Game Theory and The Cuban Missile Crisis
Game Theory and The Cuban Missile Crisis
Game Theory and The Cuban Missile Crisis
plus.maths.org/content/game-theory-and-cuban-missile-crisis
Theory of Moves
Chicken is the usual game used to model conflicts in which the players are on a collision course. The players
may be drivers approaching each other on a narrow road, in which each has the choice of swerving to avoid a
collision or not swerving. In the novel Rebel without a Cause, which was later made into a movie starring James
Dean, the drivers were two teenagers, but instead of bearing down on each other they both raced toward a cliff,
with the object being not to be the first driver to slam on his brakes and thereby "chicken out", while, at the same
time, not plunging over the cliff.
While ostensibly a game of Chicken, the Cuban missile crisis is in fact not well modelled by this game. Another
game more accurately represents the preferences of American and Soviet leaders, but even for this game
standard game theory does not explain their choices.
The Cuban missile crisis was precipitated by a Soviet attempt in October 1962 to install medium-range and
intermediate-range nuclear-armed ballistic missiles in Cuba that were capable of hitting a large portion of the
United States. The goal of the United States was immediate removal of the Soviet missiles, and U.S. policy
makers seriously considered two strategies to achieve this end [see Figure 1 below ]:
1. A naval blockade (B) , or "quarantine" as it was euphemistically called, to prevent shipment of more
missiles, possibly followed by stronger action to induce the Soviet Union to withdraw the missiles already
installed.
2. A "surgical" air strike (A) to wipe out the missiles already installed, insofar as possible, perhaps
followed by an invasion of the island.
These strategies can be thought of as alternative courses of action that the two sides, or "players" in the parlance
of game theory, can choose. They lead to four possible outcomes, which the players are assumed to rank as
follows: 4=best; 3=next best; 2=next worst; and l=worst. Thus, the higher the number, the greater the payoff; but
the payoffs are only ordinal, that is, they indicate an ordering of outcomes from best to worst, not the degree to
which a player prefers one outcome over another. The first number in the ordered pairs for each outcome is the
payoff to the row player (United States), the second number the payoff to the column player (Soviet Union).
Needless to say, the strategy choices, probable outcomes, and associated payoffs shown in Figure 1 provide
only a skeletal picture of the crisis as it developed over a period of thirteen days. Both sides considered more
than the two alternatives listed, as well as several variations on each. The Soviets, for example, demanded
withdrawal of American missiles from Turkey as a quid pro quo for withdrawal of their own missiles from Cuba, a
demand publicly ignored by the United States.
Nevertheless, most observers of this crisis believe that the two superpowers were on a collision course, which is
actually the title of one book describing this nuclear confrontation. They also agree that neither side was eager to
take any irreversible step, such as one of the drivers in Chicken might do by defiantly ripping off the steering
wheel in full view of the other driver, thereby foreclosing the option of swerving.
Although in one sense the United States "won" by getting the Soviets to withdraw their missiles, Premier Nikita
Khrushchev of the Soviet Union at the same time extracted from President Kennedy a promise not to invade
Cuba, which seems to indicate that the eventual outcome was a compromise of sorts. But this is not game
theory's prediction for Chicken, because the strategies associated with compromise do not constitute a Nash
equilibrium.
Further Reading
2/3
4. "Catch-22 and King-of-the-Mountain Games: Cycling, Frustration and Power", Steven J. Brams and
Christopher B. Jones, in Rationality and Society, Vol. 11, No. 2, pages 139-167, May 1999.
5. "Modeling Free Choice in Games", Steven J. Brams in Topics in Game Theory and Mathematical
Economics: Essays in Honor of Robert J. Aumann, pages 41-62. Edited by Myrna H. Wooders. American
Mathematical Society, 1999.
3/3