpern, The
First Historians, 41.
178 Biblical studies and the failure of history
tribal groups of the Near East in antiquity and later periods. Tribal names of this
type can be found both in Mesopotamian documents and among Arab tribes up
to the present day. Other Israelite tribal names are, however, as M. Noth has
excellently explained, either,27 first, names for people having a specific ‘occupa-
tion’ (so Issachar); second, names of landscapes (so Ephraim, Judah); or, third,
tribes which may have been named after gods (so Gad). Only Benjamin seems
to be a genuine tribal name.
In this connection, it should not be forgotten that biblical Benjaminites
may not have been the only Benjaminites of the ancient world. According
to documents from ancient Mari, a tribal group were in existence in Upper
Mesopotamia around 1800bce who were most likely called the binu jamina.
Scholars formerly doubted that the name of the Benjaminites was related to the
Marian Benjaminites since, in the cuneiform writing employed by the scribes
of Mari, the first name of the Mesopotamian Benjaminites was always rendered
as DUMU.MEŠ jamina, with a sumerogram instead of an Akkadian transcrip-
tion. According to Hayim Tadmor, this suggests that there were no Benjaminites
around Mari because the scribes of Mari never used sumerograms to render
West Semitic words. In Marian texts, sumerograms are invariably used to render
Akkadian names and concepts and a proper Akkadian rendering would not be
banu or binu jamina but maru jamina.28 Such a compound is made up of an
Akkadian word and a West Semitic one (jamina is doubtless West Semitic).
In proper Akkadian, its counterpart, imnum, is certainly very uncommon and
most scholars have therefore considered the sumerogram DUMU.MEŠ here
to be used with the general meaning to indicate members of a tribal group that
was known only as jamina. Accordingly, scholars have normally not spoken of
Benjaminites, but rather of ‘jaminites’ living in the province of Mari. The situ-
ation may have changed, as the first component of the name has now turned up
in a document from Mari, written syllabically and surprisingly as binu and not,
as to be expected, banu, making it likely that the name DUMU.MEŠ jamina was
intended to render binu jamina.29
At Mari, the name ‘the son of the south’ makes excellent sense, because there
also are traces of another tribal group called the DUMU.MEŠ sim’al – that is,
‘the sons of the north’. We are badly informed about the whereabouts of this
second group. This is not very important here. What is important is the fact that
‘the sons of the south’ carry their name in opposition to ‘sons of the north’,
much in the same fashion as Ostrogoths (eastern Goths) were so called because
27. M. Noth, Geschichte Israels (Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 1950), 56–67.
28. H. Tadmor, ‘Historical Implications of the Correct Rendering of Akkadian ‘dâku’, JNES
17 (1958), 129–41.
29. Cf. ARM XXII: 328:111. Cf. on this A. Malamat, Mari and the Early Israelite Experience
(The Schweich Lectures 1984; Oxford: University Press, 1989), 31 and 35 n. 29. Since
the syllably written name has so far only occurred as a personal name, Malamat is still
of the conviction that we should speak about jaminites, the first part a kind of semantic
indicator. However, this will not change much, as all later examples of tribal names of
this type could also be said to contain the word ‘sons of’ as ‘semantic indicators’, includ-
ing the biblical Benjaminites.
Is it still possible to write a history of ancient Israel? 179
Visigoths (western Goths) were around at the same time, though not always,
living to the west of Ostrogoths.
The question remains whether Benjaminites from Mari have anything to
do with Benjaminites of Palestine. Such a connection has been proposed by,
among others, M. Astour in his characteristically fanciful fashion.30 Astour
refers to religious ties which should have existed between the two areas. The
Benjaminites of Upper Mesopotamia lived at least seasonally in an area where
the dominant deity is supposed to have been the moon god Sin, whereas in the
Old Testament, a city name that also implies worship of the moon (i.e. Jericho)
is actually located inside the tribal area of Benjamin. If no additional arguments
could be provided, the most generous thing to say would probably be that this
theory should simply be forgotten. However, although they are hardly to be
considered conclusive, such arguments may eventually be found, and here the
‘reference’ preserved in Genesis 35:23-26 may be of interest: that Benjamin,
like other sons of Jacob, was born in Paddan-Aram (the anachronistic term
applied by P to Upper Mesopotamia in the days of the Patriarchs).
Such information demands attention because it clearly contradicts the narra-
tive of the birth of Benjamin just before the note in Genesis 35:23-26. According
to the main narrative, Benjamin is supposed to have been born in the land of
Canaan near the city of Bethlehem after the return of Jacob to his own country.
Benjamin is therefore said to be the only one among the sons of Jacob who orig-
inated in Palestine, whereas his eleven brothers were all born in Mesopotamia.
We must therefore ask how it can be that the conflicting note in Genesis 35:23-
26 has survived. Perhaps the person who included the note ‘nodded off’ or
forgot that we have just been told about the birth of Benjamin and the death
of Rachel in Canaan? However, this is hardly a reasonable explanation after
all; how should he forget such an obvious contradiction? It is more likely that
the note in Genesis 35:23-26 owes its existence to a special tradition that runs
counter to the official version of Benjamin’s birth and has to be evaluated as an
independent piece of information.
One may pay as much attention as one wishes to a special tradition; it should
still not be forgotten that it has always been characteristic of classic historical
research to focus on information that does not conform with, but rather con-
tradicts, mainstream information to be found in the available documentation.
Historians are trained to grasp such contradictions in order to show whether they
derive from a special source or have something to say which the authors of the
main traditions never intended to pass on to posterity. Such ‘fossilized traces of
tradition’ provide the historian with an opportunity to get behind his source and
evaluate its content on the basis of what the main tradition says and on the basis
of what it does not say, but which has filtered through the screen created by the
author of the main document. Even though historians of the present have found
other methods and prefer to focus on totalities and la longue durée, it should be
maintained that it is appropriate from the standpoint of source criticism not to
proposed by Alt and Noth? It can hardly have happened after 1200bce, as noth-
ing indicates a large-scale nomadic immigration into Palestine after 1200bce, at
least not before the Roman and Arab Periods.31 The date 1200bce derives from
the general Israelite immigration hypothesis, which, on the other hand, has little
support in recent discussion.32 If anything like a nomadic migration happened
in those days, the scale of action must have been so small that nobody noticed
it, and certainly not archaeologists of the present. Such a small-scale migration
would also seem inadequate to explain why we still possess a conquest tradition.
On the other hand, it would be possible to propose a date for the immigration
of Benjaminites before the ‘magical’ year of 1200bce, and to connect this migra-
tion with destructions at the end of the Middle Bronze Age. Conservatives and
evangelicals alike would, or so I assume, be only too happy with such a theory
because they would have found an explanation for the destruction of Jericho
circa 1550bce.33 To accept such a connection would, however, be premature
since it does not solve the problem of Ai, which during the sixteenth century
bce was in ruins for more than 700 years.34 Benjaminites of the sixteenth century
would still have to wait another 400 years before negotiating with the inhabit-
ants of Gibeon, as no settlement was found on this spot before the Iron Age.35
One thing speaks in favour of an early date apart from the fact that we possess
no precise information about this period (always an advantage when historical
conjectures are involved): demographic changes which occurred in the central
highlands, which were almost completely devoid of village settlements in the
Late Bronze Age, leaving only a small number of insignificant townships in
that part of Palestine.36 It is not before the beginning of the Iron Age that we
see villages reappearing in central Palestine.37 An important argument against
31. I have problems with the proposal of G. A. Rendburg, ‘The Date of the Exodus and the
Conquest/Settlement: the Case for the 1100s’, VT 42 (1992), 510–27, to be serious. It is
a desperate wish that at least a tiny part of the settlement tradition be preserved!
32. There is really no reason to discuss this subject any further at least not in light of our
present knowledge of the situation in Palestine at the end of the second millennium
bce. The two studies by the late Gösta W. Ahlström, The History of Ancient Palestine
from the Palaeolithic Period to Alexander’s Conquest (JSOT supplement, 146; Sheffield:
Academic Press, 1993) and Thomas L. Thompson, Early History of the Israelite People
(1992) stand at the end of this discussion rather than at the beginning of a renewed one.
33. The date, 1550bce, for the destruction of MB Jericho is generally accepted; cf. T. A.
Holland, ABD (1992), vol 3, 735–36. This destruction could, however, with some reason
be explained as the work of marauding Egyptian troops.
34. The former results of the French expedition under the direction of J. Marquet-Krause
(1933–5) have been reconfirmed by J. Callaway’s more recent excavations (1964–1976),
as Callaway himself has observed in several publications, the most recent being his
article ‘Ai’ in the ABD 1 (1992), 125–30.
35. This is the outcome of J. B. Pritchard’s excavations, as maintained in a number of pub-
lications, for example in his article ‘Gibeon’, EAEHL II (1976), 446–50.
36. Cf. T. L. Thompson, The Settlement of Palestine in the Bronze Age (TAVO Beihefte B,
34; Tübingen 1979).
37. Cf. on this, above all, I. Finkelstein, The Archaeology of the Israelite Settlement
(Jerusalem: Magnes, 1988).
182 Biblical studies and the failure of history
a theory of early Benjaminite migration is that they are not mentioned in any
document from the Late Bronze Age, although it should not be forgotten that
although a well-known and established feature of Late Bronze Age society, they
were known to Egyptians solely as Shasu, and to people writing in cuneiform
Akkadian as Sutu. Neither the term Shasu nor Sutu are names of individual tribal
groups. In the Amarna Age, they were used by Egyptian as well as Akkadian
scribes as designations for ‘nomads’. Thus human beings who, according to
Egyptians, should be considered members of the Shasu group would, in an
Akkadian letter, likely turn up as Sutu. Be this as it may, both Akkadian and
Egyptian texts of the Late Bronze Age provide information about nomadic
groups living in Palestine and neighbouring countries.38
I have no intention of saying that this proposal is a well-founded one, and
it would be difficult to object if colleagues would prefer to dismiss it without
further discussion. However, even if the theory should be accepted as a kind of
working hypothesis, it does not prove the Bible true. The conquest narratives in
the book of Joshua do not prove that Benjaminites conquered central Palestine
or even migrated to this area at some time between 1800bce and 1500bce. The
only conclusion we can safely draw is that inhabitants of central Palestine may
have preserved the general idea that they were not themselves indigenous, and
that they may have maintained that their origins not be sought where they lived.
Such an idea would not be remarkable, either among the inhabitants of the ter-
ritory of Benjamin or among other comparable groups. It is certainly a coinci-
dence that social anthropologist Abdul Lutfiyya, in his study of modern Beitin
(Bethel), mentions that the inhabitants of this small Palestinian town considered
themselves descendants of migrants from the Arabian Peninsula, though such
a claim has little basis in fact.39 The inhabitants of the tribal territory of Benja
minites in Palestine may never have been descendants of ancient Benjaminites
who migrated from Syria to Palestine. It is enough that they considered them-
selves to be descendants of former nomadic tribal groups, regardless of the fact
that this claim may not be true.
In conclusion, it may be argued that Old Testament historians had no idea of
history as we see it. On the contrary, the example of Benjaminite migration and
conquest narratives may illustrate the ways and manners of these ‘historians’.
The writers who composed the book of Joshua were not forced to ‘invent’ the
idea of a conquest; they possessed immigration traditions that circulated among
the inhabitants of the territory north of Jerusalem. Such writers, however, knew
little of the historical background of these legends and traditions, but it is obvi-
ous that this did not worry them. The inclusion of the Ephraimite hero of the
conquest (i.e. Joshua) should be regarded as an effort to change the outlook of
the conquest traditions from a local to a pan-Israelite perspective. I have often
maintained that little of historical value has been preserved in the Old Testament.
38. On the Sutu, cf., among others, M. Heltzer, The Suteans (Naples: Istituto Universitario
Orientale, 1981), and on the Shasu, R. Giveon, Les Bédouins Shosu des documents égyp-
tiens (Leiden: E. J. Brill, 1971).
39. A. M. Lutfiyya, Baytîn. A Jordanian Village (The Hague, 1966).
Is it still possible to write a history of ancient Israel? 183
Nobody, however, ever forbade Old Testament historians to offer something that
would turn out to be historical. The writers who created the book of Joshua will
most likely have been in possession of migration traditions, though the concrete
content of such traditions is impossible to recover today. The only thing we can
safely argue is that writers had no concrete idea of what may have happened or
when it happened. They merely turned a popular tradition into a literary inven-
tion, part of a much larger description of the early history of Israel.
The above example will not prove my case. Perhaps the next can provide my
argument with necessary strength. It concerns the relationship between David
and Omri in tradition and history. Both were kings of importance and founders
of great kingdoms. Or, at least this is what the Old Testament has to say about
David, while the importance of Omri is considerably reduced by Old Testament
historians. Omri’s greatness can only be deduced from other documents from
the ancient Near East, which mention him or members of his dynasty as impor-
tant West Semitic monarchs. The similarity between the two kings, however,
goes further. As David was succeeded by his brilliant son Solomon, Omri was
succeeded by his son, the no less important Ahab, the mightiest king Israel
was ever to see. We could also provide more similarities like the one that says
that both David and Omri were professional soldiers in the service of a previ-
ous king, whom they succeeded, not because they murdered their masters, but
because they removed usurpers who were supposed to be the real scoundrels. It
is a well-known fact that the author of ‘David’s Rise’ (1 Sam. 16 to 2 Sam. 7)
invested considerable interest in clearing his hero of accusations for having
liquidated most, if not all, of the dynasty of King Saul. Omri’s case is clearer:
he had only to remove and execute the usurper Zimri, who rebelled against his
and Omri’s master, King Elah of Israel. It is a remarkable fact that there are
plenty of references to the two Israelite kings, Omri and Ahab, while nothing
has survived that has anything to say about David and Solomon, except for
the narratives of the Old Testament.40 This could be a coincidence and would
not be very important if it were the only argument called upon when question-
ing the historicity of David and Solomon. Much more attention should be paid
to the growing conviction that no United Monarchy and no Israelite empire
ever existed in the tenth century bce, which vaguely resembled the greatness
of Omri’s kingdom. It is unnecessary to present details here. More will be said
in an article of mine that will be published in early 1994.41 Nevertheless, it is
enough to point to the size of David’s Jerusalem, the capital of a great empire,
40. This is valid as far as the moment of writing is concerned, although unconfirmed rumours
say that a new inscription has been found in an archaeological dump at Tell Dan, men-
tioning King Asah of the Beth-David as well as Ben (Bar?) Hadad. However, before its
proper publication, it is hard to say anything conclusive on this inscription.
41. Cf. note 1 above.
184 Biblical studies and the failure of history
which biblical authors extended from the Egyptian border to the Euphrates. The
‘great’ city of Jerusalem in the days of David, however, covered an area of no
more than 4 hectares, allowing (by generous calculation) for some 2000 inhabit-
ants (men, women and children). If we estimate the average size of the family
as about six persons, around 300 adult males (between seventeen to eighteen
years and forty-five years) would have lived inside the walls of this ‘city’.42 The
kingdom of David was based on the tribal population of Judah, which, of course,
numbered more than merely the inhabitants of Jerusalem. However, if we apply
the same method of calculation for other sites of Judah in the tenth century,
the total population of this area will not have surpassed 10,000 to 15,000 indi-
viduals, which allows for an army of some 2000. These conclusions are based
on the recently produced statistical material found in David Jamieson-Drake’s
study of the kingdom of Judah. He maintains that there was never an empire in
the tenth century bce, the capital of which is supposed to have been Jerusalem,
and second, that the only thing that may have existed in this area was perhaps
a small and non-centralized chiefdom, ruled by the local chief, David. On the
basis of this embryonic political assembly, a small state or kingdom was to
arise after another 200 years, the short-lived kingdom of Judah known from
the Old Testament. In the future, the results of Jamieson-Drake’s study will
certainly be questioned, and archaeologists may object to the value of his evi-
dence or his way of presenting his material (although, to date, no challenge of
importance has appeared). It should not be overlooked that the only legitimate
way to depart from Jamieson-Drake’s conclusions will be to show his statistics
totally wrong or grossly misleading; they cannot be refuted by reference to the
Old Testament. Furthermore, it is a safe assumption that it will not be possible
to present archaeological material that will make it likely that a great Judean
kingdom of the tenth century bce ever existed.43
It is a deplorable fact that no comparable statistically arranged analysis is
available for the remains of the Northern Kingdom in the tenth century bce. It is,
on the other hand, possible to draw some inferences based on the present avail-
able material. To prove the greatness of David, and especially Solomon, many
scholars have referred to the similarity between public buildings found at many
sites, dating to the tenth century bce. Such buildings may include so-called
42. Based on a calculation system explained by S. Parpola, in J. M. Sasson, Jonah (AB 24B;
New York, 1990), 311–12, allowing for 358 persons per hectare (= 2.5 acres). That this
calculation is generous to ancient Jerusalem can be seen from the fact that according to
the same system, Hazor in the Bronze Age contained at least 25,000 persons, which is
more than is usually assumed today, although Y. Yadin himself believed that the popula-
tion of Hazor may have been even bigger than that.
43. D. W. Jamieson-Drake, Scribes and Schools in Monarchic Judah (JSOT supplement,
109; Sheffield: Academic Press, 1991). His results seem to be confirmed by the inde-
pendent analysis by H. M. Niemann, Herrschaft, Königtum und Staat. Skizzen zur sozio-
kulturellen Entwicklung im monarchischen Israel (Forchungen zum Alten Testament, 6;
Tübingen: Mohr, 1993). As a matter of fact, Niemann’s results echo Jamieson-Drake’s,
though Niemann, at the time of writing, did not know Jamieson-Drake’s book, nor has
he used the same method or materials as his North American colleague.
Is it still possible to write a history of ancient Israel? 185
44. If we allow for some historical reality behind the description of Solomon’s building
activities in Jerusalem, especially his construction of a palace complex and a small
temple, this would hardly have changed the general conditions of the town or provided
the town with a major increase of its population. The public area that consisted of the
temple and the palace complex will not have been densely populated, but would mostly
have comprised of workshops, archives, ceremonial buildings and housing for the royal
family, some retainers and, perhaps, the highest officials and priests.
45. Cf. on Y. Aharoni’s criticism of Yadin’s Solomonic datings, Y. Aharoni, The Archaeology
of the Land of Israel (Louisville, KY: Westminster/John Knox Press, 1982), 192–239.
Cf. also the evaluation of this discussion in A. Mazar, Archaeology of the Land of the
Bible c.10,000–586 bce (New York: Doubleday, 1990), 381–82. Mazar favours Yadin’s
datings, as does H. Weippert, Palästina in vorhellenistischer Zeit (Handbuch der
Archäologie. Vorderasien II/1; Munich: Beck, 1988), 431. Among other scholars who
have criticized Yadin’s interpretation, we should mention K. M. Kenyon, ‘Megiddo,
Hazor, Samaria and Chronology’, Bulletin of the Institute of Archaeology 4 (1964),
143–56, and D. Ussishkin, ‘Was the ‘Solomonic’ City Gate at Megiddo Built by King
Solomon?’, BASOR 239 (1980), 1–18.
46. Cf. G. W. Ahlström, ‘The Seal of Shemae’, SJOT 7 (1993), 208–15.
186 Biblical studies and the failure of history
of which Omri and Ahab were able to create a small empire which was among
the important states of western Asia.
If so, we certainly have to discuss the background of the stories of David
and Solomon in Samuel and Kings. From a Judean angle, it seems impossible
to talk about an empire. However, the ancient world was rich in empires and
great states, so it may be that the tradition of David’s and Solomon’s greatness
derives from some other part of the Near East. It is possible that traditions which
had originally nothing to do with Judah or Jerusalem were transformed and
became Judean traditions. This is only a qualified guess. All that we can safely
say is that we are looking at a possible background for the stories about David
and Solomon. It cannot be excluded that the idea of a great Palestinian kingdom
derives from the tradition of the Omride kingdom, a tradition that was later
transferred to Judah and Jerusalem as a founding legend for the Judean kingdom
(for my purpose, here, it is immaterial whether this happened in the pre- or post-
exilic period). According to this reworked tradition, the two important Israelite
kings were no longer Omri and Ahab, but David and Solomon, who if they had
been historical personages, they ruled over an uncoordinated chiefdom in the
backyard of ancient Palestine.
This may be another example of Old Testament writers who have included
an old tradition without paying attention to its historical context. The perspec-
tive of these writers was certainly Judean and, accordingly, they transformed
David and Solomon, ancestors of the Judean royal family, the House of David,
into great kings of all Israel and creators of empire. It is an interesting fact that
nobody seems to have known of or been interested in such two ‘important’ fig-
ures of Israelite history, not even the Moabite king, Mesha, who only few years
after the time of Solomon described how he liberated his country from the yoke
of Israel, which Omri had imposed on his land. His inscription does not include
a single reference to David, supposedly the ‘Israelite’ king who subdued Moab
(and killed a great number of its male population: 2 Sam. 8:2), nor does it refer
to Mesha’s father, who Mesha, himself, describes as reigning for ‘thirty years’,
having recovered Moab by driving off the Israelite armies of Solomon.
In an article published many years ago, I demonstrated what a cunning work
the story of David’s Rise really is.47 It is clear that external parallels to this
narrative can be found in documents from Western Asia, not least the inscription
47. In my ‘David’s Rise’, JSOT 10 (1978), 2–25. Other authors have since dealt more exten-
sively with these matters. One important point should be noted, that so-called ‘negative
evidence’ (i.e. stories of David’s seemingly criminal acts, as well as the obvious cover-up
in connection with the killings of Abner, Ishbaal and Saul, respectively, which are often
considered proofs of the basic historicity of ‘David’s Rise’) can just as well be seen as
literary efforts to describe the hero as a clever ‘trickster’. As a matter of course, such
elements make it more likely that ‘David’s Rise’ and the ‘Succession Narrative’ are
products of literary invention, as only the hero of political propaganda (e.g. Idrimi) is
blameless. I owe my thanks to cand theol. Pernille Carstens of Aarhus for presenting me
with these insights into the nature of ‘the hero as trickster’.
Is it still possible to write a history of ancient Israel? 187
Conclusion
The results based on these examples could easily be multiplied if we direct our
attention to the Pentateuch. This might lead us behind the present shape of Old
Testament narrative, not only to show whether these are proper historical nar-
ratives connected with the real world or ‘merely’ brilliant fictions, but also to
study the ‘minds’ of the writers who employed such means, including historical
traditions, free of their proper historical contexts, to create a ‘history of Israel’
that conformed with the intentions of the writers and lived up to the expecta-
tions of their audience. In this, they were apparently not bothered by questions
of historical correctness and they hardly possessed means and methods for dis-
tinguishing what was historically correct from what was invention. In spite of
this, it should be maintained that their enterprise was successful since these
narratives have survived to the present and have always been able to make an
impression on the mind of the human race.
But let us return to the beginning of this chapter, where the central issue was
whether it is still possible to write a history of ancient Israel. It is important to
notice that my three examples are different in that they show three different
ways of manipulating ‘history’. The first example shows how late information is
referred back to earliest times in order to create a picture of the Israelite sojourn
in Egypt. The second example demonstrates the opposite: that older traditions
were re-employed to create a story of an Israelite conquest. The third example
clearly exposes an author who reshaped two great figures of Israelite history to
create a new entity: a Judean empire of David and Solomon, although such a
Judean realm may never have existed.
To compose a history of Israel based on the information of the Old Testament
would be the same as to make a bargain with the authors who manipulated this
history in their own interest – that is, it continues in the tradition of these authors
to make their viewpoints one’s own. This is certainly a legitimate procedure so
far as the literary content of such stories is concerned, but it is hardly advisable
for a historian interested in reaching historical ‘truth’ (whatever this means). It
48. Cf. my Ancient Israel (Sheffield: Academic Press, 1988), 53–4. The honour of having
pointed at this connection should be bestowed on G. Buccellati, cf. his ‘La “Carriera” di
David e quella di Idrimi, re di Alalac’, Bibbia e Oriente 4 (1962), 95–9.
188 Biblical studies and the failure of history
is certainly best to proceed with historical studies in such a manner that we not
confuse literary invention with historical event.49
It would be correct to maintain that we are in possession of two ‘histories’:
on the one hand, we have the history of Palestine, a history of the real world and,
on the other, a history of Israel – that is, a literary history of the Old Testament.
Sometimes, these two histories overlap, as in the description of Sennacherib
ante muros. More often, however, two such histories have little or nothing in
common. The situation of the modern historian can be summed up in the words
of the late Gösta Ahlström, who once explained to me: ‘If I were to write a his-
tory of Israel in the Iron Age, it would hardly cover more than a few pages, but if
I were to write a history of Palestine in the same period, it would take a thousand
pages.’ As is well known, he actually wrote those thousand pages.50
49. J. A. Soggin’s three ‘histories’ of Israel (A History of Israel, London: SCM, 1984;
Einführung in die Geschichte Israels und Judas, Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche
Buchgesellschaft, 1991; and An Introduction to the History of Israel and Judah, London:
SCM, 1993) show an increasing understanding of the problems involved. They are, on
the other hand, also examples of the kinds of problems that appear when biblical and
extra-biblical sources are believed to speak about the same thing: the history of biblical
Israel. Extra-biblical sources do not speak about biblical Israel.
50. Ahlström, The History of Ancient Palestine from the Palaeolithic Period to Alexander’s
Conquest.
11
A question of this kind begs a negative answer and, as a matter of fact, it is diffi-
cult to escape such an answer. As I see it, it is increasingly problematic to speak
about an Israelite religion in the way that this concept is normally used. It is
my intention to present but a select few of the arguments that might be directed
against this understanding of Israelite religion. The decision to let the historian
speak, instead of the student of religious history, is deliberate and it is my hope
that the historian’s perspective may help to cast light on the problems.
Albright.2 While it is always sad to dismiss beautiful stories about the origins of
early Israel, it must be done out of respect for modern historical research and,
in particular, the results of modern archaeological excavations in Palestine and
the ancient Near East. There was no longer room for a conquest of ‘Canaan’.
It was better to let the people of Israel fail than demand the fall of God. Men
denhall’s revision of the early history of Israel had the necessary consequence of
abandoning the competing construction of Israel’s settlement in Palestine. Few
of his fellow students of Albright regretted this part of Mendenhall’s argument.
His separation of religious from general history – an effort which reappears
in Norman K. Gottwald’s Tribes of Yahweh and which paved the way for the
thesis of a ‘revolutionary’ Israel3 – must be considered unnatural, if for no other
reason than that, in the Old Testament, history and religion are inseparable. I
have consistently stressed that, in this literature, the relationship between history
and religion is both logical and consequent.4 To be more precise, if we accept
the unity of religion and history in the Old Testament, it is clear that such unity
cannot be traced back to Israel’s early history, but is rather an axiom of later
Old Testament historiography, whose aim is to present the history of the people
of Israel and their worship as a whole. Put in another way: the Old Testament’s
history of the people of Israel is not the history of an ordinary people but rather
of the people of God. How we decide on the status of the Old Testament as a
historical source, therefore, is paramount to our evaluation of the Old Testament
as a source of the religious history of Israel. To the extent we give up the main
lines of the construction of Israel’s history as found in the Old Testament, we
will have trouble maintaining the Old Testament’s construction of religion.
Nevertheless, when introducing this subject, we must also say that it is not
possible to transfer automatically the narrow literary relationship between the
history of the people and of the Yahweh religion to the factual level of actual
history. We cannot merely assume that religion in ancient Palestine was identi-
cal with the history of the nations of that time, simply because religious and
historical event do not belong to the same logical categories. In order to avoid
such severe categorical mistakes, we need to investigate each case for itself and
find the best methods and procedures relevant.
In spite of all the objections which have been raised, we cannot exclude
in advance that Mendenhall may be correct – namely, that the history of the
people of Israel has to be submitted to a dramatic deconstruction. At the same
time, the description of the Yahwistic–Mosaic religion, as presented by the Old
Testament, may be correct – although I see little reason to suppose this to be the
case. Rejecting a naive acceptance of the biblical description of the history of
Israelite religion, I have already presented my own construction of this religious
2. Cf. the description of Mosaic faith in William F. Albright, From the Stone Age to
Christianity (New York: Doubleday, 1940).
3. Cf. N. K. Gottwald, The Tribes of Yahweh (Maryknoll, NY: Orbis, 1979).
4. N. P. Lemche, ‘The Development of the Israelite Religion in Light of Recent Studies
on the Early History of Israel’, in J. A. Emerton (ed.) Congress Volume Leuven 1989:
Supplements to Vetus Testamentum 43 (1991), 97–115, 103.
Is it still possible to speak about an ‘Israelite religion’? 191
history several times.5 Here, I concentrate on some new ideas which have arisen
in the last decade or so.
Biblical historiography
5. N. P. Lemche, Ancient Israel (Sheffield: JSOT Press, 1988), last chapter, and Lemche,
‘The Development’. Both descriptions are, in fact, too short and do not represent ade-
quate histories of Israel’s religion, though they sketch the main outline.
6. Cf. N. P. Lemche, ‘On the Problem of Studying Israelite History’, Biblische Notizen 24
(1984), 94–124, especially 111–14. The expression ‘rationalistic paraphrase’ is based on
studies by Mario Liverani and Eduard Meyer relating to the habit of extracting historical
information from Old Testament narratives by applying rationalistic means.
7. Cf. my previous evaluation of Gottwald’s acceptance of the main arguments of Martin
Noth’s Überlieferungsgeschichtliche Studien, I (Königsberg, 1943; repr. Darmstadt:
Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, 1963): N. P. Lemche, Early Israel (VT supplement,
37; Leiden: E. J. Brill, 1985), 284–99.
8. The best overview over this debate is found in Otto Bächli, Amphiktyonie im Alten
Testament (Basel: Friedrich Reinhardt Verlag, 1977).
192 Biblical studies and the failure of history
and involved perspectives on the general study of the historical tradition of early
Israel as found in the Old Testament. When there was no more reason to accept
the idea of a sacral Israelite league of twelve tribes as part of Israel’s early his-
tory, scholars were forced to look for a different background for the ideology
of twelve tribes in the Old Testament – a background that would either be in
the history of the Israelite tribes before the settlement in Palestine or after the
conclusion of this settlement, if it had, in fact, occurred as described by, for
example, Albrecht Alt.9 It is rather easy today to select which option is the most
likely because there is little prospect of any longer maintaining the notion of an
Israelite immigration, let alone a conquest.
This dismissal of the ‘Landnahme’ theory is valid in spite of several stud-
ies that have been published recently, which still concern themselves with a
historical immigration of early Israelites. For example, Gary Rendsburg dates
an Israelite conquest to the eleventh century bce. However, the argument is
not convincing.10 Just as hopeless is the proposal by Rainer Neu, who wants
to ‘embellish’ the history of Israelite tribes with anecdotes drawn from social
anthropology.11 In general, current discussions about early Israel hardly pay
much attention to the immigration hypothesis any longer. The obituary of this
discussion may have been written by Thomas L. Thompson in his The Early
History of the Israelite People and Gösta W. Ahlström in his The History of
Ancient Palestine from the Palaeolithic Period to Alexander’s Conquest.12
It is no longer legitimate to speak of the historicity of the patriarchs, Israel’s
sojourn in Egypt or the wandering of Israel’s tribes in the desert. The biblical
tradition referring to such epochs cannot be considered reflections of Israel’s
actual history, but belongs, like the conquest in the Book of Joshua, to narra-
tives rooted in a later ideology. These stories are fictive and cannot be used as
historical sources for a reconstruction of events reflected by them. Following
the stories of the immigration of the Israelite tribes into Palestine, which are
fictive and not historical sources, comes the Period of the Judges. After the
dissolution of the theory of an amphictyony, such a ‘period of the judges’ can
no longer be considered the home of historical tradition. We must change our
ideas in a fundamental way, not least because of historical arguments that Egypt
controlled Palestine, or a fair part of that land, until at least 1075bce.13 If this
9. Albrecht Alt, ‘Die Landnahme der israelitischen Stämme in Palästina (1925)’, in his
Kleine Schriften zur Geschichte Israels I (Munich: Beck,1953), 89–125.
10. Gary Rendsburg, ‘The Date of the Exodus and the Cinquest/Settlement: The Case for the
1100s’, VT 42 (1992), 510–27.
11. Rainer Nau, Von der Anarchie zum Staat (Neukirchen: Neukirchener Verlag, 1992).
12. Thomas L. Thompson, Early History of the Israelite People (Leiden: E. J. Brill, 1992);
Gösta W. Ahlström, The History of Ancient Palestine from the Palaeolithic Period to
Alexander’s Conquest (Sheffield: Sheffield University Press, 1993). Cf. also Diana
Edelman (ed.) ‘Towards a Consensus of the Emergence of Israel in Canaan’, SJOT
1991/2, 1–116, with contributions by N. P. Lemche, G. W. Ahlström, R. B. Coote, I.
Finkelstein and others.
13. See Donald B. Redford, Egypt, Canaan, and Israel in Ancient Times (Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press, 1992), 290. At the same time, it has to be said that Redford
Is it still possible to speak about an ‘Israelite religion’? 193
is true, then the time we allow for the ‘Period of the Judges’ is all too short, at
least if one reckons with an introduction of the monarchy in the last decades
of the eleventh century bce. It is highly unlikely that traditions about the early
history of Israel can be dated to a time when Israel was not yet a state. Instead
of speaking of a ‘Period of the Judges’ as the formative period of Israelite tradi-
tion, it is more common to see the period of a ‘united monarchy’ under David
and Solomon as the time when these traditions came into being – a construc-
tion which would fit the classical dating of the oldest sources in the Pentateuch
excellently, as it places the Yahwist in the tenth century bce. If we must lower
the date of the Pentateuchal sources considerably, such a change would not
itself create problems for the assumption that the tradition of Israel’s prehistory
was formed during the reigns of David and Solomon in the tenth century bce.
The problems arise when we begin to ask questions about the historicity of the
biblical tradition of the ‘united monarchy’ and the glorious days of David and
Solomon. If we have to relegate the tradition of an early Hebrew empire to the
realm of mythology, we can hardly argue in favour of seeing this mythologically
great period as the home of a historical tradition about early Israel. I find little
to recommend the hypothesis of this great Israelite kingdom in the tenth century
bce. But if this, nevertheless, is the case, then the traditions of the twelve tribe
league and of the emergence of Israelite Yahweh religion hardly belong to the
tenth century bce.
Ten years ago, hardly any serious biblical scholar would have questioned
the historicity of the Davidic Empire. During the last decade, serious objections
against the biblical imagery of Israel’s early greatness have begun to appear.
Because the historicity of this empire is relevant to our discussion, I will address
it. We have only a single source which informs us of the period of David and
Solomon (i.e. the Old Testament). Other sources, dating to the tenth century
bce, whether Egyptian, Syrian or Mesopotamian, have no information about
any such empire. According to Giovanni Garbini and others, we must see the
silence in non-biblical sources about David and Solomon as an argument against
the historicity of the biblical story and it is hardly possible to claim that such
an argument is without cause.14 According to the Old Testament, the Kingdom
of David included the area between Wadi el-’Arish to the south-west and the
Euphrates to the north-east. However, though this would have made David’s
kingdom the largest empire of its time, we have no references to its existence
outside of the Old Testament. From a methodological point of view, objec-
tions may be raised against Garbini simply because it can be described as an
argumenta ex silentio. It is also maintained that what we have of ancient Near
Eastern documents relevant to the tenth century bce is not much. Sources are,
is not talking about a stable Egyptian empire in those days, but of a weakened politi-
cal organisation. Aside from this, he – like other Egyptologists – still reckons with an
Israelite immigration with reference to the activity of the Shasu nomads.
14. Cf. Giovanni Garbini, History and Ideology in Ancient Israel (London: SCM Press,
1988), 21–32, and the serious criticism of the traditional view on this period in Redford,
Egypt, Canaan, and Israel, 283–311.
194 Biblical studies and the failure of history
indeed, few. Perhaps there were other documents yet to be found (also an argu-
ment from silence!)? It may be that the biblical historiographer is somewhat
exaggerated. David’s kingdom may have been great and important, though
hardly as large as imagined by biblical writers (again, an argument from silence
implied by this rationalistic paraphrase!15).
The argument in favour of the existence of a reduced Israelite kingdom,
provoked by a methodologically questionable discussion, may indicate that
the question about this kingdom may have been engaged from the wrong per-
spective, as the Old Testament has always been the point of departure for such
discussions. The problem is the same as those presented for earlier periods of
Israel’s history – namely, that it is not possible to bring information concern-
ing this history in the Old Testament into harmony with extra-biblical – mostly
archaeological, but also textual – evidence. The case of a ‘Davidic Empire’ is
hardly different. What has archaeology to add? For lack of something better,
we depend upon the review of material in the recent book of David Jamieson-
Drake, where it is argued that it is hardly legitimate to think of a centralized
state within the territory of Judah before the middle of the eighth century bce.16
According to Jamieson-Drake’s observations, there is no need to speculate
about a tenth century Israelite empire. If one were still to wish to save some of
the biblical tradition, one must present a rationalistic paraphrase that has little
to do with the Bible’s narrative.
Although such arguments have certainly not been received with unified
acclaim, it is easy to show that Jamieson-Drake’s evidence goes very well with
other sources related to a ‘time of David’, if for no other reason than that this
kingdom is not mentioned by a single source outside the Old Testament. There
is not a single reference to such a kingdom; nor is there archaeological evidence
for its existence at present. We may have to conclude that the historicity of
David and Solomon rests on an argument that is no different from those pertain-
ing to the historicity of Joshua.
15. Thus also Garbini, who reckons with a small Judean state of limited size (History and
Ideology, chapter 2). Speculations along this line can also be found in J. A. Soggin,
Einführung in die Geschichte Israels und Judas (Darmstadt: Wiussenschaftliche
Buchgesellschaft, 1991), 42–61, and J. Maxwell Miller and John Hayes, A History of
Ancient Israel and Judah (Philadelphia, PA: Westminster John Knox, 1986), 179–80
(with a map showing the ‘small’ Kingdom of David, 181!), but also outside the circle
of biblical scholars in Mario Liverani, Antico Oriente: Storia, società, economia (Bari:
Laterza, 1988), 669–72.
16. David Jamieson-Drake, Scribes and Schools in Monarchic Israel: A Socio-Archaeological
Approach (Sheffield: JSOT Press, 1991). Cf., especially, his résumé, 138–9: ‘There is
no evidence that Judah began to function as a state at any time prior to the tremendous
increase in population, building, production, centralization and specialization which
began the 8th century.’ See also Michael Niemann, Herrschaft, Königtum und Staat:
Skizzen zur soziokulturellen Entwicklung im monarchischen Israel (Tübingen: Mohr,
1993), 282, who concludes, evidently without knowledge of Jamieson-Drake’s book:
‘Mir scheint von den Ergebnissen der vorliegende Arbeit her, daß … für das Sudreich
Juda erst ab Ussia, für das Nordreich Israel ab Omri, von einem “Staat” gesprochen
werden kann.’
Is it still possible to speak about an ‘Israelite religion’? 195
We have reached the tentative conclusion that the Old Testament is still
important for this period simply because we have no other written sources per-
taining to David and Solomon, or to anything related to an early Hebrew mon-
archy. Second, these biblical narratives are of questionable value, if not totally
useless historically. The ‘historical account’ of the Old Testament can hardly be
reconciled with the actual history of Palestine for the Iron I and II periods – and
certainly not with any history that predates the ninth century bce (in Israel’s
case), or the eighth century (in Judah’s).17 Apparently, the Old Testament cannot
be considered a historical source in the usual sense of the term. It might, rather,
be better to give up the idea entirely that the Old Testament includes a ‘history
of Israel’ (which, however, does not exclude the fact that we find historical
information here and there). The Old Testament does not describe the past ‘wie
sie gewesen’, but presents opinions of various writers about the past.
There now remains the question of the relationship between such opinions of
the past and what actually happened regarding the history of Israel in antiquity.
Can the biblical narrative be seen as, in some way, comparable to the actual
history of ancient Israel? Does the Old Testament contain history writing, or do
we find only more literary genres there?18 When we speak of biblical writers as
historians, we can only conclude that we are almost always wrong, both in great
perspective and in minor detail.19 It would, perhaps, be better to compare these
writers to fiction writers. It is obvious that they did not see historical reality as a
problem because they did not see it as their task to cast light over the past. Their
aims were different.
On the other hand, we definitely find a ‘history of Israel’ in the Old Testament,
although it is a history that has very little in common with a proper history
of Palestine. The biblical and real history forms two independent universes. It
needs to be understood that the universe created by biblical writers was cre-
ated entirely on the basis of their situation and time. The real past was only of
17. We need a survey, in the style of Jamieson-Drake, of Judean archaeological material and
of the material from the northern part of Palestine. It is of decisive importance to ascer-
tain whether or not the many monumental remains, including remains of fortress-like
constructions, belongs to the late tenth century (i.e. to the ‘time of Solomon’ or Jeroboam
I) or to the ninth century (i.e. to the ‘time of the House of Omri’). At least so much can
be said that the archaeological situation in northern Palestine is at this time very different
from the impression we get from the southern part of the country.
18. The dichotomy between our usually rather naive use of the Old Testament, which is
commonly merely paraphrased, and methods which have been developed to deal with
other sources is remarkable. Cf., for example, the evaluation of the rabbinic sources to
the early history of Judaism in Doron Mendels, The Rise and Fall of Jewish Nationalism
(New York: Doubleday, 1992), 5: ‘Rabbinic traditions were composed and put into writ-
ing centuries after the events took place, and therefore cannot be used as evidence for the
period under discussion’ (i.e. 200bce to 135ce). It can really be said as simply as that.
19. Cf. also my review of Baruch Halpern, The First Historians: The Hebrew Bible and
History (San Francisco, CA: Harper & Row, 1988), in JNES 50 (1991), 215–17. Halpern
tries to defend biblical historiographers and considers them historians in our sense of the
word. Halpern, rather, shows – against his own intentions – that biblical historiography
and modern history writing belong to two separate categories.
196 Biblical studies and the failure of history
importance if it helped to cast light over the fate of people living at the time
of the writers of the Bible’s historiography. This is very clear when it comes
to the early ‘history of Israel’. Although it is important to establish when such
historical narratives came into being, an exact date for such historiography is
not decisive. I will, therefore, merely express my opinion briefly.
It is not possible to argue in favour of an early date for Israelite historiog-
raphy. We are forced to look for an alternative, and dates in the late monarchic
period, the exile or even after the exile recommend themselves. Little can be
said in favour of a pre-exilic date, except from the wish of some modern schol-
ars to have at least something remain from the pre-exilic period. The same can
be said about the exilic date for this literature. Only the hope of modern scholars
that the historiography – or most of it – belongs to early periods keeps such
early dates in focus. This is especially relevant for the time of Josiah. In regard
to the exile, it is as if scholars are thinking of late pre-exilic Israelites as merely
waiting to be dragged away into exile in Babylonia so that they could find the
leisure to write their memoirs.
In favour of the third option, we might well refer to John Van Seters –
although he himself favours an exilic date for the biblical historiography. He
sees a marked mixture of Babylonian and Greek features in biblical historiog-
raphy.20 However, echoes of Greek historiography are hardly to be expected in
biblical historical writings that date from the time of the exile. It is much too
early, and it does not help that Van Seters refers to Hecataeus’s history writing,21
not least as that is to be characterized as no longer extant! If Van Seters’s obser-
vations are correct, they point, rather, to another period (i.e. the period when the
Greeks ‘ruled the East’ – namely, the Hellenistic Period). We should think of the
time of the Seleucid Empire, especially the early part of its history in the third
century bce. During this period we can expect an interchange between Greek
and Babylonian culture, much in the way we find a blending of traditions in the
Old Testament.22
It is still open whether this proposal of a Seleucid date for biblical histori-
ography will stand. We are in need of comprehensive comparative studies of
biblical and Greek historiography and they are still to be written.
‘Israel’ as a people?
20. Cf., already, John Van Seters, In Search of History: Historiography in the Ancient World
and the Origins of Biblical History (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1983),
rephrased in an elegant fashion in John Van Seters, Prologue to History: The Yahwist as
Historian in Genesis (Louisville, KY: Westminster John Knox, 1992).
21. So, Van Seters, In Search of History, passim.
22. Cf. Chapter 8, this volume.
Is it still possible to speak about an ‘Israelite religion’? 197
23. Gösta W. Ahlström, Who Were the Israelites?, (Winona Lake, IN: Eisenbrauns, 1986).
24. Marit Skjeggestad, ‘Ethnic Groups in Early Iron Palestine: Some Remarks on the Use of
the Term ‘Israelite’ in Recent Research’, SJOT 6 (1992), 159–86.
25. Niels Peter Lemche, The Canaanites and Their Land: The Tradition of the Canaanites
(Sheffield: JSOT Press, 1991).
26. Philip R. Davies, In Search of ‘Early Israel’ (Sheffield: JSOT Press, 1992).
198 Biblical studies and the failure of history
of the Old Testament.27 Amused by recent trends, he states that modern histori-
ans over the last generation have written a history of the landscape of Palestine
rather than a proper history of the Israelite people. His observation is correct. As
historians, we must decide whether we prefer to write a history of the Israelite
people (i.e. a history based on the Bible) or, as ordinary historians, to concen-
trate on the fate of the landscape of Palestine and its people(s).28
27. J. Maxwell Miller, ‘Is It Possible to Write a History of Israel without Relying on the
Hebrew Bible?’, in D. V. Edelman (ed.) The Fabric of History: Text, Artefact, and
Israel’s Past (Sheffield: JSOT Press, 1991).
28. The contributions by Ernst Axel Knauf, ‘From History to Interpretation’, and Thomas
L. Thompson, ‘Text, Context and Referent in Israelite Historiography’ in Edelman, The
Fabric of History (pp. 26–64 and 65–92, respectively) show that it is possible to continue
with this terminological problem.
29. We must reckon as paradigmatic in character, exactly because of its lack of clarification,
the verdict of Mark Smith relating to the religious conditions of early Israel: ‘In sum,
the Israelites may [or may not?!] have perceived themselves as a people different from
the Canaanites. Separate religious traditions of Yahweh, separating traditions of origin
in Egypt for at least some component of Israel, and separate geographical holdings in the
hill country contributed to the Israelite sense of difference from their Canaanite neigh-
bors inhabiting the coast and the valleys. Nonetheless, Israelite and Canaanite cultures
shared a great deal in common, and religion was no exception’ (Mark Smith, The Early
History of God: Yahweh and the other Deities in Ancient Israel, San Francisco, CA:
Harper & Row, 1990), 7.
Is it still possible to speak about an ‘Israelite religion’? 199
anything that existed apart from their current Sitz im Leben – namely, of the Old
Testament. Religious life in ancient Palestine can be considered a Palestinian
variation of religion as generally found among the people of western Asia and of
the Levant, in particular. For these reasons, I concur with the remark by William
G. Dever: ‘there was little distinction between Canaanite and Israelite religion,
at least in practice. The rituals were virtually the same, even if one assumes that
Israel’s Yahwistic theology was an innovation – and that is not always evident.’30
Perhaps religion in Israel and Judah was generally the same because the god
Yahweh was the dominant deity in both countries. On the other hand, it is not so
easy to determine whether or not this Yahweh was identical with the Yahweh of
the Bible, as he may have changed character as time passed (something which
seems likely with regard to his marital status).
Although it is recommended that studies of Israelite religion change their
orientation, we need a series of studies dealing with individual aspects of that
religion because it is no longer relevant to study religious phenomena in isola-
tion. As an example, I refer to Herbert Niehr’s recent study of the develop-
ment of monotheism in the ancient Near East.31 It would also be rewarding to
present overviews of Palestinian religion in pre-exilic times along the lines of
Frederick H. Cryer’s book on divination, describing ancient Palestinian society
as ‘magical’.32 Against the impression of a Palestinian magic society, we have a
description of Israelite religion as offered by writers of the Old Testament. In the
future, we will most likely see more studies of this kind, bolstered by archaeo-
logical observations. The demonstration of an extended worship of the dead in
Judah under the kings by Elizabeth Bloch-Smith may serve as an example of
what to expect.33
A change of paradigm?
In order to return to the issue of a change of paradigm, we need to state that this
change is not automatically caused by concrete results from historical investiga-
tion or because of recent discoveries pertinent to the history of religion; nor is it
caused by new proposals for dating the sources of the Old Testament. All such
advances merely contribute to a modification of the ruling paradigm. It is not a
consequence of a new paradigm that modern scholarship is no longer interested
in talking about a conquest of Canaan by Israel or that it is becoming normal
to speak about post-exilic writers as composers of biblical literature (if this is
30. William G. Dever, Recent Archaeological Discoveries and Biblical Research (Seattle,
WA: University of Washington Press, 1990), 166.
31. Herbert D. Niehr, Der höchste Gott: Alttestamentlicher JHWH-Glaube im Kontext
syrisch-kanaanäischer Religion des 1. Jahrtausends v. Chr. (Berlin: De Gruyter, 1990).
32. Frederick H. Cryer, Divination in Ancient Israel and Its Near Eastern Environment
(Sheffield: Sheffield University Press, 1993).
33. Cf. Elizabeth Bloch-Smith, Judahite Burial Practices and Beliefs About the Dead
(Sheffield: Sheffield University Press, 1993).
200 Biblical studies and the failure of history
actually the case). Such changes belong within the old paradigm and are only
variations within that paradigm.
A new paradigm will only appear when an absolutely new understanding of
the character of biblical narrative is accepted, seeing this no longer as historical
information about the past, but as literary fiction. The effort to excavate his-
torical information from such fictive literature has been characterized by Bernd
Jörg Diebner as ‘Offenbarungs-Archäologie’.34 As long as this kind of textual
study survives, the old paradigm survives. As long as it is believed that the Old
Testament is a source in itself, nothing changes. Only when we accept that there
are two worlds involved (on the one hand, the world of the Old Testament, and,
on the other, the world of ancient Palestine) can we speak of a new paradigm.
We need to respect the individuality of both worlds, though we need also to
introduce new methods to study such worlds. We need to introduce a dialectical
situation in which it is possible to transfer the results of the one world to the
other and thereby achieve a relevant synthesis.
34. Cf. Bernd Jörg Diebner, ‘Wieder die ‘Offenbarungs-Archäologie’ in der Wissenschaft
vom Alten Testament’, Dielheimer Blätter zum Alten Testament 18 (1984), 30–53.
12
As described in Chapter 9, in the first scene of the movie The Godfather, the
old Don, Vito Corleone, head of an established mafia family in New York, gives
audience to whomever among his followers has a request to make. Among the
supplicants appears a very shy person, asking for revenge because some young-
sters have mishandled his daughter. They were arrested by the police, but in
their appearance before the judge they got a very mild and, according to the
girl’s father, absolutely insufficient sentence. The content of the dialogue which
follows is especially interesting. Don Corleone opens with a forewarning, first
of all, because the applicant had gone to the police and not to the Godfather. He
mentions that the applicant has been inattentive and has not shown him respect,
and, further, that he has never wanted his friendship because he never wanted
to owe the Godfather a service and be in his debt. As the scene continues, the
Godfather refers to the fact that the applicant needed no protection, because he
believed that the court would provide him with it. Only now, this being clearly
not the case, the applicant asks the Godfather to give him justice, but without
respect, as he still does not offer his friendship to the Godfather and is still not
prepared to address Don Corleone as Godfather. When the applicant offers to
pay for the service, the offer is simply refused as disrespectful. The applicant
should have come at once, when he was first offended and the scoundrels would
already have suffered. Finally, the Godfather offers his friendship to the appli-
cant and prompts that any enemy of the applicant will at the same time be enemy
of the Godfather and will therefore always fear the anger of the Godfather. The
scene closes as the applicant agrees to become the client of the godfather, a
relationship symbolized in his kissing the hand of Don Corleone and greeting
him as Godfather. The applicant is warned that, although the present favour
is given as a gift, the godfather may want his services at some later occasion,
which comes soon thereafter, as the movie continues.
This scene excellently embodies the essentials of the concept of patronage:
that special relationship that ideally exists between a patron and his clients or
between a ruler and the ruled of traditional societies. Patronage is, briefly, the
type of relationship found between people of different standings in decentral-
ized, partly centralized political societies, as well as in centralized states, on the
202 Biblical studies and the failure of history
1. An excellent though dated description of the Roman system on all levels of society
can be found in Ronald Syme, The Roman Revolution (revised edn, Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1951).
Kings and clients 203
other sub-concepts such as friendship, respect and fear appear. The patron asks
the client to be a friend, to ‘love’ and to show the patron respect, which is cer-
tainly not passive, but a very active expression of subordination to the patron.
On the other hand, ‘fear’ is not a part of the relationship between patron and
client but the general attitude of foreigners who experience the negative effects
of the system – for example, in a confrontation between two rival patronage
groups. Fortunately, we do not need to break entirely new ground in the present
context, although we will need to limit our discussion. Several scholars (e.g.
Glueck,5 Sakenfeld6 and Clark7) have already published analyses of a few tech-
nical Hebrew expressions that obviously refer to the ideology underlying the
patronage system. Among such studies, Nelson Glueck’s old German disserta-
tion from 1927 on the term חסדmay count as a major contribution and should
still hold its position in spite of Gordon R. Clark’s new examination of חסד.
Glueck’s study is divided into three parts, the first devoted to the human sphere
alone, the second to the attitude of humans toward God, and the third to the use
of חסדto express the attitude of God towards humans. While Glueck does not
explicitly address patronage in this small volume, some of his conclusions point
directly towards it. Let me quote from his first section of conclusions: ‘ חסדist die
einem Rechts-Pflicht-Verhältnis entsprechende Verhaltungsweise. … Versteht
man חסדals eine solche Verhaltungsweise, so erklärt sich die früher festgestellte
Tatsache, daß nur diejenigen, die in einem Rechts-Pflicht-Verhältnis stehen חסד
empfangen und erweisen können.’8 These statements precisely articulate the
essence of patronage! The rest of his book simply elaborates upon this theme;
the essentials are all contained here. It is self-evident that a number of con-
cepts can be introduced as components of Glueck’s relationship characterized
by obligations and duties; he himself immediately points to the concept of אמת.9
It is also obvious that his two subsequent chapters, which broaden the perspec-
tive to include the world of the divine being, contribute in fundamental ways
to understanding the concept. They do not change its content in any important
respect, apart from the fact that the relationship between patron and client will
necessarily be clearer under such circumstances where one party is God and the
other his creature.
It is meaningful and perceptive, however, that Glueck also includes
the concept of ‘knowledge of God’ (‘Gotteserkenntnis’) and ‘fear of God’
(‘Gottesfurcht’).10 Without difficulty, the first can be compared to the idea of
friendship as part of the system, and the second to the demand of respect for the
patron. A number of Hebrew expressions are close at hand, but I will only refer
to that of ‘knowing God’, expressed by the Hebrew verb ידע,11 and, of course
and above all, the ‘fear of God’, יראת אלהים.
When we direct our attention to the common function of these terms, our
attention is directed to the concept of covenant. As already explained by Glueck,
the establishment of חסדcan be effectuated by a ceremony, which includes a
solemn oath. When two parties decide to establish such a relationship, what
is more natural than to conclude it formally in some kind of ceremony? As
soon as we speak of an agreement of this kind, combined with such symbols
as the pronouncing of oaths and claims, we are in the middle of a discussion
on the concept of covenant. It is no accident that during the 1960s, when the
discussion about the role of the covenant in ancient Israel reached its highest,
numerous technical terms and ideas relevant to the present argument, including
those mentioned above, were central to the debate. The discussion of patron-
age may thus stimulate a renewed interest in the importance of the covenant
concept among ancient Israelites. This enquiry can, however, now be kept on
a more realistic level than previously. The old debate closed in 1969 when
Lothar Perlitt published his study of ‘Bundestheologie’, which he identified as
Deuteronomistic.12 By and large, he was correct. In most places in the Hebrew
Bible, where we find the specific expressions of the divine covenant, they are
doubtlessly either Deuteronomistic or inspired by Deuteronomistic concepts.
However, this Deuteronomistic theology is only connected in a limited way
to the Hebrew term ברית, which is certainly a solemn technical expression for
‘covenant’. The debate has overlooked that this term may not be exclusive, to
the extent that all kinds of covenants must perforce include it. Other terms may
be sufficient as expressions of the essence of the covenant relationship, whether
between the divine and the human world or among human beings alone.
At this point, we can leave the basic question of whether or not חסדexpresses
the essentials of the patronage system. The next step involves a broader view of
the old covenant discussion. Generally, ancient Near Eastern documents touch-
ing on the concept of covenant concern two different types of arrangement:
on the one hand, pacts that regulate the connection between persons of equal
standing, and, on the other, agreements that include persons on different levels.
As patronage explicitly belongs in the second category, this will be the more
promising subject to discuss in the present connection.
In 1955 when George Mendenhall started the discussion on covenant ideas,
he referred to parallels to the biblical concept found in Hittite international
treaties of the second millennium bce, and rightly so, as such treaties – mostly
vassal treaties binding vassals in Syria or Asia Minor to their Hittite overlord
– can be considered expressions of the basic notions attached to the system of
11. See also Herbert B. Huffmonn, ‘The Treaty Background of Hebrew Yāda‛’, BASOR 181
(1966), 31–7.
12. Lothar Perlitt, Bundestheologie im Alten Testament (WMANT 36; Neukirchen:
Neukirchener Verlag, 1969).
208 Biblical studies and the failure of history
13. George E. Mendenhal, Law and Covenant in Israel and the Ancient Near East (Pittsburgh,
PA: The Biblical Colloquium, 1955).
14. The Assyrian treaties are now available in Parpola, Simo and Kazuko Watanabe, Neo-
Assyrian Treaties and Loyalty Oaths (State Archives of Assyria; Helsinki: Helsinki
University Press, 1988).
15. In fact, the terrible fate of Zedekiah, contrasting with the lenient treatment of Jehoiachin,
may be a consequence of what was likely to happen when a Judean king deserted his
overlord. While Nebuchadnezzar merely confined Jehoiachin to a ‘golden prison’ in
Babylon, Zedekiah was treated by the same Babylonian king in the harshest possible
fashion. In contrast to Zedekiah, Jehoiachin was no vassal of Babylon, having been
installed by the Egyptian king, whereas Zedekiah had been placed on the throne by the
very king who was later to dispose of him. Nebuchadnezzar, therefore, had no legal
rights to punish Jehoiachin and he certainly treated him in a most gentle way – con-
sidering the manners of the time – whereas he may have felt it quite correct to destroy
Zedekiah, who had betrayed him.
16. Mario Liverani, ‘Contrasti e confluence di concezioni politiche nell’età di El-Amarna’,
RA 61 (1967), 1–18.
Kings and clients 209
kings all considered the relationship between themselves and their overlord,
Pharaoh, to be a form of patronage: they being the clients and Pharaoh the
patron. They expected Pharaoh to protect them once they paid their dues. It is,
however, also clear that the Egyptian ruler had another idea of their relationship:
the Palestinian princelets were mere low-ranking Egyptian bureaucrats and were
treated as such – that is, they were employees who needed to fulfil their duties
and would receive compensation accordingly, a compensation quite different in
kind than what was usual in a West Asiatic patronage system, where the patron
owed his loyal client a recompense. It is impossible in the present context to
continue much further along this line. However, I believe that I have formulated
a theory of one of the governing ideas of political life – and perhaps, indeed,
the central one: the relationship between client and patron. If this system was in
force in Palestine in the first millennium bce – and I believe that a fairly strong
case in favour of such a suggestion can be made – the relationship between the
kings of Israel and Judah and their subjects must have been regulated along
such lines, as the kings were patrons of their state, whereas commoners acted as
their clients, from whom the kings were entitled to expect and demand absolute
loyalty, but to whom they also needed to give recompense for their services.
A number of ideological matters concerning the status of the king point in
the same direction, not the least being the notion of the ‘just king’ who had his
place at the city gate, where he distributed justice among his people. Although
this is rather impractical for the ruler of a state, it belongs to the image of the
just king in Israel and elsewhere in the ancient Near East. Supporting this ideal
of the king as high judge, acting as personal patron of every single citizen of
the state, seeking help in critical situations, is the peculiar fact that no laws
have ever been uncovered in Israel, other than the clearly non-royal sections of
the Book of the Covenant in Exodus, with all its Near Eastern parallels. It is,
indeed, strange that no written law has ever appeared in the archives of a city in
Western Asia, not even from the highly centralized states of the Bronze Age.17
The reason for this is obviously that no one could force patrons to act against
their own judgement. The patron was, in this respect, surely a despot in Marx’s
meaning of the word and the system may be called despotic because the rulers
were the only people who had the ability to make final indisputable decisions.
At the same time, it was believed that the good ruler would act as a just arbiter
between his subjects. This faith was rooted in the understanding that the king
of Israel, like his colleagues in other parts of the ancient Near East, was a client
himself, not necessarily the client of some great king (although this was often
the case), but always the client of the God of Israel. It is a well-established
fact that from at least the days of the Amorite dynasties, at the beginning of
the second millennium bce, this notion formed a central part of royal ideology
both in the Levant and Mesopotamia, but not in Egypt, where the king was
believed to be the god himself. The god – whoever he might have been – was
the personal patron of the king and royal family. The deity did not accept such
17. See also Gerhard Liedke, Gestalt und Bezeichnung alttestamentlicher Rechtssätze
(WMANT 39; Neukirchen: Neukirchener Verlag, 1971), 57.
210 Biblical studies and the failure of history
obligation for nothing. On the contrary, the king was forever in his god’s debt
and needed to fulfil duties imposed upon him by his patron. Such a relationship
between god and king was a covenant relationship – echoing that described in
the Hebrew Bible, where we find ample evidence that such a royal covenant
must have formed the basis of the Davidic dynasty’s claim to be the rightful
royal family of Judah and Israel. There is no reason to elaborate further. It is
enough to maintain that this relationship between king and god is the reverse of
a normal relation between king and subjects. The clearest example of the inter-
changeability of such roles, is perhaps the description of the royal covenant in
2 Kings 11:17, which concludes the story of Athaliah’s reign. According to this
narrative, the high priest Jehoiada made a covenant between YHWH and the
king and between the king and the Judean nation.
What happened when the patronage system failed to operate according to
expectations? We have no hard evidence of a commoner’s reaction against the
king in such circumstances, although the Deuteronomistic history contains a
number of passages that open to this question, such as the story of Naboth’s
vineyard (1 Kgs 21) or of the confiscation of grazing land for the royal horses
in a time of famine (1 Kgs 18:3-6). A just king does not react in this way and
the complaints against the king are in these stories very severe. However, Psalm
89 represents a much more vivid example of the reaction of the client when
the patron–client relationship breaks down, though, here, the relationship is
between God and king. Without doubt, Psalm 89 provides a first-rate impression
of what may have been the usual reaction under such circumstances and there
is reason to pay special attention to the psalm’s use of the Hebrew word חסד.
Indeed, חסדmay be considered the dominant issue of the psalm, from the very
first word of the psalm’s text to its closure. At the beginning, the divine חסדhas
been established in heaven as an everlasting quality, on which basis the cov-
enant between YHWH and David was concluded. The hymn that follows (vv.
6-19; English: 5-18) merely stresses that חסדis a creation of the divine being
and, as such, should forever be considered an established fact. The plot engaged,
however, is that God, the patron, has deserted his client, who had done him no
harm and had neither broken his oath nor covenant. The hope for the future is
that the correct relationship will someday be re-established, thereby securing
the right of David’s dynasty to sit on the throne of Israel. I cannot say whether,
in ancient belief, the normal expressions of patronage were also considered as
founded in heaven; but such a likelihood can be argued since kingship, as the
Babylonians expressed it, was established in heaven and justice was a matter
for the gods. Be this as it may, the best conclusion to the present discussion
might be drawn from the famous words of Hammurabi of Babylon, who, in the
�
prologue to his codex, states:18
Law seems to play a great role in the Old Testament. The central part of the
Pentateuch, the five Books of Moses, consists of several collections of law mate-
rial, among which we could mention the Book of the Covenant, Exodus 21:23,
and the so-called Holiness Code, Leviticus 17–26. Also in Deuteronomy, the
fifth Book of Moses, we find another extensive collection of laws, from Chapter
12 to 26. How on earth can any person be induced to believe that no laws were
needed? A close look at the laws of the Old Testament, however, immediately
changes that perception, as it becomes clear that only a limited part of the laws
are laws in any normal sense of the word. In the Book of the Covenant, only the
first part, Exodus 21:2–22:16, contains what are juridical laws; the second part
(Exod. 22:17–23:16) is devoted to religious rules and regulations. Or, as it has
often been maintained, the first part of the Book of the Covenant belongs in the
realm of jus, while the second part represents fas.
Whether this distinction is absolutely clear – or was clear to people in
Antiquity – may, of course, be questioned, but a fundamental difference of style
between the laws of the first part and the religious regulations of the second can-
not be disregarded. Apart from the very first law, that concerning the Hebrew
slave (Exod. 21:2-11), which opens with ‘When you purchase a Hebrew as a
slave’,1 the laws are all in the third person singular and all should, according to
normal usage, be styled simple casuistic laws. They open with a description of
the case, while the second segment prescribes consequences to be drawn. The
above-mentioned law of the Hebrew Slave continues: ‘he will be your slave for
six years’. At the end, a special stipulation is attached to the simple law: ‘in the
seventh year, he is to go free without paying anything’.
In comparison, most of the laws or rules of the second part are phrased in
the second person singular or plural, and their form is less uniform than in the
first part. Accordingly, we find casuistic law in this section, but more dominant
are so-called apodictic laws. No situation is specified, only a prohibition against
doing or accepting something. For example: ‘You must not revile God, nor curse
1. Which is, however, hardly the original formulation. Cf. Chapter 1, this volume, and the
literature quoted there.
Justice in western Asia in antiquity 213
a chief of your own people’ (Exod. 22:28) – a style strictly related to the form
of the Ten Commandments.
The two other large collections already mentioned, the Holiness Code and
Deuteronomy, both contain religious regulations; Deuteronomy, however, also
has rules regulating the office of the king (Deut. 17:14-20), of the judge (Deut.
16:18-20; 17:8-13) and functions of the court (Deut. 19:14-21). These cannot,
however, be understood as laws in the strict sense, though Deuteronomy also
contains passages much closer in style and content to ordinary law, not least laws
– or rules and regulations, concerning marital life and norms (thus, Deut. 24).
In spite of this, it is my thesis that written law did not play any role in
Western Asia, and the presence of such legal material in the Old Testament
cannot be used in support of such a role. This can be supported by the fol-
lowing observations. First of all, it should be stressed that, apart from the Old
Testament, no laws have survived from ancient Palestine. This verdict should,
perhaps, be modified in one respect, as the ‘Temple Scroll’ found among the
Dead Sea Scrolls can be compared in many respects to the law collections of
the Pentateuch, especially the religious regulations. Various explanations have
been put forward to explain such similarity in style and content; the proposal
that the Temple Scroll was composed as part of the canonical laws of Moses is
one of the more fanciful, though not totally unreasonable.2 We do not need to
present a reasonable and exhaustive explanation for this, but only say that the
Temple Scroll and its laws should be evaluated alongside the religious regula-
tions of the Old Testament, rather than as an independent witness of a written
legal tradition in Western Asia.
Neither has any law yet turned up in the documents of Western Asia, either
in the form of single laws or as collections of laws. To the contrary, it is aston-
ishing that none of the rather ample archives of the Bronze Age Syrian states of
Ugarit and Alalah have contributed to our knowledge of written law in Western
� correctly, they have, indeed, contributed to our knowledge,
Asia. Perhaps more
but by indicating that such laws did not exist. It is our task to explain why this
was so, especially as it is obvious that these societies were not lawless bandit
societies.3 How could people survive in fairly complicated societies without
recourse to fixed rules, which could serve in disputes among the members of
these small Syrian and Palestinian states? That they were quarrelsome is evident
from reading their letters, local as well as international. Can the missing law
texts be attributed to a lack of archaeological luck or is there another way to
explain such absence?
I believe that a case can be made for the suggestion that such absence does,
in fact, reflect a specific attitude to law present in such societies and that this
2. See, thus, Hartmut Stegemann, Is the Temple Scroll a Sixth Book of the Torah – Lost
for 2,500 Years?, in Hershel Shanks, Understanding the Dead Sea Scrolls (New York:
Vintage Books, 1993), 126–36.
3. Although it could certainly be argued that most bandit societies have laws of their own,
though such laws are not normally written down, but should, nevertheless, be followed
by the members of the society in question.
214 Biblical studies and the failure of history
attitude is also reflected by the content of what is preserved as legal texts from
the ancient Near East.
In Mesopotamia, quite a few collections of law, mostly in casuistic style,
much like those in the Book of the Covenant, ranging from the beginning of
the second millennium bce (even earlier specimens may exist) and down to
Neo-Assyrian and Neo-Babylonian times. Among the best preserved are those
of Lipit-Ištar of Lagash (nineteenth century bce) and Hammurabi of Babylon
�
(eighteenth century bce), along with the anonymous law collection from Ešnunna
which is probably a little earlier than Hammurabi’s collection.4 Altogether, they
� important material and give indication
provide the student of ancient law with
of the principles of redaction behind these laws.
The famous Code of Hammurabi should particularly attract attention as it is
�
often described as a law code in use in the days of this important Mesopotamian
king. A number of topics are taken up and dealt with in these laws: simple
crimes, family matters, slave laws, etc. A certain – if not altogether conspicuous
– arrangement also seems to structure the compilation. Would anything suggest
that this collection could not have been the manual of a judge? I am not speaking
about the clearly propagandistic presentation, partly pictorial and partly in the
prologue and epilogue to this collection.
I think a double case can be made for not accepting this collection as a genu-
ine collection of laws to be followed in court. The first argument – indeed, an old
one5 – based on the long-established fact that among the thousands of juridical
documents from the time of this king, not a single definite reference to the laws
transmitted by the Codex can be found. Although this argument is certainly not
absolute, as it must be said to belong among the more taciturn of argumenta ex
silentio – it may be one of the instances where one is provoked to ask whether
the ‘ex silentio’ part simply comes from the nature of these questions. If the
basic assumption is wrong, that the Codex Hammurabi contained laws in the
modern sense of the word, then proving that �this was not the case by referring
to missing references to this law collection would hardly be enough. Some may
just argue that this only shows the limited extent of the influence of these laws
4. This law material is easily accessible in the recent edition by Martha T. Roth, Law
Collections from Mesopotamia and Asia Minor (2nd edn; Atlanta, GA: Scholars Press,
1997). Quotations from the Code of Hammurabi will follow Roth’s edition.
�
5. Basically, the one made by F. R. Kraus, ‘In zentrales Problem des altmesopotami
schen Rechtes: Was ist der Codex Hammurabi?’ Genava NS 8 (1960), 283–96. A more
recent general discussion of the character of the code of Hammurabi is to be found
�
in Horst Klengel, König Hammurabi und der Alltag Babylons (2nd edn; Darmstadt:
Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, 1992), 184–264. See also the recent discussion
in Eckart Otto, ‘Aspects of Legal Reforms and Reformulations in Ancient Cuneiform
and Israelite Law,’ in B. M. Levinson, Theory and Method in Biblical and Cuneiform
Law (JSOT supplement, 181: Sheffield: Sheffield Academic Press, 1994), 160–96,
and especially the summary in Johannes Renger, ‘Noch einmal: Was war der ‘Kodex’
Hammurapi – ein erlassenes Gesetz oder ein rechtsbuch?’, in Hans-Joachim Gehrke,
Rectskodifizierung und soziale Normen im interkulturellen Vergleich (Tübingen: Gunter
Narr Verlag 1994), 27–58. Cf. also the Introduction in Roth, Law Collections, 4–7.
Justice in western Asia in antiquity 215
6. A royal decree of justice issued at the beginning of the thirteenth century ce, and only
valid for a limited part of the Kingdom of Denmark, whereas, at the same time, compa-
rable collections of law were issued to be valid in other parts of the kingdom. In fact,
Denmark was not to have a common law valid for the whole country before the end of
the seventeenth century ce, King Christian V’s so-called ‘Danske Lov’ (Danish Law, or
rather: The Law of Denmark).
7. This should be understood literally. Traditional societies of the Middle East will have had
more than 90 per cent of the population engaged in the production of food. In Western
Asia, the percentage would be even higher.
8. We shall later deal with examples from social anthropological literature where this may
not be as simple as that.
216 Biblical studies and the failure of history
Western Asia
I am not going to continue with the Mesopotamian situation, but will instead
turn my attention to the situation in western Asia. Because the societal situation
in western Asia was less complicated than that present in Mesopotamia, it may
be better able to tell us something about the general conditions of the enactment
of justice in ancient Near Eastern societies.
On one very specific point, there was absolutely agreement between the ide-
ology of justice in western Asia and Mesopotamia. Both traditions understood
the king to be a righteous and just judge who was considered the highest institu-
tion of appeal to all subjects: the one who would distribute law and righteous-
ness.10 This, of course, is part of royal propaganda as found in any corner of the
territory and is, in itself, not very interesting as nobody would imagine the king
to be unjust. It is only in the very late biblical account of the Hebrew kingdom
that a pronounced criticism of the king as righteous can be found in the intro-
duction to the period of the kingdom in 1 Samuel 8:10-18, according to which
it should not be expected that the king will act as a just father of his country. To
the contrary, the king reserves to himself the right of taxation and will force his
subjects – men and women alike – to work for him.
This evaluation of the king’s role can only be understood as a prologue to
the highly tendentious description of the history of the Hebrew kingdom that
follows from 1 Samuel to 2 Kings, and runs counter to another description of the
right of the king in Deuteronomy 17:14-20, which could be considered to coun-
terbalance 1 Samuel 8:10-18. On the other hand, expectations are pronounced
in some Psalms of the Old Testament, especially Psalm 72, of the righteous rule
of the king, according to which God shall give his laws to the king that the king
may provide for the welfare of his people:
The parallel between these verses and the prologue to the Code of Hammurabi
� used as
is striking and shows that the idea of a human law, written down and
a guide by the judge in court, was foreign to the mind of the population of the
ancient Near East. Justice was divine business given to man from the gods and
effectuated by their representative on earth, the gracious king. A human law
would border on blasphemy (i.e. to formulate a written law as substitute of the
divine one would encroach on the prerogatives of the gods). What is written are
the practical interpretations of divine law, showing that its principles have or
will be followed.
A just king is not a very practical figure in daily life and the ideology of the
just king may be a kind of social myth explaining why it should be expected
that the enactment of law and order is per definition just and righteous, rather
than an explanation of the social placement of justice in an ancient society of
western Asia. The ideology of the righteous king not only legitimates king-
ship as such, but also the practice of law, regardless at what societal level the
practice is sought. The king is almost never part of an ordinary court case, these
being, rather, referred to in the administrative documents from Ugarit or in the
traditions of the Old Testament. Not even his administration seems to interfere
in the decisions of the court, if the case in question can be handled on a lower
– local – level.
It is true that in the Old Testament we have a story like the one in 1 Kings
3:16-28 which narrates the famous incident of the two women fighting for one
and the same child. The story is obviously not a reflection of any decision by
Solomon but stresses the importance of the king as – ideologically – the just
ruler. The concluding note to this incident is as follows: ‘When Israel heard the
judgment which the king had given, they all stood in awe of him; for they saw
that he possessed wisdom from God for administering justice.’ The king relies
on his godly overlord to provide him with the means of judging correctly.
Apart from such romances as the one in 1 Kings 3:16-28, most reflections
of the practice of law in the Old Testament point to the fact that this was local
business and not the business of the royal court. To study the background of the
missing written laws from western Asia – and probably also Mesopotamia – we
should turn to the local level of society to investigate the conditions of law,
knowing well that outside the Old Testament very little if anything is revealed
11. Biblical quotations are here from The Revised English Bible.
218 Biblical studies and the failure of history
Although the text probably expresses the opinion of some Jew of the Persian
or Hellenistic periods,13 there is, in fact, no reason to see the reference to the
evil and wickedness as a foreign element to the understanding of a text like that
found in the code of Hammurabi. Without this original distinction between good
and evil, oriental law� would have lacked legitimation, whether in the Israel of
the Old Testament14 or in the historical societies of Syria or Mesopotamia.
12. On this, including the status of law and justice in the relations between the palace and
local community in Western Asia, see especially a series of studies by Mario Liverani,
‘La royaté syrienne de l’age du Bronze Récent,’ in P. Garelli, Le Palais et la royauté
(Paris: Geuthner, 1974), 329–56; ‘Communautés de village et palais royales dans la
Syrie du IIème millénaire,’ Journal for the Economic and Social History of the Orient 8
(1975), 146–64; and ‘Communautés rurales dans la Syrie du IIe millénaire a.C.,’ Recuils
de la Société Jean Bodin pour l’histoire comparatives des institutions 41 (1983), 147–85.
13. Cf. on this below.
14. This is not the place to discuss this ‘Israel’. It will suffice to say that a number of Old
Testament scholars today distinguish between different Israels’: The historical Israel
(i.e. the state called Israel, alias Bit Humriya or Samarina, which existed in central and
northern Palestine between, say, 950bce and 720bce), the biblical Israel (i.e. the Israel
as narrated by the Old Testament) and ancient Israel (i.e. the concoction of the histori-
cal and the biblical Israel which has been created by biblical scholars). Cf. further on
this distinction, Philip R. Davies, In Search of ‘Ancient Israel’ (JSOT supplement, 148;
Sheffield: Sheffield University Press, 1992).
Justice in western Asia in antiquity 219
The code may also contain valuable information regarding the importance
of witnesses, when it is prescribed in Deuteronomy 19:14-15 that no case can
be decided on the evidence of a single witness; at least two or three are needed.
This case deals with a murder, committed in the countryside, though the mur-
derer cannot be found. Deuteronomy 21:1-9, which prescribes a special ritual
to cleanse the inhabitants of the village closest to the place of the crime, also
belongs in this category.
In looking for the social foundation of the distribution of law and justice on
the basic level of society, an explanation can be found for the missing written
legal tradition. It is a stereotype in biblical scholarship that although judges
were officially appointed (by whom?), there was no official police force to
secure the enactment of a court decision. Neither did an official body exist
which safeguarded the interests of the poor and destitute. Finally, but not least,
access to court was limited to full citizens. No case was brought before a judge
on behalf of the society or state. Such a thing as ‘The State of California against
O. J. Simpson’ would be unheard of. The state did not interfere in the lives and
whereabouts of the ordinary man; it did not protect its unfortunate citizens from
being maltreated or mishandled by more affluent members of the society. It is
therefore that the pages of the Old Testament abound with admonitions that the
rich should care for the poor and that judges should not accept or be offered
bribes. At times, the scholarly reconstruction of justice resembles a scene from
Hans Christian Andersen (or his Californian ‘translator’, Walt Disney). We are
confronted by a small-scale society where the judge – once appointed by the
king, his master – resides in court as an independent member of the local soci-
ety, as he is paid by his superior officers of the state administration and does not
have to think of his daily outcome as member of the local society in which he
is active. Before him, people of all sorts – or their representatives – will bring
their case aspiring for a fair and just decision made by this independent member
of the court.
This picture has hardly anything to do with the actual distribution of law in
an ancient oriental society. And, again, the explanation is that the royal adminis-
tration would not have any interest in interfering in local business if it were not
for tax issues or other cases, where its own interests are at stake. Why should
the royal court be interested in a simple murder if one destitute peasant had
killed another? It would have been an unrewarding enterprise for the officers of
the royal court and would have been understood by the local community as an
encroachment on its right to direct its own affairs.
If the usual way to proceed is to describe the forces which were operative
in such a society, where are we to look for the decisive institutions of such a
society: in the family or elsewhere? Let’s start with the family, because here we
are confronted with another stereotype of orientalist scholarship, according to
which the most important part of the socio-political structure on the local level
– that under the official level of the state – would be the family. It is suggested,
accordingly, that law and justice at the local level is a matter of a ‘family-
oriented’ society. This is, however, a loose definition, as the term ‘family’ is,
indeed, loose. In itself, it says little about the real centre of power in small-scale
220 Biblical studies and the failure of history
societies. We need to look for such centres where we find the foundation of the
administration of law and order. The term ‘family’ is, however, rather meaning-
less. What is intended by the term: the nuclear family or a greater entity? This
is not a reflection on oriental usage, but rather demonstrates how imprecise the
traditional orientalist expresses him or herself. The traditional oriental family
is – contrary to general opinion – not very large. According to social anthro-
pologists currently working, the family was between 4.5 and 7 persons and we
have indications that the average nuclear family in the ancient Near East may
not have exceeded the upper limit.15 It is obvious that such a tiny group will not
represent any kind of power or economic and juridical security. The family, as
such, is much too weak for this. The nuclear family is, technically speaking, a
residence group – people living together – but it is not economically, politically
or juridically autonomous. It cannot guarantee the welfare of its members but
must leave this to a higher level of integration, such as the clan or lineage, two
concepts which have often been misunderstood.16
A lineage is often considered by anthropologists to be the important polit-
ical and economic group in traditional Middle Eastern society – although it
says something about the level of sociological understanding among profes-
sional orientalists that we most often must look in vain for this term in modern
treatments of ancient Near Eastern societies. ‘Lineage’, however, is essentially
equivalent to the much less precise term extended family, supposedly consisting
of as many as twenty or more persons.17 A limited number of nuclear families
normally form a lineage and it is headed not so much by a chosen leader as by
some family member who, because of prestige, is considered the head of his
lineage.
It has often been described how the lineage becomes important in juridi-
cal matters since it is reckoned to be the level on which such matters can be
decided without the interference by state officials. The extent of the authority
of the lineage in this respect is, on the other hand, amazing and might include
even capital crimes.
Even murder may be resolved by the lineage. It is interesting that, in tradi-
tional Middle Eastern society, the saying in the Qur’an would normally be cited
15. Cf. Niels Peter Lemche, Early Israel: Anthropological and Historical Studies on the
Israelite Society before the Monarchy (VT supplement, 37; Leiden: E. J. Brill, 1985),
231–32. In general, the description of the traditional oriental family-structured society
will follow what has already been said in this volume, especially 202–44.
16. The lineage, according to the popular anthropological definition, is a kinship group,
consisting of relatives with a fair knowledge of how the single members of the lineage
are attached to it. The genealogy of the lineage should therefore be clear to all genuine
members of one and the same lineage. A clan, by contrast, is also considered a group
based on the notion of kinship. However, the single members of the clan may not know
in detail how they relate to the clan itself, or how other members of their clan relate to
it. Personally, I never found this explanation of the difference very useful, as it seems to
indicate either good or bad memory, rather than a completely different organization, as
the criterion for making the distinction.
17. Stereotypes describing up to 100 persons are more fantasy than reality.
Justice in western Asia in antiquity 221
to indicate that the murderer should die. This rule is accepted but not practised
in many places, as everyone can see that such a demand could easily lead to
blood vengeance and destructive vendettas. Instead, according to the testimony
of anthropologists, even such serious cases are solved at the level of the local
society in order to avoid that the society itself should be fractured because of
the criminal acts of one of its members.18
In reality, this would imply – according to such authorities – that in case of
manslaughter, the leaders of the lineages involved will meet in the house of
some chosen arbiter, acknowledged by both lineages, in order to settle the mat-
ter. The claim would be that the murderer should die (or a close male relative
of his) in order to re-establish the broken balance between lineages, belonging
to one and the same village. That two persons should die is, however, from the
perspective of the village, an undesirable consequence, so another solution must
be found. Therefore, negotiations start in an effort to establish the value of the
deceased and the amount of compensation to be paid by the offender’s lineage.
In general, or so we are induced to believe, such a solution will be found, after
which the tranquillity of the village is re-established.
Anthropologists are not specialists in law, and their description of how the
juridical system works in traditional societies may lack detail and precision.
However, their indications are that such societies have no use of a written law.
In general, people know what is going to happen to a murderer and that there is
no need to have this in writing. On the other hand, the demands of the ‘unwrit-
ten law’ may only occasionally be followed, which indicates that the unwritten
law, in this case, is best considered a ‘metaphor’ rather than a practical guideline
for how to act.
If even a murder be solved without resort to anything written, most juridical
cases would also be solved in the same fashion. In traditional Middle Eastern
society, it is likely that it was uncommon that state authorities should be involved
in local affairs if public interest was not directly involved. Furthermore, the
stable character of such local communities makes it absolutely unnecessary to
introduce changes to what may have been a very simple unwritten law code,
consisting of just a few practical guidelines, which would not be followed slav-
ishly, but indicated a minimal level of compensation.
We have, here, found the background of the missing written laws of west-
ern Asia in ancient times. On the local village level, where the majority of the
population should be sought, no written law was ever needed. Life was simple
and so were the basic rules of society. The lack of written prescriptions for how
to behave when even a severe crime was committed was not a hindrance to the
enactment of a form of retribution, whether this consisted of direct punishment
or resulted in compensation paid by the lineage.
18. Emrys Peters, in his article ‘Aspects of the Family Among the Bedouin of Cyrenaica’,
in Meyer F. Nimkoff, Comparative Family Systems (Boston: Houghton-Mifflin, 1965),
121–46, has described the devastating effects when such mediating forces are not at
work.
222 Biblical studies and the failure of history
Patronage
Such observations indicate that another power system may be operative in these
societies, a power system that does not necessarily follow lines of kinship or, in
which, kinship may be more a metaphor than a reflection of the realities of the
people embraced by this ideology.
Many years ago a note in a study on a Lebanese village community by the
well-known American social anthropologist John Gulick struck me as impor-
tant. After having explained the social structure of his village, he had to confess
that although it should be supposed that this social structure would also mark
the power structure in this village, there were indications, which were not to be
overlooked, that the real power structure was different from the social struc-
ture. He was, however, unable to trace the details.21 It seems likely to me that
Gulick was blocked from doing further observations by the infamous omertà, an
19. Cf. on this ‘triad’ F. C. Fensham, ‘Widow, Orphan and the Poor in Ancient Near Eastern
Legal and Wisdom Literature,’ JNES 21 (1962), 129–39.
20. The late Jacob Black-Michaud dealt with aspects of this issue in his very perceptive
contribution, ‘Tyranny as a strategy for survival in an “egalitarian” society: Lurid facts
versus an anthropological mystique’, Man NS 7 (1972), 614–34.
21. John Gulick, Social Structure and Cultural Change in a Lebanese Village (Viking
Fund Publications in Anthropology 21; New York: Wenner-Gren Foundation for
Anthropological Research, 1955), 131.
Justice in western Asia in antiquity 223
22. The classic collection of studies was published by Ernest Gellner and John Waterbury,
Patrons and Clients in Mediterranean Societies (New York and London: Duckworth,
1977). Another relevant collection would be Julian Pitt-Rivers, Mediterranean
Countrymen. Essays in the Social Anthropology of the Mediterranean (Récherches
Méditerranéennes. Études I; Paris: Mouton, 1963).
23. Smuel N. Eisenstadt and Luis Roniger, Patrons, Clients and Friends (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1984).
24. Although this may be questioned as far as the Hellenistic-Roman period is concerned, as
in the enormous cities of that time, such a segment must, of course, have been present. Its
importance may, however, have been restricted to the Greek-speaking cities of the Near
East, whereas in the countryside, still mostly unfamiliar with Greek, this class could
easily have acted as local patrons. Parallels from modern Syria are well known, where,
for example, rich people from Aleppo may turn out as the local patrons in villages in the
countryside. Cf. Louise E. Sweet, Tell Toqaan. A Syrian Village (Anthropological Papers,
no 14; Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan, 1960), and the commented review in
my Early Israel, 171–3. It should, on the other hand, not be overlooked that the practi-
224 Biblical studies and the failure of history
It may be premature to present the full lay-out of such a system, the presence
of which is almost uniformly overlooked,25 although the concept of patronage
has begun to gain importance especially in biblical studies in recent times.26 The
basic problem for the poor is simply to survive in an inhospitable environment.
In general, the Middle East is unkind to its inhabitants. Only comparatively
small stretches of land are suitable for agriculture, and rainfall is always haphaz-
ard. Droughts are common and leave ordinary man almost defenceless in times
of stress. In spite of the official propaganda of ancient times, no ‘Scandinavian’
welfare system ever existed. If one belonged to the hapless group of ordinary
beings, how does one survive in a time of crisis?
As already mentioned, the support to be drawn from family members –
and here the nuclear family is unimportant – (i.e. from the lineage) is hardly
enough to save a person from servitude, well known for being the ultimate
way of saving one’s life in Antiquity.27 Turning to some ‘benevolent’ person
might be necessary if the poor person wanted to survive. It is, therefore, my
thesis that the ancient societies of western Asia were, in fact, patronage socie-
ties and that patronage played an extremely important (though not exclusive)
role in maintaining the welfare of the inhabitants of this region of the world.
The system is never described in any detail in any source from Antiquity, prob-
ably because it was too well known.28 Its effects and especially its ideology are
almost omnipresent. In the Old Testament, it is immediately apparent when you
cal Romans turned the system into a fully developed and acknowledged element in
their state organization, and that to such a degree that it has been maintained that the
system is a Roman invention. See, on this, the classic description in Ronald Syme, The
Roman Revolution (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1939), 369–86 (‘The Working of
Patronage’).
25. An exception is the Italian Assyriologist Mario Liverani, who seems always to have been
aware of its presence and importance for molding the ideology of the ancient societies
of Western Asia. See, thus, his Prestige and Interest. International Relations in the Near
East c.1600-1100 bc. (History of the Ancient Near East. Studies, 1; Padova: Sargon,
1990).
26. In the field of New Testament studies, the importance of the concept has been stressed by
Bruce J. Malina in his The New Testament World. Insights from Cultural Anthropology
(revised edn; Louisville, KY: Westminster/John Knox, 1993). In Old Testament studies,
I have dealt with the issue in a number of essays; see Chapters 12 and 14, this volume,
and also my ‘On Doing Sociology with ‘Solomon”,’ in Lowell K. Handy (ed.) The Age
of Solomon: Scholarship at the Turn of the Millennium (SHCANE; Leiden: E. J. Brill,
1997), 312–35.
27. On this, cf. now the comprehensive study by Gregory C. Chirichigno, Debt-Slavery in
Israel and the Ancient Near East (JSOT supplement, 141; Sheffield: Sheffield: Academic
Press 1993).
28. Ancient sources never systematically deal with social or political structure, allowing for
a concise picture of the organization of society to be reconstructed. We do not know a
single word from Western Asia to be translated ‘peasant’ or ‘nomad’, probably because
there was no need to find a specialized word covering some 95 per cent of the total
population. Everybody was assumed to be a peasant (or a nomad) if nothing else was
said about him.
Justice in western Asia in antiquity 225
are prepared to look for it and it turns up in the most unexpected places. The
central biblical concept of the covenant between God and Israel should probably
be interpreted in the light of patronage ideology (it is hardly due to coincidence
that the capo di capi in the mafia is called the ‘Godfather’!).29
When, however, we return to the specific subject of this contribution, the
missing laws of western Asia in Antiquity, we have some clue as to how the
administration of justice took place. It was the duty of the rich to care for the
widow, orphan, poor and destitute. This has generally been taken to mean per-
sons who had not obtained juridical status because they were without a father or
a husband to defend them in court, or they were without lands and therefore not
fully recognized as citizens of the state.30 They could not register a complaint
against a full citizen before a judge if they were not supported by another full
citizen, who would take upon himself the safeguarding of their rights. This may
be the grim background of the life of ordinary man in ancient times. If a person
was not a grown male, owning his own land, this person would not be reckoned
a full citizen of his community and therefore was helpless if accused or attacked
by one of the ‘seigniors’ of his society. There was no help to be found, no court
of appeal, if such a person felt himself injured or his rights infringed by a land-
lord. There was, in fact, only one possibility left to the poor, either bow your
neck to the inevitable or find a patron to protect you and, in practice, ‘own’ you.
The difference between this practice and proper debt-slavery may have been
marginal and, probably, hardly recognized and the terminology would, likely, be
the same. As is well known, the Hebrew word ‘ebed (the Akkadian counterpart
is wardum) normally translated ‘slave’, also means ‘dependant’ (i.e. a person
dependent on another). It is obvious from the international correspondence of
the Late Bronze Age that any high officer of the king would term himself an
‘ebed (or wardum) when directing his message to his lord, the king. To this
officer, the king would be reckoned not only as superior but as his most impor-
tant and ultimate patron, apart from the divine.
It is just as important that monarchs, generally, used family terms when
addressing each other. Monarchs of the same standing – for example, imperial
rulers of Egypt and H atti, the Hittite kingdom of Asia Minor – would use the
�
term ‘brother’. A mightier king would be likely to call another king, not quite in
his class, ‘son’ (and, conversely, ‘father’).31
When we return to the administration of the court and take this structure of
society into consideration, an avenue opens to us to better understand quite a
few problems related to jurisprudence in the ancient Near East.
In Deuteronomy 16:18-20, we read:
In every settlement which the Lord your God is giving you, you must appoint
for yourselves judges and officers, tribe by tribe, and they will dispense true
justice to the people. You must not pervert the course of justice or show favour
or accept a bribe; for bribery makes the wise person blind and the just person
give a crooked answer. Justice, and justice alone, must be your aim, so that
you may live and occupy the land which the Lord your God is giving you.
This quotation is, of course, embedded in the ideological phrasing of the editor
of this part of the Old Testament, the so-called Deuteronomistic movement.33 It is
their ideology that carries the day. On the other hand, not even Deuteronomistic
‘welfare-theology’, as it has been styled (the Deuteronomists being especially
concerned about the poor and weak in the Jewish society) can hide the fact that
the person to whom they address their admonition, the ‘you’, is not himself a
poor person, but a representative of the influential citizens – or this group as
a whole. Without mentioning it expressly, it is therefore the obligation of this
group to care for the administration of justice and it is their duty to appoint
judges who can be trusted as impartial and righteous and do not accept bribes.
Does this make a judge independent – the mark of honour of every judge in
this world? Can it be assumed that such a judge should decide against the inter-
ests of the group that appointed him to his office and side with the weak? This
32. Basically, my studies from the 1970s, reprinted as Chapters 1–3 of this volume, will still
be valid in this regard, though the interpretation of the Akkadian term hupšu – Hebrew
�
þophšî, as ‘Client’ (see Chapter 1) may be too broad (cf. Chirichigno, Debt-Slavery, at
210ff.). It is obvious, however, that the term denoted a person in a special relationship to
his former master – whether client in the technical sense or something else.
33. This is not the place to discuss Deuteronomism and whatever attached to this phenom-
enon. Suffice it to say that it is likely a Jewish intellectual movement of the Persian and
Hellenistic periods – probably the forerunners of later Jewish parties of the Hasmonean
period – which left their impression on large stretches of the Old Testament. Other schol-
ars would place them in the late pre-exilic period (roughly the seventh to sixth centuries
bce), but this is immaterial here. Cf., for example, in an argument about the dating with
this author, Eckart Otto, ‘Programme der sozialen Gerechtigkeit. Die neuassyrische (an-)
durāru-Institution sozialen Ausglichs und das deuteronomistische Erlaßjahr in Deut 15’,
Zeitschrift für Altorientlische und Biblische rechtsgeschichte 3 (1997), 26–63.
Justice in western Asia in antiquity 227
34. To mention just a few of the more recent major contributions: Shalom M. Paul, Studies
in the Book of the Covenant in the Light of Cuneiform and Biblical Law (VT supplement,
18; Leiden: E. J. Brill, 1970), and Eckart Otto, Wandel der Rechtsbegründigungen in
der Gesellschaftsgeschichte des antiken Israel (Studia Biblica, 3, Leiden: E. J. Brill,
1988), and Rechtgeschichte der Redaktionen im Kodex Eschnunna und im ‘Bundesbuch.’
Eine rechtsgeschichtliche und rechtsvergleichende Studie zu altbabylonischen und altis-
raelitischen Rechtsüberlieferungen (OBO, 85; Fribourg: Universitätsverlag Freiburg/
Schweiz–Göttingen: Vandenhoeck and Ruprecht, 1989). In fact, over the last decade,
E. Otto has published an almost unlimited but extremely valuable series of articles
and books dealing with the relations between ancient Near Eastern and Old Testament
law, and, since 1995, he has edited a journal devoted to this subject, Zeitschrift für
Altorientlische und Biblische Rechtsgeschichte.
Justice in western Asia in antiquity 229
Old Testament scholarship to which this author belongs generally favours post-
exilic dates of composition. The Old Testament was not an old Israelite book
with a written history going back to the beginning of the first millennium bce. It
was, rather, a late composition brought about at the beginning of Jewish history,
which cannot predate the formation of Judaism as a religion and ethnic term – a
thing that certainly did not happen before the Babylonian exile. Most likely we
have to look for a much later date.35
In this light, a new understanding of the Book of the Covenant seems likely,
according to which this collection does not reflection ancient Israelite society,
but is, rather, to be attributed to the understanding of exiles – or in any case, of
former exiles – being brought up in Mesopotamia and drawing on a Babylonian
legal tradition. The sons of exiles became acquainted with the Babylonian codes
during their education or, better, with the tradition of writing such codes – a
peculiarity of the Babylonian tradition. At some stage of the composition of the
Old Testament, they chose to introduce such a collection in their tradition as
evidence of the importance of law and order for keeping the covenant of Israel’s
God – in fact, much like Hammurabi, in collecting his code, had tried to dem-
onstrate that his reign had� been lawful and righteous. In this way, the Book of
the Covenant does not belong in the tradition of law and order in Western Asia,
so much as to the Babylonian tradition. References in the Book of the Covenant
which have been understood to reflect old practices in Israel, but which are also
close to Babylonian tradition,36 should be considered ‘Babylonian’ literature in
a Jewish context. They are not reflections of Israelite tradition, inherited by late
post-exilic Jews.
35. In favour of an exilic date, see John Van Seters, Abraham in History and Tradition (New
Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1975). A post-exilic date in the Persian Period is
proposed by various members of the so-called Second Temple Group, sponsored by the
Society of Biblical Literature, and among others by Philip R. Davies. See his In Search
of ‘Ancient Israel’. Cf. now also E. Theodore Mullen, Ethnic Myths and Pentateuchal
Foundations: A new Approach to the Formation of the Pentateuch (Atlanta, GA:
Scholars Press, 1997). A Persian date was also the one offered by my Copenhagen col-
league, Thomas L. Thompson, in his Early History of the Israelite People: From the
Written and Archaeological Sources (SHANE 4; Leiden: E. J. Brill, 1992), who is now,
however, siding with this author in that the Hellenistic Period may provide an even more
promising background for biblical literature. See Chapter 8, this volume.
36. Cf. among the more glaring examples the law of the goring ox, Exod 22.28-32, and the
commentary in J. J. Finkelstein, ‘“The Ox that Gored”’, TAPhS 71 (1981), 1–89. Among
such contributions, Chapter 1 of this volume should also be reckoned. Cf., however,
the criticism against that the law of the Hebrew slave should reflect second millennium
language levelled by Oswald Loretz, Habiru-Hebräer (BZAW 160; Berlin: De Gruyter,
�
1984), 259f. It is difficult to escape the conclusion that Loretz is right.
14
4. Among the participants were Margreet Steiner from Leiden, Patrick McGovern from
Philadelphia and John Strange from Copenhagen.
5. To an outsider, this must sound almost ridiculous as there is hardly a region in this world
which has been dug as extensively as Palestine. How can it be that, after more than 100
years of excavations, several experienced archaeologists are forced to admit that hardly
any certainty about the status of the Judean territory at the beginning of the first millen-
nium bce can be reached, that we still have a long way to go before any safe or enduring
reconstruction can be presented.
6. This argument was used against my idea of a Hellenistic origin for the Old Testament
(cf. N. P. Lemche, ‘The Old Testament: A Hellenistic booked’, SJOT 7 (1993), l63–93
– especially against my view of the kingdom of David – by F. Willesen, ‘Om fantomet
David’, DTT 56 (1993), 249–65. Cf. my answer to this criticism in my ‘Det gamle
Testaments, hellenismen og David. Svar til Eduard Nielsen og Folker Willesen’, DTT
57 (1994), 20–39.
232 Biblical studies and the failure of history
There is, however, another way of entering this debate about the kind of soci-
ety to be found in the central highlands – especially its southern parts – during
the tenth century bce. That is to discuss the nature of the society supposed to be
around in those days. The normal method would be to discuss the progression
from a tribal society to a state: Die Staatenbildung der Israeliten, as Albrecht
Alt phrased it.7 This would require that we had a tribal society at one end of the
continuum, and at the other, a state. Neither of these points of departure is evi-
dent. Because of this, I decided to discuss the progression from a tribal society
to a patronage society. However, we must ask once again what we really know
about tribal societies in Palestine in the period, say, of 1300bce to 800bce? Tribe
is such a meaningless word because it embraces all kinds of traditional primitive
societies and because no conclusive definition can be reached as to what a tribe
really is except the conclusion that a tribal society is not a state.8
To avoid this problem, I have introduced the concept of patronage society as
more likely to cover the societal varieties of Syria and especially Palestine in the
Late Bronze Age (LBA) period. I am at the moment preparing a series of studies
on the nature of such societies.9 Political power structures are personalized as
the society is divided into two groups: the ‘haves’ and the ‘have nots’, the first
being so-called ‘full citizens’ known from the Hebrew Bible, and the others, the
many destitute to be cared for, the dalim, ebyonim, or whatever they may be
called in Hebrew. This model, often called ‘the Mediterranean social system’,
seems almost ubiquitous in – to use sociological terms – societies of a degree
of complexity, not yet, however, bureaucratic states. They are neither tribal nor
feudal societies, although they may develop into feudalism.10 Characteristic of
a patronage society is its vertical organization, according to which we find the
patron at the top. He is a member of a leading lineage. Below him are his cli-
ents, ordinary men and their families. The bond between patron and client is a
personal one: the client having sworn allegiance to the patron and the patron
having sworn to protect his client.
Once diagnosed, the effects of patronage can be found on all levels of soci-
ety. To mention a single example, I refer to my lecture at a recent conference
at the Robbins Collection, Berkeley University, in March 1995, dealing with
7. Cf. his article of the same name ‘Die Staatenbildung der israeliten in Palestinian’ (1930),
in his Kleine Schriften zur Geschichte Israels II (1956), 1–65 (English translation: ‘The
Formation of the Israelite State in Palestine’, in Essays on Old Testament History and
Religion, trans. R. A. Wilson; Sheffield: JSOT Press, 1989, 171–237).
8. Cf. my Early Israel: Anthropological and Historical Studies on the Israelite Society
before the Monarchy (VT supplement, 37; Leiden: E. J. Brill, 1985), 231–44 and the
literature quoted there.
9. See Chapters 9, 12 and 13, this volume.
10. See E. Gellner and J. Waterbury, Patrons and Clients in Mediterranean Societies (New
York and London: Duckworth, 1977). On the development towards feudalism in the
LBA period ; cf. M. Liverani, ‘Communautés rurales dans la Syrie du IIe millénaire a.
C.’, Recuils de la society Jean Bodin pour l’histoire Comparative des institutions 41
(1983), 147–85. Liverani describes how the independence of the village society is threat-
ened by the donation of villages as fiefs to privileged members of the palace community.
234 Biblical studies and the failure of history
ancient law.11 I traced the reason for the conspicuous absence of laws in Syria
and Palestine in the Iron Age to patronage systems, which made such laws
superfluous and unnecessary. Nobody tells his Godfather how to judge.12 It is
also obvious, from a closer juridical analysis, that passages on law and enact-
ment of justice in Deuteronomy 16:18-20, 17:8-13 and 19:14-21 do not speak
about court and justice in the normal Western sense of the word, but about the
instalment and function of an agent to act between patron families of the same
community.
The idea of a patronage as distinct from a tribal society is a very important
part of the argument for the absence of a proper state in Judah in the Iron Age
– or greater parts of Syria and Palestine in antiquity. The state is supposed
to care for its citizens and this has been part of the ideology of ancient states
since Sumerian times to Hammurabi and the Assyrian and Babylonian kings
�
of the first millennium. Famous in this connection are the social decrees from
Urnammu to Hammurabi and the prologue to the Codex Hammurabi, in which
�
the king programmatically states that he was introduced� to kingship in order
to make his subjects happy.13 This concern is conspicuously absent from the
biblical material, whether the outspoken anti-royalist tirades of Samuel (1 Sam.
8 and 12), the criticism of an unjust society in prophetic literature, or the descrip-
tion of the juridical system itself, which did not allow for ordinary people to
find help and justice in court if they did not belong among the landowning ‘full
citizens’. Social security seems to have been utterly ‘privatized’ in those days.
15. On village and city in Ugarit (and other Syrian states of the LBA period), cf. M. Liverani,
‘Communautés de village et palais royales dans la Syrie du IIème millénaire’, JESHO
18 (1975), 146–64; ‘Ville et campagne dans la royaume d’Ugarit. Essai d’analyse
économique’, in Societies and Languages of the Ancient Near East in Honour of I.M.
Diakonoff (Warminster: Aris and Phillips, 1982), 250–58. Another valuable study is
M. Heltzer, The Rural Community in Ancient Ugarit (Wiesbaden: Reichert, 1976).
16. On this, cf. Liverani, ‘Communautés rurales’. On royal agricultural estates in Ugarit,
cf. M. Liverani, especially his ‘Economia delle fattorie palatine ugaritiche’, Dialoghi di
Archeologia NS 1 (1979), 57–72.
17. From Ugarit three titles are known: the hazanu, the rab and the šakin (cf. Heltzer, Rural
�
Community, 80–83). The official headman, eventually imposed on the village by the pal-
ace administration, need not be the real head of the village itself, but just some intermedi-
ary who could represent the village in negotiations with the outside world, and to whom
the palace would direct its instructions for the villagers. A number of modern analogies
demonstrate that this office is neither much sought after nor respected. It is rather more
likely than not given to a non-important or junior member of one of the leading lineages.
18. See on this Heltzer, Rural Community, 75–7.
19. On this ibid., 63–5, Liverani, ‘Communautés rurales’.
20. Cf. T. L. Thompson, The Settlement of Palestine in the Bronze Age (BTAVO 34;
Wiesbaden: Reichert, 1979). Cf. also A. Mazar, Archaeology of the Land of the Bible
c.10,000-586 bce (New York: Doubleday, 1990), 239–41. Generally, scholars have con-
centrated on the supposed reduction of urban culture in Palestine in the LBA period; cf.
R. Gonen, ‘Urban Canaan in the Late Bronze Period’, BASOR 253 (1984), 61–73. Her
conclusions are, however, questioned by Mazar (Land of the Bible, 240).
From patronage society to patronage society 237
‘kings’,21 tiny political structures which probably allowed for a personal system
of relationships between ruler and subject. No intermediary organization was
necessary and only a most rudimentary administrative system was needed. We
hardly have sufficient information to provide a secure picture of the political
system in the nooks and crannies of Palestine during the LBA, but apart from
Hazor – certainly not a typical Palestinian city in those days – and a few places
on the plains in the north, such as Tell Keisan – by all criteria a Phoenician city
– the walled settlements are tiny, so tiny that it is apparently impossible to find
Jerusalem of the LBA. Nothing comprehensive was needed to control these
societies: a scribe and a few soldiers were sufficient. Some years ago, I referred
to the petitions of the kings of Palestine to Pharaoh for military support: ‘send
me, not a thousand or a hundred soldiers, but twenty or thirty’. Even though
the political situation in the Amarna letters is often described as catastrophic to
the loyal vassals of Pharaoh, the problems were so limited that a dozen troops
could establish order!22
If we look for parallels to the structure of Palestinian society, I would sug-
gest that we leave out greater Syria, as well as – of course – Mesopotamia
throughout antiquity. I would rather suggest that better parallels can be found
in medieval Europe, in the Burg-Gesellschaften, the ‘fortress-societies’ of the
early Middle Ages. Embryonic, centralized organizations arose around the cas-
tles (strongholds) of the patrons, later to develop into cities. Denmark provides
fine examples not least because, in those days, it was a small-scale society and
the development is well attested in history – to such a degree that it is part of
the ordinary curriculum in primary schools. Around the fortress, villagers set-
tled for protection provided by the lord of the fortress, their patron. From this,
cities developed. The proof of this is the number of medieval Danish cities
with names such as Nyborg, Fåborg, Vordingborg, Skanderborg, and Aalborg.
The Danish word borg is the same as the German Burg. Other names would
be compounds with Danish hus (house), such as the second biggest city of the
kingdom, Aarhus, or gård (farmhouses, but often used also for royal houses),
often in the form of the name Nygaard ( ‘new farmhouses), like the Russian
Novgorod (which is a Scandinavian word as Novgorod was in fact founded by
Viking chiefs as a stronghold). Even Copenhagen traces its origin back to such
a development in the twelfth century ce, as the city arose around a fortress built
by an archbishop (Absalon) in 1167ce.
The end of the LBA probably relates to a societal crisis. It was, however, a
crisis that arose not so much because of internal structural problems in the small
political communities of Syria and Palestine; it was, rather, occasioned by an
international crisis related to a breakdown of trade relations23 or by changing
21. The Egyptians purposefully and realistically called these rulers mayors, hazanu.
�
22. Lemche, Early Israel, 419–20, including references to requests for support from Abdi-
Hepa, Rib-Adda and Abimilku.
�
23. The general thesis of R. B. Coote and K. W. Whitelam, The Emergence of Early Israel
in Historical Perspective (The Social World of Biblical Antiquity Series 5; Sheffield:
Almond Press, 1987).
238 Biblical studies and the failure of history
24. As preferred by T. L. Thompson, The Early History of the Israelite People: From the
Written and Archaeological Sources (SHANE 4; Leiden: E. J. Brill, 1992).
25. Lemche, Early Israel, 274.
26. Which did not prevent this author – like so many of his colleagues – from presenting
another sophisticated but nevertheless speculative reconstruction of what an Israelite
tribe might have been. Cf. ibid., 274–90.
27. Cf. also – preliminarily – the discussion in my Ancient Israel: A New History of Israelite
Society (Sheffield: JSOT Press, 1988), 98–9. A better definition would perhaps argue that
‘tribe’ is a metaphor that expresses the functions of a state in a non-state society.
From patronage society to patronage society 239
village society,28 we may have a tribal society, but probably more likely a mix-
ture of tribal (rather, lineage) ideology and a patronage system.
This demands an explanation. Contrary to the opinion of many scholars,
but thoroughly discussed in my ‘Early Israel’, the governing structure in tradi-
tional Middle Eastern societies not yet totally embraced by a centralized state
is not the tribe but the lineage, defined as a patrilinear descent group of some
extent.29 The lineage survives political change (e.g. a shift from statehood to
chiefdom and vice versa) and it is dominant on all levels of society. An ideology
of belonging to a certain lineage dominates. Reality shows things to be differ-
ent in that only the well-to-do lineages are politically important. The rest have
to adjust their allegiance to a major lineage. This is the basis of the patronage
system, according to which members of unimportant lineages look for richer –
more influential, mightier – lineages for personal protection.
What may have happened in Palestine at the end of the LBA is that the walled
fortress of the patron, the city of the king, disappeared and was substituted
by local structures, villages, either organized without a protecting substratum
like the patron, the so-called ‘king’ – or with local influential patrons, now
impossible to trace in the remains of the villages. The presence of regional
patrons may be seen from the distribution of clusters of villages in the central
and Galilean highlands.30 In this way, the village culture of the central highlands
of Palestine simply represents an interval between two periods of more exten-
sive and well-formulated patronage systems, simply because what happened,
between 1000bce and 900bce was, in fact, the re-establishment of a system of
‘Burg-civilizations’, partly to be compared (but not identified) with the system
of the LBA of the same area. It is guesswork to present any kind of reconstruc-
tion of the history of this period, but several avenues of development are feasi-
ble. I point out only two:
1. The villages were part of a tribal society of some kind, the correct nature
of which is impossible to reconstruct. They were governed by tribal
ideology31 according to the rules of such societies. However, at a cer-
tain stage and because of certain conditions – competition for dwindling
natural resources, warfare or whatever – they had to invent a more secure
organization, reuniting into chiefdoms run by families or lineages best
described as patronage families, who later assume the language of kings
and princes.
28. I. Finkelstein, The Archaeology of the Settlement of the Israelite Tribes (Jerusalem: Israel
Exploration Society, 1988).
29. Lemche, Early Israel, 223–31 and 245–74.
30. Cf. the charts in Finkelstein, Settlements, 95 and 189. Mittmann’s Gilead survey may
provide the same picture; cf. ibid., 115.
31. Perhaps rejected in traces of what is normally understood as tribal ideology, present in
much later biblical writings. On this, F. Lambert, ‘The Tribe/state Paradox in the Old
Testament’, SJOT 8 (1994), 20–44. It is, however, my opinion that this ideology is part
of the lineage system and that it does not necessarily reflect the previous or current
existence of tribes.
240 Biblical studies and the failure of history
2. The villages were from the outset part of small-scale patronage systems,
which, under the conditions mentioned (or others – none can really tell),
were forced to be incorporated within a major patronage system, sym-
bolized by the re-establishment of a centralized construction such as a
fortress – a ‘Burg’.
In the first case, the system of government changed, but the ideology and life
inside the lineage remained (almost) the same. In the second case, almost noth-
ing happened, except that a tendency towards centralized settlement may be
the reason for the building of fortresses such as Jerusalem and Beer-sheba in
the second half of the Early Iron I period and beginning of the first millennium
bce.32 The establishment of these centres has been related to the disappearance
of village culture or at least to a reduction of the number of villages and minor
townships. We probably see a movement towards centralization and a strength-
ening of the position of some village patrons towards regional patronage, the
people we have been used to calling kings.
In his 1995 article in The Scandinavian Journal of the Old Testament, Thomas
Thompson directs his attention to the notion of a ‘house of David’ as evidence
of the presence of a patronage system, organized around the descendants of the
apical David, making the historicity of this David rather dubious and certainly
unnecessary.33 In this place, I will not repeat Thompson’s arguments, but only
supplement him by referring to the fact that the many dynastic political names
found in Western Asia in the Iron Age, stretching from such Mesopotamian
Aramaic states as Bit Adini, over Syrian Bit Gusi, down to Palestine’s Bit
H umriya and Bet David, may hardly be evidence of tribal societies which
�
changed into kingdoms. It is much more likely that they testify to the fact that
assumption of power was based not on single persons, but on major patronage
lineages, which arose among the small-scale lineages of the previous period. By
changing the origin of the Judean ‘royal’ family from a single historical person
into an eponymic ancestor of this lineage, we escape being entangled in the per-
sonalized mode of narrating history of the author of the books of Solomon. As is
well known from general anthropology, apical ancestors attract traditions with-
out themselves reflecting historical persons. A parallel to this would be the hero
kings of ancient Ugarit, Kirta and Danilu – again probably never living persons,
32. The archaeological chronology of the Late Bronze and Early Iron periods seems again
in jeopardy. According to M. Steiner (at the conference in Copenhagen in March 1995,
cf. note 4 above), no evidence of a Jerusalem in the Late Bronze period has been found
– apart from Abdi-Hepa’s six letters (EA 285–90) A fortress was built at this place in
�
the twelfth century bce, and some monumental structures were supplemented in the
tenth century bce. On this, see M. Steiner, ‘Redating the Terraces of Jerusalem’, IEJ 44
(1994), 13–20. Full evidence will be presented when her dissertation (Jerusalem in de
bronse en ijzertijd. De Opgravningen van de British School of Archaeology in Jerusalem,
1961–1967, Leiden: E. J. Brill, 1994) is published, hopefully in 1995. On the relationship
between Beersheva and its surroundings, see Finkelstein, Settlement, 37–47.
33. T. Thompson ‘House of David: An Eponymic Referent to Yahweh as Godfather’, SJOT
9 (1995), 59–74.
From patronage society to patronage society 241
who, however, function as the ancestors of the reigning house of the Kingdom
of Ugarit in the LBA period. Liverani pointed out many years ago that there is
a huge distance between the imaginary presentation of the king in the epics of
Kirta and Aqhatu and the management and royal organization of the state of
Ugarit. The king of Ugarit needed such an ancestor to think of after finishing
the tedious business of his industrial organization. He was like a modern busi-
ness tycoon going hunting for the weekend.34 That is what dreams are made of.
Acknowledgements
34. M. Liverani, ‘L’epica ugaritica nel suo contesto storico e letterario’, La poesia epica e la
sua formazione (Accademia Nazionale dei Lincei, Quaderno no 139; Rome: Accademia
Nazionale dei Lincei, 1970), 859–69, and ‘La royauté syrienne de l’age du Bronze
recent’, in P. Garelli (ed.) Le palais et la royalty (RAI; Paris: P. Geuthner, 1974), 329–56,
338–41.
15
It is common to see the Hebrew Bible, played off against its environment in the
ancient Near East, as being on a higher level than, say, Mesopotamian sources.
An example of this may be the introduction to the story of the Flood in Genesis,
often compared to Mesopotamian mythological texts. These cuneiform texts
present a far more primitive explanation for the Flood. In the Old Testament,
God realized that the human race is corrupt and therefore decides to destroy
humankind, and so he does – with the exception of one person, Noah, who
was the only righteous man of his generation. Noah’s family is also spared. In
the Babylonian versions, we are told that, after the creation of humankind, the
human race increased to such a degree that the noise they made disturbed the
gods in their sleep. The gods therefore decided to destroy all human beings.
Humankind survived only because the wise god Ea betrayed his divine col-
leagues and disclosed the secret of the coming Flood to his hero, Utnapištim
(or Atrahasis).1
�
The decision made by the gods was certainly a foolish one. The gods were
starving for the duration of the Flood, since nobody survived to till the fields and
bring sacrifices. In the Babylonian version, the story of the Flood is obviously a
total disaster for both humankind and the gods. No wonder the gods could easily
agree after the deluge on never repeating this mistake of theirs.
In the Old Testament, the story of the Flood does not bring comfort to God.
After the end of the Flood, he accepts the fact that nothing can be done to teach
humankind to be righteous. ‘I will not again curse the ground any more for
1. The Mesopotamian story of the Flood is – as is well known – preserved in more than
one edition. Famous among these are the two more complete ones: Atrahasis (cf. W. G.
�
Lambert and A. R. Millard, Atra-Hasis: The Babylonian Story of the Flood, Oxford:
�
Clarendon, 1969; recent translations in S. Dalley, Myths from Mesopotamia, Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 1991, 1–38, and in B. J. Foster, Before the Muses. I, Bethesda,
MD: CDL Press, 1993, 158–201; it is preserved in fragments going from Old Babylonian
to Late Babylonian times), and Gilgamesh (recent translation in Dalley, Myths from
Mesopotamia, 39–153), again in versions spanning more than 1000 years. In this con-
nection, see especially the epilogue to the Gilgamesh version is of interest.
Are we Europeans really good readers of biblical texts? 243
man’s sake; for the imagination of man’s heart is evil from his youth; neither
will I again smite any more every living thing, as I have done’ (Gen. 8:21, KJV).
The two versions of the story of the Flood, Babylonian and biblical, are in
agreement as far as the general evaluation of the deluge is concerned. Both
agree that it was a mistake, never to be repeated, and both devote space to
guarantee that another deluge will never happen. However, the foolishness of
the God of the Bible seems to surpass that of his Babylonian colleagues. The
Babylonian Noah, Utnapištim, survived because of a defiant god, who did not
accept the decision of the assembly of the gods to destroy humankind. Only Ea
was guilty, not the members of the divine council, if humankind once more cre-
ated problems. In contrast, the God of the Bible is the same god who destroys
humankind, yet rescues one specimen of this accursed race from the impending
catastrophe and – at the end – is forced to accept that humankind will never in
the future improve. If anything, this story seems to prove that this god is not
in control; rather, the God of the Hebrew Bible is very ‘human’, making most
obvious blunders and occasionally losing his grasp on things to come.2
The Babylonian version of the Flood has a rather surprising epilogue, when
the gods convene in order to arrange for the new order of the world after the
deluge. Ištar is the first who accuses Enlil, the god who had brought the deluge
upon humankind, because he acted without reason (or, more likely, without
reasoning). When Enlil arrives, he is, however, addressed directly by the wise
god Ea, who asks him to respect the individual and not to punish humankind
collectively in the future. Only the sinner and transgressor should be corrected
because of his or her transgression (thus according to the version of the Flood in
Gilgamesh;3 in Atrahasis we have a dialogue among the gods on the same issue,
� 4).
but in a broken context
Instead of being a myth about the original history of man, and a story that
was primarily intended to suggest that another Flood will never occur, the
epilogue to the Mesopotamian version indicates another interpretation. This
narrative has to do with justice and argues that collective punishment is mean-
ingless; only individual criminals can and should be punished, rather than a
whole community.
This message has been placed within a narrative framework that seems not to
convey the message of the epilogue; it rather has been understood to be a myth
containing a cosmic message about the duration of the world. The gods failed,
but they are not going to repeat their mistake. The message of this narrative
does not concern the moods of despotic gods. It includes a message about right
and justice to human lords who have always been too willing to sacrifice whole
communities to settle a juridical case. The principle is that if we cannot find
and isolate the culprit, we shall punish everybody. In this way we can be certain
2. This writer is, of course, acquainted with the various ways of explaining away this blun-
der of the God of Genesis 6–8, but none of these explanations can be said to carry much
weight. Evidently,this god had to be taught a lesson as well.
3. Gilgamesh XI:159–85.
4. Atrahasis III v 34–vi 40.
�
244 Biblical studies and the failure of history
that the sinner will be punished! As it stands, there is only a slight resonance of
this theme in the biblical version of the Flood in the insistence that Noah is a
righteous person and therefore to be spared. In the Genesis version, this theme
is obviously not in the proper place, as the righteous person is to be the new
progenitor of a wicked humankind, no better than the antediluvian generations.
There is, however, a parallel to the story of the Flood – namely, the narrative
about of the punishment of Sodom and Gomorrah (Gen. 19). It is obvious that
this narrative also has to do with a flood, though the story does not involve the
world but only a part of it. Moreover, it is not a flood caused by rain and water,
but of fire and brimstone.
Now, it goes without saying that this narrative in Genesis 19 deals with the
punishment of the wicked. The inhabitants of Sodom have sinned in serious and
disgusting ways and have parted company with the human race by such acts.
They are obviously to be exterminated, rightly so.One person, Lot, has no part
in their transgressions and, therefore, has to be saved. On the other hand, the
salvation of Lot and his family does not form the essence of the narrative; rather,
the narrative concentrates on the dialogue between Abraham and God about
the collective punishment of the inhabitants of Sodom. This dialogue proceeds
in the usual way of bargaining as Abraham negotiates with God and persuades
him not to let the righteous perish with the unjust. If but ten persons among the
people of Sodom are just, the city shall be spared. In the end, only one person
could be found. He is saved because of his righteousness (together with his
family). The moral of the story is that God cannot accept that a righteous person
be punished with criminals. Every person must pay for his own crimes, not for
those of others!5
This narrative will describe a certain cosmic situation: the impending destruc-
tion of the world. It is a story with an intended message that has to be repeated
until it has been delivered and understood. The message is the vital part, the
narrative a kind of envelope used to send the message. The story of David’s Rise
in 1–2 Samuel provides another example that illustrates my point. Since I have
written about this narrative in different places,6 I can be brief. It is a story about a
young man who – although the youngest – rises to power. It is related to the fairy
tale about the young hero who, in spite of obvious shortcomings, is nevertheless
destined to conquer the world, the princess and at least half the kingdom. The
same story is told about King Idrimi of Alalah, a historical king from northern
�
Syria, who reigned around 1500bce. Like David, Idrimi (who commemorates
the events of his life in an inscription on his own statue) says that he was the
youngest son of his father, the former king of Aleppo who was exiled after a
putsch in the palace. Although the royal family settles in Emar on the Euphrates
among their maternal royal relatives, the youngest son decides to change his
fate and to conquer the kingdom of his forefathers. Young Idrimi leaves Emar
5. This interpretation of the story of the flooding of Sodom and Gomorrah I owe to the
Danish biblical scholar Hans Jørgen Lundager Jensen.
6. E.g. in my Ancient Israel: A New History of Israelite Society (The Biblical Seminar 5;
3rd edn: Sheffield: SAP, 1996), 52–4.
Are we Europeans really good readers of biblical texts? 245
in order to accomplish this. His chariot driver is his only company. He passes
through the desert (in Europe he would have had to fight his way through a wild
forest, but these are in short supply in the Middle East), and arrives in another
country to become the champion of refugees (habiru) from Aleppo. After seven
years he returns to regain his father’s throne in� Alalah.7
�
Now, it is easy to recognize that something is absolutely ‘fishy’ about this
tale. Idrimi belongs to the royal house in Aleppo, and ends up as king of Alalah.
�
Alalah was the capital of the north Syrian state of Mukiš; it did not belong to the
�
state of Aleppo. In other words, Idrimi simply becomes king in the wrong place.
From the perspective of the inhabitants of Alalah, he was certainly a usurper; he
�
was not the legitimate heir to the kingdom of Mukiš.
The story of David also tells a story about an illegitimate king. It is a much
more complicated narrative than the story of Idrimi although the structure is
essentially the same. We need not in this place address the question – however
crucial it might be – of the historicity of this king of Israel.8 It does not concern
the plot of the play. The biblical narrator delivered his message about David’s
accession to the throne of Saul in the shape of a fairy tale. The story has a mes-
sage to deliver. It may not be the one most obvious when we read the narrative.
However, there can be no doubt that David – like Idrimi – was in possession of
a throne that did not rightfully belong to him.
These two stories – one about Idrimi and the other about David (more exam-
ples could be found) both belong to the genre of fairy tale. This fairy tale has
7. The autobiography of Idrimi was published by S. Smith, The Statue of Idri-mi (London:
British Institute of Archaeology in Ankara, 1949), and has been translated in J. B.
Pritchard, Ancient Near Eastern Texts Relating to the Old Testament:Supplement
(Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1969), 121–2 (557–8), and in W. W. Hallo
and K. L. Younger, The Context of Scripture. I.Canonical Compositions from the Biblical
World (Leiden: E. J. Brill, 1997), 479–80. On the character of the Idrimi text, cf. M.
Liverani, ‘Partire sul carro, per il deserto’, Annali dell’Istituto Universitario Orientale
di Napoli N.S. 22 (1972), 403–15. The relationship between this text and the narrative
about David’s Rise was recognized for the first time by G. Buccellati, ‘La “carriera” di
David e quella di Idrimi – re di Alalac’, Bibbia e Oriente 4 (1962), 95–9. The attribu-
tion to the time of Idrimi himself has been questioned by J. Sasson, ‘On Idrimi and
Šarruwa, the Scribe’, in M. A. Morrison and D. I. Owen (eds), Nuzi and the Hurrians
(Winona Lake, IN: Eisenbrauns, 1981), 309–24. See also the discussion in T. Longman
III, Fictional Akkadian Autobiography: A Generic and Comparative Study (Winona
Lake, IN: Eisenbrauns, 1981), 60–66.
8. On this theme I would like to refer to the minutes of the Conference on the Formation
of the State, held at the German Archaeological Institute in Jerusalem in June 1995. It
is published by V. Fritz and P.R. Davies, The Origins of the Israelite States (Sheffield:
Sheffield Academic Press, 1996). It was probably the general outcome of this meeting
that little can be said in favour of a Davidic kingdom in Judaea duringthe tenth century.
Here the results of D. Jamieson-Drake, Scribes and Schools in Monarchic Judah: A
Socio-Archeological Approach (JSOT supplement, 109; Sheffield: The Almond Press,
1991) and H. M. Niemann, Herrschaft, Königtum und Staat. Skizzen zur soziokulturellen
Entwicklung im monarchischen Israel (Forschungen zum Alten Testament 6; Tübingen:
J. B. C. Mohr, 1993), that no state arose in Judah before the eighth century, seem to be
confirmed.
246 Biblical studies and the failure of history
9. It is only infairy tales that the youngest brother plays the role of the hero. The case of a
junior member of the family trying to assume power by removing his older brother is a
recurrent theme in such political documents as the Amarna letters. In EA 137 the exiled
king of Byblos complains that his brother, ‘younger than I’ (l. 16), has rebelled against
him (this brother is in the same letter nicknamed ‘the dog’). Another case is Yapahu of
�
Gezer who is complaining because his younger brother is plotting against him and has
allied himself with the habiru (EA 298).
�
Are we Europeans really good readers of biblical texts? 247
to the European visitor. Nobody had repaired the roof! If this had been done,
the old man would be alive. The African reaction is different: though the vil-
lagers understood the point, they did not see it important. What was important
was, of course, why it happened exactly at the moment when the old man was
sleeping under the roof. Somehow, this must be a message: that this old man
had provoked the anger of demon or god, who wished to punish the old man.
What was important was not to repair the roof, but to prevent that such a thing
happen again: to sort out how and why the old man had angered the divine so
that his offence not be repeated. If this isthe case, the European visitor to the
foreign world of the ancient Near East or modern African traditional society is
at a disadvantage. The European might not be able to understand the meaning
of a narrative, though the plot issimple enough. Meaning may not be what you
see or what you hear. It can as well be implicit to the narrative without being
expressed. Such implied meaning can be found in Genesis 13, when Lot is
asked to choose his part of the country before his Uncle Abraham gets his share.
Abraham is believed by many readers to act in his usual gracious way, asking
the young person to step in front of him. As a matter of fact, Lot is breaking a
social code. A young person should never step on the toes of his superiors. Lot
seemingly chooses the best part for himself, but is, in the act, condemned, never
to return to the land of his fathers. After the destruction of Sodom, he moves
to Transjordan and, through his daughters, sires the nations of Moabites and
Ammonites.
It may be time for a preliminary statement. In a contribution about histori-
cal research written several years ago, I argued that there is a vast difference
between modern and ancient writers and readers of texts.10 The ancient authors
represent a pre-Aristotelian and pre-Kantian universe of logic which is not lim-
ited to the two categories of time and space. Instead, they included a third,
mythic category. If we consider our interpretation to be clear and limited as it is
to Kant’s categories and trained by the logic of Aristotle and his successor, the
third category available to the ancient storytellers may allow for a more rich and
variable interpretation. Although basically correct, I might have been wrong as
far as the ancient concept of time is involved. People of the ancient world prob-
ably had little sense of the modern concept of time.
There are many examples which show that the ancients had little understand-
ing of the importance of time as a logical category. It has been noted that no,
or only very few, official documents from ancient Syria and Palestine are dated
(I leave the Old Testament out of consideration as it is my conviction that this
document is not part of a pre-classical oriental world11). It is never indicated that
a period of time has elapsed since the death of a former king. Let me offer an
examplefrom the inscription of Mesha.12 This inscription states that, in the time
10. ‘On the Problem of Studying Israelite History-Apropos Abraham Malamat’s View on
Historical Research’, Biblische Notizen 24 (1984), 94–124.
11. Cf. Chapter 8, this volume.
12. Most extensive modern discussion in A. Dearman, Studies in the Mesha Inscription and
Moab (ASOR/SBL Archaeological and Biblical Studies 2; Atlanta, GA: Scholars Press,
1989).
248 Biblical studies and the failure of history
of Omri and his son, Israel oppressed Moab for forty years.13 We might question
the historical information. The report that Mesha liberated Moab in the time
of Ahab of Israel is not very likely in light of what is otherwise known of the
mighty King Ahab. This, however, is not the issueat present. More interesting
is the vague reference to time: the duration of Omri’s reign and half: the dura-
tion of his son’s reign.14 It equals forty years, which is, of course, a round or
‘mythical’ number, not a real date, comparable to the mythical reigns of David
and Solomon, each of forty years. I could, of course, also speak of the problems
caused by such a date for biblical historians, who have never been able to rec-
oncile this date with anything from the Old Testament.
Instead of proceeding further, I will return to one of my favourite cases, the
Amarna correspondence of King Rib-Adda of Byblus, seen through the lens of
the Italian Assyriologist Mario Liverani.15 According to Liverani, the seventy
odd letters of Rib-Adda to Pharaoh span a period of about ten to fifteen years.
None of them are, however, dated. This agrees with, for example, the admin-
istrative documents from Ugarit. They are never dated, apart from occasional
indications of the king who either issued the document, or during whose period
of reign a certain document was drafted. It is interesting that nothing really
happens in Rib-Adda’s letters. Some important events are repeated again and
again almost from the first letter to the last. Some of these events may belong
to the reign of Rib-Adda; others may precede him. This is not important. It is
possible to catch a glimpse of the realities behind the letters – for example, that
the last letters from Rib-Adda were written after he had been exiled from his
city. Otherwise, the correspondence has been structured on ‘mythic’ patterns,
most notably the theme of the righteous sufferer. This sufferer, of course, is
Rib-Adda himself. Another pattern is that of three ages. The past is the golden
period, the present a cruel reality and the future a revitalization of a golden past.
Nowhere does Rib-Adda show any interest in the ‘real world’, as we would put
it. It is always a world, seen through glasses very different from ours. The past
is interpreted in mythical patterns.
It is possible to continue this line. More examples could be taken into consid-
eration: the apology of King H attušiliš III of Hatti (a contemporary of Ramesses
II of Egypt).16 It would also� be possible to illustrate how unimportant space
13. Lines 7–8: ‘Now Omri had taken possession of a[ll the lan]d of Medaba. He lived in it
during his days and half of the days of his son(s) – forty years’ (in the translation of K. P.
Jackson, ‘The Language of the Mesha Inscription’, in Dearman, Studies in the Mesha
Inscription and Moab, 96–130, 97).
14. Evidently Omri is not primarily a name of a king in this text. It is the Bît Humriya of the
�
Assyrian inscriptions that pops up here. If Omri was seen as a person, how could he reign
for half of his son’s time?
15. Cf. M. Liverani, ‘Rib-Adda, giusto sofferente’, Altorientalische Forschungen 1 (1974),
175–205. I consider the contribution of W. L. Moran, ‘Rib-Adda: Job at Byblos?, in A.
Kort and S. Morschauser (eds)Biblical and related Studies Presented to Samuel Iwry
(Winona Lake, IN: Eisenbrauns, 1986), 173–81, to be not only a simplified version of
Liverani’s contribution; it is also more mundane and uninspiring.
16. Published by A. Götze, Hattušiliš. Der Bericht über seine Thronbesteigung nebst den
Paralleltexten (1925; reprint Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgeselschaft, 1967).
Are we Europeans really good readers of biblical texts? 249
is to such writers. This also concerns narratives of the Old Testament, where
space is used merely as a literary device. Space is not mentioned because of any
interest in geographical circumstances in the real world, but as a remedy of the
plotline.17 I will, however, hold this discussion and address, first of all, the form
of society which produced such texts and, second, the problems or even fallacies
of Western readers, confronted with ancient texts.
My colleague Frederick Cryer, the author of a major work on divination
in the ancient Near East and Old Testament,18 once told me of his experi-
ence in teaching a class of mostly Asian and African students. For most of the
time, these students had problems following the logic of his modern Western-
dominated exegesis and historical explanations. This changed when, as part of
his description of ancient society, he used the phrasing that ancient societies
were ‘magic societies’ – this is the thesis of his book on divination. As he told
me, it was easy to see that this description immediately caught the interest of his
audience, especially as he broadened his argument by describing various forms
of magic employed by the diviners of Antiquity. It dawned on these students that
Old Testament literature does not reflect a society of the Western world. On the
contrary, the society reflected by biblical texts was one of their own. This world
could be retrieved in their own country, in its villages or cities. They suddenly
realized that they could read and understand biblical texts without the scientific
apparatus of scholars from the Western world. They did not need to know very
much about English or German grammar to read biblical texts.
In a recent book, the American/French New Testament scholar Daniel Patte
has described the core of the problem.19 When a scholar of the modern Western
world reads an ancient text, he or she adopts a white, androcentric Northern
European or North American perspective. The scholar ‘forgets’ that these texts
were not composed by any who shared our Western and European culture. When
we apply our terms and remedies to the interpretation of ancient texts, the text
has little chance to defend itself.
‘Deconstruction’ has been a major issue in recent analyses of the history
related by biblical storytellers. Such deconstruction, which may only have a
slight resemblance to the one intended by a modern philosopher such asJacques
Derrida, has effectively removed the history of ancient Israel from the agenda
of the modern historian. The historiographers of the Bible have narrated a story
about ancient Israel that it is not only jeopardized and in danger of being retold
without respect for the biblical version, it has disappeared.20
17. Cf. my Die Vorgeschichte Israels. Von den Anfängen bis zum Ausgang des 13.
Jahrhunderts v. Chr. (Biblische Enzyklopädie 1; Stuttgart: Kohlhammer, 1996), 27–30,
English edition Prelude to Israel’s Past:Background and Beginnings of Israelite History
and Identity (Peabody, MA: Hendrickson, 1998), 20–23.
18. Divination in Ancient Israel and its Near Eastern Environment (JSOT supplement, 142;
Sheffield: Sheffield Academic Press, 1994).
19. Ethics of Biblical Interpretation: A Reevaluation (Louisville, KY: Westminster John
Knox Press, 1995).
20. After the effective removal of the patriarchs from the historical scene (T. L. Thompson,
The Historicity of the Patriarchal narratives. The Quest for the Historical Abraham,
250 Biblical studies and the failure of history
How can this be? It is hardly difficult to understand this in the moment we
address the problems caused by ancient texts being read by modern eyes. The
answer is simple: we have applied the wrong methodology. There can be no
doubt about it. It cannot be avoided that more than 100 years of an intensive
historical reading of Old Testament narrative has produced no more than a phan-
tom, which, among scholars generally, is called ancient Israel: a projection of
imagination.21
The reason is not that the Old Testament is, from a historical point of view,
imprecise. All ancient texts are imprecise when scrutinized by modern scholars.
We must look within ourselves; the fault is not in the ancient texts. When we
ask these texts to be historical sources for the past, we apply false categories –
namely, our concepts of ‘time’ and ‘space’.
In the modern sense of the word, history is an invention of the modern age;
it stands at the very entrance to modernity, without which the modern world is
hardly conceivable. As a concept, history hardly predates the romantic period
(i.e. the beginning of the nineteenth century), although it would be foolish to say
that it had no forerunners. Its origins should be sought in literature, not in the
actual world, as becomes clear when we approach the question of terminology.
Most modern languages cannot distinguish between ‘history’ and ‘story’, as in
English. The situation in German is typical. In German, ‘history’ is translated
as Geschichte but Geschichte also means ‘narrative’, ‘story’, though not, in
itself, Märchen – that is, ‘fairytale’. I cannot recollect the source but once saw
a reference to Goethe, who spoke of Old Testament history as Die Geschichte
sind, ‘the stories say’, whereas one generation later the same subject would be
addressed as Die Geschichte ist: ‘history says’.
BZAW, 133; Berlin: de Gruyter, 1974; and J. Van Seters, Abraham in History and
Tradition, New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1975), this process continued with
the next phase of the biblical history, first the period from the Exodus to the introduction
of the monarchy (cf. initially N. P. Lemche, Early Israel: Anthropological and Historical
Studies on the Israelite Society Before the Monarchy, VT supplement, 37; Leiden: E. J.
Brill, 1985, and now the united monarchy, cf. note 8 above). All of this was combined
into a major hypothesis by T. L. Thompson, The Early History of the Israelite People
from the Written and Archaeological Sources (SHANE, 4; Leiden: E. J. Brill, 1992),
and popularized in P. R. Davies, In Search of Ancient Israel (JSOT supplement, 148;
Sheffield: Sheffield Academic Press, 1992). Many criticisms have been voiced. Most
scholars have not yet realized that it is not a question of the Old Testament being impre-
cise as far as history goes. There is a systemic lack of precise historical information in the
Old Testament narrative which shows that this narrative has nothing to do with history
in our sense of the word. Our sense of history meant nothing to the authors of biblical
literature. This does not mean that there can be no historical information preserved by the
biblical narrative. The conclusion is that any such information is accidental and will not
allow for historical reconstruction. Cf. on this Chapter 10, this volume. This conclusion
is the backbone of such recent studies such as N. P. Lemche, Die Vorgeschichte Israel,
idem; The Israelites in History and Tradition (Louisville, KY: John Knox and SPCK,
1998); and T. L. Thompson, The Bible in History: How Writers Create a Past (London:
Jonathan Cape, 1999).
21. As described by Philip Davies, In Search of Ancient Israel, 22–48.
Are we Europeans really good readers of biblical texts? 251
This relationship between literature and history was not forgotten at the
beginning of the modern era. As late as the beginning of the twentieth century,
the relationship was still acknowledged. Thus, the famous historian of ancient
Rome, Theodor Mommsen, was awarded the Nobel Prize in literature. It is
hardly difficult to point to several European and North American historians who
were as much admired for their style and presentation as for the accuracy of
their interpretation. The transformation of the discipline of history into modern
historical investigation has been gradual and probably hardly noticed by the
public. In the end, the dominant mode of thinking in the Western world changed
and became ‘historical’. The value of history no longer consisted in the way in
which it was presented. It was believed to be accurate.
In the Western world, we live very much in the modern world and historical
thinking is the way in which we understand the past. It has often been said that
history – also modern history – is no more than narratives (somebody told us
that something happened). The fallacy of modern reading appears when it is
taken for granted that these narratives reflect what happened rather than opin-
ions about what may – or may not – have happened. In the latter case, when we
talk about what did not happen, we often refer to the literary category of propa-
ganda which, however, in a NorthEuropean and NorthAmerican understanding,
is automatically understood as lies because the only valid criterion is whether
it really happened. I suppose that all of this has sharpened in biblical studies.
The conservative religious mind (and it should not be forgotten – not even in
an age of change – that theologians are ‘conservative’) became influenced by
modern ideas about historical precision. Consequently, it analysed biblical texts
by applying modern criteria (the time and space criteria). It is hardly a surprise
that the question of historical accuracy and verification became more important
than other issues, as ethics. We could say that God had been subjected to the
tyranny of time and space.
Western tradition is truly imperialistic. It is hardly a surprise that it is also
exclusive and willing to destroy other traditions. We cannot place the blame on
ordinary men, as they have had no chance to escape the impression that we know
everything.It is an amazing and sad fact that even today, scholars who work in a
non-European environment are not aware of their inborn Eurocentrism.22
Ancient Israel is merely one of many examples of this trend in modern schol-
arship. It is – as shown by Keith W. Whitelam23 – a typical example which also
tells us how dangerous our Eurocentrism can be for other cultures. By extracting
this ancient Israel from biblical narrative, we have created a European bridge-
head among the peoples of the ancient Near East. We have focused on ancient
Israel. It has become the single most important component of our description of
22. It has never been so acidly explained as in M. Prior, The Bible and Colonialism: A Moral
Critique (Sheffield: Sheffield Academic Press, 1997).
23. The most obvious example being perhaps what happened to the non-Jewish population
of Palestine in modern times. See K. W. Whitelam, The Invention of Ancient Israel: The
Silencing of Palestinian History (London and New York: Routledge, 1996). See also on
this the notes in N. P. Lemche, ‘Clio is Also Among the Muses. Keith W. Whitelam and
the History of Palestine: A Review and a Commentary’, SJOT 10 (1996), 88–114.
252 Biblical studies and the failure of history
the ancient world. Yet, we have forgotten that it never existed apart from litera-
ture. We have also allowed this notion of ancient Israel to dominate our attitude
towards recent events and our interpretations of the modern Middle Eastern
world. It has been more than difficult for non-Europeans and for people who do
not understand our notion of the world to penetrate the screen of imagination we
have created that they might tell us that we are wrong. Sometimes explosives
have been chosen as means of getting through.
I do not want to be misunderstood. Although I argue that we have been poor
readers of ancient texts, I do not wish to say that we cannot read this literature.
Nor do I recommend that these texts should be seen as modern texts, as litera-
ture in the modern sense. At the moment, we are flooded by an endless stream
of narrative interpretations of the Bible and, for now, I welcome such readings.
They are part of the post-modern project and are necessary. On the other hand,
they are just as Eurocentric as what we have been doing since the beginning of
the last century and they repeat many of the mistakes of the past.
This has to be said in light of modern trends among literary students, who
argue that texts are no more than meaningless collections of signs until read,
and that the important part of the interchange between a reader and his text is
the reader. To the extent that we are currently enjoying our precious but short
time in the world of the living, this may be true for us – as people. However,
it is impossible to point to valid and generally accepted methods of reading.
The resulting lack of confirmed results of the literary investigations may be a
warning (as were formerly the clashes and disagreements between historians – a
point often argued by conservative theologians) that, on this occasion, we place
ourselves above the biblical texts. We do not allow them an opportunity to speak
for themselves – whatever that might mean. Historians, in a post-modern, non-
Eurocentric and non-androcentric world, may have something to contribute.
But this requires that they distance themselves from their own tradition and are
willing to read ancient texts within the context of ancient societies as products
of a mythic and magic culture.
Acknowledgements
It is with hesitation that I engage this subject as it has been so well covered by
John Van Seters in his classic study In Search of History from 1983.1 In this
monograph, Van Seters sets the standard for dealing with historiography in the
ancient world, with an extensive discussion of the genres, aims and techniques
of ancient writers, their methodological outlook, interest in the past, propa-
gandistic ideas, etc. It will be difficult to surpass this study. The scope of Van
Seters’s investigation is limited, however, by his earlier studies in the history of
the Yahwist and the origins of biblical narrative, which he considers generally
to be exilic (i.e. belonging to the sixth century bce), an opinion he has never
given up. This was revolutionary when it was first proposed more than 25 years
ago.2 It has now become mainstream and tacitly accepted by students of the
scholars formerly in opposition to the idea of such a late date for the oldest his-
tory writing in the Old Testament.3 Although this has few consequences for his
evaluation of the expressions of historical recollection within the ancient Near
East, it restricts his interest in Greek history writing to the earliest of the Greek
tradition: the logographers of the sixth century bce and Herodotus of the fifth
century bce.4 Accordingly, Herodotus is not introduced as ‘the father of history’
but as a parallel to the history writing found in the Old Testament. Van Seters’s
1. John Van Seters, In Search of History: Historiography in the Ancient World and the
Origins of Biblical History (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1983). See also on
historiography in the ancient Near East, John Van Seters, ‘The Historiography of the
Ancient Near East’, CANE IV (1993): 2433–44.
2. John Van Seters, Abraham in History and Tradition (New Haven, CT: Yale University
Press, 1975) and repeated in the same author’s The Prologue to History: The Yahwist
as Historian in Genesis (Louisville, KY: Westminster/John Knox, 1992) and The Life of
Moses: The Yahwist as Historian in Exodus-Numbers (Kampen: Kok Pharos, 1994).
3. It is quite interesting that even scholarship that may be described as ‘evangelical’ can
discuss such a date without a biased critique; cf. recently Gordon J. Wenham, ‘Pondering
the Pentateuch: The Search for a New Paradigm’, in D. W. Baker and B. T. Arnold
(eds) The Face of Old Testament Studies: A Survey of Contemporary Approaches (Grand
Rapids, MI: Baker Books, 1999), 116–44.
4. Van Seters, In Search of History, 8–54.
254 Biblical studies and the failure of history
between history guided by a divine agent and secular history, they were still
understood to be interested in describing the past as it happened. They suppos-
edly entertained ideas about the reality of the past, which could be likened to
modern ideas. Although their writings were biased and not up to the standards
of modern history writing, they provided material that allowed their modern
colleagues to reuse their description of the past in a modern analysis of what
really happened.13
As a consequence, much modern history writing – and I am not speaking
only of Old Testament scholarship, but also of Near Eastern studies, in general –
was but a modern rationalistic paraphrase of the description of the past found in
ancient literature. To use one of my favourite quotes by Mario Liverani, modern
scholars are simply lazy and therefore all too ready to accept what they find in
an ancient source as if this was a source that was likely to contain exact histori-
cal information about the past.14
Hittite history writing provides one of the specimens of ancient Near
Eastern history writing that has traditionally been held in high esteem by mod-
ern scholars.15 This embraces several genres such as royal annals, prologues
to international treaties, royal decrees and autobiographical sketches. In two
extensive articles on Hittite historiography published more than twenty years
ago, Liverani presented analyses of Hittite historical literature. In the first arti-
cle, he analyses the historical prologue to the treaty between H atti and King
Šunaššura of Kizzuwatna from the early Neo-Hittite Empire.16 �In the second,
he analyses the overview of early Hittite history found in Kking Telipinus’s
decree from the sixteenth century bce.17 This historiography has been praised
for being ‘factual’ to the point and generally trustworthy. However, this is hardly
the case. The Šunaššura prologue is a fine piece of propaganda. It seems as if
the relationship was based on equality and history is introduced to show that
the treaty merely re-established relations as they had previously existed between
13. I have dealt with this subject in a number of publications, including The Israelites in
History and Tradition (London: SPCK/Louisville, KY: Westminster John Knox, 1998),
1–21. Cf. also my ‘Om historisk erindring i Det Gamle Testamentes historiefortællinger’,
in G. Hallbäck and J. Strange (eds) Bibel og historieskrivning (Copenhagen: Museum
Tusculanum, 1999), 11–28.
14. Mario Liverani, ‘Telipinu, or: On Solidarity’, in his Myths and Politics in Ancient Near
Eastern Historiography (London: Equinox, 2004), 27–52, 28.
15. In general on Hittite history writing, cf. Hubert Cancik, Grundzüge der hethitischen und
alttestamentlichen Geschichtsschreibung (Wiesbaden: Harrassowitz, 1976). Cf. also Van
Seters, In Search of History, 100–26.
16. Mario Liverani, ‘Storiografia politica hittita – I: Šunaššura, ovvero: Della reciprocità’,
Oriens Antiquus 12 (1973), 267–97. A transcription and translation of the Akkadian
version of the treaty is published in E. F. Weidner, Politische Dokumente aus Kleinasien
(Leipzig, 1923; reprint, Hildesheim and New York: Georg Olms, 1970), 88–111.
17. Cf. Mario Liverani, ‘Storiografia politica hittita – II: Telipinu, ovvero: Della solidarietà’
(1977). A recent study on the text has been published by Inge Hoffmann, Der Erlass
Telipinus (Heidelberg: Carl Winther, 1984).
History writing in the ancient Near East and Greece 257
18. Text published and translated by Albrecht Götze, Hattušiliš. Der Bericht über
�
seine Thronbesteigung nebst den Paralleltexten (Leipzig, 1925; reprint, Darmstadt:
Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, 1964) with a supplement Neue Bruchstücke zum
großen Text des Hattušiliš und den Paralleltexten (Leipzig, 1930; reprint, Darmstadt:
�
Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, 1970).
19. Van Seters, In Search of History, 188–91.
20. Cf. Mario Liverani, ‘Memorandum on the Approach to Historiographic Texts’, Orientalia
NS 42 (1973), 178–94, but see the same author’s ‘Partire sul carro, per il deserto’, Annali
dell’Istituto Universitario Orientale di Napoli NS 22 (1972), 403–15.
258 Biblical studies and the failure of history
In his autobiography, King Idrimi claims to be the youngest son of the king of
Aleppo.21 A coup d’état led by his brother removes his father from the throne and
the royal family seeks refuge at Emar, ruled by the queen’s father. Conditions
are favourable, but Idrimi wishes to regain the throne of his father and sets out
to fulfil a vow to return to the throne in his chariot assisted only by his driver.
He travels to Canaan and lives there as a refugee for seven years when he is
recognized by some people from his hometown. He becomes the leader of these
men and becomes king – not in Aleppo, but in neighbouring Alalah.
� It is prob-
The autobiographical story of Idrimi blends history with fairy tale.
ably true that Idrimi came from Aleppo. It is probably also true that he lived in
exile for some years and it is an undisputed fact that he became king of Alalah.
�
We do not know whether it is true that he was the youngest son or that he stayed
in exile for seven years. As it is told, his story is more fairy tale than historical
report. Evidently Idrimi chose to tell a story rather than a report of historical
events. The reason seems clear: He had no claim to the throne of Alalah as it was
� of this
not his family’s traditional possession. He was not the legitimate king
city-state, but needed to present an apology for assuming power where he had
no traditional right to rule. He invented his history more than he reconstructed
the past.
We do not know whether or not his version of the past was accepted in his
new kingdom, but we do know that a similar story has been accepted for more
than 2000 years – the story of King David’s ascension to the throne. This story
is so similar to that told by Idrimi that we are entitled to say that it is the same
story with different actors and a different setting.22
What binds Idrimi and David together? Not that they were historical persons.
Idrimi certainly was, David probably not. They are, however, both usurpers to
the throne and a defence has to be made to answer objections to their ascension
to power. It does not matter much whether or not it really happened. Idrimi’s
story is invented history, David’s fate even more. Both stories show how impor-
tant it was to ancients to present the past in such a way that it could be accepted
by the present: in Idrimi’s case by his subjects, in David’s by the readers of the
biblical narrative.
Reality was not reality in Antiquity, even to the people who experienced
it. Liverani has published an excellent analysis of this in his study of the cor-
respondence of King Rib-Adda of Byblos, found among the Amarna letters
(also available only in Italian).23 He shows that Rib-Adda describes his life
according to a mythical pattern, which includes a golden past, a brazen now
and a golden future. To fit this pattern, Rib-Adda so manipulates events of his
21. Published by Sidney Smith, The Statue of Idri-mi (London: The British Institute of
Archaeology in Ankara, 1949).
22. As first seen by Giovanni Buccellati, ‘La “carriera” di David e quella di Idrimi, re di
Alalac’, Bibbia e Oriente 4 (1962), 95–9.
23. Cf. Mario Liverani, ‘Rib-Adda, giusto sofferente’, Altorientalische Forschungen 1
(1974), 175–205.
History writing in the ancient Near East and Greece 259
own time that it is almost impossible to say what really happened and what
clearly invented.
The main difference between ancient and modern history writing is probably
the concept of time. Generally speaking, time is to modern man a quantity that
can be measured in a very exact way. To the people of ancient times, it was
more a quality, something meaningful. Of course, they knew how to measure
time, but this was less important than understanding its quality. Because his-
tory belongs to past time, it is by itself meaningful. The meaning is not what
really happened but the impact the past has on the present. How can we learn
from history? People of our time have often raised this question without getting
an answer and we hear that life is meaningless, but this was never the case in
Antiquity. Life was meaningful, not as we see it, but because of the will of the
gods which directed the course of events. When it comes to ancient history writ-
ing, it was the intention of historiographers to show that life was meaningful.
With that purpose in mind, they manipulated history to fit their objective. Royal
inscriptions of all kinds were written to serve as royal propaganda. Religious
inscriptions included propaganda, praising the acts of the gods. Although we
possess from the ancient Near East only official material that illustrates my
point, I am quite convinced that ordinary people would also have manipulated
their own histories in such a way that it served their interests. Both oriental and
classic historiography relied on this manipulation of the past to present a mes-
sage of divine intent for the present. There is no great difference here between
classical authors and their Near Eastern colleagues.
If we are to speak of real differences, they relate to genres. Nowhere in the
ancient Near East do we find anything which remotely compares with Herod
otus’s Histories. Although it has a definite propagandistic touch – to describe
how the Athenians destroyed their Persian foes – Herodotus’s writings were
not governed by obviously propagandistic aims. He was not employed by some
public authority to construct an official history of the past, but was engaged in
the project of describing Greek civilization as superior to that of the Oriental
world. His Investigations – the correct translation of the title of his work – was
likely a private enterprise and not a publicly commissioned task. It is also a uni-
versal history of the world. Only after a comprehensive introduction to the his-
tory and ethnography of the civilizations of the East does Herodotus concentrate
on Greece. It is not different from the Hittite examples of history writing already
mentioned. It arranges history as it suits the author. Past history is manipulated
to improve understanding of present events. Herodotus shares a common back-
ground – the understanding of the universe – with his colleagues in the Near East.
The ancient Near East has, however, not produced anything that can even
remotely be likened to Herodotus’s investigations. Royal propaganda is offi-
cially commissioned literature – mostly prose. It does not cover world history
but has a more specific task to fulfil. World history in the form of a universal his-
tory is presented in epic form, like the creation epic of Enuma Eliš, not in prose
narrative. Albright probably understood this when he presented his theory of an
ancient Hebrew oral tradition that was secondarily transformed into the prose
260 Biblical studies and the failure of history
narrative of the biblical historical books.24 It is the prose form of the biblical
universal history that causes problems, not the existence of a universal history
within this framework.
Here we might approach a solution to the problem by comparing ancient
Near Eastern historiography with its Greek counterpart. In the ancient Near
East, prose was used as a medium of reporting the past, however, only the not
so distant past (exceptions are known such as the Tukulti-Ninurta I epic25). The
ancient past – with its mythic encounter between gods and human beings – was
mainly reserved for poetry. In Greece, epic literature existed probably early,
such as Homer (if he is really early – critical voices have been raised that argue
in favour of a much later date than often assumed, the sixth century bce or even
later) or Hesiod. In the classical period and, later, in the Hellenistic and Roman
periods, poetry has generally been substituted with prose as medium for nar-
rating the distant past. Poets were still likely to use poetry as their vehicle of
language, as is the case with Ovid, who recounts the changing of world ages
in his Metamorphoses in a poetic form that borrows its content from Hesiod’s
Work and Days.26
If we look at the historical narrative in the Old Testament, it opens with the
most distant past. All except a few verses are in prose, including the tale of the
Flood, which is so close to the Neo-Babylonian version we find on the eleventh
tablet of the Gilgamesh epic. We sometimes get the impression that the biblical
Flood story is a rewriting of the Gilgamesh tale in prose form (cf. the raven, the
first bird to go – out of context in the biblical version – to set a world record for
long distance flying for ravens; in Gilgamesh, the raven is the third bird, the one
that does not return).
Previously, it was often assumed that poetic ‘quotations’ included in the his-
torical prose narrative were more ancient than their prose context. This is hardly
a necessary assumption. Some so-called ‘archaic verses’ of the Old Testament
may be very young – for example, the reference to the Macedonians in Numbers
24:24: ‘And ships shall come from the coast of Chittim, and shall afflict Asshur,
and shall afflict Eber, and he also shall perish for ever’ (KJV), a prophecy which
Luther saw as a reference to the Romans.27 Such quotations can hardly be used
as evidence for an original Hebrew epic that was translated by the Yahwist into
prose.
After the primeval history follows the heroic past of the Hebrew nation,
almost exclusively in prose. Mesopotamian writers would, like Homer, have
presented this age in poetry, Herodotus definitely in prose. The context of the
24. Cf. as the latest summary of his opinion about archaic Hebrew verse, William F.
Albright, Yahweh and the Gods of Canaan. A Historical Analysis of Two Contrasting
Faiths (London: The Athlone Press, 1968), 1–46.
25. Cf. the Yale dissertation on this epic by Peter Machinist, The Epic of Tukulti-Ninurta I:
A Study in Middle Assyrian Literature (PhD thesis, Yale University, 1978).
26. Cf. Hesiod, Works and Days, 110–55, and Ovid, Metamorphoses, I, 90–162.
27. Note to his translation of Num 24:24, Martin Luther, Die gantze Heilige Schrift Deudsch
(Wittenberg, 1545; reprint, Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, 1972).
History writing in the ancient Near East and Greece 261
primeval history is clearly, without dispute, Near Eastern. Some may want to
discuss the relationship between the Genesis 1 and Greek (Ionian) philosophy of
the sixth century;28 but the moment we get to Genesis 2–3, we are firmly situated
within Mesopotamian tradition. The form of the primeval history is definitely
unusual and indicates a society that has found a more extensive use of prose than
was normal in the ancient Near East.
The not so distant past, the history of the Hebrew kingdoms as narrated by
the so-called ‘Deuteronomistic History’, is prose. As to form, it accords with
Near Eastern practice as well as Greek ideas about history writing. It includes
some passages that could easily be identified as archival notes, such as the pas-
sage that includes the famous incident of Sennacherib ante muros (2 Kgs 18:13-
16), or the note about Tiglat-Pileser III’s rearrangements in the north (2 Kgs
16:29-30). Maybe the biblical authors who put Joshua together also borrowed
the prose form of Assyrian royal annals (as proposed by K. Lawson Younger).29
The form of Kings is unique, however, within a Near Eastern context because
of its blend of official information – or information presented in a form that
borrows from official types of information transmission, such as royal annals,
chronicles, legend and saga. This kind of mixture we find in Greek historiogra-
phy, but hardly in the Near East in pre-Hellenistic times.
To conclude: from a form-critical perspective, the historical narrative in the
Old Testament resembles Greek historiographic tradition more than the histori-
cal recollections of the ancient Near East. However, form is not the same as
content, and content deals with intention. The intention of royal literature in
the ancient Near East is undoubtedly propaganda. It contains propaganda when
the king boasts of his mighty deeds in inscriptions that only the gods can read,
or when he directly addresses a public of human beings – even if hardly more
than a few were able to read the inscriptions. Although such inscriptions might
have been copied, it was, to the best of my knowledge, not educational literature
(i.e. it was not used in the academic educational system). Myths and epics were
copied and transmitted in writing at least in Mesopotamia in such institutions
from one generation to the next. It was more than myth: it was wisdom and
explained the wisdom of the divine arrangement of the world to the students
who, in adopting this wisdom, became scholars and, in their own eyes, the
masters of their time.
We find some resemblance to the meaning of history and history writing
in the classical world because, in the classical world, history was considered
a way to obtain wisdom and therefore an indispensable part of the academic
curriculum. I have dealt with the subject of education and history writing more
extensively in John Van Seters’s Festschrift and will not repeat the discussion
here.30 However, the quote from Cicero that stands as a gateway to antique
28. Cf. John Van Seters, ‘The Primeval Histories of Greece and Israel Compared’, ZAW 100
(1988), 1–22.
29. K. Lawson Younger, Jr., Ancient Conquest Accounts: A Study in Ancient Near Eastern
and Biblical History Writing (JSOT supplement, 98; Sheffield: JSOT Press, 1990).
30. Chapter 17, this volume.
262 Biblical studies and the failure of history
notions of history is very important: ‘Historia vero testis temporum, lux ver-
itatis, vita memoriae, magistra vitae, nuntia vetustatis’ (‘History [is] truly the
witness about the ages, the light of truth, the life of memories, the teacher of
life, and the messenger of ancient times’).31 The fact that history is ‘the teacher
of life’ is most important because it says that in order to understand the ways
of life people must study history. History provides education for the next gen-
eration – in classical academia, the children of the elite, the next generation to
govern and administer the world.
Most of what has been said about manipulating history to fit the purpose
of the present holds true when it comes to history writing in Greece and in the
Hellenistic–Roman world. Normally it was not officially sponsored – although
official literature existed such as annals and royal inscriptions of the kind
present in the Augustean Monumentum Ancyranum.32 It is mostly private in ori-
entation, part of the academic life of the learned few. It was also a genre adopted
by retired gentlemen or politicians, waiting for a new chance. It was one of
the main ways to a better understanding of the meaning of life and, therefore,
indispensable.
Greco-Roman historiography is very different from ancient Near Eastern and,
at the same time, rather similar. History as it really happened is not very impor-
tant. It is not that one might deliberately disregard facts, but it was accepted that
facts be twisted and ameliorated to conform to current needs. The critical mind
was not concerned with historical truth in the sense that things were supposed to
have happened exactly as described. The question would likely be meaningless
to both ancient historiographers and audiences alike. ‘What really happened’ is
a kind of quantitative statement and quantity was not – as already stated – the
object of the wise, but a subject reserved for business people and those engaged
in practical crafts. Instead of quantity, scholars and students asked for quality:
what the meaning of history was and not just what happened and what not.
The quality of historiography has to be kept in mind when one approaches
biblical historiography. This subject is enormous. The question is, however,
whether the historiography of the Old Testament expresses propaganda? If the
answer is yes, then we may ask: for what purpose? Should we reckon the histori-
cal narrative to represent wisdom literature? Does it have an educational aim?
Does it explain the present and does it have a programme for the future?
I am not going to answer any of these questions here as I have presented most
of the answers elsewhere – easily available or soon to be published. Nor am I
going to present any final verdict regarding the relationship between biblical
and Greek historiography and biblical and ancient Near Eastern historiography.
There are more arguments in favour of a Greek connection than an Oriental one,
but the debate continues.
Acknowledgements
John Van Seters opens his discussion on the origins of ancient Israelite histori-
ography with a paragraph devoted to early Greek historiography, most notably
Herodotus and his predecessors, the Ionian logographers.1 This seems a natu-
ral option, the genre of biblical historiography being very close to the Greek
although, to quote Van Seters, ‘the neglect of Greek historiography for any com-
parative study has been almost total’.2 There are, according to Van Seters, two
reasons for this neglect. First of all, biblical scholars have generally reckoned
biblical historiography to be older than the earliest Greek history writing by sev-
eral hundred years. It goes without saying that if the Yahwist composed his his-
toriographical literature in the glorious days of Solomon, there would have been
no direct connection between him and Herodotus or the Ionian logographers. If,
however, the Yahwist belongs to the sixth century bce, which is the opinion of
Van Seters, it is more reasonable to study the closely related and more or less
contemporary development of historiography in the Hellenic world. The second
reason for the neglect of the parallel development in Greece was the old division
created by Boman between the Greek and Hebrew mind, the Greek mind being
cyclically oriented while Hebrew writers looked on time as linear.3
Van Seters reckons the second issue to be immaterial and nullified by James
Barr, almost at the moment Boman’s monograph appeared in English. Greek
history writing was no more cyclical than that of the Bible and the Greek mind
no more cyclically structured than the Hebrew.4 The first issue is hardly relevant,
any longer, but falls with the early date of the biblical literature. Herodotus,
1. J. Van Seters, In Search of History: Historiography in the Ancient World and the Origins
of Biblical History (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1983), 8–54.
2. Ibid., 8.
3. T. Boman, Das hebräische Denken im Vergleich mit dem griechischen (Göttingen, 1954;
English translation, Hebrew Thought Compared with Greek, London: W. W. Norton and
Company, 1960). Boman’s Ideas had already been published in Norwegian before World
War II, in ‘Den semitists tenknings egenart’, NTT 34 (1933), 1–34.
4. J. Barr, The Semantics of Biblical Language (Oxford, 1961), especially 46–79. Cf. also
J. Barr, Biblical Words for Time (SBT, 33; 19692), 143–9.
Good and bad in history 265
the ‘father of history’, is, therefore, an obvious choice if we look in the clas-
sical world for parallels to biblical historiography. In spite of this, little has
appeared in this respect until recently. Only a few authors have shown interest in
the subject, though the monographs by Mandell and Freedman and by Nielsen
should be mentioned.5 Apart from them, little has appeared that sheds light on
the possible links between the Greek literary world and biblical history writing.6
However, Nielsen indicates a fruitful line of study, as it discusses the structure
of narrative and compositional technique and does not linger on minor points.
These scholars have one thing in common with Van Seters: they only include
discussions of pre-classical and early classical history writing. When scholars
refer to the logographer and Herodotus, they bypass other and only slightly
later Greek authors such as Thucydides and Xenophon.7 Their thesis repeats the
mistakes of previous scholarship. They make chronology their most important
argument. Scholars such as von Rad and Noth, on the one hand, and their North
American colleagues, on the other, reckoned the beginning of biblical history
writing to go back to the tenth century bce or earlier. For seemingly obvious
reasons they paid no attention at all to the Greek historians. Even if their dating
of biblical historiography had been correct, their neglect of developments in the
Greek world was mistaken. The similarity between Greek and Hebrew histori-
ography, including technique, style and form of narrating the past, is obvious.
Although the two bodies of literature need not be related in a direct way, they are
so close in style that the process that led to historiography may have displayed
common traits. If the oldest Israelite history writing goes back to Solomon’s
time, we might simply have an example of a similar phenomenon originating
in two separate cultures.
In this case, we would be speaking about developments taking place within
hastily changing societies, including a growing literacy, at least among rul-
ing elite groups. Both societies experienced a cultural stage dominated by
oral literature8 and both possessed a heritage of oral as well as written epic
9. Provided that the poems of Homer are really as old as they are usually believed to
be (i.e. going back to, say, the eighth century bce). Recent developments in Homeric
studies tend to point to a later date, the sixth century bce or later. Cf. M. S. Jensen,
The Homeric Question and the Oral-Formulaic theory (Opuscula Graecolatina, 20;
Copenhagen: Museum Tusculanum, 1980). The evidence of written epic literature in
Syria and Palestine consists, of course, of the epic literature of Ugarit, written – if not
composed – in the thirteenth century bce.
10. Van Seters, In Search of History, 40–51.
11. Inspired by his mentor F. W. Winnett, J. Van Seters has been singularly faithful to his
idea of the Yahwist as an exilic writer. Cf. his Abraham in History and Tradition (New
Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1975) and the argument is repeated in his more recent
studies on the Yahwist in Genesis through Numbers (Prologue to History: The Yahwist
as Historian in Genesis, Louisville, KY: Westminster John Knox, 1992, and The Life of
Moses: The Yahwist as Historian in Exodus-Numbers, Kampen: Kok Pharos Publishing
House, 1994).
Good and bad in history 267
12. J. Pasto has recently tried to demonstrate the existence of a continuum reaching from
W. M. L. de Wette (early nineteenth century ce) to P. R. Davies, K. W, Whitelam, T. L.
Thompson and this author. Like de Wette and subsequent German scholarship, in gen-
eral, the ‘revisionists’ of our time have created an artificial division between pre-exilic
and post-exilic Palestinian society that probably never was. Cf., Pasto, ‘When the End
is the Beginning? Or When the Biblical Past is the Political Present: Some Thoughts on
Ancient Israel, “Post-Exilic Judaism” and the Politics of Biblical Scholarship’, SJOT 12
(1998), 157–202. Although it is easy to sympathize with Pasto’s approach, which is well
argued, I will maintain that it has been circumvented by recent developments within the
circle of ‘revisionists’. They now argue that this line of division never existed because
ancient (i.e. early Iron Age) Palestinian society had very little or nothing to do with
the image of ancient Israel created by the biblical historiographers. It is not a reformed
society that returned to Palestine from Mesopotamia, but a completely new society that
constructed its own past. Cf. N. P. Lemche, The Israelites in History and Tradition
(Library of Ancient Israel; Louisville, KY: Westminster John Knox 1998), and T. L.
Thompson, The Bible in History: How Writers Create a Past (London: Jonathan Cape,
1999).
268 Biblical studies and the failure of history
content to biblical history. We should think first and foremost of Livy and his
Ab urbe condita, his great history of Rome from its beginning to the fall of the
Republic, dating from the principate of Augustus.17
Livy’s history differs from the historical tales of the Bible in its lack of a pri-
mary history. It opens with a résumé of the tribulations of the hero Aeneas and
his crew of refugees from Troy during his travels to Italy. This section is com-
parable to the description of the Israelites wandering around in the desert for
many years. After arriving in Italy, the Trojan hero set out to conquer a territory
for himself and his men, thus creating the foundation for the establishment of
the future Roman state. Aeneas did not found Rome. This was left to Romulus,
when kingship began.
Like the Bible’s history of ancient Israel, the scope and aim of Livy’s work
is obvious: to show how the virtues of ancient Romans deteriorated until the
Republic could no longer survive and a new political arrangement had to be
established. It functions as an apology for the changes brought about by the
Augustan restoration. The narrative centres on the fate of important men – some
good, some evil. It serves as an instruction to the reader. It is a reminder to Livy’s
contemporaries of the importance of the ancient virtues, forgotten for so long.
In short, history in Livy’s eyes is the magister vitae, the ‘teacher about life’.18
There are, of course, no direct lines connecting the historical narratives of
the Old Testament with those of Livy’s history. Biblical literature is older, in
some cases, much older than Livy’s history and it is gratuitous to say that Livy
never saw a page of what was to become the Old Testament. It is also very
easy to point to differences between the two literary works. Although such dis-
similarities involve many aspects of the narratives, they do not prevent us from
speaking of a basic unity of intention and style. It might be rewarding to probe
further into the realm of Greek and Roman historical tradition.
The studies devoted to Greek and Roman historiography, several of which
are mentioned by Van Seters, are many. I would, however, like to call atten-
tion to such a work: a twenty-year-old study on Roman historiography by the
Danish scholar Peter Ørsted. I do so not because it has never been translated
into one of the major languages and therefore basically unknown outside of
Denmark (though that is the case), but rather because it represents an interest-
ing approach.19
17. Livy was born in 59bce and died in 17ce. His history in 142 books was written between
26bce and 17ce.
18. The expression was coined by Cicero, De oratore II.IX.36: ‘Historia vero testis tempo-
rum, lux veritatis, vita memoriae, magister vitae, nuntia vetustatis’ (‘History is truly the
witness about the ages, the light of truth, the life of memories, the teacher of life, and the
messenger of ancient times’).
19. P. Ørsted, Romersk historieskrivning (Copenhagen: Gyldendal, 1978).
270 Biblical studies and the failure of history
20. Notably Quintilian’s (c.40–100) Institutio Oratoria or Cicero’s theoretical writings such
as De oratore Brutus and Orator.
21. Thucydides, The Pelopponesian War, I.22.
Good and bad in history 271
of the classical world, with the great persons of the past providing examples to
follow or scorn.
22. E.g. A. Lemaire, Les écoles et la formation de la Bible dens l’ancien Israel (OBO, 39;
Fribourg: Presses Universitaires, 1981).
23. Cf. K. L. Younger, Ancient Conquest Accounts: A Study of Ancient Near Eastern and
Biblical History Writing (JSOT supplement, 98; Sheffield: Sheffield Academic Press,
272 Biblical studies and the failure of history
Pentateuch or the Deuteronomistic History has ever been found among the lit-
eratures of the ancient Near East. As a matter of fact, the ties that bind biblical
literature to classical historiography are much more evident. While it is common
for scholars to state that we know little or nothing about the identity of biblical
historiographers, we do possess their literature and can describe the authors
by referring to, first, its form, content, biases, ideas, ethics, etc., and, second,
the information they provide (i.e. the range of their knowledge and education).
This is an invitation to take up comparative studies of the Greco-Roman tradi-
tion with biblical literature. It is not my intention to go further here, although
I cannot resist presenting some preliminary observations and ideas that might
serve as an indication of how fruitful such comparison can be for understanding
biblical historiography.
Evidently, biblical writers chose history as the medium most suitable for con-
veying their image of the past in a way that might also serve as instruction to the
present generation. The Deuteronomistic History, for example, presents history
as a perpetual struggle between good and evil. It turns on the careers of great
men, mostly the kings of Israel and Judah – some of them good, many more
instruments of evil. Only two are perfect: David and his late successor Josiah.
The psychological characterization is clear from the beginning: the character of
a person never changes and the original verdict is never ameliorated.24 A good
person may fail, as is the case of the great King David, but it does not change
his character. He is a just king and an obedient servant of the Lord in spite of
occasional human weaknesses. In opposition to him, we find his son Absalom
– a truly tragic hero in the Greek style and a person who cannot escape his
destiny. Never does Absalom change. He is forced by circumstances to oppose
his family when his sister is raped by his brother – the very situation that does
not allow for public revenge – but when pardoned by his father, he acts like the
condemned person he truly is and cannot change. Moving on, Solomon’s rash
son Rehoboam, like many other kings of Israel and Judah, cannot repent and
change; nor is it possible for Ahab and his queen to act as righteous people.
As a king acts, so does his nation. According to the biblical tradition, the
great men are symbols of their time and their choices are the choices of their
nation. When Ahab sins, it is Israel that sins and is punished because of its
transgressions. At the end of its moral decline after so many bad kings, Israel is
forsaken by the Lord and given over to the enemy. The fate of Judah is no better.
In spite of its just King Josiah, there is no hope left; he is only able to postpone
the inevitable. History is seen through the lens of the morality of its characters.
The course of fate is inevitable. To stress this point, biblical historiographers
use a number of rhetorical devices. Secondary figures make their appearance
in the form of prophets, who openly confront the monarchs and correct them
1990), who points to this similarity but uses the comparative material to make impossible
statements about the content of the biblical literature.
24. Except in Chronicles when Manasseh is said to change character after he has been
dragged into exile in Babylon (2 Chronicles 33). Like the post-exilic Jewish people,
Manasseh became a different and better person after his tribulations.
Good and bad in history 273
because of their transgressions. These prophets also inaugurate the future of the
nation by speeches, as does Samuel (1 Sam. 12) or Ahijah (1 Kgs 11), or they
foretell the destiny of kings, such as Micaiah, the son of Imla, who foresees the
death of the king of Israel in battle (1 Kgs 22:17). The historiographers also
introduce speeches for other occasions. Sometimes, such speeches are delivered
by an angel who foresees the future of Israel (Judg. 2). On other occasions,
characters in the plot, such as Joshua, address the leaders of Israel in a speech
(Josh. 23). The author may even speak directly to his readership, as when he
explains why Israel was destroyed (2 Kgs 17), or indirectly, as when he deliv-
ers his condemnation of the people in the form of a prophecy from Yahweh (2
Kgs 21). Such comments on the tragedy of Israel fulfil the role of a chorus in
the Greek tragedy.
The biblical historiographers’ understanding of history as a place of struggle
between good and evil employs the same ‘technique’ as classical authors use.
Had it been in the biblical historiographers’ interest, they could just as well
have presented the life and fate of their characters in pairs as Plutarch did in his
collection of great Greeks and Romans.25 It is obvious that biblical historians
are rhetorically trained as they make frequent use of speeches as the medium
to convey the meaning of history. They are, however, not Greeks. They trace
the cause of history back to the act of the God in a very direct fashion. It is
ultimately Yahweh who punishes Israel as a consequence of its sins. Although
all classical authors would see the divine as ultimate cause of historical events,
this aspect of history never played a vital role. It is, after all, difficult to blame
people – good or evil – if everything is decided in advance by divine agents.
The moral lesson to be learned from history is less persuasive if deities arranged
everything, without regarding human concerns and conditions.
This is not true of biblical historians. They see themselves as members of a
people chosen by God, in opposition to all other nations. They are the religious
elite, members of the new Israel, with whom God has created his new covenant
(Jer. 31:31). They are among the law-abiding few who, according to the proph-
ecies of Isaiah, are destined to survive and gather at Zion (Isa. 4). They are
certainly members of a religious congregation, if not a sectarian movement in
conflict – real or imagined – with the rest of the world. While Greek and Roman
historiographers focused on human beings as good or bad, whose personal fate
provided a lesson to other people, good and bad acts of human beings – kings
– brought disaster on ancient Israel. The lesson of biblical historiography is
not the difference between good and bad, but those who love God and those
forsaken by God because of their sins.
Al1 of this tells us that even though the biblical historians received an edu-
cation perhaps very similar to that of their Greek and Roman colleagues, they
remained Jewish sectarians. They were representatives of a minority group,
which established borders between itself and the outside world. They eventually
turned their Greek training against the Greeks themselves, when the Maccabees
25. Plutarch (c.46–120ce). His Lives belongs to the later part of his production.
274 Biblical studies and the failure of history
openly opposed the Hellenization of the Jewish nation. Greek rhetoric became
the medium of divine communication, but the message of biblical historiogra-
phers was very different from that of their classical colleagues.
I have presented a partial picture of authors who received an education in
many respects very different from that found in the ancient Near East. Their
education was, however, common in Greek and Roman academic institutions.
In spite of this, biblical authors were also people of the Orient. They were well
acquainted with oriental tradition – Palestinian, Mesopotamian and sometimes
Egyptian. They were able to integrate such traditions within their work in a
fashion that is vastly superior to the way in which it was done by Herodotus.
Herodotus was never able to incorporate his information from the Orient syn-
thetically. He considered the Near East exotic and exciting and an inexhaustible
source of anecdotes, but he was not able to integrate this tradition in his descrip-
tion of the reasons for the great clash of Greek and Oriental civilization.
The biblical historiographers’ incorporation of Near Eastern tradition in their
narratives made these traditions an organic part of the narratives themselves.
This becomes obvious from the very beginning of biblical narrative in Genesis
2–3. The oriental tradition was a part of the biblical historiographers themselves,
a mental matrix that was not erased by their training. The conclusion to this
observation seems logical: biblical historiographers were Hellenized Orientals.
18
Now in the fourteenth year of king Hezekiah did Sennacherib king of Assyria
come up against all the fenced cities of Judah, and took them. And Hezekiah
king of Judah sent to the king of Assyria to Lachish, saying, I have offended;
return from me: that which you puttest on me will I bear. And the king of
Assyria appointed unto Hezekiah king of Judah three hundred talents of silver
and thirty talents of gold. And Hezekiah gave him all the silver that was found
in the house of the Lord, and in the treasures of the king’s house. At that time
did Hezekiah cut off the gold from the doors of the temple of the Lord, and
from the pillars which Hezekiah king of Judah had overlaid, and gave it to the
king of Assyria. (2 Kgs 18:13-16, KJV)
1. More about this in my The Israelites in History and Tradition (Library of Ancient Israel;
Louisville, KY: Westminster/John Knox, 1998), 1–21 and 22–34.
276 Biblical studies and the failure of history
This story, which can be found in 2 Kings 18–19, opens with notes about
King Hezekiah’s reign, how he behaved well in the eyes of the Lord and
how he revolted against the Assyrians and smote the Philistines. The narra-
tive about King Hezekiah is broken off by a short interlude explaining how
King Shalmanasser of Assyria besieged and conquered the city of Samaria – an
event already mentioned in the preceding chapter. After this break, the narrative
continues with a description of Sennacherib’s attack on Hezekiah’s fortified
cities. While the Assyrian king rests at Lachish, King Hezekiah gives in and
surrenders to the Assyrians and pays a handsome tribute to mollify his overlord,
the king of Assur. After this tribute has been paid, the Assyrian king sends his
general to Jerusalem. Then there is the famous Rabshakeh incident, when the
Assyrian officer stands in front of the gates of Jerusalem and delivers a harsh
speech, with the intention of scaring the inhabitants of Jerusalem and its king
that they might surrender to the Assyrians. In great distress, Hezekiah turns to
the prophet Isaiah who promises divine assistance against the Assyrians. The
Assyrian general returns to his master with his army at Libnah in order to move
against an Egyptian army, which is attempting to outflank the Assyrian army.
Rabshakeh sends a letter to Hezekiah repeating many of the threats against
Judah already delivered in his speech in front of Jerusalem. When he receives
this letter, Hezekiah approaches the Lord for help against the Assyrians. As a
result, the avenging angel of the Lord kills 185,000 Assyrian soldiers during the
night, whereupon Sennacherib returns to Assyria in dismay, only to be murdered
some time later.
Even a casual reading of these chapters makes it clear that the narrative does
not constitute a homogenous description of the events of the fateful year 701bce.
The Rabshakeh incident is clearly superfluous as Hezekiah had already sur-
rendered and paid his tribute to the king of Assyria before Rabshakeh moved to
Jerusalem to deliver his speech. There was no reason for the Assyrian king not
to return home since he had already achieved his goal, stopping the rebellion in
south-western Palestine. In the text, however, we find a letter from Rabshakeh
to Hezekiah that includes the same themes as the speech, which provoked the
intervention of Isaiah and lead to God destroying the Assyrian army. It is as if
the author of this narrative presents his scenes in pairs. However, from a modern
historian’s point of view, it should be possible to distinguish between Droysen’s
Bericht and Überreste in 2 Kings 18–19. Such a historian would look for histori-
cal information primarily in the short description of Sennacherib’s campaign in
the opening chapters of the narrative rather than in the literarily elaborated pas-
sage which follows. Most would say that after paying the tribute, what remains
is Bericht (i.e. a reflection from a later date on the events of 701bce).
We actually possess another version of this campaign in Sennacherib’s royal
annalistic report of the campaign.2 In this version, the campaign opens with a
diversion to Phoenicia, to Sidon, to clear obstacles that might arise behind the
front lines and to safeguard a route of retreat. The Sidonian king flees before
2. ANET 3, 287–8.
On the problems of reconstructing pre-Hellenistic history 277
the Assyrians. The main aim of the campaign is, however, to settle matters in
Palestine, where the Judean Hezekiah (Sennacherib’s wording) has interfered
with loyal Assyrian vassals, including Padi, the king of Ekron, who is kept as a
prisoner by Hezekiah. Hezekiah and his allies had also approached the king of
Egypt and an Egyptian army had arrived and prepared for a battle at Elteqeh.
The Egyptian army, however, was no match for the Assyrians and Sennacherib
could, after having dismissed the threat from Egypt, continue to settle matters
along the coast of Palestine. He conquers the cities of Elteqeh and Timnah and
attacks and occupies Ekron. Hezekiah is persuaded to set Padi of Ekron free and
return him to his city, where he is reinstalled as an Assyrian vassal. Hezekiah
does not yield any further, and Sennacherib devastates his country, destroys
forty-six fortified cities and shuts Hezekiah in his city of Jerusalem, like a bird
in a cage. The devastated parts of Hezekiah’s kingdom are handed over to the
Philistine cities. Hezekiah gives up the hope of fighting the Assyrians and pays
a heavy tribute that is delivered to the Assyrian king in Nineveh.
There can be no doubt that the biblical narrative and Sennacherib’s annalis-
tic report are two reflections of the campaign of Sennacherib that ended when
Hezekiah gave in and paid the tribute which the Assyrians demanded – includ-
ing his daughters. There are many differences between the biblical and the
Assyrian version, but they also agree on several important points. Hezekiah
rebelled against the Assyrians. Sennacherib attacked his country and destroyed
many cities. At the end, Hezekiah paid a tribute, but Jerusalem remained in his
hands unharmed. The astonishing claim made by 2 Kings that the Assyrians did
not conquer Jerusalem is obviously a historical fact. Otherwise differences have
mostly to do with chronological details and numbers, such as when and where
Hezekiah sent his tribute (how large was this tribute?). These are minor points.
Basically the two accounts are in agreement.
When these two versions are compared it is obvious that the Rabshakeh
incident may have been invented by the author of 2 Kings in order to create
the impression that Sennacherib did not conquer Jerusalem because the holy
city was saved by its God.3 Rabshakeh’s actions follow the payment of the
tribute. The Assyrians had already closed the case on the rebellion. Although
this section includes one piece of historical information – the appearance of an
Egyptian army in Palestine – it is a safe guess to conclude that there is nothing
historical about the Rabshakeh incident. The biblical narrative that follows the
payment of the tribute is invented history or simply fiction.
This example is simple. Others are less obvious. The story about the cam-
paign of the kings of Israel and Judah against King Mesha of Moab in 2 Kings
3 opens with a note that Mesha had paid a heavy tribute to Israel and that he
had also revolted against his master after the death of Ahab. The king of Israel,
accordingly, invited his colleague in Jerusalem to join him in a war against
3. For a different look at the Rabshakeh incident as historical, cf. among others Brevard
S. Childs, Isaiah and the Assyrian Crisis (SBT SS, 3; London: SCM, 1967), 76–93, and
more recently Mordechai Cogan and Hayim Tadmor, II Kings. A New Translation with
Introduction and Commentary (AB, 11; Garden City, NY; Doubleday, 1988), 240–44.
278 Biblical studies and the failure of history
Moab with the king of Edom. This campaign opens with a seven-day march,
which, however, is halted for lack of water. The kings turn to a prophet for help,
and, on the prophet’s instructions, rites are performed and water made avail-
able by miracle. The prophet also delivers an oracle predicting the fall of all of
Moab. However, the battle between the Israelites and Moabites which follows
ends in disaster for the Moabites and Mesha retreats to his city of Kirhareseth.
After an unsuccessful breakout, Mesha sacrifices his son on the wall of the city,
‘and there was great indignation against Israel’ (King James Version), or bet-
ter: ‘there was such great consternation among the Israelites’ (Revised English
Bible) that the Israelites lifted the siege and returned home.
Is this a historical report? The central part of the story deals with a water
miracle and the Moabite misinterpretation of it, which brings disaster on their
head. Miracles are certainly out of focus in historical reports of events that
really happened and very impractical for historical analysis. From a historian’s
point of view, it never happened. Does this mean that this narrative is devoid
of historical information? Hardly, as we are in possession of two inscriptions,
which bear the name of Mesha, king of Moab. One of them is a short fragment,
the second is probably the most important royal inscription ever found in the
southern Levant.4
Mesha too had a story to tell in which he describes how Omri oppressed
Moab for forty years in all of his time and half of his son’s time. Mesha, how-
ever, attacked Israel and destroyed it forever. Most of the inscription is devoted
to a description of the cities retaken from Israel and their rearrangement by
Mesha, all of this made possible by Chemosh, Moab’s god. If we compare the
biblical story in 2 Kings 3 with this inscription, there is a slight measure they
have in common. Both texts explain how Mesha revolted against Israel and
reckon Mesha as king of Moab. Otherwise, it is hopeless to try to harmonize the
information in the biblical text with that provided by Mesha himself. Although
the biblical text perhaps includes one or two pieces of information that are his-
torical, it has little to do with Mesha’s text. Mesha has a different story to tell.
Mesha’s story may constitute a historical report, but that is far from certain. It
may be literature as much as the version in 2 Kings 3. Mesha is not telling the
truth. It is clear that his inscription, to a large degree, is also fictional propaganda
and includes such stereotypical elements from popular literature as a period of
oppression of forty years. Mesha makes a show of not knowing the name of any
king of Israel except Omri. He ‘forgets’ to mention Omri’s successor, Ahab –
after all, a very important king in his time, mentioned by the Assyrians – and
thereby makes Omri the oppressor of Moab also in his son’s time.
4. Cf. John C. L. Gibson, Textbook of Syrian Semitic Inscriptions, I: Hebrew and Moabite
Inscriptions (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1971), 71–84. For an extensive analysis of the
main text, cf. Andrew Dearman (ed) Studies in the Mesha Inscription and Moab (ASOR/
SBL Archaeology and Biblical Studies, 2; Atlanta, GA: Scholars Press, 1989). Although
the second inscription from Kerak is broken at the beginning where one might expect to
find Mesha’s name, the name of his father (kmšyt) has been so well preserved that it is
beyond doubt that this is a second inscription by Mesha king of Moab.
On the problems of reconstructing pre-Hellenistic history 279
5. For a recent review of this evidence, cf. my The Israelites in History and Tradition, 51–5.
6. Saxo, a monk in the service of the Bishop Absalon, the founder of Copenhagen, wrote
his Res gestae danorum towards the end of the twelfth century ce.
7. The reference dates to 845 ce when Regner’s army of Normans at the Seine was
destroyed by a plague. He may also be mentioned in other contemporary sources as one
of the main figures in the Danish process of conquering England in the second half of
the ninth century ce.
280 Biblical studies and the failure of history
other information than what is included in the text. If we do not possess external
evidence, it is the scholar who decides what is history and what fiction, for only
common sense is the guide. This is a systemic problem with historical-critical
studies.
Historical-critical scholarship operates within a hermeneutical circle that is
really a logical circle. The source of information is a biblical text, which stands
alone. Conversation moves between a scholar who studies the text and the text
itself. The scholar presents a theory, based on the text, and the text confirms
that theory. It is amazing that this has been acceptable for almost 200 years,
since the early days of modern scholarship at the beginning of the nineteenth
century. Nevertheless, every historical-critical scholar admits there is a problem
which has largely been ignored in writing history. The standard procedure is to
assert – according to Bernd Jørg Diebner – that although we cannot prove it,
it is a fact! We cannot prove that Moses ever existed but as we cannot explain
the development of Israelite monotheism without Moses, he must have existed.
Otherwise we would have to invent him … disregarding the possibility that
ancient writers had done exactly that! When in a bad mood, one may be will-
ing to say that historical-critical scholarship is a bluff. The procedure – locked
within the hermeneutical circle – is, from a scientific point of view, false. The
recognition of false procedures in science tells you that results obtained are false
and can be discarded without further ado. That historical-critical scholarship is
based on false methodology, leading to false conclusions, simply means that we
must disregard 200 years of biblical scholarship and commit it to the dustbin. It
is hardly worth the paper on which it is printed.
No warrant is gained by claiming that this is the only way we can draw his-
torical information from the Bible. That is merely a poor excuse for laziness. It
also reflects greediness: scholars want to say more than they can. Since the Bible
deals with religion and since most scholars have been and are still religious,
there is a constant pressure on biblical scholars to produce results, which concur
with those obtained in other fields, such as general history, and biblical scholars
have readily lived up to such expectations. In my dissertation on Early Israel
(1985), I presented a number of maxims, the first of which was that the most
important thing is to acknowledge your ignorance. The second added that when
you know the extent of your ignorance, you also have an idea about what you
know.8 Such maxims form a Procrustean bed on which to place various forms of
biblical studies. The demand is that we start our investigation by accepting that
we know almost nothing about the past and must begin with that little we know.
Some may object. Is it really true that we know so little about ancient Israel
that we cannot reconstruct its history and religion? The truth is that from the time
before the so-called ‘Hebrew Monarchy’, we possess a single external source
mentioning Israel. This is included among a host of vanquished foes in Palestine
in an Egyptian inscription dating to the time of Pharaoh Merenptah circa
9. ANET 3, 376–8.
10. Ibid., 279.
11. Avraham Biran and Joseph Naveh, ‘An Aramaic Stele Fragment from Tel Dan,’ IEJ 43
(1993), 81–98, and ‘The Tel Dan Inscription: A New Fragment,’ IEJ 45 (1995), 1–18. As
to this writer’s present position on the inscription, cf. his The Israelites in History and
Tradition, 38–43.
12. ANET 3, 282–4; cf. 2 Kgs 15:29-30.
13. Ibid., 563–4.
282 Biblical studies and the failure of history
To conclude this section, it is obvious that the history of Israel and Judah,
as related by biblical historians, is not entirely devoid of historical information.
The people who wrote the historical narratives of the Old Testament at least
knew some facts about Israelite and Judean history. We might even say that
there is a number of Überreste (i.e. historical remains) included in the texts of
the Old Testament. There might even be a coherency which binds such informa-
tion together and provides a chronological framework for the narrative.
This is rather unproblematic. Problematic is the task confronting us when we
try to decide what is Überreste and what Bericht, when reading of events which
are not comparable to external evidence. How do we avoid the hermeneutical
circle already described?
We could analyse ancient Near Eastern historiography, in general, to see
how it worked and how far it can be trusted. We could first establish the gen-
res of historiography in antiquity. Two dominate: the year-chronicle system,
which lists every year the most important events in a form of shorthand, and the
more extensive royal inscriptions, such as the Assyrian royal annals claiming
Assyrian world conquest.
Sometimes the authors of 1 and 2 Kings refer to the chronicles of Israel or
Judah.14 If we are to trust these notes as references to something that really
existed (we must never forget that it was not uncommon in literature from
ancient times to include fictitious references in order to create confidence), these
chronicles would most likely be of the shorthand type. Such annals included
only short references to past events. They would probably not have contained
extensive narrative, much less long reports. If we turn to the chronicles of
Assyrian and Babylonian kings, it might be possible to gain an impression of
what kind of information we should look for to reconstruct this source. Again,
we should not forget that the biblical author may have invented the reference
while writing in a chronistic style as suited his purpose.15
In regard to royal literature of the type found, for example, in Assyrian
inscriptions, it is much more difficult to establish the presence of similar sources
in the Old Testament. A large part of the Assyrian inscriptions contain war
reports. Although it cannot be excluded that such literature also existed in Israel
and Judah during the Iron Age, we cannot be certain on the basis of the books
of Kings that it did. It must be realized that as soon as we approach this genre,
we move into literature, into the world of fiction and invention. This is certainly
the case in regard to many Assyrian inscriptions where the acts of the king are
embellished and defeats hardly acknowledged. Such reports are always written
14. E.g., 2 Kgs 15:6, 11, 15, 21, 26, 31, 36.
15. Cf. on the possibility of information coming from royal Israelite and Judaean archives,
J. A. Montgomery, ‘Archival Data in the Books of Kings’, JBL 53 (1934), 46–52. The
question by Gösta W. Ahlström is, however, very relevant: ‘But where have these
archives been preserved so that the material could be used by later scribes or historiog-
raphers?’ (The History of Ancient Palestine from the Palaeolithic Period to Alexander’s
Conquest. With a contribution by Gary O. Rollefson. Edited by Diana Edelman, JSOT
supplement, 146; Sheffield: Sheffield Academic Press, 1993, 661 n. 9).
On the problems of reconstructing pre-Hellenistic history 283
with a purpose and are often composed to make an impression on the gods who
were to approve the acts of the king in question. Some might call it propaganda!
Although minor sections of Kings may have an annalistic background in
royal chronicles, most of the literature neither belongs to this genre nor to that
of the royal inscriptions of the Assyrian and Babylonian type. This is a natural
consequence of the aim and scope of the books of Kings, which are not written
in praise of kingship in Israel and Judah or to establish an exalted position for
kings. On the contrary, the impression gained from reading these biblical books
is the opposite: that their human kingdom represented a departure from the just
rule of God and that its human exponents were hardly heroes of Yahwistic faith.
Very few among the kings of Judah are praised for piety – all the kings of Israel
are condemned. Royal laudatory inscription is the wrong type of literature to
compare and is hardly implied by the narratives of Kings. Rather than trying
to trace non-existent historical events, we should study the topoi of the Kings.
It would be the goal of such an investigation to identify the patterns which
can be found. Several years ago, scholars realized that the books of Chronicles
are dominated by a series of stereotypical topoi – each of them with a special
purpose, either to recommend a king loved by God or to reject one as godfor-
saken.16 The very character of the narrative in 1 and 2 Kings speaks against
extensive use of royal inscriptions. The authors used some extant annalistic
information, but merely selected what suited their purpose. Their selection was
dominated by the wish to create a negative impression of the period.
When a modern author writes historical fiction – for example, books such
as Robert Graves’s I Claudius – we do not expect such a writer to be faithful
to history. We allow such an author liberty to reformulate history in such a way
that it supports the author’s intention to make history conform to his fictive
goals. Although we may be in possession of an interpretation of the past by pro-
fessional historians, we enjoy and appreciate historical fiction. This, however,
is quite extraordinary and contrary to the expressed beliefs of many scholars.
Furthermore, people today can be more interested in literature than in history.
Hollywood would have gone bankrupt long since without such an ability to
disregard historical facts.
If we – having studied history in a scientific way for 200 years – do not
always think that historical exactitude is a virtue that cannot be counterbalanced
by morally acceptable fiction, what about people of ancient times who never
shared such a sense of history? Would they have paid attention to the historical
correctness of a narrative about the past or would they have placed emphasis on
aesthetic and moral values? The answer is not provided by ancient Near Eastern
literature – we know very little about the reception of this literature among
ordinary people – but by the discussions of classical intellectuals on the value
of history. Cicero’s famous characterization of history as the ‘teacher of life’ is
important: on the basis of Hellenistic philosophy, Cicero regards history not as
16. Cf. the interesting study by Peter Welten, Geschichte und Geschichtsdarstellung in den
Chronikbüchern (WMANT, 42; Neukirchen: Neukirchener Verlag, 1973).
284 Biblical studies and the failure of history
a literary genre dealing with the past, but as a genre that uses the past to educate
present and future generations.17
We should not limit our interest in Kings to a search for historical informa-
tion. Such may only be present in short notes. We should pay attention to the
purpose of this literature because it is a safe guess that this literature was com-
posed to impress the present rather than save recollections of the past for their
own sake. It is a long story, which exceeds the limits of a short article.18 It is my
thesis that the authors of ancient literature of the type that is found in the Old
Testament did not care much about the historical exactitude of descriptions of
the past. The past was not interesting, except for its examples of good and bad
behaviour which might be provided for the present and future. The past was
interesting because it explained the present – even sometimes made present
arrangements seem legitimate or natural. Otherwise, let the dead bury the dead!
This is one side of the coin. The other has to do with the claim that we
should not expect ancient historical narrative to be precise about the past or
even related to it except in a superficial way. How can I prove my case? The
easy solution to this problem is to say that it is sometimes possible to point at
passages where the authors of Kings directly say that they are not interested in
history. The previously mentioned references to the chronicles of the kings of
Israel and Judah actually tell us this. Thus, King Omri is done away with in a
few verses in 1 Kings 16. We are informed that he assumed power by a coup
d’état and that he ruled Israel for twelve years and built Samaria. After this the
focus changes and we hear about his sins against Yahweh. The author of 1 Kings
16, however, knows that Omri was a great king, but advises his reader to go
and look for himself in the chronicles of the kings of Israel (1 Kgs 16:27)! The
biblical historiographer has no intention of providing his reader with a report
of Omri’s reign, although he accepts the idea that Omri was a great king. After
all, after his death his kingdom carried his name for more than 100 years, a fact
which is immaterial from the perspective of the ancient history writer. Omri’s
greatness is not denied; it is silenced.
A more complicated way to solve the problem presented will be to establish
whether or not the history of ancient Israel, as narrated by biblical writers, is
precise in any comprehensive way. It can be split into several succeeding peri-
ods: the period of the patriarchs, of the Exodus, of the Israelites travelling in the
desert for forty years, of the conquest of Canaan, of the hero-judges of Israel,
of the national greatness under David and Solomon, of ever-impending disaster
under the kings of Israel and Judah, etc. Has this anything to do with the real
past of this geographical region, otherwise known as the southern Levant or
Palestine? I have no intention of reviewing this history in detail now. I have
already presented such in several publications.19 Other scholars have contrib-
uted as well. The history of Israel as told by the Old Testament begins with the
patriarchal age. It continues with the sojourn in Egypt, followed by the Exodus
and the wanderings in the desert. It then follows, successively, the conquest of
Canaan, the Period of the Judges, the empire of David and Solomon, the era
of the Hebrew kings, the exile and the Persian period. This history ends with
Ezra’s promulgation of the Torah, the Law of Moses, in front of the assembled
inhabitants of Jerusalem and Judah.
1999 represents the silver anniversary of the final settlement – represented by
the contributions by Thomas L. Thompson and John Van Seters – with the idea
that there ever was a patriarchal period.20 This is based on family stories, sagas
and legends about the past, and has nothing to do with history. The idea once
formulated by Albrecht Alt that there was a special patriarchal religion based
on the belief in der Gott der Väter, ‘the God of the fathers’, is simply nonsense
as Alt based his argument on Nabataean evidence from the second century bce
through the second century ce.21
A long time ago, the Exodus passed from history into fiction. It never hap-
pened. Neither did the conquest. Several biblical scholars, including myself,
have made this clear. From a historical point of view, Israelites could not have
conquered Canaan by destroying Canaanite forces for the simple reason that
Egyptians still ruled Canaan when Joshua is supposed to have arrived (i.e.
shortly before 1200bce).22 Second, there is no trace of foreign immigration and,
third, even the biblical account about the conquest is contradictory (compare
Josh. to Judg. 1).
In my original monograph on the Period of the Judges, which appeared
some thirty years ago, I argued that the narratives in Judges about the heroic
exploits of the Israelite judges were coloured by later experience.23 They were
also dominated by the wish to demonstrate how Israel should fight its enemies
– Canaanites, Moabites, Ammonites, Philistines, Arameans, etc. – in a paradig-
matic way. These narratives do not allow us to reconstruct the history of the
period between a non-existent conquest and a likewise non-existent empire of
David and Solomon. The stories about the judges of Israel belong among the
genre of heroic tales that most civilizations include among their memories of
the past.
The empire of David and Solomon, believed to have existed in the tenth
century bce, is apparently based on a fictional representation of the past. Many
20. Cf. Thomas L. Thompson, The Historicity of the Patriarchal Narratives: The Quest for
the Historical Abraham (BZAW 133; Berlin: De Gruyter, 1974), and John Van Seters,
Abraham in History and Tradition (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1975).
21. Albrecht Alt, Der Gott der Väter. Ein Beitrag zur Vorgeschichte der israelitischen
Religion (BWANT 48; Stuttgart: Kohlhammer, 1929; English translation by R. A.
Wilson, ‘The God of the Fathers’, in Albrecht Alt, Essays on Old Testament History and
Religion, The Biblical Seminar, Sheffield: JSOT, 1989, 1–77).
22. For a recent evaluation of the duration of the Egyptian empire in Asia, cf. Donald B.
Redford, Egypt, Canaan, and Israel in Ancient Times (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Press, 1992), 283–97. Redford dates the Egyptian withdrawal to circa 1150bce.
23. Israel i dommertiden: En oversigt over diskussionen om Martin Noths ‘Das System der
zwölf Stämme Israels’ (Tekst og Tolkning 4; Copenhagen: CEG Gad, 1972), 86–7.
286 Biblical studies and the failure of history
things speak in favour of this conclusion. One of them has to do with the status
of Jerusalem in the tenth century bce when Jerusalem was at most a village or
small town.24
We have already discussed the period of the Hebrew kings. Although the two
kingdoms of Israel and Judah are historical facts, we are in possession of very
little in the way of solid knowledge about them. Furthermore, when reviewing
the evidence we have in the Old Testament and other sources, it is evident that
the Old Testament has distorted our view of ancient Palestinian history. This
was far more complicated and included many more actors than merely these
two kingdoms. The Old Testament never explains why or how this territory got
the name Palestine (‘the land of the Philistines’). Foreigners, including Assyrian
authors of royal annals and Herodotus, knew the name Palestine. Herodotus
simply states that Palestine is the part of Syria that is situated between Lebanon
and Egypt.25
There is hardly time to discuss the historicity of the exile, which might not
have been as important as described by the Old Testament. Recent investiga-
tions have shown that the ‘land of Israel’ was not deserted in the time of the
exile and that it only affected very few among the population of Palestine. There
was no ‘empty land’ as postulated by the biblical books of Chronicles and other
biblical literature.26
The Persian period is, finally, a dark spot on the historical map of Palestine.
We know almost nothing about this period. Ezra, the great hero of post-exilic
Judaism, is probably a late invention (by Pharisaic authors?), probably 200
years old when he arrived (his father was killed by Nebuchadnezzar’s general,
Nebuzaradan, in 587bce – according to the biblical evidence).27
24. I have no intention to go into a detailed discussion about the historicity or non-historicity
of David and Solomon. The idea of a united monarchy of Israel/Judah died as terminol-
ogy changed. Now, it is preferable to see the period from circa 1250 to circa 900 as one
long intermediary period, a ‘transitionary period’, and the way to approach this period
has been demonstrated by, for example, Israel Finkelstein, ‘The Emergence of Israel:
A Phase in the Cyclic History of Canaan in the Third and Second Millennia bce,’ in I.
Finkelstein and N. Na’aman (eds) From Nomadism to Monarchy: Archaeological and
Historical Aspects of Early Israel (Jerusalem: Israel Exploration Society, 1994), 150–78,
and Shlomo Bunimowitz, ‘Socio-Political Transformations in the Central Hill Country
in the Late Bronze-Iron I Transition,’ in Finkelstein and Na’aman (eds) From Nomadism
to Monarchy, 179–203.
25. Cf. Herodotus, The Histories, I, 105; II, 104; III, 5.91; IV, 39; VII, 89.
26. Cf. Hans M. Barstad, The Myth of the Empty Land: A Study in the History and Archae
ology of Judah During the ‘Exilic’ Period (Oslo: Scandinavian University Press, 1996).
See, however, also Ehud Ben Zvi, ‘Inclusion in and Exclusion from Israel as Conveyed
by the Use of the Term “Israel” in Post-Monarchic Biblical Texts’, in S. W. Holloway
and L. K. Handy (eds) The Pitcher is Broken. Memorial Essays for Gösta W. Ahlström
(JSOT supplement, 190; Sheffield: Sheffield Academic Press, 1995), 95–149, and the
discussion in Lester L. Grabbe (ed.) Leading Captivity Captive: The ‘Exile’ as History
and Ideology (JSOT supplement, 278; Sheffield: Sheffield Academic Press, 1998).
27. Cf. Ezra’s pedigree, Ezra 7:1: Ezra, son of Seraiah, son of Azariah, son of Hilkiah, son of
Shallum, etc. On Seraiah’s death, cf. 2 Kgs 25:18. Hilkiah was high priest in the days of
On the problems of reconstructing pre-Hellenistic history 287
Josiah, 2 Kgs 22:4. Of course, many scholars will maintain that the genealogy is either
false or telescoped.
288 Biblical studies and the failure of history
Acknowledgements
28. Cf. the short discussion by Patrick E. McGovern, ‘Beth-Shean’, ABD I, 694–5. The Late
Bronze Age phase of occupation continued to about 1000bce. Only after that date does
a new stratum reveal different layouts and culture. The city was hardly Philistine (the
author of 1 Sam. 31 got it totally wrong); only a single piece of Philistine pottery has
been found at the tell (McGovern, ‘Beth-Sheen’).
29. See Chapter 14, this volume.
19
In the good old days – not so long ago – a biblical text was usually dated by its
historical referent. A text that seemed to include historical information might
well belong to the age when this historical referent was likely to have existed.
This was the general attitude. The referent was the decisive factor. If the infor-
mation included in the referent was considered precise or at least likely, the text
that provided this information was considered more or less contemporary with
the event – that is, the historical referent, though the only source for such an
event, was often the text in question. Everyone spoke of a ‘hermeneutical circle’
and it was generally accepted that the study of ancient Israel was based logically
on a circullus logicus vitiosum. Nobody within biblical studies believed that it
was possible to avoid this logical fallacy. A classical example of such ‘method-
ology’ – or lack of methodology – relates to studies dealing with the last years
of Judah’s history. It has become common to argue that the united monarchy
of David and Solomon never existed. It is also accepted, in regard to the early
days of the independent kingdoms of Israel and Judah, that most information
in the books of Kings is legendary. Nevertheless, when it comes to the closure
of the history of Judah, scholars consider large sections of the Deuteronomistic
History to include vital historical information about Judah in the seventh and
early sixth centuries bce. The reform of King Josiah is still generally assumed to
have taken place in 623/622bce, much as described in 2 Kings. That Chronicles
has a different story of this reform does not worry scholars who too readily
accept the version presented in 2 Kings. Chronicles has King Hezekiah and not
Josiah as the great reformer (2 Chron. 29–31). Although it knows the story of
Josiah’s reform (2 Chron. 34–35), it is Hezekiah and not Josiah who reinstates
the Passover as it had been in the days of old. Apparently, even if the author of
Chronicles had borrowed from the Deuteronomistic History, he did not accept
that view of the past, demonstrating greater independence than many schol-
ars of the present have shown, who simply paraphrase 2 Kings, disregarding
Chronicles’ caveat.
It is obvious that ancient historiographers handled so-called historical nar-
rative in different ways. Sometimes, they elaborated upon a text, describing
a well-known historical event, such as Sennacherib’s attack on Hezekiah in
701bce. The biblical historiographers include a short note with a series of ‘facts’
290 Biblical studies and the failure of history
relating to Sennacherib’s campaign (2 Kgs 18:13-16). This note might well have
been found in an archive.1 It is, however, more than likely that the biblical his-
toriographers used it as a jumping-off point for an elaborate invented story of
the liberation of Jerusalem from the mighty Assyrians (2 Kgs 18:17–19:37).2 At
other times, these historiographers found historical information about the past
within their own tradition, but were not able to localize it historically.3 They
were also able to create ‘history’ nearly from scratch.4 Altogether, it is clear that
biblical historiographers did not share the modern idea of history as a scholarly
discipline.5 They rather fit a tradition of the past to the version of the history of
Israel they offered their audience, sharing in a common tradition of historiogra-
phers in the ancient world.6 The past was not something that merely happened
and thereafter forgotten. It was part of a living tradition, brought to life again
and again whenever an ancient author called on the past to illustrate the present.
Because of such standards for dealing with the past, it is unlikely that we can
date a biblical narrative by its historical referent. It is obvious that historical
truth was not a criterion employed by historiographers of the ancient world who
constructed a past in this way.7 They evidently had a programme, and narrative
1. Compare this note in 2 Kings with the version presented by Sennacherib (ANET, 287–8).
Although the two versions are not identical or in total agreement concerning the course
of events, they include much the same information.
2. Cf., further, my ‘Om historisk erindring i Det Gamle Testamentes historiefortællinger’
(‘On Historical Remains in the Historical Narratives of the Old Testament’), in
G. Hallbäck and J. Strange (eds) Bibel og Historieskrivning (Forum for Bibelsk
Eksegese, 10; Copenhagen: Museum Tusculanum, 1999), 11–28 (20–24).
3. Examples of this are the anachronistic note about Pithom and Ramses in Exod. 1:11, the
settlement of the Benjaminites and the Kingdom of David; cf. Chapter 10, this volume.
4. In Lemche, ‘Om historisk erindring’, 24–6. The example that illustrates this is 2 Kings
3: the legendary story of an Israelite and Judaean campaign against Moab. The only
historical element could well be Mesha, the name of the king of Moab.
5. It is a revealing fact that Greek ῾ιστορία (from the verb ῾ιστορέω, ‘to enquire’) primarily
means ‘enquiry’, and comes closest to ‘history’ in our sense when it is used in regard
to reports of enquiries (cf. Liddell and Scott, Greek–English Lexicon, 9th edn; Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 1925, 842). Herodotus opens his report in this way: ῾Ηροδότου
῾Αλιχαρνησσέος ῾ιστορίης α᾽ πόδεξις η῾΄δε, ω῾ ς μήτε τὰ γεγόμενα ε’ ξ α᾽ νθρώπων τω ι̃ χρόνω
ε’ ξίτηλα γένηται, μήτε ε’΄ργα μεγάλα τε καὶ θωμαστά, τὰ μὲν ῾Ελλησι, τὰ δὲ βαρβάροισι
α᾽ ποδεχθέντα, ακλεα̃ γένηται, τὰ τε α᾽΄λλα καὶ δι᾽ η῾΄ν αι᾽τίην ε’ πολέμησαν α᾽ λλη΄λοισι (‘The
enquiries of Herodotus from Halicarnassos presented here, in order that what people
have done should not vanish with time, or that the great and wonderful deeds of the
Greeks and the Barbarians should not fall into oblivion, but also why they engaged in
a war among them’; Herodotus, Book 1, the opening). He does not present himself as a
scholar so much as a journalist.
6. Cf. further, with reference to the similarity to Greek and Roman historiography, Chapter
17, this volume. On the whole process of creating the past, cf. Thomas L. Thompson,
The Bible in History: How Writers Create a Past (London: Jonathan Cape, 1999).
7. Whereas Greek and Roman authors have been well served by modern students of
ancient literature, the historiography of the ancient Near East has not evoked the same
kind of interest. For a recent overview, cf. John Van Seters, ‘The Historiography of the
Ancient Near East’, in J. M. Sasson (ed.) Civilizations of the Ancient Near East, IV
How does one date an expression of mental history? 291
was the medium selected to present their case. Specific ideas and sentiments,
religious convictions, as well as ideas about the nation and people of Israel
directed their thinking.8 We may call it propaganda or educational literature as
we wish. The aim of such literature was not only to entertain their contemporar-
ies, but also, and more importantly, to impress the next generation.9
Political ideas and religious sentiments come together to form the ‘mental
matrix’ of a person, governing the expressions of all writers – ancient as well as
modern. Moreover, biblical historiographers carried within themselves mental
matrices that were decisive when they chose what to include and what to leave
out in retelling the past. The student of such literature should investigate whether
or not it is possible to reconstruct such mental matrices. Were they governed by
ideas that originated in ancient Palestine, Mesopotamia or Egypt, or had Greek
philosophy already influenced them to such a degree that knowledge of Greek
(Hellenistic) civilization is apparent? What did biblical historiographers know?
They were governed by an antiquarian interest, which they share with modern
colleagues, the historians of the present. However, this is a superficial similarity
that merely implies that ancient historiographers wanted to attribute to their own
time the meaning of the past.
To understand such interest in the past, it must be stressed that ancient
societies were very conservative – if not reactionary. This is nowhere better
reflected than in the tale of the ages of the world of an original ‘golden age’
supplanted by a less prosperous ‘silver age’, which, for its part, was supplanted
by a ferocious ‘brazen age’.10 Everything in the beginning was perfect: ‘And
God saw everything that he had made and, behold, it was very good’ (Gen.
1:31). Innovation was carried out to re-establish an original world order. This
was the ideology behind, for example, the mišarum acts of old Babylonia, when
debts were abolished and property handed back to an original owner.11 Ancient
(New York: Simon & Schuster, 1995), 2433–44, but also John Van Seters, In Search of
History: Historiography in the Ancient World and the Origins of Biblical History (New
Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1983) and, finally, the discussion in John Van Seters,
Prologue to History: The Yahwist as Historian in Genesis (Louisville, KY: Westminster/
John Knox Press, 1992), chapter 2, ‘Myth and Tradition in Ancient Historiography’,
24–44.
8. Cf. also on this my The Israelites in History and Tradition (Library of Ancient Israel;
Louisville, KY: Westminster/John Knox Press, 1998), especially chapter 4, ‘The People
of God: The Two Israels in the Old Testament’, 86–132.
9. Cicero’s characterization of history, in his De oratore, 2.9.36, Historia vero testis tempo-
rum, lux veritatis, vita memoriae, magistra vitae, nuntia vetustatis … (‘History [is] truly
the witness about the ages, the light of truth, the life of memories, the teacher of life, and
the messenger of ancient times …’), should never be left out of consideration when we
evaluate ancient historiography. Cf. further on this Chapter 17, this volume.
10. Cf. Hesiod, Works and Days, 110–55, and Ovid, Metamorphoses, I. 90–162.
11. The classical studies on these decrees are F. R. Kraus, Ein Edikt des Königs Ammi-
úaduqa von Babylon (SDOAP 5; Leiden: E. J. Brill, 1958) and F. R. Kraus, Königliche
Verfügungen in altbabylonischen Zeit (Studia et documenta ad iura orientis ad iura
antiqui pertinentia 11; Leiden: E .J. Brill, 1984).
292 Biblical studies and the failure of history
12. Which has little to do with modern ideas of history as the reconstruction of the past for
its own sake – wie es eigentlich gewesen, as expressed by Leopold von Ranke. Cf. also
the ‘Prolegomena’ to my The Israelites in History and Tradition, 1–8.
13. I found this wonderful line some years ago in a Danish newspaper in a review of a book
about the Icelandic sagas. I have forgotten both the author of this line and the exact
place where it was originally printed. It does, however, express in a most precise way
the difference between pre-modern and modern ideas of history.
14. This is definitely a subject that could be expanded upon. The ‘meaning of history’ has
nothing to do with modern concepts such as ‘la longue durée’ of Les annales school
which says that certain conditions are likely to produce certain developments over time
(e.g. that in a certain geographical area the natural geography is likely to promote specific
historical processes). ‘La longue durée’ promotes a kind of historical determinism that
could, at best, be termed ‘quantitative’. The meaning of the ‘great deeds of the past’ was,
in antiquity, rather qualitative.
How does one date an expression of mental history? 293
‘structural similarities’.15 Scholars have pointed out the many such parallels as
evidence of a physical relationship between Essenes (supposed to be the authors
of the Dead Sea Scrolls) and early Christians.16 In the same way, other scholars
have stressed the divergences between the New Testament and the scrolls from
Qumran. Although it is a fact that the New Testament and the Dead Sea Scrolls
are related in one way or another – both groups of texts belong to approximately
the same age – it would be wrong to maintain that the authors of the Dead
Sea Scrolls were Christians. However, the similarity between the two bodies of
literature remains, though it should not be understood to establish an identity
between early Christians and Essenes. The similarity has to do with the issues
raised by both the Dead Sea Scrolls and the New Testament.
Every period has special questions and topics of discussion. An overview of
scholarship within Old Testament studies during the twentieth century makes
this not only obvious, it is a truism. Around the turn of the nineteenth century,
the ‘Babel–Bible’ controversy was at the centre of scholarly (and public) inter-
est, following the discovery of the ancient civilizations of Mesopotamia.17 This
controversy died before the outbreak of World War I. All studies which centre
on this discussion can, accordingly, be dated safely to the period between the
decipherment of Akkadian cuneiform in the nineteenth century and 1914. After
that date, it has been largely irrelevant, though scholars of this period had not
resolved the controversy.
The amphictyony became a major subject after the publication in 1930 of
Martin Noth’s study of Israelite society in the Period of the Judges.18 For the
next forty years this hypothesis dominated every single study on pre-monarchic
Israel. Although most scholars adopted the hypothesis as their own, a few
important divergent voices were heard. However, even scholars who rejected
the amphictyony had to address the question of such a tribal organization, if
what they wrote was to be considered seriously.19 For the last two decades there
has been almost total silence regarding an amphictyony after a series of studies
15. Cf. Niels Hyldahl, ‘Qumran og den ældste kristendom: En kort introduktion og problem-
orientering’, in N. Hyldahl and T. L. Thompson (eds), Dødehavsteksterne og Bibelen
(Forum for Bibelsk Eksegese 8; Copenhagen: Museum Tusculanum, 1996), 9–16.
16. This is certainly not the place to get involved in the current discussion about the origin
of the library found at Qumran. I have a certain preference for the theory of a library
with mixed content, probably from Jerusalem and stored away in the Judaean Desert, by,
perhaps, 63bce. This theory requires a new dating of the scrolls to show that they belong
to the first century bce rather than the first century ce.
17. A recent overview of this discussion can be found in Mogens Trolle Larsen, ‘The Bable/
Bible Controversy and its Aftermath’, in J. M Sasson (ed.) Civilizations of the Ancient
Near East, I (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1995), 95–106.
18. Martin Noth, Das System der zwölf Stämme Israels (BWANT 4.1; Stuttgart: W.
Kohlhammer, 1930).
19. Among the scholars who never accepted the hypothesis about the amphictyony, we may
mention two important names: Otto Eissfeldt and Georg Fohrer. On the criticism of the
amphictyony, cf. my Israel i Dommertiden: En oversigt over diskussionen om Martin
Noths ‘Das System der zwölf Stämme Israels’ (Tekst og Tolkning 4; Copenhagen: G. E.
C. Gad, 1972), 31–8.
294 Biblical studies and the failure of history
had appeared during the early 1970s, removing the historical foundation for
its existence. In 1984, I was able to conclude the discussion in this way: ‘The
hypothesis of the amphictyony by now is irrelevant to the investigations into
Israel’s past history.’20
Between 1954 and 1970, as a consequence of the publication of George
Mendenhall’s articles about the relationship between the Sinai covenant and
Hittite vassal treaties from the Late Bronze Age, Old Testament scholars
invested a great deal of interest in covenant theology.21 For a decade and a half,
everything had centred on the covenant that was supposed to appear here, there
and everywhere in the Old Testament. After 1969, when Lothar Perlitt merely
announced that covenant theology was invented by a circle of Deuteronomistic
theologians towards the end of the independent Israelite and Judean history,
nobody continued the subject, which went into oblivion as if it had never
existed.22
These are only rather insignificant examples from a minor field within the
academic world. However, they illustrate how every period will give birth to
a number of questions – within philosophy, religion or politics – that bear a
specific context within this period, hot subjects for a while, but soon forgotten.
The same was true in ancient times, although, because of limited communica-
tion, the stream of ever-changing ideas did not flow as fast as it does today.
Every era included issues, which specifically related to the period and became
subjects of lively discussion among that period’s intellectuals. We should not
be surprised when two corpora of texts, belonging to the same period, display
many similarities and yet are as different as texts of the New Testament and the
Dead Sea Scrolls. The New Testament and the Dead Sea Scrolls need not agree
simply because they are more or less from the same period. It is an old scholarly
hoax that people belonging to one and the same period should agree on any-
thing and everything. To the contrary, in a society of the real world, there are
always nearly as many opinions as people to discuss them. It is not the variety
of opinions but the number of issues that is limited. Niels Hyldahl, accordingly,
does not speak about individual points of contact but about a systemic kind of
relationship: similar questions, but different answers.
Since the beginning of academic discussion, it has been a favourite pastime
of scholars to indulge in comparative studies. I will not elaborate upon this
theme here. I only refer the reader to James G. Frazer’s The Golden Bough
as a famous, but also contested, example.23 It is too easy to find similarities
20. Cf. my ‘Israel in the Period of the Judges: The Tribal League in Recent Discussion’, ST
38 (1984), 1–28; cf. also Georg Fohrer, ‘Methoden und Moden in der alttestamentlichen
Wissenschaft’, ZAW 100 Supplement (1988), 243–54 (244–8).
21. Cf. George E. Mendenhall, ‘Covenant Forms in Israelite Tradition’, BA 17 (1954),
50–76.
22. Lothar Perlitt, Bundestheologie im Alten Testament (WMANT 36; Neukirchen-Vluyn:
Neukirchener Verlag, 1969).
23. James G. Frazer, The Golden Bough: A Study in Magic and Religion (New York: St
Martin’s Press, 1990 [1890]).
How does one date an expression of mental history? 295
between literary expressions of different cultures when they belong to the same
stage of development, particularly when we talk about relatively simple socie-
ties with more or less uniform socio-economic systems, such as subsistence
agriculture. In such agrarian cultures, peasants all over the world share ideas
without ever having been in mutual contact. The details are, in themselves, an
interesting scholarly issue and can – when collected – result in something like
Stith Thompson’s index of folk-motifs of fairy tales and legendary stories, origi-
nating mostly in oral environments and, at times, elaborated upon in writing.24
When, however, cultures are more complicated and diversification of occu-
pation in an old Durkheimian25 fashion creates separation within one and the
same society, cultural expressions also become more elaborate and sophisti-
cated. In this case, a systemic similarity as the one discussed above more likely
reflects political and especially cultural interchange between interrelated cul-
tural zones, such as Mesopotamia, Western Syria and the Levant in the Bronze
Age, or Mesopotamia and Egypt already before the dawn of history. The famous
saying that Graecia capta ferum victorem cepit, ‘conquered Greece conquered
its barbaric conqueror’,26 states succinctly that Romans became Hellenized
when they entered into contact with Greece and were overwhelmed by its supe-
rior civilization and cultural tradition.
The moment we approach the problem of dating an Old Testament text – not
to say the Old Testament itself – we are confronted with the literary remains of
a culturally very rich civilization. Primitive literature is not found in the Old
Testament. Every part of the collection included in the Old Testament displays
a sophistication that brings us far beyond the cultural borders of an undevel-
oped and basically agrarian society. The primary history (Genesis to 2 Kings)
is a fine example of this and need not be discussed in this context.27 Of more
interest in this connection are the patriarchal narratives. Although these sto-
ries include many motifs from folk literature and reflect popular stories, they
are much too complicated to have originated within a milieu that was almost
exclusively oral – Gunkel’s notorious campfire society – or one which had just
changed from an oral to a written stage of transmission. I will not reiterate the
ideas of André Jolles that oral literature is necessarily simple and devoid of
28. Cf. André Jolles, Einfache Formen, Legende, Sage, Mythe, Rätsel, Spruch, Kasus,
Memorabile, Märchen, Witz (Tübingen: Max Niemeyer, 1974 [1930]).
29. Milman Parry and Albert B. Lord, Serbo-Croatian Heroic Songs Collected by Milman
Parry (Publications of the Milman Parry Collection; Text and Translation Series, 1–2, 4,
12; Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1953–86).
30. This means that Abraham was old before he became wise, and probably never got it
right – until the very moment when he was about to sacrifice his son, his hope for the
future and the essence of Yahweh’s promise to him.
31. Although it cannot be ignored that part of this literature, such as the story of ‘Sinuhe’
or the ‘tale of the two brothers’ that was preserved also at a much later date may have
influenced biblical authors.
32. Cf. K. Lawson Younger, Jr, Ancient Conquest Accounts: A Study in Ancient Near Eastern
and Biblical History Writing (JSOT supplement, 98; Sheffield: JSOT Press, 1990), who
mixes an acceptable form-critical analysis with impossible historical conclusions.
33. Cf. the examples of Assyrian annals written on both sides of stone slabs, also on the side
of the stone that turned inside and could not be read by anyone except the gods. Other
examples are the many Assyrian stones buried in the foundations of temples which com-
memorated the mighty deeds of the king who built them.
How does one date an expression of mental history? 297
keep these remarks in mind when we want to describe the mental matrices of
these authors.
In his In Search of ‘Ancient Israel’, Philip R. Davies distinguishes between
three different kinds of ‘Israel’. One is ‘historical Israel’ – that is, the state other-
wise known from Assyrian sources as Bît Humriya or Samarina. This Palestinian
state came into being sometime in the �ninth century bce and was destroyed
by the Assyrians in 722bce. Historical Israel did not include the Palestinian
petty state called Judah, which only appeared on the historical scene as a state
sometime after 800bce and was in existence as a semi-autonomous political
entity until 597 or 587bce.34 The second Israel is ‘biblical Israel’, the creation
of the authors of the Old Testament, and can only partly be related to historical
Israel. Third, modern scholars created still another Israel, the so-called ‘ancient
Israel’. This Israel represents a curious mixture of biblical Israel and historical
Israel.35 Although I have always respected the Dumézilian theory regarding the
importance of the number three in Indo-European tradition, Davies’s theory of
three different ‘Israels’ is one short of being correct. There are not one, but two
biblical ‘Israels’. In my recent study The Israelites in History and Tradition, a
comprehensive section has ‘The People of God’ as its subject.36 ‘The People of
God’ includes the concept of the Israelite nation created by the authors of the
Old Testament prose narratives from Genesis to 2 Kings. It is my argument that
there is more than one biblical Israel in the Old Testament; there are, indeed,
two ‘Israels’ here. One of them is ‘old Israel’, understood as the people of the
covenant written in stone (cf. the Sinai-complex but also Josh. 24); the second is
the ‘new Israel’, the people of the covenant written in the heart (Jer. 31:31-34).
According to the Old Testament, the Babylonian exile constitutes the divi-
sion between old and new Israel. Old Israel is destroyed and its people banished
because they rejected their God and broke the covenant. The new Israel is the
Israel which is supposed to arise in the future: the true people of God. It has been
identified variously with Judaism and the Christian church (cf. Rom. 9–11). Any
sectarian group within Judaism or Christianity can be expected to refer to itself
as the true ‘new Israel’.
It is often argued that the same nation, which the Babylonians forced into
exile, returned to Palestine during the Persian period. It is, however, still an
unsolved question whether there was, in fact, a return of the dimension envis-
aged by the Old Testament – namely, a significant movement of people from one
34. I do not wish to reopen the discussion about the origins of these states in this essay. The
important study by David W. Jamieson-Drake, Scribes and Schools in Monarchic Judah;
A Socio-Archaeological Approach (JSOT supplement, 109; The Social World of Biblical
Antiquity, 9; Sheffield: Almond Press, 1991) that argues in favour of these dates has
been the subject of much criticism. It should, however, be noticed that Israel Finkelstein
supports such dates, cf. his ‘The Beginning of the State in Israel and Judah’, Eretz-Israel
26 (1999), 132–41 (Hebrew, 134; English résumé, 233).
35. Cf. Philip R. Davies, In Search of ‘Ancient Israel’ (JSOT supplement, 148; Sheffield:
JSOT Press, 1992).
36. Lemche, The Israelites in History and Tradition, 86–132.
298 Biblical studies and the failure of history
part of the Middle East to another.37 I will maintain that the ‘exile’ in Babylonia
never ended, and that the presence there of exiled people from Palestine lasted
at least until 1951ce.38 We probably have no other sources than the texts of the
Old Testament, which suggest that a major migration actually took place. Most
of the constructions of Jewish history in the Persian period depend on the same
type of hermeneutic circular exegesis already described. It is an extraordinary
fact that scholars have paid so little attention to the meaning of the different
images of Jerusalem and Judah found in Chronicles, Ezra and Nehemiah. When
we read Nehemiah, it is as if the author of Nehemiah 1–4, the so-called ‘autobi-
ography of Nehemiah’, had never read Ezra. We cannot say with any certainty
that ‘Nehemiah’s autobiography’ is a historical document, reflecting conditions
in Jerusalem during the fourth century bce. It could be a form of novel from a
much later period – that is, the Hellenistic period. Whether it is a piece of litera-
ture going back to a historical person with the name Nehemiah, Nehemiah 1–4
describes conditions in Jerusalem and its environment that are very different
from the impression of Jerusalem in the Persian period that is found in other
biblical books. Has a Jewish community already appeared in Jerusalem during
the fourth century bce? This is an open question. From an archaeological per-
spective, do we possess evidence that a major migration took place at the end of
the sixth century bce from Mesopotamia to Palestine? If this had been the case,
if Jews from Babylonia had really returned to Jerusalem and Judah in large num-
bers between 538bce and 516bce, where are their Babylonian cooking-pots?
Would women leave their homes without bringing their utensils with them?39
The point is that the figure of ‘old Israel’ is a construct of biblical authors and
the ‘new Israel’ is a utopia created by the same authors as an expression of their
religious and national programme for the future. There never was the ‘old Israel’
the Bible describes. A ‘new Israel’ is also an invention, representing a project for
the future: God-loving people will found this ‘new Israel’, for only the righteous
will survive to assemble on Zion under the Lord’s protection (Isa. 4).
Two ideas inform the concept of the ‘new Israel’: a covenant between God
and Israel and God’s torah, the law. The covenant of Sinai failed miserably to
unite the people of Israel with its God. The new covenant of Jeremiah 31 will
substitute the old one and cannot be broken because it is not external, but part
37. On the historical value of the biblical idea of Palestine as ‘the empty land’ in the exilic
period, cf. Hans M. Barstad, The Myth of the Empty Land: A Study in the History and
Archaeology of Judah during the ‘Exilic’ Period (Symbolae Osloenses, 28; Oslo:
Scandinavian University Press, 1996). Jamieson-Drake is not of the same conviction.
According to his analysis of the evidence, a total breakdown of Judaean society took
place in the sixth century bce. Cf. his Scribes and Schools in Monarchic Israel, 145–7.
38. That is, until the seventh ‘Alia’ that transferred most of the Iraqi Jewish community to
Israel.
39. I made this point in my ‘Jordan in the Biblical Tradition: An Overview of the Tradition
with Special Reference to the Importance of the Biblical Literature for the Reconstruction
of the History of the Ancient Territories of the State of Jordan’, Studies in the History and
Archaeology of Jordan VII, Department of Antiquities, Amman, 2001, 347–51.
How does one date an expression of mental history? 299
of the person who has entered the covenant. Together with the covenant goes
God’s torah, or instruction. This instruction guides the new Israel that it one day
enter Zion. Without the torah there is no path to God. Most people will perish
before they ever reach this place of blessing: ‘They have cast away the law of
the Lord of Hosts and despised the word of the Holy One of Israel’ (Isa. 5:24).40
The ‘new Israel’ is the people of God, a people of twelve tribes assembled
around the shrine of Yahweh at Zion. It is believed to include people with a com-
mon blood and a common religion – to a lesser degree, with a common language
and with a land of its own.41 The mental matrix of biblical authors centres in the
establishment of this new Israel: an expression of a sectarian view of society,
creating a division between two kinds of people – the righteous who belong to
this society and the unjust who will be condemned and discarded. The criterion
for deciding who is righteous and who is not is entirely a religious one: whether
people keep the covenant and follow its instructions. This sectarian community
– like similar organizations in the Hellenistic world – excludes itself from the
greater society surrounding it.42
Without the torah there will never be a new Israel. What does such a state-
ment tell us about the authors who introduced the concept of torah? The
Decalogue opens the torah (Exod. 20:1-21; in Deut. it serves the same purpose:
5:6-21). Regardless of its origin and tradition history, it might serve as an index
for the following sections of the legislation of Moses, opening with the ‘Book
of the Covenant’ in Exodus 21–23. The Assyriologist Raymond Westbrook
has argued that the first so-called ‘secular’ part of this collection represents
Mesopotamian legal tradition.43 He is certainly correct – we need only refer
to the great similarity examined by, among others, Shalom Paul and Eckhart
Otto.44 Westbrook believes that this proves the Book of the Covenant to be
old. However, in Mesopotamia, the tradition of law codes lasted for millennia,
40. Cf. further on this my ‘“For de har forkastet Hærskarers Herres lov” – eller “vi og de
andre!” – Om forfatterne, der skrev Det Gamle Testamente’, in E. K. Holt (ed.) ‘Alle
der ånder skal lovprise Herren’: Det Gamle Testamente i tempel, synagoge og kirke
(Frederiksberg: Anis, 1998), 63–90; English translation ‘“Because They Have Cast
Away the Law of the Lord of Hosts” – Or “We and the Rest of the World” – The Authors
Who “Wrote” the Old Testament’, SJOT 17 (2003), 268–90.
41. Cf. the virtual ‘re-establishment’ of the amphictyony in my The Israelites in History and
Tradition, 97–107. This amphictyony is not the old one invented by Noth and has no part
in the history of ancient Israel; it is a written mental structure.
42. Cf. the conclusion to Isa. 6. Only the elect among the elect will survive the ordeal (vv.
11-13). It is safe to assume that the author who wrote these verses will not reckon himself
to be among the condemned.
43. Cf. Raymond Westbrook, Studies in Biblical and Cuneiform Law (Cahiers de la Revue
Biblique 26; Paris: J. Gabalda, 1988).
44. Cf. Shalom Paul, Studies in the Book of the Covenant in the Light of Cuneiform and
Biblical Law (VT supplement, 18; Leiden: E. J. Brill, 1970), and Eckhart Otto, Wandel
der Rechtsbegründigungen in der Gesellschaftsgeschichte des antiken Israel: Eine
Rechtgeschichte des ‘Bundesbuches’ Exod. XX 22-XXIII 13 (Studia Biblica, 3; Leiden:
E. J. Brill, 1988).
300 Biblical studies and the failure of history
from Sumerian times until at least the coming of the Greeks and probably even
longer (the cuneiform literary tradition did not die totally out before the first
or second centuries ce). This legal tradition was, rather, stable and not easily
exported. More importantly, it was not a tradition in the usual sense of the word,
but an academic construction only remotely related to life in the court. It was
nourished in the universities of the time (the misnamed ‘scribal schools’) and
belonged exclusively to this milieu. In short: Mesopotamian law codices are
not primarily expressions of forensic experience, but belong among wisdom
literature and represent an academic pastime.45
Biblical collectors or authors of legal traditions, which are included among
the instructions of Moses, apparently chose one of the Mesopotamian law codes
(or created their own within Babylonian tradition) as the first part of the divine
legislation. They thus reveal where they were educated. They must have studied
in the university institutions of their time, most likely in Mesopotamia (a safe
assumption as long as we have no evidence of comparable institutions outside
of Mesopotamia – at least in the Iron Age, during the first millennium bce). It
is clear that our collectors and/or authors had an academic background. They
belonged to academic circles and were brought up within a system of education
that had already lasted for more than 2000 years.46
We now know two things about our authors. In regard to religion, we know
they were sectarians, people who believed themselves among the chosen few
and destined to survive when God returns his people to Zion. We also know
that they were academics and part of an old educational system. None of this
proves our authors to be late, let alone from the Hellenistic–Roman period.
They obviously postdate the events of 587bce (if this is a historical date, the
Old Testament is the only testimony to the second destruction of Jerusalem)
or at least of 597bce (the date of the conquest of Jerusalem according to the
Babylonian Chronicle).47 The destruction of Jerusalem is a necessary part of the
construction as it is of fundamental importance for the future return of the ‘new
Israel’ to Zion. The question is only whether the authors belonged to the Persian
or the Hellenistic period.
45. In Chapter 13, this volume, I try to explain why no written law was really necessary
in Western Asia in antiquity. On the Babylonian ‘law codes’, cf. the literature quoted
in note 5, on p. 214, to which we have to add the introduction to Martha T. Roth, Law
Collections from Mesopotamia and Asia Minor (SBL Writings from the Ancient World
Series 6; Atlanta, GA: Scholars Press, 2nd edn, 1997), 4–7.
46. This assumption is valid regardless of whether we choose an Iron Age date for these
authors or we prefer the Persian or Hellenistic–Roman periods.
47. Cf. D. J. Wiseman, Chronicles of Chaldaean Kings (626–556 bc) in the British Museum
(London: The Trustees of the British Museum, 1956), BM. 21946, rv. 11–13. It is so
easy to forget that 587bce is a biblical date. That 597bce is derived from external sources
does not prove that the destruction of 597bce really took place. It is probably likely that
something like 587bce happened, but it cannot be proven. The presence of members
of the Judaean royal family at the Babylonian court in Neo-Babylonian times does not
presuppose the destruction of 587bce – not even according to the Old Testament – it only
presupposes the abduction of Jehoiachin in 597bce (cf. ANET, 308).
How does one date an expression of mental history? 301
It is perhaps not fair to say that the Persian period has been popular among
scholars because we know so little about it – that is, as far as Palestine is con-
cerned. However, the attractiveness of the Persian period for modern scholars
compares well with the estimation of ‘early Israel’ as the cradle of Israelite
civilization a generation ago. Like ‘early Israel’, the Persian period constitutes
a ‘black box’. We know so little about early Israel, but only slightly more about
the Persian period. Many scholars think that the biblical tradition either origi-
nated or developed into the literature we know from the Old Testament during
the Persian period. The capacity of being a ‘black box’ makes the Persian period
a likely candidate as it cannot be refuted by extant evidence, suggesting the
opposite. The unknown within the ‘black box’ makes everything possible and
enables a scholar to propose theories that cannot be controlled. The procedure is
illegitimate, as it provides hypotheses which cannot be falsified.48 It is possible
that a religious idea such as the dualism between good and evil, which is found
in Old Testament texts, but much more expressly in para-biblical literature such
as the War Scroll from Qumran (clearly Hellenistic–Roman in date), is the result
of influences from Persian religion.49 It may also be that the idea of a theocratic
government in Yehud was modelled on the basis of the citizen–temple–soci-
ety system as developed elsewhere in the Persian Empire.50 Evidence of such
a theocratic system from Judah, however, hardly predates the second century
bce.51 At the end of the day, we must admit that we know too little about the
Persian period to use it as a viable possibility. Accordingly, it is not only wish-
ful thinking that the Old Testament was written largely during the centuries of
the Persian occupation of Palestine. If there are reflections in Old Testament
literature of ideas current within the Persian Empire in the fifth or early fourth
centuries bce, we cannot identify such ideas with any certainty. We cannot place
biblical texts within an intellectual development otherwise unknown to us.
Matters improve as we turn to the Hellenistic and Roman periods, as we are
well informed of the general development of intellectual history in this era, not
least from our acquaintance with the history of philosophy of the Hellenistic
world, and we possess a fair amount of Hellenistic literature, mostly, but not
exclusively, of Greek origin. We also have an impression of the impact of Greek
civilization upon the Near East. We know too little about the precise history
of this development, especially in remote areas, such as the many crannies of
48. Adopted from the falsification claim of Karl Popper, which says that a hypothesis must
be the subject of a falsification process, and if this is not possible, the hypothesis is
redundant.
49. The origin of the idea of dualism (i.e. the war between good and evil) that became
popular within Judaism towards the end of the first millennium bce has traditionally
been reckoned to be Persian. Cf., for example, Helmer Ringgren, Israelite Religion
(Philadelphia, PA: Fortress Press, 1966), 314–15.
50. Cf. especially Joel Weinberg, The Citizen-Temple Community (JSOT supplement, 151;
Sheffield: Sheffield Academic Press, 1992).
51. This statement is gratuitous as we know next to nothing about the second century bce
apart from information provided by Josephus of the late first century ce.
302 Biblical studies and the failure of history
Palestine. We must hope that in the future it will be possible to describe how
Greek civilization gradually extended its influence from region to region during
the third and second centuries. The initial centres of Greek–Hellenistic influence
were in Egypt and Mesopotamia, but Hellenistic civilization spread to areas
including Palestine and Jordan during the second century bce.52
The question is whether it is possible to find traces of the general intellectual
climate of Hellenism in biblical literature. Traditions of the ancient Near East
are much in evidence in the Bible. It is foolish to say anything else. From the
very beginning of the collection of writings in the Old Testament, Near Eastern
tradition manifests itself both in single and more complex narratives. If we are
to understand the authors and collectors of biblical literature, we must keep
ancient Near Eastern culture in mind.
The analysis can be compared to an archaeological excavation. In the text
of the Old Testament, a variety of items from different places and times are
available. Mesopotamian material is obvious. For example, the story of the crea-
tion in Genesis 2 is embedded within Mesopotamian tradition and the story of
the flood in Genesis 6–8 is closely related to the Neo-Babylonian version in
the Gilgamesh Epic. Some biblical material comes from Egypt – for exam-
ple, the chapters of Proverbs that are shared by the Egyptian wisdom book of
Amenemopet (Prov. 22:17–24:22).53 More Egyptian or ‘Egyptianized’ material
can be found in stories about Israel in Egypt.54 Ideas and notions from Syria
and the Levant abound, for example, in allusions to the battle between God and
the sea in many Old Testament psalms. Biblical authors share many genres of
literature with their Near Eastern colleagues, such as the already-mentioned law
tradition, but they also share wisdom literature in its many forms.
Although Near Eastern influence is apparent, it is not enough to date its
literary context. As in archaeology, a literary stratum must be dated according
to the youngest item found, rather than the oldest. Any piece of literature may
reflect ideas and concepts that trace their origins millennia earlier in the history
of humankind. If the text also includes elements belonging to a more recent
period, the context will always be that of the youngest item at the earliest.
This hardly is a surprise to students of the Old Testament, who have looked for
centuries for solutions to the problem, not least by splitting biblical literature
into several literary strata, sources or documents. In a recent contribution, I
52. Not before the second and first centuries bce. The Hellenization of the Southern Levant
has hardly been a major area of interest to students of Hellenistic culture, probably with
some justification, as – apart for some major cities – Hellenization only slowly became a
major cultural factor in the remote areas of Palestine and Jordan. ‘The Early Hellenistic
archaeological lacuna and the late Hellenistic expansion and prosperity in the southern
Levant can be understood within the context of the attitudes, policies and practices of
the Ptolemaic and Seleucid governments’: conclusion to Robert H. Smith, ‘The Southern
Levant in the Hellenistic Period’, Levant 22 (1990), 123–30.
53. Amenemopet, cf. ANET, 421–5.
54. Especially in the Joseph Story, cf. Donald B. Redford, A Study of the Biblical Story of
Joseph (Genesis 37-50) (VT supplement, 20; Leiden: E. J. Brill, 1970).
How does one date an expression of mental history? 303
55. Cf. my Prelude to Israel’s Past: Background and Beginnings of Israelite History and
Identity (Peabody, MA: Hendrickson, 1998), 62–3.
56. The Chaldeans do not appear in Mesopotamian sources before the ninth century bce. The
earliest mentioning is by Assurnirari II in 878: KURkaldu. Cf. on this Dietz Otto Edzard,
‘Kaldu (Chaldäa)’, Reallexikon der Assyriologie, 5 (Berlin: W. de Gruyter, 1976–80),
291–7.
57. The date was established by R. Walz in his ‘Zum Problem des Zeitpunktes der
Domestikation der altweltlichen Cameliden’, ZDMG 101 (1951), 29–51, and the
same author’s ‘Neue Untersuchungen zum Damestikationsprobblem der altweltlichen
Cameliden’, ZDMG 104 (1954), 45–87. To the best of my knowledge, Walz’s date still
stands.
58. John Van Seters, In Search of History (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1983).
304 Biblical studies and the failure of history
contact was the early ‘logographers’ of the Greek world: writers of the sixth
century bce who collected memories and traditions from ‘ancient times’. The
comparison does not end there. We may question how Near Eastern intellectuals
got to know the tradition of the logographers as early as the Iron Age. Although
contacts between the Aegean Archipelagos and the Levant existed, there are no
traces of any influence from the logographers in any Iron Age source from Syria
or Palestine, let alone Mesopotamia. Van Seters’s idea of an early transmission
of Greek culture to the Levant is part of his general appraisal of the exilic period
and dating of the Yahwist to the sixth century. It is a weak link in his argument.
Other scholars have gone further. A series of studies has appeared recently or
are in process of publication which argue for a dependency between biblical his-
tory writing and Herodotus’s Histories of the middle-fifth century bce. Jan-Wim
Wesselius has published a series of articles – partly in Dutch – about Herodotus
and the Old Testament, among them a recent contribution to the Scandinavian
Journal of the Old Testament, where he argues for a dependency between the
primeval history in Genesis and Herodotus’s work.59 This comparison is to be
expanded in a forthcoming monograph.60
Obviously, Wesselius, like Flemming A. Nielsen in his recent work on Greek
history writing and the Deuteronomistic History,61 concentrates on the strik-
ing similarity between Herodotus and Old Testament historical prose narrative.
The focus of attention shifted from the sixth to the fifth century bce! Still, the
comparison between the Bible and Herodotus’s Histories seems directed by the
same tendency, as is evident in Van Seters’s link to the logographers. Herodotus
stands at the beginning of Greek historiographical tradition and, although he
borrows from the logographers, later Greek and Roman traditions considered
him, probably correctly, ‘the father of history’. There is no reason to limit our
investigations to the relationship between Herodotus and the Bible.
In my ‘Good and Bad in History’, I present a different approach to the
study of biblical and Hellenistic history writing.62 In this study, I will argue
that the History of Rome by Livy is actually closer to the biblical history than
Herodotus’s ‘investigations’ – not because biblical literature presupposes the
existence of Livy’s extensive work, which dates from the end of the first cen-
tury bce, but because it presupposes the historiographic tradition, within which
Livy’s history must be situated. Livy’s work is part of the Hellenistic tradition
of writing history, within the Greek system of education in the third and second
centuries bce.
59. Jan-Wim Wesselius, ‘Discontinuity, Congruence and the Making of the Hebrew Bible’,
SJOT 13 (1999), 24–77, see especially 38–48.
60. Jan-Wim Wesselius, The Origin of the History of Israel: Herodotus’ Histories as
Blueprint for the First Books of the Bible (JSOT supplement, 345; Sheffield: Sheffield
Academic Press, 2002).
61. Flemming A. Nielsen, The Tragedy in History: Herodotus and the Deuteronomistic
History (JSOT supplement, 251; Copenhagen International Seminar 4; Sheffield:
Sheffield Academic Press, 1997).
62. Chapter 17, this volume.
How does one date an expression of mental history? 305
been preserved of the works of Manetho and Berossus, but that they appeared
more or less at the same time (early second century bce) in different places
illustrates the early impact of Greek literary tradition in the centres of the Near
East.
When we put the evidence together and ask for a place where the amal
gamation between oriental and Greek traditions might have taken place, the
fact that the historical literature of the Old Testament presupposes an amalga-
mation between Greek and Oriental academic traditions is important. Within
the Hellenistic–Roman educational system, history was an integral part of the
academic curriculum, identified with the dominating discipline of rhetoric. We
therefore have to look for a place where oriental and Greek traditions came
together in an educational system or academic environment that included both
traditions.67
Many years ago, I playfully proposed a new theory about the origin of the
Pentateuch, which was never intended to be published. It was publicly referred
to as ‘Lemche’s famous “three pub hypothesis”’. The ‘hypothesis’ claims that
the Pentateuch came into being over a very short time in the third century bce, in
three different pubs of a Jewish suburb in Babylon. One of these was called ‘J’,
another ‘E’ and the third ‘P’. It took little more than three months of lively inter-
change between the three pubs to finish the first four books of Moses. Although
no more than a joke, it may be closer to reality than we realize. We should, how-
ever, probably not look to Babylon for the intellectual milieu of our authors. In
the third century bce, people gradually deserted Babylon and resettled in newly
founded Seleucia, the present Baghdad. The Seleucid Empire was, however,
excellently set up to provide the intellectual conditions for an amalgamation
between Mesopotamian and Greek traditions that could also have provoked the
appearance of Old Testament historical prose literature.
It is probably more likely that the centre of this intellectual development
was Mesopotamia. Syria might be considered an alternative (Damascus?). The
utopian character of the concept of the ‘people of God’ and its likewise utopian
concept of the land of Israel in the Old Testament speak in favour of an origin of
the historical literature of the Old Testament outside of Palestine. If Hellenism
came late to Palestine, we may have yet another argument in favour of a non-
Palestinian origin of this literature.
In two very different studies published during the first half of the 1990s, David
Jamieson-Drake and Michael Niemann reached results remarkably similar con-
cerning the early history of the Judean state.1 Jamieson-Drake’s synthetic study
of the archaeological artefacts and settlement patterns shows how unlikely it
would be to speak about a proper state in the southern part of the central high-
lands of Israel/Palestine before the eighth century, when a sharp increase in set-
tled areas becomes visible. Niemann, for his part, bases his study on an analysis
of archaeological remains as well as information within the Bible itself. It is a
classical study according to the best principles of the historical-critical school
of Old Testament studies and should be acceptable to most scholars, though its
results are controversial. Niemann also concludes that a state in the proper sense
of the word did not exist in Judah during the tenth century and only gradually
developed during the next 100 years or so.2
What Niemann suggests is a form of patronage state, as this writer described
in a lecture delivered at the German Archaeological Institute in Jerusalem in
1995.3 By ‘patronage state’, I mean a state organized as a personal possession
around a ruling family. It does not have an extended bureaucracy, except to
regulate relations between the ruling family – the patrons – and their clients,
the ordinary population. That kind of state dominated the area during the Late
Bronze Age, and survived as a typical form of political organization well into
the Iron Age.
I have described certain aspects of the system in a series of articles,4 includ-
ing personalized forms of relationship between ruler and the ruled, regulated by
contracts, treaties or covenants, with a distribution of local law that was neither
written nor codified. Patrons were autonomous and such political formations did
not need an extended bureaucracy. The few officers mentioned in the overviews
of David’s and Solomon’s administrations would suffice – a point that did not,
of course, escape Niemann’s attention. I am less ready, however, than he to
accept such lists as reflecting information from the tenth century. A proper state,
ancient as well as modern, is in need of an administration that can record mun-
dane matters such as tax lists and the salaries of soldiers, bureaucrats, artisans,
etc., employed by the state. Its administration plans and directs the business of
the state. It also maintains relationships with similar administrations of other
states. It writes documents and stores them in archives, though we have indica-
tions that archival records in the ancient Near East were not kept for great peri-
ods of time, as in modern state archives. A side effect of the existence of state
records is the establishment of a chronological framework for such administra-
tion. At least in major centres, a chronology was established, normally based on
the regnal years of the king. Other systems were known, such as the Assyrian
limu system, according to which a year would be named after the holder of the
office of the limu – a solution to the problem of recording time that was close to
the Roman system of the consular year.5 Sometimes such classification resulted
in the establishment of state chronicles (i.e. short year lists), including one or
two important events relating to the year in question. At other times this kind of
chronicling developed into a literary composition of annals.
On the other hand, we should not overemphasize the importance of chronol-
ogy and annals. As far as I know, we have no records of any kind of chrono-
logical reckoning from Bronze Age Syria and Palestine. In spite of a plethora
of documents and inscriptions, Ugarit has never yielded any chronological list
or royal annal. Nor were official documents normally dated in Ugarit – for
example, to Niqmadu’s second regnal year or to Niqmepa’s fourth year. An
incantation or ritual text does mention a series of deceased kings of Ugarit,6
who are reckoned as the predecessors of the present king, showing that people
were capable of keeping records of past events or major figures of the past.
However, nothing has been found in the form of an official administrative docu-
ment, with precise information, which might contribute directly to a chronology
in ancient Ugarit. The relevant question is whether the states named Israel and
Judah had archives, which included chronicles? The question was addressed by
Montgomery nearly seventy years ago and his answer remains important.7 How
Most of these notes are very general with almost no related information. A few
include regnal years, and a few more, additional information about wars. They
are normally attached to notes about a change of regency, regnal years, burial or
succession, but it is not clear – though likely – that this additional information
comes from the Chronicles. The same can be said about information enclosed
in the narrative and associated with references to the Chronicles, such as the
note of Pul’s attack on Israel in the days of Menahem, and of Menahem’s tribute
(2 Kgs 15:19-20). If an old chronicle of the kingdom of Israel had existed, we
know next to nothing of its content.
Will we get more relevant information when we turn to The Chronicles of the
Kings of Judah ֵסֶפר ִדְּבֵרי ַה יִָּמים ְלֵמלֵכי יְוָּדה:
310 Biblical studies and the failure of history
Everything said about the content of references to the Chronicles of the Kings of
Israel is equally valid when it comes to references to the kings of Judah, except
that there are no indications of regnal years in any of these notes. Only once, in
the case of Rehoboam about fortifications, is a note included. We have no idea
of the shape and content of this chronicle. We do not even know if there was,
in fact, a state chronicle in Judah. Both the Chronicles of the Kings of Israel
and the Kings of Judah may be no more than stray collections of information,
relevant or irrelevant: perhaps a prototype of the history of these kingdoms
from the Iron Age. But we cannot know. A couple of references are followed by
the information that a continuous war raged between the king of either Israel
or Judah and his colleague in the south or the north. In concluding, we must
say that these notes have very little interest for the historian other than that the
information included also relates to the Chronicles. This is possible but cannot
be proved. We cannot preclude the possibility that references to the Chronicles
are nothing but a literary device, employed by the composer of 1–2 Kings.
This demands a more extensive argument; but, at the moment, I can only
refer to a more extensive argument in an article I wrote about the concept of
time in the Old Testament, available in Danish.8 The argument deals with the
existence of two different notions of time in the Old Testament/Hebrew Bible:
first, a quantitative understanding, which calculates hours, days, weeks, months
and years, much as we count them today. A different system is also present that
reveals an interest in the qualitative meaning of time. This system shows no
interest in the exact measurement of time, but rather in the importance of time.
It makes use of so-called ‘pregnant’ (i.e. significant) numbers such as seven
and forty. The idea is not that seven days are exactly seven, but that the number
of seven is a special number, having significance in itself. The Hebrew slave
of Exodus 21 works for six years and is set free in the seventh. Joshua’s army
circles the walls of Jericho for six days, to see them tumble down on the seventh
and so on. The number forty has a similar quality and includes periods of time
governing the rain in the flood story or Israel’s punishment for forty years in the
desert. Seventy can also be used in this manner, such as the duration of the exile
in Jeremiah (Jer. 25:11).
Sometimes the two systems are in conflict, as in the story of the flood in
Genesis. In this regard, I might refer to an article I published twenty years ago
on the chronology of the flood,9 where I argued that there were, in fact, three
systems of reckoning time present in that narrative, the third representing an
effort to harmonize the different types of information presented by the two other
systems. One works with intervals of seven and forty days, while the other with
fixed dates, such as the first day of the first month in Noah’s 601st year. The third
system emerged because of calculations which incorporated fixed dates of the
second system within the system of pregnant dates of the first system. This pro-
duced odd numbers, such as the date of the flood’s beginning, the seventeenth
day of the second month in Noah’s 600th year and of the end of the flood on the
twenty-seventh day of the second month of Noah’s 601st year.
What kind of system rules the information in 1–2 Kings about regnal years
of Israelite and Judean kings? If we begin with Israel, after the division of the
Kingdom of David and Solomon, Jeroboam rules for twenty-two years, Nadab
for two, Basha for twenty-four and Ela for another two. None of these numbers
carry any significant value, in themselves, although it is interesting that together
these figures equal fifty years – or one year of Jubilee. We might argue that the
calculation indicates that from the death of Solomon to the ascension of Omri,
a period of one Jubilee elapsed (disregarding Zimri’s ‘seven’ days – which, I
think, is allowable). We might also argue that the numbers are casual, reflecting
the actual periods of these early kings’ reigns. Omri ruled for ‘six’ years, and
in the seventh his son, Ahab, who, like Jeroboam, ruled twenty-two years, suc-
ceeded him. His successor was Ahaziah, who ruled two years. All together the
dynasty of Omri reigned thirty years.
Thirty years is not a pregnant number that carries a meaning of its own. We
may, of course, speculate about the numbers of the regnal years of the kings of
Israel from Jeroboam to the end of the house of Omri. Three kings rule for some
twenty years each (the exact numbers are twenty-two, twenty-four and twenty-
two) and are in each case followed by a son who rules for two years. It is sig-
nificant that Omri ruled six years, but in the seventh … It may also be significant
for the reconstruction of an exact chronology that the thirty years of the house
of Omri follows the fifty years of the first four kings of Israel. Altogether, these
early kings of Israel ruled for eighty years or exactly the length of time covered
by David and Solomon. It looks like a chronology that is not exact, but based
on speculation in numbers that was weighted with the importance of ‘preg-
nant’ numbers, in this case forty. Some may, however, still argue that the round
number eighty, from the death of Solomon to the ascension of Jehu, is merely
coincidence and that the information regarding the regnal years may, indeed,
rely on real information (e.g. from state-sponsored chronicles).10
When we move on to the dynasty succeeding the House of Omri, the line of
Jehu, Jehu himself ruled twenty-eight years, Joahaz seventeen, Joash sixteen,
and Jeroboam forty-one. The resulting 102 years seems to offer no reason to
assume the presence of round numbers. We should, however, not forget that the
last king of the line, Zechariah, ruled six months, indicating a change during
the pregnant seventh month. The final dynasty of the kings of Israel includes:
Shallum – one month; Menahem – ten years; Pekaiah – two years; Peka – twenty
years; and Hosea nine years; altogether forty-one years and an odd month. No
pregnant numbers here, not even when we put together the regnal years from
Jehu to Hosea – 133 years and 7 months.
In conclusion, these figures lend support to the assumption that some infor-
mation about regnal years of the kings of Israel was available to the author(s) of
1–2 Kings. This is more likely after the ascension of the house of Jehu. Until that
date, we do not know if official information about regnal years existed in Israel.
We may question the validity of the information about the four kings follow-
ing Solomon. We might also follow in the footsteps of Thomas Thompson and
cast doubt on the historicity of Omri, the ruler of Israel for six years, who was
followed by his son in the seventh.11 We should not be surprised if the Kingdom
of Israel/Samaria/Beth Omri did not possess any kind of official chronicle and
that the author of this part of 1–2 Kings constructed the regnal numbers of that
dynasty. We cannot, of course, prove our case, but it is highly likely.
Why does the character of the numbers change after the ascension of Jehu?
We can only guess, but I think that a qualified answer has to do with Jehu’s and
his successors’ status as vassals of the Assyrians. Perhaps the Assyrian admin-
istration wanted exact numbers and dates to incorporate information from the
10. It has to be stated at this point that although many scholars, from William F. Albright to
Erwin R. Thiele to John. H. Hayes, have diligently tried to make sense of the chronologi-
cal information in the Old Testament about Israelite and Judaean kings, their approach
has disregarded the possibility of pregnant numbers, and established detailed lists of
regnal periods based on numbers never intended to be quantitatively precise. Cf. among
the more recent contributions, which also includes most of the relevant literature, John
H. Hayes and Paul K. Hooker, A New Chronology for the Kings of Israel and Judah
and Its Implications for Biblical History and Literature (Atlanta, GA: John Knox Press,
1988).
11. Cf. Thomas L. Thompson, The Bible in History: How Writers Create a Past (London:
Jonathan Cape, 1999), 11–14.
Chronology and archives 313
West into their own system of calculation? Perhaps the administration of Jehu’s
kingdom had been influenced by the habits of the Assyrians and changed from
a system without a fixed-time reckoning – a system resembling that apparently
in currency in the Bronze Age – into a system with exact dates?
When we turn to the numbers of the kings of Judah, will they show a similar
change of ‘pattern’ in Judah’s history? Of course, the two great kings of Judah,
David and Solomon, both ruled for forty years. No less would do. Moreover,
David’s reign is divided into two periods: seven years and six months in Hebron,
and thirty-three years in Jerusalem. The Hebron period plays with variations of
the pregnant number seven, allowing for the use of the numbers six, seven and
eight in this connection.12 Rehoboam follows Solomon and rules for seventeen
years, whereas his son and successor, Abiah, was only allowed three years on
the throne. The numbers look casual, but when we put them together, we have
twenty years (i.e. half the time of either David or Solomon). This may be coinci-
dental and not important. However, let’s turn to the next king of Judah, Asa, who
reigns for forty-one years. It is, of course, very close to forty but not a round
number. The ‘extra’ year creates a problem, which might, however, be solved
when we calculate the period from David’s ascension to the first Babylonian
conquest of Jerusalem on the basis of the regnal years of the kings of Judah.
This period lasts for 461 years and, from the ascension of Solomon, 421 years
– an impossible date. A seemingly unnecessary addition of one year to Asa’s
reign disturbs the harmony? So, why was this number added? I will return to
this question shortly.
After Asa follows Joshaphat, who is allowed twenty-five years on the throne,
Jehoram with eight years, Ahaziah with one year and Athaliah with six years.
All numbers look casual but put together they cover exactly forty years. It is
worth noting that Athaliah ruled for six years in order to be substituted by Joash
in her seventh regnal year. By now we have seen this pattern so many times that
we should not be surprised. Joash follows Athaliah. He rules – believe it or not
– for an additional forty years.
A series of kings follow Joash until the first conquest of Jerusalem. Amaziah
rules twenty-nine years, Azariah fifty-two, Jotham sixteen, Ahaz sixteen,
Hezekiah twenty-nine, Manasseh fifty-five, Amon two, Josiah thirty-one, Joahaz
three months, Jehoiachim eleven years and, finally, Jehoachin for three months.
There is no apparent trace of a system here and no specific reward implied by a
long rule. Unlike the Books of Chronicles, which have problems with the untidy
length of Manasseh’s rule (indicating that the chroniclers considered the number
12. Cf. the observations by Mario Liverani, ‘Ma nel settimo Anno’, in Studi sull’ Oriente e
la Bibbia offerte a P. Giovanni Rinaldi nell 60o compiuanno (Genoa: Editrice Studio e
Vita, 1967), 49–53.
314 Biblical studies and the failure of history
they inherited from their source to be problematic; cf. 2 Chron. 33), there is no
reward for good behaviour in the form of a long reign. Nothing seems to speak
against an extra-biblical source for the regnal years of these kings of the eighth
through seventh centuries. However, problems may be involved. If the numbers
are added together, they result in 241 years from the ascension of Amaziah to
Nebuchadnezzar’s first conquest of Jerusalem. Again, we have a superfluous
year! As in the calculations of the kings of Israel, the two regnal periods of three
months for Joahaz and Jehoiachin have not been considered. If the system is
artificial, why does it include an extra year?
I feel much like the treasurer of a small company, struggling to make his
accounts balance and comes short by a quarter of a dollar (I have, for many
years, been the treasurer of our local scholarly organization, the Collegium
Biblicum, so I speak from experience). One is obsessed by the need to make
the account balance. The missing quarter is the lost son, dearer to you than
all the others! The only possible solution I can think of is the additional nine
years from the first conquest of Jerusalem to the rebellion of Zedekiah, which
would render 250 years from the death of Joash to the rebellion of Hezekiah,
if we include Zedekiah’s reign until the moment when he starts his rebellion
against the Babylonians. But then we may ask why it was not the second and
final destruction of Jerusalem that formed the basis of the calculation? I have
no answer to this question at this time but am still speculating about a solution
that might also have historical implications.
Conclusion
Now for an evaluation: in the case of Israel there was a definite change of sys-
tem after the ascension of Jehu. Numbers become casual – accidental – and may
reflect the existence of an official chronicle patterned after Assyrian practice. In
the case of Judah we have a series of round and pregnant numbers until the death
of Joash. The character of the numbers then change, but we cannot be certain
that this is not due to a change in time reckoning or whether this can be traced
to some complicated calculations from the perspective of the historiographer. It
would have been nice not to get so close to a pregnant number, when the indi
vidual figures are put together.
The system of the second part of the history of the Kingdom of Jerusalem
may be based on a complicated system created by the author of 2 Kings. In that
case, the historiographer had to pay attention to other information. After all,
the references to kings of Judah in Assyrian annals, place them in the – accord-
ing to our modern historical calculations – correct centuries and in the right
order. If the system of the kings of Judah, even in the second part of its history,
is a construct, it likely concurred with information like that in the Assyrian
Chronicles and royal annals. I shall not dwell on this point, but return rather to
the beginning of Judah’s history.
Four kings of Judah rule for forty years (disregarding Asa’s additional year).
The system begins with two times forty, followed by an interlude of twenty years,
Chronology and archives 315
which is again followed by another forty (in fact, forty-one) years, followed by
an interlude of forty (divided between three kings and a queen) followed by
another reign of forty years. This is simply too good to be true. It seems certain
that there are only two possibilities. Either the authors of 1 and 2 Kings had a
system of pregnant numbers at their disposal, which indicated regnal years, or
they invented the system. We should not be disturbed by the sequence following
Asa: twenty-five years plus eight plus one plus six. As already mentioned, the
numbers appear accidental, but when added together, they make forty years. It
seems that the author of 1–2 Kings had decided in advance on a period of forty
years. At the same time, he divided it between four different characters. It is not
unimportant that his account end with a pregnant period of six years that it might
be followed by a change in the seventh year (the ascension of Joash).
This decision to split a pregnant number into lesser units that individually are
unimportant is not unique. As already indicated, we may have further examples
in 1–2 Kings. There are, however, other more and less complicated examples of
this technique. One can be found in the list of so-called ‘minor judges:’ Judges
10:1-5; 11:8-15. The list includes five judges, reigning, respectively, twenty-
three years, twenty-two, seven, ten and eight years, altogether seventy years.
Now, seventy is a pregnant indication of time and not quantitatively exact. We
can be sure that the list is either preserved in its entirety or has been manipulated
to reach this round number. Perhaps, such manipulation relates to the story of
Jephtah, which is framed by the list of minor judges. By now, none should be
surprised to hear that Jephtah reigned for a period of six years. I would very
much have liked to know what happened in that seventh year!
However, let us return to the early history of Judah from David to Joash. Is
it possible to find an explanation that clarifies the principles behind the selec-
tion of kings who reign for forty years and those who reside on the throne for
a shorter period of time? I believe so and the central issue has to do with the
worship of Yahweh in Jerusalem. What puts David, Solomon, Asa and Joash
in the same category seems to deal with worship. David introduced Yahweh to
Jerusalem, brought his holy ark there and instituted the worship there. Solomon
built the temple. Asa reformed Jerusalem’s cult and, therefore, can be likened
to ‘David his father’ in the eyes of the historiographer who composed 1 Kings
(1 Kgs 15:11). Finally, Joash also acted in favour of the cult in Jerusalem by
repairing the temple and reforming it – also viewed as particularly significant.
This seems to be a fixed topos, according to which the righteous king acts in
favour of Yahweh’s cult in Jerusalem and is rewarded with a reign of forty years.
Of course, two other kings also act in favour of the cult, Hezekiah and Josiah,
but they are not included in the system of forty years. How is this change to be
explained? I would suggest the possibility that in the case of Judah, the histo-
riographers were in possession of some official information of regnal periods,
but not before the end of the ninth century. Before 800bce, we have, at the
most, traditional history writing like chronicles of the early Middle Age (my
first choice will always be Saxo Grammaticus and his Gestae Danorum), where
it is impossible to distinguish fact from fiction. After 800bce, the historiographer
was in possession of additional information, which restrained his freedom for
316 Biblical studies and the failure of history
Acknowledgements
This chapter is a slightly revised version of my lecture at the First Meeting of the
European Association of Biblical Studies, Utrecht, The Netherlands, in August
2000. I have kept the ‘tone’ of the original lecture.
21
1. Knud Jeppesen, Grœder ikke saa saare. Studier i Mikabogens sigte (Aarhus: Aarhus
Universitetsforlag, 1987), 63–84.
318 Biblical studies and the failure of history
2. Martin Noth, Das System der zwölf Stämme Israels (BWANT IV:1; Stuttgart: Kohl
hammer, 1930).
3. Cf. his discussion of the origin of the Israelite tradition in his Geschichte Israels
(Göttingen: Vandenhoeck and Ruprecht, 1950), 105–30.
4. Cf. Martin Noth on this in his Überlieferungsgeschichte des Pentateuch (Stuttgart:
Kohlhammer, 1948), especially 45–48.
5. Among the critical studies we may mention Niels Peter Lemche, Israel i Dommertiden.
En oversigt over diskussionen om Martin Noths ‘Das System der zwölf Stämme Israels’
(Tekst og Tolkning 4; Copenhagen: CEG Gad, 1972); Andrew D. H. Mayes, Israel in
the Period of the Judges (SBT supplement, 29; London: SCM, 1974); and Cornelius
H. J. de Geus, The Tribes of Israel: An Investigation into Some of the Presuppositions
of Martin Noth’s Amphictyonic Hypothesis (Studia Semitica Neerlandica 18; Assen: Van
Gorcum, 1976). The discussion was summarized by Niels Peter Lemche in ‘Israel in
the Period of the Judges – the Tribal league in Recent Research’, Studia Theologica 38
(1984), 1–28. In my recent monograph The Israelites in History and Tradition (Library
of Ancient Israel; Louisville, KY: Westminster, 1998), 97–107, I propose to restate the
amphictyonic hypothesis. It did not belong to history but should be seen as an ideological
construct of the biblical historiographers, part of the literary construct called ‘ancient
Israel’.
6. I consider this interpretation the logical consequence of the Immanuel prophecy in Isa.
7:14-16. In the context of Isaiah 7, the disappearance of Judah’s enemies indicates that
Judah shall not fear anymore. It also means that it will be possible for Messiah to estab-
lish his kingdom. The reference to the king of Assyria at the end of v. 17 is secondary,
a redactor being influenced by the subsequent reference to Assyria and its king (v. 20)
in the prophecies that follow the Immanuel prophecy. Seen in the light of vv. 18-25, the
‘Because they have cast away the law of the Lord of Hosts’ 319
prophecy of Immanuel has been read as a prophecy of doom, not as a prophecy of the
coming of Messiah, which I believe it to be. The two passages, Isa. 7:14-17 and 18-25
have been joined because both passages refer to ‘butter and honey’ (vv. 15 and 22). These
references work differently in the two passages. In v. 15, it refers to the messianic meal.
In v. 22 people will eat butter and honey as a consequence of the catastrophe that reduces
the country to a basic agrarian society. However, in vv. 18-25 it is never stated that there
should not be enough to eat. On the contrary, the point is not lack of food but the identity
of this food. Butter and honey are products that suit a society that has been liberated from
the haughty ladies of Jerusalem (Isa. 3:16-17), a bitter metaphor that denounces civilized
(i.e. urban) society.
7. Cf. the Deuteronomistic sermon in 2 Kings 17.
8. Among the many studies contributing to this new line in Old Testament studies, the
following are especially important: Heinz Heinrich Schmid, Der sogenannte Jahwist.
Beobachtungen und Fragen zur Pentateuchforschung (Zürich: TVZ, 1976); John Van
Seters, Abraham in History and Tradition (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press,
1975); cf. also John Van Seters, Prologue to History: The Yahwist as Historian in Genesis
(Louisville, KY: Westminster, 1992), and The Life of Moses: The Yahwist as Historian
in Exodus–Numbers (Kampen: Kok Pharos, 1994). Cf. also Erhard Blum, Studien
zur Komposition des Pentateuch (BZAW 189; Berlin: De Gruyter, 1990), and R. N.
Whybray, The Making of the Pentateuch (JSOT supplement, 53; Sheffield: JSOT Press,
1987), and finally Joseph Blenkinsopp, The Pentateuch: An Introduction to the First Five
Books of the Bible (The Anchor Bible Reference Library; New York: Doubleday, 1992).
320 Biblical studies and the failure of history
9. This is particularly evident in the Book of Jeremiah, cf. Winfried Thiel, Die deuter-
onomistische redaktion von Jeremia 1–25 (WMANT 41; Neukirchen: Neukirchener
Verlag, 1973), and Die deuteronomistische redaktion von Jeremia 26–45 (WMANT 52;
Neukirchen: Neukirchener Verlag, 1981). The best discussion of the place of prophetism
in an exilic environment is probably to be found in Robert P. Carroll, When Prophecy
Failed: Reactions and Responses to Failure in the Old Testament Prophetic Tradition
(London: SCM, 1979), and From Chaos to Covenant: Uses of Prophecy in the Book of
Jeremiah (London: SCM, 1981).
10. Martin Noth, Überlieferungsgeschichtliche Studien. Erster Teil. Die sammelnden und
bearbeitenden Geschichtswerken im Alten Testament (Schriften der Königsberger
Gelehrten Gesellschaft. Geisteswissenschaftliche Klasse 18, 43–266; Königsberg, 1943;
reprint, Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, 1963), 3–110.
11. Cf. texts such as Deuteronomy 4 (some might prefer all of Deuteronomy to be included
in this connection); furthermore Joshua 23; Judges 2; 1 Samuel 12; 2 Kings 17; 21.
‘Because they have cast away the law of the Lord of Hosts’ 321
12. The appropriate decision of the Hebrew Bible to include the historical books from Joshua
to 2 Kings among prophetic literature is based on this inner coherence. The prophetic and
historical books are certainly connected in this very obvious way.
13. Cf. on this, Niels Peter Lemche, Ancient Israel: A New History of Israelite Society (The
Biblical Seminar; Sheffield: JSOT Press, 1988), 175–6.
14. Cf. the introduction to the Book of Nehemiah, Neh. 1:2-3.
322 Biblical studies and the failure of history
means both ‘exile’ and ‘Diaspora’, the common reference to the many Jewish
communities who existed across the Mediterranean, and which defines Jewish
communities as living ‘in exile’. The condition of exile is, to Judaism, a world-
view more than historical reality.
A few biblical scholars today are very sceptical in regard to the historical
reality of the Babylonian exile – at least as part of the Jewish national story.15
Although they may be right, the idea of an exile is part of Judaism’s religion
from its very beginning. It is therefore without consequence for the production
of Old Testament literature whether or not this exile happened in the world of
reality. The exile is by all means the intellectual matrix for this literature. To
liberate the idea of exile from the narrow confines of the sixth century bce and
change it to an everlasting condition establishes new possibilities for under-
standing and dating Old Testament literature with references to the exile. Jews
were not only in exile under the Babylonians, but also in the Persian, Hellenistic
and Roman periods. We should not doubt the relevance of John Van Seters’s
reference to Greek historical tradition and its influence on Old Testament his-
toriography.16 Van Seters believes, in a rather traditional fashion, in an exile
limited to the sixth century bce, when the Greeks had hardly introduced his-
toriography as a literary genre before it was borrowed by Jewish authors liv-
ing in far-away Mesopotamia. Van Seters may be more right than he is aware.
Greek historians (especially of the fifth century bce and Hellenistic period) had
an important influence on Old Testament historiography and we should not be
surprised when we are confronted with Greek mythological and cultic ideas or
with a similar understanding of history as is found in classical historiography
(e.g. in Herodotus).17
A revision of the notion of exile in the Old Testament will provide biblical
scholars with a possibility to change the dates of biblical literature from the
sixth century to the second half of the first millennium bce. If a biblical book
was written in the third or second centuries bce, this does not imply that it can-
not be oriented towards the exile. Moreover, instead of assuming a very short
period for the production of biblical literature, between 587 and 539bce, it is still
15. Cf. Philip R. Davies, In Search of Ancient Israel (JSOT supplement, 148; Sheffield:
JSOT Press, 1992), 78–87. Davies does not deny the obvious, that certain deportations
occurred, which led people from Judah and Jerusalem in Neo-Babylonian times – depor-
tations were standard in those days. He understands, however, the biblical tradition of
a ‘national’ Israelite exile in Babylonia to be an ideological reflection over the past. Cf.
also Thomas L. Thompson, Early History of the Israelite People. From the Written and
Archaeological Sources (Studies in the History of the Ancient Near East, 4; Leiden: Brill,
1992), 417–18.
16. John Van Seters, In Search of History: Historiography in the Ancient World and the
Origins of Biblical History (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1983), 8–54, and
Prologue to History, 78–104.
17. Cf. also Flemming A. J. Nielsen, The Tragedy in History: Herodotus and the Deuter
onomistic History (JSOT supplement, 251/CIS, 4; Sheffield: Academic Press, 1997). I
would suggest that the comparison should go further and include subsequent Hellenistic
(and Roman) historiography. Cf. Chapter 17, this volume.
‘Because they have cast away the law of the Lord of Hosts’ 323
possible to argue that Old Testament literature did not come into being ‘over-
night’. The possibility remains that this literature was written and rewritten over
a considerable period, which covered several generations. It might well be that
the composition of the Old Testament went hand in hand with the development
of Judaism. We cannot exclude the possibility. On the contrary, it is likely that
some of the biblical books are contemporary with other Jewish literature that
was not included in the Hebrew Bible. Although this literature was not accepted
as part of its Bible, it might have been, at the time of its composition, just as
representative of Jewish tradition and religious norms as the books which were
included.
Literature from the ancient Near East is almost always anonymous. Old
Testament books are not. All of them are attributed to pseudonymous authors.
However, the real authors of this literature may leave some indication of their
identity, like a face among the crowd in a church painting of the Middle Ages.
The book attributed to the prophet Isaiah is the product of a very complicated
redaction. It not only consists of three major ‘blocks’ of prophetic tradition,
referred to as Proto-Isaiah, Deutero-Isaiah and Trito-Isaiah, respectively, but
it also reflects a series of large and small inserts. Its redaction is complicated.
In the first part, we find pieces of texts that are clearly more recent than most
of the material included in the next two sections.18 Literature from the ancient
Near Eastern world is generally the product of a tradition. A concept such as
‘copyright’ was not meaningful in early antiquity – it is an invention of the
modern age. The Book of Isaiah may have included many sources from differ-
ent authors belonging to different times and places. It cannot be precluded that
some of the sayings might have belonged to a prophet Isaiah (supposing he is a
historical person). It is, however, certain that large sections are products of the
authors/redactors of this book. To quote Knud Jeppesen, the distance between
the two sayings ‘wasn’t it Isaiah who once said …’ and ‘it was Isaiah who once
said …’ is a short one.19
The question of isolating passages which might belong to the prophet Isaiah
– his ipsissima verba – is not interesting. Staying with the Book of Isaiah as
it is handed down to us, it is my intention to look for fingerprints that may
disclose the identity of the authors/redactors who put this work together. Such
fingerprints may tell us who they were and how they saw themselves. They can
be found in at least three passages. The first is Isaiah 4:2-6, a short passage con-
cerning the future community assembled at Zion. The second is Isaiah 5:8-24,
prophesying to the unfaithful how they will be swallowed by death, because
they do not pay attention to the law of Yahweh. Finally, Isaiah 6:11-13 relates to
the identity of the holy seed which will remain when Israel has been punished.
Isaiah 4:2-6
In my previous discussion of the idea of society in the Old Testament and Dead
Sea Scrolls, Isaiah 4:2-6 played an important part. The new Israel (i.e. the sur-
viving few that take up residence in Jerusalem) is a religious community with
well-defined borders, separating it from the rest of the world. This Israel con-
sists of the few who are ‘written among the living in Jerusalem’. This last line
also declares that those who are not of the select few will perish. The remnant is
‘holy’ and identified with the assembly of Zion, protected by Yahweh as Israel
had been in the desert, alluding to Exodus–Numbers. It will stay in a ‘hut’, סוכה
– another allusion to the Israelites in the desert and the feast of booths, when
the people of Israel lived in huts. This hut is the one that symbolically protects
Zion; the cloud, the fire and the shelter (Hebrew חופהalso means ‘bridal cham
ber’): all these signs of divine presence embrace the holy remnant and create a
mystical relationship between the new nation and its God, making clear that this
remnant is truly God’s people.
The impression gained from this array of mystical phenomena which sur-
rounds the new Israel is supported by the phraseology at the beginning of the
passage. The text speaks of ‘the branch of the Lord and the fruit of the earth’.
This is the only place in Proto-Isaiah where ‘branch’, Hebrew צמח, is used. It
echoes the messianic passages of Proto-Isaiah, where we find allusions to the
new David, such as Isaiah 11:1: ‘And there shall come forth a rod out of the stem
of Jesse, and a Branch shall grow out of his roots.’ Although the King James
version uses ‘branch’ in both passages, it does not translate the same Hebrew
word. In Isaiah 11:1 the two nouns are חטרand נצרcombined with the two verbs
יצאand פרה.
20. Niels Peter Lemche, ‘The Understanding of Society in the Old Testament and in the
Dead Sea Scrolls’, in F. H. Cryer and T. L. Thompson (eds) Qumran between the Old and
New Testaments (JSOT supplement, 290/Copenhagen International Seminar, 6; Sheffield
1998), 181–93.
‘Because they have cast away the law of the Lord of Hosts’ 325
Deutero-Isaiah makes frequent use of the verb ( צמחIsaiah 42:9; 43:19; 44:4;
45:8; 55:10). In Isaiah 42:9 it relates to Yahweh freeing his people from prison
(Isaiah 42:5-9): The new tidings that have been announced will go forth. The
passage is part of the first ‘servant song’ (Isaiah 42:1-9) and is permeated with
messianic connotation. The servant in Isaiah 42 must be the new David. A
number of textual elements connect this passage and Isaiah 11. The possession
of the spirit of righteousness is common to both the new David of Isaiah 11 and
the servant of Isaiah 42. It is also a common motif that the servant/Messiah shall
free prisoners, bring justice to the poor and bring the elected back to paradise
(i.e. to God’s own country or Zion).
The situation in Isaiah 43:19 is very much the same. ( צמחas in Isaiah 42:9)
is connected to the ‘new’ – that is, ‘growing’ – in a context that alludes to the
sojourn of the Israelites in the desert. In Isaiah 44:4, the people of the future
shall grow, blessed by Yahweh, while in Isaiah 45:8 righteousness appears with
salvation. The Messiah in this passage is Cyrus (Isaiah 45:1).
Trito-Isaiah uses the noun צמחonce as part of a metaphor of crops growing,
much like Isaiah 44:5 and 45:8. The context of Isaiah 61 speaks of liberation
from prison (cf. also Isa. 42), the good tidings to the poor and the consecration
of the people of God as priests of Yahweh and servants of God (Isa. 61:6). צמח
is also used as a verb in Isaiah 58:8,21 which combines themes of liberation and
righteousness in a way similar to other passages already mentioned where צמח
is used.
In the Book of Zechariah, צמחhas a messianic meaning. In Zechariah 3:8,
צמחis simply ‘my servant’ who will appear or ‘grow forth’ (6:12). The same
is the case in the Book of Jeremiah, where Yahweh ‘will raise unto David a
righteous Branch’. In Jeremiah 33:15, צמחis used both as noun and as verb,
ואצמח לדוד צמח צדקה. Other passages are relevant to the discussion. It is clear that,
in Isaiah 4:2-6, the assembly of holy ones is not only the remnant spared from
exile and punishment; it is also a holy community, assembled in the name of the
Messiah. Although the Messiah is not mentioned directly, the text is permeated
with allusions and hopes that belong to this context.
Who are ‘the holy ones’ who have been ‘spared’ ( ?)והנתרWho perished? In
the Book of Isaiah, the principal answer to such questions is, of course, that
they were the ancient Israelites, the idol worshippers, whose children lived in
foreign countries and have returned from their exile. Is this answer sufficient?
Is it precise? Was it enough to be accepted within the new Israel that a person
had merely to show his or her pedigree? Were other qualifications required? An
answer to these questions may be found in Isaiah 5:8-24.
21. The King James Version (KJV) ‘thine health shall spring forth speedily’, which is much
closer to the sense than the Revised English Bible (REB) ‘a new skin will speedily grow
over your wound’. The Hebrew text says וארכתך מהרה תצמח. ארוכהis also used in Neh
4.1 about the repair of the walls of Jerusalem. According to the Dictionary of Classical
Hebrew I, 372, the primary meaning is ‘restoration’, which indicates an exilic context
for the passage (exile and restoration).
326 Biblical studies and the failure of history
Isaiah 5:8-24
22. Most commentators agree that Isa. 10:1-4 completes this passage. It is a woe over per-
sons who do not care for the widow, the orphan and the poor.
23. It is without consequence whether this passage is part of a saying attributable to the
prophet Isaiah or to some redaction of the book carrying his name. It is not even important
if v. 24b is a secondary insertion in the passage, as proposed by several commentators
since the days of Marti and Duhm (cf. Hans Wildberger, Jesaia, Biblischer Kommentar.
Altes Testament X/1; Neukirchen: Neukirchener Verlag, 1972), 191. Such commentators
are influenced by the idea that we may be able to trace the words of the prophet Isaiah
himself. Because v. 24b is present in the text as it stands, it tells us how the authors or
editors of this passage looked upon themselves.
24. Cf. on this Niels Peter Lemche, ‘Indledningen til Davids salmer’, in Lone Fatum and
Mogens Müller (eds) Tro og Historie. Festskrift tio Niels Hyldahl i anledning af 65 års
fødselsdagen den 30. December 1995 (Forum for Bibelsk Eksegese, 7; Copenhagen:
‘Because they have cast away the law of the Lord of Hosts’ 327
Museum Tuscukanum, 1996), 142–51. The point made here is that Psalms 1 and 2 are
considered by the editors of the Book of Psalms a single psalm. Although Psalm 2 may
have existed before the editors chose it to introduce their collection, it is now part of the
introduction that presents David as the Messiah of the people of Yahweh. Remember
that Psalm 2 has no introduction like Psalm 3, מזמור לדוד. Why? Yahweh first installs
his messianic David on his throne in Ps. 2:6-7. After that, the following psalms can be
attributed to this Messiah, either believed to be his poems or poems about the Messiah.
That David and the king are the Messiah is certain. When the king is introduced in Ps.
2:2, it is as the Messiah. The connection between Psalms 1 and 2 is finally established
by the inclusio marked by the formula NN אשריthat appear in the first verse of Psalm 1
and the last of Psalm 2.
25. This is the main thesis in Wellhausen’s famous Prolegomena zur Geschichte Israels
(Berlin: Georg Reimer, 1878). To mention one example of the impact Wellhausen has
made upon modern Bible translations, the REB translates תורהin Isa. 5:24 as ‘for they
have spurned the instruction of the Lord of Hosts’ instead of KJV’s ‘because they have
cast away the law of the Lord of Hosts’.
26. Νόμος means ‘that which is habitual practice, use or possession’, and then ‘custom’ and
finally ‘law’ (cf. Liddell and Scott, Greek–English Lexicon, 9th edn, Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1925, 1180).
328 Biblical studies and the failure of history
that was probably never intended by Old Testament authors. They distinguished
between ‘instruction’ and ‘law’ and believed the law to belong to so-called ‘late
Judaism’ (i.e. the Jewish world of the Second Temple – never much appreciated
among Christian exegetes of the past). Ancient Israel, the construction of the
same scholars, was not yet Judaism. The law of Moses did not yet exist, which,
in their eyes, created Judaism.27
Scholars brought up within this Christian tradition never understood that
such a thing as a written law code, to be used in courtrooms (i.e. composed
for practical use) were uncommon in the ancient Near East (if they existed
at all). Law was not ‘law’ in the modern sense of the word and courts did not
function in the way they do today – or, for that matter, in Roman tradition.
It is now common knowledge among Assyriologists that the famous law col-
lections of Mesopotamia were not put together with a practical use in mind.
They were school texts and academic exercises occasionally turned into royal
propaganda.28 Like the Mesopotamian law-codes, biblical collections, like the
Book of the Covenant (Exod. 21–23), did not function as juridical textbooks.
They belonged to a tradition of ‘scholastic’ law that was studied in universities
(traditionally called scribal schools by modern scholarship). In short, legal lit-
erature was wisdom literature. It is this academic law that should be studied
day and night, as is the case in the schools of the rabbis, not because this is the
law, but because it is the source of wisdom and life (cf. Ps. 1:3). Hebrew תורה
means exactly this. It is ‘instruction’ for life. When we disregard the understand-
ing of the law common to Paul and the early Christians, there is no reason to
postulate a difference between occurrences of תורהin the books of the prophets,
in Psalms, or in the Pentateuch and Deuteronomistic literature. Isaiah 5:8-24,
like Psalm 1, does not make a contrast between the pious and the impious. The
distinction made has to do with the student of law and everyone else.
In the eyes of the law student, a person not conversant with the law will auto-
matically be reckoned among the merry fellows who are swallowed by death.
27. A revised view on the content of the תורהof the Old Testament that denies that we can
separate ‘law’ and ‘instruction’ as belonging to two different periods in the history of
Israel will have other consequences as well. The artificial distinction between ‘instruc-
tion’ and ‘law’ is false and cannot be used to date the Pentateuch vis-à-vis the Prophets
and Psalms. We therefore have no reason to think that Psalms and Prophets are far
removed in time from the Pentateuch and the Deuteronomistic literature. This literature
belongs to Judaism. Scholars will have to choose between two options. The first one says
that biblical literature must be part of Judaism of the second half of the first millennium
bce. The second argues that most if not all of it must belong to the Iron Age (i.e. the
period of the Hebrew kings), something still maintained by a number of Israeli scholars
of the present.
28. This is not the place to deal extensively with this issue. Cf. the short introduction to the
theme by Martha T. Roth, Law Collections from Mesopotamia and Asia Minor (Writings
from the Ancient World 6; 2nd edn; Atlanta, GA: Scholars, 1997), 1–10. I deal with the
system of justice in Syria and Palestine in Chapter 13, this volume. Here the lack of
written law is attributed to the socio-political system, a patronage system that did not
need written law.
‘Because they have cast away the law of the Lord of Hosts’ 329
The unfaithful (i.e. one who does not know the law) has no part in the kingdom
of God. He is condemned and, without mercy, shall be placed in darkness. Here
‘they shall pass through it … they shall fret themselves, and curse their king and
their God … and they shall be driven to darkness’ (Isa. 8:21-22).
The identity of the author (or editor) of the passage in Isaiah 5:8-24 is obvi-
ous. In this dichotomy between the faithful and the unfaithful, the author reckons
himself among the faithful ones, the students of law. He has no part in the merry
doomed company and does not share their fate because they have cast away
the תורהof God. There is no middle course between the student of the law and
the multitude of unfaithful, the prey of Death. Our student is found among the
holy ones assembled at Zion and protected by the glory of Yahweh. It is, there-
fore, certain that our author cannot belong to the pre-exilic period. The vision
indicates that we will meet next year in Jerusalem because punishment is over.
Isaiah 6:1-13
A party of law students such as described here has no part in the profane and
worldly life of common people. Such a group is elitist in its outlook: students
or teachers at academic institutions. It should not be difficult to locate such
institutions. The Book of the Covenant’s close ties to Mesopotamian law codes
points at Mesopotamia as the place of origin of Judaism. At the middle of the
first millennium bce, academic institutions had been in existence for more than
2000 years. These institutions are usually described as learned scribal schools.
However, the knowledge of those days – whether literature, mathematics,
astronomy (generally in the disguise of astrology), medicine, law or religion
– was studied in these schools. According to any definition, they were the uni-
versities of their time.
A group of academics as described here will normally look upon itself as
something special in comparison to the rest of society. Its membership will live
‘in its own world’. Its study of the contemporary world will be based on its own
ideas and it will easily be persuaded into believing that the rest of the world is
(or should be) following the same rules as those accepted within the group of
academics. Falling short, in this respect, leads to rejection from the paradise of
the academic circle, involving ridicule and contempt.29
A final example may clarify this attitude among the authors of biblical lit-
erature. It is obvious that the idea of belonging to the elite allows for a self-
understanding that leaves no room for other people. Everybody else can die as
they live. God does not love them! The last few lines of the call narrative of
29. Modern universities, which have developed into industrial plants, producing candidates
in thousands and tens of thousands, have little in common with the universities of the
past. We have merely to travel one generation back in time to find the academic popula-
tion at the universities locked within its own contexts, so-called ‘ivory towers’, where
it was believed that scholarship must be pursued without interference from an outside
world.
330 Biblical studies and the failure of history
Isaiah (Isa. 6:11-13) may contain the clearest formulation of this idea of belong-
ing among the chosen few in the Old Testament.
Many of the problems caused by this short passage have to do with textual
matters, but are not very important in this context. Textual corruption may have
happened and emendations may change the meaning of some parts of the text.
Only major corrections will, however, alter the meaning of the entire passage,
such as if the last line is omitted,30 it gives meaning to the whole passage. The
remnant that survives is ‘holy’. The passage states that when Isaiah asks how
long his people will not understand, the answer is ‘until the cities be wasted
without inhabitants’. If one person in ten survives, the rest shall be destroyed.
Only a stump of the tree will survive. It is holy seed. If we are serious about the
translation of the passage found in modern bibles, this suggests that exile and
punishment has to come. When the punishment is over, only a remnant will sur-
vive. The multitude of the people has vanished. The passage presupposes, first
of all, that the exile is a reality and, second, that the myth of ‘the empty land’
has been accepted. This myth had, however, little to do with the situation in the
territory of the former state of Judah in Neo-Babylonian times.31 It is a myth
created to establish a line of division between the people said to have ‘survived’
the exile and the very few who will become ‘the holy seed’.
What kind of information about the understanding of the world current among
the authors or collectors of Isaiah may be deduced from this evidence? Isaiah
6:11-13 is part of the so-called ‘Isaiah’s Gedenkschrift’ (Isa. 6–9:6). This was, in
a very naive way, believed by earlier scholarship to be the product of the prophet
Isaiah, himself – because of the use of ‘I’ in this section of the book – or at least
of a circle of students very close to their master. This idea of a Gedenkschrift
is impossible. This section of the Book of Isaiah contains several specimens of
Deuteronomistic influence, among these a passage quoted from 2 Kings (Isa.
7:1 being almost identical with 2 Kgs 16:5). It is impossible to quote something
that does not exist. If the Gedenkschrift contains Deuteronomistic phrases, it
can hardly have been put together before – in the classic sense of the word – the
exilic period. It is not the product of the eighth or seventh century bce. The ‘I’
formula is an example of a narrator, changing style. It is not an indicator that
says something about the authors of this section of the Book of Isaiah.
It is a reasonable assumption to consider the passage about ‘holy seed’ to
be an expression of the elitist self-understanding of the law-faithful circle of
authors who brought together large parts of Old Testament literature. These
authors and their circle are the ‘holy seed’. Their membership is extremely
limited, and they do not care because they know the ‘truth’ (i.e. the law of God,
their subject of study and contemplation). To them belongs the coming King
dom of God and they will live on Zion, the mountain of God. It is no concern
of theirs whether the rest of the world perishes in the process. All that matters is
the survival of the people of God.
30. Cf. BHS, Isa. 6:13 f-f- dl – however, without any textual support whatsoever.
31. Cf. Hans M. Barstad, The Myth of the Empty Land: A Study in the History and Archaeology
of Judah During the ‘Exilic’ Period (Symbolae Osloenses 28; Oslo: Aschehoug, 1996).
‘Because they have cast away the law of the Lord of Hosts’ 331
‘The Taliban’
32. Cf. Jer. 31:29-30: in the new Israel there is no need of a collective punishment. Everybody
must answer for his own transgressions. Here the concept of the ‘exile’ has almost the
same meaning as the Flood story – the one of water and the one of fire – in Genesis.
When the water destroyed humankind, it was a meaningless collective punishment:
Human beings were evil and were punished collectively (Gen. 6:11-12). However, they
also remained evil after the Flood (Gen. 8:21). In the second case when Sodom and
the other cities of the Jordan region were destroyed by a fire from heaven, Abraham
negotiates his case in front of God by claiming that the righteous cannot perish together
with the unjust. This is the point made by the epilogue to the Neo-Babylonian version
of the Epic of Gilgamesh: in the future, a person must carry responsibility for his or her
own actions. Collective punishment leads nowhere (Gilgamesh XI, iv; cf. Stephanie
Dalley, Myths from Mesopotamia: Creation, The Flood, Gilgamesh and Others: A New
Translation, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1989, 115). Thus, both Jeremiah and
Ezekiel reject the implications of the famous saying ‘the fathers have eaten a sour grapes,
and the children’s teeth are set on edge’ (Jer. 31:29-30; Ezek. 18:2ff.).
332 Biblical studies and the failure of history
themselves to belong to Israel will be rejected and cast out. They are no more
than abominable idol worshippers.
The Old Testament proposes a programme for the annexation of a coun-
try, including the removal of any person who does not live up to the religious
expectations that relate to this ‘conquest’ of the land of the fathers. The conquest
narrative in the Book of Joshua has a paradigmatic role to play in this context.
It shows that it is in accordance with the will of the God of Israel to destroy
any person who is not a member of the true people of God. Such persons are
condemned and shall be killed because they are Canaanites and placed under
the þerem. According to the Book of Joshua, it is a regrettable fact that the
Canaanites were not entirely annihilated but some were spared. Israel sinned
against the Lord by sparing the lives of a few Canaanites and did not live up to
the expectations and demands of its divine patron.33
The section is called ‘The Taliban’ (an Arab term, from Arabic talaba mean-
ing ‘those who seek [God]’). The title indicates that a parallel may be found
to religious political movements of the present, not least active in the Muslim
world. The members of the Taliban movement in Afghanistan are often dubbed
by the mass media ‘students’, and not without reason. Some, if not all, of
its founding members were law students educated at Muslim law schools in
Pakistan who set out to ‘return’ to the land of their fathers to create the ideal
Muslim republic. To them it is a paradise on earth, to other people a nightmare.
The holy, unpolluted new Israel whose existence is totally absorbed in the
study of the law of God – of course, a metaphor, but one with content – is planned
as a ‘theocracy’, a much-favoured favoured term of the past. This theocracy was
probably never a political fact, although often believed to be so. It was more
a programme for an intolerant society supposed to execute any person who
might not repent, conform and follow the ways of God. Richard D. Nelson has
recently described the content of the term þerem in Deuteronomistic literature
in a different way. He does not take this expression to be a sign of paranoia and
xenophobia, directed against any person who did not conform religiously. He
places the concept of þerem in an old Israelite socio-cultural context, not related
to the texts of the Old Testament.34 This is completely misleading. After all,
the pages of the Old Testament include the demand that a ban is placed upon
every non-Israelite citizen of the Promised Land. They are all condemned and
should be killed to please God. To modify a quotation from the inventor of the
33. On the literary character of the Canaanites of the Old Testament, cf. the last chapter in
Niels Peter Lemche The Canaanites and Their Land: The Tradition of the Canaanites
(JSOT supplement, 110; Sheffield: JSOT Press, 1991), 151–73. Here the argument says
that the Canaanites are the ‘bad guys’ in the biblical drama. The Israelites are no more
real. They are the ‘good guys’.
34. Richard D. Nelson, ‘Herem and the Deuteronomistic Conscience’, in M. Vervenne
and J. Lust (eds) Deuteronomy and Deuteronomistic Literature. Festschrift C. H. W.
Brekelmans (Bibliotheca Ephemeridum Theologicarum Lovaniensium 133; Leuven:
Peeters, 1997), 39–54.
‘Because they have cast away the law of the Lord of Hosts’ 333
Kalashnikov rifle, it is not the text which kills, it is the people who read the text
and wish to carry out its programme.
We do not know whether the Old Testament ‘Taliban’ ever succeeded in cre-
ating their theocratic state. If they succeeded, we should probably identify them
as ‘Maccabees’ who were politically active in a period otherwise dominated by
Jewish nationalism. John Strange has argued that the Book of Joshua should be
understood as a programme for a conquest that relates to this movement and
its aspirations.35 He might well be correct. The Book of Joshua may have func
tioned as a Hasmonean manifesto. But this does not automatically mean that the
Book of Joshua was composed in the Maccabean or Hasmonean period. It could
well be older but understood to formulate a political programme by the people
supporting the Maccabean cause.
It was not the aim of this chapter to present a dogmatic, not to say ‘final’,
answer to the question of authorship of this literature. It is enough to indicate
a way to penetrate deeper into this intricate question. To a great extent, this
literature is the expression of a religious and political programme. Following
the guidelines of the argument in this chapter, we may be close to the senti
ments and ideas which created Judaism as a conglomerate of Syro-Palestinian
and Mesopotamian ideas and notions, and which have been submitted to heavy
Greek cultural influence, sometimes adorned with Egyptian motifs.
Acknowledgements
35. John Strange, ‘The Book of Joshua: A Hasmonaean Manifesto?’, in A. Lemaire and
B. Otzen (eds) History and Traditions of Early Israel: Studies Presented to Eduard
Nielsen May 8th 1993 (SVT 50; Leiden: E. J. Brill, 1993), 136–41.
Index of biblical references
Joshua 2 Samuel
7:16-18 205 5:17 91n
9 109n 7 161
10:33 81n 8:2 186
10–11 81n 8:15 27
19:5 81n 17:25 11
19:21 93n
23 320n 1 Kings
24 297 3:16-28 217
24:25 27 3:28; 6:12; 8:45, 49,
59; 10:9; 11:33 27
4 83n, 318
Judges 4:1 40n
2 320n 6:1 122n
3:15 17, 21, 177n 9:15-19 185
8:22ff. 112n 11 273
9 81n 14:19 309
10:1-5 325 14:29 310
11:8-15 325 15:7 310
19–21 63 15:11 309, 315
15:23 310
1 Samuel 15:31 309
4 89 16 291
4:1‑5 89, 90 16:5 309
4:6 92 16:14 309
4:6, 9 84n, 89, 91, 92 16:20 309
4:9 90, 92 16:27 284, 309
4:9‑10 92 18:3-6 210
8 144, 234 21 210
8:10-18 216 22:17 273
12 234, 273, 320n 22:39 309
13–14 89 22:46 310
13:3 84n, 89n, 90
13:3(?), 19 89 2 Kings
13:3, 7(?), 19 84n 1:18 309
13:3-4 90 3 277, 278, 27
13:4 90 4:1 20n, 40
13:19 89 8:23 310
14:11 89 10:34 309
14:11, 21 84n 11:17 210
14:21 18n, 91 12:20 310
16–2 Sam. 7 183 13:8 309
17:7 25 13:12 309
17:10 91n 14:15 309
17:25 24, 25 14:18 310
22:2 91n 14:28 310
25 140 15:6 310
Index of biblical references 337