Hobbes 032323 MBP
Hobbes 032323 MBP
Hobbes 032323 MBP
8]<OU ~ 164650 g
?ELICAN iiLM ***
A 36 7
HOBBES
RICHARD PETERS
HOBBES
Richard Peters
PENGUIN BOOKS
Penguin Books Ltd, Harmondsworth, Middlesex
U.S.A. :
Penguin Books Inc,. 3300 Clipper Mill Road, Baltimore 1 1, Md
CANADA: Penguin Books (Canada) Ltd, 178 Norseman Street,
Toronto 18, Ontario
AUSTRALIA: Penguin Books Pty Ltd, 762 Whitekorse Road,
Mitcham, Victoria
SOUTH AFRICA: Penguin Books (S.A.) Pty Ltd, Gibraltar House^
Regent Road, Sea Point, Cape Town
THOMAS HOBBES
CONTENTS
Editorial Foreword 9
Preface i o
5 SPEECH I
19
6 MOTIVATION 138
IO RELIGION 240
Index 267
EDITORIAL FOREWORD
THE series to which this book belongs is devoted
both to the history and to the problems of philo-
sophy in all its various branches. It is intended for
the general reader, but not exclusively. The aim is
to write at a level which will also interest the
specialist. Beyond this there has been no attempt
at uniformity. The series is not designed to reflect
the standpoint of any one philosophical school.
In recent times the fame of Thomas Hobbes has
rested chiefly his political philosophy, which is
on
principally distinguished by his theory of sove-
reignty. But, as Mr
Peters shows, this is by no
means the only thing for which he is worth reading.
In particular his theory of language remains of the
greatest interest. Hobbes was an exceptionally
acute thinker, and even those who are unable to
accept his thorough-going materialism will find
that they have much to learn from a comprehen-
sive study of his work.
A. J. AVER
PREFACE
THE Hobbes' works used and referred to in this book are
texts of
those edited Sir William Molesworth. 1 The English Works of
by
Thomas Hobbes (edited by Molesworth in eleven volumes and pub-
lished in 1839) will be abbreviated to E.W. and the Opera Latina
13
HOBBES
church door, struck him and fled to London, where he died
in obscurity. Thomas, however, was fortunate in having a
rich, respectable, and childless uncle who paid for his educa-
tion. He was sent to school at four at Westport church and
was learning Latin and Greek at six. At eight he was sent
to a small private school in Malmesbury where a certain
Mr Robert Latimer, *a good Grecian and the first that
1
came into our Parts hereabout since the Reformation',
took a great interest in him and used to instruct him and
one or two other boys till nine o'clock at night.
At the age of fourteen, having already attained sufficient
competence in Latin and Greek to translate Euripides'
Medea into Latin iambics, he was sent by his uncle to
Magdalen Hall, Oxford, where he remained for five years
before taking his bachelor's degree. At Oxford he was bored
by his Aristotelian teachers, though he thought himself a
good disputant had a strong Puritan
at logic. His college
tradition. This may well have perturbed him, though his
later reflections on Oxford indicate that the prevalent
drunkenness, wantonness, gaming, and other vices, which
occasioned frequent commissions and campaigns for reform,
impressed him more than the religious threats to peace.
Later in his life he was to launch furious attacks on the Uni-
versities as hotbeds of sedition planted by the Roman
Catholic Church in the Middle Ages to perpetuate the
challenge to secular power, for which purpose they were
also used later by the Puritans. But it is doubtful whether
Hobbes was politically conscious enough to see them in that
light while he was an undergraduate; rather, if we can
tru$t Aubrey, his interests lay more in trapping jackdaws
than in baiting Puritans. He also preferred going to book-
binders' shops and gaping at maps to poring over theories
of sense-perception. For at this time it was the new and
strange worlds charted by Drake and Magellan that fired
his imagination rather than the intellectual voyages of
'4
LIFE AND PROBLEMS
On leaving Oxford in 1608 Hobbes was fortunate to be-
come tutor to the young son of William Cavendish, Earl of
Devonshire for in this way he was introduced to influential
;
16
LIFE AND PROBLEMS
for his own ends. For to Bacon and his followers knowledge
meant power - power to use Nature for human purposes.
This conviction, shared by so many of the new men of the
seventeenth century and evidenced by the rapid development
of experimentation and technology, is one of the keys to
understanding Hobbes' thought. Like Bacon, he was to coin
some of his most pungent epigrams for the discomfiture of
the Aristotelians; like Bacon, he replaced reverence for
tradition by belief in method, albeit a different method;
and, like Bacon, he believed that knowledge was power. His
hope was to devise a civil philosophy which would provide a
rational ground-plan for the reconstruction of civil society
by those who could penetrate the secrets of human nature.
There is, too, another significant similarity between
Hobbes and Bacon. Both men used language to say things
clearly, pungently, and in order to convert. They believed
that ambiguities in language were intolerable. Bacon refer-
red to them as idols of the market place which lie at the
source of much nonsense and misunderstanding; Hobbes
thought that society could almost be saved by definitions
and tracked down the various types of ambiguity and vacu-
ousness in scholastic terminology which he regarded as
*
they are the money of fools.' For both men the primary
1
'9
HOBBES
the function of the historian was 'to instruct and enable men,
by the knowledge of actions past, to bear themselves pru-
1
dently in the present and providently towards the future'.
The historian, while remaining truthful, should select and
record events which seem most significant for instructing
mankind. Hobbes, in his introduction to his translation,
described Thucydides as 'the most politic historiographer
that ever writ' 2 who 'least of all liked democracy' and
praised the government of Athens most when Peisistratus,
the tyrant, reigned, and when at the start of the Pelopon-
nesian War 'it was democratical in name, but in effect mon-
archical under Pericles. So that it seemeth, that as he was of
3
regal descent, so he best approved of the regal government.'
In his autobiographies Hobbes stressed that he published
his translation because he wished to point out the unsuit-
ability and danger of democracy to his fellow-countrymen.
Had not Thucydides traced the downfall and degeneration
of Athens to the time when representatives of the people
like Cleon, the eloquent tanner, took the place of Pericles ?
In 1628, when Hobbes published his translation, Charles I
had been on the throne for three years and was already at
loggerheads with Parliament led by Eliot and Pym. In 1627
the king's favourite, Buckingham, had been decisively de-
feated at La Rochelle in trying to help the French Hugue-
nots. In 1628 an election had returned a Parliament most
hostile to the King Sir Edward Coke, the great defender of
;
20
LIFE AND PROBLEMS
government' like Hobbes than to publish the warnings
21
HOBBES
major problem; his translation of
Thucydides indicated his
rough and ready diagnosis the;
method of geometry sug-
gested a way of reaching an indisputable diagnosis which
would end for ever the arguments of Arminians and con-
tentious sectaries; the Baconian conviction that knowledge
meant power, with geometry as the paradigm of knowledge,
suggested as a manner of cure the reconstruction of society
on rational lines like a geometer's figure. But this rehabilita-
tion of the body politic required a vision of content as well
as of form; for a new society could not be
constructed solely
out of a knowledge of lines, planes, and solids. And it was
Hobbes third journey to the Continent which provided him
5
what is the heart but a spring; and the nerves but so many
strings; and the joints but so many wheels, giving motion to
the whole body, such as was intended by the artificer?' 1
Hobbes claimed originality for two main parts of his
-
philosophy his optics and his civil philosophy. Between the
time of his discovery of geometry and his return to England
in 1637 he wrote a Little Treatise in geometrical form in
which he tried to give an explanation of the act of sense in
terms of a general theory of motion. Whatever the exact
date of the Little Treatise between 1630 and 1637 - and
i. E.W. III,ix.
22
LIFE AND PROBLEMS
scholars are not agreed about this - it obviously represents
an exercise in the newly discovered geometrical method in
an attempt to solve a particular problem. But why this
seemingly sudden interest in sensation ? At the end of his
prose autobiography he relates how after his study of
1
23
HOBBES
trine as a lynch-pin of the Catholic conspiracy against the
state, and Hobbes mentions in a letter to Newcastle, when
reporting on his fruitless attempts to find a copy of Galileo's
Dialogues in London in 1633, that 'it is called, in Italy, as a
book that will do more hurt to their religion than all the
J1
books have done of Luther and Calvin. . . . In the Little
24
LIFE AND PROBLEMS
about the relationship between our subjective experiences,
our bodies, and the world outside our bodies. No doubt
Hobbes turned to such philosophical puzzles partly because
of his fear of civil unrest and because of his anger at the
mystery-mongering of the Aristotelians which he regarded
as one of its main sources. But to suggest that this was the
main cause of his turning to philosophy is to underrate the
ferment of intellectual excitement on the Continent which
Hobbes shared with other exponents of the new natural
philosophy. It looks as if Hobbes tended to be caught up in
the excitement of theoretical problems while he was on the
Continent and to revert to predominantly political prob-
lems when in England or when his compatriots came later
to Paris laden with English sorrows.
It is difficult for us, who inherit the world-view forged by
thinkers from Copernicus to Newton, to picture the intel-
lectual ferment of the seventeenth century which followed
the gradual acceptance of the heliocentric theory of Coper-
nicus and the law of inertia which was first formulated in
rather a clumsy way by Galileo. And the intellectual excite-
ment was not just the product of replacing one or two old
conceptions by new ones; it was due also to the vast scope
fornew explanations which was opened up by these shifts in
fundamental assumptions. Hobbes' inspiration came from
the law of inertia as well as from the method of geometry
which actually made possible its formulation. 1 What ex-
cited him was the possibility of deducing consequences from
the law of inertia in spheres to which it had not yet been
- sensation, psychology, and politics. When he
applied
speaks in his verse autobiography of his obsession with the
omnipresence of motion, what he was in fact doing was
acclimatizing himself to the fundamental shift in thought
required by Galileo's law. For in the Aristotelian world-
view rest had been regarded as the natural state for bodies.
Things only moved when motion was imparted to them by
a mover. As soon as this influence ended bodies relapsed
into their normal state. But Galileo imagined motion as the
i . See infra, p. 66.
25
HOBBES
They continued in motion to in-
'natural state' for bodies.
were impeded. In other words everything
finity unless they
was moving, including the world itself as suggested by
Copernicus; the problem was to account for why things
seemed to stop moving. Rest was a limiting case of motion.
This was the imaginative idea which so excited Hobbes and
which he applied to the problem of the cause of sense as well
as to psychology and politics.
In 1637, the year in which Descartes produced his Dis-
course on Method, Hobbes returned home stimulated by his
own venture in philosophy and by his contact with Mer-
senne's circle. Like Descartes he was fired by the thought of
a universal system of philosophy. The first part on 'Body'
would outline the general principles of magnitude and
motion and deal with the behaviour of natural bodies; the
second part on 'Man' would show how man's feelings, sen-
sations, thoughts, and desires could be explained in terms
of the peculiar internal motions in the human body in con-
tact with other bodies; the third part on 'Citizen' would
reveal the state as an artificial body to be constructed out
of the movements of men towards or away from each other.
But the course of political events necessitated postponing
this grand design in favour of issuing abbreviated state-
ments to influence the contemporary situation. He arrived
home when the ship-money dispute was raging. The at-
tempt, also, to impose a Book of Common Prayer upon the
Scots caused a riot in Edinburgh in 1637 and led to the
Covenant of 1638, the subscribers to which swore to resist
to the death such religious innovations. War broke out soon
after in Scotland and in 1640 Charles had to summon the
English Parliament in order to raise the money to fight it.
Before they would discuss the grant of subsidies by the king,
Pym listed the grievances which had first to be redressed -
attacks on parliamentary privilege, religious innovations,
ship-money. The king insisted on the prior discussion of
the grant of subsidies and, when it was clear that Parlia-
ment would not consider it, dissolved Parliament on 5
May.
26
LIFE AND PROBLEMS
Hobbes, on his return, was living with the young Earl of
Devonshire, and mixed with Lord Falkland, Hyde, and
other perplexed politicians. No wonder that he turned aside
from his wider speculations and published The Elements of
Law in 1640 during the assembly of Parliament. This book
was circulated in manuscript form and dealt only with
'Man' and 'Citizen', the more theoretical questions about
'Body' being almost omitted. Later, in 1 650, these two parts
were published separately under the titles of Human Nature
and De Corpore Politico. The work demonstrated the need for
undivided sovereignty, but the arguments were taken from
general principles of psychology and ethics rather than from
assertions about Divine Right. Hobbes characteristically
remarked later that his life would have been in danger be-
cause of this publication had not the king dissolved Parlia-
ment - an exemplification of his claim that he and fear had
been born twins at the time of the Spanish Armada. 1 But
Hobbes' fear was that of a self-made man whose feeling of
insecurity and desire for esteem expressed itself in the flat-
tering delusion that men were taking note of him and plan-
ning his decease; it was not an unreasoning panic. Similarly
Hobbes' flight to the Continent six months later, when
Parliament reassembled and impeached Strafford, was the
well-calculated move of a man who sees events in terms of
threats to himself. He was over fifty and confident of a
friendly reception by Mersenne whose circle flourished
under the approving eye of Richelieu, renowned for his
patronage of the sciences. For a man with a major work to
write and who, though favouring monarchy, must have
been aghast at the ineptitude and foolhardiness of Charles I,
Paris presented much better prospects than London. If he
stayed at home, he might well, so he thought, have lan-
guished in the Tower. And his loyalty was not such that, at
the age of fifty, he would contemplate taking up arms if
civil war broke Hobbes prided himself on being 'the
out.
of all
first that fled'. As always his fear was mingled with an
exaggerated sense of his own importance,
i. L.W. I, Ixxxvi.
27
HOBBES
On his arrival in Paris Hobbes was welcomed by Mer-
senne and was asked by him to compose some objections to
Descartes' Meditations in advance of their publication.
Hobbes gladly obliged with sixteen objections from an
anonymous Englishman. Descartes replied, but the inter-
change became increasingly acrimonious; for Hobbes sent
with his further objections a paper on optics, later published
in 1644 in Mersenne's Optique, which was critical of Des-
cartes' Dioptric (1637). Descartes accused the Englishman
of plagiarism - an improbable charge in view of Hobbes'
early fascination with the problem of sense. Hobbes dealt
in a dignified way with these accusations, pointing out that
some of the opinions, which he was accused of having taken
from Descartes - for instance, the view that secondary
-
qualities like sound and colour were subjective phantasms
had been publicly expressed by him as early as 1630. Hobbes
and Descartes actually met in Paris in I648 and discussed
1
28
LIFE AND PROBLEMS
and Descartes, 1 the main cause of the enmity between
Hobbes and Descartes was that they agreed on two doc-
trines which were basic to the new mechanical picture
of Nature - maleria subtilis, an imagined medium between
non-contiguous bodies, and the subjectivity of sense-quali-
ties - and that they arrived at their conclusions on these
issues independently of each other. Both were self-made
men and very conscious of points of prestige; the question of
priority was therefore very important to them as they both
regarded themselves as founders of a new philosophy, con-
sciously discarding an old tradition and making a fresh
start.Paternal pride made them both possessive of their
ideas and blind to their indebtedness to others without
whose intellectual labours their ideas would never have
been born.
Hobbes did not settle down to
After writing his Objections
work away on his ambitious project for a complete
straight
philosophy of nature, man, and citizen, but issued another
contribution to the English controversy. This was his De
Give published in 1642 in which he tried to demonstrate
conclusively the proper purpose and extent of the civil
power. The Long Parliament, after the impeachment and
execution of Strafford, spent much time on a bill to exclude
the clergy from participation in civil affairs and on the
general reform of church organization and ceremonial.
John Milton's tract Of Reformation Touching Church-Discipline
in England had appeared in 1641 and the activities of the
various sects opposed to the Church of England were greatly
on the increase. England was seething with religious in-
dividualism. The De Give was a Latin version of that part of
the earlier Elements of Law which later appeared as De Corpore
Politico] but it was expanded considerably so as to deal in
more detail with the topical issue of the relationship be-
tween the church and the civil power. These religious con-
troversies provided Hobbes with the occasion to express his
29
HOBBES
style of an insecureman, and when he writes about religious
organizations his furious pen seems almost to jab and lacer-
ate the paper as if it were a Puritan or a Catholic. He as-
signed great importance to the religious causes of the Civil
War. In his later work on the causes and course of the Civil
War 1 Hobbes made a list of those who corrupted and
seduced the people and so brought about the war. 2 Presby-
terians, Papists, and the various Nonconformist sects were
mentioned first on his list before the city of London and
other towns of trade, classical scholars, and spendthrifts. In
3
his verse autobiography Hobbes spoke of the interruption
to his studies occasioned by a disease which swept England
in 1640. Anyone affected by it thought that the laws of God
as well as the laws of man were revealed to him personally.
5
This remark epitomized Hobbes attitude towards the Puri-
tan conscience.
Though Hobbes considered his De Give to be a funda-
mental and original work in which the grounds of natural
justice were clearly set out, the fragment surviving of A
Minute or First Draught of the Optiques - a treatise in English
which he sent to the Marquis of Newcastle in 1 646 4 -
makes clear that he thought his optical theory equally im-
portant and original. The former he considered the most
profitable, the latter the most curious of all his work. In
1644, too, he contributed a long section to Mersenne's
Ballistica which amounted to an abbreviated statement of
his psychological theory. This period between the publica-
tion of De Give in 1642 and the completion of the optical
treatise in English in 1646 was spent in the intellectual
haven of Mersenne's circle. Hobbes, now an acknowledged
leader of the new philosophy, was working continuously on
the details of his natural philosophy, the first part of his
trilogy which was later to appear as De Corpore. In his verse
autobiography Hobbes recorded that for four years he
1. Behemoth. Published posthumously in 1682.
2. E. W. VI, 167-8.
3. L.W. I, xc.
4. E.W.VII, 47 i.
30
LIFE AND PROBLEMS
pondered on the Torm' of De Corpore and that the material
was all in order for writing 1 when the Prince of Wale-3 came
to Paris with other fugitives from Naseby. But perhaps be-
cause of his desire to establish himself as an equal of Des-
cartes in optical theory, 2 he turned aside from the De Corpore
to write his A Minute or First Draught of the Optiques and then
external events interrupted his more ambitious project. For,
at the end of 1646, when Hobbes was on the verge of
1. L.W.I,xcii.
2. Sec Brandt, op. cit., p. 190 and Gh. VI passim.
3. Gassendi was professor of mathematics in the College Royal. He
probably exerted great influence on Hobbes' thought. His materialism
stemmed from Greek atomism, his De Vita et Moribus Rpicuri being pub-
lished in 1647.
31
HOBBES
days later, however, Hobbes consented to receive the sacra-
ment from Dr Cosin, who later became Bishop of Durham,
on condition that the English prayer-book was used. This
occasion later stood him in good stead when he was accused
of atheism and heresy; for he was able to refer his accusers
to the testimony of the Bishop of Durham.
Hobbes recovered and contact with the exiled Royalists
stimulated him to arrange for his views on church and state
to be more widely known. A second edition of the De Give
death of Mersenne.
i. J. Aubrey, Brief Lives, p. 151.
32
LIFE AND PROBLEMS
Political events provided a fitting prelude to the publica-
tion of Hobbes' Leviathan. The king was executed in 1649
after the abortive attempt of the Presbyterians to establish
him in power. Up
till
1653, when Cromwell was made Pro-
tector, there was constant discussion and experimentation
to find an appropriate form of government to succeed the
33
HOBBES
connexions, in spite of his claim that his work Trained the
minds of a thousand gentlemen to a conscientious obedience
to present government' (i.e. the Protectorate). 1
On the second issue, the subject's right to resist, Hobbes,
in spite of his general condemnation of anarchy and the
exercise of the individual conscience, put forward a doc-
trine which provided a loophole for both parties when they
were not in power. The subject, he maintained, was bound
to obey the government only so long as it fulfilled its sole
function, which was to govern. At a time of civil strife, there-
fore, it became a nice question for the subject to decide
when he was justified in rebelling because of the govern-
ment's failure to preserve the peace.
The third issue was, perhaps, one of the most interesting
of the time - the status of law. The traditional view, defen-
ded so ably by Sir Edward Coke in his controversy with
James I, was that there was a fundamental law binding on
king and subjects alike, which was there to discover. Parlia-
ment had been regarded as a kind of court, and its statutes,
like the decisions of judges, were deemed to be declarations
of what the law was. With the advent of James I, Charles I,
and especially the Long Parliament, it became increasingly
evident that laws were being made which bore little relation
to the immemorial customs of the realm. Laws were being
made; the fiction could no longer be maintained that the law
was being declared. Hobbes, therefore, like many other reflec-
tive people, maintained that the laws were the commands of
the sovereign. They issued from his will; they were not, as
Coke maintained, 'the artificial perfection of reason'. But
as John Milton, the redoubtable Puritan, held also that
laws were the commands of the sovereign, there was no-
thing very partisan in Hobbes' view; he only differed from
Milton about who the sovereign should be.
On the fourth burning issue, the position of the Church,
Hobbes' views were decided but not unusual. He feared and
hated any religion which afforded the individual an author-
ity other than the sovereign. The Church should be sub-
i. E.W.VII,336.
34
LIFE AND PROBLEMS
ordinated to the state and the sovereign should be finally
responsible for ecclesiastical affairs both in relation to
organization and ritual and in relation to the proper inter-
pretation of divine law and the Scriptures. The Puritan who
appealed to the newly translated Bible or to his own leadings
from God was just much a danger to peace as the Catho-
as
lic who appealed to
papal authority.
In brief, Hobbes believed that the only hope for the per-
manent preservation of peace was an absolute sovereign,
whose commands were laws enforced by judges, bishops,
and thfe military, all of whom should be responsible to him
and appointed by him alone. Obedience to such a sovereign
was always obligatory unless he should prove an ineffective
autocrat. This was a geometer's panacea for peace, the
clear-cut, rational construction of a ruthless theoretician
who thought that definitions and demonstrations could re-
veal solutions to problems which had blunted the wits and
the swords of practical men. And because it ignored many
of the age-long traditions of Englishmen and ridiculed many
of their newly-found convictions, because it smacked of a
Continental salon rather than of an English council chamber,
there was much in it to offend as well as to fascinate any of
hiscountrymen who read it.
The French, too, because of Hobbes' withering attack on
the Papacy, were incensed that they had given asylum to
such a scorpion. One of the first tangible results, therefore,
5
of the Leviathan was Hobbes banishment from the Court
soon after Charles' return in 1651 from his humiliation at
Worcester which ended the ill-fated Scottish expedition.
vide a mere passport for himself. For ever since 1640, when
Hobbes Law to his friends, he had
issued his Elements of
believed that he had drawn up a ground-plan for peace.
The De Give was merely an expansion and the Leviathan a
fuller and popularized English edition of the views he had
them give him the power necessary to keep the peace, what-
ever they thought of his claim to Divine Right. Hobbes was
a dogmatist who believed that most of his countrymen were
either stupid or riddled with various brands of anarchic
individualism or both. Surely the Leviathan is the over-con-
fident appeal of an angry, and intellectually
insecure,
arrogant theoretician; not a querulous hint to an auto-
it is
crat for his fare home. Indeed the importance of the Levia-
than did not lie at all in the conclusions reached, but in the
37
HOBBES
Hobbes' consent. Bramhall was understandably indignant
and in 1655 published the whole controversy under the title
A Defence of the True Liberty of Human Actions from Antecedent
or Extrinsic Necessity. In 1656 Hobbes replied, printing
Bramhall's book together with some new and entertaining
observations on it - his Questions Concerning Liberty, Necessity,
and Chance. Bramhall replied in 1658 with Castigation of
Hobbes' Animadversions and a bulky appendix entitled The
Catching of Leviathan the Great Whale. Hobbes replied to the
latter about ten years later, Bramhall having died in 1663.
The controversy with Bramhall was important in that it
provided scope for Hobbes to make some interesting points
on a topic of perennial philosophical interest. Hobbes' views
are worth studying in some detail, along with those of
Spinoza, because they represent the climate of opinion out
of which so many of the misunderstandings about determin-
ism were born. The same, however, cannot be said for the
other major controversy in which Hobbes was embroiled for
most of the twenty years that still remained to him. Hobbes
had always been an outspoken critic of the Universities. He
thought that they were hotbeds of civil disobedience be-
cause of their Puritan and Catholic connexions. He thought,
too, that much of their old curriculum, inherited from the
scholastic tradition, should be abandoned in favour of the
38
LIFE AND PROBLEMS
Petty, and Christopher Wren were also members of this
brilliant group of men. They were disciples of Bacon both
in their eagerness to explore Nature and in their desire to
use their findings for the improvement of life. United in the
Puritan religion they believed that the end of scientific
learning was the 'glory of the Creator and the relief of man's
estate John Wilkins, for instance, who later became Bishop
5
.
39
HOBBES
Hobbes' original manuscript on squaring the circle the
three abortive attempts at the problem which preceded his
final and futile solution. Wallis specialized in this kind of
detective work he had deciphered the King's papers taken
;
espied him, putt of his hatt very kindly to him, and asked
him how he did.' 1 The King was well disposed towards his
former tutor thenceforward to whom he granted a pension
of 100 per year and 'free accesse to his Majesty, who was
always much delighted in his witt and smart repartees. The
witts at Court were wont to bayte him. But he feared none
of them, and would make his part good. The King would
call him the Beare. . . .
' 2
Hobbes had, in fact, become an
institution.Only once again did he fancy himself in mortal
danger. And on this occasion he had good cause for his
apprehension. For, after the Plague and the Fire of London
in 1665-6, some reason was sought for God's displeasure.
What more likely than that a people should suffer who gave
shelter to a notorious atheist like Thomas Hobbes? A bill
was brought before Parliament for the suppression of athe-
ism and a committee was set up to look into the Leviathan.
The bill passed Parliament but was eventually dropped,
probably through Charles' influence. Hobbes breathed
again, but he was forbidden to publish his opinions.
Perhaps one of the greatest disappointments of Hobbes'
declining years was the attitude of the Royal Society to-
wards him. At the Restoration Robert Boyle had gone to
Gresham College and had acquired recognition for the 'in-
visible college' as the Royal Society in 1662. Hobbes
thought that, in view of his Continental reputation and the
royal favour that had been shown him, he should be made
a fellow. He submitted papers and demonstrations, but was
never elected. This hurt him. But it was hardly surprising
1. J. Aubrey, Brief Lives> p. 152.
2. J. Aubrey, op. cit. 9 pp. 152-3.
41
HOBBES
in view of the fact that Ward, Wallis, and Wilkins from
Oxford were the leading spirits of the Society, which had a
predominantly Puritan membership. Hobbes showed his
resentment by attacking Boyle's theory of the air. His
general criticism of the Society was that they spent too much
time on new fangled devices and experiments and too little
on working out the fundamental theory of motion as
Galileo and Harvey had done. This was a shrewd criticism ;
43
HOBBES
the minutes of his thoughts, which he penned in the afternoon. He
thoughtmuch and with excellent method and stedinesse, which
made him seldom make a False step.
He had an inch thick board about 16 inches square, whereon
paper was pasted. On this board he drew his lines (schemes). When
a line came into head, he would, as he was walking, take a rude
his
Memorandum of it, to preserve it in his memory till he came to his
chamber. He was never idle; his thoughts were always working.
His dinner was provided for him exactly by eleaven, for he could
not now stay till his Lord's howre - sell about two that his stomach
:
44
CHAPTER TWO
46
METHOD MAKETH MAN
methods of social and political organization but also chal-
lenges to traditional ways of thought. Wisdom was not now
something that lay in the past to be gained by laboriously
thumbing the pages of Aristotle or by listening to the
priests. Men were exhorted to find out things for them-
selves, to consult their own consciences, to communicate
with God directly instead of through the intermediary of
the priest. The discovery of America, the improvement of
communications through the spread of trade, the invention
of printing, the development of the new heliocentric theory
of the heavens - all these influences combined to produce
the conviction that there were new secrets to wrest from
Nature and new possibilities for human life on earth. There
were certain exceptional men who struck out on their own
and who thought that the success which they achieved was
due to the method of enquiry which they had adopted.
They therefore wrote up accounts of their techniques to
guide others on the road, and assured others that any
rational man could acquire by himself the knowledge which
had previously been passed on in a tradition. The age of the
manual, guide, and correspondence course was beginning
to dawn. There thus emerged Bacon's Novum Organum and
Descartes' Discourse on Method and Regulae, books which
assured their readers that all men were equal in the posses-
sion of reason and that if they used the proper method they
could not fail to read the secrets of Nature. Of course Bacon
and Descartes disagreed about what the proper method was,
but they agreed on the fundamental point that there was
such a method. Spinoza's Ethics was another such book ex-
plicitly written to guide any rational being along the path
of human blessedness. The parallel in politics had been
Machiavelli's Prince - a book of political maxims written
explicitly for usurpers who were to found new states or
restore existing ones to health.
Hobbes' Leviathan was therefore not an unusual book in
it exhibited the belief that knowledge meant power
so far as
and that knowledge could only be obtained by adopting a
certain kind of method. Its originality consisted in applying
47
HOBBES
man, and nature all at once. Hobbes
this belief to society,
dreamed up a picture of man in society which was a system-
atic delusion, the creature of a rigorous method, rather than
a calm after-image of experience. Perhaps his basic delusion,
which he shared with so many others, was just this belief in
the efficacy of method. Generally speaking our under-
standing of nature and man has not been advanced by
people who have applied a method which could be mastered
or a technique which could be conned. Making discoveries
is not like making sausages. There seems to be no recipe for
5
METHOD MAKETH MAN
putteth any thing into the fire, to see what effect the fire will
produce upon it or not made by us, as when we remember
:
51
HOBBES
'causes' possible by science. Machiavelli's maxims for
made
his prince were only counsels of prudence culled from a
study of Livy. They were as different from a true science of
statecraft as Hobbes' early translation of Thucydides was
from his Leviathan. Hobbes considered that he had, in his
own thinking, progressed from shrewd, fallible, common
sense about his country's plight to the certain knowledge of
the scientist.
From a brief survey of Hobbes' account of what science
or philosophy was not - experience, prudence, history -
something has been gleaned of his conception of scientific
knowledge. It was the product of reason rather than of
sense; it yielded universal truths that were hypothetical in
character; it permitted knowledge of Causes', not simply of
5*
METHOD MAKETH MAN
ing statements logically with each other. Science is 'a know-
ledge of all the consequences of names appertaining to the
1
subject in hand.' It gives us certain knowledge not of the
nature of things but of the names of things. 'The only way to
know is by definition.' 2
This account of reasoning is manifestly a generalization of
the method of mathematics. We start with certain terms or
names about whose definition we agree. We connect these
terms together into statements like 'A man is a rational, ani-
mated body' just as we add together items in an account.
We then find that if we follow certain methods of combining
the statements so created, conclusions follow which were con-
tained in our premisses but of which we were ignorant be-
fore we started our reckoning. We might for instance start
with the definition of 'man' as 'living creature' and of 'crea-
ture' as 'animated body'. We could then argue: Every man
is a living creature; every living creature is a body; there-
53
IIOBBES
in question. 'Now primary propositions are nothing but defini-
tions, or parts of definitions, and these only are the prin-
ciples of demonstration, being truths constituted arbitrarily
by the inventors of speech, and therefore not to be demon-
strated.' l This is Hobbes' rendering of the Aristotelian
method of explanation in which to explain a thing was to
refer to the essential properties of the natural kind or class of
54
METHOD MAKETH MAN
geometry, which is the only science that it hath pleased
God hitherto to bestow on mankind, men begin at settling
the significations of their words; which settling of significa-
J1
tions they call definitions Why should not men do the
. . .
55
IIOBBES
Hobbes himself makes a when he differ-
similar distinction
entiates necessaryfrom contingent propositions. 1 In a neces-
sary proposition like 'man is a living creature' we cannot
conceive of anything which we would call by the subject
('man') without also calling it by the predicate ('living
creature'); also the predicate is either equivalent to the
subject as in 'man is a rational living creature' or part of an
equivalent name as 'man is a living creature'. A contingent
for, as Hume
saw, geometrical propositions may be
necessarily true but need have no application in the world
in which we live. Definitions may be constructed and pro-
positions generated which are indubitable; but what is the
use of them in Hobbes' ambitious project for 'the benefit of
mankind' if they tell us nothing about the world? The
problem which haunted Kant was how it comes about that
mathematical propositions - e.g. Newton's laws - are some-
times true explanations of events in the world. Hobbes,
however, assumed like Descartes that nature had an under-
lying mathematical structure which was not apparent to
sense but which could be unfolded by the definitions and
demonstrations of the geometrical method. But how were
i. E.W. 1,38.
56
METHOD MAKETH MAN
the appearances to be saved ? How could what was ration-
ally revealed be related to what could be seen with the eyes ?
For in the natural and social sciences it is not sufficient to
define terms precisely; we must also choose those 'primary
propositions' whose deduced consequences agree with what
can be observed. Certainly definitions are important in that
verbal misunderstandings are minimized; certainly the
deductive method is employed in exploring the conse-
quences of the postulates with which we start. But observa-
tion is decisive in deciding between such postulates. In this
57
HOBBES
is'sought out by natural reason and syllogisms, drawn from
the covenants of men, and definitions, that is to say, signi-
fications received by use and common consent of words;
such as are all questions of right and philosophy . truth
. .
1. K. R. Popper, The Open Society and Its Enemies, Vol. II, p. 18.
2. Op. cit., p. 282,
59
HOBBES
ism be justified. this, again, would show the relative un-
But
importance of definitions. For agreement about definitions
would then be the symptom rather than the cause of civil
concord.
The stress on the need for definitions is often linked by
Hobbes with the contract theory of the origins of civil
society. In setting up a commonwealth men agree to use
words in a certain way as well as to accept the arbitration
of a sovereign on matters relating to the preservation of
peace. There are passages, however, where Hobbes pushes
this theory of truth by convention to its logical conclusion.
For men may disagree about definitions. 'It is needful
therefore, as oft as any controversy ariseth in these matters
contrary to public good and common peace, that there be
somebody to judge of the reasoning, that is to say, whether
that which is inferred, be rightly inferred or not; that so the
controversy may be ended. But there are no rules given by
Christ to this purpose, neither came he into the world to
teach logic. It remains therefore that the judges of such
controversies, be the same as those whom God by nature
had instituted before, namely, those who in each city are
constituted by the sovereign. Moreover, if a controversy be
raised of the accurate and proper signification, that is the
names or appellations which are com-
definition of those
monly used insomuch as it is needful for the peace of the
;
61
HOBBES
ciple of sense : for the truth of a proposition is never evi-
dent, until we conceive the meaning of the words or terms
whereof it consisteth, which are always conceptions of the
mind nor can we remember those conceptions, without the
:
1
thing that produced the same by our senses.'
Now there are several points of interest in this key pass-
age. In the first place Hobbes makes the interesting and
important distinction between speaking truth and knowing
truth. A
man with scientific understanding must know
truth and not just speak it. This involves not only speaking
in accordance with agreed definitions but also having con-
ceptions of 'evidence' or of the 'meaning' of terms. By
'meaning' he does not refer to the definition of terms by
introducing other terms but to mental conceptions which
are supposed to accompany speech. Whatever the merits of
the theory of meaning here suggested, it is surely significant
that Hobbes sees the necessity for introducing the notions of
evidence and meaning. In the second place it is important
that Hobbes links this very subjective account of meaning
with the doctrine that our conceptions originate in sense
experience. His doctrine of evidence thus preserves a con-
nexion, albeit a very tenuous one, between observation and
knowledge of truth. For we cannot have true knowledge
without 'conceptions' and these are produced in us from
without by our sense experience of things. Names are then
given to the things of which we have conceptions and are
joined together to make true propositions. These in their
turn are joined together into the syllogisms of scientific
demonstration. This working on the material provided by
sense with the help of the tools of definition and deduction
differentiates science from prudence. For the latter is merely
the experience of the effects of things working on us from
without. This may lead to error if we are mistaken in our
perceptions, memories, or expectations. But we are only
guilty of falsehood if we speak. For instance, if we see the
image of the sun in water and imagine it to be there, and
act as if it were there, we are in error. But we only commit a
i. E.W. IV, 28.
62
METHOD MAKETH MAN
falsehood if we go on to call both the heavenly sun and the
sun in the water 'sun', and say that there are two suns.
It seems, then, as if Hobbes thought that true knowledge
or science involved correct speech in accordance with defi-
nitions but that thishad meaning because it mirrored con-
ceptions derived from sense experience. There are two pro-
cesses - and thinking - which go on concomitantly
talking
and which culminate in the enunciation of the basic postu-
which symbolize our simple and clear con-
lates of science
65
HOBBES
manifestly a generalization of the method of geometry. Al-
though much has been said about Hobbes' mistake in
equating the method of geometry with that of physical
science, it was quite understandable in view of the great
contribution of the geometric method to the development
of the new science of motion from which Hobbes obtained
his third characterization of scientific - that it
knowledge
yields knowledge of causes.
There is a sense in whichit is misleading to stress too
66
METHOD MAKETH MAN
merits were very important in Galilean method. We shall
find Hobbes having recourse to them. Indeed this is the
most convincing way of interpreting his account of the state
of nature and the social contract.
We tend to think of Galileo as a lone pioneer at war with
the Inquisition; but a little research reveals him as the in-
heritor of a long tradition of the Averroistic branch of
Aristotelianism that had flourished at Padua for centuries. 1
His famous resoluto-compositive method, which Hobbes
adopted, was taken over from Zarabella and fused with a
new mathematical tradition that had gathered support at
Padua after the translation of Archimedes' works into Latin
in 1543. Hobbes adopted the terms 'analysis' and 'synthe-
for his method which were the terms used by Euclid and
sis'
67
HOBBES
in mathematical terms by deducing consequences from the
laws discovered. The situation has been transformed into
a rational structure of mathematical relations. In view of the
great deductive power of this method, is it surprising that
Galileo and his followers thought of shape, size, quantity,
and motion as the reality behind the appearance of colours,
and other properties unamenable to mathe-
tastes, smells,
matical expression ?
When, therefore, Hobbes spoke of the search for causes
we must bear in mind that his paradigm for causal explana-
tion was the resolution and composition of the Paduan
school. One of his most famous definitions of philosophy or
scientificknowledge occurs at the beginning of De Corpore :
68
METHOD MAKETH MAN
objects, which is little less than to be dead/ 1 Similarly, in
the section 'Of cause and effect' in De Corpore, Hobbes
equates cause with 'the aggregate of all the accidents both
of the agents how many soever they be, and of the patient,
put together; which when they are all supposed to be pre-
sent, it cannot be understood but that the effect is produced
at the same instant; and if any one of them be wanting-, it
5
cannot be understood but that the effect is not produced 2 .
The effect has been broken down by analysis into the vari-
ous circumstances necessary and sufficient to produce it.
69
HOBBES
Such a mental experiment can only be carried out if we
make use of names to register our conceptions and names ;
70
METHOD MAKETH MAN
to explain 'apparition itself, the fact that some 'natural
bodies have in themselves the patterns almost of all things,
3
and others of none at all which had puzzled him on his
,
for the lines and figures from which we reason are drawn
and described by ourselves; and civil philosophy is demon-
strable because we make the commonwealth ourselves. But
because of natural bodies we know not the construction,
but seek it from effects, there lies no demonstration of
what the causes be we seek for, but only of what they may
be.' 2 This explains the link in Hobbes' thought between
71
HOBBES
men in society as a particular case of the motion of bodies
having sense organs and animal spirits.
In general, there is little mystery about Hobbes' theory of
causation; for it was the usual theory adopted by the new
natural philosophers. In his Epistle Dedicatory to the De Cor-
pore Hobbes announced his indebtedness to Copernicus who
revived the opinion of Aristarchus, and Philolaos in his
heliocentric theory of the heavens; to Galileo, 'the first that
opened to us the gate of natural philosophy universal, which
5
*
is the knowledge of the nature of motion and to Harvey ;
72
METHOD MAKETH MAN
motions. 'That and no other is in the proper sense to be
called cause, at whose presence the effect always follows,
and at whose removal the effect disappears.' 1 To all in-
tents and purposes a scientific explanation of an event
amounts to finding the antecedent motions co-present and
co-absent with the event to be explained.
73
HOBBES
be determined. After physics we could proceed to moral
-
philosophy or a study of the motions of the mind appetite,
aversion, love
- whose causes should be investigated. This
science, which we would now call psychology, would follow
physics because the motions of the mind had their causes
in sense and imagination which were the subject of physical
74
METHOD MAKETH MAN
to make up a civil government and 'how men must be agreed
amongst themselves that intend to grow up into a well-
75
HOBBES
this if he were to examine his own mind.
This admission
seems to indicate the possibility of an almost self-contained
civil philosophy depending only on certain axioms of moral
pared his work with Plato's Republic, whose main theme was
that society could not be saved till philosophers became
kings or kings philosophers. Hobbes did not go quite so far
as this. He claimed only that a sovereign who understood
his science of natural justice, which neither Plato nor any
other philosopher hitherto had worked out, could learn to
govern. Perhaps some sovereign would gain possession of
his writing and 'convert this truth of speculation, into the
76
METHOD MAKETH MAN
phy depends upon the acceptance of this assumption.
really
The evidence Hobbes gives is mainly introspective. He asks
us to look into ourselves and to agree with him that these
considerations alone move us to act. Hobbes, like Descartes,
seems to have thought that if postulates are self-evident,
they are true. Men cannot doubt that they are moved solely
by pride or fear; this seems to them to be self-evident when
they look into themselves ; therefore it must be true. This is
surely a mistake; for although some statements that are true
may also seem self-evident, they are not true because they are
self-evident, and many statements that are not true may
seem to be self-evident. The history of thought is littered
with self-evident assumptions that were later discarded.
Newton, for example, tried several other formulations of his
laws of motion before coming back to the one for which he
is famous because this formulation did not seem to him to
79
CHAPTER THREE
Corpore.
The problem which haunted Hobbes is stated in a cele-
brated and striking passage of De Corpore: 'Of all the pheno-
mena or appearances which are near us, the most admirable
is apparition itself, TO
</>alvcrOai ; namely, that some natural
bodies have in themselves the patterns almost of all things,
and others of none at all/ 1 We are familiar with Hobbes'
perplexity about the cause of sense, of which the learned
doctors were ignorant, 2 and of his imaginative idea that the
cause of everything, including sensation itself, was in varia-
tions of motion. His Little Treatise and his early optical
i. E.W. I, 389. 2. Sec supra, p. 23.
80
NATURE AND MIND
treatises were his first attempts at working out this specula-
tive suggestion. The De Corpore was a more ambitious attempt
to solve this problem by constructing a system of principles
which would also be adequate as a foundation for a science
of man and citizen. Motion, which obsessed Hobbes on his
third journey to the Continent, permeated his treatment of
geometry, physics, and animal psychology. Sensation occu-
pied a shadowy central position between the motions of the
external world and the endeavours or minute motions of the
bodily organs.
The De Corpore, then, represented a greatly expanded
version of a picture the elements of which were sketched in
the Little Treatise. But in spite of this expansion the details of
the deductive system were not elaborated with too close a
watch on the appearances. No engineer, after reading
Hobbes, would return to his daily tasks with a clearer grasp
of heat, velocity, or the paths of projectiles. But he might
derive a certain intellectual excitement from Hobbes'
mechanical vision. For Hobbes is to be regarded as the
metaphysician of the new scientific movement rather than
as one of its Whitehead has described meta-
field-workers.
physics as 'the science which seeks to discover the general
ideas which are indispensably relevant to the analysis of
1
everything that happens'. It involves 'the utilization of
specific notions, applying to a restricted group of facts, for
the divination of the generic notions which apply to all
facts'. Hobbes used the specific notions of the new physical
2
84
NATURE AND MIND
of sense, we cannot begin our search of them from any other
phenomenon than that of sense itself. But you will say, by
what sense shall we take notice of sense ? I answer, by sense
itself, namely, by the memory which for some time remains
1
in us of things sensible, though they themselves pass away.'
Hence the great wonder of apparition for without it there ;
85
HOBBES
the attainment of scientific understanding. The second part
analyses the main concepts necessary for a mechanical ex-
planation of nature in general and sensation in particular.
Amongst these the most important are motion, body and
accident, space and time, cause and effect. The third part
is concerned with the details of the various modes of magni-
3. Motion
saw quite correctly not only that his psychology and poUtics
must describe human action in terms of bodies in motion in
order to be deducible from his science of mechanics and
physics, but also that, if his mechanics and physics were to
be deducible from his basic science of geometry, then his
geometry too must contain statements about motion in its
initial definitions. Hobbes' speculative feat was the two-way
extension of motion into geometry on the one hand and
into psychology and politics on the other.
Little need be said about the details of Hobbes' geometry
87
HOBBES
tention, but that he himself was 'the first that hath made the
grounds of geometry firm and coherent'. The mathematical
1
development.
Geometry, then, was the science which dealt with those
simple motions involved in the construction of lines, circles,
and the other geometrical properties of bodies. It paved the
way for mechanics which dealt with the effects of the
motions of one body on another, and for physics which ex-
plained the generation of sensible qualities out of the in-
sensible parts of a body in contact with other moving bodies.
8
Geometry, as has been seen, was a demonstrable science; for
we ourselvesmake the motions which generate lines and
figures just aswe ourselves construct commonwealths; but
we are not responsible in the same way for the generation of
natural bodies, so we have to proceed by analysis to dis-
cover what their causes may be rather than must be.
Causation, or the production of effects in nature, consisted,
according to Hobbes, in a continuous process. There is con-
tinuous mutation in substances which affects other sub-
stances. The fire gets hotter and the bodies close to it are
affected as the heat spreads outwards. It was a cardinal
principle of Hobbes' philosophy that all such mutations
consisted in motion and that 'There can be no cause of
motion, except in a body contiguous and moved
41
He as-
.
i. E.W.VII,242.
a. Sec Laird, pp. 102-9.
3. See supra, p. 71.
4. E.W. I, 124.
88
NATURE AND MIND
hearted attempts to prove it. Action at a distance was to
philosophers of this period an intuitively repugnant idea. If
bodies were not contiguous and yet influenced each other,
contact must be brought about either by means of emana-
tions or through a medium. In his Little Treatise Hobbes
89
HOBBES
inertia first formulated by Galileo with regard to horizontal
90
NATURE AND MIND
having But
in themselves the patterns of almost all things.
greatly indebted.
4. E.W. I, 351. 5. E.W.I,2ii.
91
HOBBES
plained by the propagation of conatus motions in a medium.
Hobbes also used the conatus concept to give an account of
appetite and aversion. Thus, to quote Brandt: 'The conatus
concept enters freely into Hobbes' collective endeavour to
understand everything by motion. What is common to the
different uses of the conatus concept is merely this that it
refers to very small motions; it is therefore used in appar-
92
NATURE AND MIND
pleaseth it. And endeavour, when it tends towards
this first
such things as are known by experience to be pleasant, is
called appetite, that is, an approaching; and when it shuns
what is troublesome, aversion, or flying from it.' 1 Appetite
and aversion are thus the first endeavours of animal motion.
The postulation of these minute movements in the bodies of
animals and men made the suggestion plausible that human
action as well as the movement of projectiles can be ex-
plained mechanically. After all men move towards and away
from objects and each other. And just as there are minute
incipient movements involved in resistance, weight, and
93
HOBBES
all mankind, a perpetual and restless desire of power after
power, that ceaseth only in death.' The prospect of the ces-
1
94
NATURE AND MIND
observed played a very important part in his explanations.
For 'endeavours' were movements of such minute un-
observable bodies. Of course the ordinary man calls some-
thing a body which he can touch or see; but he has not
achieved scientific understanding.
Hobbes maintained that there was nothing else in the
world but bodies. How, then, did he deal with the claims of
theologians that there are spirits or incorporeal substances
also? In Leviathan Hobbes boldly equated 'substance* with
c
away, the body also would perish. All other accidents are
appearances either of motions of the mind of the perceiver
or of the bodies themselves which are perceived.
This account of accident was a weak point in Hobbes'
philosophy; for his definition of accident as 'the manner by
i. E.W. III, 381. 2. E.W. IV, 313. 3. E.W. I, 103.
95
HOBBES
which any body is conceived' overlooked the status of ex-
tension and figure which was quite different from that of all
'
other accidents. For these are defining attributes of 'body ;
96
NATURE AND MIND
explanation of them in terms of bodies characterized by
primary qualities.
The explanation of this lack of consistency in Hobbes'
treatment is probably that he never seriously questioned the
underlying assumptions of the new science of motion. He
accepted without question the underlying presupposition
that the real world was characterized only by those quali-
ties, called the primary ones, which were susceptible to
mathematical treatment in the sciences of geometry and
mechanics. They are also qualities which are accessible
through more than one sense modality. This methodological
convenience, which was his underlying criterion of distinc-
tion,was exalted by all members of the new movement into
a metaphysical postulate about the reality behind the
appearances. But he, like Descartes and Locke, got into
difficulties when he tried to rationalize this criterion in
terms of the conceivability of bodies with some qualities rather
than with others. For his underlying concept of 'body' was
that defined by the postulates of the mathematical sciences.
As soon as he started bringing in questions of conceiva-
bility the common-sense notion of body insinuated itself
with ensuing havoc to the unassailable status of the scien-
tist's 'body'. Berkeley was later to take his stand on common-
97
HOBBES
tasm'. He defines space phantasm of a thing existing
as 'the
without the mind simply'. 1 By this he meant that what we
call space is the appearance of externality. He maintained
that it was a phantasm because if the world of physical
things were to be destroyed and a man were to be left alone
with his imaginations and memories, some of these would
appear external to him, or located in space, which must
therefore be a subjective frame of reference. This conviction
is reinforced by the consideration that 'when we calculate
98
NATURE AND MIND
(psychological space) and the co-ordinate systems construc-
ted by physical scientists. It may well be the case that what
we call space and time are abstractions from our experience
of extended bodies in motion. But what is the relationship
between such private frames of reference which are notor-
iously unreliable and the dependable inter-subjective con-
structs of the scientist? Hobbes typically failed to see the
99
HOBBES
technical contexts and them to bridge gaps in his
to use
100
NATURE AND MIND
consequences. Hobbes never produced such a theory. In-
stead he produced a redescription of what we already know
in rather a bizarre terminology or descriptions which seem
absurd because of the inapplicability of mechanical con-
cepts. Certainly his enthusiastic diffusion of the concepts of
mechanics involved him in the dubious extension of the
3
term 'endeavour to bridge the gap between minute
motions and animal strivings; it also occasioned a cavalier
disregard for whether thoughts and feelings were motions
of the brain and corporeal organs or just accompaniments
of them, a disregard that was fostered by his terminology of
movement. In general such an extension of the concepts of
a science, without developing another science for the new
sphere covered by the extrapolation, will lead to constant
perplexities created by the clash between the technical
meaning of terms and their common-sense usage. This is
particularly in evidence in Hobbes' treatment of 'body' and
its 'accidents' and in his tantalizing treatment of space and
101
CHAPTER FOUR
Introductory
I O2
SENSE AND IMAGINATION
political thinker, was an interesting mino- philosopher'.
This verdict on Hobbes is also a comment on the modern
/. Sense
103
HOBBES
of the more obvious characteristics of perception as we
experience it. And some of these are bound to prove
troublesome for any such mechanical theory; for when we
perceive something, it is not just an atomic event initiated
by an external stimulus. There is always an element of
recognition in perception; we select and group what is
before us in the light of our past experience and present
interests. Hobbestried to account for recognition and
mechanical terms. Perception, he said, is not
selectivity in
a simple reaction of bodies. If it were so, all bodies that
react would have sense, a theory that some philosophers
have actually suggested. But a simple reaction requires the
constant presence of the object to which the reaction is
made. The phantasm, if it could be produced by the reac-
tion of an inanimate body, would cease as soon as the object
was removed. Sense organs relieve us from the necessity of
constant contact; for they act as retainers for the move-
ments of external bodies which bump into us and pass on
their way. Without such retention of motions what we call
sense would be impossible; for 'by sense we commonly
understand the judgement we make of objects by their
phantasms namely, by comparing and distinguishing those
;
104
SENSE AND IMAGINATION
one object rather than another selected from amongst the
many possible objects that could be perceived on any
occasion? Hobbes said nothing of the interests and atti-
tudes which predispose us to see some things rather than
others. Indeed his idco-motor theory made it very difficult
for him to do so for according to this theory all reactions of
;
105
HOBBES
These rather sketchy remarks about sensation exhibit
1
Hobbes interest in it as limited to a phenomenon that can
be mechanically explained. Like the British Empiricists who
followed him, he was a martyr to the current physiological
account of sensation according to which objects imprinted
themselves on us by isolated, disconnected sorties on our
sense-organs. Hobbes ingeniously combined this sort of
account with deductions from the theory of motion. It is
true that he tried to explain phenomena like attention,
selectivity, and the ineradicable intrusion of past experience
into present perceptions. But the limitations of his mech-
anical hypothesis precluded him from giving these aspects
of perception the attention they deserve.
We must now pass to the other facet of Hobbes' limited
interest in sensation his view that secondary qualities were
subjective appearances of the movements of bodies having
only primary qualities. In his early Elements of Law Hobbes
stated succintly, using the example of colour, the main
points of his contention :
(1) That the subject wherein colour and image are inherent, is
not the object or thing seen.
(2) That that is nothing without us really which we call an
image or colour.
(3) That the said image or colour is but an apparition unto us
1 06
SENSE AND IMAGINATION
caused by the primary properties of external objects inter-
acting with our sense-organs but representing nothing outside
us. He adduced in support of this claim facts like double
tance, the real and very object seem invested with the fancy
it begets in us; yet still the object is one thing, the image or
1
fancy is another.'
Hobbes, however, wished to establish that secondary
qualities were subjective in a further sense - the sense in
which the distinction between a quality and our representa-
tion of a quality cannot be made. For he maintained that
in the case of secondary qualities what we call qualities of
107
HO HUES
between primary and secondary qualities. For it is absurd
to make such generalizations about the relativity of percep-
tion to the individual percipient without taking into account
the conditions of perception and the state of the percipient.
All cows look grey in the twilight and there are objective
tests for establishing that a man is colour-blind. Also, as
i. El. of L., p. 6.
1 08
SENSE AND IMAGINATION
rabbits of the new
science of motion popped out of the hat.
He was the arch-metaphysician of motion.
The basic trouble with Hobbes' philosophical arguments
was that he never examined the relationship of 'represent-
ing'which he presupposed in his wonder that some natural
bodies had in themselves the patterns of all things. Presum-
ably he thought that there was nothing mysterious about a
phantasm, which is a motion in some internal substance of
the head, being a pattern of motions in external bodies. He
never asked himself, as Berkeley was later to ask Locke, how
we could ever know that such a pattern was a correct pat-
tern of an external body if we could never know anything of
an external body except by means of our private patterns of
it.Hobbes may have thought that as a motion can only
produce another motion, so a motion (in this case a phan-
tasm) could never represent anything like a colour unless it
was also a motion. But it does not seem that he was ever
much troubled by this kind of problem. He simply deve-
loped a causal theory of sensation and saw no need for a
theory of representation.
Hobbes, therefore, in his theory of phantasms, took the first
step down the path that was to be trodden later by so many
of his countrymen but he neither saw nor pursued the impli-
;
from the opening of the Elements of Law, and from the pass-
ages on heat and light and so on in the fourth part of De
Corpore, Hobbes was greatly intrigued by current explana-
tions of secondary qualities; it looks as if his interest in
1 10
SENSE AND IMAGINATION
2. Imagination
in
HOBBES
The suggestion is made, also, that a mechanical explana-
tion can be given for the more impressive feats of the
1 1 12
SENSE AND IMAGINATION
ifconviction of pastness distinguishes memory from imagi-
nation, would we be said to remember a street in a certain
town when we were convinced that we had seen it before
while all the evidence from our previous travels indicated
that we could never have been there ?
Many have attempted to give subjective criteria like
114
SENSE AND IMAGINATION
ity which many have thought to be implicit in it. He had
the insight to see that such trains of thought are unimpor-
tant in comparison with those regulated by some desire or
design. For a seventeenth-century thinker it would have
required something akin to clairvoyance or pre-cognition to
suggest that even apparently wild rangings of the mind
were controlled by desire. For at this period it was unthink-
able that a desire could be unconscious. Too many people
criticize Aristotle and Aquinas for not having read Darwin,
and Hobbes and Hume for ignoring Freud.
Hobbes' account of regulated thinking owed a lot to and
was an improvement on Aristotle's analysis of deliberation.
Desire for an end holds the train of thought together and
determines the relevance of its content. Hobbes suggested
that the strength of the attraction of the end is so great that
it not only
prevents our thoughts from wandering but some-
times even prevents or hinders our sleep. There are two
main types of regulated thinking. One is the classic Aristo-
telian type where desire provides us with an end and we work
backwards with the planning of means until we come to an
action which it is in our power to perform here and now.
Hobbes instanced searching the mind for a place to begin
looking for something that has been lost, 'or as a spaniel
ranges the field, till he finds a scent; or as a man should run
over the alphabet, to start a rhyme. u This search for the
means of producing an end or faculty of invention is shared
by the animals. Man, however, is alone capable of the other
kind of regulated thinking which Hobbes called prudence.
For animals have no curiosity - only sensual passions like
hunger, thirst, lust, and anger. In prudence we do not work
from an end but start from an action within our power and
use our store of past experience to speculate about its prob-
able effects. 'As he that foresees what will become of a
criminal, reasons what he hath seen follow on the like crime
before; having this order of thoughts, the crime, the officer,
the prison, the judge, and the gallows.' 2 Deliberation in
this case leads on to an end which is either desired or feared.
i. E.W. Ill, 14. 2. E.VV. Ill, 14, 15.
"5
HOBBES
This a very valuable addition to Aristotle's analysis;
is
116
SENSE AND IMAGINATION
the internal motion which makes the phantasm in the
absence of external stimulation, and the making up with
'other fictitious parts' of the parts of our phantasms which
are decayed and worn out by time. Fourthly, when we
dream we 'admire neither the places nor the looks of the
1
things that appear to us'. Neither is our wonder aroused at
rinding ourselves in a strange place without consciovisness of
how we came there. This is because wonder presupposes
comparison with the past whereas in sleep all things appear
as if the)* were present. Fifthly, we never remark on the
i. E.W. Ill, 9.
118
CHAPTER FIVE
SPEECH
Introductory
"9
HOBBES
whom the theories of metaphysicians have provided genera-
tions of ghosts to be exorcized by linguistic analysis.
Most prominent amongst the cherished doctrines of the
Schools was the theory of universals which, according to
Hobbes, encouraged belief in mysterious entities and so
perpetuated the superstitious hold of the Catholic Church
on the minds of men. 'It is to this purpose, that men may no
they say his soul, that is his life, can walk separated from
his body, and is seen by night amongst the graves. Upon the
same ground they say, that the figure, and colour, and taste
of a piece of bread, has a being, there, where they say there
is no bread. And upon the same ground they say, that faith,
the case for fire. A more fruitful suggestion was that the
differences in nature as it appeared to the senses were due
to different mathematical combinations of the underlying
121
HOBBES
why things are as they are and behave as they do. Hence the
great importance of essences in Aristotelian thought. The
mathematical road of the atomists to the One in the Many
was rejected; instead, science must aim at a vast catalogue
- i.e. names of in-
consisting in definitions of all essences
Jimae species like 'man' or 'horse' plus their defining formulae.
Explanation of the behaviour of a thing consisted in looking
up the essential properties of the natural kind or class of
i. E.W. 111,678.
122
SPEECH
being necessary to postulate a realm of occult essences which
they were alleged to designate.
123
HOBBES
that they are what are often called natural signs. And
Hobbes distinguished natural signs from arbitrary ones. A
thick cloud is a natural sign of rain. Similarly animals use
natural signs when they give warnings of danger or sum-
monses to food. These noises burst forth from the animals
in certain typical predicaments. There is very little variety
in them because their predicaments and nature are similar
the world over. But human language comes about through
decision and the signs employed are arbitrary, 'namely, those
we make choice of at our own pleasure, as a bush hung up,
5
1
signifies that wine is to be sold there Animals may under-.
124
SPEECH
animals, even if he did violence to the ordinary use of the
term 'reason'.
The arbitrariness of speech, which distinguishes it from
animal signs, is one of Hobbes' favourite themes. Speech,
like civil society, is an not a natural
artificial construction,
'25
HOBBES
contrast the arbitrariness of human speech with the
'natural necessity' of that of animals.
Hobbes saw that speech has many specific uses as well as
the general one of transferring 'the train of our thoughts
into a train of words'. Itis used to register what we find to
be the cause of any thing and its effects, to share this know-
ledge with others, to make known our wills and purposes so
as to ensure mutual help, and to please and delight our-
selves and others by playing with words. Hobbes' main in-
by a name.
designated
Hobbes' position with regard to universal names of bodies
was radically nominaiistic. Indeed, he should have said
that names stood for pictures of 'one thing only' or of
'divers particular things'. For according to his definition of
names they were signs of our conceptions of things, not of
things themselves. It is obvious that words are not signs of
things themselves, for 'that the sign of this word stone should
be the sign of a stone cannot be understood in any sense but
this, that he that hears it collects that he that pronounces it
127
HOBBES
were those which stood for images having this indeterminate
character. But Hobbes, like Berkeley, maintained that all
'
128
SPEECH
for their similitude insome quality, or other accident'. 1 So
obviously his account of names of properties like 'extended'
is very important. Many have held that it was inconsistent
that the man, and the living body is the same thing; because
the consequence, if he be a man, he is a living body, is a true
consequence, signified by that word is. Therefore, to be a
body, walk, to be speaking, to live, to see, and the like infini-
to
tives; also corporeity, walking, speaking, life, sight, and the like,
that signify just the same, are the names of nothing.' 3
Hobbes' treatment of the copula is interesting; for he
seems to have adumbrated later attempts to remove the
ambiguities of the word 'is'. There is a sense of 'is' or 'ex-
ists* which assigns a date and a place to something. If we say
130
SPEECH
and always if X is man then X is a living body*. We arc not
a
committing ourselves to the existence of men in the first
sense of'is' or 'exists'. We
could equally well say 'centaurs
are four-legged animals'. Hobbes suggested that terms like
'moved' and 'extended' refer to accidents of bodies as they
are caused by them through the intermediary of concep-
tions, just as do terms like 'stone' and 'tree' which are names
of bodies. When propositions are invented the copula of
class-inclusion enables us to calculate and reason about the
accidents of bodies without having to move them about or
have them actually in front of us. But people are misled by
the copula into thinking that 'is' refers to an entity or
essence. Thus, when they use abstract terms like 'motion' or
ever, had one great strength and two great weaknesses. Its
i. See E.W. I, 66-9. 3. E.W. I, 68.
a. See J. Laird, Hobbest p. 148.
X32
SPEECH
strength consisted in its exposure of the redundancy of
abstract entities, which, in his view, rested on the fallacy of
treating universal names as if they were a species of proper
names, distinguished by the status of the entities which they
were alleged to designate. No one disputes that there are
bodies, that they are extended, and move about. Sometimes
we use a name like 'Churchill' to designate one of them; at
other times we use a name like 'man' to designate any body
conforming to the expectations we have which can be
verbalized in the definition or connotation of 'man'. Dogs
can be taught the difference between these two classes of
names; and they have no inward eye, as far as we know, to
intuit essences. For on hearing a certain kind of whistle a
dog can be trained to expect his master and no one but his
master, Mr Brown. Yet, on hearing a different kind of
whistle, he can be trained to expect any object which he will
be able to eat - i.e. conforming to certain criteria which
could be verbalized in a connotation. Without such univer-
sal names language would be of very limited value; for it
would merely be a mass of proper names reduplicating all
the bodies we happened to encounter. But the fact that we
can use such universal names does not necessitate the
- that there
explanation which is often given of this fact
must be essences designated by the names in the same way
as individuals are designated by proper names. Hobbes
133
HOBBES
do its main job - to show that, on the assumption about
names shared both by himself and his opponents, the postu-
lation of abstract entities to account for the differences be-
tween singular and universal names was superfluous.
The major weakness of his account sprang from his fas-
cination with phantasms and with mechanical explanations.
Words were for him marks which could be manipulated like
a mathematician's counters. They are caused by external
things through the intermediary of phantasms, the word
standing for the private phantasm and yet somehow caused
by it. He spoke of accidents as the causes of concrete names
just as they are the causes of our conceptions. But he also
spoke of names as denoting bodies and accidents. But he
never examined the logical relations expressed by terms like
'denote', 'refer to', and 'designate', any more than he ex-
amined the relation of representation in his account of
phantasms. It may well be that there is little that can be
said about a relation like that expressed by the term 'refer-
ring', it being a primitive relation which cannot be ex-
plained in terms of anything simpler and for which most
analogies are unilluminating. But it certainly does not help
to muddle it with a causal relation. For though perhaps a
causal explanation can be given for words which, like the
signs of animals and birds, have only an expressive or an
evocative function, it seems fantastic to suggest that a
descriptive language, with all its artificiality and arbitrari-
ness, can be causally explained simply by the movements of
bodies impinging on the sense-organs. Hobbes set his face
against this suggestion when he contrasted the arbitrariness
of human language with the 'natural necessity' of animal
signs. But at times his obsession with mechanical explana-
tions led him to ignore the implications of his own insight.
For the possession of reason, which enables men to construct
descriptive languages, makes men different from moving
bodies as well as from brutes.
The second weakness in his account was the presumed
intermediary of phantasms between things and names which
was part and parcel of his peculiarly private theory of
134
SPEECH
meaning. derived from his general view that we are con-
It
fronted with our own phantasms of things, not with things
themselves, and from his mechanical theory. He thought
that our conceptions are marked by names which are like
signposts rearing themselves out of an unfamiliar country;
these marks, when uttered as words, bring to the minds of
those whohear them similar conceptions as they, too, go on
their journeys. But this presupposes not only that the speaker
and the hearer always have a similar conception when they
hear a word, but also that they always have some conception.
And by 'conception' Hobbes meant a concrete determinate
image. Both these assumptions seem plainly false. For words
evoke all sorts of different imagery in different people and,
as was demonstrated with great labour by the Wiirzburg
school of introspective psychologists, 1 talking and problem-
solving can be carried on perfectly well without any deter-
minate imagery at all. In his account of evidence 2 Hobbes
suggested that meaningful talk was different from parrot-
talk in that our words mirrored our conceptions. Is this
135
HOBBES
not by God but by our failure to understand the function of
the copula. We have also seen that he thought that a great
deal of mental confusion was the product of failure to start
fiom agreed definitions. But more interesting than either of
these suggestions was his view that metaphysicians are led
into absurdities by being insensitive to the logical behaviour
of different classes of words.
Hobbes believed, roughly speaking, that names could
name bodies, accidents, or names. Now if one of these classes
of names were used as if it belonged to another class, all
sorts of confusions were likely to be propagated. For in-
136
SPEECH
histheory of names was a bludgeon for pulverizing some of
the more extravagant verbal structures of the schoolmen
and a crude theory of meaning modelled on what he thought
to be the practice of those whose thoughts were limited to
the contemplation of bodies in motion. And this was more
or less all that he set out to do in constructing a theory of
names.
'37
CHAPTER SIX
MOTIVATION
Introductory
139
HOBBES
1
possible, be quite taken away'. Similarly, in the case of
2
pleasure the spirits are guided by the help of the nerves to
preserve and augment the motion. When this endeavour
tends towards things known by experience to be pleasant, it is
called an appetite; when it shuns what is painful, it is called
aversion. Appetiteand aversion are thejirst endeavouis of ani-
mal motion. They are succeeded by the flow of animal spirits
into some receptacle near the 'original' of the nerves which
brings about a swelling and relaxation of the muscles
causing contraction and extension of the limbs, which is
animal motion.
There are some appetites and aversions which are born
with men 'as appetite of food, appetite of excretion and
exoneration, which may also and more properly be called
aversions, from somewhat they feel in their bodies and some ;
other appetites, not many'. 3 These sound very much like the
'drives' about which so much has been heard in recent
4
psychological theorizing. But even in these cases Hobbes
thought that the initiation of movement was from without.
Food seen causes the organism to move towards it. This
sounds an insufficient account of the matter. For there is
good evidence to suppose that organisms are born with in-
nate needs which predispose them to seek out and pay atten-
tion to some features of their environment rather than
1. E.W.I, 407.
2. The notion of 'spirits' is whose work the
to be found in Galen, in
tradition of the Pneumatists reached culmination. Life is due to
its
'spirit' which charges the blood at the key centres of the body
- the liver,
the heart, and the brain. Blood, which was produced by the liver and
charged with natural spirits, met air from the lung at the heart and be-
came Vital spirits' to be distributed by the arteries. Some of these went
to the brain where they became transformed into a third type of spirits,
'animal spirits'. These were distributed by the nerves which were pic-
tured as hollow tubes. Hobbes, like Descartes, abandoned this picture on
account of Harvey's discovery of the circulation of the blood. But he still
retained the notion of animal spirits coursing through the nerves as the
means by which animal motion was propagated.
3. E.W. Ill, 40.
4. See G. Hull, Principles of Behaviour ; E. Tolman, Purposive Behaviour
in Animah and Men ; and P. T. Young, Emotion in Man and Animal.
140
MOTIVATION
1
others, and to move towards
or away from them in ways
which need not be learnt. And, as we said in commenting on
Hobbes' account of sensation, only those external stimuli
register which relate to the needs of the organism.
Hobbes' account of the increase and decrease in vital
motions was also vague. Yet this was a crucial point in his
transition from physiology to psychology. His suggestion was
that increase in vital motions round the heart, occasioned
by contact with an external object, is felt as pleasure or pain.
He was referring to movements of Vital spirits' in what we
would now call the autonomic nervous system. But surely
there is not a simple correlation between increase in such
internal motions and pleasure; some pains are accompanied
by a great increase in vital motion. Hobbes must have meant
more than the simpleincreasing or impeding of motion, but
doubtful whether his account, as it stands, amounts to
it is
141
HOBBES
this observation not merely Hobbes' devotion to motion;
is
by foresight of the end. This is not the case. There is, first of
all, the ambiguity already noted in the concept of 'end'
which can mean the object of pursuit or the state of satisfac-
tion which follows the capture of the quarry. Behaviour is
seldom initiated by foresight of an end of the second sort.
Huntsmen are lured by thoughts of killing foxes, not by
thoughts of the satisfaction of having killed them. But more
important are the cases where we move towards ends in the
first sense which we do not consciously envisage as objec-
ally decided to stay in bed that he did not exert his will.
Rather it is deliberation carried on under the aegis of self-
regard, in which self-regard reinforces what Hobbes called
an appetite and enables it to be the last one in the field.
3. The Passions
For Hobbes love and hate were more or less the same as
144
MOTIVATION
such a complicated set of assumptions. Hobbes' model of
explanation is plausible, perhaps, for what we call 'motives'
like fear, hunger, sex, and thirst where there are obvious
external stimuli and internal organic conditions which
initiate action and which are felt as pleasant or unpleasant,
where there are palpable goals towards which actions are
consciously directed, and where there are recognizable end-
states of quiescence which enable us to assign a function to
the action. But is it plausible to suggest that covetousness,
ambition, liberality, impudence, and countless other of
Hobbes' 'passions' conform to this model ? Some of these
terms certainly imply that actions have typical objectives.
Ambition, says Hobbes, is a desire for office and precedence,
and covetousness is desire for riches. But can it be said that
the actions of an ambitious or covetous man are initiated by
antecedent tensions in the same sort of way as the actions of
a hungry man ? To explain an action in terms of ambition
is surely only to suggest a typical objective or reason for it; it
is not to ascribe an efficient cause to it, or even to imply one.
Of course, there may be occasions on which actions per-
formed out of covetousness or ambition are initiated by the
impeding of vital motions occasioned by the absence of
certain objects which could be felt as gnawings, hankerings,
cravings, and so on. But we would not have to assure our-
selves of the occurrence of these antecedent motions before
145
IIOBBES
these we are ascribing traits of character to a person. are We
classifying his action as being in accordance with a certain
of the agent and the efficient cause are the same thing. But
they are considered with this difference, that cause is so
called in respect of the effect already produced, and power
in respect of the same effect to be produced hereafter; so
that cause respects the past, power the future time.' 1 But
surely Hobbes missed the point in his reference to future
time in the analysis of 'power'. To ascribe a power to some-
thing is not to refer to anything actually occurring in the
is to say that if certain conditions
past, present, or future. It
are fulfilled, then certain other things happen. Solubility is
a 'power' of sugar; for if it is put into water (at any time,
past, present, or future) then it dissolves. To ascribe a
cause to something, on the other hand, is to indicate an
event actually occurring at a particular time which is a neces-
sary condition for another event to occur. But Hobbes
refused to give any terms which describe bodies a disposi-
tional interpretation; all terms refer to actual occurrences.
We have seen the importance of this in his account of 'en-
deavour'. 2 It also had a considerable influence on his
account of the passions. For Hobbes even interpreted habits
as actual motions made more easy and more ready by per-
petual endeavours.
Now of all terms that are used to explain human behavi-
our 'habit' is the most obviously dispositional. To say that
i. E.W. I, 127-8. 2. See.rw/>ra, pp. 91-2.
146
MOTIVATION
a person has a habit of punctuality is not to say that he is
doing anything at a particular moment. It is to say that if
he goes to the office, he is always there at the stipulated
time, that if he goes to catch a train, he never misses
it, and so on. A great number of terms for giving an
i. Talking about e.g. the desire for power can suggest an actual pic-
147
HOBBES
ism. And he certainly gave only a very broad outline of a
theory of the passions because of his predominantly political
bias. Indeed, it is only when we pass on to the passions which
seemed to him politically important that Hobbes' account
comes to life again. One of the striking features which
rejuvenates his treatment is his fascination for motion which
bursts forth again when we pass from arid classification to
social implications.
Social life, for Hobbes, was a race for precedence which
had no termination except death. To last in the race
final
needed foresight and scheming. There are therefore specific
pleasures and pains which encourage or deflect men on
their journey. These are the mental pleasures and pains
which 'arise from the expectation that proceeds from fore-
sight of the end or consequence of things for whether those
;
148
MOTIVATION
surely a more restricted sense of 'power' than the first sense
which refers generally to bodily or mental faculties. Indeed,
the term 'power' is another bridging term like 'endeavour'.
Hobbes used it most ingeniously to fashion a psychological
theory suitable for his political theory. For instance, his
celebrated announcement: 'So that in the first place, I put
for a general inclination of all mankind, a perpetual and
restless striving of power after power, that ceaseth only in
5 x
death would be comparatively innocuous, though quaint,
if itreferred just to his general theory that all striving for
future ends involves a conception of our power to produce
them. For Hobbes often did use his general theory to say
rather bizarre things - for instance, that the fear of death
involves the fear of our inability to produce effects. But
'power' in most of the key passages where he speaks of the
desire forpower means our ability to dominate or win pre-
cedence over others. He passes smoothly from the more
general to the more limited sense. To fail to compete was to
die.
It follows that in their dealings with others men are very
sensitive tohonour or the acknowledgement of power. They
cherish their power generative which shows itself in beauty
'consisting in a lively aspect of the countenance and other
2
signs of natural heat'. They are honoured, too, for their
power motive whose signs appear in bodily strength, and
for their faculty of knowledge which appears in their ability
to teach or persuade. Riches, nobility, authority, and good
fortune are also honourable adjuncts since they are acquired
by various powers. A
man who is convinced that his own
power overshadows that of his rivals is subject to what
Hobbes called 'glory' or 'internal gloriation or triumph of
the mind', which may be just, false, or vain, depending on
whether it is based on his own experience, other people's
H9
HOBBES
a like calamity may befall ourselves. This was the sort of
deduction from his theory that rankled with Hobbes'
critics. For pity was transformed by it into a sophisticated
sort of self-interest.
Hobbes prided himself on being the to give a con-
first
But all men are not equally skilled in science; nor are
they equally equipped in wits on which worldly success
mainly depends. Hobbes put down these differences in
attainment to differences in passion. He ruled out differ-
ences in the natural temper of the brain for if that were the ;
150
MOTIVATION
honour and glory which presuppose imagination of the
future. Such dullness probably derives from 'a grossness and
1
difficulty of the motion of the spirits about the heart'.
Quick ranging of the mind, which, joined with curiosity,
leads to grasping the similarities and differences between
2
things, spring from 'a tenuity and agility of spirits'. Levity
is a sign of excessive mobility in the spirits, which prevents
physics and the striving for power prepared his readers for
his political theory.
To endeavour, is appetite.
To be remiss, is sensuality.
To consider them behind, is glory.
To consider them before, is humility.
To lose ground with looking hack, vain glory.
To be holden, hatred.
To turn back, repentance.
To he in breath, hope.
To be weary, despair.
To endeavour to overtake the next, emulation.
To supplant or overthrow, envy.
To resolve to break through a stop foreseen, courage.
To break through a sudden stop, anger.
To break through with ease, magnanimity.
To lose ground by little hindrances, pusillanimity.
To fall on the sudden, is disposition to weep.
To see another fall, is disposition to laugh.
To see one out-gone whom we would not, is pity.
To see one out-go whom we would not, is indignation.
To hold fast by another, is to love.
i. E.W.IV,53-
152
MOTIVATION
To carry him on that so holdcth, is charity.
To hurt one's self for haste, is shame.
Continually to be outgone, is misery.
Continually to outgo the next before, is felicity.
4. Psychological Hedonism
154
MOTIVATION
natural history, not provable immediately by reason'. 1 So
much for Hobbes' method.
Hobbes' theory, according to Butler, rested on the failure
to make two cardinal distinctions. Firstly, Hobbes treated
all action as if it were calculating action in which the agent
aimed at an increase of his own power. But many actions
proceed without foresight of an end to be achieved. 'Though
a man hated himself, he would as much feel the pain of
hunger as he would that of gout. One man rushes upon
. . .
'55
IIOBBES
Hobbes, argued Butler, was able to treat benevolence as
a special case of self-love because he failed to distinguish the
object towards which an action is directed from the satisfac-
tion which may attend its attainment. The cruel man aims
at hurt to his neighbour. He may get satisfaction from hurt-
156
MOTIVATION
marry common-sense with science, and rather unconvincing
science at that. His scientific theory was an attempt to re-
construct rationally the causes of action; men were pic-
tured as natural machines pushed towards or away from
objects. Every such movement increased or impeded the
vital motions, and this was felt as pleasure or pain. The
pleasure and pain resulting from action was therefore an
integral part of his scientific account. This is not absurd.
Most modern theories of behaviour employ some such
homeostatic principle of explanation. The function of goal-
directed behaviour, it is maintained, is to preserve the
equilibrium of the organism. But this does not imply that
organisms consciously aim at attaining an equilibrium state.
Hobbes also held an ideo-motor theory of actions which
assigns the cause of actions to external stimuli which produce
phantasms transmitting push. But Hobbes never suggested
that as actions bring about an increase or decrease in vital
motion they must always be initiated by an image of this
result. Actions which bring mental pleasures or pains (joy
or grief for Hobbes)" are initiated by foresight of pleasure to
come together with consciousness of our power to produce
something. But this is not the case with sensual pleasures.
It is true that his account of sensual pleasures is sketchy;
but it would be very difficult to conclude that he thought
5
that 'all onerations and exonerations of the body together
with actions directed towards preserving what is 'pleasant,
in the sight, hearing, smell, taste, or touch' were initiated by
157
HOBBES
its intrusion into common-sense questions about actions
proved disastrous. And one of the disasters occasioned by it
was the theory popularly known as psychological hedonism.
This point is of such general philosophical importance that
it must be briefly explained.
are not aimed solely at the agent's own pleasure. Butler was
obviously right about this ; he was the champion of morals
and common-sense. But the psychologist wants to know
more about actions. He is not content to find out a man's
intentions he is intrigued by the causes of actions or what
;
159
CHAPTER SLVEN
Introductory
3
These words do not name some
}
and aversion, evil. . . .
3. E.W.III,4i.
4. E.W. Ill, 41.
161
HOBBES
who uses it. It differs in this respect from a term like
for when we call a box square it needs consider-
5
'square ;
163
HOBBES
find satisfying. This surely the point of Mill's often criti-
is
cized remark that the sole reason that can. be given for calling
something desirable is that people actually desire it. But
this is not, surely, the sole reason for commending some-
thing; still less is it part of what 'good' means. Hobbes was
misled by the contingent fact that people often desire what
they call good and often call things good because they have
qualities which they in fact desire, into thinking that there
is a necessary connexion between being good and being
by the speaker.
actually desired
There is another aspect of Hobbes' theory of goodness
which is more interesting than the rather crude analysis
which we have outlined to date. He often spoke of 'good' in
the context of rationality. 'Reason declaring peace to be
good, it follows by the same reason, that all the necessary
means to peace be good also.' 1 This he contrasted with men
swayed by 'irrational appetite, whereby they greedily prefer
the present good'. A man may not in fact desirepeace at a
particular moment; but he would desire it if he reflected
calmly on what would give him pleasure on the whole and
in the long run. Sobered by the fear of death he would see
the desirability of peace and of the means necessary to
attain it. It is as if a guardian were giving advice to his ward
and said, 'I know you want to go on the stage, but under-
standing you as I do, I feel confident that the best thing for
5
164
MOTIVES AND MORALITY
personal and normative force of the term. To say that some-
thing is good implies that it should be chosen or pursued
and that there are good reasons which any man would
accept for this advice. In Hobbes' case the good reasons
derived from an assumed identity of interests on the part of
all men. Certainly it would sound odd to say 'The rational
165
HOBBES
all men. As rational beings all men were equal, whatever
their civic status and as rational beings men could not doubt
;
167
IIUBBES
was to be found in this tendency to maintain some kind of
social order. Keeping non-injury to life
faith, fair dealing,
and property were ways of behaving as natural to man as
pursuing his own interests. They gave rise to the civil laws
of different states which, though conventional and based on
utility, depended on the 'natural obligation' to keep con-
tracts. Natural law, therefore, which comprised all the
simple rules for living together which any rational and social
being could not help accepting, was the foundation of all
systems of civil and international law.
Hobbes, with his eye on Grotius' account, maintained
that more or less the same set of principles could be deduced
from man's nature as a being who becomes rational through
his fear of death. The state of nature was a state of war, not
of social co-operation as Grotius taught. 'All society, there-
fore, is either for gain or for
glory; that is, not so much for
love of our fellows as for the love of ourselves.' 1 Men are
equal enough in body and mind to render negligible any
palpable claims to superior benefits, and even the weakest
is able to kill the strongest. So all men have more or less
1 68
MOTIVES AND MORALITY
society into its clear and distinct parts so as to reconstruct
the whole in order of logical dependence rather than of his-
torical genesis. He could thus treat men 'as if but now sprung
out of the earth and suddenly, like mushrooms, come to full
maturity'. Having isolated the underlying movements of
1
169
HOBBES
do ye to them.' The third law follows 'that men perform
their covenants made'. 1 And so Hobbes
proceeded with the
deduction of the various rules and virtues which seemed to
him essential to peace.
But in what sense can Hobbes be said to have demon-
strated from the maxims of human nature arising from its
i. E.W.III, 130.
170
MOTIVES AND MORALITY
But this more ambitious and more interesting undertaking
has, surely, grave logical objections to it. For it presupposes
that statements prescribing how men ought to behave can be
deduced from statements describing how they in fact behave.
And this breaks one of the first rules of deductive logic,
which is that no statement can feature in the conclusions of
a valid deduction which is not contained explicitly or
implicitly in the premisses. If physics and psychology pro-
vide the premisses, then they contain only descriptions, It
follows, therefore, that no statement other than a descrip-
tion can feature in the conclusion. It is only if a rule like
5
'men ought to endeavour peace one of the premisses that
is
171
I10BBES
would be the vacillation of men between the pursuit of their
long-term and short-term interest. Hobbes' rules of natural
justice, then, if we treat them as deductions from psychology,
would either be invalid deductions or they would be logi-
cally valid but otiose counsels of prudence for men whose
nature was to be prudent anyway.
Suppose, then, that we admit the necessity for a prescrip-
tive premiss. Hobbes argument is now very interesting and
5
173
HOBBES
out, the question 'What this to me?', when asked about a
is
175
HOBBRS
when they are the sorts of belief for which no reasons can be
given, that we seem justified in passing from the question of
validity to the question of causes. If, for instance, a man is
convinced that his hands are covered in blood or that a
room is occupied by an invisible friend, and if, as in the first
case, all the evidence seems to point against it, or, as in the
second case, there seems to be no evidence which could count
against it, then it seems legitimate to ask 'What causes him
to believe this ?' But it is only the absence of reasons that
makes the causal question seem relevant.
The
ingenuity of Hobbes' theory was that his account of
the causes of action ruled out the possibility of any reason
other than that of self-interest being effective. To use a
modern term, all other reasons were rationalizations, a
facade to render pride and fear socially respectable. It is as
if the human machine had
only two gears. Unless the
reasoning engaged one of them it would move neither for-
wards nor backwards. But this presupposed the tenability
MOTIVES AND MORALITY
of his analysis of our basic motives, of psychological hedon-
ism, and of the ideo-motor theory of action. And, as has
been indicated, there seem to be good reasons for rejecting
allthese presuppositions. Indeed, there is a sense in which
the tables can be turned on Hobbes. For much of what pur-
ports to be causal analysis in Hobbes' attempt to fit all the
1
passions into the desire-aversion model was in fact merely
indicating the typical objectives of (reasons for) a man's
action. There is therefore a strong case for saying that in a
great number of cases he was really giving the reasons for
actions when he thought that he was giving their causes.
Nevertheless, in spite of its psychological and logical
defects, there is much to be said in favour of Hobbes' ambi-
tious attempt to deduce the necessity of covenants and rules
from principles of human nature. His theory provides a
refreshing contrast to those which postulate mysterious un-
observable qualities described by ethical terms or which
suggest transcendental sources of obligation. Hobbes be-
lieved both that it is idle to ask what is good for man without
a thorough understanding of human nature and that there is
a close connexion between man's needs and purposes and
what he ought to do. By making the connexion one of logical
deducibility he made it too close. He was mistaken in think-
ing that psychology or any other science can of itself tell us
what is good for we have to decide. Similarly he was mis-
;
H. G 177
HOBBES
be intuited with a cavalier disregard for psychological
findings.
5. Free-will
178
MOTIVES AND MORALITY
impediments to action that are not contained in the nature
and intrinsical quality of the agent'. 1 A person is thus Tree
to do a thing, that may do it if he have the will to do it, and
2
may forbear if he have the will to forbear'. 'Proper and
generally received meaning' presumably refers to the ordin-
ary language of educated people. Hobbes was pointing out
that, if this criterion of usage is adopted, to speak of liberty is
not to make any suggestions about whether or not a person's
will or desire is caused; it is rather to suggest that a man is
179
HOBBES
cur to the production of that action hereafter, whereof if
any one thing now were wanting, the effect could not be
produced'. And all human actions are caused by motions
1
183
HOBBES
'Determined', in other words, has often meant, for those who
have shared his scientific optimism, inevitable as well as
causally explicable. 'This concourse of causes, whereof
everyone is determined to be such as it is by a like concourse
of former causes, may well be called (in respect they were
all set and ordered by the eternal cause of all things, God
1
Almighty) the decree of God.' Many chains of causes
stretch from God Almighty, some of them being motions
impinging on the sense organs and moving us to and fro in
We only think that things could be other-
deliberation.
wise than they are because of our limited knowledge of
causes.
Now this assumed coincidence of inevitability with
causal explicability is surely simply a mistake occasioned by
the peculiar circumstances of the rise of science. It so hap-
pened that the scientific advance, which consisted in the
184
MOTIVES AND MORALITY
like Pavlov and Freud who shared the scientific optimism of
the seventeenth century.
In humanaffairs this alleged coincidence of inevitability
and causal explicability is so manifestly lacking that almost
the reverse is the case. For knowing the causes of what
we tend do is often a necessary condition of preventing
to
ourselves from doing it. If we know that irritability at
breakfast is caused by late nights, we know how to prevent
irritability at breakfast. Of course, what we say about its
inevitability depends very much on our temporal position
as an observer. If we look back on our choice of a wife and
see the causes that led up to the scene in the registry office,
we may often reflect that the course of events was inevitable.
But if we approach a courting couple with a battery of
psychological laws at our disposal (if such laws existed) and
ask ourselves whether, knowing the couple as we do, there
are grounds for saying that their marriage is unavoidable,
the position is very different.
There are, however, some cases where actions can be
shown to have causes of such a kind that they are rendered
inevitable, within a certain range of circumstances. For
instance, it is claimed that the 'lack of opportunity for
forming an attachment to a mother-figure during the first
three years', or 'deprivation for a limited period - at least
three months and probably more than six - during the first
three or four years' (of maternal care) not only causes traits
like 'unfriendliness', 'distractability', 'lack of self-inhibi-
1
tion', but also that the cause is of such a kind as to render
that sort of behaviour unavoidable. Deliberation by the
- all
delinquent, good resolutions, change of foster-home
these remedial devices are no good. Knowledge, too, of
what he is do makes no difference to what he in
likely to
fact does in the given circumstances. But causal discoveries
of this kind in psychology are extremely rare. Unfortu-
nately it has often been assumed by those who have inheri-
ted the outlook of the seventeenth century that there is a
similar inevitability about conduct wherever the ingenuity
i. J. Bowlby, Maternal Care and Mental Health, Geneva, 1951, p. 47.
HOBBES
of the psychologist has unearthed a cause. But it has yet to
be shown that the man whose pipe-smoking is a continua-
tion of biting his mother's nipples cannot give up his expen-
sive habit or that a man can do nothing about his parsi-
To
the charge of injustice Hobbes replied that 'the law
3
regardeth the will and no other precedent causes of action'.
This is quite correct. For the law is only interested in a
187
HOBBES
tion of punishment is that people could have avoided doing
what they did. This is more or less what we mean when we
say that a person is responsible for his actions. When a judge
imposes a light sentence for a crime committed under great
provocation or in the heat of the moment, it is surely because
he thinks that a man's responsibility for his action is thereby
diminished. Hobbes was right only in maintaining that the
'necessity' of actions makes no difference to the operation of
law, if he meant only by 'necessity' causal explicability.
For we may be able to give a perfectly adequate and com-
plete causal explanation of a person's intentional behaviour
in stealing from his employer. But this is irrelevant. For
showing that the behaviour was caused does not also show
that his behaviour was unavoidable or that his intentions
were redundant. But if the type of cause revealed was also
of the sort to render his behaviour unavoidable, if it could be
established that reflection on the consequences of his action,
his resolutions and his attempts to escape his overmastering
impulse, could make no difference to what he in fact did;
then the 'necessity' would suiely affect the operation of law
and moral judgement. Whether this was the case about the
operation of the legal system in the seventeenth century is
dubious. But it certainly is the case about the operation of
our present legal system.
We have here the same kind of clash between the com-
mon-sense practical judgement of judges and the theoretical
speculations of a developing science which we noted in our
discussion of Hobbes' psychological hedonism. 1 Moralists
and judges are concerned primarily with the reasons for
actions or people's intentions; psychologists, on the other
2
hand, are interested in their causes and function. Hobbes
assumed that reasons can be explained in terms of causes.
We have repeatedly questioned this assumption. But the
practical consequences of psychological discoveries for our
judgements of praise and blame have yet to be adequately
assessed. Certainly the Erewhonian period, when crime was
likened to disease, and when all reasons were regarded as
I. Sec supra, pp. 153-8. 2. See supra,, pp. 144-5.
1 88
MOTIVES AND MORALITY
rationalizations,is
passing, together with the fatalism which
was the heritage of the seventeenth century. There is a
cautious return to the pre-evolutionary view that the pos-
session of reason distinguishes men from brutes, and en-
ables us to counteract the influences of early childhood and
economic conditions which were once thought to provide
rails along which we ran towards the buffers of our destiny.
There is, perhaps, increasing acceptance of Kant's view
that man is distinct from the rest of nature in being able to
regulate his conduct because of his understanding of scien-
tific laws, and, in the normative sphere, in being able to live
180
CHAPTER EIGHT
THE STATE
Introductory
190
THE STATE
common-wealth. We may discount Burke's bias against
change; but it remains true that people tend to ask them-
selves about 'the foundations of common-wealth' at a time
of insecurity and social change. The philosopher's question,
when asked seriously rather than just as an academic exer-
cise, is indicative of stresses and strains in the social fabric.
For philosophy is intellectual unrest made explicit.
What then has been the worry made explicit in the ques-
tion about the nature of the state ? Surely it has been a worry
about what attitude to adopt and what policies to pursue
masquerading as a worry about the reality behind the
appearances. When Plato suggested that the state was really
an organism in which there was specialization of function
for the common good, he was constructing a model for re-
jecting and counteracting the growing tendencies towards
individualism and equalitarianism in fourth-century
Athens. Philosophers have tended to wave words instead of
flags. Their abstract accounts of the nature of the state have
had very obvious valuative implications. Now Hobbes com-
pared his Leviathan to Plato's Republic in so far as he thought
that a knowledge of his theory would help a ruler to grapple
with contemporary unrest and bewilderment. What were
the problems to which he could have been providing
answers in picturing the state as an artificial machine based
on a contract between individuals? Quite briefly, they were
problems thrown up by the development of two comple-
-
mentary, but opposed tendencies individualism and abso-
lutism. In order to explain this we must say something of
the great social changes which had led to these problems.
Societies cannot continue without some form of social
control; but they can change gradually as one form of social
control takes the place of another. Under the Feudal system
the predominant social control had been that of tradition.
This prescribed a man's status and the roles he had to play
in the various departments of life. Economic life was static
and secure, regulated by the Guild system which blocked
undue competition and self-assertion. There was little social
192
THE STATE
partly averted by the king winning the support of the more
wealthy of the new middle class. Trade and strong govern-
ment go well together. Henry VII and Elizabeth, for in-
stance, made great use of this class of new men who made
money by ability and achieved social status by buying land
with Hence the great disposal of Crown lands during the
it.
193
HOBBES
the magistrate legitimately invade ? These were the burning
questions which theories of the state had to face. These so-
called theories incorporated decisions and valuations as well
as factual assumptions. Hobbes, as is well known, pictured
the state as an artificial machine based on a social contract
and controlled by an absolute monarch with unlimited,
perpetual, and indivisible sovereignty. How was this
macabre model of the state arrived at and what sort of an
answer did it give to the questions which gave rise to it? We
are now in a position to look at the main details of Hobbes'
theory.
/. The Social Contract Theory
196
THE STATE
holding the social order. Finally, membership of a civil
society and submission to government are not voluntary
undertakings like those of a promisor entering into a con-
veyance and submitting to fines if he fails to honour his
obligation. How could we bind our descendants to accept a
legal system and obey a government even if we were the
Pilgrim Fathers? Yet they are bound without having to
make any explicit promise when they come of age.
What, then, made the model of the contract seem so
appropriate in spite of these obvious objections ? For it is not
enough to say that the social contract theory was embedded
in Greek thought and that, after the Renaissance, it was
popularized together with many other muddles initiated by
Greek thinkers. For why was this particular theory seized
on and used so universally rather than others ? The general
point must first be made that just because these objections
seem obvious to us, it does not follow that they were obvious
then. Thinkers of this period did not conceive either of man
or society in evolutionary terms. They supposed that men
and social institutions had always been much the same. After
all, did the kings in the Old Testament behave very differ-
ently from their kings ? Were money-lenders at the time of
Christ much different from their own ? Were governmental
forms described by Aristotle so different from those with
which they were familiar ? Machiavelli perused the pages of
Livy to find maxims which could be used by a ruler to set
sixteenth-century Italy once more on the road to greatness.
It did not occur to him that the social and economic order in
197
IIOBBES
theory was one way in which this insight into the arbitrari-
ness and artificiality of human institutions found expression.
The model of the contract, however, was much more than
a way of exhibiting the artificiality of human institutions.
It was a device which gave expression to a shift in attitude
towards authority whose significance was not then properly
appreciated. The momentous social changes which were
then in full swing could be graphically desciibed as the rise
of the fatherless society. Patriarchalism, as a system of
authority spreading beyond the family to all institutions,
was on the wane. And even with regard to the family itself
there are most interesting discussions in the works of writers
at this period, including Hobbes, about the proper extent of
parental authority. But in the wider context of civil author-
ity men were coming slowly to realize that patriarchalism
was a system incompatible with human dignity and re-
sponsibility, that men are responsible themselves for the
institutions which shape and stunt their lives. After all, the
Colonists were founding new states and moulding constitu-
tionsby common consent. Why should the mother countries
submit to the patriarchal pretensions of monarchs ?
To the medieval mind a king or a baron was not an in-
dividual with various interests arid functions; he was a total
person whose status and roles were prescribed by traditions
stretching back into time immemorial. Obedience was a
matter of personal loyalty within an area of accustomed
obligations. But with the rise of self-made men whose wealth
bought status and equipped the king's navy, the old pattern
of authority made decreasing sense. Men like the Cecils, who
wielded such enormous power under the Tudors, could claim
no authority stretching back into the distant past. Neither
could Samuel Pepys who did so much to re-organize the
navy. They owed their authority to their brains and to the
wealth which royal patronage enabled them to acquire. A
pattern of authority was emerging with which we are much
more familiar. Max Weber called it legal-rational authority. 1
198
THE STATE
When we want to insult it we call it bureaucracy. But Weber
himself regarded bureaucracy as the most crucial social
phenomenon in the development of the Western world, as
it is the most efficient way of exercising power over human
aoo
THE STATE
that human beings arc responsible for its structure which,
unlike nature's regularities, can be moulded according to
human demands and aspirations; that human beings may
have have fathers by nature but that there is no need to
to
institutionalize their infantile dependency in their attitude
to a monarch. The device was widespread and popular be-
cause of its usefulness to the rising forces of individualism,
commercialism, and Protestantism. Hobbes' great ingenu-
ity consisted in taking over this logical weapon and slewing
it round so that its broadsides were directed against those
who had fashioned it.He used it to show that absolutism
was the logical outcome of consistent individualism. To this
masterstroke we must now turn.
202
THE STATtt
203
HOBBES
ment. For in such cases the individual could not be said to
be aiming at any good to himself. The mutual transferring
of rights is called contract. When one of the contractors
delivers the thing contracted for on his part and leaves the
other person to perform his part at some determinate time,
or when both postpone completion, it is called a covenant, or
pact. The third law of nature, as we have seen, is 'that men
perform their covenants made'.
Hobbes deduced this transfer of rights from his postulate
that men are led by the fear of death to act reasonably and
to accept the law of nature which prescribed such a transfer
of rights. But men are not really safe yet. For in a state of
nature there may be danger in keeping covenants. Men,
too, may decide not to keep their contracts because of their
belief that some greater advantage may accrue to them by
breaking them. If men arc to be really consistent in their
determination to avoid death, they must make some
arrangement whereby it would never be in anyone's interest
to break a covenant or transgress any of the other laws of
nature. For the laws of nature were only theorems that any
rational man would accept. They needed the backing of the
sword to ensure peace. 'And covenants, without the sword,
are but words, and of no strength to secure a man at all.' 1
Men are not like ants or bees which live sociably together
and work for the common good. They agree by contract
only, and to make their agreement constant and lasting they
need a 'common power to keep them in awe, and to direct
their actions to the common benefit'. 2 This is the only hope
for strong and undivided action against external aggressors
and disturbers of the peace at home.
The social contract therefore follows as the only logically
consistent step to take to ensure lasting peace. The contract
is a
pacturn unionis 'that may reduce all their wills, by plural-
3
ity of voices, unto one will'. They constitute themselves a
civil society by appointing a sovereign to act for them in their
204
THE STATE
to man, or to this assembly of men, on this condition,
tliis
that thou give up thy right to him, and authorize all his
actions in like manner'. 1 This contract unites the multitude
into one people and marks the generation of a common-
wealth, of that great LEVIATHAN, or rather, to speak more
reverently, of that mortal God, to which we owe under the
immortal God, our peace and defence'. 2 Thus the under-
lying basis or essence of the state consists in the alienation of
rights to a person or assembly who acts on behalf of all. The
definition of commonwealth is therefore 'one person, of
whose acts a great multitude, by mutual covenants one with
another, have made themselves every one the author, to the
end he may use the strength and means of them all, as- he
shall think expedient, for their peace and common defence'. 3
The person that results is called sovereign and everyone else
his subjects. He is created by the contract but is not a party
in the contract being a pactum unionis betv/een individuals.
it,
205
HOBBES
like 'commonwealth'. For commonwealths are not natural
wholes like potatoes or penguins in which the relations
making the skin or the wings 'parts' are not difficult to
discern. Social wholes are to a large extent constructions
out of individuals according to a variety of different
criteria. An individual may be a member of a group like a
206
THE STATE
jj.
The Reasons for and Causes of Political Obligation
fact that the sword dangles over the head of every member
of a state, no motive would be strong enough to counteract
the disruptive passions of men. And because Hobbes
assumed that men were driven irresistibly by fear like a
stone rolling downhill, he was able to deduce that men must
establish the rule of the sword. For, like men under the in-
fluence of an irresistible impulse, the only reasons that they
would accept would be those indicating means to objectives
dictated by their fear. 8 Thus, given the de facto existence of
civil society, Hobbes' analysis revealed fear as its only pos-
sible constitutive cause and self-preservation as the only
possible reason for its institution. He was also able to deduce
that since this is the underlying rationale of civil society,
men, in so far as they pursue the logical consequences of the
reasons for its institution, must institute a perpetual, un-
207
IIOBBES
of government by popular consent once the real interests of
any man in consenting to government are properly realized.
The claims of Royalists and Parliament men could be re-
conciled if it were realized that either Charles or Cromwell
could be an absolute ruler by consent. The Royalists would
have to give up their patriarchal pretensions and the theory
of divine right; the Parliament men would have to waive
their objections to absolutism. Then peace would reign and
allcould pursue such private interests as did not endanger
the peace - trade, for instance, or mathematical study.
The force of Hobbes' argument depends largely on the
truth of his premisses. Reasons have been given for doubting
his account both of the causes of actions and of the acceptable
reasons for them. 1 But even if we were to accept his starting-
5
208
THE STATE
which both terrifying and an insult to human dignity. A
is
H. H
209
HOBBES
even be a conclusive reason; but it certainly is a very good
reason that carries much weight with most of us if we have
ever thought seriously about breaking the law.
If we turn to Hobbes' theory about the causes of political
peace the lessons learnt in war. Gamps are the true mothers
of cities.' Central government is to be explained more in
211
HOBBES
of natural dominion he tried to extend the new rational way
of conceiving legitimacy into the strongholds of traditional
authority. He was indeed one of the mouthpieces of
the gradual transition from traditional to legal-rational
1
authority.
Was Hobbes' view at all plausible that some kind of con-
tract or consent is
implicit in the existence of any civil
society whatever? Obviously not in the sense that civil
society could not exist if individualshad not actually come
together and made promises. But Hobbes' analysis did not
require this; for he often spoke of 'tacit covenants'. But if
the consensual basis of society is watered down sufficiently
to cover even this, then any government must rule by con-
sent when there is not either open rebellion or mass emigra-
tion. And the distinctive feature of contract would be lost;
for a society arranged according to status and tradition
could equally well be said to be based on 'tacit covenant'.
Perhaps this is part of what Hobbes wanted to show. But it
is rather trivial in that all it achieves is to make
acquiescence
in government part of the definition of government. Yet, on
the other hand, it may be one of those analytic propositions
whose enunciation has considerable recommendatory force.
People often say, in a certain tone of voice, that the func-
tion of government is to govern. This is trivial in descriptive
content; but it is a way of demanding that the government
should get on with its main job rather than range round too
much new-fangled legislation and plans for social
for
suppose.
214
CHAPTER NINE
Introductory
215
HOBBES
except in the form of a definition to which the assent of the
magistrates was essential. Had the king, then, a master who
could 'put a bridle on him' ?
The answer to this crucial conundrum was both negative
and affirmative. For there were two distinct but overlapping
spheres of authority which have been called those of guber-
naculum and jurisdictio. 1 The sphere of gubernaculum was
that of the king's prerogative. It concerned rights touching
the crown like the king's marriage, the keeping of the peace,
and external defence. In such matters the king was the sole
authority. But in the sphere of jurisdictio, which concerned
the traditional of the - to - the
rights subject e.g. property
king's discretion was limited by precedents of the Common
Law. He was bound by oath to proceed by law and not
otherwise, and the judges, though appointed by theking,
were bound by their oaths to determine the rights of the
2l6
SOVEREIGNTY
property was a matter of their Common Law rights which
could not be touched without their consent.
It is true that the king could always ignore the dividing
line between jurisdictio and gubernaculum by claiming a
national emergency or the pretext of 'reasons of state'. But
a wise monarch used this pretext very warily. Elizabeth, for
instance, was very sensitive to the feelings of Parliament on
such matters and, as in the case of monopolies, gave way on
occasion to their demands. But James I, who came from
Scotland where the dual tradition was not firmly established,
was not so sensitive. He maintained that the 'fundamental
law' guaranteeing authority applied only to himself. Not
only had Parliament no business to meddle with affairs of
state; but also the liberties of the subject were purely the
gift of the king, deriving from his supreme authority. The
king's silence on matters of custom simply denoted his
assent. The duality of the tradition was a fundamental
illusion. No wonder Coke replied that 'When the king says
he can not allow our liberties of right, this strikes at the root.
We serve here for thousands and for ten thousands.' This
explicit rejection of the dual tradition helped to precipitate
the struggle. For Parliament in its turn insisted on its right
to discuss matters of the king's prerogative. The intellectual
outcome was a spate of theories claiming the supreme
authority either of Parliament or of the King. Milton, for
instance, voiced demands for the absolute and undivided
sovereignty of Parliament. Hobbes inclined towards abso-
lute monarchy. The significant feature of such theories was
the determination to break away from authority guaranteed
by tradition and precedents and to institute a clear, ration-
ally understandable, and unambiguous chain of command.
217
HOBBES
forward demands in such an explicit manner. For he
his
held that in every commonwealth there must be a sovereign
authority. And the 'must' was meant to be a logical 'must',
though there are grounds for interpreting it as a normative
'must' dressed up as a logical one. There could, on his view,
be reasonable dispute about the advisability of the sovereign
authority being wielded by an individual or by a body of
men. But there could be no dispute about the logical neces-
sity for the existence of such a sovereign authority if a
multitude was to become a people.
This conclusion is acceptable enough if it meant simply
that the existence of a commonwealth entails the existence
of authority as distinct from the exercise of naked power. For
'authority' as distinct from 'power' presupposes that power
is exercised legitimately or in accordance with certain rules
sovereignty
- Common Law
rights, for instance - would be
logically inconsistent with the type of authority set up.
There were, however, certain rights, whose peculiarity
5
we have already noted, which it was psychologically im-
possible for any individual to surrender - e.g. th$ right to
1. E.W. Ill, 163. 3. E.W. Ill, 195. 5. See supra, pp. 202-3.
2. E.W. Ill, 164. 4. E.W. Ill, 199.
219
HOBBES
preserve himself or to resist imprisonment. The liberty of
the subject, therefore, consisted in those acts which it would
be vain for the sovereign to forbid as well as in those which
he had not in fact forbidden. But this, surely, is a very thin
analysis of the relationship between law and liberty. For the
question of the liberty of the subject only arises when at-
tempts are made to prevent people doing what they want to
do. It is odd to talk about our liberty to choose our own diet
because it has rarely occurred to anyone in this country,
except during a food-shortage, to prevent us eating what we
want. And it may be true that we are free to dream what we
like, because no one has yet found a way of stopping us; but
it is only in sentimental lyrics that questions of our liberty
his choice; for law itself came about by his choice. Who,
then, or what was not constraining his choice in deciding to
accept the constraint of law? For talk of liberty in general is
vacuous talk. It means too little because it means too much.
It is like the terms 'same* or 'equal', which convey little in-
formation until the respects are specified in which people
are being compared. Until we know what constraint is
pre-
sumed be lacking in preventing a person from doing what
to
he wants, little is conveyed by speaking of his liberty. Cer-
tainly this general type of liberty was not that to which
Hobbes referred when he said, 'As for other liberties, they
depend on the silence of the law.' This was an informative
1
222
SOVEREIGNTY
Common Law rights were outside the sphere of prerogative.
'Prerogative/ he said, 'is
part of the law, but "sovereign
power" no parliamentary word.
is Magna Charta is
. . .
5
such a fellow that he will have no "sovereign". Hobbes'
reply was again an appeal to a necessary truth. For if the
term 'people' or 'commonwealth* meant a multitude who
had set up an authority to protect them, how could there be
one people if there were more than one authority? Their
224
SOVEREIGNTY
U.S.A., with the express intention of there being no overall
sovereign in Hobbes' sense. If we say that no common-
wealth exists where there is an explicit division of authority,
then we are ruling out a great number of forms of com-
monwealth by definition. For there is no reason why in-
dividuals should not decide that a necessary condition of
being one people is that no one person or body should
exercise supreme authority over them. Their unity could be
defined as consisting in decisions and actions issuing from
compromises between their representatives in different
departments of state.
Of course, very few commonwealths have in fact been
instituted in such a clear-headed way. This is the illusion
about states popularized by the model of the social contract.
Authorities develop in different spheres; often they clash
and intellectual confusion as well as more overt forms of
conflict develop. Then a geometer like Hobbes comes along
and tries to work out a logically consistent structure of com-
mand. But there is little reason why his proposals for calling
a collection of individuals 'one people' should be accepted
rather than anyone else's. For they were deductions from
his convictions about the proper business of government.
But government has no business except that which those who
practise it and suffer from it assign to it. And this is a matter
of political preference rather than of dispassionate analysis.
5
Is there, then, almost nothing to be said for Hobbes con-
viction that the existence of a commonwealth entails the
existence of a sovereign ? This, as has been stressed, depends
on what criteria we are going to use for calling a collection
of individuals a commonwealth. Most people would main-
tain that a necessary condition would be the existence of a
common legal system, and there is a sense in which sover-
eignty indispensable for the working of a legal system. For
is
226
SOVEREIGNTY
It is surely inadvisable to propose a form of authority that
no one can ever have the actual power to exercise. In theory
a monarch can be given unlimited authority; but in prac-
tice he is limited in what he can command by the major
interests of his subjects and their deep-rooted traditions, and
227
HOBBES
money into the public coffers; treasurers appointed for
2. Law as Command
228
SOVEREIGNTY
hold of the opposition to the Stuarts - can be seen from his
writings on legal theory. In Leviathan he declared his interest
in law to be that of an analytic philosopher enquiring into
the nature of law rather than that of a legalist looking into
the details of particular legal systems. 1 Nevertheless, in
spite of his considerable contribution to legal theory, his
treatment of law at a theoretical level had very obvious
practical consequences for the English legal system. These
were most explicit in his Dialogue between a Philosopher and a
Common Laws of England - a sustained attack on
Student of the
the theory of law held by Sir Edward Coke and other
champions of the Common Law against the Stuarts.
Law in Feudal times had been regarded as a declaration of
existing custom. The law was there to discover - a sort of
property belonging to the people - as it applied to particu-
lar circumstances. With the development of Common Law
or the King's Law this view still persisted. The King and his
Courts never made laws he declared what the law was.
1
.,
1. E.W. 111,251.
2. See, e.g. H. Maine, Ancient Law (Everyman Ed.), pp. 18, 19.
3. See G. H. Mcllwain, The High Court of Parliament, New Haven, 1910.
229
HOBBES
in similar categories, was presumed to be in accordance with
reason, though the lawyers like Sir Edward Coke held that
itrequired the special sort of 'artificial reason' which only a
lawyer with a long training could acquire, to interpret it.
And if the system of precedents, on which the Common Law
proceeded, resulted in a gross wrong being done for which
there was no redress in law, then the subject could appeal
to the Court of Chancery where the Chancellor had author-
230
SOVEREIGNTY
practical necessity for the supremacy of the statute-making
authority and that in the seventeenth century it was still
that any custom of its own nature can amount to the author-
ity of a law. For if the custom be unreasonable, you must,
with all other lawyers, confess that it is no law, but ought to
be abolished; and if the custom be reasonable, it is not the
3
custom, but the equity that makes the law.' The alterna-
tive would be a regress of judgements depending upon pre-
cedents terminating in some ignorant man's decision.
Although Hobbes stressed the character of civil law as
command - for it was authority, not wisdom, that made a
law - he nevertheless contrived to hang on to the accepted
presumption that law could not be unreasonable. In effect
he wished to do away with the Common Law and the 'arti-
reason' necessary to interpret its precedents and in its
ficial
231
HOBBES
sumably Hobbes had eye on the Court of Chancery; but
his
his case for Equity, especially in Leviathan,was formulated
in terms of the relationship between the civil law and the
laws of nature. 'The law of nature, and the civil law, con-
tain each other, and are of equal extent.' 1 Nevertheless he
remained clear about the distinction. The laws of nature
were 'but conclusions, or theorems concerning what con-
duce th to the conservation and defence of themselves'. 2
Civil law, on the other hand, 'is to every subject, those rules,
which the commonwealth hath commanded him, by word,
writing, or other sufficient signs of the will, to make use of,
for the distinction of right, and wrong; that is to say, of what
is contrary, and what is not contrary to the rule'. 3 Laws
properly so called were rules issuing in writing from a deter-
minate source which were enforced by the sword; we are
obliged by them. Justice in a commonwealth was simply
what was commanded by law. The only sense in which a
law could be unjust was if it were abrogated by another law.
Of course, a law could be unequitable; but this must be dis-
tinguished from being unjust in a strict sense of 'unjust*.
This should rarely happen; for the sovereign and his
appointed judges were guided by the laws of nature or con-
siderations of equity in making and interpreting laws. In-
deed, in Hobbes' ideal experiment a commonwealth was
created when the theorems of natural law were converted
into the commands of the civil law by being officially issued
in statutesand supported by the sword of the sovereign. Yet
there was a reciprocal connexion. For men were imagined
as having covenanted to obey the civil law and the third law
of nature was that men should keep their covenants made.
Thus, 'Civil, and natural law are not different kinds, but
different parts of law; whereof one part being written, is
232
SOVEREIGNTY
whose reason it is, that shall be received for law', 1 It could
not be any private reason; for that would make as many
contradictions in the law as there were in the Schools.
Neither could it be 'as Sir Edward Coke makes it, an artifi-
cial perfection of reason, gotten by long study, observation,
and experience, as his was'. 2 For long study might only
c
serve to increase and confirm erroneous sentences. So it is
not that juris pmdentia, or wisdom of subordinate judges; but
the reason of this our artificial man the commonwealth, and
his command, that maketh law'. 3
The subordinate judges
should have regard to the reason which moved the sovereign
in making the laws; for though they were written, they had
to be interpreted not by the letter but by their 'intendment
or meaning'. 4 Equity was to enter in at all stages of the
making and interpreting of law. And the sovereign was
ultimately the sole judge of equity. In fact, of course, his
Chancellor was, and Hobbes staunchly resisted Coke's
claim that the Chancellor should be a lawyer and supported
the traditional view that he should be an ecclesiastic well-
versed in the law of nature. 5
It not clear what Hobbes' proposals amounted to in in-
is
clear whether Hobbes realized that court also had developed its
this own
system of precedents. See E.W. VI, 63-8.
233
HOBBES
mind, quite clear that his main proposal was to do away
it is
235
HOBBES
view. It is attractive because
it points to the
prescriptive
character of legal language which distinguishes it from
statements of fact. The trouble, however, about the view is
that 'command' is too strong a word, which suggests the
picture of a sergeant-major rather than of a judge or legis-
lator. So many laws obviously do not command - e.g. en-
5. Forms of Government
236
SOVEREIGNTY
one man, some men, or all men. There were no further
possibilities. Thus the classification of commonwealths into
monarchies, aristocracies, and democracies was exhaustive
as sovereign power was indivisible. Words like 'tyranny',
5
and 'anarchy were only emotive descriptions
'oligarchy',
of monarchy, aristocracy, and democracy by people who did
not like them; they did not refer to logically distinct types of
commonwealth .
237
HOBBES
rights on
their behalf. But, in spite of the logical priority of
democracy, its inconveniences for promoting the peace and
security of the people are so manifest that monarchy is in-
finitely to be preferred.
In the first place, members of a sovereign assembly have
238
SOVEREIGNTY
control rather than the breeding and training of a ruling
class of philosophical shamans was the only effective safe-
239
CHAPTER TEN
RELIGION
Introductory
H i
241
HOBBES
social fabric threatened by the absurd vapourings of ignor-
ant, credulous, and passionate men. And he had good cause
to be afraid. For the main enemies of the sort of absolutism
which he envisaged were indeed those whose belief in in-
dividual liberty assumed predominantly religious forms or
those who, because of their Catholic convictions, could
never give the kind of undivided allegiance to a sovereign
which he demanded of them.
We have no intention of following Hobbes into the
minutiae of Scriptural exegesis, but will be content to deal
with his general views on the subject of religious belief and
his use of the Scriptures to justify his demand for absolute
243
HOBBES
ments and direction. In his account of the passions he put his
view succinctly: Tear of power invisible, feigned by the
mind, or imagined from tales publicly allowed, RELIGION;
not allowed, SUPERSTITION. And when the power ima-
gined is truly such as we imagine, TRUE RELIGION.' This
1
244
RELIGION
strongest, and most man. 1 Hobbes seems
insistent wishes of
246
RELIGION
isbut one person. The attributes of God, therefore, which are
words by means of which we worship him, must be settled
by agreement. For 'whatsoever may be done by the wills of
particular men, where there is no law but reason, may be
done by the will of the commonwealth, by laws civil.' 1 It
follows therefore that the sovereign must decide on God's
attributes.
The comparative helplessness of reason in deciding on
God's attributes must not, however, lead us to abandon it.
For it is a gift of God for our use till the Second Coming of
Jesus. It is therefore not 'to be folded up in the napkin of an
implicit faith, but employed in the purchase ofjustice, peace,
and true religion.' 2 For though many matters connected
with God cannot be rationally demonstrated, yet there is
nothing in God's word contrary to reason. If we think that
there is, then usually we are at fault in our reasoning. We
must therefore be prepared, to a certain extent, to 'captivate
our understanding to the words; and not to labour in sifting
out a philosophical truth by logic, of such mysteries as are
not comprehensible, nor fall under any rule of natural
science. For it is with the mysteries of our religion as with
wholesome pills for the sick; which swallowed whole, have
the virtue to cure ; but chewed up, are for the most part cast
3
up again without effect.'
Hobbes did not play down the use of reason in religious
matters in order to exalt the inner light of the individual.
Indeed, some of his most scathing comments were reserved
for those who claimed individual intimacy with the will of
247
HOBBES
which a sovereign can compel at least outward conformity to
the authorized religion. And how seriously are we to take
this talk of supernatural sense ? For if a man says that God
phets have been informed of the will of God which has been
recorded in the Scriptures. These mediate revelations to
prophets being the foundation on which Hobbes thought
religious belief was built, the crucial question was how true
prophets could be distinguished from false ones. Hobbes
suggested two criteria: the working of miracles and not
teaching religious doctrines at variance with those already
established. Both criteria must be satisfied, neither being in
itself sufficient. But as miracles had now ceased there was
no sign left whereby acknowledge the pretended revela-
to
tions or inspirations of any private men. Since the time of
Jesus the Holy Scriptures had supplied the place of and
sufficiently recompensed the want of all other prophecy.
From these 'by wise and learned interpretation, and care-
ful ratiocination, all rules and precepts necessary to the
248
RELIGION
enunciated mean ? Hobbes subjected the books of the Bible
to scrutiny and suggested, amongst other things, that the
books ascribed to Moses must have been written after his
death. The authority of the Old Testament could be traced
back only to the time of Esdras. However, most of the Old
Testament could be accepted as genuine; so also could the
New Testament, though the authority for it could not be
traced back before the Council of Laodicea. With regard to
the authentic texts there could be no dispute about the
genuineness of the revelation therein incorporated. For who
could know that they were God's word save the prophets
themselves? The question of authority was not suitably
raised in connexion with the authenticity of their divine
source, but in connexion with the authority by which they
were made law. And to this there could only be one answer
for those who themselves were not favoured with super-
natural intimations - the authority of the commonwealth
whose commands had already the force of laws. For how
else could agreement be established about the implementa-
tion of God's commands ?
249
HOBBES
terms. This usage of 'body', however, is more general than
that of common people who call only those parts of the uni-
verse 'body' as 'they can discern by the sense of feeling, to
or by the sense of their eyes to hinder them
resist their force,
from a farther prospect.' 1 Therefore, in the common lan-
guage of men, air and aerial substances are not taken for
bodies but are called wind, breath, or spirits - the Latin
word spiritus signifying all these. For instance, the aerial
substance, which gives life and motion to the bodies of
living creatures, is called vital and animal spirits. Ignorant
men, however, often use the term 'bodies' or 'spirits' to refer
to 'those idols of the brain, which represent bodies to us,
where they are not, as in a looking-glass, in a dream, or to a
distempered brain waking.' The term 'spirits' is favoured
2
250
RELIGION
he is.' 1 Hobbes then proceeded to cite strings of passages
from the Scriptures in which reference was made to the
spirit of God and tried to show how his various senses of
'spirit' could take care of them. 'Holy Ghost' and 'Holy
Spirit' were rather a trouble to him. For 'Jesus was full of
the Holy Ghost.' 2 Hobbes took this as meaning zeal to do
the work for which he was sent by God the Father! For
to interpret it of a ghost, is to say, that God himself, for
'
. . .
so our Saviour was, was rilled with God; which is very im-
251
HOBBES
reason, an acknowledgement and belief that there be also
1
angels substantial and permanent.'
The term 'inspiration' can only be used metaphorically
in the Scriptures. For literally it means 'blowing into a man
some thin and subtle air or wind, in such manner as a man
2
filleth a bladder with his breath.' If it says in the Scriptures,
spoken but
to prophets; it is also used metaphorically to
1. E.W. 111,436.
2. E.W. Ill, 437.
3. See A. W. Yen-all's classic exposition of this technique for saying
what it is dangerous to say in his Euripides the Rationalist.
253
IIOBBES
Adam had lost the gift of eternal life by his sin, but Jesus had
- to
recovered it for believers enjoy, however, at the resur-
rection of the dead. There was no scriptural evidence for
saying that this boon would be experienced 'in another
Jerusalem and Mt
9
l
higher heaven, called caelum empyreum.
Zion were singled out by Isaiah as the dwelling place for the
people of God. Christians must keep their feet on the
ground. For those not fortunate enough to rise again, no
situation was promised in the Scriptures - only rather de-
pressing company, e.g. deceased giants. Predictions of hell
fire were to be taken metaphorically, and terms like 'Satan'
and 'Devil' were appellations of an office rather than proper
names of persons; they were variables whose values were the
earthly enemies of the Church. To be saved was the same
as to enjoy eternal life 'when God shall reign at the coming
again of Christ in Jerusalem.'
Hobbes in fact interpreted the Scriptures in such a way
that there was danger of his readers thinking with his
little
254
RELIGION
relationship between church and state it is not surprising
that Hobbes glossed over in the Scriptures passages which
sectaries and Catholics brought so prominently to his notice
when he left his study.
255
HOBBES
perly meant a commonwealth, instituted, by the consent of
those which were to be subject thereto, for their civil
government, and the regulating of their behaviour, not only
towards God their king, but also towards one another in
point of justice, and towards other nations both in peace
and war; which properly was a kingdom wherein God was
king, and the high-priest was to be, after the death of Moses,
his sole viceroy or lieutenant.' 1
The civil and ecclesiastical
256
RELIGION
founded - probably somewhat inadvertently. Hobbes divi-
ded the time between the Ascension and the Second Com-
-
ing into two main periods before and after civil sovereigns
embraced the Christian religion. During the former period
'power ecclesiastical' was with the aspotles and those to
whom the Holy Spirit was transmitted by the laying on of
hands. They were left no coercive power by Jesus; only
authority to proclaim the kingdom of God to be and to per-
suade men to prepare themselves for it. They were thus
schoolmasters rather than commanders, and their precepts
were not laws but wholesome counsels. The time between
the Ascension and the Second Coming was a regeneration,
not a reigning. The non-coercive character of ecclesiastical
authority was evidenced also by Jesus' comparison of
apostles to fishers of men, by the nature of faith which is not
to be coerced, and the instructions of Jesus and St Paul
257
HOBBES
the Scripture was only law where the lawful civil power had
made it so. Councils like that of Laodicea, which first settled
the canonical Scriptures, were purely meetings for agreeing
about what was to be taught; they did not establish canons
or laws in the strict sense. There was no Scriptural authority
for setting up 'canons against laws, and a ghostly authority
power over their subjects, that can be given to man, for the
government of men's external actions, both in policy and
religion and may make such laws as themselves shall judge
;
258
RELIGION
therefore, committed government in matters of religion to
the Pope, the latter only exercised that charge in another's
dominion in the right of the civil sovereign. He was on a par
with supreme pastors, assemblies of pastors, or any other
persons charged with the supervision of religion. But *his
was purely a matter of convenience. The civil sovereign had
merely delegated his authority to interpret and teach the
Scriptures. No division of sovereignty was thereby implied.
After a lengthy and learned demolition of Cardinal
Bellarmine's 'defence of Rome's challenge to the temporal
power in his De Summo Pontifice, Hobbes reiterated his recipe
for protection against false prophets, whose individualistic
and anarchic outpourings were just as much a danger to the
state religion as the 'ghostly authority' of Rome. 'All that is
NECESSARY to salvation,' he maintained, was 'faith in
Christ and obedience to laws.' 1 Under obedience came cha-
rity and love because they both imply a will to obey righte-
:
ousness because the will to give every one his own, that
it is
259
HOBBES
the laws of nature and in defiance of the counsels of the
apostles. Faith, too, was internal and invisible and could not
be damaged by such compliance. A man who risked his life
for his faith might expect his reward in heaven, but should
not complain of his lawful sovereign. Martyrs there could
be the first degree of martyrdom however was reserved for
;
those who were called to preach that Jesus Christ was risen
from the dead on first-hand evidence of his resurrection.
Martyrs of the second degree were those who were called to
preach that Jesus the Christ. This was the sole message
is
260
RELIGION
into the Madonna The Latin language em-
with Child.
ployed by the Church was the ghost of the old Roman lan-
guage. The whole set-up resembled fairy tales told by old
wives. The Pope was the counterpart of the king of the
fairies. 'The ecclesiastics are spiritual men and ghostly
fathers. The fairies are spirits and ghosts. Fairies and ghosts
inhabit darkness, solitudes, and graves. The ecclesiastics
walk in obscurity of doctrine, in monasteries, churches and
1
churchyards.' Both fairies and ecclesiastics snatch away
the reason of the young, marry not, and dwell in enchanted
castles. Superstition was inevitable; as most men were ignor-
ant and all were fearful. But the papacy ruthlessly ex-
ploited the fear of ignorant men to perpetuate the power of
unscrupulous priests as a rival to the secular power.
Hobbes left his readers in little doubt about the types of
religious belief which he considered pernicious! He also
made it reasonably clear what beliefs he thought it desirable
for a subject to confess publicly. But his own private beliefs
on these matters were not so readily apparent. Certainly he
held that faith was radically different from knowledge. The
object of both faith and knowledge were propositions. But
the reasons for accepting them were different. In the case of
knowledge we consider the proposition itself and call to
mind what its terms signify. For instance we know that two
plus two make four because we have agreed about how
these symbols are to be used. Truth is a matter of following
out the consequences of our definitions. We are thus enabled
to settle such problems as whether theft is injury or not; for it
261
HOBBES
only makes those things which exceed human
for explication
262
RELIGION
very dangerous in those days, as Hobbes discovered when he
was sought as a scapegoat for the Great Fire. 1 Nothing much
can be assumed about Hobbes' convictions from the evi-
dence of these explicit attacks. Some might say, in fact, that
he protested too much. Anyway, he obviously thought, like
Spinoza, that atheism was dangerous for those who had not
acquired scientific understanding. The Church helped to
render peaceable those who had not a clear understanding
of the principles of natural justice.
But it was obvious that the existence of God even as
rather a remote and incomprehensible first cause did not
seem as clear and distinct to Hobbes as some of his postu-
lates of natural and civil philosophy. Indeed, he remarked
in the same De Give footnote than the proposition that there
is a God was no more likely to be clear to the understanding
263
HOBBES
Probably Hobbes was very confident of his own interpre-
tation of the Scriptures on certain key points - that Jesus'
kingdom did not begin till the Second Corning, that in the
meantime civil obedience was prescribed both by Jesus and
St Paul, that the cardinal article of faith was that Jesus was
the Christ, that Jesus only gave authority to his followers to
teach and preach, and that there never was a divinely in-
stituted spiritual authority independent of or a rival to the
state* Most
of his Scriptural exegesis were directed towards
establishing these points. He probably thought, however,
that a great many beliefs, which were not so politically im-
portant, could be substantiated or refuted by appeal to the
Scriptures. But these could be merely a matter of inner con-
viction; Hobbes probably only had convictions on Scrip-
tural matters that were politically important. He was
patently not a religious man, and though he stated that be-
lief was necessary for salvation, he probably never
in Jesus
felt very deeply about the state of his own soul or anyone
else's. That was a matter of private conviction when shorn
names of, 128-35, 136 Body, concept of, 81, 94- 7i 249-50
Acquisition (see Commonwealth) as conti gurus, 889
Action, at a distance, 89, 99 and mind, 83, 101, 117
causes of (see Motivation) and place, 98
function of (see Function) names of, 126-8, 129, 136
reasons for (see Reason) or objectives of Bovi E, R., 38, 41, 42
(set Objectives) BOWLBY, J , 18511.
ADLER, A., 152 BR ACTON, II , 215
ALEXANDER THE GREAT, 166 BRAMHALI, Bishop, 37-8, 95, 178, 180,
A Minute or First Draught of the Optiques, 30, 183, 186
31,33 BRANDT, F , 28, agn , sin., gon., 91, 92
Analytic, method, 53-4, 69-71, 73, 75 (see BROWNE, Sir T., 18
also Resolute-compositive method) BUCKINGHAM, Duke of, 20, 238
truths, 55-7, 58, 212 (see also Truth) BURKE, E., 190-1, 210
Angels, 251-2 BURTT, E. A., 72n.
Apparition, the wonderof, 80, 83-5, 102 BUTLER, Bishop, 154-8, 159
Appetite and aversion, 92, 93, 139-43,
146, 155
AQUINAS, T, 115, 119 CALVIN, J., 24
Arbitrariness, of authority, 208-9, 239 Causation, as motion, 73, 88-91
of institutions, 197-8,200 Causes, efficient, 73, 81, 90, 142, 144,
of speech, 123, 124 US, 147, 157-9, 183
Aristocracy, 237
and reason*?, 161, 176-8, 183
215-17, 225
Church, definition of, 255
and state, 34-5, 255-60
208-9
arbitrariness of,
and power, 218-19, 226-7 CICERO, 119
and sovereignty, 218-19, 223 Circle, definition of, 51, 64, 87
BACON, Sir F., 15-19, 24, 39, 42, 47, 81, CLARENDON, Earl of (see HYDE), 35, 36
136 ^Class-inclusion (see Comprehension)
Behemoth, 30, 42, 64 CLEON, so
267
INDEX
CLINTON, Sir G., 21 Dialogue between a Philosopher and a Student
COKE, Sir E., 20, 34, 42, 217, 222, 229, of the Common Laws of England, 42, 229
233 Dispositions, 146-7
Common Law (see Law) Divine Right of Kings, 33, 36, 37, 211,
Common-sense, 97, 147, 156-7, 158-9, 230
179, 188 DODD, C. H 254n. ,
analysis of, 205-6, 212-14, 215, 218, Dreams, theoiy of, 116-18
223-4, 22 s
) Drives, 140
types 236-9 (see also State)
of,
Copula, function of, 130-1, 136 (see also End, of action, 141-2, 156, 157
Existence) Equity, Court of, 230, 233
COSIN, Dr, 32 as law of nature, 231-2, 233, 234
268
INDEX
GALEN, i4on. Inertia, law of, 25, 90, 1 1 1
GALILEO, G., 15, 16, 22, 24, 25, 42, 63, 66, Inevitability (see Unavoidabihty)
68, 72, 73, 74, 80, go, 96, 167, 170, 192, Infallibility, 262
201, 213 Injustice, 75, 219
GASSENDI, P., 22, 31, 36, 72 Inspiration, 2^2
Geometry, Ilobbrs' discovery of, 21 Institution, I9<>, 206, 211, 212-13
method of, 21, 25, 48-63, 213, 215, 223
and civil philosophy, 74, 213, 215, 223,
JAMES I, 20, 34, 217, 230
225 JFSUS CHRIST, 60, 247, 248, 251, 252, 254,
and motion, 87-8, 100
256, 257, 259, 261, 263, 264
and space, 72
JOB, 246
Ghosts, concept of, 251 Justice, 203, 232
explanation of, 117-18 natural, 76, 160, 172, 234
God, definition of, 95
existence of, 245-6, 264
KANT, I., 45, 55, 56, 189, 263
kingdom of, 255-60
nature KEPLER, J., 14, 15, 16, 72
of, 245-7
Gods, nature
Kingdom of God, (see God)
of, 243
Knowledge, historical, 6^-5
Goodness, analysis of, 161-5.
scientific or philosophical, 52-72
GROTIUS, H., 167-8
and faith, 260-5
as power, 16-17, 22, 46
26Q
INDEX
MACHIAVELLI, N., 47, 52, 192, 197, 241 Natural law, 165-73 ( see Laws of
MAGELLAN, F., 14, 85 Nature)
MAINE, Sir II., 22gn. \iNature, laws of (see Laws of Nature)
Martyrs, 260 state of, 1 68, 202
MARX, K., 45, 78 Necessitation (see Determinism)
MclLWAiN, G. H., 21611., 22gn. NEWCASTLE, Marquis of, 30, 31, 37, 178
Meaning, theory of, 62-3, 134-5, 137 NEWTON, Sir I., 25, 56, 77
Mechanical explanation, 82, 83, 86, 88, Nominalism, 126-37 ( see k Names)
93, 134 (see also Motion)
Medium, theory of, 29, 89, 91 Objectives, of action, 142, 144, 145, 146,
149, 157-9 ( set a ?so Reasons for Action)
Memory, 112-13
MERSENNE, Abbe M , 22, 27, 28, 30, 31, Obligation, contractual, 196, 200
32, 72, 174 natural, 169, 171, 235 (ste also Laws of
Naturalism, 177 (see also Prescriptions) 153, 168, 171, 172, 176
27O
INDEX
Predestination, 184 RICHELIEU, Cardinal, 27
Prerogative, 199, 215 Rights, analysis of, 202-3
Presbyterians, 30 Common Law, 216, 219, 223, 224
Propositions, definition of, 129 45, 120, 122, 241, 242, 258-9, 260-1
necessary and contingent, 56 Royal Society, 16, 38, 39, 41-2, 240
primary, 53-4, 61
and religious beliefs, 261, 264
Safety (set Security)
PROTAGORAS, 48
St Paul, 257, 261,264
Prudence, 51, 62, 84, 99, 1 15
Salvation, 259-60, 261, 264
Psycho-analysis, 186
SAVILE, Sir H., 38
Psychological hedonism, I53~9> *74> "77.
1 88 Scriptures, authority of, 248-9, 261
concepts of, 249-55
Punishment, 186-8
interpretation of, 254, 255, 257-8, 263,
Puritans, 14, 30, 35, 38, 39
264
PYM, J., 20, 26, 237
Security, 192-3, 201, 208, 210, 214, 22 i,
Pythagoreans, 48, 49
224
SELDEN, J., 37
Qualities, primary and secondary, 96^ Selectivity, explanation of, 104-5
97, 100, 103, 106-10 Self-interest, 64-5, 150, 154-8, 171,
271
INDEX
STRAFFORD, Larl of, 27, 29 Universities, 1 4., 38, 39
Substance, 94 Unpredictability, 182-3
incorporeal, 95 Utilitarianism, 187
Superstition, 244, 245
Synthetic method, 53, 69, 70
truths, 55-7, 58 VERRALL, A. W., 253n
o
, lf
WmrFHEAD,
* T
A. N.,8i
Tractatus Otticus, 89, 91
_. ,
_ , _ WlIDMAN,
_..
J 241 ,
212
rf/'-i
WILKINS, J 38, 42 ,
^
Trams,
r
, rue
r i
of thought,
Traits, of character, 146, 147
,
Truth, theory
,
55-63
r
of,
i
u 3- 1
^
6
Will, 93,
...
'
^'
Deliberation,
mmism)
.
.
*
142-3, 178, '
1
Free-will,
80,
...
181
and
,
(ste also
_,
Dcter-
Wisdom, 51
by convention, 5 > -6 1, 175
"' '
'
elf-cvidence theory of, 61-3, 76, 77, 154,
V\ui7burg School, of psychologists, 135