Nature of Judicial Review The
Nature of Judicial Review The
Nature of Judicial Review The
Harry H. WeIfingtont
* This Article was originally presented, in somewhat different form, as the Thirty-Sixth Annual
Benjamin N. Cardozo Lecture, delivered on March 31, 1981, to the Association of the Bar of the City
of New York. See 36 REC. A.B. CITY N.Y. 360 (1981).
t Dean and Edward J. Phelps Professor of Law, Yale Law School.
1. B. CARDOZO, THE NATURE OF THE JUDICIAL PROCESS (1921).
2. 5 U.S. (1 Cranch) 137 (1803).
3. See R. JACKSON, THE STRUGGLE FOR JUDICIAL SUPREMACY (1941); Lerner, The Great Con-
stitutional War, 18 VA. Q. REV. 530 (1942); Leuchtenburg, The Origins of Franklin D. Roosevelt's
"Court-Packing" Plan, 1966 SUP. CT. REV. 347.
4. Brown v. Board of Educ., 347 U.S. 483 (1954).
5. Reynolds v. Sims, 377 U.S. 533 (1964); Baker v. Carr, 369 U.S. 186 (1962).
6. Doe v. Bolton, 410 U.S. 179 (1973); Roe v. Wade, 410 U.S. 113 (1973).
7. See, e.g., J. CHOPER, JUDICIAL REVIEW AND THE NATIONAL POLITICAL PROCESS (1980); J.
ELY, DEMOCRACY AND DISTRUST (1980); M. PERRY, THE CONSTITUTION, THE COURTS, AND
HUMAN RIGHTS: AN INQUIRY INTO THE LEGITIMACY OF CONSTITUTIONAL POLICY MAKING BY THE
JUDICIARY (forthcoming).
8. See, e.g., A. BICKEL, THE LEAST DANGEROUS BRANCH (1962); C. BLACK, THE PEOPLE AND
THE COURT (1960); Wechsler, Toward Neutral Principlesof ConstitutionalLaw, 73 HARV. L. REV.
1 (1959). See also Deutsch, Neutrality, Legitimacy, and the Supreme Court: Some IntersectionsBe-
tween Law and Political Science, 20 STAN. L. REV. 169 (1968).
9. See generally C. BLACK, STRUCTURE AND RELATIONSHIP IN CONSTITUTIONAL LAW 77-78, 89-
90 (1969) (nonlegislative actions, such as those of law enforcement officers, also give rise to constitu-
tional decisions).
2
Majoritarianism, taken by itself, may be thought to require that each
citizen be granted one equal vote, and that simple majorities control the
course of government.10 Although adopted in more or less this form by the
reapportionment cases," this simple theory of political fairness1 2 is neither
established by nor easily reconciled with the Constitution. That document
forbids the direct popular electioni of the President; it does not forbid ger-
rymanders. 13 And by direct constitutional command, Senators chosen by
electorates of varying size wield equal voting power.14 Moreover, the Con-
stitution protects the important advantage of wealth in the political pro-
cess: the First Amendment forbids significant governmental restraints on
individuals who have the means and the desire to finance the widespread
expression of their political opinions.1"
When we move from the deep structure of the Constitution to well-
established legislative practice we find-and it is hardly a surprise-a fur-
ther dilution of majority rule. Thus, although recently diminished, senior-
ity prerogatives remain considerable, 6 and committee chairmen exercise
substantial power." Congressmen are dependent on their staffs, and con-
gressional staffs advance their own agenda.18 The press,1 and lobbyists
and lawyers representing powerful corporate and union clients, exert ex-
traordinary influence on the legislature and, of course, on other branches
of government-elected and appointed.20
The standard practices of government departments and agencies diverge
still further from simple majoritarian precepts. Extensive job security and
sheer numerical weight invest bureaucrats with considerable control over
policy. 21 Indeed, the bureaucracy is often entrenched firmly enough to ex-
ercise its power in the teeth of popular mandates. 22 Nor is it easy for the
people's representatives to revoke the broad delegations of power that
make such entrenchment possible. The needs that initially prompted the
establishment of an agency or bureau may still exist, or, indeed, have
grown increasingly acute. In such circumstances, the legislature's depen-
dence on the agency will force it to acquiesce in at least certain unpopular
agency initiatives. 23 Moreover, even when the legislature is willing to
abolish a particular agency or bureau, private groups that have relied on
its policies or existence may fiercely oppose the revocation of delegated
power. 4 It is the rare case in which neither a sizeable group of legislators
18. See M. MALBIN, UNELECTED REPRESENTATIVES: CONGRESSIONAL STAFF AND THE FUTURE
OF REPRESENTATIVE GOVERNMENTS (1980).
19. See, e.g., D. CATER, THE FOURTH BRANCH OF GOVERNMENT (1959) (discussing power of the
press); Robinson, Television and American Politics: 1956-1976, 48 PUB. INT. 3, 11-14 (1977) (dis-
cussing influence of television news coverage on political opinions).
20. As one commentator notes:
[Ilt is generally agreed that by transmitting pertinent information to key lawmakers, by skill-
fully and selectively applying pressure at critical points in the system, and by expending mas-
sive sums of money-not infrequently in an abusive, occasionally criminal, manner-they
[lobbyists] are able to exercise power well beyond the force of the numbers of people they
represent.
J. CHOPER, supra note 7, at 23. See also R. DAHL, DEMOCRACY IN THE UNITED STATES 454 (3d ed.
1976); M. MAYER, THE LAWYERS 51-52 (1966); D. TRUMAN, THE GOVERNMENTAL PROCESS 352-94
(2d ed. 1971).
21. See W. NISKANEN, BUREAUCRACY AND REPRESENTATIVE GOVERNMENT 138-54 (1971) (bu-
reaucracy acts contrary to popular will). The point is well made by Hodding Carter with respect to
the Department of State. See Carter,The Unequal BureaucraticContest, Wall St. J., Jan. 8, 1981, at
21, col. 3; see also A. DOWNS, INSIDE BUREAUCRACY 134-35, 152-53 (1967) (difficulty of controlling
bureaucracy); Cutler & Johnson, Regulation and the Political Process, 84 YALE L.J. 1395, 1408-09
(1975) (ability of politicians to influence agency policy decreases as agency ages and presumption of
independence and expertise grows).
22. See W. NISKANEN, supra note 21, at 138-54; Cutler & Johnson, supra note 21, at 1401 n.21
(Federal Reserve continues to implement monetary policies despite attacks); c. Nathan, The "Admin-
istrative Presidency," 44 PUB. INT. 40 (1976) (controlling bureaucracy is one of most difficult jobs
facing President).
23. With respect to many regulatory endeavors, "it may be impossible in the nature of the subject
matter to specify with particularity the course to be followed." Stewart, The Reformation of American
Administrative Law, 88 HARV. L. REV. 1667, 1695 (1975). In addition, Congress' own institutional
shortcomings compel it to accept some agency discretion as an inevitable cost of effecting its regulatory
goals. Id. at 1695-96.
24. Thus, for example, businesses typically support regulations that insulate them from competi-
tion in the marketplace. See R. NOLL, N. PECK, & J. MCGOWAN, ECONOMIC ASPECTS OF TELEVI-
SION REGULATION 205-07 (1973); Wilson, The Rise of the BureaucraticState, 41 PUB. INT. 77, 98-99
nor a powerful private group has a large stake in the survival of a govern-
ment bureau. Therefore, it is common for individuals who are neither
elected nor recently appointed by elected officials to direct or influence
significantly the course of government.
It is possible to view these countermajoritarian forces in the Constitu-
tion, legislatures, the bureaucracy, and private associations as flaws in our
democratic system, and to characterize government as a failed attempt to
achieve the simple majoritarian ideal. "5 But such a view seems mistaken.
While countermajoritarian forces impede the immediate implementation
of majority preferences and sometimes result in their reformulation, the
delay and reformulation often is a prudent constraint on governmental
action.
Such forced incrementalism provides several important benefits: First,
impediments to the instant gratification of majorities allow proposals for
legislative change to be considered carefully. This may be desirable even
though the creation of a particular majority itself has been time-consum-
ing. For it is surely the case that, in creating a majority for a proposal,
proponents may fail to examine fully the proposal's demerits.2 6 Second,
reliance on extended debate allows the political system to gauge the inten-
sity with which a position is advanced, rather than merely the number of
people who advance it.27 Third, while it is easy to belittle an earlier gen-
eration's exaggerated faith in administrative expertise, it is also easy to
forget that the influence of the bureaucracy in departments and agencies
does allow dedicated administrators with on-site experience to make con- 28
structive and often unpopular contributions to government policy.
Fourth, the deliberate allocation of power to groups not dominated by a
present coalition of fifty-one percent insures both that no one "faction"
will acquire too much power, and that affirmative governmental decisions
(1975). They also favor regulations that simply impose additional costs; having invested heavily to
comply with governmental requirements, businesses often fear the comparative cost-advantage deregu-
lation would afford future entrants into their markets. See N.Y. Times, Aug. 2, 1979, at A14, col. 1
(GM, after investing to meet fuel-efficiency standards, supports them).
25. See infra note 68. But see Shapiro, JudicialModesty, Political Reality, and Preferred Posi-
tion, 47 CORNELL L.Q. 175 (1962).
26. See Bickel, supra note 8, at 70 (by refusing to act through jurisdictional and other techniques,
the Court seeks to "elicit the correct answers to certain prudential questions" from the political pro-
cess); Bickel & Wellington, Legislative Purposeand the Judcial Process: The Lincoln Mills Case, 71
HARV. L. REV. 1, 27 (1957) (Congress, in responding to popular will, may unknowingly sacrifice
long-range values for immediate results; such values are protected through judicial review).
27. See Kendall & Carey, The "Intensity" Problem and Democratic Theory, 62 AM. POL. SC.
REV. 5 (1968). See also A. BICKEL, REFORM AND CONTINUITY 16, 17 (1971) (American political
system recognizes that opinions, preferences and interests vary in intensity); R. MUSGRAVE & P.
MUSGRAVE, PUBLIC FINANCE IN THEORY AND PRACTICE 113-15 (2d ed. 1976) (intensity of preference
registered through log-rolling and coalition formation).
28. A. BURNS, REFLECTIONS OF AN ECONOMIC POLICY-MAKER 418-22 (1978) (discussing ability
of Federal Reserve to advance unpopular policies).
will rest on a broader and more stable base than simple majorities can
provide.29 Finally, by promoting stability, countermajoritarian practices
protect from abrupt defeat expectations invited by existing arrangements."
The majoritarian theory adopted by the reapportionment decisions does
not override these justifications of countermajoritarian practices. For the
reapportionment decisions have had no effect on countervailing doctrines
that either explicitly or implicitly established the constitutional importance
of incremental change. The vagueness and delegation doctrines, for exam-
ple, have been described as requiring legislatures to engage in careful de-
liberation before they substantially alter the legal landscape." When so
employed, these doctrines impose upon law-makers duties of care that are
neither mandated by, nor in many circumstances consistent with, a simple
majoritarian scheme.
Other doctrines (also unaffected by the reapportionment decisions) do
not directly foster, but instead presuppose incremental change, and thus
provide constitutional support for those countermajoritarian practices that
make incremental change possible. In particular, the efficacy of doctrines
that emphasize the importance of an individual's "reliance interest" de-
pends substantially on the political stability that our countermajoritarian
practices foster. Such doctrines have been developed, among other areas,
under the due process, takings, and contract clauses. For example,
whether an interest rises to the level of "property" for purposes of the
due process clause depends to a considerable extent on whether the rele-
vant authorities have led the possessor of that interest to rely on its secur-
ity and inviolability." Similarly, a takings or contract clause claim may be
seriously weakened by a showing that the possessor of the interest at issue
had always been aware of the existence of a superseding regulatory mech-
anism.3 Indeed, one commentator has noted that the contracts clause, al-
29. See A. BICKEL, supra note 27, at 16-19; R. DAHL, supra note 20, at 53-59 (American politics
not fully democratic; partitioning ecourages incremental changes by creating strongholds from which
minorities can block policy changes); Black, NationalLawmaking by Initiative?Let's Think Twice, 8
HUM. RTS. 28, 30-31 (1979) (legislative process contains structural and procedural safeguards that
protect minority interests and promote compromise). On incremental change generally, see D.
BRAYBROOKE & C. LINDBLOM, A STRATEGY OF DECISION (1963).
30. See G. CALABRESI, A COMMON LAW FOR THE AGE OF STATUTES 3 (1982).
31. See id. at 18.
32. See, e.g., Perry v. Sindermann, 408 U.S. 593 (1972) (whether state provided de facto support
for complainant's reliance is relevant to status of complainant's interest under due process clause);
Board of Regents v. Roth, 408 U.S. 564 (1972) (property interest not created by unilateral or merely
subjective expectation).
33. With respect to the contract clause, compare Allied Structural Steel Co. v. Spannaus, 438 U.S.
234, 249-50 (1978) (law impairing private pension agreement void because, among other things, it
imposed an unanticipated retroactive obligation in field that legislature had not previously regulated)
with Veix v. Sixth Ward Bldg. & Loan Ass'n, 310 U.S. 32, 38 (1940) (fact that complainant had
"purchased into an enterprise already regulated in the particular to which he now objects" relevant to
constitutionality of impairment).
With respect to the takings clause, compare Kaiser Aetna v. United States, 444 U.S. 164 (1979)
though originally of broader scope, has been narrowed to bar only the
disruption of reasonable expectations.34
The instability fostered by a government that instantly gratified majori-
ties would slow or halt the growth of reasonable expectations."5 By thus
destroying the foundations of reliance, such an overridingly majoritarian
scheme would eventually deprive the property and contract clauses of
what they are currently understood to protect.
Indirect support for the countermajoritarian value of continuity is also
provided by the broad constitutional prohibition of ex post facto laws.3"
That proscription is intended to allow reliance upon the particular rights
and duties established by the legislature.37 Such security and repose as the
proscription seeks to protect, however, could never develop in the absence
of mechanisms that often impede short-run, direct accountability.
These features of our social and legal organization reinforce the pro-
position that the bureaucracy, the congressional staff, the special pleaders,
and others cannot be condemned because of their countermajoritarian
character. To the contrary, it is precisely by exercising their limited free-
dom from the majority that these political forces advance values important
to our complex constitutional design.
3
Although not worrisome simply because they are countermajoritarian,
at least some of the political forces discussed above are worrisome indeed.
The perspective of minority power holders is often constrained by the
needs of their constituents. Yet those constituents are not themselves disin-
terested: where they seek to check the efforts of the majority, they do so
out of self interest. Accordingly, these countermajoritarian forces cannot
be relied upon merely to restrain majority willfulness. Instead, if given the
opportunity, such forces may hold hostage to minority demands even those
(government's attempt to compel free public use of corporation's assets went so far beyond ordinary
regulation as to interfere unconstitutionally with corporation's reasonable investment-backed expecta-
tions) with Penn Cent. Transp. Co. v. New York City, 438 U.S. 104, 124, 135-36 (1978) (relevant to
landmark preservation law's validity that it did not interfere with "distinct investment-backed expec-
tions") and City of Pittsburgh v. Alco Parking Corp., 417 U.S. 369 (1974) (incremental increase in
preexisting gross-receipts tax not taking even where tax, in combination with government-subsidized
competition, renders business unprofitable).
34. See J. ELY, supra note 7, at 92.
35. See G. CALABRESI, supra note 30, at 3 ("If legal-political institutions are too responsive to
change, however, temporary and unstable majorities are apt quickly to impose their will. New laws
are passed only to be followed by quick reversal at the next election, leading to uncertainty and to the
defeat of legitimate expectations.")
36. U.S. CONST. art. I, § 10.
37. See Weaver v. Graham, 101 S. Ct. 960, 964 (1981) (Framers sought through prohibition "to
assure that legislative acts give fair warning of their effect and permit individuals to rely on their
meaning until explicitly changed").
38. This problem is discussed in Calabresi's splendid book, see supra note 30, at 6, 48-49, 124-29.
It is worth noting that Calabresi's solution is carefully tailored to preserve the balance between con-
tinuity and change that has distinguished American common law. Id. at 118-19.
39. See Fiss, The Supreme Court, 1978 Term-Foreword: The Forms of Justice, 93 HARV. L.
REV. 1, 12-13 (1979). By disinterested, of course, I do not mean uninterested. I do mean one who is
not influenced by selfish motives or personal advantage. And by generalist, I do not necessarily mean a
Renaissance Person. I certainly do not mean an amateur. I do mean one who is engaged with and
knowledgeable about the law, conceived broadly.
40. See id. at 1-12; Wellington, Common Law Rules and ConstitutionalDouble Standards:Some
Notes on Adjudication, 83 YALE L.J. 221, 248-49 (1973).
41. See A. BICKEL, THE SUPREME COURT AND THE IDEA OF PROGRESS 86-87 (1970); Wellington,
supra note 40, at 246-48.
42. This point is elaborated in Wellington, supra note 40, at 246-48.
ues to which it has long adhered 4 3-the courts may be seen as the key
political institution charged with taking account of our public traditions.
The costs of uniting present and past should be acknowledged: our
predecessors too were imperfect. Nevertheless, a governmental structure
that fails to unite a nation's present with its past necessarily fails to pre-
serve values to which its citizens may attach considerable weight. It fails
to make a contemporary effort to understand what we have been or have
wished as a people to become, and thus it fails to give effect to what might
be called the moral ideals of the community. Those ideals cannot be un-
derstood by the bureaucracy, the special pleaders, and the congressional
staffers. Theirs is a tunnel vision, and the tunnel vision of one is not offset
by that of the others. Nor would these ideals be given adequate voice in a
simple majoritarian government where the passionate and self-interested
concerns of the moment were too easily accorded sovereignty. 4
Many may have trouble with the view that courts should seek to dis-
cover and use the moral ideals of the community as a source of legal prin-
ciples.4 5 But it is less controversial, and for present purposes sufficient, to
note that courts do in fact seek to preserve principles that are threatened
by majority preferences, and that they do so even in cases where the aban-
donment of those principles would not raise constitutional questions.
The most important method courts use in this task is statutory interpre-
tation. It is standard and appropriate for courts to employ general legal
principles to construe the open texture of statutes.46 This is not necessarily
countermajoritarian, although sometimes statutory purpose and general
legal principles pull in different directions.47 Sometimes interpretation is
clearly countermajoritarian as the following three cases show. In none am
I concerned with whether the particular decision is correct. The cases are
used to demonstrate an approach, a judicial function, that contributes to,
and is inherent in, the judicial process.48
Roto-Lith v. Bartlett," a contract case, provides an example of this ju-
dicial function. The common law, concerned with the principle of volunta-
rism, had long required assent as a necessary condition of binding con-
50. See Iselin v. United States, 271 U.S. 136, 139 (1926); Prescott v. Jones, 69 N.H. 305, 305-6,
41 A. 352, 352-53 (1898); More v. New York Bowery Fire Ins. Co., 130 N.Y. 537, 547, 29 N.E. 757,
759 (1892). For an interesting historical perspective on voluntarism and competing concepts in con-
tracts, see Gordley, Equality in Exchange, 69 CALIF. L. REV. 1587 (1981).
51. See U.C.C. § 2-207 (1972).
52. Id.
53. 297 F.2d 497, 500 (1st. Cir. 1962).
54. See, e.g., Comment, Commercial Law-Offer and Acceptance-Under Uniform Commercial
Code Purchaserof Goods Is Bound by Disclaimerof WarrantiesContainedin Seller's Expression of
Acceptance, 76 HARV. L. REV. 1481, 1482-83 (1963) (criticizing Roto-Lith); Comment, Nonconform-
ing Acceptances Under Section 2-207 of the Uniform Commercial Code: An End to the Battle of the
Forms, 30 U. CHI. L. REV. 540, 553-54 (1963) (same).
55. The Supreme Court recently applied a very similar principle to protect states from the inad-
vertent assumption of burdens stemming from "contracts" or agreements executed by the federal gov-
ernment pursuant to its spending power. See Pennhurst State School & Hosp. v. Halderman, 451
U.S. 1 (1981). The Court narrowly construed a federal "grant-in-aid" statute to limit the obligation it
imposed on states as a condition of the receipt of federal funds. The Court did not prospectively forbid
the imposition of substantial obligations on states, but merely required, in accordance with the com-
495
mon-law principle advanced in Roto-Lith, that those obligations be stated clearly and specifically by
Congress. Id. at 22-27. The Court also instructed Congress to make unmistakably plain its intent to
rely on Section 5 of the Fourteenth Amendment. Id. at 15-16. This instruction makes more difficult
the enactment of legislation that coerces state behavior; it also insures that states receive notice of the
federal requirements with which they must comply.
Neither this discussion of Pennhurstnor my use of any other case is intended to imply agreement
with substantive results. While endorsing the judicial technique that moderates majorities without
permanently foreclosing legislative choices, I would readily concede that this technique, like every
other, can be abused.
56. 380 U.S. 263 (1965).
57. Id. at 268.
58. Id. at 269-70.
59. Id. at 270.
60. "It is no longer disputed that workers cannot be dismissed from employment because of their
union affiliations." Phelps Dodge Corp. v. NLRB, 313 U.S. 177, 183 (1941). See J. GETMAN, LABOR
RELATIONS 113-14 (1978).
61. 380 U.S. 263, 267 (1965).
496
state of economic due process today makes it certain that "the clearest
manifestation of [contrary] legislative intent" would succeed.
Vincent v. Pabst 6 2 provides a more complicated
example of counter-
majoritarian judicial revision and reveals a different aspect of the judicial
role. That case involved a Wisconsin statute that denied recovery to a tort
plaintiff whose own negligence was equal to or greater than the negli-
gence of the defendant."3 Its retention of contributory negligence put the
statute at odds with the common law, which, by the time Vincent was
decided, was moving rapidly toward full comparative negligence.6" Thus,
the circumstances underlying Vincent were both different from and simi-
lar to those from which Roto-Lith and Darlington arose: in each case
legislation, for better or worse, compromised principles of importance in
the relevant jurisprudence. In Vincent, however, the common law had
overtaken the legislation. The principle involved was relatively new in
terms of its legal status. Unlike the courts in Roto-Lith and Darlington,
the Vincent court was not acting as a guardian of the past.
The Vincent court, moreover, did not directly vitiate and rewrite the
Wisconsin statute to conform to the principle of the common law. Perhaps
because it was aware that the legislature had considered and rejected com-
parative negligence, members of the court chose the less intrusive, though
still countermajoritarian, tactic of threatening to rewrite if the legislature
did not act itself. 5 In order to make that threat credible, they had first to
establish that the court possessed the power to apply the common law."6
They accomplished this through a deliberate and plain misconstruction. In
particular, several Justices held that the statute covered only those cases in
which the plaintiffs negligence was less than the defendant's; as to all
other cases, these Justices found the statute to be silent. Tailored to per-
mit a consistent application of the common law, this misconstruction con-
stituted not direct, but "prospective" countermajoritarian revision.
The insight to be taken from this brief excursion into non-constitutional
adjudication is that even when no constitutional question is raised, the
courts, like other imperfectly representative institutions, may sometimes
blunt the efforts of majorities. Unlike those other institutions, however,
the courts check majorities in a selective and deliberate fashion. In partic-
ular, they seek to preserve principles that, from their generalist perspec-
tive, are, for one reason or another, significant. 7
62. 47 Wis. 2d 120, 177 N.W.2d 513 (1970). My knowledge of the case, and my analysis of it,
stem from G. CALABRESI, supra note 30, at 36-43, 210 nn.16-29.
63. WIS. STAT. ANN. § 895.045 (West 1966).
64. See G. CALABRESI, supra note 30, at 210 nn.18-19.
65. Id. at 36.
66. Id. at 36-37.
67. See Bickel & Wellington, supra note 26, at 27.
4
The foregoing discussion provides reasons for challenging the standard
critique of judicial review. That critique supposes that from our practice
in the normal course, adherence to the principle of simple majority control
can be inferred. According to the critique, divergences from this principle
are not deliberate; instead, no matter how frequently encountered, they
are dismissed as inadvertent failures to achieve the majoritarian ideal. 8 As
I have suggested, however, few of our practices are overridingly
majoritarian. To the contrary, wherever our system creates a danger of
majority willfulness, some tempering device is interposed. Accordingly, the
critics of judicial review should not ask us to assume that any failure to
support the preferences of majorities requires special or extraordinary jus-
tification. Indeed, it may be that the critics should bear the burden of
persuasion. After all, it is they who question a one hundred and fifty-year
old precedent that fits comfortably within our complex governmental
structure and that makes a distinctive contribution to that structure.
Of course, the critics may respond that other countermajoritarian insti-
tutions do not exercise power after the enactment of legislation. Thus, one
commentator has recently suggested that "[t]he existing antimajoritarian
influences in . . . legislatures, capable though they may be in blocking
legislation, are not well situated to get legislation passed in the face of
majority opposition."'" This commentator does recognize that "[tihere may
• . . exist situations in which a majority cannot pass a law repealing old
legislation because of minority resistance." 70 And I am sure he knows that
countermajoritarian institutions do, apart from judicial review, exercise
power after the fact. Statutory interpretation by agencies, departments,
and courts, for example, often departs from legislative intent. But more
importantly, it is not so much the timing, as it is the nature, of a declara-
tion of unconstitutionality that is significant. Assume that the Court, in
order to make the short-run effects of judicial review more like "[t]he ex-
isting antimajoritarian influences in legislatures," issued binding constitu-
tional opinions only before the legislature acted. Would it matter very
68. See A. BICKEL, supra note 8, at 18 ("[I]mpurities and imperfections, if such they be, in one
part of the system are no argument for total departure from the desired norm in another part."); J.
CHOPER, supra note 7, at 57-59 (that representative institutions are imperfectly majoritarian does not
affect legitimacy of judicial review); R. DWORKIN, TAKING RIGHTS SERIOUSLY 141 (1977) (that legis-
latures are imperfectly majoritarian "does not so much undermine the argument from democracy as
call for more democracy"). See also J. ELY, supra note 7, at 67. But see Hazard, The Supreme Court
as a Legislature, 64 CORNELL L. REV. 1, 10-11 (1978) (arguing that democratic principles tolerate
allocation of some power to unrepresentative institutions); Rostow, The DemocraticCharacterof Ju-
dicial Review, 66 HARV. L. REV. 193, 197-200 (1952) (noting similarity between judicial review and
other well-established countermajoritarian practices).
69. See J. ELY, supra note 7, at 67 (citing Choper, The Supreme Court and the Political
Branches: Democratic Theory and Practice, 122 U. PA. L. REV. 810, 830-32 (1974)).
70. Id.
much, for these purposes?" I think not because I believe that the real
anxiety over judicial review is not its countermajoritarian nature as such;
it is rather the seeming finality of a constitutional pronouncement by the
Supreme Court.
5
The task of defending judicial review is a different one if the anxiety
over the practice derives from problems of finality rather than from the
inescapable fact that judicial review is countermajoritarian. In order to
distinguish between these tasks, it may be helpful, before addressing the
issue of finality, to examine briefly a justification of judicial review that is
concerned primarily with its countermajoritarian nature.
Today the most prominent such justification draws its inspiration from
the second and third paragraphs of footnote four of a 1938 case, United
States v. Carolene Products Co. 72 But for the footnote, the case would not
be remembered. It stands with others of its time in sustaining economic
legislation that less than a decade earlier would have been invalidated
under the due process clause. Speaking for the Court, Justice Stone made
it plain that economic legislation was to enjoy a powerful presumption of
constitutionality, indeed, that it would survive challenge under that once
formidable clause if the legislation had a "rational basis."
The footnote, after suggesting that this presumption might have less
force when legislation is questioned under constitutional provisions that
are more linguistically precise than due process, continues as follows:
71. For reasons largely unrelated to the countermajoritarian difficulty, Article III has been con-
strued to forbid premature judicial judgments. See Poe v. Ullman, 367 U.S. 497 (1961). For a differ-
ent view of Article III, see A. BICKEL, supra note 8, at 115-16.
72. 304 U.S. 144, 152 n.4 (1938).
73. Id. at 152, 152 n.4, 153.
While malfunction in the process may be a good reason for the exercise
of judicial review, the notion that its absence requires the denial of review
is, at least on first impression, both striking and contrary to our intuitions.
Are there not substantive malfunctions that require serious judicial re-
view? Is it not the case, for example, that government sometimes intrudes
on individual autonomy and privacy without sufficient justification? Is not
the Court's capacity here as great, and its role as important, as when the
perceived malfunction is one of process?
Professor Ely's "answer" is emphatically negative:
den on proponents of judicial review. Surely Ely does not overcome the
problem that he thinks they present. For there are at least two inevitable
and fatal difficulties with his attempt to bar consideration of values in
constitutional adjudication. First, the judicial diagnosis of a process mal-
function may itself entail a value determination. For example, given the
method for selecting United States senators and the gerrymander, it is far
from clear how, in many situations, a court can know whether a legisla-
tive apportionment is improper, unless, of course, it develops a theory of
political fairness. But can anyone develop such a theory without making
at least one value determination?" Second, the judicial cure for a process
malfunction also may require judges to make value determinations. Con-
sider free speech. "Courts must," as Ely tells us, "police inhibitions on
expression and other political activity because we cannot trust elected offi-
cials to do so: ins have a way of wanting to make sure the outs stay out." 8
Agreed. But a court must place a value on reputation if it is to fashion a
First Amendment rule protecting expression considered defamatory under
state law. New York Times v. Sullivan79 may be the correct cure for a
process malfunction. But after reading the case, it is apparent that Justice
Brennan found it necessary to make more than one value determination.
Judicial value determinations are inescapable. As I have argued, they
are also unexceptional. What is exceptional in judicial review is that value
determinations in constitutional cases have the appearance of finality. And
this is perceived even though the Court has neither purse nor sword; 0
even though the Congress has power over the Court's appellate jurisdic-
77. For the value determinations that Ely makes, see id. at 123.
78. Id. at 106.
79. 376 U.S. 254 (1964).
80. As Alexander Hamilton put it:
Whoever attentively considers the different departments of power must perceive that, in a
government in which they are separated from each other, the judiciary, from the nature of its
functions, will always be the least dangerous to the political rights of the Constitution; because
it will be least in a capacity to annoy or injure them. The executive not only dispenses the
honors but holds the sword of the community. The legislature not only commands the purse,
but prescribes the rules by which the duties and rights of every citizen are to be regulated. The
judiciary, on the contrary, has no influence over either the sword or the purse; no direction
either of the strength or of the wealth of the society; and can take no active resolution
whatever. It may truly be said to have neither FORCE nor WILL, but merely judgment; and
must ultimately depend upon the aid of the executive arm even for the efficacy of its
judgements.
THE FEDERALIST No. 78, at 465 (A. Hamilton) (C. Rossiter ed. 1961).
tion;8" indeed, even though there is, within the Constitution itself, the pos-
sibility of amendment. 2
If it can be shown, however, that often there is less finality in a consti-
tutional decision than meets the eye, and that (unlike bureaucrats) the
value determinations of judges in constitutional cases are constrained by
norms applicable generally in adjudication, then perhaps we can accept
more readily the legitimacy of judicial review.
6
The finality of judicial review, even as generally perceived, may seem
less troublesome if compared with the accepted judicial function of statu-
tory interpretation. In the Rotolith, Darlington, and Vincent cases, we
saw how courts sometimes depart sharply from legislative intent; some-
times they do more. In some situations statutory interpretation forecloses
legislative change. Thus, it may have more finality than we imagine (more
indeed than many constitutional interpretations), and therefore, it can be
more closely related to the standard picture of judicial review than is often
supposed. 3
Consider two examples: administrative agencies-particularly when
they are young-sometimes interpret statutes with a zeal that is a variety
of the tunnel vision I mentioned earlier. Instead of harmonizing the law it
administers with the general law, an agency may ignore the surrounding
jurisprudence, and its constitutional configurations. On review, the courts
may then reinterpret the statute to avoid confronting the constitutional
questions presented by the agency's single-minded devotion to its mis-
sion. 4 This describes the National Labor Relations Board in its spring-
81. The scope of the power is not clear. Ex parte McCardle, 74 U.S. (7 Wall.) 506 (1869), is the
leading case. It should be read with Ex parte Yerger, 75 U.S. (8 Wall.) 85 (1869). See C. BLACK,
DECISION ACCORDING TO LAW (1981); Van Alstyne, A Critical Guide to Ex Parte McCardle, 15
ARIZ. L. REV. 229 (1973). See also Sanger, The Supreme Court, 1980 Term-Foreword: Constitu-
tional Limitations on Congress' Authority to Regulate the Jurisdiction of the Federal Courts, 95
HARV. L. REV. 17 (1982) (discussing limits of congressional authority to contract jurisdiction of fed-
eral courts). Compare Wechsler, The Appellate Jurisdictionof the Supreme Court: Reflections on the
Law and the Logistics of Direct Review, 34 WASH. & LEE L. REV. 1043 (1977) (to insure against
nullification of constitutional rights, Supreme Court must scrutinize state court decisions of law and
fact) with Hart, The Power of Congress to Limit the Jurisdiction of FederalCourts: An Exerdse in
Dialectic, 66 HARV. L. REv. 1362 (1953) (suggesting that state courts may be ultimate guarantors of
constitutional rights).
82. Only four Supreme Court decisons have been set aside by constitutional amendment: Oregon
v. Mitchell, 400 U.S. 112 (1970); Pollock v. Farmers' Loan & Trust Co., 157 U.S. 429 (1895); Dred
Scott v. Sanford, 60 U.S. (19 How.) 393 (1857); Chisholm v. Georgia, 2 U.S. (2 Dall.) 419 (1793).
Justice Black, criticizing the Court's reinterpretation of a statute, has said: "[W]here the only alter-
native to action by this Court is the laborious process of constitutional amendment and where the
ultimate responsibility rests with this Court, I believe reconsideration [of a constitutional decision] is
always proper." Boys Mkts. v. Retail Clerks Union, 398 U.S. 235, 259 (1970) (Black, J., dissenting).
83. As will become clearer later, my claim is also that the reasons for this are related to the
reasons for finality-when there is finality-in judicial review.
84. For an example of judicial disagreement over the propriety of this type of agency behavior in
time. It had a propensity to read the Wagner Act as if there were no First
Amendment to the United States Constitution. 5 When unions organized,
employers were at risk if they spoke, as they often did, in favor of the
open shop."6
The Supreme Court, through statutory interpretation, denied the Board
this power. To read the statute as the Board had would raise serious con-
stitutional issues although it might be that the reading was constitutional.
The issue could be avoided by interpretation that was sensitive to the
value our law attaches to free expression. 7
Because the Court did not render a constitutional decision in these
cases, Congress retained the formal power to amend the statute to make it
conform to the agency's interpretation. But in fact this would not have
been easy. It is hard to rewrite labor statutes, and often it is difficult for
Congress to ignore values that may be of constitutional dimension and
that are called to its attention by the Supreme Court.8
In this statutory situation there is more finality than meets the eye, but
little doubt about the legitimacy of the Court's role. Indeed, even if the
Court did not have the power to declare legislation unconstitutional, it
would have the authority to review agency action and the obligation to
accommodate, through statutory interpretation, particular legislation to
the principles that underpin our law.
The second example is again from labor law, but does not involve an
administrative agency. Under the Railway Labor Act,"9 the union selected
by a majority of employees in a bargaining unit is the exclusive represen-
tative of all employees in the unit. The statute is absolutely silent, how-
ever, on the question of the union's obligations to the employees it repre-
sents. In 1944 the practice of the brotherhoods, as some of the railway
unions are called, was to discriminate and to do so with vigor."' Some
employees who suffered sued. Their case made its way to the Supreme
Court, which held that the "fair interpretation of the statutory language is
a non-constitutional setting, compare the majority and dissenting opinions in D.A. Schulte, Inc. v.
Gangi, 328 U.S. 108 (1946).
85. See H.R. REP. NO. 245, 80th Cong., 1st Sess. 33 (1947) ("Although the Labor Board says it
does not limit free speech, its decisions show that it uses against people what the Constitution says
they can say freely.")
86. See NLRB v. Golub Corp., 388 F.2d 921, 926 (2d Cir. 1967) ("Under the Wagner Act.
the Board condemned almost any antiunion expression by an employer.")
87. See NLRB v. Virginia Elec. & Power Co., 314 U.S. 469 (1941) (construing National Labor
Relations Act narrowly to avoid clash between requirements of Act and employer's First Amendment
rights); cf.Thomas v. Collins, 323 U.S. 516, 537 (1945) (application of state labor statute that im-
posed prior restraint on organizer held unconstitutional).
88. Some of the subsequent history of employer speech and the congressional response to Board
and Court protection is traced in NLRB v. Golub Corp., 388 F.2d 921 (2d Cir. 1967).
89. 45 U.S.C. §§ 151-88 (1976).
90. See H. WELLINGTON, LABOR AND THE LEGAL PROCESS 145-55 (1968).
The common-law doctrine that the Chief Justice grafted onto the stat-
ute-namely, that an agent must represent his principal fairly-is not a
doctrine that a legislature could, even under tremendous political pressure
from powerful groups, easily reject by amending the statute over which it
theoretically has authority. 3 There is more finality in the interpretation of
statutes, when that interpretation reflects the principles of our jurispru-
dence, than we sometimes imagine.'4
7
In addressing the issue of finality in judicial review itself, it is essential
to distinguish among various types of constitutional decisions. Some con-
stitutional decisions do not even appear to be final. Others deal primarily
with means rather than ends, and thus leave more than a little legislative
discretion intact. Finally, certain types of decisions, although facially final,
are properly subject to thorough revision, the principle of stare decisis
notwithstanding.
The class of plainly non-final decisions might best be understood in
terms of the Court saying to another governmental entity: "You may be
able to achieve the substantive result you desire but you must proceed
toward your objective in a different fashion." There is a family of such
91. Steele v. Louisville & N. R.R., 323 U.S. 192, 202 (1944).
92. Id.
93. Nor can this finality be explained simply on the theory that Steele was, at bottom, a constitu-
tional decision. Justice Murphy, concurring, did argue that Steele should have been decided on consti-
tutional grounds. 323 U.S. at 192, 208-09. At the time, however, this suggestion was innovative. The
state action doctrine in 1944 was a long way from what it is today. For its application to unions, see
Machinists v. Street, 367 U.S. 740 (1961), decided seventeen years after Steele. Moreover, Steele
preceded Brown v. Board of Educ., 347 U.S. 483 (1954), by ten years; in 1944, the common-law
notion of fair representation may have operated more powerfully on behalf of minorities than the
equal protection clause.
94. See supra p. 502.
8
Justice Stevens, dissenting in Fullilove v. Klutznick, 10 applied another
variety of structural or procedural, and therefore non-final, review. The
case involved the constitutionality of the minority business enterprise, or
"set aside," requirement of the Public Works Employment Act of 1977.
That provision requires, absent an administrative waiver, that at least ten
percent of federal funds allocated to local public works projects be used to
95. See, e.g., Hampton v. Mow Sun Wong, 426 U.S. 88 (1976); Kent v. Dulles, 357 U.S. 116
(1958); see also Gewirta, The Courts, Congress,and Executive Policy-Making: Notes on Three Doc-
trines, 40 LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS. 46 (1976).
96. See, e.g., Cramp v. Board of Pub. Instruction, 368 U.S. 278 (1961); Thornhill v. Alabama,
310 U.S. 88 (1940).
97. See, e.g., United States v. Robel, 389 U.S. 258 (1967); Zwickler v. Koota, 389 U.S. 241
(1967).
98. See A. BICKEL, supra note 8, at 111-98.
99. See generally Bickel & Wellington, supra note 26 (discussing circumstances in which courts
should "remand" statutes to Congress for further consideration).
100. See Wellington & Albert, Statutory Interpretationand the Political Process: A Comment on
Sinclair v. Atkinson, 72 YALE L.J. 1547, 1560 n.42 (1963).
101. 448 U.S. 448, 548-49 (1980).
The very fact that Congress for the first time in the Nation's history
has created a broad legislative classifiction for entitlement to benefits
based solely on racial characteristics identifies a dramatic difference
between this Act and the thousands of statutes that preceded it. This
dramatic point of departure is not even mentioned in the statement
of purpose of the Act or in the reports of either the House or the
Senate Committee that processed the legislation, and was not the
subject of any testimony
10 3
or inquiry in any legislative hearing on the
bill that was enacted.
9
The Justice's approach invites us to examine other procedural due pro-
cess or related constitutional interventions by the Court that may have less
finality than we generally associate with judicial review. Consider the at-
tempted judicial regulation of police behavior through such continuingly
controversial decisions as those that established the Miranda require-
ments0 7 and imposed the exclusionary rule. 0 8 I say "attempted" because
part of the controversy turns on whether the requirements and the rule do
make any difference in police behavior. Of course, in determining whether
the Court's decisions are justified it may not matter. The point is that
neither Miranda nor the exclusionary rule questions any substantive goal
of any governmental entity. Both structure the means of achieving an end;
both, perhaps, make the end's achievement more difficult. So do other
things we tolerate, indeed, embrace. For example, police unions may in-
terfere with efficient police work and the efficient administration of crimi-
nal justice as much or perhaps more than do these constitutional decisions.
Moreover, there is as much certainty of the continuing existence of police
unions as there is of the survival of Miranda and the exclusionary rule,
and the voter may have as little direct control over one as he does over the
other.
10
This discussion of structural or procedural judicial review highlights
the important role of the Supreme Court as umpire-at-the-margin of the
appropriate processes of other governmental entities. It reveals that judi-
cial review, when so employed, does not preclude substantive legislative
goals and accordingly that, so far as substantive finality is concerned, such
constitutional adjudication closely resembles common-law and statutory
interpretation: all three may make it harder for legislatures to reach par-
ticular goals; usually none prevents the attainment of those goals.
The examples employed of structural or procedural judicial review
were, of course, meant to be suggestive; plainly, they are not exhaustive. I
do, however, want to continue the discussion in one additional context,
that of equal protection. The place to begin is with an observation made
by Justice Jackson in Railway Express Agency v. New York.109 The case
The burden should rest heavily upon one who would persuade us to
use the due process clause to strike down a substantive law or ordi-
nance. . . . Invalidation of a statute or an ordinance on due process
grounds leaves ungoverned and ungovernable conduct which many
people find objectionable.
Invocation of the equal protection clause, on the other hand, does
not disable any governmental body from dealing with the subject at
hand. It merely means that the prohibition or regulation must have a
broader impact.110
Justice Jackson has a point, but the point is of limited utility if the
issue is-as it is for us-the relative finality of judicial review. For equal
protection cases vary considerably in the breadth and permanence of the
restraints they impose on legislatures. Some equal protection cases are
structural in the same way procedural due process cases may be;"' some
are essentially substantive due process cases;" 2 some are republican form
of government cases,' or at least they seem to be when the verbal mask is
stripped away. Others, such as the race cases, which involve affirmative
governmental discrimination, are final in any realistic sense because they
imagine a nation that must be profoundly different from one in which the
Constitution would permit the discrimination. Moreover, they entail a re-
medial program that, while it may not achieve the ideal of racial equality,
does substantially rearrange the country's priorities." 4
Yet ei6en the desegregation cases were initially provisional. The finality
we see today reflects today's acceptance of the value derived and articu-
lated as law by the Supreme Court in 1954, namely (with certain qualifi-
cations), that government may not affirmatively discriminate on the basis
of race. Without today's acceptance there would be no finality; but at the
time of decision, such acceptance was in doubt.
In the most substantive of constitutional cases there is always doubt
about finality at the time of decision because there is always the possibility
of judicial mistake and the inevitability of social change. When we talk of
mistake and social change-both terms that need elucidation-we are face
to face with questions about the sources of law.
11.
Two types of judicial mistake concern us here. Each is related to a type
of justification that a court might offer for a decision. And it is this rela-
tionship that connects the topic of judicial mistake with that of the sources
of law. Courts-at least appellate courts-generally believe themselves
under an obligation to justify what they hold. There are many standard
modes of justification: an appeal to a legislative command, to a judicial
precedent, to legislative history, or to analogous developments in other ju-
risdictions or in related areas of law. Moreover, the consequences that
may attend a legal rule can sometimes serve as the justification for a judi-
cial decision; so sometimes can an appeal to the moral ideals of the
community.
The latter two types of justification are the most problematic in appli-
cation. And they typically come into play when the more standard modes
of justification themselves become problematic. It is fair to conclude, there-
fore, that they most often give rise to judicial mistake.
The first type of justification is consequentialist; it looks to the future.
The rule on which a holding rests will, according to the rationale of the
decision, change the behavior of individuals or institutions. The articu-
lated rule serves a policy that in turn is designed to effectuate a societal
goal; the justification sounds in terms of benefits and costs.
The second type of justification looks to the past. Its persuasiveness is
not in what will be; it does not move us toward a goal. Instead, the rule
has persuasiveness because it vindicates a principle embedded in the moral
ideals of the community; the justification sounds in terms of rights and
obligations.
Of course, the vindication of a principle may have significant effects.
Indeed, it may entail-as in desegregation-remedial efforts that change
the nature of society. But this does not mean, in this class of cases, that
effect should be equated with justification any more than it should be
when a court carries out a legislative command by enforcing a statute.
There too the decision has an effect, but the justification for the decision
does not therefore become its effect; it remains the authority of the
legislature.
Earlier I suggested that final responsibility for the moral ideals of the
community cannot adequately be lodged in either countermajoritarian in-
stitutions with tunnel vision or majoritarian institutions in which the pas-
sionate and self-interested concerns of the moment may prevail too easily.
It does not follow, however, that courts-because they are better suited to
derive and articulate the community's moral ideals-will not make mis-
takes in doing so. And, of course, courts are also apt to make mistakes
when using forward looking policies to justify their rules; indeed, in the
policy area courts have no comparative institutional advantage.
It should be added that the two types of justifications I have adum-
brated are hard to discover in pure form in the judicial world. Courts tend
to mix them together. And, although they may be easy enough for a phi-
losopher to describe, a lawyer cannot easily separate them. Still, either a
forward looking policy or a backward looking principle may be dominant
in the explanation of a legal rule. And it behooves us, in trying to under-
stand legal phenomena, to try to draw the distinction. While Cardozo in
The Nature of the JudicialProcess did not explicitly make that effort, his
lectures are-as he might have put it-instinct with the idea.
Both policies and principles are important sources of law, including
constitutional law. In a formal sense-so far as judicial review is con-
cerned-they, along with history and precedent, give content to the open
texture of the Constitution. An example of each will serve to clarify the
distinction between them.
12
The major justification for the rule announced in New York Times v.
Sullivan"' is a policy. The case held that, absent actual malice,"' the
First Amendment (via the Fourteenth) bars a public official from recover-
ing damages for false and defamatory statements relating to his official
conduct. The goal to be fostered through this rule is-at its most ab-
stract-the sound working of American democracy and, at a somewhat
reduced level of abstraction, "a commitment . . . that debate on public
issues should be uninhibited, robust, and wide-open ... .""I The Court's
justification in part took the form that without such a rule, "critics of
official conduct may be deterred from voicing their criticism, even though
it is believed to be true and even though it is in fact true because of doubt
whether it can be proved in court or fear of having to do so.'"" The
common law of defamation, the Court reasoned, "dampens the vigor and
limits the variety of public debate.""' The rule, in short, is justified by
predictable consequences that serve a desirable goal.
Contrast this with the dissent of Justice Brandeis in the famous 1928
case of Olmstead v. United States.120 At issue in that case was whether
wiretapping by federal officers constituted an unreasonable search and
seizure under the Fourth Amendment. According to Brandeis:
13
This distinction between a forward looking policy justification and a
backward looking justification from principles embedded in the moral ide-
als of the community in turn suggests a distinction between two types of
judicial mistake. If it were to become clear that the rule in New York
Times v. Sullivan did not have the consequences the Court predicted-if it
became clear that the behavior of potential critics of government did not
change and that "the vigor and variety of public debate" had not been
altered-then New York Times v. Sullivan would be either a constitu-
tional mistake or, at least, a decision in search of a new justification.
Speaking in a different context and about common-law cases, Cardozo
said: "Those that cannot prove their worth and strength by the test of
experience, are sacrificed mercilessly and thrown into the void." 'M But
what do we mean by "the test of experience"? A plausible answer is social
science investigation, empirical research based upon a statistically sophisti-
cated methodology. In addition to New York Times v. Sullivan, consider
some other subjects-hypothetical and real-for this "test of experience":
a constitutional rule excluding the introduction of illegally obtained evi-
dence, justified by the rule's deterrent effect on unlawful police behav-
ior; 12 a constitutional rule requiring at least twelve on a jury, justified by
the proposition that the protection afforded the defendant is decreased by
a decrease in jury size; a determination that the death penalty is unconsti-
tutional in felony-murder cases, because it fails to deter felony murder.
Without in any way implying criticism of the social sciences, one can
agree that in at least some of these situations-or others one could think
of-scientific tests of experience would not lead to clear conclusions, if
indeed scientific tests were possible.2 2 Nor is any other "test of experi-
ence," such as informed intuition, apt to be better.
This conclusion-that there may be no clear conclusions-raises ques-
tions about the use of consequentialist or policy justifications in constitu-
tional law. From this perspective it. seems acceptable enough if the evi-
dence on which the policy is based is clear. When it is not, when judges
must rely on intuition because social scientists or other data collectors can-
not tell them very much about the consequences of legal rules, should not
policy choices be left to the legislatures? Should choices not be subject to
14
The second type of judicial mistake is associated with rules that are
justified by looking to the past, rules that are persuasive because they vin-
dicate principles embedded in the moral ideals of the community. The
Brandeis dissent in Olmstead is the example of this second type of justifi-
134. Consider, as related to the theme I am developing, Andrew Jackson's veto message of July
10, 1832 on a bill to recharter the Bank of the United States:
It is maintained by the advocates of the bank that its constitutionality in all its features ought
to be considered as settled by precedent and by the decision of the Supreme Court. To this
conclusion I cannot assent. Mere precedent is a dangerous source of authority, and should not
be regarded as deciding questions of constitutional power except where the acquiescence of the
people and the States can be considered as well settled.
Jackon's message is reproduced in 2 MESSAGES AND PAPERS OF THE PRESIDENTS 576 (Richardson ed.
1896). But cf Cooper v. Aaron, 358 U.S. 1 (1958) (Court is supreme arbiter of Constitution). Had
Cooper been decided in 1832, Jackson could not have fashioned his argument in the manner presented
above: that all officers of government are bound by the judgments of the Supreme Court would not
have been a matter open to debate. But Jackson's argument could have been reshaped. As Bickel
noted, decisions of the Supreme Court, unlike the injunctive order at issue in Cooper, see infra note
138, are not self-executing. See A. BICKEL, THE MORALITY OF CONSENT 111 (1975). The legal free-
dom thus accorded parties not bound by concluded litigation may well, like any freedom, be abused.
But there is no reason to suppose that private resistance to constitutional decisions is always or usually
invidiously motivated; nor is there reason to assume the infallibility of the courts.
135. See supra note 3.
136. 347 U.S. 483 (1954).
137. The "Southern Manifesto" was a document signed by 101 Congressmen from Southern
states. The document maintained that Brown v. Board of Education was an abuse of judicial power,
and expressed its signers' intention to reverse the decision. Pursuant to the Manifesto's purpose, legis-
latures in the South sought to evade integration decrees by, among other things, closing schools, pro-
viding tuition grants for private education, and establishing "freedom of choice" attendance plans. See
H. HOROWITZ & K. KARST, LAW, LAWYERS, AND SOCIAL CHANGE 256 (1969).
138. Governor Faubus of Arkansas had relied on the threats of violence made by groups opposed
to integration to justify a failure to comply with remedial injunctions ordering desegregation. In
Cooper v. Aaron, 358 U.S. 1 (1958), the Supreme Court cut short the governor's attempts to evade the
rule of Brown v. Board of Education, 347 U.S. 483 (1954), holding that desegregation decrees must
be enforced, local hostility notwithstanding. See also R. COLE, CHILDREN OF CRISIS 111, 373 (1967);
A. GRIMSHAW, RACIAL VIOLENCE IN THE UNITED STATES 448, 520 (1969), R. KLUGER, SIMPLE
JUSTICE 223, 747, 754 (1975).
139. See, e.g., D. BATES, THE LONG SHADOW OF LITTLE ROCK 69-76 (1962) (discussing treat-
ment of "Little Rock Nine"); D. GARROW, PROTEST AT SELMA 133-61 (1978); C. KING, MY LIFE
WITH MARTIN LUTHER KING JR. 188-207 (1969) (discussing impact of sit-ins and freedom riders);
M. KING JR., STRIDE TOWARD FREEDOM: THE MONTGOMERY STORY (1958) (discussing successful
boycott of Montgomery bus system).
ciated with the abortion cases 140 includes sophisticated election tactics by
highly visible "right-to-life" and "freedom-of-choice" groups, campaign
rhetoric at every level, and efforts at constitutional amendment' 41 and leg-
142
islative nullification.
When the Justices are right about the moral ideals of the community,
their decisions become settled and accepted. The turmoil, the resistance,
and the threats from other governmental entities, from private groups, in-
stitutions and individuals diminish with time. Thus, few today can be
heard to endorse government supported racial segregation or other state
practices that discriminate against blacks.
When the Court is wrong, criticism and analysis help to reveal the mis-
take-so do the turmoil, the threats, the approval and the resistance, from
all the sources that make up our community. Remember, it is the moral
ideals of the community and not of the wise philosopher that concern the
Court. And it is a wise court that pays attention to the community-not
3
out of fear, but out of obligation. 1
When the Court recognizes that it has made a mistake, it should, in the
appropriate case, rectify the situation. Needless to say, there is no rule in
constitutional law, any more than there is a rule at common law, to tell a
court when to disregard or modify a precedent. The subject is difficult and
no generalization is readily apparent. It is instructive, however, to con-
sider some aspects of the Court's handling of the abortion issue since its
140. For a discussion of the political reaction to Roe v. Wade and Doe v. Bolton, see Rubin, The
Abortion Cases: A Study in Law and Social Change, 5 N.C. CENT. L.J. 215, 247-53 (1974). See also
DeWitt, Abortion Foes March in Capitolon Anniversary of Legislation, N.Y. Times, Jan. 23, 1979,
at C1, col. 1; N.Y. Times, April 24, 1981, at A16, col 1.
141. See, e.g., S.J. Res. 110, 97th Cong., 1st Sess. (1981) (proposed constitutional amendment
permitting Congress and states to legislate with respect to abortion); H.R.J. Res. 372, 97th Cong., 1st
Sess. (1981) (same); S.J. Res. 19, 97th Cong., 1st Sess. (1981) (proposed constitutional amendement
guaranteeing "right-to-life" to unborn); H.R.J. Res. 32, 97th Cong., 1st Sess (1981) (same).
142. See, e.g. S. 158, 97th Cong., 1st Sess. (1981) (declaring human life to begin at conception);
H.R. 900, 97th Cong., 1st Sess. (1981) (same). See also S. 9583, 97th Cong., 1st Sess. (1981) (limit-
ing jurisdiction of federal courts to hear abortion cases); H.R. 73, 97th Cong., 1st Sess. (1981) (same).
143. Is this not the flip side of the following segment of President Lincoln's First Inaugural Ad-
dress, delivered on March 4, 1861?
I do not forget the position assumed by some that constitutional questions are to be decided
by the Supreme Court, nor do I deny that such decisions must be binding in any case upon the
parties to a suit as to the object of that suit, while they are also entitled to very high respect
and consideration in all parallel cases by all other departments of the government. And while it
is obviously possible that such decision may be erroneous in any given case, still the evil effect
following it, being limited to that particular case, with the chance that it may be overruled and
never become a precedent for other cases, can better be borne than could the evils of a different
practice. At the same time, the candid citizen must confess that if the policy of the Government
upon vital questions affecting the whole people is to be irrevocably fixed by decisions of the
Supreme Court, the instant they are made in ordinary litigation between parties in personal
actions the people will have ceased to be their own rulers, having to that extent practically
resigned their Government into the hand of that eminent tribunal.
2 THE COLLECTED WORKS OF ABRAHAM LINCOLN 494 (Basler ed. 1953).
1973 decision in Roe v. Wade,"" for the Court seems to have some, per-
haps as yet only partially conscious, sense that its decision to permit abor-
tions freely was overly broad, and, in that respect, a mistake. The Court
itself has, indirectly and perhaps unknowingly, retreated in some subse-
quent cases by distinguishing its 1973 holding.
In Maher v. Roe,' 4- decided in 1977, the Court sustained a Connecticut
welfare regulation denying Medicaid recipients payments for medical ser-
vices related to nontherapeutic abortions. And in the summer of 1980, in
Harrisv. McRae,146 the Court upheld the Hyde Amendment's prohibition
on the use of federal Medicaid funds for abortion, "except where the life
of the mother would be endangered if the fetus were carried to term; or
except for such medical procedures necessary for the victims of rape or
incest .... ,47
Since Roe v. Wade had held unconstitutional a statute making it a
crime to "procure an abortion," except to save the life of the mother, 14 8 it
might seem sufficient for the Court to point out, as it did, the "basic dif-
ference between direct state interference with [a woman's freedom of
choice which, under Roe v. Wade, is absolute during the first trimester of
pregnancy] and state encouragement of an alternative activity consonant
with legislative policy,"' 49 namely, carrying the fetus to term. The trouble
with this is that the holding in Roe v. Wade rests on the premise that the
morality of an abortion is none of the government's business, while the
Connecticut welfare regulation and the Hyde Amendment represent gov-
ernmental decisions against a woman's freedom of choice based exclusively
on the proposition that government assistance for all but a limited class of
abortions is immoral. There can be no other explanation for the Connecti-
cut regulation and the Hyde Amendment. Those governmental decisions
were not taken to save money: medical services incident to childbirth are
generally more expensive than abortion. Nor is there any reason to imag-
ine that they were taken because of a direct governmental conunitment to
population growth. 150
The Connecticut welfare regulation and the Hyde Amendment reflect
151. This does not mean that there is nothing to the distinction between direct state interference
with a woman's freedom of choice and state encouragement of the way in which she exercises that
freedom. It does mean that Roe v. Wade is too broad, given the Court's subsequent conclusion that a
legislature has the constitutional authority to effectuate the proposition that government assistance, for
all but a limited class of abortions, is immoral.
152. H.L. v. Matheson, 450 U.S. 398 (1981).
153. Although the Court assumed that the statute did not apply to "emancipated" or "indepen-
dent" minors, id. at 406-07, this narrowing construction may well fail to constrain the statute's actual
reach. To avoid the parental notification requirement, a minor must first convince her doctor that she
is "emancipated" or "independent." It is not unreasonable to assume that doctors, lacking any clear
standard against which to judge their patients' maturity, and subject to criminal and civil sanctions if
their judgment regarding "emancipation" is later reversed, would err on the side of parental
notification.
there is as much reason to think that this would be good as to suspect that
it would be bad. Moreover, and more importantly, increased political ac-
tivity over Supreme Court decisions does not constitute disrespect for law.
Our law must be based on consent. It is everyone's obligation to insist that
all branches of government, including the courts, remain true to this cen-
tral understanding."" Peaceful resistance is part of the minorities' arsenal
of weapons against the majority. 55' It is a standard political weapon of
16
minorities and the majority against the Court.
15
It is time to examine where we are and what judicial review looks like
from this position. It comes to this: concern- with judicial review is exag-
gerated if-as is generally the case-the concern focuses on the counter-
majoritarian nature of the practice. Concern is appropriate, however, if
prompted by the apparent finality of constitutional decisions. It is not
helpful, in trying to alleviate this concern, to seek to insulate the Court
from the realm of values by limiting judicial review to diagnosing and
curing the process malfunctions of other governmental entities. That ap-
proach fails to remove the Court from the realm of values and unwisely
excludes it from areas of substantive malfunctions.
The key to mitigating concern with judicial review is found when one
analyzes the concept of finality and relates it to the judicial process. Many
constitutional decisions deal with means and not ends. Accordingly, they
are often less final than might be supposed. Moreover, because value de-
terminations of either the policy or the principle variety are problematic,
judges are apt to make mistakes. But, at least where principles are in-
volved, mistakes can be discovered and mistaken decisions amended by
normal judicial processes. '
154. See H. ARENDT, Civil Disobedience, in CRISES OF THE REPUBLIC 51, 51-57 (1972). See also
A. BICKEL, supra note 8, at 244-72.
155. My views on this are developed to some extent in Wellington, On Freedom of Expression,
88 YALE L.J. 1105, 1136-42 (1979).
156. See supra pp. 1, 515-16. Justice Jackson was surely correct when he said, in Brown v. Allen,
"We are not final because we are infallible . . . ," 344 U.S. 443, 540 (1953) (concurring in the
results), and just as surely incorrect when he continued, "but we are infallible only because we are
final." Id. In fact, the Justices are neither final nor infallible.
157. A remaining question concerns the relationship between the techniques of avoidance, or
"passive virtues," see Bickel, supra note 8, at 111-98, and the arguments concerning the judicial
function presented here. That relationship has been touched upon in the discussion of th delegation,
void-for-vagueness and overbreadth doctrines and in some of the analysis of statutory interpretation.
Moreover, where severe social flux imposes particular difficulty on the judicial task I have described,
the use of techniques of avoidance may seem attractive. In such circumstances the danger of jldicial
mistake may be substantial. But there are difficulties with this approach if carried as far as Bickel
proposes. Quite apart from the familiar criticisms, see Gunther, The Subtle Vices of the "Passive
Virtues'--A Comment on Principle and Expediency in Judicial Review, 64 COLUM. L. REV. 1
(1964), one might ask whether passive avoidance is as non-intrusive as commonly supposed. Deliber-
ate passivity, after all, seeks to shift responsibility by placing burdens on other institutions. Some of
16
Mistake might seem a relatively static concept that should be contrasted
with growth and change or-if one is optimistic-progress in constitu-
tional law. But the distinction is not sharp because mistaken judicial deci-
sions affect the moral ideals of the community in ways that defy general-
ization. And the ensuing political unrest in turn affects the law. At any
rate, the question of growth and change, as a discrete question, has been
much remarked."' 8 If there is anything new to say about it, it would best
be left for another time. Let me only observe, and with this observation
close: growth, change, and progress are inconsistent with finality in any
strong sense; nor is there reason to suppose that they present problems in
understanding the nature of the judicial process that can be ignored in
attempting to understand the nature of judicial review.
the time, and in some situations, those institutions may be ill-suited to perform the additional task.
Bickel, of course, was moved to his position, at least in part, by his anxiety over the countermajori-
tarian nature of judicial review. If one is less worried about this, perhaps one can afford to worry
more about the misallocation of institutional responsibility that may be entailed in the otherwise ques-
tionable avoidance of a constitutional decision.
158. In The Nature of the Judicial Process, supra note 1, Cardozo's central concern is with
growth, change, and progress.
David Wippman
Editor-in-Chief
Randall Kennedy Ellen R. Porges
Note & Topics Editor Managing Editor
Richard Bartlett Tim Atkeson
George C. Harris Russell Hayman
Robert Silver Jonathan R. Macey
George Wyeth Theodore A. Paradise
Note Editors Alan 0. Sykes
Article & Book Review Editors
Kathleen Cully Rick Levy Alfred 0. Rose
Robert D. Gilbert David R. Lewis Dietrich L. Snell
Charles Glick John Lewis Hector Torres
Mark A. Goldberg Rory K. Little Lynn A. Stout
Candice Hoke Jonathan E. Richman Monique Witt
Senior Editors