Goldner (1988) Generations and Gender - Family Process
Goldner (1988) Generations and Gender - Family Process
Goldner (1988) Generations and Gender - Family Process
This essay argues that gender is an irreducible category of clinical observation and theorizing, as crucial to the family
therapy paradigm as the concept of "generation." Gender, therefore, is not a secondary, mediating variable like race,
class, or ethnicity, but, rather, a fundamental, organizing principle of all family systems. The author analyzes the history
and politics of family therapy in order to explicate how gender, as a co-equal concept, was erased as a universal
principle of family organization, leaving only generation. The theoretical and clinical implications of situating gender at
the center of family therapy are then discussed.
The primary purpose of this essay is to rescue the topic of gender from the category of the "special case" or "special
issue," and to locate it where it belongs, at the center of family theory. By considering gender a central theoretical category,
and opposing its marginalization, I am following an established tenet of feminist scholarship. This is to insist on a
constructivist view of knowledge that takes nothing for granted, and asks the same question of every idea: Does it make
room for both male and female experience or does it make man the measure of woman?
Establishing the truth value of ideas by evaluating them against this standard is a habit of mind with a social history.
Indeed, it is arguably the single most significant accomplishment of the original, humbly conceived, consciousness-raising
groups of the 1960s. As women met together to compare notes on their lives, they began to realize that they had been
deprived of their subjectivity by a culture that expected them to be sexual objects for men and facilitating environments for
everybody. The more they talked and laid claim to themselves, the more of themselves they found had been left out of the
world. And this led to a striking insight: gender dichotomies were not only restrictive, they were also constituitive. In other
words, the gendering of social spheres not only constrained personal freedom, but gender categories also determined what it
was possible to know.
Coming to this discovery was historic. It meant that the feminist project that had brought women together had to be
reconceived. It was no longer a matter of demanding equal access to a man's world, but of asking what the world would be
like if women had equal power in creating it. This meant that gender could no longer be conceptualized as simply a barrier
to be transcended, because it was itself a metaphysical category, a central organizing principle of knowledge and culture.
This paradigm shift in our view of the problem has led academic feminists to theorize about the gendering not only of
social spheres but also of the act of knowing itself. There is now a burgeoning literature elaborating the premise that
thinking is gendered and that different modes of thought produce different kinds of knowledge (3, 9, 16, 27). Having staked
out this claim for cognitive variation, feminist investigators have been led, inevitably, to challenge the hegemony of
traditional (masculine) forms of intellectual inquiry and even to question the fundamental assumptions underlying
traditional canons of knowledge.
This conceptual revolution has made its mark in philosophy, literature, anthropology, history, and psychoanalysis. In
family therapy, feminist criticism is at an earlier stage. We have done extensive and important work in documenting the
androcentric biases of clinical theory and practice, but we have only just begun to tackle the intimidating project of the
conceptual transformation of our discipline as a whole. It is time.
Family therapy, as a field, has finally taken notice of feminism and has taken it seriously. The noisy feminist presence of
the past few years has been virtually impossible to ignore, and, in any case, family therapists by political temperament do
not like to be on the "wrong side" of a socially progressive issue. Indeed, reactivity to feminism has now become so intense
that political responses, which typically take a decade to unfold, seem to have been condensed into a scant few years.
Looking back at this very recent history, it appears that, after a long period of polite silence, family therapists suddenly
developed an intense curiosity about what feminists were saying. This was followed by hurried attempts to incorporate
feminist concerns into the field, which was ambivalently received by feminists who liked the attention to their agenda but
feared that the price of admission would be cooptation.
Not surprisingly, as the dialogue developed, reactivity intensified, generating increasing polarization and even political
backlash. More recently, there seems to be evidence that feminist ideas are being assimilated into the mainstream, but the
professional climate remains "edgy" and intermittently adversarial. A systems consultant describing the process would
probably observe that a short, intense period of uncertainty, ambiguity, and unstable coalitions quickly congealed into a
predictable, symmetrical spiral between discrete factions.
If we are to move beyond this rebuttal, retort, and rejoinder mode of transaction, feminists will need, once again, to
elevate the level of discourse about gender. This will involve demonstrating that our primary goal is not the moral reform of
1
______________________________________________________________________________________________________________
errant colleagues, but the transformation of our theory of familiesand family therapy will only gain in the process. Such a
transformation requires situating gender at "ground zero."
A man can copulate with any woman who passes, the more anonymous the better. Men can also have clandestine
affairs... Human beings have also tried out the arrangement of multiple husbands or wives characteristic of some
species. Most commonly, men select a single mate for life and remain with her constantly; at least this is the myth of
monogamy in middle-class America ... [13, p. 45]
This paragraph is telling in a number of ways. Not only are women made to disappear by use of a universalizing male
pronoun, but, when they do appear, they are not represented as sexual subjects who can claim men for anonymous sex, have
clandestine affairs, or choose life-long monogamy. They surface only as objects of male desire, not as subjects in their own
right.
In other words, what Haley seems to mean by asserting that the "human species, with its complex capabilities, can follow
any of the mating habits of other animals" (p. 44), is that human males have the freedom to "exchange women" for purposes
of sex in as many ways as other male animals. Stated this way, Haley has unwittingly observed what anthropologists,
beginning with Levi-Strauss (19), have had to explain: that men have "certain rights [to] female[s] ... and that women do
not have the same rights [to] males" (26, p. 177).
2
______________________________________________________________________________________________________________
By losing hold of gender as an irreducible, orthogonal axis of family organization, Haley (13) buries women in his prose,
and then intermittently brings them back to life, as in this feminist swipe at psychoanalysis:
Many wives ... discontented with the narrow pattern of suburban life, have been stabilized for years by intensive
analysis. Instead of encouraging them to take action that would lead to a richer and more complex life, the therapy
prevents that change by imposing the idea that the problem is within their psyche rather than in their situation. [p.
43]
A similar incongruity between Haley's protofeminism and his patriarchal presumptions is to be found in his discussion of
hierarchy in Problem-Solving Therapy (14), published three years later in 1976. When making the point that every
"therapist must think through his [sic] ethical position" (p. 102),1 Haley writes:
Although one must accept the existence of hierarchy, that does not mean one needs to ... accept the status quo
either in terms of the economic structure of society or [in terms] of a particular [family] hierarchy. Everywhere there
are hierarchical arrangements that are unjust. One economic class suppresses another. Women are kept in a
subordinate position in both family and work groups merely because they are female. People are placed in
subordinate positions because of race or religion. Children are oppressed by their parents, in the sense of being
restricted and exploited in extreme ways. [p. 101-102]
Here, gender inequality, located inside as well as outside the family, appears along with race, class, religious and even
age oppression, as "wrongs that need righting" (14, p. 102). In other words, gender, like race and class, is construed by
Haley as a secondary, mediating variable that structures social existence, often in oppressive ways.
But having already distinguished gender from these other mediations by observing that gender (like age) orders
intrafamilial as well as extrafamilial hierarchies, Haley drops the subject. Two paragraphs later, gender has already been
obliterated as a distinctive social category by use of the generic "people," and generation now emerges as the "most
elementary" family hierarchy.
When we look at the family in terms of hierarchy, the organization includes people of different generations, of
different incomes, and of different degrees of intelligence and skills.... The most elementary hierarchy involves the
generation line [because] at the most simple level it is parents who nurture and discipline children ... [14, pp.
102-103]
Privileging generational relations by presuming there is anything simple and universal about parents caring for children
is anthropologically naive and factually inaccurate. Malinowski (20) made this claim in 1913, and revisionist critics ever
since have been documenting his errors. Indeed, if there is anything universal about the social organization of childcare it is,
as the anthropologist Rosaldo (25) concludes, that "women almost everywhere have daily responsibilities to feed and care
for children ... while men's ... obligations tend to be less regular and more bound up with extra-familial sorts of ties" (p.
394). Similar conclusions were reached by another anthropologist, Fox (8), who writes that "whether or not a mate
becomes attached to the mother on some more or less permanent basis is a variable matter" (p. 39).
In other words, one can never "simply" (to borrow Haley's word) talk about parenthood. There are only mothers and
fathers producing progeny, after which fathering seems to be a highly variable social occupation. Thus, it appears that the
division of labor by sex, with women bearing primary responsibility for childcare, may be even more "basic" to the
structure of kinship than the hierarchical organization of family members by age.
Determining which is more primary, "gender" or "generation," is not as important as establishing that both are essential
to any description of family relations. Even Freud took this premise as a given, situating the conditions of civilization on the
resolution of a universal family drama organized around the erotization of generational relationshipsthe Oedipus
complex. Thus, for Freud, Parsons, and Lévi-Strauss, the politics of age and sex hierarchies constituted the central force
field of family life and culture. In the context of this broadly based, intellectual tradition, the mysterious omission of the
category of gender from the first premises of family therapy becomes stranger and stranger.
3
______________________________________________________________________________________________________________
This strategy was almost certainly not intentional, yet it was accomplished painlessly and elegantly by what, with
hindsight, could be called a theoretical sleight of hand. By privileging the category of generation, and trivializing the
category of gender, Haley could dispense with the vexing question of sexual inequality in marriage thus: spouses, by virtue
of being at the same generational level, are, by definition, equals. In other words, merely by being age peers, and therefore
having generational parity, husbands and wives were presumed to occupy the same level of the domestic power hierarchy.
Haley's cautiously abstract definition of "generation" in Problem-Solving Therapy illustrates the elision through which
gender becomes incidental to generation: "By generation is meant a different order in the power hierarchy, such as parent
and child or manager and employee" (14, p. 109).
4
______________________________________________________________________________________________________________
Interestingly, in a 1954 revision of the paper, Parsons (23) abandoned this line of argument and actually conceded that
some degree of gender inequality was necessary for the preservation of the family unit! He rationalized this conclusion with
his special brand of functionalism:
It follows that the preservation of a functioning family system even of our type is incompatible with complete
equality of opportunity.... [This] is attributable to its conflict with the functional exigencies of personality and
cultural stabilization and socialization. [p. 422]
Yet, when stripped of functionalist rationalizations, Parsons' observations were stark and prescient. In his paper "Age
and Sex in the Social Structure," for example, Parsons asserted without equivocation or apology that the male world of
work, from which women were excluded, was the primary site of power and prestige in America. He went on to speculate
that if women were to compete with men in that public arena, the structure of family life would have to go through a
profound transformation:
[The wife/mother] is excluded from the struggle for power and prestige in the occupational sphere ... It is of course
possible for [her] to follow the masculine patterns and seek a career ... in direct competition with men of her own
class [but] this could only be [accomplished by] profound alterations in the structure of the family. [24, pp.
258-259]
These conclusions, which were theoretical hypotheses for Parsons in the 1940s, are now empirically based givens in the
sociological research literature on marriage and divorce. But even before the "evidence" was in, Parsons clearly had stated
his belief that the maintenance of the nuclear family under capitalism depended upon sexual inequality in the form of role
complementarity and the prescription of separate, gendered spheres. This is far more explicit and compromising than
Haley's (14) cool, contradictory assertion that families, by definition, are headed by two co-equal executives, Mom and
Dad, although he simultaneously asserts: "Women are kept in a subordinate position in both family and work groups merely
because they are female" (p. 102).
This oddly inconsistent position has gone without challenge in our field because the ideas occupying each of those
clauses have been kept apart from each other. Contradictions that Parsons had to confront could remain inconsequential in
family therapy as long as gender remained a marginal category. In fact, with the exception of Haley's remarks, I could not
find a single reference to gender, let alone gender inequality, in any of the classic family texts.2 Insofar as feminist concerns
entered our field at all, they were kept outside the family. This was accomplished by a reworking of the doctrine of separate
spheres.
5
______________________________________________________________________________________________________________
[T]hose who attempt to come to grips with man's [sic] interdependence often resort to mystical or holistic
philosophies connecting man with the universe. It is less painful to conceive of man as part of a universal
intelligence than as part of the family network, a living organism closer to our experience. We can embrace man the
cosmic hero, but we would prefer to turn a blind eye to his fight with his wife over who should have locked the front
door. [p. 12]
However, for Minuchin the rhetorician (21) the "family organism" begins to take on an ideological function. Indeed, the
organism metaphor seems to fuel his sense of mission because he maintains the political posture that to be for the family is
to be for the individual. This militant holism is not only an implicit critique of the culture of capitalism. It is also an explicit
political attack on the modern Welfare State, whose activities he perceives as intrusions into realms of privacy that threaten
self-determination, especially for the poor (21). Thus, by protecting the "family organism," we are protecting our sense of
personal integrity and individuality.
This view of the family-as-victim of the public sector has been most systematically developed by Lasch. In Haven in a
Heartless World (18), the first of a series of books on this theme, Lasch argued that the modern liberal approach to the
family was ultimately an excuse for middle-class professionals to tell private citizens how to live. He attempted to show
how the modern welfare state had displaced the family, writing of the "forces that ... invade the private realm" (p. xvii), and
the "assertion of social control over activities once left to individuals and their families" (p. xiv). He even has a section
entitled "The Proletarianization of Parenthood" (pp. 12-21), in which he analyzes the means whereby the state has usurped
parental prerogatives.
The politics of this account informed the rhetoric and professional agenda of both Haley and Minuchin during the
expansion of family therapy in the 1970s. They saw the family as being dismembered, invaded and regulated by
professional experts with their own agendas-bureaucratic, psycho-analytic, medical. Stating it crisply in Problem-Solving
Therapy, Haley (14) wrote, "Despite its humanitarian nature, the clinical field is also an important arm of social control in
society" (p. 196). Protecting the family against the intrusive violations by the social welfare and mental health industries
became part of the political culture of family therapy, and remains a central focus of Minuchin's current work (21).
What is important about the history of these ideas is that it highlights how our thinking about families was shaped by this
battle with the bureaucrats and the "experts" they relied on. Set against the specter of an enormously powerful, unwittingly
destructive, social control apparatus, we conjured up an image of "family" as a beleaguered but still hearty, "natural" unit.
"The family," Minuchin and Fishman (22) wrote in 1981, "is the natural context for both growth and healing ... The family
is a natural group which over time has evolved patterns of interacting" (p. 11).
This emphasis on Nature is the key, because it is related to the privileging of generational relationships and the
marginalizing of gender conflicts in our theory of family systems. Looking back, once again, to Haley's formal exposition of
the family life-cycle framework in Uncommon Therapy, it is clear that situating the family in Nature was crucial to his
universalizing of the generational construct.
The intellectual conceit organizing his discussion relies on a semi-whimsical, semi-serious play of analogies between the
social practices of human beings and those of other "beasts." Haley (13) writes:
6
______________________________________________________________________________________________________________
The systematic study of the human family ... has coincided with the study of the social systems of other animals ...
[H]uman beings as well as the other beasts of the field and the birds of the air have been observed in their natural
environment.... Men [sic] have in common with other creatures the developmental process of courtship, mating,
nest building, child rearing and the dislodging of offspring into a life of their own, but because of the more complex
social organization of human beings, the problems that arise during the family life cycle are unique to the species.
[p. 44]
The power and wit of exploiting this analogy becomes clear in the next page with a breathtaking one-liner: "A crucial
difference between men and all other animals is that man is the only animal with in-laws" (p. 45)!
By borrowing metaphors from ethology instead of confronting the dilemmas of cultural anthropology, Haley could keep it
simple, generating an image of "the family" that suited the demands of theory and the political agenda of the field in general.
By suggesting, for example, that symptoms could be understood as "comments" that conveyed distress about the predictable
difficulties of generational development throughout the life cycle, Haley exploited a developmental metaphor to score a
political point. This is because his assertion contained the implication, made more or less explicit, that families, if they were
not interfered with, could evolve home-grown solutions to many of these developmental crises.
This idea eventually came to incorporate Minuchin's image of family-as-organism and Bateson's "mind and nature"
metaphors. In its current usage, "family development" is analogically tied to representations of evolution so that the
argument now reads something like this: Were it not for developmental snags and external meddlers, families would
"naturally" grow and develop, and in the process emerge as more complex forms of life.
Much has been accomplished (and obscured) by this evolutionary analogy. By turning families into organisms, a
naturalistic, developmental frame could be used to normalize psychological problems. This has been useful in protecting
individuals and the sphere of private life from the truly destructive impact of medical and psychiatric interventionism.
Moreover, the generational emphasis, with its associated imagery of the timeless universality of cycles of birth and death,
has been empowering to parents needlessly intimidated by professional advice givers. In this regard, we might remember
that the standard clinical maneuver of "putting the parents in charge" is less a comment to unruly children than a challenge
to interfering professionals.
Thus, by proselytizing about the integrity of the family unit, and emphasizing the "natural order" of the generations,
family therapists were actually waging a political battle on behalf of parents against the State (and competing with other
segments of the mental health establishment for those parents' allegiance).
7
______________________________________________________________________________________________________________
8
______________________________________________________________________________________________________________
and talk that, however imperfectly, preserves the integrity of the clinical enterprise. This, in turn, requires a philosophically
precise definition of what psychotherapy is, and what it is not.
The best contemporary description we have generated is captured by Maturana's phrase "the conversational domain,"
although I prefer crediting the idea to its earliest source, "Anna O," (a.k.a. Bertha Pappenheim), who coined the phrase "the
talking cure" to describe her work with Breuer almost 100 years ago. Pappenheim's poetic and prescient image,
anticipating the modern constructivist view of the treatment situation, provides a point of entry into the problem at hand.
Containing psychotherapy within the conceptual boundaries of a conversation clarifies its limits and possibilities.
Therapeutic talk is, of course, all about the politics of influence. It is a conversational domain that is a concrete as well as
symbolic platform on which players maneuver for position and control of meaning. If, then, we were to take as our subject
the politics of heterosexual relationships, and the means by which those politics organize the politics of family therapy, we
could then define our clinical task as the search for a way to talk to families about both these politicized spheres. In other
words, the question becomes: How can we make the sexual politics of observed and observing systems a subject for
therapeutic conversation?
Bringing sexual politics into the dialogic realm would mean discussing the dilemmas of love and power, and discussing
the problems of discussing those dilemmas in relation to a therapist of a particular sex and point of view. For example, in a
recent case seen at the Ackerman Institute by Gillian Walker and myself, Walker asked a Black man who had been
"resisting" our line of questioning, "What best explains your not wanting to tell me too much: that I'm White, female, or
highly educated?" The man, married to a White woman, answered immediately, "Mostly that you are a woman. I'm used to
White people and I don't care that much about education." This exchange freed up the conversation so that sex, race, and
class (in that order) were no longer forbidden subjects, but became the subject of the therapy.
Similarly, in another case that Robert Simon and I saw at the Ackerman, a young, decidedly "unfeminist" wife
complained, after some prodding, that she was afraid she would forget what she had to say while waiting for her husband to
finish speaking. When I, intrigued, asked her what she thought it meant that I'd asked her husband to speak first, she blurted
out, "Well, we live in a patriarchal society. I guess you are caught up in it too."!
Once it becomes absolutely clear that psychotherapy is nothing more and nothing less than talk, then it is best to
conceive of family therapy as a rhetorical strategy that helps elucidate the dilemmas of love and power between men and
women living in a patriarchal society. This means capturing in language a double description of the bonds of love, a
description that includes both circular reciprocity and hierarchical inequality. Developing questions, metaphors, and stories
that make such talk possible has become the central focus of my clinical work.
REFERENCES
1. Bateson, G., Naven. Stanford CA: Stanford University Press, 1958.
2. Beechey, V., Women and production: A critical analysis of some sociological theories of women's work. In A.
Kuhn & A.M. Wolpe (eds.), Feminism and materialism. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1978.
3. Belenkey, M., Clinchy, B., Goldberger, N. and Tarule, J., Women's ways of knowing. New York: Basic Books,
1986.
4. Bogdan, J. L., Family organization as an ecology of ideas: An alternative to the reification of family systems.
Family Process, 23, 375-388, 1984.
9
______________________________________________________________________________________________________________
5. Braverman, L., Beyond families: Strategic family therapy and the female client. Family Therapy, 8, 143-152,
1986.
6. Collier, J., Rosaldo, M. and Yanagisako, S., Is there a family? New anthropological views. In B. Thorne (ed.),
Rethinking the family. New York: Longman, 1982.
7. Dimen-Schein, M., The anthropological imagination. New York: McGraw-Hill, 1977.
8. Fox, R., Kinship and marriage. London: Penguin Books, 1967.
9. Gilligan, C., In a different voice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1982.
10. Goldner, V., Feminism and family therapy. Family Process, 24, 31-47, 1985.
11. Goldner, V., Warning: Family therapy may be hazardous to your health. Family Therapy Networker, 9(6), 18-23,
1985.
12. Goldner, V., Instrumentalism, feminism and the limits of family therapy. Journal of Family Psychology, 1,
109-116, 1987.
13. Haley, J., Uncommon therapy: The psychiatric techniques of Milton H. Erickson, M.D. New York: W.W. Norton,
1973.
14. Haley, J., Problem-solving therapy. San Francisco: Jossey-Bass, 1976.
15. Howard, J., Blumstein, P. and Schwartz, P., Sex, power, and influence tactics in intimate relationships. Journal of
Personality and Social Psychology, 51, 102-109, 1986.
16. Keller, E. F., Reflections on gender and science. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1985.
17. Kollock, P., Blumstein, P. and Schwartz, P., Sex, power, and interaction: Conversational privileges and duties.
American Sociological Review, 50, 34-46, 1985.
18. Lasch, C., Haven in a heartless world: The family besieged. New York: Basic Books, 1977.
19. Levi-Strauss, C., The elementary structures of kinship. Boston: Beacon Press, 1969.
20. Malinowski, B., The family among the Australian aborigines. London: University of London Press, 1913.
21. Minuchin, S., Family kaleidoscope. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1984.
22. Minuchin, S. and Fishman, H. C., Family therapy techniques. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1981.
23. Parsons, T., Essays in sociological theory. New York: Free Press, 1954.
24. Parsons, T., Age and sex in the social structure. In R.L. Coser (ed.), The family: Its structure and functions. New
York: St. Martin's Press, 1964.
25. Rosaldo, M. Z., The use and abuse of anthropology: Reflections on feminism and cross-cultural understanding.
Signs, 5, 389-417, 1980.
26. Rubin, G., The traffic in women: Notes on the political economy of sex. In R. Reiter (ed.), Toward an
anthropology of women. New York: Monthly Review Press, 1978.
27. Ruddick, S., Maternal thinking. In B. Thorne (ed.), Rethinking the family. New York: Longman, 1982.
28. Sluzki, C. E. and Ransom, D. C., (eds.). Double bind: The foundation of the communicational approach to the
family. New York: Grune & Stratton, 1976.
Manuscript received February 1, 1987; Revisions submitted August 26, 1987; Accepted August 31, 1987.
1Haley does make a formal, footnoted disclaimer in Problem-Solving Therapy (p. 2) about his use of "he" when referring to
therapists who can be of either sex. Apparently, he became aware of the "pronoun problem" after the publication of Uncommon
Therapy, in which he uncritically used "men" as a synonym for "human beings."
2From this perspective, Haley's inconsistencies, however politically problematic, represent an attempt to address a problem that
no one else thought to name. See Braverman (5, p. 149) for other examples of Haley's prescient attention to matters of sexual
politics.
10