MODULE MGT 202 Good Governance
MODULE MGT 202 Good Governance
MODULE MGT 202 Good Governance
CHAPTER 1
Nature of Morality
Learning Outcomes:
• To describe three major theoretical approaches in integrity and ethics
• To explain the various approaches to the study of morality
• To understand what morality is and how it differs from aesthetics, nonmoral behavior,
and manners
• To explain the influence of Filipino culture on the way students look at moral experiences
and solve moral dilemma problems.
INTRODUCTION:
The fundamental question is, not “What things are moral, or morally good or right?” It is,
“What is morality anyway; what is this moral quality we say some things have?” When we say
that something has a metallic quality, we mean that there is such a “thing” out there in nature as
“metallic-ness”; it really exists and can be studied and has properties and laws. Similarly most
people think there is a realm of nature in which Moral things exist independently of you or me,
especially Moral qualities and Moral Laws, and they think that actions we carry out will in fact
be Moral, or Immoral, just as some objects will in fact be metallic or not, and if they are they
will obey the laws that metallic things follow. Whether or not an object is metallic is in no way
dependent on what anyone thinks or wishes or prefers. It either is or is not metallic. Either way
we are dealing with an objective fact. This is how most people think about morality; they think
that whether or not a particular action is Moral is a matter of Moral fact. Most people, in other
words, take an “Objectivist” view of morality, do not realize any other view exists, and indeed
would have great difficulty imagining that any other could exist.
The crucial and huge distinction here is between mere preferences, and Moral facts.
Most people would say that the Moral quality of cruelty is in no way a matter of human
preference; it is a matter of fact. Cruelty they would say is in fact Morally wrong, regardless of
what humans prefer. Even if all people on earth liked being cruel, and approved of it, it would
still be Morally wrong, because its Moral quality is a matter of fact that is in no way influenced
by what humans prefer. The Moral Law is thought of as being the same as physical law in this
regard -- whether a particular object is metallic or not is in no way dependent on whether people
would prefer it to be metallic.To most people all this seems indubitable; of course this is the
nature of Morality. How could Morality be otherwise? But to we Subjectivists, all the above is
totally and sadly confused and mistaken.
Firstly, the Objectivist can give no good reason for thinking that a Moral realm or that
Moral facts exist. Consider the enormity of the claim. If a person says that Gorillas exist, or
magnetic fields exist, or that there are metals, he is making huge claims about the nature of the
universe; he is saying that these things exist out there somewhere. You shouldn’t do that unless
you can give us pretty convincing reasons to believe that these things do exist. The best way is
to show them to us. The Objectivist cannot do this. How could be begin to show that “…cruelty
is in fact Morally right”? How could you go about trying to establish this? Consider Human
Rights. Most/all objectivists believe we have/possess a right to, e.g., freedom of speech, as if
this is something built into our nature just as we have ears. How could such a claim be proved?
The Subjectivist says it is obvious that rights are no more than behaviors etc. which we think it
is important/desirable to allow/protect etc?
Thus, the terms the Objectivist uses are meaningless, because they refer to nothing that exists.
More accurately they do mean something to the user; they refer to things that can be described
and understood in a sense, but which do not exist anywhere. They are like the terms “fairies”
or “evil spirits”; we know what these terms mean, refer to, but those things don’t exist.
The words "moral" and "ethics" (and cognates) are often used interchangeably. However, it
is useful to make the following distinction:
Morality is the system through which we determine right and wrong conduct -- i.e., the guide to
good or right conduct.
Ethics is the philosophical study of Morality.
What then is a moral theory?
A theory is a structured set of statements used to explain (or predict) a set of facts or
concepts. A moral theory, then, explains why a certain action is wrong -- or why we ought to act
in certain ways. In short, it is a theory of how we determine right and wrong conduct. Also,
moral theories provide the framework upon which we think and discuss in a reasoned way, and
so evaluate, specific moral issues.
Seen in this light, it becomes clear that we cannot draw a sharp divide between moral
theory and applied ethics (e.g., medical or business ethics). For instance, in order to critically
evaluate the moral issue of affirmative action, we must not attempt to evaluate what actions or
policies are right (or wrong) independent of what we take to determine right and wrong conduct.
You will see, as we proceed, that we do not do ethics without at least some moral theory
Another important distinction:
Are moral theories descriptive or prescriptive?
In presenting a moral theory, are we merely describing how people, in their everyday
'doings' and 'thinkings,' form a judgement about what is right and wrong, or are we prescribing
how people ought to make these judgements?
Most take moral theories to be prescriptive. The descriptive accounts of what people do is
left to sociologists and anthropologists. Philosophers, then, when they study morality, want to
know what is the proper way of determining right and wrong.
(10) Contractarianism
The principles of right and wrong (or Justice) are those which everyone in society would
agree upon in forming a social contract.
Various forms of Contractarianism have been suggested. In general, the idea is that the
principles or rules that determine right and wrong in society are determined by a hypothetical
contract forming procedure. Here is John Rawls's example.
Through a thought experiment, Rawls developed a way of getting people to come up with
universal principles of justice. The basic idea is nothing new -- i.e., of impartial developing a
social contract of universal principles -- but many find Rawls' novel method very appealing. The
idea is to start by thinking, hypothetically, that we are at the beginning of forming a society and
we want to know which principles of justice to ground the society. However, in this 'original
position' we do this without knowing which position we will occupy in the future society -- we
don't know if we will be rich or poor, male or female, old or young, etc. We then advocate those
principles that will be in our self-interest (though we don't know what 'self' that will be). This
forces us to be impartial, and if we are rational, to propose universal principles. The idea of the
thought experiment is not to think that we actually begin again, and construct a society from
scratch. Rather, we can use the thought experiment as a test of actual principles of justice. If a
principle is one that would not be adopted by people in the original position, behind the 'veil of
ignorance' (about who they will be), then it is unjust and should be rejected. [Rawls claims that
people in this original position will choose conservatively when developing principles
governing the distribution of benefits and burdens. This conservatism, Rawls claims, will lead
to the choosing two basic principles:
(1) that each member of the society should have as much liberty as possible without
infringing on the liberty of others; and
(2) the 'maximin' rule for decisions about economic justice -- namely, that they will
choose those rules that would maximize the minimum they would receive. In other words, make
the society in which the least well off are in the best possible position. Deviations from equality
of distribution of benefits and burdens is justified only if it advantages the least well off. Rawls
thought that some inequalities would be adopted because rewarding on the grounds of merit and
hard work, for example, would lead to a society in which there was a greater production of
social benefits, so the least well of would be better off than in a society of pure equality.
1.3 Determinism
Determinism is a far-reaching term affecting many areas of concern, that most widely and
radically states that all events in the world are the result of some previous event, or events. In this
view, all of reality is already in a sense pre-determined or pre-existent and, therefore, nothing
new can come into existence. This closed view of the universe and of our world holds all events
to be simply the effects of other prior effects. This has radical and far-reaching implications for
morality, science, and religion. If general, radical, determinism is correct, then all events in the
future are unalterable, as are all events in the past. A major consequence of this is that human
freedom is simply an illusion.
1.The World
Why should we start so globally, speaking of the world, with all its myriad events, as
deterministic?
One might have thought that a focus on individual events is more appropriate: an event
E is causally determined if and only if there exists a set of prior events {A, B, C …} that
constitute a (jointly) sufficient cause of E. Then if all—or even just most—events E that are our
human actions are causally determined, the problem that matters to us, namely the challenge to
free will, is in force. Nothing so global as states of the whole world need be invoked, nor even
a complete determinism that claims all events to be causally determined.
2. The way things are at a time t
The typical explication of determinism fastens on the state of the (whole) world at a particular
time (or instant), for a variety of reasons. Why take the state of the whole world, rather than
some (perhaps very large) region, as our starting point? One might, intuitively, think that it
would be enough to give the complete state of things on Earth, say, or perhaps in the whole solar
system, at t, to fix what happens thereafter (for a time at least). But in making vivid the “threat”
of determinism, we often want to fasten on the idea of the entire future of the world as being
determined. No matter what the “speed limit” on physical influences is, if we want the entire
future of the world to be determined, then we will have to fix the state of things over all of space,
so as not to miss out something that could later come in “from outside” to spoil things. 3.
Thereafter
For a wide class of physical theories (i.e., proposed sets of laws of nature), if they can be
viewed as deterministic at all, they can be viewed as bi-directionally deterministic. That is, a
specification of the state of the world at a time t, along with the laws, determines not only how
things go after t, but also how things go before t. Philosophers, while not exactly unaware of this
symmetry, tend to ignore it when thinking of the bearing of determinism on the free will issue.
The reason for this is that we tend to think of the past (and hence, states of the world in the past)
as done, over, fixed and beyond our control. Forward-looking determinism then entails that these
past states—beyond our control, perhaps occurring long before humans even existed—determine
everything we do in our lives. It then seems a mere curious fact that it is equally true that the
state of the world now determines everything that happened in the past.
4. Laws of nature
In the loose statement of determinism we are working from, metaphors such as “govern”
and “under the sway of” are used to indicate the strong force being attributed to the laws of
nature. Part of understanding determinism—and especially, whether and why it is metaphysically
important—is getting clear about the status of the presumed laws of nature.
In the physical sciences, the assumption that there are fundamental, exceptionless laws of
nature, and that they have some strong sort of modal force, usually goes unquestioned. Indeed,
talk of laws “governing” and so on is so commonplace that it takes an effort of will to see it as
metaphorical. We can characterize the usual assumptions about laws in this way: the laws of
nature are assumed to be pushy explainers. They make things happen in certain ways , and by
having this power, their existence lets us explain why things happen in certain ways. 5. Fixed
We can now put our—still vague—pieces together. Determinism requires a world that (a)
has a well-defined state or description, at any given time, and (b) laws of nature that are true at
all places and times. If we have all these, then if (a) and (b) together logically entail the state of
the world at all other times (or, at least, all times later than that given in (a)), the world is
deterministic. Logical entailment, in a sense broad enough to encompass mathematical
consequence, is the modality behind the determination in “determinism.”
How could we ever decide whether our world is deterministic or not? Given that some
philosophers and some physicists have held firm views—with many prominent examples on each
side—one would think that it should be at least a clearly decidable question.
Unfortunately, even this much is not clear, and the epistemology of determinism turns out to
be a thorny and multi-faceted issue.
1. Laws again
Determinism to be true there have to be some laws of nature. Most philosophers and
scientists since the 17th century have indeed thought that there are. But in the face of more recent
skepticism, how can it be proven that there are? And if this hurdle can be overcome, don't we
have to know, with certainty, precisely what the laws of our world are, in order to tackle the
question of determinism's truth or falsity? The first hurdle can perhaps be overcome by a
combination of metaphysical argument and appeal to knowledge we already have of the physical
world. Philosophers are currently pursuing this issue actively, in large part due to the efforts of
the anti-laws minority.
2. Experience
Determinism could perhaps also receive direct support—confirmation in the sense of
probability-raising, not proof—from experience and experiment. For theories (i.e., potential laws
of nature) of the sort we are used to in physics, it is typically the case that if they are
deterministic, then to the extent that one can perfectly isolate a system and repeatedly impose
identical starting conditions, the subsequent behavior of the systems should also be identical.
And in broad terms, this is the case in many domains we are familiar with. The cases of
repeated, reliable behavior obviously require some serious ceteris paribus clauses, are never
perfectly identical, and always subject to catastrophic failure at some point. But we tend to think
that for the small deviations, probably there are explanations for them in terms of different
starting conditions or failed isolation, and for the catastrophic failures, definitely there are
explanations in terms of different conditions.
3. Determinism and Chaos
If the world were governed by strictly deterministic laws, might it still look as though
indeterminism reigns? This is one of the difficult questions that chaos theory raises for the
epistemology of determinism.
A deterministic chaotic system has, roughly speaking, two salient features: (i) the evolution
of the system over a long time period effectively mimics a random or stochastic process—it
lacks predictability or computability in some appropriate sense; (ii) two systems with nearly
identical initial states will have radically divergent future developments, within a finite (and
typically, short) timespan.
We will use “randomness” to denote the first feature, and “sensitive dependence on initial
conditions” (SDIC) for the latter. A simple and very important example of a chaotic system in
both randomness and SDIC terms is the Newtonian dynamics of a pool table with a convex
obstacle (or obstacles).
The usual idealizing assumptions are made: no friction, perfectly elastic collisions, no outside
influences. The ball's trajectory is determined by its initial position and direction of motion. If we
imagine a slightly different initial direction, the trajectory will at first be only slightly different.
And collisions with the straight walls will not tend to increase very rapidly the
difference between trajectories. But collisions with the convex object will have the effect of
amplifying the differences. After several collisions with the convex body or bodies, trajectories
that started out very close to one another will have become wildly different—SDIC.
4. Metaphysical arguments
Let us suppose that we shall never have the Final Theory of Everything before us—at least
in our lifetime—and that we also remain unclear (on physical/experimental grounds) as to
whether that Final Theory will be of a type that can or cannot be deterministic. Is there nothing
left that could sway our belief toward or against determinism? There is, of course:
metaphysical argument.
Metaphysical arguments on this issue are not currently very popular. But philosophical fashions
change at least twice a century, and grand systemic metaphysics of the Leibnizian sort might
one day come back into favor. As likely as not, for the foreseeable future metaphysical
argument may be just as good a basis on which to discuss determinism's prospects as any
arguments from mathematics or physics.
The free will vs determinism debate revolves around the extent to which our behavior is the
result of forces over which we have no control or whether people are able to decide for
themselves whether to act or behave in a certain way. The determinist approach proposes that
all behavior has a cause and is thus predictable. Free will is an illusion, and our behavior is
governed by internal or external forces over which we have no control.
Freewill
Free will is the idea that we are able to have some choice in how we act and assumes
that we are free to choose our behavior, in other words we are self-determined. For example,
people can make a free choice as to whether to commit a crime or not (unless they are a child
or they are insane). This does not mean that behavior is random, but we are free from the
causal influences of past events. According to freewill a person is responsible for their own
actions. One of the main assumptions of the humanistic approach is that humans have free
will; not all behavior is determined. Personal agency is the humanistic term for the exercise
of free will. Personal agency refers to the choices we make in life, the paths we go down and
their consequences.
Critical Evaluation
Psychologists who take the free will view suggest that determinism removes freedom and
dignity, and devalues human behavior. By creating general laws of behavior, deterministic
psychology underestimates the uniqueness of human beings and their freedom to choose their
own destiny. There are important implications for taking either side in this debate.
Deterministic explanations for behavior reduce individual responsibility. A person arrested for
a violent attack for example might plead that they were not responsible for their behavior – it
was due to their upbringing, a bang on the head they received earlier in life, recent relationship
stresses, or a psychiatric problem. In other words, their behavior was determined.
The deterministic approach also has important implications for psychology as a science.
Scientists are interested in discovering laws which can then be used to predict events. This is
very easy to see in physics, chemistry and biology. As a science, psychology attempts the same
thing – to develop laws, but this time to predict behavior. If we argue against determinism, we
are in effect rejecting the scientific approach to explaining behavior.
Mental illnesses appear to undermine the concept of freewill. For example, individuals
with OCD lose control of their thoughts and actions and people with depression lose control
over their emotions. Clearly, a pure deterministic or free will approach does not seem
appropriate when studying human behavior. Most psychologists use the concept of free will to
express the idea that behavior is not a passive reaction to forces, but that individuals actively
respond to internal and external forces.
1.7What is Ethics
Ethics are the code of conduct agreed and adopted by the people. It sets a standard of how a
person should live and interact with other people. The word "ethics" is derived from the Greek
"ethos" (meaning "custom" or "habit"). Ethics differs from morals and morality in that ethics
denotes the theory of right action and the greater good, while morals indicate their practice.
Ethics is not limited to specific acts and defined moral codes, but encompasses the whole of
moral ideals and behaviors, a person's philosophy of life (or Weltanschauung).
Ethics is two things.
First, ethics refers to well-founded standards of right and wrong that prescribe what humans
ought to do, usually in terms of rights, obligations, benefits to society, fairness, or specific
virtues. Ethics, for example, refers to those standards that impose the reasonable obligations to
refrain from rape, stealing, murder, assault, slander, and fraud. Ethical standards also include
those that enjoin virtues of honesty, compassion, and loyalty. And, ethical standards include
standards relating to rights, such as the right to life, the right to freedom from injury, and the
right to privacy. Such standards are adequate standards of ethics because they are supported by
consistent and well-founded reasons.
Secondly, ethics refers to the study and development of one's ethical standards. As mentioned
above, feelings, laws, and social norms can deviate from what is ethical. So, it is necessary to
constantly examine one's standards to ensure that they are reasonable and well-founded. Ethics
also means, then, the continuous effort of studying our own moral beliefs and our moral
conduct, and striving to ensure that we, and the institutions we help to shape, live up to
standards that are reasonable and solidly-based.
Ethics is based on well-founded standards of right and wrong that prescribe what humans
ought to do, usually in terms of rights, obligations, benefits to society, fairness, or specific
virtues. A person following his or her feelings may recoil from doing what is right. In fact,
feelings frequently deviate from what is ethical. Most religions, of course, advocate high ethical
standards. Yet if ethics were confined to religion, then ethics would apply only to religious
people. But ethics applies as much to the behavior of the atheist as to that of the devout religious
person.Religion can set high ethical standards and can provide intense motivations for ethical
behavior. Ethics, however, cannot be confined to religion nor is it the same as religion.Being
ethical is also not the same as following the law. The law often incorporates ethical standards to
which most citizens subscribe. But laws, like feelings, can deviate from what is ethical. Our own
pre-Civil War slavery laws and the old apartheid laws of present-day South Africa are
grotesquely obvious examples of laws that deviate from what is ethical.
Finally, being ethical is not the same as doing "whatever society accepts." In any society,
most people accept standards that are, in fact, ethical. But standards of behavior in society can
deviate from what is ethical. An entire society can become ethically corrupt. Nazi Germany is a
good example of a morally corrupt society. Moreover, if being ethical were doing "whatever
society accepts," then to find out what is ethical, one would have to find out what society
accepts. To decide what I should think about abortion, for example, I would have to take a
survey of American society and then conform my beliefs to whatever society accepts. Further,
the lack of social consensus on many issues makes it impossible to equate ethics with whatever
society accepts. Some people accept abortion but many others do not. If being ethical were
doing whatever society accepts, one would have to find an agreement on issues which does not,
in fact, exist.
Definition of Law
The law is described as the set of rules and regulation, created by the government to
govern the whole society. The law is universally accepted, recognized and enforced. It is
created with the purpose of maintaining social order, peace, justice in the society and to provide
protection to the general public and safeguard their interest. It is made after considering ethical
principles and moral values. The law is made by the judicial system of the country. Every
person in the country is bound to follow the law. It clearly defines what a person must or must
not do. So, in the case of the breach of law may result in the punishment or penalty or
sometimes both.
Ethics and laws are found in virtually all spheres of society. They govern actions of
individuals around the world on a daily basis. They often work hand-in-hand to ensure that
citizens act in a certain manner, and likewise coordinate efforts to protect the health, safety and
welfare of the public. Though law often embodies ethical principals, law and ethics are not co-
extensive. Based on society’s ethics, laws are created and enforced by governments to mediate
our relationships with each other, and to protect its citizens. While laws carry with them a
punishment for violations, ethics do not. Essentially, laws enforce the behaviors we are expected
to follow, while ethics suggest what we ought to follow, and help us explore options to improve
our decision-making.
Ethical decision-making comes from within a person’s moral sense and desire to preserve
self respect. Laws are codifications of certain ethical values meant to help regulate society, and
also impact decision-making. It is not always a clear delineation though. Many acts that would
be widely condemned as unethical are not prohibited by law — lying or betraying the confidence
of a friend. In addition, punishments for breaking laws can be harsh and sometimes even break
ethical standards. Take the death penalty for instance. Ethics teaches that killing is wrong, yet
the law also punishes people who break the law with death.
The phrase unjust law can serve as a starting point for understanding that laws can be
immoral. We also have “shysters,” or crooked lawyers, who are considered unethical within their
own profession. Obviously, morality and the law are not necessarily one and the same thing
when two people can be lawyers, both having studied a great deal of the same material, and one
is moral, whereas the other is not. The many protests we have had throughout history against
unjust laws, where, more often than not, the protestors were concerned with “what is moral” or a
“higher morality,” would also seem to indicate that distinctions must be made between law and
morality. Law is a public expression of social morality and also is its sanction. Law cannot in
any way replace or substitute for morality, and therefore we cannot arbitrarily equate what is
legal with what is moral. Many times the two “whats” will equate exactly, but many times they
will not; and indeed many times what is legal will not, and perhaps should not, completely cover
what is moral.
t some behaviors are more constrained than others and that there
References:
https://www.pearsonhighered.com/assets/samplechapter/0/2/0/5/0205053149.pdf
https://www.unodc.org/e4j/en/integrity-ethics/teaching-guide/overview-of-modules-and-learning
outcomes.html
https://home.sandiego.edu/~baber/gender/MoralTheories.html
https://www.pnas.org/content/107/Supplement_2/9015
https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/morality-definition/
http://thesimplerway.info/Morality.htm
https://www.simplypsychology.org/freewill-determinism.html
https://courses.lumenlearning.com/atd-epcc-introethics-1/chapter/ethics-and-
law/ https://www.atrainceu.com/content/4-ethics-and-law
CHAPTER 2
Going Deeper into the Ghetto
Learning Outcomes:
• To understand and discern the difference between cultural relativism, ethical relativism
and normative relativism.
• To analyze the structure of the arguments for relativism and assess the truth value of the
premises and the logical structure of the argument.
• To examine the alternatives to relativism to begin the process of crafting a better
understanding of the source and nature of ethical values.
• To understand the relationship between taking responsibility and being ethical, and how
this applies to one's own life
INTRODUCTION
The term ghetto refers to an urban area with low property values and relatively little
public or private investment. The word is slang and is generally considered an offensive
stereotype because ghettos have historically been inhabited by racial minorities. Ghettos are also
characterized by high unemployment, high rates of crime, inadequate municipal services, and
high drop-out rates from schools. Urban neighborhoods classified as ghettos may be severely
underpopulated with abandoned homes, or they may be densely populated with large families
living in small spaces.
The phenomenon of ghetto has existed for centuries. The original ghetto emerged in
medieval Europe, Jews were segregated by religious authorities as the source of moral corruption
and carriers of diseases, such as the Venetian Ghetto. In the modern society, some parts of the
world still have ghettos in cities, such as African-American ghettos in United States. As a special
community that combines with social, economic and historical elements, the definition of ghetto
is being put forward under a controversial position. For instance, some scholars insist that ghetto
should be defined by racial segregation and subjugation without limitations on poverty and class.
Others argue that areas with concentrated poverty are ghettos despite racial or ethnic makeup.
Still some scholars synthesize all the characteristics to consider the ghetto.
According to a large number of investigations and debates, several constituents of ghetto
could be concluded below: concentrated poverty; involuntary segregation and spatial
confinement; racism, stigma and constraints; institutional encasement. To do a deeper research of
ghetto needs a clear starting point, it is the definition. What the ghetto is? Who live in the ghetto?
What are the constituents of a ghetto? Does the concentrated poverty stand for the ghetto or not?
So many puzzled questions and debates linger in our minds. This paper will introduce three
typical ghettos briefly first, and combining those examples with several scholars’ points to
analyze every constituent of the ghetto mentioned above for achieving a more explicit concept of
the word ‘ghetto’.
➢ Japanese Burakumin
Burakumin were seen officially as rural outcasts and the lowest class in Tokugawa era (1603
– 1868). The Tokugawa government divided people into four classes: samurai, peasant, artisan
and merchant. Burakumin ranked behind merchant and were usually formed of hinin and eta,
‘hinin’ includes town guards, street cleaners and executioners, ‘eta’ includes butchers, tanners,
leather-makers, and undertakers (Slater, 2009). Both hinin and eta are discriminated words,
‘hinin’ means ‘non-human’ and ‘eta’ means ‘filthy’ in Japanese, they are all untouchable in the
eyes of Buddhism and Shinto. Burakumin had to obey various rules which were set legally,
firstly, they lived in Buraku only, and could enter into the town during daytime; secondly, they
had to wear yellow collars and to walk on barefoot; thirdly, they were forced to drop on their
hands and knees when met commoners; the fourth rule, marriages were limited, they just could
married with Burakumin.
Burakumin were emancipated in 1871, they could move into cities but with notorious
conditions, for instance, living in districts around garbage dumps, jails or crematoria with high
crime rate and messy social order; job opportunities hanged in the range between low-paying and
dirty works; separated schools established for them to be educated; permanent marks of
Burakumin stay still for the existence of a ‘family registration system’ in Japan (Devos &
Wagatsuma, 1966). The Burakumin Defense League counted that around three million
Burakumin were trapped in 6,000 ghettos in Japanese cities in late 1970. According to some
Japanese citizens, they said it is difficult for Burakumin to find a job because they will be
identified by the address information even in nowadays.
“Ethical relativism, the doctrine that there are no absolute truths in ethics and that what is
morally right or wrong varies from person to person or from society to society.” Ethical
relativism is the theory that holds that morality is relative to the norms of one's culture. That is,
whether an action is right or wrong depends on the moral norms of the society in which it is
practiced. The same action may be morally right in one society but be morally wrong in another.
For the ethical relativist, there are no universal moral standards -- standards that can be
universally applied to all peoples at all times. The only moral standards against which a society's
practices can be judged are its own. If ethical relativism is correct, there can be no common
framework for resolving moral disputes or for reaching agreement on ethical matters among
members of different societies.
Most ethicists reject the theory of ethical relativism. Some claim that while the moral
practices of societies may differ, the fundamental moral principles underlying these practices do
not. For example, in some societies, killing one's parents after they reached a certain age was
common practice, stemming from the belief that people were better off in the afterlife if they
entered it while still physically active and vigorous. While such a practice would be condemned
in our society, we would agree with these societies on the underlying moral principle -- the duty
to care for parents. Societies, then, may differ in their application of fundamental moral
principles but agree on the principles.
Also, it is argued, it may be the case that some moral beliefs are culturally relative whereas
others are not. Certain practices, such as customs regarding dress and decency, may
depend on local custom whereas other practices, such as slavery, torture, or political repression,
may be governed by universal moral standards and judged wrong despite the many other
differences that exist among cultures. Simply because some practices are relative does not mean
that all practices are relative. Other philosophers criticize ethical relativism because of its
implications for individual moral beliefs. These philosophers assert that if the rightness or
wrongness of an action depends on a society's norms, then it follows that one must obey the
norms of one's society and to diverge from those norms is to act immorally.
This means that if I am a member of a society that believes that racial or sexist practices are
morally permissible, then I must accept those practices as morally right. But such a view
promotes social conformity and leaves no room for moral reform or improvement in a society.
Types of Relativism
❖ Cultural Relativism
Describes the simple fact that there are different cultures and each has different ways of
behaving, thinking and feeling as its members learn such from the previous generation.
There is an enormous amount of evidence to confirm this claim. It is well known by just
about every human on the planet that people do things differently around the globe.
People dress differently, eat differently, speak different languages, sing different songs,
have different music and dances and have many different customs.
❖ Descriptive Ethical Relativism
Describes the fact that in different cultures one of the variants is the sense of morality: the
mores, customs and ethical principles may all vary from one culture to another. There is a
great deal of information available to confirm this as well. What is thought to be moral
in one country may be thought to be immoral and even made illegal in another
country. ❖ Normative Ethical Relativism
Is a theory, which claims that there are no universally valid moral principles. Normative
ethical relativism theory says that the moral rightness and wrongness of actions varies
from society to society and that there are no absolute universal moral standards binding
on all men at all times. The theory claims that all thinking about the basic principles of
morality (Ethics) is always relative. Each culture establishes the basic values and
principles that serve as the foundation for morality. The theory claims that this is the case
now, has always been the case and will always be the case.
Absolutism, the view that at least some truths or values in the relevant domain apply to all times,
places or social and cultural frameworks. They are universal and not bound by historical or social
conditions. Absolutism is often used as the key contrast idea to relativism.
Objectivism or the position that cognitive, ethical and aesthetic norms and values in general, but
truth in particular, are independent of judgments and beliefs at particular times and places, or in
other words they are (non-trivially) mind-independent. The anti-objectivist on the other hand,
denies that there is such thing as simply being ‘true’, ‘good’, ‘tasty’ or ‘beautiful’ but argues that
we can coherently discuss such values only in relation to parameters that have something to do
with our mental lives.
Monism or the view that, in any given area or topic subject to disagreement, there can be no
more than one correct opinion, judgment, or norm. The relativist often wishes to allow for a
plurality of equally valid values or even truths.
Realism, when defined in such a way that it entails both the objectivity and singularity of truth,
also stands in opposition to relativism.
Arguments for Ethical Relativism
(i) Herodotus, the Greek historian of the 5th century BC, advanced this view when he
observed that different societies have different customs and that each person thinks his
own society’s customs are best. But no set of social customs, Herodotus said, is really
better or worse than any other. Some contemporary sociologists and anthropologists have
argued along similar lines that morality, because it is a social product, develops
differently within different cultures. Each society develops standards that are used by
people within it to distinguish acceptable from
unacceptable behavior, and every judgment of right and wrong presupposes one or
another of these standards. Thus, according to these researchers, if practices such as
polygamy or infanticide are considered right within a society, then they are right “for
that society”; and if the same practices are considered wrong within a different
society, then those practices are wrong for that society. There is no such thing as what
is “really” right, apart from these social codes, for there is no culture-neutral standard
to which we can appeal to determine which society’s view is correct.
(ii) A second type of argument for ethical relativism is due to the Scottish philosopher David
Hume (1711–76), who claimed that moral beliefs are based on “sentiment,” or
emotion, rather than on reason. This idea was developed by the 20th-century school
of logical positivism and by later philosophers such as Charles L. Stevenson (1908–
79) and R.M. Hare (1919–2002), who held that the primary function of moral
language is not to state facts but to express feelings of approval or disapproval toward
some action or to influence the attitudes and actions of others. On this view, known as
emotivism, right and wrong are relative to individual preferences rather than to social
standards. Ethical relativism is attractive to many philosophers and social scientists
because it seems to offer the best explanation of the variability of moral belief. It also
offers a plausible way of explaining how ethics fits into the world as it is described by
modern science. Even if the natural world ultimately consists of nothing but value
neutral facts, say the relativists, ethics still has a foundation in human feelings and
social arrangements.
Finally, ethical relativism seems especially well suited to explain the virtue of
tolerance. If, from an objective point of view, one’s own values and the values of
one’s society have no special standing, then an attitude of “live and let live” toward
other people’s values seems appropriate.
Criticisms of Ethical Relativism
Ethical relativism, then, is a radical doctrine that is contrary to what many thoughtful people
commonly assume. As such, it should not be confused with the uncontroversial thought that
what is right depends on the circumstances. Ethical relativism merely the idea that different
people have different beliefs about ethics, which again no one would deny. It is, rather, a theory
about the status of moral beliefs, according to which none of them is objectively true. A
consequence of the theory is that there is no way to justify any moral principle as valid for all
people and all societies.
Critics have lodged a number of complaints against this doctrine. They point out that if
ethical relativism is correct, it would mean that even the most outrageous practices, such as
slavery and the physical abuse of women, are “right” if they are countenanced by the standards
of the relevant society. Relativism therefore deprives us of any means of raising moral objections
against horrendous social customs, provided that those customs are approved by the codes of the
societies in which they exist.
Critics say, it is a mistake to think that relativism implies that we should be tolerant,
because tolerance is simply another value about which people or societies may disagree. Only an
absolutist could say that tolerance is objectively good. Critics also point out that disagreement
about ethics does not mean that there can be no objective truth. After all, people disagree even
about scientific matters. Some people believe that disease is caused by evil spirits, while others
believe it is caused by microbes, but we do not on that account conclude that disease has no
“real” cause. The same might be true of ethics—disagreement might only mean that some people
are more enlightened than others.
Anthropologists have observed that, while there is some variation from culture to culture,
there are also some values that all societies have in common. Some values are, in fact, necessary
for society to exist. Without rules requiring truthfulness, for example, there could be no
communication, and without rules against murder and assault, people could not live together.
Lastly, to the claim that there is no legitimate way to judge a society’s practices “from the
outside,” critics may reply that we can always ask whether a particular cultural practice works to
the advantage or disadvantage of the people within the culture.
2.3 Egoism
Egoism is the philosophy concerned with the role of the self, or ego, as the motivation
and goal of one's own action. Different theories on egoism encompass a range of disparate ideas
and can generally be categorized into descriptive or normative forms. People act for many
reasons; but for whom, or what, do or should they act—for themselves, for God, or for the good
of the planet? Can an individual ever act only according to her own interests without regard for
others’ interests. Conversely, can an individual ever truly act for others in complete disregard for
her own interests? The answers will depend on an account of free will. Some philosophers argue
that an individual has no choice in these matters, claiming that a person’s acts are determined by
prior events which make illusory any belief in choice.
Nevertheless, if an element of choice is permitted against the great causal impetus from
nature, or God, it follows that a person possesses some control over her next action, and, that,
therefore, one may inquire as to whether the individual does, or, should choose a self-or-other
oriented action. Morally speaking, one can ask whether the individual should pursue her own
interests, or, whether she should reject self-interest and pursue others’ interest instead: to what
extent are other-regarding acts morally praiseworthy compared to self-regarding acts?
ETHICAL EGOISM
1. Common-sense Egoism:
According to this view, egoism is a vice. It involves putting one’s own concerns over those
of others. One’s behavior is egoistic if it involves putting one’s own interests over those of others
to an immoderate degree.
2. Psychological Egoism
❖ Argument For: Human agents always, at least on a deep-down level, are all egoists
insofar as our behavior, explainable in terms of our beliefs and desires, is always aimed at
what we believe is our greatest good (Baier, 1991, p. 203).
❖ Objection: The psychological egoist confuses egoistic desires with motivation. An agent
may act contrary to his desires and what is in his own best interest. People often act in
ways that they know are detrimental to their well being. Moreover, what one most wants
may not be in their own self-interest (e.g., giving money to Amnesty International rather
than buying a new CD). MacKinnon adds that, “Even if it were shown that we often act
for the sake of our own interest, this is not enough to prove that psychological egoism is
true. According to this theory, we must show that people always act to promote their own
interests”
3. Egoism as a Means to the Common Good
❖ Argument For: According to the economist, Adam Smith, when entrepreneurs are
unimpeded by legal or self-imposed moral constraint to protect the good of others, they
are able to promote their own good and, as a result, provide the most efficient means of
promoting the good of others (Baier, 1991, p. 201; see MacKinnon, p. 24). Such a view
leads to the doctrine that, “if each pursues her own interest as she conceives of it, then the
interest of everyone is promoted” (Baier, 1991, p. 200).
❖ Objection: Apart from positing an “invisible hand” guiding the market processes, the
common-good egoist makes the fallacy, ascribed to J.S. Mill, that if each person
promotes her own interest, then everyone else’s interests are thereby promoted. “Clearly,
this is a fallacy, for the interests of different individuals or classes may, and under certain
conditions (of which the scarcity of necessities is the most obvious), do conflict. Then the
interest of one is the detriment of the other” (Baier, 1991, p. 200).
4. Rational Egoism:
Rational egoism is concerned with reasonable action.
❖ Strong Rational Egoism: It is always rational to aim at one’s own greatest good, and
never rational not to do so (Baier, 1991, p. 201).
❖ Weak Rational Egoism: It is always rational to aim at one’s own greatest good, but not
necessarily never rational not to do so (Baier, 1991, p. 201).
❖ Argument For: When doing something does not prima facie appear to be in our interest,
our doing said act requires that we justify our action by showing that it is in our interest,
thereby justifying our action.
❖ Objection: Such an approach to justifying actions in our own interest may be abused if
we do not have criteria established to determine what the interests of agents amount to. If
such criteria are established, such actions may be reasonable so long as they do not result in
conflicts between agents. In such cases, creative middle ways are called for. 5. Ethical
Egoism:
Coupled with ethical rationalism—”the doctrine that if a moral requirement or
recommendation is to be sound or acceptable, complying with it must be in accordance
with reason”—rational egoism implies ethical egoism (Baier, 1991, p. 201).
❖ Strong Ethical Egoism: It is always right to aim at one’s own greatest good, and never
right not to do so (Baier, 1991, p. 201).
❖ Weak Ethical Egoism: It is always right to aim at one’s own greatest good, but not
necessarily never right not to do so (Baier, 1991, p. 201).
❖ Argument For: If we accept rational egoism, and if we accept ethical rationalism, then we
must accept ethical egoism. This is the case because if acting in one’s own self-interest is
reasonable, then it is a moral requirement that one acts in one’s own self-interest.
❖ Objection: Ethical egoism is incompatible with ethical conflict-regulation. Consider the
following example from Kurt Baier, regarding the problem over whether it would be
morally wrong for me to kill my grandfather so that he will be unable to change his will
and disinherit me (1991, p. 202)
Assuming that my killing him will be in my best interest but detrimental to my grandfather,
while refraining from killing him will be to my detriment but in my grandfather’s interest, then if
ethical conflict-regulation is sound, there can be a sound moral guideline regulating this conflict
(presumably by forbidding this killing). But then ethical egoism cannot be sound, for it precludes
the interpersonally authoritative regulation of interpersonal conflicts of interest, since such a
regulation implies that conduct contrary to one’s interest is sometimes morally required of one,
and conduct in one’s best interest is sometimes morally forbidden to one.
Normative Ethics
Normative Ethics (or Prescriptive Ethics) is the branch of ethics concerned with
establishing how things should or ought to be, how to value them, which things are good or
bad, and which actions are right or wrong. It attempts to develop a set of rules governing
human conduct, or a set of norms for action. Normative ethical theories are usually split into
three main categories:
a.Consequentialism (or Teleological Ethics) argues that the morality of an action is contingent
on the action's outcome or result. Thus, a morally right action is one that produces a good
outcome or consequence. Some consequentialist theories include:
❖ Utilitarianism, which holds that an action is right if it leads to the most happiness for
the greatest number of people ("happiness" here is defined as the maximization of
pleasure and the minimization of pain). The origins of Utilitarianism can be traced
back as far as the Greek philosopher Epicurus, but its full formulation is usually
credited to Jeremy Bentham, with John Stuart Mill as its foremost proponent.
❖ Hedonism, which is the philosophy that pleasure is the most important pursuit of
mankind, and that individuals should strive to maximize their own total pleasure (net of
any pain or suffering). Epicureanism is a more moderate approach (which still seeks to
maximize happiness, but which defines happiness more as a state of tranquillity than
pleasure).
❖ Egoism, which holds that an action is right if it maximizes good for the self. Thus,
Egoism may license actions which are good for the individual, but detrimental to the
general welfare. Individual Egoism holds that all people should do whatever benefits him
or her self. Personal Egoism holds that each person should act in his own self-interest, but
makes no claims about what anyone else ought to do. Universal Egoism holds that
everyone should act in ways that are in their own interest.
❖ Asceticism, which is, in some ways, the opposite of Egoism in that it describes a life
characterized by abstinence from egoistic pleasures especially to achieve a spiritual
goal.
❖ Altruism, which prescribes that an individual take actions that have the best
consequences for everyone except for himself, according to Auguste Comte's dictum,
"Live for others". Thus, individuals have a moral obligation to help, serve or benefit
others, if necessary at the sacrifice of self-interest.
b. Rule Consequentialism, which is a theory (sometimes seen as an attempt to reconcile
Consequentialism and Deontology), that moral behavior involves following certain rules, but
that those rules should be chosen based on the consequences that the selection of those rules
have.
c. Negative Consequentialism, which focuses on minimizing bad consequences rather than
promoting good consequences. This may actually require active intervention (to prevent harm
from being done), or may only require passive avoidance of bad outcomes.
Pluralistic Deontology is a description of the deontological ethics propounded by W.D. Ross
(1877 - 1971). He argues that there are seven prima facie duties which need to be taken into
consideration when deciding which duty should be acted upon: beneficence (to help other people
to increase their pleasure, improve their character, etc); non-maleficence (to avoid harming other
people); justice (to ensure people get what they deserve); self-improvement (to improve
ourselves); reparation (to recompense someone if you have acted wrongly towards them);
gratitude (to benefit people who have benefited us); promise-keeping (to act according to explicit
and implicit promises, including the implicit promise to tell the truth). In some circumstances,
there may be clashes or conflicts between these duties and a decision must be made whereby one
duty may "trump" another, although there are no hard and fast rules and no fixed order of
significance.
Contractarian Ethics (or the Moral Theory of Contractarianism) claims that moral norms
derive their normative force from the idea of contract or mutual agreement. It holds that moral
acts are those that we would all agree to if we were unbiased, and that moral rules themselves are
a sort of a contract, and therefore only people who understand and agree to the terms of the
contract are bound by it. The theory stems initially from political Contractarianism and the
principle of social contract developed by Thomas Hobbes, Jean Jacques Rousseau and John
Locke, which essentially holds that people give up some rights to a government and/or other
authority in order to receive, or jointly preserve, social order. Contractualism is a variation on
Contractarianism, although based more on the Kantian ideas that ethics is an essentially
interpersonal matter, and that right and wrong are a matter of whether we can justify the action to
other people.
Virtue Ethics, focuses on the inherent character of a person rather than on the nature or
consequences of specific actions performed. The system identifies virtues (those habits and
behaviors that will allow a person to achieve "eudaimonia", or well being or a good life),
counsels practical wisdom to resolve any conflicts between virtues, and claims that a lifetime of
practicing these virtues leads to, or in effect constitutes, happiness and the good life.
❖ Eudaimonism is a philosophy originated by Aristotle that defines right action as that
which leads to "well being", and which can be achieved by a lifetime of practicing the
virtues in one's everyday activities, subject to the exercise of practical wisdom. It was
first advocated by Plato and is particularly associated with Aristotle, and became the
prevailing approach to ethical thinking in the Ancient and Medieval periods. It fell out of
favor in the Early Modern period, but has recently undergone a modern resurgence.
Ethics of Care was developed mainly by Feminist writers, and calls for a change in how we view
morality and the virtues, shifting towards the more marginalized virtues exemplified by women,
such as taking care of others, patience, the ability to nurture, self-sacrifice, etc.
Descriptive Ethics
Descriptive Ethics is a value-free approach to ethics which examines ethics from the
perspective of observations of actual choices made by moral agents in practice. It is the study of
people's beliefs about morality, and implies the existence of, rather than explicitly prescribing,
theories of value or of conduct. It is not designed to provide guidance to people in making moral
decisions, nor is it designed to evaluate the reasonableness of moral norms. It is more likely to
be investigated by those working in the fields of evolutionary biology, psychology, sociology,
history or anthropology, although information that comes from descriptive ethics is also used in
philosophical arguments. Descriptive Ethics is sometimes referred to as Comparative Ethics
because so much activity can involve comparing ethical systems: comparing the ethics of the
past to the present; comparing the ethics of one society to another; and comparing the ethics
which people claim to follow with the actual rules of conduct which do describe their actions.
Applied Ethics
Applied Ethics is a discipline of philosophy that attempts to apply ethical theory to real-
life situations. Strict, principle-based ethical approaches often result in solutions to specific
problems that are not universally acceptable or impossible to implement. Applied Ethics is much
more ready to include the insights of psychology, sociology and other relevant areas of
knowledge in its deliberations. It is used in determining public policy. The following would be
questions of Applied Ethics: "Is getting an abortion immoral?", "Is euthanasia immoral?", "Is
affirmative action right or wrong?", "What are human rights, and how do we determine them?"
and "Do animals have rights as well?"
2.5 Utilitarianism
Utilitarianism is a philosophical view or theory about how we should evaluate a wide
range of things that involve choices that people face. Among the things that can be evaluated are
actions, laws, policies, character traits, and moral codes. Utilitarianism is a form of
consequentialism because it rests on the idea that it is the consequences or results of actions,
laws, policies, etc. that determine whether they are good or bad, right or wrong. In general,
whatever is being evaluated, we ought to choose the one that will produce the best overall
results. In the language of utilitarians, we should choose the option that “maximizes utility,” i.e.
that action or policy that produces the largest amount of good.
Utilitarianism appears to be a simple theory because it consists of only one evaluative
principle: Do what produces the best consequences. In fact, however, the theory is complex
because we cannot understand that single principle unless we know (at least) three things: a)
what things are good and bad; b) whose good (i.e. which individuals or groups) we should aim
to maximize; and c) whether actions, policies, etc. are made right or wrong by their actual
consequences (the results that our actions actually produce) or by their foreseeable consequences
(the results that we predict will occur based on the evidence that we have).
What is Good?
Jeremy Bentham answered this question by adopting the view called hedonism.
According to hedonism, the only thing that is good in itself is pleasure (or happiness). Hedonists
do not deny that many different kinds of things can be good, including food, friends, freedom,
and many other things, but hedonists see these as “instrumental” goods that are valuable only
because they play a causal role in producing pleasure or happiness. Pleasure and happiness,
however, are “intrinsic” goods, meaning that they are good in themselves and not because they
produce some further valuable thing.
Likewise, on the negative side, a lack of food, friends, or freedom is instrumentally bad
because it produces pain, suffering, and unhappiness; but pain, suffering and unhappiness are
intrinsically bad, i.e. bad in themselves and not because they produce some further bad thing.
Whose Well-being?
Utilitarian reasoning can be used for many different purposes. It can be used both for moral
reasoning and for any type of rational decision-making. In addition to applying in different
contexts, it can also be used for deliberations about the interests of different persons and groups.
ii. Groups
People often need to judge what is best not only for themselves or other individuals but
alsowhat is best for groups, such as friends, families, religious groups, one’s country, etc.
Because Bentham and other utilitarians were interested in political groups and public policies,
they often focused on discovering which actions and policies would maximize the well-being of
the relevant group. Their method for determining the well-being of a group involved adding up
the benefits and losses that members of the group would experience as a result of adopting one
action or policy. The well-being of the group is simply the sum total of the interests of the all of
its members.
To illustrate this method, suppose that you are buying ice cream for a party that ten
people will attend. Your only flavor options are chocolate and vanilla, and some of the people
attending like chocolate while others like vanilla. As a utilitarian, you should choose the flavor
that will result in the most pleasure for the group as a whole. If seven like chocolate and three
like vanilla and if all of them get the same amount of pleasure from the flavor they like, then you
should choose chocolate. This will yield what Bentham, in a famous phrase, called “the greatest
happiness for the greatest number.”
❖ Ontological moral dilemmas, on the other hand, involve situations wherein two or more
moral requirements conflict with each other, yet neither of these conflicting moral
requirements overrides each other. ... A self-imposed moral dilemma is caused by the
moral agent's wrongdoings.
❖ Self-imposed moral dilemma is when a person knows that two promises are conflicted
therefore it is caused by the agents' wrongdoings.
A self-imposed moral dilemma is caused by the moral agent's wrongdoings. ... A World-imposed
moral dilemma, on the other hand, means that certain events in the world place the agent in a
situation of moral conflict.
❖ Obligation dilemma exists where an agent faces a choice situation in which two (or
more) of her available act alternatives are morally obligatory and yet it is impossible for
her to perform both of those two act alternatives.
❖ Prohibition dilemmas are choice situations in which all feasible. actions are forbidden. I
argue that they are conceptually possible, and that the standard principles of deontic logic
need to be revised so as not to rule them out.
Multiple Moralities
Another issue raised by the topic of moral dilemmas is the relationship among various
parts of morality. Consider this distinction. General obligations are moral requirements that
individuals have simply because they are moral agents. That agents are required not to kill, not to
steal, and not to assault are examples of general obligations. Agency alone makes these precepts
applicable to individuals. By contrast, role-related obligations are moral requirements that agents
have in virtue of their role, occupation, or position in society.
General obligations and role-related obligations can, and sometimes do, conflict. If a defense
attorney knows the whereabouts of a deceased body, she may have a general obligation to
reveal this information to family members of the deceased. But if she obtained this
information from her client, the role-related obligation of confidentiality prohibits her from
sharing it with others.
” The expression, “dirty hands,” is taken from the title of a play by Sartre (1946). The
idea is that no one can rule without becoming morally tainted. The role itself is fraught with
moral dilemmas. For opponents of moral dilemmas, the problem of dirty hands represents both a
challenge and an opportunity. The challenge is to show how conflicts between general
obligations and role-related obligations, and those among the various role-related obligations,
can be resolved in a principled way. The opportunity for theories that purport to have the
resources to eliminate dilemmas—such as Kantianism, utilitarianism, and intuitionism—is to
show how the many moralities under which people are governed are related.
Conclusion
The debate between act utilitarianism and rule utilitarianism highlights many important
issues about how we should make moral judgments. Act utilitarianism stresses the specific
context and the many individual features of the situations that pose moral problems, and it
presents a single method for dealing with these individual cases. Rule utilitarianism stresses the
recurrent features of human life and the ways in which similar needs and problems arise over and
over again. From this perspective, we need rules that deal with types or classes of actions:
killing, stealing, lying, cheating, taking care of our friends or family, punishing people for
crimes, aiding people in need, etc. Both of these perspectives, however, agree that the main
determinant of what is right or wrong is the relationship between what we do or what form our
moral code takes and what is the impact of our moral perspective on the level of people’s well
being.
REFERENCES:
• Aristotle. Nichomachaean Ethics. Various translations available. Book IX being most pertinent. •
Baier, Kurt. “Egoisim” in A Companion to Ethics. Ed. Peter Singer. Blackwell: Oxford. 1990. • Feinberg,
Joel. “Psychological Egoism” in Ethics: History, Theory, and Contemporary Issues. Oxford University
Press: Oxford. 1998.
• Garvin, Lucius. A Modern Introduction to Ethics. Houghton Mifflin: Cambrirdge, MA, 1953. •
Hargreaves-Heap, Shaun P. and Yanis Varoufakis. Game Theory: A Critical Introduction. Routledge:
London, 1995..
https://www.plato-philosophy.org/teachertoolkit/ethical-relativism/
https://www.unodc.org/e4j/en/integrity-ethics/teaching-guide/overview-of-modules-and
learning-outcomes.html
https://www.britannica.com/topic/ethical-relativism
http://www2.econ.iastate.edu/classes/econ362/hallam/OtherMaterial/EthicalRelativism.pdf
https://www.investopedia.com/terms/g/ghetto.asp
https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/egoism/
https://www.britannica.com/topic/utilitarianism-philosophy
https://iep.utm.edu/util-a-r/