Epistemology in Art and Beauty
Epistemology in Art and Beauty
Epistemology in Art and Beauty
Abstract
This paper explains how to see knowledge in art and beauty by objectively perceiving the
subjectivity of art. The author uses the theory of aesthetics and mathematics concept of evaluating
art and beauty, while using epistemology as its aligning principle. Various artwork from different
periods will be used to illustrate the theory behind what we essentially call beautiful. The objective
is to critique art deeply by examining its value to knowledge and through other artworks. This
understanding is valuable today especially today’s art whereas artist break the concept of aesthetics
where they value solely on the experience that triggers in the audience.
Introduction
The concrete concept of art has only been around since the 16th century when Giorgio
Vasari, incidentally a known friend of Michelangelo, published his highly influential book called
Lives of the Most Excellent Painters, Sculptors, and Architects (1550). Taking a more greater
value to individual creativity rather than collective production. Within a single generation,
people’s attitudes about objects and their makers shifted dramatically. Now taking notice of the
makers of the art rather than one who commissioned or bought it. It elevated the statuses of artists
and solidified the definite gap between art and craft the still persists today.
Looking into ancient Greece during Plato and Aristotle’s time, the notion of beauty or art
is not clear. Plato suggests that art is a mimicry of things that we see as beauty. Moreover, Plato
thought that the artist could only imitate sensible objects which are themselves imitations of some
form. On his view, such imitation results from a lack of knowledge of the forms, the true essences
of which artistic representations are but deficient approximations. Aristotle, on the other hand,
sees beauty as its own form. The concept of form, especially in terms of formal causality, which
connected the beauty of an object to its form. In other words, an object’s form is the cause of its
beauty. The main difference between Aristotle’s notion of form and Plato’s notion of the Forms is
that Aristotle thought the form of the object was constituted by the essential or species-defining
properties inhering in the object. Plato maintained that the Forms of each thing existed in a realm
In terms of aesthetics, Thomas Aquinas focused his comments mostly on the notion of
beauty. Thomas’ definition of beauty is that beauty is what gives pleasure when seen . This
definition suggests a subjective understanding of what we call beautiful. The ambiguity comes
from this word ‘seen,’ which in turn is concentrated on visual arts. Knowing beauty is not the
result of a discursive process, but a process of visual perception and feedback. Nevertheless, it is
an activity of the mind and eyes. Knowledge occurs when the form of an object, without its matter,
Art can be interpreted of its purpose and function in many different ways. Christianity, like
many religions before it and since, has become involved with the making of art. Its theme has
dominated the European art for thousands of years. It has been clear in using art for an
understandable purpose: to make its message more resonant, emotionally attractive and popularly
appealing. In Thailand during the 15th century, sculptures have made enumerable statues of
Buddha. The purpose of this art is clear: You’re to look at the Buddha and take inspiration,
becoming a little more as he is. Art became an advertisement for its ideas.
For most of its history art has been put on a concrete definition: to glorify religion, to share
its ideas among people or as simply propaganda. Modern art is a result of a swerve because of
these reasons. Art has been revered and yet somehow still in question. Using the words of the poet,
Théophile Gautier, which argues that art must free itself from agendas of religions and
governments. The point of art is always just for its own sake as he put it in French, “l’art pour
l’art”, art for art’s sake. This doctrine of art for art’s sake became the motto of the new generation
of artists. Art is an end in itself and doesn’t try to change or do or speak about anything.
Art can serve as a way communicate thoughts, ideas and feelings, just as written text does
the same. The aim of paintings is to target the mind of the artist and communicate these mental
pictures by visual means. Paintings or drawings can convey a reality unique not only to the artist,
but characteristic of a time, people and culture. Similarly, written communication presents a range
of ideas including fiction, faith, and fact. Although there is a unique reality to any idea once it
assumes existence in the mind. That is why what we as see as reality to be true is debatable. An
artist creates as a way of communicating feelings to other people – oftentimes that can’t be
Art as Knowledge
Art in its technical epistemological perspective is defined as judgement of sentiment and
taste.3 Since art is subject to various interpretations, some deliberate direction must be posited for
relating it to ways of knowing. Just as knowledge relies upon its source for credibility, art relies
upon the artist for its quality. In both cases, the creator’s source of motivation can be examined.
Since each is attempting to convey a truth about reality, we are compelled to query the center of
their beliefs and how they intend to arrive at their conclusions. Such inquiry yields the source of
Immanuel Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason (1781) describes how knowledge can be
acquired by empirical means and discusses the limits of reason. To draw the line between what
humans can and cannot know is the task of epistemology.5 The principles is limiting but can
Scottish philosopher David Hume argues that the important thing about art is its
‘agreeableness’, the pleasure we derive from it, and that this is a matter of our sentiments, not its
intrinsic nature. ‘Judgements’ about good and bad in art, according to Hume, are not really
judgements at all ‘because sentiment has a reference to nothing beyond itself, and is always real,
wherever a man is conscious of it’6 Tackling the question, “is it good?” Hume made it clear that
the truth is a concept grasp in philosophy and art is the presentation and apprehension of truth by
means of imagery.
The question whether art is of any epistemic value is an old question in the philosophy of
art. If art is of epistemic significance, they maintain, then it has to contribute to our quest of
achieving our most basic aim, namely knowledge. Unfortunately, recent and widely accepted
analyses of knowledge make it very hard to see how art might significantly contribute to the quest
of achieving this aim. Therefore, by the lights of recent epistemology, it is highly questionable
Addressing this argument with means of defining art not as in its form, but by its structure.
The intention is not to observe the artwork as a whole, rather by how we can analyze each stroke
part by part to redeem a pattern. Essentially follows to find some form of truth.
The kind of knowledge claim we can have about art concerns the sort of information art
can provide about the world. It is widely accepted that art does, in fact, convey important insight
into the way we order and understand the world. It is also widely acknowledged that art gives a
certain degree of meaning to our lives. Art can elicit new beliefs and even new knowledge about
the world.
The extraction of knowledge in visual aesthetics would require for artworks to have a
having the same common ground. Explanations suggest that one holds itself to a personal truth or
taste simply because they already believe it to be true. This is motivated by the comfort given in
beliefs and is generally opinion or faith-based. The artist uses those visual ideas along with making
his own contribution to the public domain of knowledge that is communicated visually.
and describe them. Among the hardest patterns we've tried to understand is the concept of turbulent
flow in fluid dynamics. As difficult as turbulence is to understand mathematically we can use art
to depict the way it looks. In June 1889, Vincent van Gogh painted the view just before sunrise
from the window of his room at the St. Paul de Mausole asylum7 where he'd admitted himself after
mutilating his own ear in a psychotic episode. In the “Starry Night”, his circular brush strokes
create a night sky filled with swirling clouds and eddies of stars.
Figure 1 Van Gogh's Starry Night, art medium: Oil on canvas, Museum of Modern Art,
New York City
Van Gogh and other impressionists represented light in a different way than their
predecessors seeming to capture its motion. The effect is caused by luminance, the intensity of the
light in the colors on the canvas. The more primitive part of our visual cortex which sees light
contrast and motion but not color will blend two differently colored areas together if they have the
same luminance, but our brains primate subdivision will see the contrasting colors without
blending with these two interpretations happening at once the light.8 In many impressionists works
seems to pulse, flicker and radiate oddly. that's how this and other impressionist works use quickly
executed prominent brushstrokes to capture something strikingly real about how light moves.
have struggled for centuries to describe turbulent flow — some are said to have considered the
problem harder than quantum mechanics. It is still unsolved, but one of the foundations of the
modern theory of turbulence was laid by the Soviet scientist Andrei Kolmogorov in the 1940s.
Experimental measurements show Kolmogorov was remarkably close to the way turbulent
flow works. Although a complete description of turbulence remains one of the unsolved problems
in physics. A turbulent flow is self-similar if there is an energy cascade in other words big eddies
Scientists looked at van Gogh's paintings to see whether they bear the fingerprint of
turbulence that Kolmogorov identified. "'Turbulent' is the main adjective used to describe van
Scientists studied the luminance in Van Gogh's paintings in detail they discovered that
there is a distinct pattern of turbulent fluid structures close to Kolmogorov’s equation hidden in
many of Van Gogh's paintings. The researchers digitized the paintings and measured how
brightness varies between any two pixels. From the curves measured for pixel separations, they
concluded that paintings from Van Gogh's periods of psychotic agitation behave remarkably
similar to fluid turbulence. his self-portrait with a pipe, from a calmer period in Van Gogh's life,
showed no sign of this correspondence. And neither did other artists work that seemed equally
Conclusion
References
1
Healy, N. H. (2003) | Proof of the Existence of God (pp .32-36) Thomas Aquinas: Theologian of the Christian Life
2
Spicher, M. R. | Medieval Theories of Aesthetics | Retrieved from https://www.iep.utm.edu/m-aesthe/#H1
3
Zangwill, N. (Feb. 28, 2003) | Aesthetic Judgment | Retrieved from https://plato.stanford.edu
4
Fekula, M (2005) | Aligning Art and Epistemology: Illustrations to
5
Klinke, H (2014) | The Image and the Mind Art Theory as Visual Epistemology | Retrieved from
https://philpapers.org/rec/KLIATA
6
Graham, G (2005) | Art and pleasure Philosophy of the Arts | Retrieved from https://books.google.com.ph
7
Pickvance, Ronald (1986) | Van Gogh In Saint-Rémy and Auvers | |Retrieved from https://yalebooks.yale.edu/
8
Visual cortex | Retrieved from https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Visual_cortex
9
Ball, P. (July 7, 2006) | Van Gogh painted perfect turbulence | Retrieved from
https://www.nature.com/news/2006/060703/full/news060703-17.html