BLOXHAM-Why History. A History
BLOXHAM-Why History. A History
BLOXHAM-Why History. A History
Why History?
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
Why History?
A History
D O NA L D B L OX HA M
1
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
1
Great Clarendon Street, Oxford, OX2 6DP,
United Kingdom
Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford.
It furthers the University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship,
and education by publishing worldwide. Oxford is a registered trade mark of
Oxford University Press in the UK and in certain other countries
© Donald Bloxham 2020
The moral rights of the author have been asserted
First Edition published in 2020
Impression: 1
All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in
a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, without the
prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted
by law, by licence or under terms agreed with the appropriate reprographics
rights organization. Enquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of the
above should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford University Press, at the
address above
You must not circulate this work in any other form
and you must impose this same condition on any acquirer
Published in the United States of America by Oxford University Press
198 Madison Avenue, New York, NY 10016, United States of America
British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data
Data available
Library of Congress Control Number: 2019957614
ISBN 978–0–19–885872–0
Printed and bound in Great Britain by
Clays Ltd, Elcograf S.p.A.
Links to third party websites are provided by Oxford in good faith and
for information only. Oxford disclaims any responsibility for the materials
contained in any third party website referenced in this work.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
Preface
With a young family I took this project on at entirely the wrong time, so my
apologies, as well as my greatest debts of gratitude, are owed to three Beatties:
Cordelia, Yasmin, and Zahra. For helpful discussions and references I thank Zubin
Mistry, David Patterson, Natasha Wheatley, Tom Brown, Reinbert A. Krol, Thomas
Ahnert, and Bill Aird. For the same things, and for their time and effort in reading
and commenting on one or more chapters I thank Douglas Cairns, Felicity Green,
Adam Fox, Lucy Grig, Jürgen Matthäus, Louise Jackson, Jane Caplan, Stephan
Malinowski, Martin Shuster, Cordelia (again), Chris Given-Wilson, Fabian Hilfrich,
Guy Halsall, Rick Sowerby, Michael Bentley, David Laven, and Colin Richmond.
Steve Rigby read the entire manuscript with the most helpful rigour and generosity
of intellectual spirit.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
Contents
Introduction1
On ‘Modern Historical Consciousness’ 1
Continuity and Change in Justifications for History 9
1. Classical History between Epic and Rhetoric 16
Introduction16
Genealogy, Ethnography, and Historical Consciousness 19
Rhetoric, Purpose, Truth 25
Useful and Pleasurable History 29
From Greek to Roman Historiography 33
Philosophy, Poetry, History: A Greek in Rome 35
Roman Historiography in the Late Republic 38
History under Monarchy 39
Pre- and Anti-Christian Influences 43
2. History, Faith, Fortuna45
Introduction45
Classical–Christian Fusion 45
Christianity and Judaism 47
Early Christian Historiography 50
Christian Philosophy of History 53
On Causation: Determinism and Human Agency 58
3. The ‘Middle Age’ 62
Introduction62
Annals and Ancestry 63
Exemplarity, Allegory, and the Presence of the Past 71
Periodization and the Conceptualization of Change 77
Theology, Religious Hermeneutics, and History as Communion 84
Socio-Economic Change and the Function of Genealogies 95
History and Developments in Political Identity 99
‘Others’ Present and Past 101
4. Renaissances and Reformations 105
Introduction105
Re-Encounters108
Romans, Greeks, Goths 111
Developments in Source Criticism? 115
Changed Circumstances, Contested Purposes 117
The Return of Similitudo Temporum124
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
x Contents
Contents xi
Introduction
1 N. D. Fustel de Coulanges, The Ancient City (Kitchener, ON: Batoche, 2001 [orig. 1864]), 5–6.
2 Ibid. 8; L. P. Hartley, The Go-Between (New York: New York Review Books, 2002 [orig. 1953]),
17, 313.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
2 Why History?
historian’s ‘elemental question’: ‘How has this come out of that?’3 Insofar as this
book makes no effort to forget what came afterwards in the study of any given
historical ‘epoch’, perhaps it contravenes the spirit of Fustel’s first sort of enquiry.
Then again, perhaps he set an unnecessarily exacting standard. There is no
contradiction between trying to take the inhabitants of a long and diverse past ‘on
their own terms’ while also seeking to comprehend how their thoughts and
actions contributed to changes that affected other, later inhabitants. Nor is there
any reason that different approaches cannot be accommodated in the same book.
In combining the two approaches it becomes impossible to separate the elem
ents of this enquiry that might be said to be of purely intrinsic interest from those
that are of more utilitarian concern. When contemplating what of the past
remains and what has been lost along the way, one is casting light, directly or
indirectly, on the present. This can be done in such a way as to strew petals down
the royal road to the here and now, or to show how fortuitous were the twists and
turns of that route to the present, or to subject the present to critical scrutiny.
The present work surveys the development of historical thinking within the
baggy, porous, and influential ‘western tradition’. Its aims are to understand how
earlier students of the past justified what they did and also to illustrate the func-
tions of what they did, whether or not they recognized those functions. The study
concludes with a lengthy critical reflection on History’s purposes and functions
today. The book does not seek to provide a comprehensive history of the evolu-
tion of the discipline over three thousand years. It does have to probe aspects of
that general evolution to varying depths, but only insofar as is necessary for
explaining the historical evolution of answers to the questions of what History is
for, and why History matters.
Which aspects of the mainstream are relevant? On the whole, Histories of the
discipline of History have emphasized the changes that have occurred between
epochs, and two related sets of changes have preoccupied the lion’s share of
attention. One is in the area of technique and critical discernment. The other
concerns changes culminating in what is sometimes called ‘modern historical
consciousness’, which in this context means the idea that the past is wholly past,
significantly different to the present, a foreign country with its own particular
ways of knowing, being, doing, and valuing—a foreign country towards which
the historian needs a mode of comportment different to any that she adopts
toward the present.
None of this terrain is free from interpretative conflict, and what follows in
this introduction is but a taste of the fine scholarship that has joined battle.
Some historians trace the roots of a particularly ‘modern’ critical-contextual style
of his
toric al thought to the secularization of theological exegesis, others to
3 Arnold J. Toynbee, A Study of History, abridgement of vols. VII–X ed. Robert Somervell (Oxford:
Oxford University Press 1985), 353.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
Introduction 3
4 Amos Funkenstein, Theology and the Scientific Imagination from the Middle Ages to the
Seventeenth Century (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1986), part IV and the wider range of
Funkenstein’s work discussed in Samuel Moyn, ‘Amos Funkenstein on the Theological Origins of
Historicism’, in Robert S. Westman and David Biale (eds.), Thinking Impossibilities: The Intellectual
Legacies of Amos Funkenstein (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 2008), 142–66; Allan Megill,
‘Aesthetic Theory and Historical Consciousness in the Eighteenth Century’, History and Theory
17 (1978), 29–62.
5 Zachary Sayre Schiffman, The Birth of the Past (Baltimore: John Hopkins University Press, 2011),
144 ff.. Some of this draws on Peter Burke, The Renaissance Sense of the Past (London: Arnold, 1969).
Further on classic examinations of the innovations of the Quattocentro in terms of conceptualizing
the past, see the literature invoked in Gary Ianziti, ‘Humanism’s New Science: The History of the
Future’, I Tatti Studies in the Italian Renaissance, 4 (1991), 59–88, here 59.
6 On Guiccardini, Jacques Bos, ‘Renaissance Historiography: Framing a New Mode of Historical
Experience’, in Rens Bod, Jaap Maat, and Thijs Weststeijn (eds.), The Making of the Humanities, 2 vols
(Amsterdam: Amsterdam University Press, 2010 and 2012), vol. 1, 351–65, here 362; on Bodin,
Robert A. Nisbet, History of the Idea of Progress (New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction, 2009), 119–24;
J. Samuel Preus, Explaining Religion: Criticism and Theory from Bodin to Freud (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1996); also Schiffman, Birth, 183 ff. As to sixteenth-century France, see
Donald R. Kelley, Foundations of Modern Historical Scholarship: Language, Law, and History in the
French Renaissance (New York: Columbia University Press, 1970); Claude-Gilbert Dubois, La
Conception de l’histoire en France au XVIe siècle (Paris: Nizet, 1977); Zachary Sayre Schiffman, On the
Threshold of Modernity: Relativism in the French Renaissance (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University
Press, 1991).
7 Bradley Nelson Seidel, ‘Giambattista Vico and the Emergence of Historical Consciousness’
(Marquette University: PhD thesis, 1996).
8 Frank Ankersmit, Sublime Historical Experience (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2005).
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
4 Why History?
either side of the French Revolution’s destruction of the ancien régime, and also
as a result of industrialization and technological development.9 With regard to
that nineteenth-century context, another historian has identified a ‘new’ interest
in older, written sources, as opposed to eyewitness accounts. He sees that devel-
opment as commensurate with a shift away from the time-honoured tradition of
History as contemporary History—but yet another historian sees the same shift
occurring in Italian historianship of the fifteenth century.10
Historical events loom large in many explanations for shifting conceptualiza-
tions of the relation of past to present, but events are so many and various that we
cannot look for much consensus there. The French Revolution was surely signifi-
cant, but changes in historical thought were encouraged inter alia by: the Greco-
Persian and Peloponnesian wars; the rise and fall of the western Roman empire;
the Norman conquest of large parts of Britain; the withdrawal of the Holy Roman
Empire from the Italian peninsula; what Guicciardini called le calamità d’Italia in
the late fifteenth century; the Reformation and its theological and political after-
maths; nineteenth-century nation-state-building and industrialization; the World
Wars; and decolonization. These and many more instances, often of upheaval and
antagonism, have left their mark on conceptions of the present’s relationship to
the past, and thus on conceptualizations of the point of History.11 So, too, have
cross-cultural encounters of the sort that led the seventeenth-century philoso
pher René Descartes to compare foreign journeys to ‘living in the company of
the men of other times’.12 From Herodotus to Herder via ‘Marco Polo’ and
Montesquieu, other ways of life have been revealed, expanding the conceptual-
ization of human difference across space and by extension time. The most
self-serving and exploitative such instances include the invasion of the Americas,
a.k.a the ‘new world’ as opposed to the Eurasian and southern Mediterranean
‘old’ one, but despite the attention lavished on that encounter, akin to the focus on
the impact of the French Revolution, it was just one in a series of salient events. At
the other end of the spectrum encounters have been more like awkward family
reunions, as when Latin Christendom became more extensively reacquainted
with certain ancient Greek traditions of thought and a tranche of classical histori-
anship from the late fourteenth century.
Even on the more purely technical front it is very difficult to establish which
of very many rich accounts most merits credence. The ancient Greek historian
9 Reinhart Koselleck, Futures Past: On the Semantics of Historical Time (New York: Columbia
University Press, 2004).
10 Ianziti, ‘Humanism’s New Science’, 64–5; cf. Jaap den Hollander, ‘Beyond Historicism: From
Leibniz to Luhman’, Journal of the Philosophy of History 4 (2010) 210–25, here 220–1.
11 On some of these moments, see Daniel Woolf, ‘From Hystories to the Historical’, in Paulina
Kewes (ed.), The Uses of History in Early Modern England (San Marino, CA: Huntington Library,
2006), 31–68, here 35–6.
12 René Descartes, Discourse on Method, trans. Andrew Wollaston (Harmondsworth: Penguin,
1960), 40.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
Introduction 5
Polybius wrote that each later historian ‘makes such a parade of minute accuracy,
and inveighs so bitterly when refuting others, that people come to imagine that all
other historians have been mere dreamers . . . and that he is the only man who
has made accurate investigations, and unravelled every account with intelligence’.
The British historian of the classical world J. B. Bury credited Polybius’s predeces-
sors with being the first to apply genuine criticism to historical evidence. The
nineteenth-century ‘Whig’ historian E. A. Freeman, however, found the twelfth-
century William of Malmesbury to be the first properly critical historian—the
sort of claim that has fallen out of fashion recently.13 Renaissance historian
Gary Ianziti claims a Copernican Revolution (analogies to scientific revolutions
being popular in historiographical periodization) in source criticism in the work
of fifteenth-century scholars like Lorenzo Valla and Flavio Biondo.14 Anthony
Grafton sees sixteenth-century historiographical disputes as comprising the
forgotten crucible of much of the inheritance of the later professionalized
discipline.15
Whatever the diversity of modern historiography, the most influential accounts
of how the discipline got to where it is today are anchored in a conception of a
cultural modernity that emerged in the sixteenth or seventeenth century and
found its apotheosis in the nineteenth century. Sometimes such accounts draw on
a symmetry of classical and/or patristic (early Christian) scholarship on one side
and humanist-influenced History on the other.16 Both tendencies have a great
deal going for them, but they share an absence, or at least a much diminished,
often caricatured presence: the ‘medieval’. In the first set of accounts, the medieval
world is that from which modernity has departed. In the second set the medieval is
the absent point around which the symmetry is forged.
In exemplification of the first tendency, consider Koselleck’s virtuoso accounts
of the development in the early modern period of a ‘new quality’ of ‘historical
time’. He also dubs this novelty ‘a temporalization [Verzeitlichung] of history’ as
opposed to the supposedly ‘achronological’ character of prior historical thought.17
His insights on trends of thought between roughly 1500 and 1850 are less relevant
13 Frederick J. Teggart, Theory and Processes of History (Berkeley: University of California Press,
1962), 12–14.
14 Ianziti, ‘Humanism’s New Science’, 65.
15 Anthony Grafton, What was History? The Art of History in Early Modern Europe (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2007).
16 Dimitri Levitin captures the richness of the more recent of the two symmetries, and includes
most of the relevant references: Levitin, ‘From Sacred History to the History of Religion: Paganism,
Judaism, and Christianity in European Historiography from Reformation to “Enlightenment”’, The
Historical Journal 55:4 (2012), 1117–60. Burke, The Renaissance Sense of the Past, creates a symmetry
between Roman and Renaissance historiography. Anthony Grafton and Megan Williams, Christianity
and the Transformation of the Book: Origen, Eusebius, and the Library of Caesarea (Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press, 2006), Coda, considers relations between Renaissance palaeography and
Hebraism and patristic scholarship. The title of Arnaldo Momigliano’s Classical Foundations of
Modern Historiography (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1990), is self-explanatory.
17 Koselleck, Futures Past, 10, 11.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
6 Why History?
here than his characterization of what went before, notably his conception of the
relationship between ‘the’ medieval sense of time and theologically influenced
Christian philosophies of the historical process. Now Koselleck is writing on a
grand scale, so large generalizations are inevitable, but his generalization tends
towards caricature. Thus what is first described in one of his essays as ‘the history
of Christianity’ becomes two pages later the History of ‘the Church’, as if these
were co-extensive.18 Even the former usage is ambivalent between the history of
Christianity understood as ways of conceiving the historical process within
Christian civilization or as an account of that civilization itself. One suspects the
latter: we learn that Guicciardini’s insights stem from his being ‘in Italy, the land
where modern politics originated’, as if the practice of modern politics were
coterminous with the sort of political theory that Machiavelli and others have
some claim to have founded. For our nascent moderns, ‘Weighing the probability
of forthcoming or nonoccurring events in the first instance eliminated a concep-
tion of the future taken for granted by religious factions: the certainty that the
Last Judgment would enforce a simple alternative between Good and Evil through
the establishment of a single principle of behavior’. From this we can only infer
that prior to Koselleck’s chosen point in time, political leaders did not think about
issues of probability in deciding on their action, that they could not distinguish
between long-term prognoses and immediate situations, and so forth. Koselleck
tells us that ‘Prognosis produces the time within which and out of which it weaves,
whereas apocalyptic prophecy destroys time through its fixation on the End.
From the point of view of prophecy, events are merely symbols of that which is
already known.’19 Only post-medievals are apparently aware of the importance of
‘foresight’, as if, say, the thirteenth-century Dominican friar Thomas Aquinas had
not thought long and hard on ‘prudence’, or that one should be prepared for ‘sur-
prise’, with its implications of contingency planning.20 There is a sense of a fine
mind getting carried away by the logic of its own arguments when Koselleck sug-
gests that various calculations of Frederick the Great around the First Partition of
Introduction 7
Poland were ‘clearly possible only in a particular historical situation’. Unless that
statement is pure tautology, in which Frederick’s actions are to be defined in terms
of the precise situation against which he was reacting, it is a negative generaliza-
tion which is not tested against any actions from the vast tracts of time outside of
that ‘situation’. Only one counter-case would be needed to falsify it, but counter-
cases from outside the time in question are absent. Even when Koselleck rather
erases some of the distinctions that he has himself forcibly made—‘the distance
separating the early modern political consciousness of time from that of Christian
eschatology was nowhere near as great as it might seem’—the reductive associ
ation of medieval political consciousness with ‘Christian eschatology’ remains.21
Koselleck has no monopoly on such characterizations.22 Even those like the
medievalist Bernard Gunée who have protested in ‘defence’ of the medieval, and
the historian of the Renaissance Peter Burke who has somewhat revised his influ-
ential views in light of such accounts, have ended up saying something to the
effect that the medievals had their own historical sense—one that was historical
in some meaningful fashion, but nonetheless different to Renaissance or high
modern senses. This represents a conceptual advance, and after all one does not
want to pretend that nothing changed across time, because a great deal did. But
we still end up with a sort of relativism that maintains the hard periodizations
already established and with them a misleading concept of different historical
‘epochs’ each with corresponding, discrete outlooks on the past.23
21 Koselleck, Futures Past, 20, 21. See also Koselleck, The Practice of Conceptual History: Timing
History, Spacing Concepts (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2002), 111–12, and Koselleck
‘Begriffsgeschichtliche Anmerkungen zur “Zeitgeschichte”’, in Victor Conzemius, Martin Greschat,
and Hermann Kocher (eds.), Die Zeit nach 1945 als Thema kirchlicher Zeitgeschichte (Göttingen:
Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 1988), 17–31.
22 Hanan Yoran, ‘Florentine Civic Humanism and the Emergence of Modern Ideology’, History and
Theory 46 (October 2007), 326–44, also deploys the generic ‘medieval’ to perform the work of con-
trast, even as he ultimately recognizes the significance of a distinctly medieval trend—nominalist
philosophy—in preparing the ground for what he sees as humanism’s break with this medieval. Nor
do I have any monopoly on contesting such characterizations. See for instance Judith Pollmann,
Memory in Early Modern Europe, 1500–1800 (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2017), who on pp. 9–10
takes issue with Koselleck and others whose position is relevantly similar to his. My own analysis and
accompanying corrective goes further back than Pollmann’s.
23 And this despite the evidence unearthed by the likes of Gunée that shows commonalities as well
as differences across time: Bernard Gunée, ‘Y a-t-il une historiographie médiévale?’, Revue Historique
258 (1977), 261–75. For Burke’s latter-day position which concurs with medievalist R. W. Southern
that medievals had a sense of the past, one which was then replaced by a different such sense, see his
‘The Sense of Anachronism from Petrarch to Poussin’, in Chris Humphrey and W. M. Ormrod (eds.),
Time in the Medieval World (Woodbridge: York Medieval Press, 2001), 157–73, here 162. (Southern’s
piece is ‘Sense of the Past’.) Compare this to Burke’s 1969 pronouncement (Renaissance Sense, 1) that
‘during the whole millennium 400–1400, there was no “sense of history” even among the educated’.
On the evolution of Burke’s thought, see Margreta de Grazia, ‘Anachronism’, in Brian Cummings and
James Simpson (eds.), Cultural Reformations: Medieval and Renaissance in Literary History (Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 2010), 13–32, here 27.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
8 Why History?
Now the table of contents may suggest that at certain points this book has
replicated a version of the epochal schema just criticized, but examination of the
text itself will show merely that some familiar placeholders have been deployed
in order to break down the account into digestible chunks. While a broadly
chronological development underpins the volume’s structure, cleaving to calen-
drical markers too rigorously would seriously blunt the argument. One reasons
that is so is that some issues simply do retain their relevance for long periods;
such themes are elaborated in the second part of this introduction. Another rea-
son is that the moment of the translation and reception of certain ideas in certain
places is often separated from the moment of their production in other places.
There is a great deal of ‘cross-hatching’ between the ‘horizontal’ chronological
arrangement of the chapters and the ‘vertical’ themes.
Amongst other things, this book attempts a new way to relate ‘the medieval’ to
what went before and after. The purpose of the operation follows both of Fustel’s
lines. ‘Medieval’ and other instances of historical scholarship are placed in what-
ever are held to be the salient contexts of their writing at different junctures, in
the attempt to ‘do justice to them’ by their own standards and according to their
own purposes. But the aim is also to try to blur the distinctions between ‘ancient’,
‘medieval’, and ‘modern’ by illustrating powerful continuities as well as changes in
historical thinking. This is an especially important task in relationship to the
medieval and the modern because these two ‘epochs’ still stand as interdefined
‘others’, mutually constituted opposites.
One way of deconstructing the medieval–modern opposition is to trace the
presence of some allegedly modern thought in the heart of the medieval ‘other’,
whether that thought originated in the Middle Ages or was merely sustained or
enhanced therein. Another way is to press the narrative of change forward well
beyond whenever the medieval period is held to have ended. The coming con-
templation of the development of ‘modern’ historical thought moves beyond even
the concluding points that most detect in the eighteenth and especially nineteenth
century and stretches the issue right up to, and through, the present. Looking
backwards, alongside significant departures, some enduring conceptions may be
traced back to the beginning of the western historiographical tradition. Along the
way from that beginning to the present, newer justifications for History have only
overlain their predecessors without always superseding them. We would do well
to appreciate this when we talk about ‘modern historical consciousness’. It will
help us to understand the ongoing tensions elaborated in the final chapter in the
way ‘we’ orient ourselves towards the past today.
The matter is more than a purely scholarly debate. It is not only scholars who
are interested in the past, and History, as in the pursuit of reflection on the past,
has a correspondingly significant social role to play. In social affairs evidence
from the past is an important element in guessing at the social future, and atti-
tudes to the past much of what we have in prescribing for the future.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
Introduction 9
Judging by the historical scholarship that has survived, ancient Greek historians
had at least eight justifications for History at their disposal. Most if not all of those
were available from the very outset of Greek prose History in the ‘Classical
Period’, the fifth and fourth centuries bce.24 The justifications appear here in no
order of priority.
One was recreational, with an emphasis on evoking the romance and drama of
the past through the performative tradition. This will be referred to as ‘History as
Entertainment’. As a justification it is partly substantivist, meaning that entertain-
ment depends on the content of the past described, and partly formalist, in the
sense that a tale requires authorial skill in organization or ‘emplotment’. A vital
element is enargeia, in Latin evidentia. Whatever connotations ‘evidence’ has now,
enargeia referred then to vividness of depiction, the capacity to evoke audience
feelings appropriate to the event under representation. If this History is not
already being performed theatrically then the objective for the writer is to try to
render readers or listeners into spectators. Enargeia ‘is in the verbal realm the
counterpart of verisimilitude in the visual arts’.25
A second justification appears in Herodotus’s opening lines and again blends
substantivism and formalism. His aim was ‘preserving from decay the remem-
brance of what men have done, and of preventing the great and wonderful actions
of the Greeks and the Barbarians from losing their due meed of glory; and withal
to put on record what were their grounds of feud’. This justification is dubbed
‘History as Memorialization’.
A third justification lies in much of Herodotus’s subject matter and is more
wholly substantivist. He is a founder member of an enduring tradition of study-
ing other cultures in such a way that, as the poet G. K. Chesterton put it, one may
finally ‘set foot on one’s own country as a foreign land’.26 The project may be fur-
thered by travel back in time as well as across place. The label for this justification
is ‘History as Travel’.
A fourth justification is equally substantivist. It is present in Polybius
(c.200–c.118 bce), who wrote in what is today called the Hellenistic period, which
succeeded the Classical period, but it is there in Herodotus too. It involves tracing
24 François Bédarida, ‘The Modern Historian’s Dilemma: Conflicting Pressures from Science and
Society’, Economic History Review, 2nd ser. XL:3 (1987), 335–48, here 340, mentions three. I take those
and add some more.
25 Andrew D. Walker, ‘Enargeia and the Spectator in Greek Historiography’, Transactions of the
American Philological Association 123 (1993), 353–77, here 358; Stefania Tutino, Shadows of Doubt:
Language and Truth in Post-Reformation Catholic Culture (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014)
67–8. On theatricality, Gregory Nagy, Poetry as Performance: Homer and Beyond (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1996).
26 G. K. Chesterton, ‘The Riddle of the Ivy’, Tremendous Trifles (London: Methuen, 1909), 203–10,
here 204.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
Introduction 11
Dionysius wrote of the historian’s ‘obligation in the first place to choose a good
subject of lofty character which will be truly profitable to the reader, and in the
second place to devote the utmost care and industry to the task of providing
himself with proper sources for his own composition’.30 Memorial and didactic
functions were often one and the same. Herodian of Antioch, writing in the first
half of the third century ce, was surely not the first to fuse them with the further
concern for ‘scrupulous exactitude’ and also the hope that his History, the History
of the Roman Empire after the Death of Marcus Aurelius, was ‘not without enter-
tainment for future generations’.31 With significant continuity in the fortunes of
History as Entertainment and History as Travel, much of the relevant recent his-
tory of History concerns the mutation of the remits of History as Lesson.
The decline of History as Lesson—the discarding of the Roman rhetorician
Cicero’s belief that History was magistra vitae, the teacher of life32—is often taken
to be one index of History’s modernization. Decline there was but it was by no
means total and in key instances what looks like decline can just as well be inter-
preted as revision according to intellectual circumstance. It is a matter of perspec-
tive whether the emphasis is on the changes or the unifying underlying conviction
that the substance of the past has something to teach us. In any case, such is the
prominence of substantivist rationales across large tracts of time that their evolu-
tion is one of the key thematic sinews connecting successive chapters in the book.
A whistle-stop tour might help in the orientation.
Let us say that at some point it became embarrassing in intellectual circles to
admit to consulting History books for advice on comportment. The reason may
have been an appreciation of the difference of historical circumstances and/or
cultures and/or the development of philosophies of politics and of the individual
that sought a conscious break with the past. Some of the logic of didactic exem-
plarity could nonetheless be salvaged by an idea devised in classical antiquity. In
the concept of similitudo temporum certain civilizations, epochs, and moments
shared characteristics and dilemmas with earlier counterparts. Everything did
not need to be the same, as long as some things were. Appropriately enough for
an idea about periodic resurfacing, the idea resurfaced periodically, with especial
vigour in the turmoil after the Reformation, but also well into modernity—it is
still with us today in dilution.33
So much, then, for positive relevance, in the sense of resonances of the present
in the past and vice versa. Negative relevance, or relevance by contrast, could be
just as useful if we consider some of the ways in which eighteenth-century
30 Dionysius, The Ancient History of Rome, Book I, ch. 1, repr. in Arnold J. Toynbee, Greek Historical
Thought (New York: Mentor Books, 1952), 53.
31 Book I, ch. 1, repr. in Toynbee, Greek Historical Though, 77.
32 Marcus Tullius Cicero, De Oratore, II.ix.36, in Cicero: On the Orator, Books 1–2, trans.
E. W. Sutton and H. Rackham (London: Heinemann, 1967), 224.
33 A. Dwight Culler, The Victorian Mirror of History (New Haven: Yale University Press, 2009).
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
Introduction 13
Since this book does not just consider change over time but also the coexistence
of differing conceptions of History’s utility, and what happens when one such
conception periodically brings its arsenal of supporting assumptions to bear on
another, one further ‘Greek’ rationale needs to be thrown into the mix. It is a con-
ception at least as old as any of the candidates, and as enduring as any—indeed
one can identify it in Herodotus despite his broad sympathies. It is History as
Identity, the great chameleon. History as Identity is substantivist, concerned with
the content of the past. It is primarily genealogical, in the sense of establishing
causal relations and relations of identity between past and present, but as noted
(p. 2) it can be enacted in different spirits. The more open-minded and potentially
self-critical version involves understanding where the present has come from, in
the knowledge that identity is historically conditioned. The alternative is more
narcissistic and self-justificatory, involving the vindication of present identities
and projects by retrospective legitimation—this brand can often avail itself of the
Memorial tendency. Along with Entertainment Histories, Identity Histories of
differing sorts are the ones that fill bookshops. They are the most consumed
Histories in our societies and tell us a great deal about the nature of general inter-
est in the past irrespective of the rationales academic historians come up with for
their activities.
If in terms of Geschichtsinteressen—reasons for concerning oneself with the
past—there is at least as much variation within any given period as across periods,
is it too much to suggest that the same applies to ‘historical consciousness’?
Consider some examples from the study of geology. In the late eighteenth and
early nineteenth centuries, which as it happens was a key period in the institu-
tionalization of the discipline of History, geologists and other scientists estab-
lished a substantial professional consensus about the great age of the earth, and its
vast pre-human history, on the basis of evidence such as dinosaur fossils and sedi-
mentary rocks. All this helped pave the wave for the reception of Darwin’s theory
of evolution, which, with the rise of geology and ‘geo-history’, marked a grand
historical turn in the natural sciences just as parts of the occident at least were
entering an especially historically obsessed period in terms of concepts of the
nation.34 Decades later, in 1872, the archaeologist George Smith rediscovered
what came to be known as the Epic of Gilgamesh, a Babylonian story of ‘Noah’s’
flood—written at least a millennium before the book of Genesis. A public stir
ensued, leading a latter-day historian of the controversy to ask himself why that
should have been so if ‘the idea of deep time was more or less settled for “western”
savants’? Most obviously, he concluded, because ‘savants are not an entire culture’.
Had the Victorians as a whole ‘internalised ideas about deep time (the 4.55 billion
34 Martin J. S. Rudwick, Worlds before Adam: The Reconstruction of Geohistory in the Age of Reform
(Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2008), with ‘geohistory’ at 389.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
years of history in which we now believe)’, then the rediscovery ‘would have been
of interest principally to antiquarian specialists rather than the newspaper- and
periodical-reading masses’. As it stood, the diverse group of people that we call
Victorians grappled protractedly over the shift from a shortish anthropocentric
history, Garden of Eden and all, to a far more removed, impersonal origin tale of
seas and sludge.35 As for ‘modern historical consciousness’ in the study of human
affairs, remember Fustel. When preparing his work on classical antiquity The
Ancient City (1864), he encountered many who talked of the Greeks and Romans
as if they were ‘talking of the French or the English of their own time. They nearly
always imagined these people as living in the same social conditions as we do and
as thinking like us on nearly all issues.’36 And this only a few generations after the
grand historical rupture of the French revolution. Still today, politicians and cab
drivers are prone to invoke the Lessons of History even when academics can see
nothing but contextual variance.
The media of History vary as much as do historical interests and inferences.
For all the attention justifiably devoted to the historiographical significance of
Herodotus and Thucydides, these historians were but one of many tributary influ-
ences on historical thought in their time. Painted vases, relief sculpture, and epic
poetry were as important then in creating an image of the past as historical novels
and films and museums are today; legal and political ritual, ceremonies, drama,
and civic space and architecture endure across the temporal divide. While matters
of manageability and space prohibit examination of novels, films, museums, and
other fora of popular historical engagement explored by the likes of Raphael
Samuel and David Lowenthal, the final chapter nonetheless tries to grapple with
some of the issues arising in the present at the interface of professional and popu-
lar reckoning with the past.37
Manageability still remains a problem since this is a historiographical enquiry
in a broad sense, with a correspondingly eclectic base of primary and secondary
sources. At many of the moments under consideration those people who are most
identifiable as historians by today’s lights were not the key influences on historical
thought. Theologians, philosophers, jurists, political theorists, and social scien-
tists often loom as large in this book even when the study of the past was not their
35 Vybarr Cregan-Reid, Discovering Gilgamesh: Geology, Narrative, and the Historical Sublime in
Victorian Culture (Manchester: Manchester University Press, 2013), 4.
36 Fustel’s inaugural lecture, 1862, repr. in Fritz Stern (ed.), The Varieties of History (New York:
Meridian, 1956), 179–88, here 184.
37 On some ancient Greek historical media, Lloyd Llewellyn-Jones, ‘The Great Kings of the Fourth
Century and the Greek Memory of the Persian Past’, in John Marincola, Lloyd Llewellyn-Jones, and
Calum Alasdair Maciver (eds.), Greek Notions of the Past in the Archaic and Classical Eras: History
without Historians (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2012), 317–46. On non-academic sources
of History in the present, Raphael Samuel, Theatres of Memory (London: Verso, 1994), David
Lowenthal, The Past is a Foreign Country (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985), and
Lowenthal, The Heritage Crusade and the Spoils of History (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1998).
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
Introduction 15
38 John Burrow, A History of Histories (London: Allen Lane, 2007); Ernst Breisach, Historiography:
Ancient, Medieval and Modern (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2007); Donald R. Kelley, Faces
of History: Historical Inquiry from Herodotus to Herder (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1998);
Jeremy D. Popkin, From Herodotus to H-Net: The Story of Historiography (Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 2015). As compared to these works, mine has more of the broad conceptualization of historiog-
raphy manifest in Aviezer Tucker (ed.), A Companion to the Philosophy of History and Historiography
(London: Wiley, 2009); Michael Bentley (ed.), Companion to Historiography (Abingdon: Routledge,
2007); and the five-volume The Oxford History of Historical Writing (Oxford: Oxford University Press,
2011–12) under the general editorship of Daniel Woolf.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
1
Classical History between Epic
and Rhetoric
Introduction
1 Richard Whitaker, ‘History, Myth, and Social Function in Southern African Nguni Praise Poetry’,
in David Konstan and Kurt A. Raaflaub (eds.), Epic and History (Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell, 2010),
381–91, here 386, 389.
2 David Morgan, ‘The Evolution of Two Asian Historiographical Traditions’, in Bentley (ed.),
Companion, 11–22, here 17–20.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
3 Kyong-Jin Lee, The Authority and Authorization of Torah in the Persian Period (Leuven: Peeters,
2011); Paula Gooder, The Pentateuch: A Story of Beginnings (London: T&T Clark, 2000), 30 ff.; 41ff.;
Jean Louis Ska, Introduction to Reading the Pentateuch (Winona Lake, IN: Eisenbrauns, 2006) 225–8.
On Babylonian influence see also the next note.
4 Interesting comparisons and contrasts between different epic and epic-historical traditions are
explored in Konstan and Raaflaub (eds.), Epic and History. Generally in this area, see John Marincola,
‘Introduction’, to Marincola et al. (eds.), History without Historians, 1–13. Further on Herodotus’s
antecedents and milieu, Nino Luraghi (ed.), The Historian’s Craft in the Age of Herodotus (Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 2001).
5 Hannah Arendt, The Life of the Mind (New York: Harcourt, 1978), 216; G. J. Basile, ‘Τhe Homeric
ἵστωρ and oath-taking’, Cuadernos de Filología Clásica. Estudios griegos e indoeuropeos 28 (2018),
17–39, with quote at 25.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
reinforces a norm. In the absence of his father, Odysseus’ son Telemachus grows
from boy to man, and part of the process of self-assertion is public rebuke of his
mother Penelope. ‘Speech’, he says, meaning authoritative public utterance, ‘will
be the business of men’.6 Even in this epic, which gives not insignificant attention
to women, their speech can only be in the private sphere, which is at once to deni-
grate it and to ensure it will not be recorded. (As the Athenian statesman and
general Pericles pronounces in one of Thucydides’ best-known passages, ideal
was the woman who was not discussed between men in any terms, glowing or
derogatory.) Fifthly, while for a long time many Greeks seem to have assumed
that the period of heroes and gods portrayed by the poets was real and provided
clues to ‘the way the world works’,7 we may detect a different though not necessarily
contradictory tendency in Homer. With the end of the heroic age, which is when
the heroes ultimately return after the Trojan wars, the gods no longer intervene
directly in earthly affairs and mortals are no longer so large or strong. This sense
of qualitative difference across time may prefigure the ‘historical consciousness’,
as we seem bound to call it, that is present in subsequent Greek historiography—
and present in the historiography of all subsequent periods too, if with differing
emphases.8
This opening chapter establishes the foundations on which the rest of the book
is built since post-classical western scholarship largely develops from classical
models or is shaped by its reaction against those models. The chapter addresses a
series of conceptual issues that have recurring relevance, including: differing con-
ceptions of the nature of historical truth; the relationship between History and
ethnography; the relationship between rhetoric and historianship; the relation-
ship between philosophy, poetry, and History; and the relationship between ‘use-
ful’ and ‘pleasurable’ Histories. In a more empirical vein the chapter discusses the
relationship between Greek and Roman historianship and accounts for different
tendencies in the development of historiography in each culture—tendencies like
a greater or lesser interest in the outside world, and a greater or lesser interest in
individuals as opposed to power structures or the study of society and culture.
The question of the consciousness of qualitative historical change is also discussed
in the case of a number of historians. In the 900 or so years of historianship
covered in this chapter no rationale for History that is present at or near the out-
set was ruled out by the end, though of course many avenues of possibility were
more fully explored. It is more than coincidence that the survey opens and closes
6 On this and many later echoes in the occidental tradition, Mary Beard, ‘The Public Voice of
Women’, London Review of Books, 20 March 2014, 11–14.
7 Emily Baragwanath, ‘The Mythic Plupast in Herodotus’, in Jonas Grethlein and
Christopher B. Krebs (eds.), Time and Narrative in Ancient Historiography (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2012), 35–56, here 35; Charles Edward Muntz, Diodorus Siculus and the World of the
Late Roman Republic (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2017), 91.
8 A proponent of the view is Strasburger, cited in Fleming A. J. Nielsen, The Tragedy in History:
Herodotus and the Deuteronomistic History (Sheffield: Sheffield Academic Press, 1997), 33.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
with species of History as Identity, beginning with the most elementary type of
that genre: genealogy.
9 Charles William Fornara, The Nature of History in Ancient Greece and Rome (Berkeley:
University of California Press, 1983), 4–12; Peter Hunt, ‘Hecataeus of Miletos’, The Encyclopedia
of Ancient History (Wiley online library, 2012): https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/abs/10.1002/
9781444338386.wbeah08075
10 On these historians, see Charlotte Schubert, ‘Formen der griechischen Historiographie: Die
Atthidographen als Historiker Athens’, Hermes 138:3 (2010), 259–75; Felix Jacoby, Atthis: The Local
Chronicles of Ancient Athens (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1949).
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
priestesses of Hera, and assigned noteworthy events to the nth year of the relevant
priestess. The point of these exercises was to connect events and people and con-
struct meaningful temporal frameworks around these connections, rather than
inserting events into an already given frame.11
Herodotus adopted Hecataeus’s distinction between the spatium mythicum
and the spatium historicum, though he went far beyond the work of genealogies
to study events in a way that is much more fully characteristic of subsequent
History.12 Naturally, events further in the past were apt to be more likely to fall
into the spatium mythicum, but again clarification is needed. Herodotus did not
think the spatium mythicum to be filled with what today we call myths, but rather
that the recountability of genuine History in that ‘space’ had been compromised
by the mythoi of poets who blended historical truth and fiction.13 The existence
of the distinction does not mean Herodotus was always correct in his claims
for what was verifiable, or that his sense of historical likelihood was like those
of twenty-first-century historians. With Hecataeus and Hellanicus, Herodotus
believed that the spatium historicum went back to the time of the supposed recon-
quest of the Peloponnese by the Heracleidae (descendants of Heracles), after the
Trojan War. He further believed that the Trojan War, dated to some time in what
we would now call the twelfth or thirteenth century bce, occurred in roughly the
manner assumed in Greek collective memory, as opposed to there simply having
been some sort of war at some point at a place dubbed Troy.14
In his view of what could be treated historically Herodotus was not arbitrary,
even if we might sometimes think him incorrect. When investigating the deeper
past he engaged with the engraved and written records of Egypt and the collective
memory of its priesthood, which he saw as more historically reliable than the
Greek epics.15 It was precisely his enquiries among non-Greek sources that
corroborated, to his satisfaction, parts of what were otherwise suspect Greek
accounts of the Trojan War. Equally, those enquiries influenced his circumspec-
tion about what could be claimed about the causes of the war.16 Further to the
11 Kai Brodersen, ‘Hellanicus of Mytilene’ and Denis Feeney, ‘Chronography’, both in The
Encyclopedia of Ancient History (Wiley online library 2012): https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/abs/
10.1002/9781444338386.wbeah08076 https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1002/9781444338386.
wbeah08035
12 Muntz, Diodorus, 90–3.
13 Virginia J. Hunter, Past and Process in Herodotus and Thucydides (Princeton: Princeton
University Press, 1982), 87.
14 Ibid. 90; Nielsen, The Tragedy, 33–5; Fornara, The Nature, 9.
15 In general terms official record-keeping, which was the function of ‘the archive’, and an
important source of documented state memory, was better established in other, older Mediterranean
societies, be they Hittite, Babylonian, Sumerian, or Egyptian.
16 Suzanne Saïd, ‘Herodotus and the “Myth” of the Trojan War” ’, in Emily Baragwanath and
Mathieu de Bakker (eds.), Myth, Truth and Narrative in Herodotus (Oxford: Oxford University Press,
2012), 87–106, here 88–92. Also on Egyptian sources, see Hunter, Past and Process, 74. Note that while
Herodotus lost faith in a Greek time of the gods, he still believed in a time of the gods, just a much
earlier one, corresponding to Egyptian chronologies.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
17 T. James Luce, The Greek Historians (London: Routledge, 1997), ch. 3.
18 On which see the defence by Hunter, Past and Process, 91–2.
19 Carole Atack, ‘The Discourse of Kingship in Classical Athenian Thought’, Histos 8 (2014),
329–62, here 332.
20 On Herodotus’s blend, Baragwanath, ‘The Mythic Plupast’; on Hecataeus’s various contributions,
see Fornara, The Nature, 4–14. On the different strands of historical writing, Felix Jacoby, ‘Über die
Entwicklung der griechischen Historiographie und den Plan einer neuen Sammlung der griechischen
Historikerfragmente’, Klio, 9:9 (1909), 80–123.
21 Quotes and material from Baragwanath, ‘The Mythic Plupast’, 36. On alleged timelessness in
Herodotus, Johannes Fabian, Time and the Other: How Anthropology Makes its Object (New York:
Columbia University Press, 2014), 80, 196 n. 10.
22 J. A. S. Evans, ‘Father of History or Father of Lies: The Reputation of Herodotus’, The Classical
Journal, 64:1 (1968), 11–17; James Redfield, ‘Herodotus the Tourist’, Classical Philology, 80:2 (1985),
97–118. On the antiquity of the praise as well as the allegations, Momigliano, Classical Foundations,
39–40.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
23 On relativist-sounding pronouncements: Herodotus, Histories, Book 3.38, cf. Book 7.152. See
also the discussion of Egyptian customs in Book 2. On Persia, see Paul Cartledge, ‘Historiography and
Ancient Greek Self-Definition’, in Bentley (ed.), Companion to Historiography, 23–42, here 29. On
Herodotus as cultural pluralist, Thucydides as a monist, Lauren J. Apfel, The Advent of Pluralism:
Diversity and Conflict in the Age of Sophocles (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011), Part Two.
24 Jonas Grethlein, The Greeks and their Past: Poetry, Oratory and History in the Fifth Century bce
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010), 204—and 135 on the deployment by Herodotus and
Thucydides of techniques used in the epics.
25 On dialect, Warren Treadgold, The Early Byzantine Historians (Basingstoke: Macmillan, 2010), 8.
26 Arnaldo D. Momigliano, ‘The Historians of the Classical World and their Audiences’, Annali
della Scuola Normale Superiore di Pisa, 3rd series, 8 (1978), 59–75.
27 On Herodotus’s influence, Christopher A. Baron, Timaeus of Tauromenium and Hellenistic
Historiography (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2013), ch. 10; for the specific phrases, 237.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
28 Thucydides, The Peloponnesian War: The Crawley Translation (New York: Random House, 1982),
Book I, 21–2.
29 Ibid. 9–19. See also Rosario Munson, cited in Muntz, Diodorus, 92.
30 Thucydides, The Peloponnesian War, I.5–6.
31 The analytical philosopher of History Frederick Teggart long pre-empted Fabian’s exposition of
the point that for many Europeans, looking across to things like the transatlantic ‘new world’, different
cultures were understood as primitive versions of the European. Teggart, Theory, 93–5; cf. Fabian,
Time and the Other.
32 On the Romans, Burke, The Renaissance Sense, 139–41.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
What we may say is that one of the many ways in which Thucydides’ work
iffered from Homer’s, as from Hesiod’s myth of the ages in Works and Days, is
d
that in the epics the distinction between past and present is more greatly empha-
sized in virtue of the superiority of the denizens of the past, whether or not the
heroes were actually depicted as godly.33 Whether we understand this particular
difference between History and mythic poetry as large enough to be a matter of
nature as opposed to mere degree depends on one’s yardstick of measurement. An
argument for categorical difference is that while the poets and the historians all
deployed exempla for didactic purposes, the epic established the exalted, indeed
ideal(ized) standards set by its heroes, while History of the Thucydidean variety
sought to endure through its relationship to its readers, who would be bound
to each other across time by recognizing the constancy of key facets of their
own nature.34
An argument that epic and History differ in degree only comes from the
classicist Christopher Pelling. He writes that if the past of the poets provides ‘a
matrix for thought experiment’, it does so ‘because it allows moral issues to be
addressed with a smaller encumbrance of circumstantial detail than they carry in
real life, then encourages the reapplication of that thinking to make sense of the
more confusing everyday world’. In this sense, epic poetry is more like philosoph-
ical abstraction than the thick description one is apt to encounter in the novel, or
again historiography, which ‘does engage with that mass of real-life circumstance’.
Yet Pelling also writes that ‘The historians themselves are also extrapolating and
suggesting recurrent patterns to make sense of what-Alcibiades-did-and-suffered,
and helping readers to disentangle the telling facts from the purely contingent
to see how this might be a case study for broader truths about, say, Athens or
democracy or individualism or rhetorical flair’. Each sort of author does ‘part of
the thought-experimental work; in some genres and authors they do more and in
some they do less. But the rest is up to the audiences, both the immediate and the
long-term, both them and us.’35 At the junction of Homer with Thucydides, just
as in epic-like izibongo, evaluation of the ‘real’ or imagined past is judgemental
because it sees itself at some level as being commentary of general relevance.36
33 Cf. Jonas Grethlein, who substantiates a sense of the difference of the past in Greek epics as
opposed to its depiction in historical literature, but sees this difference as a somewhat different sort of
difference to that discerned between present and past-as-foreign-country in modern historiography.
See his and Christopher B. Krebs’s ‘The Historian’s Plupast: Introductory Remarks on its Forms and
Functions’, in Grethlein and Krebs (eds.), Time and Narrative in Ancient Historiography: The ‘Plupast’
from Herodotus to Appia. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 2012) 1–16.
34 Jonas Grethlein, ‘“Historia magistra vitae” in Herodotus and Thucydides? The Exemplary Use of
the Past and Ancient and Modern temporalities’, in Alexandra Lianeri (ed.), The Western Time of
Ancient History (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2011), 247–63; Grethlein, ‘Homer and
Heroic History’, in Marincola et al. (eds.), History without Historians, 14–36, here 33.
35 Christopher Pelling, ‘Commentary’, in Marincola et al. (eds.), History without Historians, 347–65,
here 365.
36 Observations I owe to Whitaker, ‘History, Myth, and Social Function’, 386.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
Talk of general relevance brings us to the funeral oration by the statesman and
soldier Pericles in Book II of Thucydides’ History. The speech was a compelling
piece of advocacy for the values of the Athenian demos, though like Pericles him-
self Thucydides was more oligarch than democrat. In this set-piece, Thucydides
departed from strict reliance on ‘proofs’ and instead took licence to imagine
the sort of thing that would have been said on such occasions, just as would
distant successors such as the medieval Geoffrey of Monmouth. These moments
of rhetorical flourish are not merely incidental, but are rather crucial for an
understanding of the narrative structure of Thucydides’ work. Specific examples
like the speech highlighted the exemplary nature of the entire text. At the
same time, undue focus on them can distract from the rest of Thucydides’
prose where plain-speaking could produce its own seductions. The scholarly
consensus has now moved more towards viewing Thucydides as an ‘artful
reporter’.37
What exactly is meant by describing someone as an artful reporter varies with
what one expects of them in the first place; how one understands what they were
trying to do, and how one understands contemporary audience expectations of
works of that sort. This is immensely complex terrain given that we are dealing
with the inception or very early development of a genre that existed in relations
with more established literary forms and overlapped with them often to a consid-
erable degree. Further, from fifth-century Greece through late antiquity, rhetoric
was considered one of the highest arts and no historian could ignore that even if
they desired to. They knew their audiences had literary expectations and wanted
their works to be embraced as literature as well as History, which helps explain
intertextual allusions as well as elegant digs at other historians. They pursued
celebrity just as much as the actors whose deeds they recounted—indeed
Thucydides and many of his successors had themselves been men of action (sol-
diers) earlier in life. The second-century ce Anabasis of Alexander by Arrian of
Nicomedia recounts a story of Alexander the Great laying a wreath at the sup-
posed tomb of his hero Achilles and noting Achilles’ good fortune in having a
poet—Homer—to celebrate his deeds and sustain his memory.38 Happy for the
historian that he was needed just as much as the hero! But he must be up to the
task, and better qualified than potential competitors, as a researcher, perhaps, but
also as a herald. Quite what doing justice to the achievements of an Alexander
might mean is a good question, since recording them was apt to be inseparable
37 Virginia Hunter, Thucydides the Artful Reporter (Toronto: Hakkert, 1973), and for an earlier
emphasis on Thucydides’ artistic side Francis MacDonald Cornford, Thucydides Mythistoricus
(London: Edward Arnold, 1907).
38 Arrian of Nicomedia, The Anabasis of Alexander, 1.12.1, at p. 53 of Arrian vol. 1, trans. E. Iliff
Robson (London: William Heinemann, 1967).
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
from burnishing them in a way tailored to contemporary tastes and poetic con-
vention. Given appropriate substitutions, the same went for describing villains,
anti-heroes, and catastrophes. Let us try to take the bull by the horns and explore
the question of historians and truth in the light of rhetorical, literary, and other
concerns. That question has conventionally been at the forefront of comparisons
and contrasts between ancient and modern historiography.
It is a blunder to conceive rhetoric as necessarily opposed to truth and to see
it as illegitimate persuasion rather than effective communication. Of course
rhetoric can be opposed to truth: the Roman master of rhetoric, Cicero, had to
stipulate that while rhetoricians could stray from the path of truth when needed,
historians ought never to do so. More important for present purposes is establish-
ing the varieties of rhetoric’s more ‘positive’ relationships to the truth. Some his
torians deployed the technique of ecphrasis, which combines their immediate,
situated perspective as eyewitnesses to events, and their broader perspective as
historians who have colligated other viewpoints and after-the-fact knowledge.
Thus a historian might ‘recall’ things that he could not have been in a position to
see at the moment he purports to have seen them—such as fine details of an army
that was scores of miles distant—but this does not mean that such details were
made up.39 We can adapt the seventeenth-century historical theorist Agostino
Mascardi’s terms of the true verisimilar and the false verisimilar, with the former
denoting what the apostles of Christ were up to, and the latter denoting some-
thing purely fictitious, which may include but is not limited to deceit.40 As
Mascardi himself saw, it is not easy even for the historian who wishes to portray
things precisely as they were to avoid verisimilitude, but that would not have been
a surprise or a problem for very many centuries’ worth of historians. In Cicero’s
Latin (to which it is not illegitimate to refer at this stage given the debt of Roman
rhetoricians to Greece), the skills of elocutio (style), dispositio (organization),
combine with inventio, which Cicero considered the most important of the rhet
orical arts, and is embedded in ingenium, which pertains to creativity and origin
ality. Inventio means the ‘discovery’ of what ‘needs’ to be said, and is not to be
confused with the arbitrariness or bad faith of modern ‘invention’. Quintilian’s
Institutio Oratoria averred that it was never a question of truth itself, which was
absolute, but of ‘invented’ judgements as to the nature of the truth. Iudicium is the
faculty of judgement that most directly pertains to truth. Enargeia along with
concilium (prudence), kairos (the capacity to discern what is appropriate as well
as opportune), ethos (the establishment of credibility) and pathos (emotional con-
nection with the audience, often established by bringing the audience into the
39 Gavin Kelly, Ammianus Marcellinus: The Allusive Historian (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 2008), 83–6.
40 Tutino, Shadows of Doubt, 66.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
appropriate mode of receptivity for the message), can all augment logos (reasoned
argument) as well as betraying it.41
Then there is the question of the sort of truth that is to be conveyed. The most
common concept of historical truth today is something like accordance with par-
ticular facts about some bygone time. With Pericles’ speech, however, Thucydides
was depending by his own admission on a conception of truth as plausibility or
likelihood, which is not so very different from Homer recounting what might
have happened in the Trojan Wars.42 A related concept, and one that can also be
traced at least as far back as Hecataeus, was captured by Herodotus when he
called mythos not just that which was ‘incapable of proof ’ but that which was
‘unintelligent’, i.e. incompatible with evidence or reason. When it is not a question
of specific sources at issue there may be an appeal to a sort of common-sense
arbitration that can rely on the concept of a ‘mythical’ story as being one that
seemed ‘contrary to nature’.43 Then there is the idea of general/universal rather
than specific/particular truth—i.e. the desire to transmit the truth about wars as
such, as well as (or even instead of) the particular war under scrutiny. Since at
any point a historian might be using one of a range of rhetorical techniques to
indicate one of a range of types of truth, we get a sense of the multiple layers at
which works of History had to be read, the scope for confusion among those
unaccustomed to the salient techniques and concepts, and the space for historians
to introduce agendas of their own that might run contrary to this or that or every
concept of truth.
How far any particular sort of truth might be manipulated or abandoned varies
from case to case. One especially controversial instance emerges at the very end
of the period with which this chapter is concerned: Ammianus Marcellinus’ Res
Gestae, written in the 380s ce. In his study of Ammianus, the historian Gavin
Kelly nicely epitomizes his subject matter by declaring himself ‘agnostic and non-
committal on the question of veracity’, partly because ‘the question rarely admits
of definite proof ’, but also because the veracity question is ‘the wrong question’.
I take Kelly to mean that it is wrong to ask if Ammianus was a ‘romantic’ or
‘allusive’ historian as opposed to a ‘proper’ or ‘literalist’ one, because these binaries
are spurious ones within the context of classical antiquity—and, to some extent,
even now. After all, one cannot say that Ammianus has no interest in reporting
historical particulars as accurately as he can: frequently he does the mundane
44 Kelly, Ammianus, 64–5, 94; Treadgold, Early Byzantine Historians, 76. In terms of the contro-
versy over Ammianus—basically whether he should be viewed as a truth-seeking historian or be read
as a work of literature—Kelly forges a third way (not a splitting of the difference) against
John F. Matthews, The Roman Empire of Ammianus Marcellinus (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University
Press, 1989) and Timothy D. Barnes, Ammianus Marcellinus and the Representation of Historical
Reality (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1998).
45 Kelly, Ammianus, 84.
46 Ibid. 69–70. On Ephorus’s much earlier preference for detail about contemporary events,
Fornara, The Nature, 9.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
In the generation after Thucydides, the most influential historian was Xenophon
(c.430–354 bce), a student of the great philosopher Socrates. While, like
Thucydides, he was an eyewitness to many of the events he narrated, sometimes
as a mercenary in Sparta’s service, he was not quite a match for Thucydides in the
quality of his research. His Hellenica continued Thucydides’ History from 411 to
362 bce, recounting Sparta’s declining fortunes after its costly victory in the
Peloponnesian wars. Xenophon was also party to an argument over the purpose
of historical enquiry, a debate whose terms were shaped by the cultural environ-
ment at the waning of the ‘golden age’ (i.e. the Classical period), after the
Peloponnesian wars and the defeat of the Athenian-led Delian League. In essence
this historiographical controversy addressed the relative merits of ‘pleasurable’
History—History as Entertainment—as opposed to ‘useful’ history—especially
History as Lesson. Concerns about accuracy and analysis were integral to the
dispute.
Those demanding utility included Theopompus of Chios (c.380–c.315 bce)
and Ephorus (c.400–330 bce), author of a partly thematic History from the time
of the Heraclidae up to one of Philip of Macedon’s later victories in 340 bce.49
Their targets tended to be the scholars charged with taking most poetic licence
in their writing, prioritizing ‘vividness’ and the stimulation of emotion, such as
Ctesias, who produced a History of Persia around the turn of the fifth–fourth
centuries, and Duris of Samos (born c.350 bce). In latter-day scholarship, owing
probably to Polybius’s insinuations, Phylarchus of the early third century is some-
times thought of in the same category. Duris it was who responded to Ephorus
and Theopompus that their work offered neither a portrait nor pleasure for the
reader. History ought to depict life in the way tragedy does.50
A preliminary thought is that whatever Ctesias, Duris, and Phylarchus did or
did not do, we ought not assume that they were breaking any implicit contract of
trust with readers—nor that Ephorus et al. were themselves innocent of the ‘faults’
with which they charged others.51 This is partly because of audience expectations,
partly because what is pleasurable and what is useful are not mutually exclusive
categories. The pre-Socratic philosopher Gorgias (c.485–c.380 bce) influentially
argued that the reader, observer, or listener might be improved by enjoyment of
the sort promoted by arts like tragedy or poetry. This was a roundabout argument
to utility. The same point from the other side, and this is the argument to rhetoric
as broadly conceived, is that such utility as History was thought to have was best
served by rendering historical accounts digestible, attractive, i.e. in some way
pleasurable, by some combination of intelligent periodization and narration,
leavened perhaps by interesting digressions.52
‘Useful’ meant didactic in some sense, whether in fostering the facility of pru-
dence or in instructing the moral faculty more directly by use of moral examples.
49 Frances Pownall, Lessons from the Past: The Moral Uses of History in Fourth Century Prose (Ann
Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 2007).
50 Jan P. Stronk, Ctesias’ Persian History: Introduction, Text, and Translation (Düsseldorf: Wellem
Verlag, 2010), concludes that whatever Ctesias said about his Persian royal archival sources, his infor-
mation about them was oral and second-hand, and that rather than being assessed by the straightfor-
ward standards of historianship, even Herodotus-like historianship, he should also or even instead be
assessed by the standard of a novelist or a poet in the sense of a creative writer. Ctesias may well have
seen himself as a tragedian, as Duris saw himself. See pp. 42–3 on the discussion of Ctesias and Duris
together.
51 On contracts and different sorts of truth, Tim Whitmarsh, Beyond the Second Sophistic:
Adventures in Greek Postclassicism (Berkeley: University of California Press, 2013), 23.
52 Frank W. Walbank, Polybius, Rome and the Hellenistic World (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 2015), 231–4.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
In either case, the goal was to influence the praxis of the reader. Praxis is not any
old action. It is ‘action in the sense of a deed’, something which, when done, one
‘has’ as one’s work, or ergon. ‘What do I keep having from this ergon? The hexis
[habit] I have exercised in doing the praxis.’53 Hence the idea that History can
be a teacher of life: it is up to the student to live up to the lessons by actually
living them.
At the same the subject matter of much ‘useful History’ tended to be the behav-
iour of states and militaries, or individuals qua commanders or representatives,
and thus pertained to life in the polis, the public sphere. Obviously this does not
mean the History was evacuated of moral content. Clearly different moral consid-
erations might apply in public as opposed to public life, where such distinctions
exist, but this is a far cry from saying that public life has ever been free of moral
considerations.54 Thucydides is in this sense bound together with the more obvi-
ously moral-didactic agendas of Ephorus and Theopompus, both of whom had
been students of the sophist rhetorician Isocrates. Thucydidian international
relations ‘realism’ is predicated upon moral characterizations of the nature of
state actors and norms, as is abundantly clear in Thucydides’ famous Melian
dialogues.
The likes of Theopompus might also have common cause with the likes of
Thucydides in opposition to the likes of Duris on those occasions when the
‘pleasurable’ did seem to come into tension with the ‘useful’, as when the deploy-
ment of vividness was considered not to aid or give point to moral reflection but
to suborn it by sensationalization or prejudicial emotivism. Fear of subornment
along these lines was prominent in Polybius’s mind in the second century bce,
when targeting Phylarchus. Polybius was not uninterested in moral judgement
and its attendant instruction, but he believed that such judgement must be impar-
tial, in the sense of not being biased and not automatically favouring one party
over another. We ought not ‘shrink from accusing our friends or praising our
enemies, nor need we be afraid of praising or blaming the same people at differ-
ent times . . . We must therefore detach ourselves from the actors in our story, and
apply to them only such statements and judgements as their conduct deserves.’55
Judgement, explicit or tacit, must also be based on rigorous causal investigation in
order that whoever is blamed or praised, the grounds are correct. Here emotivism
may be an obstacle. So when discussing the Cleomenean War of 229/228–222 bce
between Sparta and the alliance of Macedon and the Achaean League, Polybius
53 Jill Frank, A Democracy Of Distinction: Aristotle and the Work of Politics (London: University of
Chicago Press, 2005) 34–5. On praxis/praxeis and res gestae, see Raoul Mortley, The Idea of Universal
History from Hellenic Philosophy to Early Christian Historiography (New York: Edwin Mellen, 1996),
ch. 2.
54 Pownall, Lessons from the Past, describes many of the relevant relations and tensions.
55 Polybius, The Rise of the Roman Empire, trans. Ian Scott-Kilvert (London: Penguin, 1979),
editor’s introduction 9–40, here 20–3; quotation from p. 55 (Book I.14 of Polybius’s Histories).
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
was dismissive of Phylarchus, whose purpose he deemed to have been ‘to emphasize
the cruelty of Antigonus and the Macedonians and also that of Aratus and the
Achaeans’ in the victimization of the Mantineans. ‘In his eagerness to arouse
the pity of his readers and enlist their sympathy through his story’, Phylarchus
‘introduces graphic scenes of women clinging to one another, tearing their hair
and baring their breasts’. While there is an implied call for a sort of dry History,
as against Phylarchus’s ‘ignoble and unmanly’ account, this does not mean that
Polybius’s primary objection was to the emotive element per se. Rather, Polybius
believed that the Mantineans had brought their own misfortune on themselves,
and as such did not deserve the pity which Phylarchus’s description might elicit.
Had Phylarchus devoted more energy to explaining the causes of the Mantineans’
plight he would have realized this, Polybius was saying.56
In the period of Ephorus et al., one of the moments in which the political uses
of History came to a head concerned the use of the written word by a group of
aristocrats, Plato (420s–c.348/7 bce) in their number, to combat the oratory of
the Athenian democrats. Against earlier failures of oligarchy, and in the teeth
of the more radical democratic order, the best way to try to retain some control
over the future was to influence elite paideia, meaning, like German Bildung, a
sort of rounded cultural education. Access to the realm of prose was perforce
limited to men of a certain class, so textual historians could channel the past
through the written word to inculcate aristocratic norms. At the same time Plato
assailed the orators’ ‘abuse’ of the historical record in pursuit of their democratic
goals.57 This is the context for his mockery of the likes of the Atthidographers as
they stoked the fancy of the populace with tales of ‘the genealogies of heroes and
men . . . and the foundations of cities in ancient times’ (Hippias Major 285d), and
for his parody in Menexenus of the Thucydidean tradition of inventing speeches
for performative effect.58
That Plato needed rhetoric too is beyond contestation—again, who and what
rhetoric served was what was really at stake—as he acknowledged in his last work
on the topic, the Phaedrus. Yet his attitude remained consistent with his animus
towards the philosophy of Gorgias and thus towards poetry, in the broad sense of
something created by the writer or speaker, as opposed to something found or
identified in the present world or the historical record. In Plato’s philosophy the
entire sensible world was one of ‘seeming’ and ‘becoming’, a world of appearances,
impermanence, and fallible ‘common-sense’ (doxa) in rude approximation to a
realm of pure, eternal ‘being’ and logos, literally word, but here meaning pure
reason or truth. For Plato, philosophical theory, theoria (‘looking-on’), required
56 Polybius, Histories, II.56 (Polybius, The Rise of the Roman Empire, 167–8); Cf. Walbank, Polybius,
Rome and the Hellenistic World, 235–6. On pp. 231–41 Walbank has important observations to make
on the question of utility versus pleasure.
57 Pownall, Lessons from the Past, 38 ff. 58 Atack, ‘Discourse of Kingship’, 338.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
laying aside practical matters in order to face the kosmos without any distraction
of contingent interest.59 Only with such an attitude could the dimensions of the
world beyond the mind be comprehended, and its well-ordered structure repli-
cated in the philosopher’s soul through the process of mimesis. Here the role of
even the least ‘fanciful’ History is unclear, since although History need not be
‘deceitfully’ creative as poetry is, the best that it can aspire to is recording the
world of becoming rather than the world of being, so it was already a diminished
sort of knowledge. One use of History became apparent when Plato moved from
the philosophical endeavour of ontology—a branch of metaphysics concerned
with the nature of existence—to the more mundane matter of political philoso-
phy and social science. His Republic and Laws are thus informed by data about
the past organization of different Greek poleis. The third book of the Laws, for
instance, shows the philosopher engaged in a comparative constitutional History.
This was at once a form of negative exemplarity, showing what measures to avoid
in the setting up of a new government from scratch, and an exercise in abstrac-
tion that produces the elements of the best conceivable social framework from
the existing models. That best framework is the closest available thing to an ideal
political arrangement.
For all that Plato showed History could be deployed for the purposes of a social
science, historiographical innovations were tending to focus more on individual
political actors. Thus Xenophon’s life of Agesilaus II of Sparta, Theopompus’s
account of the exploits of Philip of Macedon, Philippica, and then Callisthenes’
slightly later The Acts of Alexander, wove together History as Lesson and biog
raphy, such that the lives became the exemplary acts.60 It was perhaps appropriate
to the monarchical nature of the Macedonian polity that Philip should be the
prism through which one explored Macedon prevailing over Athens and then
driving eastward. This personalization of history was the culmination of a trend
begun by the Atthidographers with their focus on past kings. The trend was per-
petuated by the continuators of Theopompus, whose works had in turn continued
Xenophon’s.
Two significant developments of third-century bce historical scholarship were
direct results of conquests by Philip’s son, Alexander ‘the Great’. One was an
expansion of ethnographic literature, as in the early-century work of the Ionian
Megasthenes on India. This sort of ethnography ‘did not simply describe the
59 On theoria, Eric Voegelin, Published Essays, 1953–1965 (Columbia: University of Missouri Press,
2000), 115.
60 On Philippica, see Cartledge, ‘Historiography and Ancient Greek Self-Definition’, 28, 34.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
world as it was; it created an imagined sense of where the world had been, where
it was now, and where it would be through the language of custom, habit, origins,
discovery, and exchange’.61 It was also partner to a revived chronographic project
of synchronizing timescales in ever more territories to provide the inclusive
chronological framework for new synthesizing Histories.62
Ethnographic interests spurred the study of Rome by Timaeus of Tauromenium
(c.356–c.260 bce), a historian and chronographer best known as the butt of later
criticism by Polybius, and perhaps the first historian to deploy the pan-Hellenic
Olympic games as a yardstick with which to integrate multiple political histories.
While only fragments of Timaeus’s works remain, there is evidence to suggest
that Polybius, in fact, had some respect for him, and was thus trying to discredit
him as a rival. It has been both claimed and denied that Timaeus identified the
growing significance of Rome, which would have made him the first Greek his
torian so to do. Irrespective, it is a mild coincidence that his probable date of
death was only a few years into the First Punic War (264–241 bce), which was the
first of the Roman Republic’s military engagements beyond the peninsula, into
Timaeus’s homeland of Sicily. Polybius (Histories, I.5.I) tells us that Timaeus
ended his History in 264, when the Romans arrived in Sicily.63
As far as we know, although again we only have the work in fragments, the first
major Roman prose History was written around the close of the third century by
Quintus Fabius Pictor (born c.270 bce).64 A senator at the time of writing his
History of Rome, Fabius had previously served in the army, and had seen some of
the Second Punic War (218–201 bce). He is generally assumed to have written in
Greek, though there is some doubt on this, and a suggestion that he may have
been translated from the Latin. In any case, his work evinces Greek literary influ-
ences as well as Roman civic pride by beginning the story at Rome’s mythic point
of Romulan origin. So many subsequent Roman works started ab urbe condita,
‘from the founding of the city’, and this was not true only of prose Histories. Thus
Fabius’s younger contemporary Quintus Ennius (c.239–169 bce) penned an epic
poem over eighteen books that spanned the fall of Troy and Marcius Porcius
Cato’s time as Roman censor, 184 bce. It became one of the most influential texts
on Roman history and was only supplanted as the canonical work of epic poetry
by the Aeneid of the Roman Homer, Virgil (79–19 bce), which provided a
c ompelling vision of Rome’s foundation, the moment of constitution of the political
‘we’, via the myth of the Trojan refugee Aeneas’s arrival on Italy’s shores.65
Fabius’s History was also characteristic of later work in its elite political author-
ship which links author and author-ity (auctoritas) in the sense of position, quali-
fication, and experience. Another theme common to both Fabius and later writers
was the defence of Roman external policy. Fabius sought to blame the Second
Punic War on a few of the Carthaginian leaders, and to justify the course and
content of Roman action.66 Internal Roman developments are more often the
subject of criticism, albeit against the standards set by Roman traditional virtues.
Accordingly, Cato’s Latinate Origines criticized elements of the Roman political
elite after the Second Punic War for sins including arrogance and the mistreat-
ment of provincial subjects and allies, as measured against past achievements and
the wisdom of the citizenry at large.
The ‘universal’ Histories of the Greek politician and soldier Polybius (203–120
bce) stand in contrast to the particularist Roman narratives. He took up his
story from Timaeuss’ endpoint, 264 bce, working through Rome’s victory over
Macedon in 168 bce, and ending with the obliteration of Carthage in 146 bce.
Ephorus’s heir in the scale of his canvas, Polybius rejected Ephorus’s partly ethno-
graphic approach to focus more exclusively on political and military affairs. He
described the ascent of the Roman Empire with the purpose of instructing his
fellow Greeks in the nature of the force that had superseded their dominion and
gained Mediterranean hegemony in only a few generations. For all of his calls for
impartiality in explanation and judgement, one imagines that the project was not
disadvantageous to his personal prospects in Roman custody as a comfortable
hostage. Indeed, while it would not be until the 50s bce that Romans chronogra-
phers systematically aligned Roman consuls with Greek temporal markers,
Polybius took some important steps from the Greek side in the symbolically
important act of grafting the two timelines together.67
65 Virgil was not the first to do this, merely the most influential, presumably because he himself
was a Roman, giving Romans ownership of an idea once imposed upon them by the Greeks: he was
preceded by several centuries by Hellanicus of Mytilene.
66 For the orthodoxy on Fabius, and the characteristics of Roman historiography, Uwe Walter,
‘Annales and Analysis’, in Andrew Feldherr and Grant Hardy (eds.), The Oxford History of Historical
Writing: Beginnings to AD 600 (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011), 265–90, here 265–6. On the
question of Greek vs Latin, see A. J. Woodman, Lost Histories: Selected Fragments of Roman Historians
(Newcastle: Histos, 2015), 4–22. For an example of Polybian citation and contestation of Fabius on the
Second Punic War, Polybius, Histories, III.8–9 (Polybius, The Rise of the Roman Empire, 185–7).
67 On 50s bce Roman chronography, Feeney, ‘Chronography’.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
to describe, not the thing that has happened, but a kind of thing that might hap-
pen, i.e. what is possible as being probable or necessary. The distinction between
historian and poet is not in the one writing prose and the other verse—you
might put the work of Herodotus into verse, and it would still be a species of
history; it consists really in this, that the one describes the thing that has been,
and the other a kind of thing that might be. Hence poetry is something more
philosophic and of graver import than history, since its statements are of the
nature rather of universals, whereas those of history are singulars. By a universal
statement I mean one as to what such or such a kind of man will probably or
necessarily say or do—which is the aim of poetry, though it affixes proper names
to the characters; by a singular statement, one as to what, say, Alcibiades did or
had done to him. In Comedy this has become clear by this time; it is only when
their plot is already made up of probable incidents that they give it a basis of
proper names, choosing for the purpose any names that may occur to them. . . . In
Tragedy, however, they still adhere to the historic names; and for this reason:
what convinces is the possible; now whereas we are not yet sure as to the possi-
bility of that which has not happened, that which has happened is manifestly
possible, else it would not have come to pass.69
Poetry performed a certain abstraction that gave it a more general utility than
History—and ‘general’ is a good way to understand what Aristotle means by
68 Walbank, Polybius, Rome and the Hellenic World, chs. 12 and 13.
69 Aristotle, Poetics, IX, in Aristotle, On the Art of Poetry, trans. Ingram Bywater (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1920), 43–4.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
time, Polybius had to keep something of Aristotle’s sense of necessity (as opposed
to accident) in order to address, beyond the question of interconnectedness, the
question of plot—which is why there is such a teleological element in his ‘all lead-
ing up to one end’. There had to be a ‘tragic’ element, and this came in the form of
tyche, here meaning something like an overweening force of historical destiny.
In detecting and reporting the operations of tyche, the work of the appropriately
insightful historian—meaning Polybius himself—was promoted to the level of
theoria, looking-on, rather than poetry, creation.74
As we shall see in the next chapter, tyche came in other manifestations than
grand destiny. One point of Polybius’s work, at the micro-level of practical
instruction, was to show by example how the study of the past could help readers
cope with capricious fortune rather than succumbing to fatalism. Another, at the
meso-level of institutional arrangements, was to suggest that the Roman adoption
of a mixed constitution could delay the operations of the historical cycle.75 Finally,
the grand explanatory exercise Polybius set himself presupposed the explicit
investigation of cause, as opposed to the less obviously analytical narration of
events as they occurred. Such explanation sometimes reached for the hand of
tyche, but his fame as a causal historian would scarcely have endured if this were
all there was to it.
Historians Hans Beck and Uwe Walter credit Polybius’s achievements in causal
explanation as a key influence on what they call the ‘modernization’ of Roman
historiography. Other factors included the growth of a more erudite reading pub-
lic which demanded Latin imitation of Greek literary styles, and the extension
of the Republic in terms both of its territorial conquests and its emancipation of
non-Roman Italians. This modernization occurred in the period of the late
Republic, which is generally dated from 147 to 30 bce, and more precisely around
the end of the second century bce. Alas, the first wave of Roman historians that
Beck and Walter categorize as modernizers have only come down to us fragmen-
tarily. They include the likes of Coelius Antipater and Sempronius Asellio.76
The best-known of the Roman historians are renowned for their literary qual
ities and rhetorical facility, as Latin letters reached their golden age in the two
74 Hartog, ‘Polybius and the First Universal History’, esp. 35–9.
75 Connor, ‘Historical Writing in the Fourth Century BC and the Hellenistic Period’, 56–7;
Walbank, Polybius, Rome and the Hellenic World, 185–6, 239–41.
76 Beck and Walter, Die frühen römischen Historiker, 17 ff., and in connection with Lucius Coelius
Antipater, discussed at 35 ff. Further on Polybius’s impact and Greek borrowings more generally,
Dieter Timpe, ‘Memoria and Historiography in Rome’, in John Marincola (ed.), Greek and Roman
Historiography (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011), 150–74, here 166–7.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
centuries either side of the birth of Jesus. How far a commitment to truthfulness
cohered with the demands of literary art varied from case to case, in the works of
writers such as Julius Caesar (100–44 bce), Sallust (86–35 bce), Livy (59 bce—ce
17), and Tacitus (c.56–c.120 ce).77 It is a reasonable hypothesis that artistic and
intellectual reflection was stimulated by the crises and military conflicts of the
long first century bce, corresponding to the period of the Late Republic. Putting
aside the many external wars of the period, the evidence from within suggests
that the institutions that might have been fit for a city state proved inadequate for
the administration of an expanding empire: that evidence includes the failed
‘Gracchan revolution’ of 133–121 bce, three slave wars up to 71 bce, the Social
War of 91–88 bce between Rome and its Italian allies, the civil wars of 88–80 bce
culminating in Sulla’s dictatorships, the Catiline conspiracy of 77 bce, and the
Triumvirate period and ensuing civil wars from 53 to 30 bce. The developments
of the long first century accentuated an existing tendency to venerate the distant
Republican past as against the present and help to explain the sense of historical
change that has been claimed as a feature of the work of those approximate con-
temporaries, variously poets, rhetoricians, and antiquarians, Lucretius, Virgil,
Horace, Cicero (106–43 bce), and Varro (116–27 bce).78
If we also categorize as historians Suetonius (born c.69 ce) and the Greek Plutarch
(46–120 ce), plus the first emperor himself (63 bce–14 ce), author of the self-
serving funerary inscription Res Gestae Divi Augusti (Deeds of the Divine
Augustus), we notice the recurrence of a historiographical pattern. As Rome
passed from Republic to Empire much the same historiographical shifts occurred
as had occurred during the transition, roughly speaking, from Thucydides to
Theopompus: a more pronounced emphasis developed on individuals at the
power centre. That might mean the emperor alone, or the emperor in relation to
senators, as in Tacitus, or, as in the case of Sallust, who did not live to witness the
Principate, an emphasis on plotters and other actors in the internecine political
warfare that presaged the downfall of the Republic. Plutarch wrote matched biog
raphies of Greek and Roman luminaries, and Suetonius recorded the lives of
twelve successive Julio-Claudian and Flavian caesars, beginning with Julius
77 On Sallust’s attitude see William Batstone, ‘The Drama of Rhetoric at Rome’, in Erik Gunderson
(ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Ancient Rhetoric (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009),
212–27, here 221 ff.
78 On whom see Burke, Renaissance Sense, 139–41. On the distance of Rome’s ‘golden age’ and the
claim that ‘Recent history had for centuries been held to show a degeneration from this legendary
ideal’, see editor’s ‘Introduction’, p. xxxi, in Tacitus, Tacitus: The Annals and the Histories, ed. Hugh
Lloyd-Jones (New York: Washington Square Press, 1964).
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
Caesar. Writing thematically, in aid of comparison, each life was for Livy a form
of History as Moral Lesson, as he deployed the range of rhetorical skills in
enkomium or damnation.
Writing ab urbe condita (‘from the birth of the city’) up to 9 bce, Livy’s vastly
popular and influential general History of Rome does not conform to this pattern.
With the declared intent ‘to record the story of the greatest nation in the world’,
his agenda was rather less subtle than that of Polybius, though like Polybius his
conception of history had both linear and cyclical aspects.79 As with almost all
classical historiography Livy had ample space for prominent individuals, such as
Hannibal and Scipio Africanus in his account of the Punic wars, but he also
resembled Herodotus in his ethnographic concern to recreate the ‘mood’ of a
time or place. A patriot writing in something of the spirit of Porcius Cato’s
Origines, the main object of Livy’s admiration was the Roman past, not its pre-
sent, and in this sense History had the task of holding up an improving mirror. In
‘the study of history it is especially improving and beneficial to contemplate
examples of every kind of behavior . . . From it you can extract for yourself and
your commonwealth both what is worthy of imitation and what you should avoid
because it is rotten from start to finish.’ More specifically,
I ask that each person pay close attention for himself to the following, namely
what was the way of life and the traditions, through which men[,] and by what
abilities, both civic and military, the empire was created and increased; next,
let him mentally trace those traditions as first they slipped, together with the
gradual decline of their proper inculcation, then collapsed more and more, and
then began to tumble headlong, until we have come to our current straits.80
This was History as Lesson and a critical form of History as Identity, looking
backwards for moral and practical inspiration as Virgil and Horace did. It was
clearly not pro-monarchist but nor was it anti-monarchist, since the rot had set in
during the Republican period whose earlier phase Livy venerated. Moreover,
while his attitude towards Augustus is not entirely clear, and coming to an estima-
tion on it is not helped by the fact that we do not know when he finished writing
his work, Livy was not insensible to the order that Augustan rule produced since
he wrote so much of his History in that context.
More than half a century ago one of Livy’s translators noted that Livy’s invita-
tion to ponder the degradation of the world was indeed ‘a solemn invitation; but
most people enjoy being collectively scolded for their wickedness, and Livy’s
79 On Livy’s cyclicism, see Gary B. Miles, ‘The Cycle of Roman History in Livy’s First Pentad’, The
American Journal of Philology 107:1 (1986), 1–33; on his linearity, Ianziti, ‘Humanism’s New Science’,
71–2. Livy quote from the opening paragraph of Book I.1 of Livy’s History of Rome, in Livy, The Early
History of Rome, trans. Aubrey de Sélincourt (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1960), 17.
80 Translation from Adam, ‘Annales and Analysis’, 268–9.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
c ontemporaries accepted it with ardour’. The work did indeed sweep all other
accounts before it even if its length meant many people only encountered it in
abbreviated form. The ‘collective’ element is key here, more particularly the element
of collective memory, in light of Augustus’s own determination to ‘re-awaken’
Roman awareness of tradition. The conflicts under account were conflicts of the
collective past by the time Livy wrote, while the values he venerated might be
collectively renewed in modified circumstances. It was after all the people that
were at the centre of Livy’s thoughts, which may be explained by the fact that,
unusually amongst the other historians mentioned here, Livy himself was not an
active politician involved directly in power squabbles, but a more aloof rhetor or
man of letters. He seems to have conceived the people almost as an organism that
developed over time and had to adapt itself, but which still had a true nature to
which it should adhere.81
Like Livy, and setting off in his Annals from where Livy finished, Tacitus
(c.56–c.120 ce) engaged with the grand subject matter of warfare, but his abiding
concern is the workings and psychology of power. He is one of the great stylists,
though in the tradition of Sallust rather than Cicero or Livy.
Tacitus’s epigrams are like the thrust of a knife, clean and wounding; they imi-
tate, in their very unadorned economy, the terrible times they describe. Tacitus’s
antitheses are never pretty; they are images which contrast appearance and real-
ity with almost brutal concision, and always at the expense of reality. The
Romans are elegant in the forum and ruthless in the field: Solitudinem faciunt,
pacem appellant—‘They make a desert, and call it peace’. The Britons mistake the
trapping for the essence of culture: Humanitas vocabantur, cum pars serviutis
esset—‘They called it civilization, when it was part of servitude’.82
These famous phrases come not from the Annals, which covered the period from
the death of Augustus and Tiberius’s ascension to Nero’s death (14–68 ce), nor
the earlier-written Histories, which went from 69 ce to Domitian’s death in 96 ce,
but from a yet earlier work written in 98 ce, a laudation of Tacitus’s father-in-law
Agricola, who was at the forefront of the conquest of Britain. The Agricola might
as well have been written as a rejoinder to the recommendation in Sallust’s The
War with Catiline that ‘men should strive with all their resources not to pass their
lives unnoticed’.83 It shuns vainglorious resistance to overwhelming force while
81 On this and the previous paragraph see Adam, ‘Annales and Analysis’, 268–9, 271–2. For the
quote on collective scolding, Livy, The Early History of Rome, trans de Sélincourt, 13: emphasis added.
Further on the element of identity-construction, Andrew Feldherr, ‘Livy’s Revolution: Civic Identity
and the Creation of the Res Publica’, in Thomas Habinek and Alessandro Schiesaro (eds.), The Roman
Cultural Revolution (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997), 136–57. On Livy’s biography,
popular focus, and the organism idea, see Timpe, ‘Memoria and Historiography in Rome’, 169–70.
82 Peter Gay, The Enlightenment: An Interpretation (New York: Norton, 1966), 158.
83 Sallust quoted in Batstone, ‘Drama of rhetoric’, 221.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
recalling how a good man tempering decency with prudence could endure even
under bad rulers who sought to wield the imperial power structure as a tool for
their designs. Like Tacitus’s Germania (also 98 ce) with its ‘noble savage’ view of
Germanic tribes, and with as little first-hand experience, Agricola also contains
ethnographic reflections on Britain.
At first glance the Annals are straightforwardly anti-imperial, the latest instal-
ment in a long tradition of decline literature. With the advent of the Principate
‘the state had been revolutionized, and there was not a vestige left of the old
sound morality. Stripped of equality, all looked up to the commands of a sovereign
without the least apprehension for the present.’ Yet while Tacitus did not share
the opinion of Livy or the less well-known Velleius Paterculus (19 bce–31 ce) that
the imperial order could actually restore some Republican virtue, he nonetheless
saw it as important in the establishment of peace within the empire, and in the
return of law to corrupt provinces hitherto run by greedy governors. He was
critical of the emperor Domitian (81–96) in Agricola and in such parts of the
Histories as survive, but since Domitian was the last of his dynasty, the Flavian
line, this was hardly a challenge to successive new emperors, Nerva and Trajan.
Further ambiguity coloured Tacitus’s estimation of the prospects for the influ-
ence of the senatorial class—of which he and Agricola were members—under
an emperor. Yet, in the final analysis, there can be little doubt that his overall
approach bears the imprint of senatorial class consciousness.84 In insisting
on writing with reference to the consular year, as against the periodization
provided by the reigns of emperors, Tacitus was making a political as well as
aesthetic choice.
In his claim to write sine ira et studio, without anger or partiality (Annals I:1),
Tacitus was manifestly not promising to avoid evaluation, or to tell the story
aperspectivally. He was declaring sufficient detachment from the affairs under
scrutiny as to pass judgement where, and in the measure, due. This sentiment
stands alongside Polybius’s claim to avoid political bias, irrespective of the success
of either in adhering to his own standards, which for Tacitus were the exalted
norms of a class memory of yesteryear. Whatever we make of Tacitus’s avowed
judgementalism, it stands in as great a contrast to the moral exemplarity that pro-
vides a paean to current mores as it does to the History that purports neutrality.
It was of a piece with Cicero’s definition of historical truth as defined against sym-
pathy or favour, and Sallust’s refusal to be influenced by ‘hope, fear, or political
partisanship’.85
84 Tacitus, Annals, I.4 (p. 5) and the editor’s ‘Introduction’, pp. xxxi–xxxviii, in Tacitus, ed. Hugh
Lloyd-Jones; Ellen O’Gorman, ‘Imperial History and Biography at Rome’, in Feldherr and Hardy
(eds.), The Oxford History of Historical Writing: Beginnings to AD 600, 291–315, here 294, 300–8.
Further on Tacitus’s ambiguities, Momigliano, Classical Foundations, 117.
85 On Sallust and Cicero, Walter, ‘Annales and Analysis’, 276.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
86 David S. Potter, ‘Greek Historians of Imperial Rome’, in Feldherr and Hardy (eds.), The Oxford
History of Historical Writing: Beginnings to AD 600, 316–45, here 316–17, 325, and 329 on the deliber-
ate archaisms; Sulochana R. Asirvatham, ‘Historiography’, in Daniel S. Richter and William A. Johnson
(eds.), The Oxford Handbook of the Second Sophistic (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2017), 477–92.
On Cassius Dio’s Atticism, his archaisms, and his relationship to sophism and the Second Sophistic,
Brandon Jones, ‘Cassius Dio—Pepaideumenos and Politician on Kingship’, in Carsten Hjort Lange and
Jesper Majbom Madsen (eds.), Cassius Dio: Greek Intellectual and Roman Politician (Leiden: Brill,
2016), 297–315, here 297–9.
87 Potter, ‘Greek Historians of Imperial Rome’, 328.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
2
History, Faith, Fortuna
Introduction
Classical–Christian Fusion
Besides traducing the Jewish religion, one of the easiest ways for theologians to
contrast Christianity with Judaism was to stigmatize Judaism’s adherents, notably
3 John Hermann Randall, Nature and Historical Experience (New York: Columbia University Press,
1958), 124–6; Rex Warner, The Greek Philosophers (New York: New American Library, 1958), 225–6.
4 On the adoption of Platonism see Dermot Moran, ‘Platonism, Medieval’, in Edward Craig (ed.),
Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy, vol. 7 (London: Routledge, 1998), 431–9. On Plotinus, Lloyd
Gerson, ‘Plotinus’, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2014 edition), ed.
Edward N. Zalta, https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2014/entries/plotinus/ On Augustine,
C. W. Wolfskeel, De Immortalitate Animae of Augustine: Text, Translation and Commentary
(Amsterdam: Grüner, 1977), 10–20. On Origen, Edward Moore, ‘Origen of Alexandria’, Internet
Encyclopedia of Philosophy: http://www.iep.utm.edu/origen-of-alexandria/#SH5b
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
with the allegation of deicide. This also helped divert responsibility for Jesus’s
death from Rome, facilitating coexistence with the worldly power and proselyt
ization amongst the empire’s peoples. At the same time the early propagandists
of Christianity also needed to sustain the link with Judaism to which their own
religion was said to be a successor. One contribution to the project of superces-
sion was the manipulation of extant works of History, notably the work of the
great Jewish historian Josephus (37–c.100 ce). Josephus’s Antiquities of the Jews
was prized for its wealth of material on early Christianity in the first century ce,
such that Cassiodorus later included it on his influential list of suitable Christian
reading alongside the major ecclesiastical historians of the fourth and fifth
centuries.5 Josephus supposedly said in his Antiquities, which was written around
the early 90s ce:
Now there was about this time Jesus, a wise man if it be lawful to call him a man,
for he was a doer of wonders, a teacher of such men as receive the truth with
pleasure. He drew many after him both of the Jews and the Gentiles. He was the
Christ. When Pilate, at the suggestion of the principal men among us [that is, the
Jews], had condemned him to the cross, those that loved him at first did not
forsake him, for he appeared to them alive again the third day, as the divine
prophets had foretold these and a thousand other wonderful things about him, and
the tribe of Christians, so named from him, are not extinct at this day.
(Antiquities 18:63–4)
5 For the reading list, Peter W. Edbury and John Gordon Rowe, William of Tyre: Historian of the
Latin East (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990), 34. Alongside Eusebius of Caesarea, we
encounter ‘Paulus’ Orosius, and the Historia tripartita which combined works of the Greek Christian
historians Socrates, Sozomenus, and Theodoretus.
6 David Patterson and Alan L. Berger, Jewish–Christian Dialogue: Drawing Honey from the Rock
(St Paul, MN: Paragon House, 2008), 82–3.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
of the timespan for the creation of the world in Genesis, and the claim in Psalms
that a millennium was but a day in God’s eyes, the world was said to be scheduled
to last for 6,000 years after the creation plus another thousand years of rest to
match the seventh, Sabbath day. Christ was apparently born precisely halfway
through the world’s last standard millennium, in 5,500. After the second coming
of Christ, there would be a further, eighth ‘day’, a timeless, supramundane one.7
A complement to chronological synchronization was the way in which ‘figural’
readings of events and personages intimated religious succession, in keeping with
the basic proposition that the coming of Jesus was a fulfilment of Old Testament
prophecy. Tertullian again made notable developments in this line of thought.
A figura is partly metaphor, partly allegory. Figural reading is best understood in
its relation to the concept ‘prefiguration’, by which, for instance, Moses could be
tied to Jesus by the imputation of a reciprocal relationship. Moses presaged Jesus
and Jesus fulfilled Moses. Both were at once concrete historical individuals and
gained their shared significance as expressions of God, infused with vital force and
accorded special architectural powers by this shared essence.8 So on one hand, as
we have seen, Christians, like Romans, oriented their sense of time around key
moments in the past, meaning that their sense of time was always historical in
some fairly orthodox sense.9 On the other hand, some of their ‘historical’ think-
ing pertained to a realm out of time: Moses and Christ could not be linked in
any temporal, causal sense of one thing prompting another in ‘horizontal’, linear
fashion—their relationship could only work if ‘vertically’ referred to the atemporal
deity. According to the pivotal theorist of figural thought, Erich Auerbach, it was
this fusion of real historical event and ‘providential world-history’ which gave
Christianity its ‘tremendous powers of persuasion’, underpinning its medieval
hegemony.10
Figural reading was but one strand of a rich patristic and medieval interpret
ative tradition. Indeed within occidental history we might say that while the great
techniques of writing and speaking were elevated to a high level by the Greeks
and Romans, the techniques of reading and interpretation collectively known
as hermeneutics were honed to a finer point in the Christian world, as, amongst
other things it drew on rich Jewish traditions of scriptural exegesis. Both
7 Michael Whitby, ‘Imperial Christian Historiography’, in Feldherr and Hardy (eds.), The Oxford
History of Historical Writing: Beginnings to AD 600, 346–70, here 347–8.
8 David Dawson, Christian Figural Reading and the Fashioning of Identity (Berkeley: University of
California Press, 2001), 88 ff., 163–4; Eric Auerbach, Mimesis: The Representation of Reality in Western
Literature (New York: Doubleday, 1957), 73 ff.
9 On historical as well as theological time, Rosamond McKitterick, ‘Constructing the Past in the
Early Middle Ages’, Transactions of the Royal Historical Society 6th ser. VII (1997), 101–29, here 104.
On foundational and original moments in ecclesiastical History, Momigliano, Classical Foundations,
ch. 6.
10 Terry Cochran, Twilight of the Literary: Figures of Thought in the Age of Print (Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press, 2001), 58–60. Auerbach’s text is ‘Figura’ in Eric Auerbach, Scenes from the
Drama of European Literature (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1984), 11–76.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
monotheisms had sacred texts around which to orient their sense of past, present,
and future, and to provide life rules and morality tales. Interpreting these texts ‘cor-
rectly’ was therefore a task of the highest importance, with the promise of nothing
less than getting as close as possible to the thought of god.11 Given the breadth of
the texts’ contents, hermeneutics came to bridge theology, philosophy, and law. As
we shall see further in the next chapter, historical–critical study was increasingly
important to the interpretative endeavour, whence ‘History as Communion’.
Early in the third century ce, Origen had sketched a tripartite scheme of bib
lical exegesis, incorporating moral, literal, and allegorical levels of meaning.
John Cassian (c.360–435) added a fourth level and his quadriga became the
standard medieval reading scheme, though Cassian’s contemporary Augustine
practised a variation. The quadriga comprised (i) historical or literal, (ii) moral
or tropological, (iii) allegorical, typological or analogical, and (iv) eschatological
or anagogical readings. Figural reading is subsumed in the third of these category-
groups. The meaning of each group was elaborated in the mnemonic Litera, gesta
docet; quid credas, allegoria; moralis, quid agas; quo tendas anagogia; ‘The letter
teaches events, allegory what you should believe, morality what you should do,
anagogy what mark you should be aiming for’.12 One of the quadriga’s purposes
was to ensure that reading and learning were not passive exercises providing
once-and-for-all comprehension, but rather comprised an arduous, interactive,
and ongoing process.13 At the same time, multi-layered readings permitted the
circumvention of otherwise tricky contradictions, and the rationalizing of dis-
tasteful chronicle—not every level of interpretation needed to be applied together
to every text. Such reading practices helped reconcile the New Testament with the
Old. They also underwrote the legitimacy of separating some History from
knowledge of God, including thus separating some biblical facts from theological
interpretation.14
Alongside these reading practices, early Christianity produced its own written
History, of which that of Eusebius of Caesarea (c.255–339 ce) stands out for its
11 David R. Olson, The World on Paper: The Conceptual and Cognitive Implications of Writing
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), 150.
12 Quote from the Glossa Ordinaria, cited in Gianfrancesco Pico della Mirandola, Pico della
Mirandola: Oration on the Dignity of Man: A New Translation and Commentary, ed. Francesco
Borghesi, Michael Papio, and Massimo Riva (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2012), 72 n. 16.
13 Werner H. Kelber, ‘The Quest for the Historical Jesus’, in John Dominic Crossan, Luke Timothy
Johnson, and Werner H. Kelber, The Jesus Controversy: Perspectives in Conflict (Harrisburg, PA: Trinity
Press, 1999), 75–116, here 78 ff.
14 Peter Van Nuffelen, ‘Theology versus Genre? The Universalism of Christian Historiography in
Late Antiquity’, in Liddel and Fear (eds.), Historiae Mundi, 162–75; see also Momigliano, Classical
Foundations, ch. 6.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
The successions of the holy apostles along with the times extending from our
Saviour to our own day; the magnitude and significance of the deeds said to
have been accomplished throughout the ecclesiastical narrative, how many
governed and presided over these affairs with distinction in the most famous
communities; how many in each generation served as ambassadors of the
15 Treadgold, Early Byzantine Historians, ch. 2; Grafton and Williams, Christianity and the
Transformation of the Book, ch. 3, which also shows continuities between the Chronicle and Origen’s
Hexapla.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
Divine Logos [the word of God], either in unwritten form or through written
compositions; the identities, number and dates of those who, thanks to a yearning
for innovation, drove on to the heights of error and proclaimed themselves the
introducers of what is falsely called knowledge and mercilessly attacked Christ’s
flock like vicious wolves; and in addition, what befell the whole Jewish people
right after their plot against our Saviour; how many times and in what ways
war was waged against the Divine Logos by the Gentiles during each time
period; how great were the contests fought in each period on Its behalf, through
blood and torture, and in addition the martyrdoms of our very own day, and the
gracious and kind relief of our Saviour that came at last . . .16
The framing of divinely imposed punishment for Jews alongside Christian mar-
tyrdom and fortitude shows that this is far from a secular History in its purposes
and meaning. Nonetheless there are many mundane elements to it, including the
treatment of Jesus’s human life. It is better researched than Eusebius’s Chronicle,
notwithstanding its use of the altered Josephus. It makes extensive use of quota-
tions from works at Caesarea’s great library, including accounts of the lifetimes of
ancient writers (plucked ‘like the flowers of verbal fields’17), and some Roman
documentation as well as biblical sources.
If Eusebius’s Chronicle and History intimated a favourable teleology by tracing
the ascent of Christianity through Rome, the work of Augustine’s student ‘Paulus’
Orosius (born c.380–5 ce) reflected the challenges to Christian Rome during
its author’s lifetime. Orosius complemented Augustine’s theological treatise
Concerning the City of God against the Pagans with a more explicitly historical
tract aimed at the same target. His Historiae adversum paganos or (The Seven
Books of ) History against the Pagans served to counter the claim that Rome had
fallen because it had weakened by embracing Christianity—a claim Gibbon wove
into a wider explanation 1,400 years later. Orosius pointed to the extent of vio-
lence and disaster entailed in the expansion of republican Rome, arguing that it
was greater than anything that had occurred since Rome’s adoption of Christianity.
He was especially scathing of Roman conduct in the Punic wars. At the same time
the possibility of Christ’s intercession, once he had revealed himself, paved the
way for human improvement. More recent disasters could be rationally explained
as just punishment for wrongs, but also as the result of the continued existence of
pagans—and Jews. The sack of Rome was anyway mild in comparative historical
terms. Alaric and his fellow ‘Goths’ (Visigoths) had respected the sanctity of the
churches in Rome, and before long, by 417–18, so Orosius maintained, the city
16 Eusebius of Caesarea, The History of the Church: A New Translation, ed. and trans.
Jeremy M. Schott (Oakland: University of California Press, 2019), 39 (Book I, ch. 1, 1–2 of the
original).
17 Ibid. 40 (Book I, ch. 1, 4 of the original).
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
returned to normalcy. Above all else, this forced encounter with barbarians
enabled the fulfilment of Christ’s injunction (Matthew 24:14) to spread the gospel,
in this case into the lands from which the barbarians came. Emblematic of the
prospects for the future was the marriage in 414 between the Visigoth King
Ataulf, and Galla Placidia, daughter of the former Roman Emperor Theodosius.
Apparently Ataulf had thought to replace ‘Romania’ with ‘Gothia’ but had been
persuaded by his wife to restore and enhance Rome.18 Orosius’s account was
enduringly popular in medieval Europe perhaps because it fitted the conceits of
later Christianized European ‘barbarians’ who formed the martial and demographic
backbone of western Christendom.
Orosius, Augustine, Julius Africanus, and Jerome all subscribed to some version
of the theory that came to be known as translatio imperii, transfer of dominion.
The most influential source of the idea of four successive dominant kingdoms is
the dreams and visions recounted in the Old Testament book of Daniel with its
apocalyptic overtones, whereby the end of the fourth kingdom brings the end
of days and the advent of god’s kingdom. In fact this is another motif that tied
together both of the monotheistic religions with some pagan traditions. The four
kingdoms idea may have originated in Persia and was certainly present in Greek
tradition well before the composition of Daniel. Herodotus listed Assyria, Media,
and Persia; after the successes of Alexander, Macedon or Greece could easily be
added. Polybius appended fallen Carthage to the list of Assyria, Media, and
Persia, which explains why Jerome thought Polybius necessary to interpret
Daniel.19 Most Jewish and Christian exegetes took Daniel to be alluding to the
Babylonian empire, the Medio-Persian empire, the Greek empire, and the Roman
empire. One can therefore imagine the significance attached to the seeming collapse
of the Roman empire and, conversely, to Orosius’s vision of Rome’s endurance in
a new form.
Looking forward from late antiquity and the fall of the western Roman empire,
it was of vital symbolic import when the title emperor was revived in 800, when
it was bestowed by Pope Leo III on the Christian Frank, Charlemagne. In 962,
after a series of early tenth-century disputes in which the title was lost by the
18 See especially David Rohrbacher, The Historians of Late Antiquity (London: Routledge, 2002),
135–49; also Richard Godden, ‘The Medieval Sense of History’, in Stephen Harris and Bryon L. Grigsby
(eds.), Misconceptions about the Middle Ages (New York: Routledge, 2008), 204–12, here 206.
19 George Wesley Buchanan, The Book of Daniel (Eugene, OR: Wipf and Stock, 1999), 68; Conrad
Trieber, ‘Die Idee der vier Weltreiche’, Hermes, 27 (1892), 311–42. On Jerome and Polybius, Arnaldo
Momigliano, Essays in Ancient and Modern Historiography (Chicago: University of Chicago Press,
2012), 79.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
Carolingian line, the crown was given to the founder of the Ottonian dynasty,
Otto I. The position of Emperor was constantly occupied until the Napoleonic
wars and the dissolution in 1806 of what had by then long been known as the
Holy Roman Empire. As the translatio imperii concept developed, it was con-
tended, most influentially and perhaps originally by the chronicler and universal
historian Otto of Freising (1114–58), that history’s unfolding also involved a
gradual east to west movement of civilization.20 The ‘evolution’ from the Middle
East through the eastern Mediterranean through to the Holy Roman Empire,
and then by some estimates to France and then England, still has some pale echo
today, in the rhetoric of manifest destiny in a certain westerly successor to
Middle Eastern Christendom. By this account it is more than a literal observa-
tion that the sun rises in the east (the Orient, in German Morgenland, literally
morning-land) and sets in the west (Occident; Abendland; evening-land). It is
figuratively true.
Overall, Christian philosophies differed from most of their Greco-Roman pre-
decessors in three ways. The first difference concerned the nature of divinity and
the cosmos. As opposed to classical conceptions of the cosmos as possessing its
own immanent purpose or teleology, in the Christian conception god was outside
of the natural order entirely, though could intervene in it and even incarnate
‘himself ’ within it. Neoplatonic metaphysics blurred this distinction somewhat
with its conception of a sort of sliding scale of immaterial to material, divine to
mundane.
The second difference concerned the shape or pattern of human history. If the
most famous classical models depicted either constancy or a kind of cyclical or
spiralling passage of rise and fall (Hesiod, Polybius, even Herodotus) or some
sort of future recurrence-in-reverse-order of past events (as in Virgil21), then
the Christian model, like the Jewish model before it, was predicated upon a
more linear movement. The difference is certainly not absolute, given, on the
one hand, the linear aspects of Polybius’s and Livy’s work, which offered an
example helpful to smoothing over civilizational differences, and, on the other
hand, that ‘Christian time’ could also be circular or liturgical, basing its calcula-
tions on both Hebrew lunar and Roman solar elements. The annual cycle of festi-
vals was tied both to fixed points such as Christmas and the moveable feast that
was Easter.22
The third difference between the two sets of philosophies is less a matter of
pattern than of point, purpose, and meaning, as enshrined in what, for Christians,
20 Samantha Zacher, Rewriting the Old Testament in Anglo-Saxon Verse: Becoming the Chosen
People (London: Bloomsbury, 2013), 89; Marie-Dominique Chenu, Nature, Man, and Society in the
Twelfth Century (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1968), 186–7, 195–6.
21 Richard Jenkin, Virgil’s Experience: Nature and History; Times, Names and Places (Oxford:
Clarendon Press, 1998), 205.
22 Ianziti, ‘Humanism’s New Science’, 71–2; cf. McKitterick, ‘Constructing’, 104–6.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
lay at the end of the historical process. Here we notice the particular continuity with
the ‘Old Testament’ conception of History, a continuity implicit in twentieth-
century historian Josef Yerushalmi’s observation that while Herodotus was the
‘father of History’, the ‘fathers of meaning in history were the Jews’.23 Again, the
difference between Judeo-Christian and Greco-Roman models is not absolute,
because Christian universal History retained some of the assumptions of Platonic
philosophy in its reliance on a fixed point of reference for whatever happened in
the mundane realm. This very contrast with the atemporal realm concerned not
just the mortal life of man but the life of the world. Time must, in other words,
run out—this was the eschatological dimension of Christian thought, meaning its
preoccupation with finality, with endings, and it was associated with the idea of
divine interventions in history from beyond it, and figural readings. The ques-
tions of when and how time would run out, and who had authority to interpret its
course, were of the essence in theological terms and increasingly, too, in terms of
the church’s worldly power.
Following the Protestant theologian Paul Tillich, we might divide the linear
visions of Christian future-oriented history into prophetic and apocalyptic ver-
sions. Both the prophetic and apocalyptic versions had the clearest of origin sto-
ries, and were carried along by a sense of history as unfolding divine reason and
improvement in consciousness of god’s grace.24 Both versions recognized kairoi
(plural of kairos, meaning event-like interruptions of continuous human history
around which it could be periodized) but the prophetic version was conservative
in the sense that it claimed that the final major earthly event had already occurred,
with Christ’s advent. Following Julius Africanus, Augustine tended to the con-
servative stance, albeit with some particular interpretative differences. The his-
torical process was, like the week, divided into seven stages, with earthly history
comprising six, of which Augustine fancied that he lived in the last.25 He antici-
pated the seventh, Sabbath stage of eternal rest, the end of time and the advent of
the heavenly city that was prefaced by final judgement. Augustine’s position may
also be called ecclesiastical in a particular sense. Ecclesia, derived from the Greek
ekklesia, the lawmaking assembly of Athenian citizens, means variously a literal
church building and something like the assembly of the faithful. In practice,
the claim to speak for this elect was arrogated to the church hierarchy, just as the
Athenian assembly comprised a small elite. Since its authority was based on
the view that history was in its final period, there was no ground for radical
23 Samuel Moyn, ‘Jewish and Christian Philosophy of History’, in Tucker (ed.), History and
Historiography, 427–36; analysis and quote from 428.
24 Andrew Fear, ‘Orosius and Escaping from the Dance of Doom’, in Liddel and Fear (eds.),
Historiae Mundi, 176–88.
25 The concept of six earthly stages and the idea of four successive kingdoms, while apparently in
tension, need not be so in fact. Both implied overall unity in the evolving experience of the known
world, and the sixth age and fourth kingdom were of the Romano-Christian present.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
critique of the order that it underpinned. The fourth-century church declared the
competing apocalyptic vision a heresy.
In that apocalyptic or ‘sectarian’ vision, which came to have revolutionary
connotations, the final event was yet to come. This vision borne by chiliasts, or
millenarians as they are sometimes dubbed, entailed a utopia on earth before the
end of days, a utopia of social justice in which the Holy Spirit was with everyone,
and intermediary authorities unnecessary. Joachim of Fiore (c.1135–1202) was
the most prominent high medieval sectarian, whose tripartite division of history
characterized the Old Testament period as the age of the father and of law, i.e. the
time of ‘man’s’ obedience to the laws of God, the New Testament period as the
age of the Son and of grace, with man as God’s progeny, and the impending (from
1260) age of the Holy Spirit and of love, when man and God would be in direct
contact. Joachim’s lead was taken by a group of radical Franciscans known as
the Spirituals, and his spirit endured through the Reformation and the English
revolution in the bodies of Taborites, Anabaptists, and certain revolutionary
peasants and Puritans.26 Despite the anti-Judaism of chiliasts such as Tertullian,
in some respects their beliefs accorded with Jewish theodicy conceived at a time
of political weakness, with its concept of a coming fulfilment by revelation of
what yet remained hidden.27 Apocalypticism could in principle promote a more
activist ethos than propheticism, and here too it bore some resemblance to Jewish
thought as opposed to the conservative prophetic mode which could encourage a
tendency simply to ‘mark time’ until the end.28
If in the vastly influential Augustinian theology the past comprised a text
communicating God’s message to man—with the ‘Old Testament’ not only being
history, but also constituting ‘the shadow of the future’29—then, at the same time,
doctrinal disputes and the very refusal of history to come to an end prompted
growing contestation about timings and meanings on all sides. It also prompted
some to give up on the prediction game in line with Eusebius’s doubts about the
predictive value of chronology. In but one example from the central middle ages,
26 Paul Tillich, The Protestant Era (London: Nisbet, 1955), 25–7; Marjorie Reeves, The Influence
of Prophecy in the Later Middle Ages: A Study of Joachimism (Oxford: Oxford University Press,
2000).
27 On Jewish theodicy, Moyn, ‘Jewish and Christian Philosophy of History’, 428–9.
28 On Jewish philosophies of History, see chapter 3 of Berger and Patterson, Jewish–Christian
Dialogue, esp. 72. Note—and here I draw also on correspondence with the author of that chapter,
David Patterson—that ‘Israel’ means ‘one who strives with God’, implying interaction of the temporal
and eternal realms, where one ‘lives God’, as it were, by one’s comportment towards other people, as
commanded in the Torah. The holy Jewish calendar works not from the first day of creation but the
sixth, the day of the creation of the first human. In Judaism, one’s acts in this world towards others are
also actions towards God. And this world is a changing one, an unfolding, developing one, in much
the same way relationships—among humans and with god—unfold and develop.
29 Marc Bloch, Feudal Society (London: Routledge, 1989), 88–102, ‘the shadow of the future’ at 90;
Peter Haidu, The Subject of Violence: The Song of Roland and the Birth of the State (Bloomington:
Indiana University Press, 1993), 16.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
thirty-fifth year of the reign of the glorious and invincible Henry, king of the
English. The sixty-ninth year from the arrival in England, in our own time, of
the supreme Norman race. The 703rd year from the coming of the English into
England. The 2,265th year from the coming of the Britons to settle in the same
island. The 5,317th year from the beginning of the world. The year of grace
1135 . . . We are leading our lives, or—to put it more accurately—we are holding
back death, in what is the 135th year of the second millennium.
Henry reflected on the inhabitants of the corresponding year in the first millennium
and then spoke to the people of the year 2135, asking them to pray for him: ‘In the
same way, may those who will walk with God in the fourth and fifth millennia
pray and petition for you, if indeed mortal man survives so long.’ Against those
who would ask ‘Why do you talk in this way about future millennia when the
conclusion of Time will come in our own epoch and we are in daily and trembling
expectation of the end of the world?’ Henry provided his own reasons for the
great endurance of the ‘truth promised for many ages’, but he also noted that ‘no
one knows the extent of Time except the Father of all’.30
The obstinate determination of time to carry on was a problem in different
ways for the prophetic Histories and their apocalyptic competitors, though
Histories of both sorts continued to be produced. Not long before Joachim of
Fiore made his intervention, Henry of Huntingdon’s younger contemporary Otto
of Freising restored an eighth era to Augustine’s model. Variations on both sides
continued to be written for centuries, and recognition of variation gets us away
from the idea of two pure and purely opposed types of theological history. Even
Augustine’s theology, which was on the prophetic side of the divide, concerned
elements of interaction between God and man that were present in Jewish the
ology and in Origen’s increasingly disfavoured thought. This ambiguity had
connotations for understanding the course of human history as well as divine
intervention. If one’s metahistorical outlook was still shaped by a sense that men
could influence the destiny of humankind, history was open to reinterpretation in
light of earthly events as observers strained to locate the present in relation to the
moment of salvation.31 Amongst other things, this meant that ‘ordinary’ historians
were not irrelevant to the great philosophers of the historical process.
30 Henry of Huntingdon, The History of the English People 1000–1154, ed. and trans. Diana
Greenway (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002), 119–20. See also p. 146 for the editor’s note on the
problematic nature of some of Henry’s dating. Note too that, as the title of this edition suggests,
Henry’s work was revised up to 1154.
31 On relevant renaissance and modern scholars, see e.g. Ianziti, ‘Humanism’s New Science’, 73,
especially n. 40 and Godden, ‘Medieval Sense’, 204. Godden also explains the diversions from
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
Augustine. Further to the ‘ambivalence’ of Augustinian historical time, Jacques Le Goff, Time, Work,
and Culture in the Middle Ages (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1980), 32. On Otto and
Augustinian theology and history, and on the relevant thought of Gerhoch of Reichersberg, see Peter
Claasen, ‘Res Gestae, Universal History, Apocalypse’, in Robert L. Benson and Giles Constable (eds.),
Renaissance and Renewal in the Twelfth Century (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1985), 387–417, here 403
ff. On Otto and Joachim, Reeves, The Influence of Prophecy, 302. On Otto as propagandist for the
empire, Chenu, Nature, 186–96.
32 Also Tacitus, Annals, Book VI.22: ‘Most men . . . cannot part with the belief that each person’s
future is fixed from his very birth’, yet ‘some things happen differently from what has been told
through the impostures of those who describe what they do not know’, which ‘destroys the credit of a
science, clear testimonies to which have been given by past ages and by our own’.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
is not an omen. In the Odyssey Eurymachus observes that ‘lots of birds fly around
under the rays of the sun, and they don’t all mean something’. An oracular vision
‘is usually an indeterminate prediction, or a determinate prediction that leaves it
vitally unclear by what route it will come true’. Only in some scenarios are we ‘told
that a certain thing will happen whatever we do, although it is just the kind of
thing we might hope to avoid by action. Moreover, if efforts to avoid the outcome
helped in fact to bring it about, this is a reliable sign, after the event, that the
supernatural has been at work.’ ‘So far from fatalism ruling out all effective action
of any kind, its characteristic quality, on the contrary, demands that some action
and decision do have an effect. It is not that people’s thoughts and decisions never
make a difference, but that, with regard to the vital outcome, they make no differ-
ence in the long run.’33
Procopius of Caesarea (c.500–c.554), widely viewed as the greatest Byzantine
historian of the sixth century, showed how Christian concepts could slip quite
easily into the structural role vacated either by the will of the gods or the more
arbitrary fortune of the later classical period. The weight of opinion now is that
Procopius was a Christian, though some still see him as a ‘pagan’. While a gulf
separates the religious elements of his works and those of other late antique ‘secu-
lar historians’ on one hand, and the work of ecclesiastical historians of the fourth
and fifth centuries from Eusebius onwards on the other hand, Procopius may
have emulated the ecclesiastical historians’ strategic incorporation of pagan con-
cepts. Part of the interpretative problem is that as a classicizing writer he was
constrained by a Thucydidean idiom and literary style, whilst in the socio-religious
context he was shaped by orthodox Christian views with a Neoplatonic influence.
So fortune, tyche, could sometimes appear to operate separately from God’s influ-
ence and even to work counter to it. On the whole, though, tyche seems either to
have been synonymous with divine will or to have been viewed as an intermedi-
ary servant of that will. The final conception is especially interesting, because it
coheres with the orthodoxy that God does not intervene directly most of the
time, and that ‘his’ will is mysterious. Given this mysteriousness, it was quite con-
sistent at once to submit to divine will but also to rely on one’s virtue (Arete) in
the negotiation of things that seem to be ‘up to us’.34
33 Bernard Williams, Shame and Necessity (Berkeley: University of California Press, 2008), 139–41.
34 On Procopius’s Christianity, Averil Cameron, Procopius and the Sixth Century (Berkeley:
University of California Press, 1985), especially 118–19 on conflicting religious and literary contexts,
and also harmonization of tyche and Christian divinity. Anthony Kaldellis, Procopius of Caesarea
(Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 2004) claims paganism. See especially his pp. 217–18
on tyche coming ‘close to usurping the place of God’, on the tension between god and tyche, as in the
claim that tyche ‘never acts in the interests of justice’. Further to Christianity and the Neoplatonic
colouring that allowed for supernatural entities below god, like demons, see Treadgold, Byzantine
Historians, 210–11 andJames Murray, ‘Procopius and Boethius: Christian Philosophy in the Persian
Wars’, in Christopher Lillington-Martin (ed.), Procopius of Caesarea: Literary and Historical
Interpretations (New York: Routledge, 2018), 104–19, here 106–7. Murray also includes the point
about Arete and the things that are ‘up to us’. On the blending of Christian and pagan motifs, and the
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
hardly ever claimed personally to have foretold anything; they were simply mak-
ing, in retrospect—a fact which they made no effort to conceal—what appeared
to them or others to be reasonable connections between certain significant
events. Preternatural phenomena, after all, were evidence—like documents, or
like the personal testimony of reliable witnesses—and evidence was what a good
historian was meant to be interested in.35
The only real generalization that can be made is that the presence and role of the
divine hand was variable within works and between authors, as the following
rather random assemblage of scholars attests. The Ecclesiastical History of the
English People by the Northumbrian monk Bede (672/3–735) combines many
accounts of miracles—manifestations of the divine in human affairs—with more
mundane explanations of causation and accompanying human responsibility. The
courtier Einhard’s biography of his late patron, Charlemagne, testifies more in
form and rhetorical content to Suetonius’s panegyric to Augustus Caesar than to
any other influence (despite claims to the effect that such influences were min
imal until the Renaissance rediscovered classical literary styles). In Einhard’s Vita
Caroli, composed between 829 and 836, there is certainly no divine controller
directing Charlemagne’s actions.36 This is very different to the hagiographies,
which replicate in microcosm Christian philosophies of the historical process
as they illustrate the saint’s relationship to god.37 William of Tyre, the historian
of the First Crusade and the resulting Latin eastern kingdoms from c.1095 to
1184, drew through Einhard on Suetonius for many of his character sketches.
While his subject matter and his own ecclesiastical standing meant that he gave
God a commanding overall presence in history, William was parsimonious in
debt in this respect to the ecclesiastical historians of the fourth and fifth centuries, from Eusebius to
Theodoret, see Chesnut, The First Christian Histories, 190 n. 77.
3
The ‘Middle Age’
Introduction
This chapter, like all the chapters to one degree or another, is concerned with the
balance of continuity and novelty that shows how arbitrarily delineated a ‘period’
of history is. The balance did not just change over time but also differed between
contemporaries. There was not just one medieval sense of the past or rationale for
studying it, because the ‘medieval mind’ was no more homogeneous than that of
any other time. Sometimes it is difficult to establish what is novel and what con
tinuity, given that on the whole those in search of origins of ‘the modern’ have
started in modernity and worked backwards. That approach can well mean stop
ping when some precursor or ostensible caesura is located, without going yet
further back to ascertain whether the precursor had precursors or the caesura
was real. Since an element of what follows is to date some developments further
back it may be that this work falls into just the same trap, and ignores yet earlier
developments that confound or at least heavily qualify its claims about novelty in
period X. If this process of correction and qualification is taken back as far as it
can go, it may be that there just is not anywhere near as much novelty—whenso
ever dated—as most Histories of historiography suggest, only a changing balance
of emphasis distributed between strands of thought that were there in the earliest
historical accounts. All we are left with are fine judgements about the relative
significance of certain developments, and an awareness that old wine can appear
in new stylistic skins, while the endurance of old forms can conceal novelty in
content.
The first two sections of the chapter illustrate considerable continuity with
elements of late antique and classical historiography in the areas of History as
Identity, History as Memorialization, and History as Lesson. Remaining sections
show that within historically oriented medieval thought there were three tenden
cies for which the medieval world is not generally renowned: the conceptualization
of human cultural difference over time, with its associations of an awareness of
anachronism and accompanying debates over the relevance of the past to the
present; a literal sense of the past, with its associations of specificity and accuracy;
and the capacity for often quite sophisticated source criticism. This is not to say
that such tendencies denoted dominant trends, because dominance is relative to
interest, and interests varied.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
Where the ancient Greeks had chronographies, Christian civilization, like pre-
Christian Rome, had annals. We are straight into muddy terminological waters
because at varying points, late antique (like Cassiodorus), medieval, and modern
writers have distinguished in different ways between annals, chronicles, and
Histories. For some, annals and chronicles were identical, with both terms being
used for long lists of yearly dates next to some of which successive, mostly
anonymous scribes listed events in a pro forma fashion. However, especially in the
1 For some of the new range see the early chapters of Sharon Dael, Alison Williams Lewin, and
Duane J. Osheim (eds.), Chronicling History (Pennsylvania: Pennsylvania State University Press,
2007). For the inheritance from classical antiquity and the patristic age, Shami Ghosh, Writing the
Barbarian Past: Studies in Early Medieval Historical Narrative (Leiden: Brill, 2016), 27–38.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
first half of the second millennium ce, the kind of works we are now apt to term
Histories—substantial prose accounts recounting some event or development
or polity—were also apt to be called chronicles by their authors. The definitional
blur is appropriate because the genres were often far from distinct, but the initial
focus is on the simplest, ‘ideal type’ annal form.
In a faulty ‘orthodox view’, ‘the development of early medieval historical forms
[is] an evolutionary process in which the annal is forever portrayed as a primitive
specimen’.2 To be sure, at first glance one can imagine why uninitiated contem
porary readers would find bewildering entries like that for 776 in the Anglo-Saxon
Chronicle: ‘Here a red sign of Christ appeared in the heavens after the sun’s set
ting. And that year the Mercians and the inhabitants of Kent fought at Otford;
and snakes were seen extraordinarily in the land of the South Saxons [Sussex].’ It
does seem curious that serpents and skies merit more attention than the outcome
of the battle at Otford. Such laconic, apparently disconnected entries can appear
even for the first year of any given annal, where one might expect some sort of
introduction. These entries would fit only the most expansive definitions of a nar
rative and adding consecutive ones together might well not make any difference
given that yet other ostensibly disconnected issues were apt to be discussed in
following years, often with no attempt to refer to previous entries. Furthermore,
the annal has no proper ending in the sense of a conclusion, thus no ostensible
overall explanatory purpose.3
The first thing to be said to redress misunderstandings is that snakes and heav
enly phenomena were presumed to have meaning, even if the chroniclers were
not certain what the meaning was. In any case such symbols do not dominate the
majority of annal entries, and are absent from many. Nor are all entries as terse as
the Anglo-Saxon Chronicle’s for 776. Different, even if now unknown, authors
within the same series could bring their own styles. Sometimes, especially when
working backwards to fill in years from before the beginning of their own contri
butions, as was the case with all of the Anglo-Saxon Chronicle’s entries for before
the end of the ninth century, the recorders import prose wholesale from more
‘conventionally’ historical accounts, or even from sagas. Eyewitness accounts are
occasionally included. And manifestly some annalists refused to be constrained
by the small, single-line spaces originally drawn on the manuscripts.4 The follow
ing is from the entry for 858 in the Annales Fuldenses, the Annals of Fulda,
2 Sarah Foot, ‘Finding the Meaning of Form: Narrative in Annals and Chronicles’, in Nancy Partner
(ed.), Writing Medieval History (London: Hodder Arnold, 2005), 88–108, here 93.
3 Discussion of the 776 entry and the annals form in Foot, ‘Finding the Meaning of Form’, 88 ff.; the
entry itself as used here is taken from the slightly different translation in The Anglo-Saxon Chronicles,
ed. Michael Swanton (London: Phoenix, 2000), 50.
4 Swanton, ‘Introduction’ to his edition of the Anglo-Saxon Chronicles, pp. xi–xxxv, here pp. xvi–xviii;
Cecily Clark, ‘The Narrative Mode of the Anglo-Saxon Chronicle before the Conquest’, in Peter
Clemoes and Kathleen Hughes (eds.), England Before the Conquest: Studies in Primary Sources
Presented to Dorothy Whitelock (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1971), 215–35. For much
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
that concerned the Kingdom of the East Franks, one of the portions of the
now-divided Carolingian empire. It concerns the background to the invasion of
West Francia by East Francian King Louis the German (Louis II). I did not choose
it quite at random, but nonetheless there are enough entries of similar quality
that it cannot be said to be unrepresentative of the Annals:
In July, after the armies had been gathered together and formed up and were
about to set out, suddenly the king [Louis] was burdened with a great weight of
troubles. For messengers came from the west, Abbot Adalhard and Count Odo,
asking him to comfort with his presence a people sore pressed and in peril. If he
did not do this swiftly and they were denied hope of liberation at his hands, they
would have to seek protection from the pagans with great danger to the Christian
religion, since they could not get it from their lawful and orthodox lords. They
declared that they could no longer bear the tyranny of Charles [‘the Bald’].
Anything that was left to them, after the pagans from outside had plundered,
enslaved, killed and sold them off without even a show of resistance being made
to them, the king destroyed from within with his evil savagery. There was now no
one left in the whole people who still believed his promises or oaths, and all
despaired of his good faith. Hearing these things, the king was very disturbed,
and found himself in a dilemma. If he acceded to the request of the people, he
would have to move against his brother, which would be wicked. If, however,
he spared his brother, he would have to turn back from liberating the people in
danger, which would be equally wicked. Besides this there was the not negligible
consideration that the people in general would suspect that all that was being
done in this matter was not done out of concern for the people’s well-being but
simply out of a desire to extend his kingdom, although the matter was quite dif
ferent from the vulgar opinion, as all those who knew of the king’s plans truly
testify. Thus placed beneath a weight of cares, he at length agreed to the advice of
his wise men and relied on the purity of his conscience, preferring to act for the
good of many rather than in agreement with the obstinacy of one man. He
yielded to the prayers of the legates and promised according to the people’s wishes
that with God’s help he would come to those who longed for his presence.5
Here we have the ingredients of an explanatory narrative that is internal to, and
largely independent of, the overall form of the annal as such.6 The same applies to
the same point as regards another set, see the editor’s introduction, Annals of St-Bertin ed. Janet
Nelson (Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1991), 1–19, here 1–2.
5 The Annals of Fulda, ed. Timothy Reuter (Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1992), 41–2
(year 858).
6 The idea of narrative internal to and separable from the annal as a whole needs to be taken into
account in assessing the credence of Hayden White’s claim that annals can have no plot because they
have no meaning-revealing ending: White, The Content of the Form, 20–1.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
many lengthy accounts of events that occurred within the parameters of a year.
The 858 narrative, written with due literary concern, tells of how a king came to a
decision to move against his brother in light of weighing moral issues and likely
outcomes. While Louis supposedly acts in the interests of the Christian religion
and the ‘good of many’, there is no divine determinism and no divine interven
tion, only hope for God’s endorsement of a decision already made, which is a
common feature of such accounts.
Sometimes in the annals, as in Sulpicius Severus’s hagiographic Life of Martin
(c.397), we see allusions the like of which the late antique secular historians were
proud: Sallust and Tacitus are invoked en passant.7 However ‘Christian’ the author
or the story, throughout the medieval world it would continue to be acceptable to
invoke classical authors and events from classical antiquity, as when the twelfth-
century historian of the crusades Bishop Guibert de Nogent used analogies with
the Trojan War.
Further to the Roman connection, the works of Sallust, Tacitus, and Livy all
corresponded more or less obviously to the year-by-year annalistic form, despite
the sometime mockery of this convention by Cato and Cicero. Thus within a few
pages, amidst some protracted descriptions of the events of particular years,
Livy’s History of Rome from its Foundation 2.15–2.19, moves through a number of
consular years in swift succession: ‘The consuls for the following year were
Marcus Valerius and Publius Postumius. During the year there were successful
operations against the Sabines . . .’; ‘The consuls of the following year, Opiter
Verginius and Spurius Cassius, proceeded at once to attempt the reduction of
Pometia . . .’; ‘In the following year Postumus Cominius and Titus Lartius were
elected consults’; ‘Nothing of importance occurred the following year, when the
consuls were Servius Sulpicius and Manlius Tullius; but the year after that, when
Titus Aebutius and Caius Vetusius were in office, saw the siege of Fidenae, the
capture of Crustumeria, and the secession of Praeneste from the Latins to Rome.’8
Organizationally speaking, such was the case with very many Histories since the
annalistic form had been pioneered in prose in the Annales of Calpurnius Piso
(born c.180 bce, consul 133 bce), and some of the reasons for the organization
are closely analogous to some of the Christian reasons.9 These commonalities are
especially noteworthy in anticipation of the next chapter, and the formative
impact on ‘Renaissance’ historiography of Livy and Tacitus, which is the sort of
influence so often contrasted to that of Christian chronicle.
7 e.g. Annals of Fulda, 59 (year 869), 78 (year 875). On the literary qualities of the Annals and the
absence of supernatural overtones, see Timothy Reuter’s introduction to the Annals, 1–14. On
Sulpicius Severus see Sulpicius Severus’ Vita Martini, ed. Philip Burton (Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 2017).
8 At pp. 106–9 of de Sélincourt’s translation, Livy, The Early History of Rome.
9 Walter, ‘Annales and Analysis’, 284–7 on Roman reasons, including reference to similarities in
content like mention of omens.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
The formal similarities between the Roman works and Christian annals suggests
that on one axis of comparison we are better off conceiving of a continuum from
the sparsest annal on one end to the most obviously History-like work at the
other end. For a Christian example around a mid-point on this continuum, con
sider but the most important single source about the Merovingian dynasty up to
the 590s, the Ten Books of Histories, a.k.a. The History of the Franks, by Gregory
of Tours (538–95). Its essays focus especially on the Christianization of Gaul
that had begun in the third century, then the conversion to Nicene (‘Catholic’)
Christianity of Clovis I in 496, then the history of Merovingian rule in the
Frankish empire that Clovis in particular had expanded.10 Book V is illustrative.
A number of its chapters seem like random interspersions linked to others by
nothing other than their simultaneity (though had they been written in classical
antiquity we might describe this feature as a rhetorically attractive break from
dense narrative11). So we have: ‘6. In this year [576], the year in which Sigibert
died and his son Childebert began to reign, many miraculous cures were per
formed at the tomb of saint Martin . . .’; ‘7. I must now record the names of the
men who were summoned home by God this year . . .’; ‘11. Since our God is ever
willing to give glory to His bishops, I will tell you what happened this year to the
Jews in Clermont-Ferrand . . .’ . But we also have: ‘13. I must now return to my
subject’, with that subject being the major theme of the book, which concerns
developments in the dynasty relating to the kings Childebert and Chilperic.12
Another example is Part I of the sermon De Excidio et Conquestu Britanniae,
The Ruin and Conquest of Britain, written by the British monk Gildas at some
point in the first half of the sixth century. This relatively short account is polem
ical in its denunciation of the leaders of the Britons, yet it is nonetheless ‘properly
historical’ in its presentation of an extended account purporting to provide a lit
eral explanation of a real set of developments. It deals with the period from the
Roman conquest to the Roman departure and then the parlous state depicted in
Gildas’s present, as the post-Roman Britons were engaged in warfare with Picts
and then the ultimately victorious Saxons.13 Gildas was not England’s Gregory,
however; Bede (c.672–735) was. He completed his Ecclesiastical History of the
English People in 731, and with it popularized the dating system of the Anno
10 Gregory of Tours, History of the Franks, ed. Lewis Thorpe (London: Penguin, 1974).
11 Note that while on one hand the yearly annalistic structure of (for example) Livy might mean it
was easier to address the relationship between simultaneous events in multiple location (Walter,
‘Annales and Analysis’, 286), it can also hinder ‘setting out a logical sequence of events; [Livy’s] reader
sometimes feels as though he were reading a serial novel by Dickens, where several groups of characters
all have to have their quote in each new instalment, and must keep turning back to remind himself
how things stood. Sometimes we cannot see the wood for the trees.’ Betty Radice, ‘Introduction’ to
Livy, The War with Hannibal, trans. Aubrey de Sélincourt (London: Penguin, 1987), 7–22, here 12–13.
12 Walter, ‘Annales and Analysis’, 263–7.
13 Gildas, The Ruin of Britain, Fragments from Lost Letters, The Penitential, Together with the Lorica
of Gildas, ed. Hugh Williams (London: Bedford Press, 1899); for analysis, Karen George, Gildas’s De
Excidio Britonum and the Early British Church (Woodbridge: Boydell, 2009).
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
Domini (ad) era, which in this book and elsewhere now is called the Common
Era (ce).14 Bede is relevant in illustrating that the same author could produce
works at different points on the History–annal continuum. He compiled a major
chronographic account, De ratione temporum, as well as a multi-book prose
History, much as had Eusebius, whose Historia Ecclesiastica inspired Bede’s title,
and whose Chronicon had been such a major influence on the proliferation of
annals from the fourth century.
Above all, even if elaborate prose entries did not exist, and all annals comprised
the barest and most laconic recordings, the progressivist view would still be
wrong in seeing these works as rude approximations to later, ‘proper’ History.
Equally, the intellectual historian Hayden White, while correct in rejecting the
view of the annals as an ‘infantile’ form of discourse, was incorrect, at least in one
important sense, in his alternative assessment. He came to see annals as a sort of
competitor to ‘proper History’, and possibly a superior one at that given that, in
his view, Histories impose a spurious continuity by their linkage of events across
time whereas the annals reflect and encourage a vision of discontinuity attendant
upon a sensibility of the sublime, with any order as there might be in the world of
events inaccessible to human cognition.15 White’s view is already weakened by
entries such as that in the Fulda annals of 858, which display ‘proper’ Histories,
meaning complete if brief narratives, within a particular year, but viewing the
annal form as a whole—rather than any given entry—through either the prism of
immature History or as a competitor to it in its grasp of the nature of ‘reality’ in
the earthly realm obscures a major function. The open-endedness of the annals is
a strong clue here, because of the association with ongoing chronology. The dates
are markers on a continuum that began with the incarnation and continues until
the end of all earthly affairs. The years are a story in themselves, as they had been
for Hecataeus, the Atthidographers, and the Roman annalists.16 What differs is
the biblical timeline and the religious lineage, but the purpose and form of the
annal genre are similar. For the Roman annalists, the time was Roman, traceable
to Rome’s deep origins, dictated to Rome’s dominions and associated with succes
sive annual magistracies who at once embodied and vouchsafed freedom for the
citizenry. The annalistic form was associated with the Roman tradition since
Fabius Pictor of writing ab urbe condita, from the foundation of the city, and drew
in turn on the Greek chronographic project. The name Annals, as in Tacitus’s
work, links the historian’s libri annales with the tabula annalis, annual pontifical
14 The ad system was invented by Dionysius Exiguus (c.470–544) though Eusebius’s chronologies
were an important step in that direction. Note that Dionysius used it to identify Easters in Easter
tables. One of the tributary origins of the Christian annals was probably marginal notes in Easter tables,
which helps explain why the annal entries were often small, especially early on.
15 White, Content of the Form, chs. 1–3, ‘infantile’ at 9.
16 This being a major argument of Foot, ‘Finding the Meaning of Form’.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
lists of important events ‘attested for pre-literary sacred record keeping’.17 For the
Christians Christ’s birth is one obvious point of originary interest, the creation
another. Thus, differing slightly from Julius Africanus’s estimates, the 6 bce entry
of the Anglo-Saxon Chronicle records that 5,200 years have passed since the
beginning of the world, and occasionally thereafter the reader is reminded of the
current tally.
Annals also had a political role for Christian rulers, as they did for Rome. They
provided historical or historio-religious legitimation, with genealogical and fig
ural functions intertwined.18 Wars and the deaths of kings and bishops are a regu
lar feature. The marking of holy days gives a sense of reassuring continuity
alongside linear unfolding (much the same had been achieved in Roman annals
by recounting rituals like consular inauguration, the priests’ work of expiation,
and sacrifices19), and serves to indicate the piety of favoured subjects, namely
royal families. The Royal Frankish Annals of 741–829—predecessor of the Annals
of Fulda, though covering the whole of the Carolingian empire—constitute a
story of the Frankish people since the death of Charles Martel, as embodied in the
Carolingian dynasty. It is these rulers and their people who become associated
with the temporal framework measured from the incarnation, and thus associ
ated with God’s design.20
The precise proportions of political and religious legitimation could vary. If the
Royal Frankish Annals constitute an especially clear-cut example of annal-writing
as a vehicle for expressions of the identity of a ‘national’ people, it is a matter of
debate as to the role of the Anglo-Saxon Chronicle vis-à-vis the Angelcynn, i.e. the
English. The Anglo-Saxon Chronicle was begun in the early 890s but recorded
back to 60 bce and the advent of the Romans, and continued to be updated in one
version well into the twelfth century. Probably initiated under the auspices of
17 On which, including the quotation, see Timpe, ‘Memoria and Historiography in Rome’, 163–4.
Walter, ‘Annales and Analysis’, 286–7 considers additional factors, including the relation to consular
years and elections. (Note that even under the principate elections were still held for the key magis
tracies.) Moreover while Tacitus wrote with reference to imperial reigns, he also used consular
years—ibid. 284–5.
18 On the figural element of the History of the Franks, Martin Heinzelmann, Gregory of Tours:
History and Society in the Sixth Century (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001).
19 Walter, ‘Annales and Analysis’, 286.
20 For such reasons one needs to take issue with White (Content of the Form, 8) when he writes of
the Anni Domini in the left-hand column of most annals that ‘We should not too quickly refer the
meaning of the text to the mythic framework it invokes by designating the “years” as being “of the
Lord”, for these “years” have a regularity that the Christian mythos, with its hypotactical ordering of
the events it comprises (Creation, Fall, Incarnation, Resurrection, Second Coming’), does not pos
sess. The regularity of the calendar signals the “realism” of the account, its intention to deal in real
rather than imaginary events. The calendar locates events, not in the time of eternity [what, one asks
of the point of departure implicit in ‘Anno Domini’?], not in kairotic time, but in chronological time,
in time as it is humanly experienced.’ To reiterate the point of the main text here and of Foot, ‘Finding
the Meaning of Form’, what is inconvenient for White’s argument is the way that earthly political
concerns can fuse with concerns about divine legitimation through the association of temporal and
kairotic time.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
Alfred the Great, it was the first effectively continuous History in the vernacular
(Old English) of any European population group. In one school of thought the
Chronicle illustrated the agenda of unifying Anglo-Saxon ‘England’ out of its
diverse kingdoms.21 The alternative view is that while the Chronicle was clearly
keen on showing the triumph of the West Saxon dynasty from which Alfred came,
it was less concerned with promoting a vision of pan-English unity.22 If the latter
view is correct then it highlights a tension with Bede’s eighth-century vision of a
unified England. Now for Bede, properly observed Christianity was the force that
would unify all the inhabitants of the island.23 Indeed since his loyalties finally lay
with Rome, the real significance of the deeds of kings was tied up with conversion
to and maintenance of a disciplined Roman Christianity. For kings themselves,
and for many of their chroniclers, the dictates of the Church were not insignifi
cant but they were not the only major considerations. Looking forwards, for
twelfth-century historians like Henry of Huntingdon, William of Malmesbury,
and Geoffrey of Monmouth, the kings were at the centre of the picture as the
genealogical, even genetic thread linking the state through history.24
When thinking of biological connections, we should not allow accounts of the
modern construction of nationhood and the modern provenance of biological
racism to blind us to earlier iterations of nation and race: religious and civili
zational genealogies might well be fused with kinship associations of a more
genetic type. Origines gentium, tales of the foundational moment of discrete
groups, were known in post-Roman Europe from the sixth century at the latest.
Along with the Old Testament, which was a repository of inspiration in early
medieval Europe given the story of the flight of the tribes of Israel from Egypt,
the fall of Troy inspired tales of ethnogenesis as the result of the defeat and dis
persal of a people, with the hope of redemptive triumph as a new Rome.25 More
than this, Trojan antecedence was claimed for some non-Roman peoples,26 and
would continue to be in certain circles for the best part of a thousand years
21 Foot, ‘Finding the Meaning of Form’, 96–102; Sarah Foot, ‘The Making of Angelcynn: English
Identity before the Norman Conquest’, Transactions of the Royal Historical Society, 6th ser. 6 (1996),
25–49. Swanton, ‘Introduction’, p. xx. Further on the issue of national consciousness, Patrick Wormald,
‘Engla Lond: The Making of an Allegiance’, Journal of Historical Sociology, 7:1 (1994), 1–24.
22 The most substantial critique of the Angelcynn argument is George Molyneaux, The Formation of
the English Kingdom in the Tenth Century (Oxford: Oxford University 2015), ch. 5, esp. pp. 201–6, with
a salient contrast on p. 206 to the Royal Frankish Annals.
23 Bede, Ecclesiastical History of the English People, ed. Leo Sherley-Price and D. H. Farmer
(London: Penguin, 1990). On unity from diversity, see Farmer’s introduction, 19–38, here 27; Foot,
‘Finding the Meaning’, 100–1.
24 Given-Wilson, Chronicles, 163–4.
25 Len Scales, ‘Central and Late Medieval Europe’, in Donald Bloxham and A. Dirk Moses (eds.),
The Oxford Handbook of Genocide Studies (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010), 280–303, here
284–5; Charles F. Briggs, The Body Broken: Medieval Europe, 1300–1520 (London: Routledge 2011),
284; Joseph H. Lynch and Phillip C. Adamo, The Medieval Church (London: Routledge, 2014), 206–7.
26 Rosamond McKitterick, History and Memory in the Carolingian World (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2004), 7–8, 208–9; Gabrielle M. Spiegel, The Past as Text: The Theory and Practice of
Medieval Historiography (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1997), 96–7, 106.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
thereafter. Important in the Frankish embrace of the Trojan myth was quite
widespread embrace of the Chronicle of Fredegar, which did for a people what the
Atthidographers did for cities.
As is common in the genre, the Fredegar chronicle (or annal, depending on
precise definition) accepted and continued earlier chronicles, whose authors had
done the same in their turn. Eusebius had been translated and continued by
Jerome, who was built on by Hydatius and Gregory, who were then incorporated
alongside other earlier chronicles into the Chronicle of Fredegar. Just as interesting
as the entries after Gregory’s account and up to 642 are the ‘interpolations’ or
additions. In this case the additions made to the incorporated chronicles of the
Liber Generationis, Jerome, and Hydatius are unsourced. They served to fuse
Judeo-Christian and classical-Trojan ancestry, whereas Gregory had only estab
lished the former lineage. The Trojan King Priam is depicted as the first king of
the Franks, himself descended from one of Noah’s three sons, Japeth. The Trojans
supposedly split into two major groups of which one, the Frigii, under King
Francio, ended up between the Rhine and the Danube, where, along with the
Saxons, they provided the only successful resistance against the Romans.
Ultimately the author of the additions established the harmony of kinship
between Franks and Latins by claiming Friga, of Priam’s house, as the brother of
Aeneas. Thus the Franks gained historical independence amongst, but also con
nection to, the other major influences in Christendom, namely the Papacy and
Byzantium. Modifications to established chronicle narratives build a ‘bridge
between universal history into which Frankish matter is interpolated and
Frankish history into which universal matter is interpolated’. The ego of the
Franks was stroked. ‘Fredegar’ promoted the gens Francorum, via its elite, to the
status of binding element in the Merovingian regnum of the time, bringing
together political and ethnic considerations.27
Complex prose rarely falling into one genre alone, many of the Histories with a
genealogical identity function also had an exemplary purpose. In the use of
27 J. M. Wallace-Hadrill, ‘Fredegar and the History of France’, Bulletin of the John Rylands Library,
40 (1958), 527–50, quote from 539; 97–114; Ghosh, Writing the Barbarian Past, 97–114; Robert
Flierman, Saxon Identities, ad 150–900 (London: Bloomsbury, 2017), 74–5. For an extensive recent
treatment of Fredegar in connection with the universal History and ethnicity questions, see Helmut
Reimitz, History, Frankish Identity and the Framing of Western Ethnicity (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2015), ch. 7, especially p. 174 to the effect that the Fredegar chroniclers ‘were aiming
to underscore the fact that the name of the Franks did not represent a local identity or a single region
at the edge of the regnum. It stands for the governing class, which from the start had preserved the
destiny and continuity of the gens Francorum and bound the different areas and populations of this
regnum to each other.’
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
And so on and so forth, through the ‘middle ages’ and beyond. Writing at the close
of a fourteenth century riven with Anglo-French conflict, Jean Froissart provided
the standard justification for his endeavour: the hope ‘that the h onourable enter
prises, noble adventures and deeds of arms which took place during the wars waged
by France and England should be fittingly related and preserved for posterity, so that
brave men should be inspired thereby to follow such examples’.32
With the continued deployment of History as Lesson came the familiar range
of levels of truth and meaning:
The words are those of historian Chris Given-Wilson. His work on medieval
chronicles makes important contrasts between what medieval chroniclers did and
modern conceptions of History. Accordingly, implied in the second half of Given-
Wilson’s passage is a moral explanation for success, which contains a ‘universal
truth’ about fighting battles as much as a point about any particular battle. The
‘classical’ concept of truth as plausibility (see p. 27) was also deployed in medieval
chronicles, as for example by the Thucydidean use of invented speeches.34
Medieval historians also followed their classical forebears in parading their
qualifications as authorities about the past in order to impart the quality of trust
worthiness to their accounts. Sometimes this was achieved by the rhetorical device
of admitting ignorance. Eyewitness testimony—of the author or suitably accredited
informants—remained of great importance throughout the middle ages, though
the bureaucratic revolution of the central middle ages provided a larger supply of
written records than hitherto and produced a number of historians who inserted
reference to documentary sources as well as other Histories into their text. A
position of giving credence to earlier accounts appears to have been the default
one, as with Herodotus vis-à-vis orally transmitted memory, and sometimes truth
was actually conceived as the faithfulness of one text to another, earlier one.35
Significant continuity across the centuries can also be traced in the sex of most
historians and the sexed and gendered nature of their subject matter. Nevertheless,
beside wealthy women patrons of male historians there were a few renowned
female scholars like the Ottonian Hrotsvitha of Gandersheim (c.935–c.1002),
author of a History of the Ottonian dynasty up to 965 and a History of the
Gandersheim house monastery, and, assuming she actually wrote what is attrib
uted to her, the Byzantine Anna Komnēnē (1083–1153).36 Christine de Pizan’s
Book of the City of Ladies (1405), a study of exemplary female lives drawn from
across time and from myth, was in its subject-matter an exception to a pretty firm
rule, though not unprecedented: she took inspiration from Giovanni Boccaccio’s
Concerning Famous Women (composed 1361–2), most of whose biographical
subjects came from the history and mythology of classical antiquity. Meanwhile
even if chroniclers were reluctant to identify them as eyewitness informants, it is
probable that not a few women nonetheless featured in that capacity.37
Of broader sociological import in the relationship between present and past
was the involvement of many more women and girls in a range of day-to-day
memorial practices, such as preserving family genealogical information or par
ticipating in communal exercises, like the ninth-century dancers of the farandole
to celebrate the gesta of the likes of King Clothar II and Bishop Faro of Meaux two
centuries earlier.38 In Carolingian society as in others, women, especially of the
elite, were not merely supposed to pass on instruction but were also expected to
embody moral examples in their everyday lives, partly because of gendered doc
trines stemming from Jerome, partly because they had wider access than did
clerics to other women, children, and social ‘inferiors’. At once this role enhanced
their social significance and opened them further to criticism should they be
perceived to fall short.39
Illiterate populaces as a whole were likely to encounter some version of the past
via the compendia of exempla used for sermons by preachers who realized the
efficacy of philosophy by example.40 For the commonality, the orally transmitted
epics also provided a storehouse of metaphors just as well stocked as the scrip
tures and the hagiographies of saintly lives. The composition of these popular
chansons de geste was not always insulated from the officially sanctioned charters
and chronicles.41
As for the literate orders, while a healthy circulation of undetected documen
tary forgeries points to the limits of a certain sort of critical concern, this does not
The Frankish World, 750–900 (London: Hambledon Press, 1996), ch. 11. In terms of focus on women
in historically minded works, it is interesting that pictorial miniatures in a number of late medieval
vernacularizations of the Aeneid depict women—Dido, Camilla—in ways that challenge conventional
gender roles: Christopher Baswell, Virgil in Medieval England (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1995), 25–8.
detract from the historically oriented belief system that the stories sustained.
Moreover there is evidence that when it really mattered to them, clerics were
competent in distinguishing forgeries, just as they were in, for instance, question
ing the Frankish myth of Trojan antecedence or rejecting stories about the legend
ary Merlin.42 Geoffrey of Monmouth’s grand fantasy Historia Regum Britannie
(1136), History of the Kings of Britain, which was replete with tales of Merlin,
Kings Arthur and Lear, and ‘Old King Cole’, back to the arrival of the mythical
Trojan Brutus in the twelfth century bce, met with specialist scepticism within a
few decades. Nonetheless, its main lines of interpretation were absorbed into col
lective historical memory and resurfaced in subsequent Histories, partly because
it provided a useful origin story and chimed with general assumptions about the
origins of peoples in principle, partly because it fitted with prevailing literary
fashion and helped idealize the present in the same manner as it did the past.43
Especially when it came to allegorical or analogical reading, it was not neces
sarily a question of medieval people’s lacking a sense of the past’s difference, or
being blind to matters of source criticism. Rather, such interpretative practices
were oriented to the historian’s and reader’s self-understanding as actors in the
present. The point of allegorical reading was to reveal the eternal or necessary
beneath the chaff of the contingent; Aristotle’s criticism of History as opposed to
poetry was thereby rebutted. The imagery is that of the linguist rendering some
thing from a foreign or archaic idiom into the language of the present in order to
preserve what merited preservation. Such a conception still had its adherents
until at least into the eighteenth century, with the philosopher-historian Henry
St John, Viscount Bolingbroke (1678–1751) citing the poet Nicolas Boileau-
Despréaux (1636–1711) on the art of translation:
42 McKitterick, Carolingian World, 25, 210. On forgery detection and myth criticism, Andrew
Jotischky, The Carmelites and Antiquity: Mendicants and their Pasts in the Middle Ages (Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 2002), 319–20; Damian-Grint, New Historians, 206.
43 Given-Wilson, Chronicles, 3–6; Damian-Grint, New Historians, 195–6.
44 Henry St John, Lord Viscount Bolingbroke, Letters on the Study and Use of History (London:
T. Cadell, 1779), 51.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
45 Wendy Olmstead, Rhetoric: An Historical Introduction (Oxford: Blackwell, 2006), 54–5; on the
medieval inheritance of the classical device of topoi, see Justin Lake (ed.), Prologues to Ancient and
Medieval History: A Reader (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 2013), pp. xiii–xiv.
46 Monika Otter, Inventiones: Fiction and Referentiality in Twelfth-Century English Historical
Writing (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1996).
47 Janet Coleman, Ancient and Medieval Memories: Studies in the Reconstruction of the Past
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005), 582.
48 These were vernacular translations of the chronicles produced in Latin by the monks of Saint-
Denis. In the thirteenth century the monks were official historiographers to the French monarchy.
49 Hans-Werner Goetz, Geschichtsschreibung und Geschichtsbewußtsein im hohen Mittelalter
(Berlin: Orbis mediaevalis, 1999); cf. Bernard Guenée, Histoire et culture historique dans l’Occident
médiéval (Paris: Aubier Montaigne, 1980), especially ch. 8. See also Hans-Werner Goetz, Die
Geschichtstheologie des Orosius (Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, 1980). On Notre
Dame and the Grandes Chroniques see Spiegel, The Past as Text, 105–7.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
We owe the stereotype of the ‘middle ages’, as we owe the epithet itself, to the
‘Renaissance’, which was in turn a term coined by Jules Michelet in the nineteenth
century that captured the sense among sixteenth-century Italians of there having
been in recent centuries a rinascita or rebirth of learning and artistic skill that
harked back to the classical past. Among the motivations of a few notable inhabit
ants of the fourteenth and fifteenth centuries to reinvent their present we might
count disillusion in the face of protracted warfare, long-term conflict between
papacy and Holy Roman empire, papal scandal and the Great Schism of 1378–1417,
and the Black Death—a series of crises whose cumulative force ultimately
exceeded the cohesive power of the metaphor of the body of Christ that notion
ally held Christendom together. ‘Italian’ states in particular were set at odds from
the twelfth century in the battle between Guelphs and Ghibellines and competing
factions within those states.
An especially famous expression of disaffection with elements of the prevailing
culture was the ‘Letter to Posterity’ of Boccaccio’s older contemporary Petrarch
(1304–74), who has variously been dubbed ‘the first modern man of letters’, ‘the
first modern writer of autobiography’, and, almost inevitably, ‘the first modern
man’. He wrote:
Among the many subjects which interested me, I dwelt especially upon antiquity,
for our own age has always repelled me, so that, had it not been for the love of
those dear to me, I should have preferred to have been born in any other period
50 Ibid.184.
51 Jay Winter, ‘Museums and the Representation of War’, Museum and Society, 10:3 (2012), 150–63.
On heritage see Lowenthal, The Past is a Foreign Country and The Heritage Crusade.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
than our own. In order to forget my own time, I have constantly striven to place
myself in spirit in other ages, and consequently I delighted in history.
Petrarch has also been called the first modern tourist, which may allude to the
capacity to objectify his world about him as if a tourist rather than an indigene. It
also concerns his trading in the metaphorical as well as literal dimensions of
travel, as a wide-ranging wanderer in time and space.52 But whatever the innov
ations of Renaissance humanism, European self-reflection was aided by events
that can only be excluded from the definition of ‘medieval’ by sleight of hand.
Let us mention the ‘twelfth-century Renaissance’, of which the monastic ‘refor
mation’ of that century was an integral part, and before that the ‘Carolingian
renaissance’ of the eighth and ninth centuries. As the Carolingian renaissance had
synthesized aspects of Roman, Christian, and Germanic tradition for its own pur
poses, restored Latin as a language of literature, and preserved much Roman
prose and poetry in its copying-schools, so the twelfth-century Renaissance leant
on the recovery of more of Aristotle’s oeuvre, as well as borrowings from Arabic
mathematics, medicine, and astronomy with their Platonic influence. Under
some of these influences nature could be ‘read’ as a self-sufficient, seamless ‘text’
of physical revelation with its own internal, horizontal relations, as opposed or in
addition to the vertical relations stressed in the patristic approach as it linked
natural entities to higher spiritual truths.53
The sense of secular periodization that broke up the flow of the chronicler’s
continuous time is famously attributed to the post-Petrarchian Renaissance,54
though the idea of a ‘middle age’ (medium aevum, Mittelalter) may have been
popularized more by sixteenth-century Lutherans, especially Philip Melanchthon,
to stigmatize the period between their present and a purer, pre-medieval
Christianity, thereby distinguishing between the papacy that they disliked and the
early church.55 Whatever the novelty of this particular periodization, tripartite
52 Petrarch passage from Kenneth R. Bartlett (ed.), The Civilization of the Italian Renaissance:
A Sourcebook (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 2011), 28. For the epithets, and an effective
endorsement of them, see Arthur Augustus Tilley, The Dawn of the French Renaissance (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1968), 4. For the tourism issue, see Henk van Oort, The Inner Rainbow:
An Illustrated History of Human Consciousness (Sussex: Temple Lodge, 2014), 56–7 and
Theodore J. Cachey, Jr, ‘Petrarchan Cartographic Writing’, in Stephen Gersh and Bert Roest (eds.),
Medieval and Renaissance Humanism: Rhetoric, Representation and Reform (Leiden: Brill, 2003),
73–92, here 74 ff.
53 Charles Homer Haskins, The Renaissance of the Twelfth Century (Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press, 1927). On the hermeneutic implications, Peter Harrison, The Bible, Protestantism,
and the Rise of Natural Science (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998). See also the useful
review of this book by James Altena, ‘Secular Hermeneutics’, Touchstone 14:6 (2001), 50–5, some of
which I have paraphrased here.
54 From at least Wallace K. Ferguson, The Renaissance in Historical Thought (New York: Houghton
Mifflin, 1948) onwards.
55 Harold J. Berman, Law and Revolution II: The Impact of the Protestant Reformations on the
Western Legal Tradition (Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press, 2003), 22.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
who were engaged in the struggle. And apart from this they were so indifferent
in their practice of archery that they drew the bowstring only to the breast, so
that the missile sent forth was naturally impotent and harmless to those whom it
hit. Such, it is evident, was the archery of the past. But the bowmen of the pre
sent time go into battle wearing corselets and fitted out with greaves which
extend up to the knee. From the right side hang their arrows, from the other the
sword. And there are some who have a spear also attached to them and, at the
shoulders, a sort of small shield without a grip, such as to cover the region of
the face and neck. They are expert horsemen, and are able without difficulty
to direct their bows to either side while riding at full speed, and to shoot an
opponent whether in pursuit or in flight. They draw the bowstring along by the
forehead about opposite the right ear, thereby charging the arrow with such an
impetus as to kill whoever stands in the way, shield and corselet alike having no
power to check its force. Still there are those who take into consideration none
of these things, who reverence and worship the ancient times, and give no credit
to modern improvements.57
So much for the elucidation of change via content; Procopius’s work made the
same point by form, in much the same way as earlier Atticists like Cassius Dio.
Procopius was careful not to confuse with terms like ekklesia, given its earlier
Athenian meaning, when he was talking about a Christian church building.
Ironically, here, his use of the antiquated ‘high style’ of Attic Greek, as exempli
fied in Thucydides, at once put him at a disadvantage in terms of communicating
with a contemporary audience with a somewhat differing grammar and vocabu
lary, and kept him and the audience attuned to the fact of the changing referents
of certain linguistic signifiers by a forced self-distancing from the present. So we
have ‘one of the priests whom they call “bishops” ’, and so forth. While it modified
itself somewhat, this tradition of writing endured to the very end of the Byzantine
empire.58
Procopius’s content and form pose problems for a common modern concep
tion of the medieval sense of the past, a conception illustrated by Reinhard
Koselleck’s reflections on Albrecht Altdorfer’s 1529 painting Alexanderschlacht,
which depicted the Battle of Issus in 333 bce. Altdorfer had tried scrupulously
to obtain information as to the number of combatants, dead, and prisoners.
Nonetheless, the armies could be taken for medieval fighters, with the Persians
looking like the Ottoman forces who had besieged Vienna in the year of the pic
ture’s painting. Koselleck holds these features to support his argument that in the
middle ages the ‘present and the past were enclosed within a common historical
57 Procopius, History of the Wars, trans. H. B. Dewing (London: Heinemann, 1914), I. i. 6–17.
58 Ibid. II. ix.14; J. A. S. Evans, ‘The Attitudes of the Secular Historians of the Age of Justinian
towards the Classical Past’, Traditio 32 (1976), 353–8, here 357.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
plane’, that temporal ‘distance was not more or less arbitrarily eliminated; it
was not, as such, at all apparent’.59 Yet alternative explanations of Altdorfer’s
approach are possible. One is that, as in so much pre-modern History, Altdorfer
was knowingly blending different sorts of truth, literal (combatant numbers) and
otherwise, and thus the anachronism was quite conscious given the belief that for
specific purposes the differences between 333 and 1529 were less important than
the similarities.
Cassiodorus made his ancients–moderns distinction not to embrace change
but rather to ensure maximal preservation of Roman culture under the new con
ditions of Ostrogothic rule.60 This is the same sort of thinking evinced by the
Romans who had themselves venerated the established even while innovating
furiously. There is a sense in which someone can be instrumental in huge novelty
even whilst professing renewal, just as one can think oneself a revolutionary
whilst actually carrying forward much of the inheritance of the past. The ancient
Greek rhetorician Isocrates had it about right: he tacitly recognized that it would
always be a matter of some blending of continuity and change when he wrote
about the effect of talking of old things in new ways or vice versa.61
In understanding ‘medieval’ attitudes to change two tendencies are noteworthy,
and while in some ways they dovetailed, in other ways they sat in tension.
On one hand was the distinction between a conception of change as creation
ex nihilo, out of nothing, and the conception of change as creating something
out of something else. From at least Augustine the assumption was that only
God could create ex nihilo, though the belief may be traced to the Aristotelian
tendency to consider humans and the human soul as part, albeit a privileged
part, of the natural order, such that human laws should imitate natural laws
rather than aspire to complete originality.62 This assumption led to an idea of a
basic ontological stability outside periods of divine intervention. On the other
hand there was an idea, expressed from Hesiod through Virgil’s contemporary,
Ovid, and translated fairly straightforwardly to a medieval view of early
Christianity, of an ideal past order of which the present was merely a degenerate
version.63 Both tendencies encouraged fidelity to what had gone before, either
because what had gone before still pertained or because it provided an ideal
standard, yet the latter doctrine contradicted the former in portraying real change
rather than basic continuity.
If one side of the coin was fighting the tide of the new with innovations,
the other side was modifying the old dispensations in recognition of the new.
The Benedictine cleric Regino of Prüm (died 915) was author of a famous
chronicle that continued the Royal Frankish Annals, and a collection of canons
on ecclesiastical discipline, Libri duo de synodalibus causis et disciplinis ecclesias-
ticis. He warned that he had felt obliged to incorporate newer provisions in the
latter work, ‘things which I have deemed more pertinent to these our perilous
times’, because of a range of new offences ‘which were unheard of in olden times
because they were not committed and thus were not written and condemned in
established rulings’.64 With the spread of individual confession some three hun
dred years later we encounter concerns about priestly laxity in the imposition of
penance as against the harsher penances prescribed by the early church fathers.
Alain de Lille’s late twelfth-century Liber Poenitentialis argued that the relaxation
of standards was legitimate on the grounds that ‘human nature used to be stronger
once’, which meant that his contemporaries could not bear what had once been
thought necessary.65
By Regino’s time the inflection of ‘modern’ had already changed somewhat in
influential strands of thought. The historian and theologian Walafrid Strabo
(808–49) announced the arrival of ‘saeculum modernum’ (‘the modern age’) in
the era of Charlemagne.66 Antiquity, as opposed to modernity, was at that point
understood in different ways; sometimes it was conceived as including ‘pagan’
classical antiquity plus the time of the early church fathers, though Augustine
himself had announced the Christian era as ‘new’. Equally modernity could be
conceived as a more longstanding state or the description of the immediate pre
sent.67 In his biography of Charlemagne, Walafrid’s contemporary Einhard
recorded the life of ‘the greatest man of all those living in his own period’, one
whose achievements could ‘scarcely be matched by modern men’.68 The palm was
still offered to the past, but it was conceivable that exceptional ‘moderns’ were
worthy of their forebears, and by Alain’s time in the twelfth century a more exten
sive re-evaluation of the modern was well in train, even if not everyone could
agree on how to periodize it.
Sometimes ‘modernity’ was designated by the period for which historians
could rely on evidence before their own eyes, rather than on books written
by others. In the prologue to his Abbreviationes chronicum, Ralph of Diceto
64 Zubin Mistry, Abortion in the Early Middle Ages, c.500–900 (York: York Medieval Press, 2015), 205.
65 Alexander Murray, Conscience and Authority in the Medieval Church (Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 2015), 75; Thomas N. Tentler, Sin and Confession on the Eve of the Reformation (Princeton:
Princeton University Press, 1977), 17–18.
66 Elisabeth Gössmann, Antiqui und Moderni im Mittelalter: eine geschichtliche Standortbestimmung
(Paderborn: Schöningh, 1974), 35–6; Chenu, Nature, 317.
67 Gössmann, Antiqui und Moderni, 35, 37.
68 Einhard and Notker the Stammerer, Two Lives of Charlemagne, 52. On Notker as well as Einhard
see Gössmann, Antiqui und Moderni, 36.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
(1148–1202) divided historical events into three: the oldest, pagan times, vetustis-
sima; old times, the Christian era, vetera; and modern times, moderna, since the
year of his birth. Ralph’s contemporary Walter Map (1140–c.1210) identified the
most recent one hundred years as modernitas.69
As to the glorification of ‘modern’ men by History as Memorialization, it was
certainly in Map’s interest as a courtier of Henry II of England to petition for liter
ary recognition of the king’s ‘generosity’, and to bolster his case with reference to the
‘reverence’ accorded to the Roman emperor Nero, despite Nero’s ‘tyranny’. But Map
also made the broader point that while the deeds of the ancients were preserved, the
same was not true of the achievements of recent times, even those achievements
that offered ‘something not unworthy of “the buskin of Sophocles” ’. The problem
was not, indeed, a dearth of ‘the illustrious deeds of modern men of might’, but
rather a dearth of poets in an age where blame came more easily than veneration.70
As was the case with Arrian (pp. 25–6), whose work Map invoked, writers were as
important in memorialization as the great men that constituted their subject matter.
Indeed Map recognized the creative element of the writer’s task generations before
Dante and Plutarch noted the complementarity of Caesars and poets, arma et litte-
rae, whereby eternal recognition was attained ‘by both war and ingenium’, tam bello
quam ingenio. This is important since the self-consciousness of creation from the
original mind of the author is another of those things attributed to the Renaissance
‘mind’ as it supposedly departed from its ‘medieval’ predecessor.71
The twelfth-century biographer of Alexander the Great, Walter of Châtillon,
bemoaned that ‘we moderns stray from the footsteps of our ancestors’, rather as
Eusebius had vilified those whose ‘yearning for innovation’ drove them to ‘error’
(p. 52), but by Walter’s time his was but one side in a dispute about whether mod
ern ways were superior to the ancient. The dispute might be characterized by the
competing propositions from Job (12:12) that ‘with the ancient is wisdom’ and
from Paul’s call for the Ephesians (4:22–4) to ‘put off the old man, and put on the
new man, who has been created according to God’. Paul certainly removed some
of the stigma of ‘newness’ or novelty, redolent as that was of novissima, the end of
the world, indicative of the move to the last of ‘man’s’ three phases of life. Within
the theological realm the church fathers were denied a monopoly on doctrinal
interpretation and the twelfth century saw a telling juxtaposition of the fathers
and their adherents to the magistri moderni, monkish ‘masters’ who were not
cloistered, but were teachers in the new universities.72
The disputes between ‘ancients’ and ‘moderns’ from the twelfth to the fourteenth
centuries were not primarily historians’ disputes; they were much more import
ant. They were mainly conducted between theologian-philosophers, though they
especially Jacques Le Goff, ‘What Did the Twelfth-Century Renaissance Mean?’, in Peter Linehan and
Janet L. Nelson (eds), The Medieval World (Oxford: Routledge, 2001), 635–47. Albert Zimmermann
and Gudrun Vuillemin-Diemand (eds.), Antiqui und Moderni: Traditionsbewußtsein und
Fortschrittsbewußtsein im späten Mittelalter (Berlin: De Gruyter, 1974), contains essays on most salient
aspects of the advent of the moderni.
73 Arendt, The Life of the Mind, 152. See also 154, 214.
74 Jotischky, The Carmelites and Antiquity, 306; Giles Constable, The Reformation of the Twelfth
Century (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002), introduction; Beryl Smalley, ‘Ecclesiastical
Attitudes to Novelty, c.1100–c.1250’, Studies in Church History 12 (1975), 113–31; and for the relation
ship between tradition and reform in an area of direct relevance to this book, see Joachim Ehlers,
‘Monastische Theologie, historischer Sinn und Dialektik. Tradition und Neuerung in der Wissenschaft
des 12. Jahrhunderts’, in Zimmermann and Vuillemin-Diemand (eds.), Antiqui und Moderni, 58–79.
75 R. W. Southern, History and Historians: Selected Papers of R. W. Southern, ed. R. J. Bartlett
(Oxford: Blackwell, 2004), 42–3.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
extended into the realm of legal hermeneutics, at this time of the codification of
canon law.76 They were disputes about ways of justifying knowledge in the deepest
sense. In fact they are fundamental in a long-term shift in the development of
philosophy, away from ontology, which is, remember, the study of what exists in
the most basic sense, to epistemology, which is the study of what/how we can
know about what exists. The History practised by Christian chroniclers was in
one of its functions an auxiliary science to the study of religion, just as chronicle
was a lower activity than biblical hermeneutics: the main science is more signifi
cant than the auxiliary, but the relationship means that changes in the nature
of religious authority and scriptural exegesis were related to changes in the arts of
reading past religious texts, which should be set alongside secular, political influ
ences on and changing popular uses of History. We may thus diverge slightly
from Anthony Grafton, one of the most brilliant contemporary intellectual his
torians, when he differentiates humanists from scholastics by endorsing claims
for the ‘modernity’, in the form of the ‘fundamentally historical approach’, of the
Renaissance philologist and poet ‘Poliziano’ (1454–94):
76 Janet Coleman, Piers Plowman and the Moderni (Rome: Edizioni di Storia e Letteratura, 1981),
20; Andrea Padovani and Peter G. Stein (eds.), The Jurists’ Philosophy of Law from Rome to the
Seventeenth Century (Dordrecht: Springer, 2007), 143.
77 Anthony Grafton, Defenders of the Text: The Traditions of Scholarship in an Age of Science, 1450–1800
(Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1991), 8–9; see also 55.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
quite different way from the genre of fiction’.78 Prominent scholastics sometimes
maintained the coherence of their systems by historical enquiry, not just by logic.
Arguably the greatest mind of high medieval Christendom, Thomas Aquinas
(1225–74), who tried to fuse Hellenic naturalism with monotheistic supernatur
alism, endorsed the hermeneutic quadriga but insisted that the literal sense was
foundational.79 Here Aquinas was consistent with a trend that began with Anselm
in the eleventh century and was especially evident in the work of the legal thinker
Ivo of Chartres (c.1040–1115). Ivo set off along the path that would be followed
in the first half of the twelfth century by Peter Abelard (1079–1142) and the
Bolognese monk, Gratian. Gratian’s Decretum is regarded as the foundation-stone
of canon law, and was itself composed from biblical sources, writings of the early
church fathers, the decrees of the papacy and church synods and councils, and
Roman law, as passed down primarily through the Digests compiled under
Justinian in the sixth century, and rediscovered in 1070. Abelard’s competitors at
the Abbey of St Victor in Paris, Hugh (1096–1141) and Andrew (c.1110–75), pur
sued their own line of historical-theological exegesis which pointed towards his
torical literalism, though in a slightly different way to that taken up by Aquinas.
In this process, they and other Augustinian canons at St Victor were greatly aided
by the renewal of contact with Jewish exegetical traditions, through the work
of Joseph Karo, Samuel ben Meir, and in particular Rashi (acronym of Rabbi
Shlomo [Y]Itzhaki, 1040–1105),80 who also influenced Aquinas’s influence, Moses
Maimonides (1135–1204). The wider twelfth-century circulation of commentaries
by or attributed to the fourth-century father John Chrysostom was also relevant—
Chrysostom’s ‘Antiochene’ tradition of more literal exegesis differed from the
allegorizing ‘Alexandrian’ tradition which was better known to that point in Latin
Christendom.81
Hugh of St Victor claimed that ‘our task is to commit history to memory, as
the foundation of doctrine’. Hugh was a teacher, tasked with ensuring that his
78 In an otherwise highly stimulating piece: Alexandra Walsham, ‘Migrations of the Holy:
Explaining Religious Change in Medieval and Early Modern Europe’, Journal of Medieval and Early
Modern Studies 44:2 (2014), 241–80, here 265. In places this piece does show sensitivity to the signifi
cance of high medieval developments for what are often thought of as Reformation questions.
79 Christopher Ocker, Biblical Poetics before Humanism and Renaissance (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2002), 40.
80 Sara Lipton, Images of Intolerance: The Representation of Jews and Judaism in the Bible moralisée
(Berkeley: University of California Press, 1999), 73; Beryl Smalley, ‘L’Exégèse biblique du 12e siècle’, in
Maurice de Gandillac and Edouard Jeauneau (eds.), Entretiens sur la renaissance du 12e siècle (Paris:
Mouton, 1968), 273–83, here 273–5; Rainer Berndt (ed.), Schrift, Schreiber, Schenker: Studien zur Abtei
Sankt Viktor in Paris und den Viktorinern (Berlin: Akademie Verlag, 2005), 97 ff. on discerning authorial
intentions; passim on the intellectual context and antecedents of Andrew’s work. On differences to
Aquinas, Ocker, Biblical Poetics, 40.
81 On differences between Alexandria and Antioch, Wilhelm Dilthey, ‘The Development of
Hermeneutics’, in Dilthey: Selected Writings, ed. H. P. Rickman (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1976), 246–63, here 252.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
students learned deeply and properly. The capacity to memorize was highly
valued then, and for a few centuries to come. It was sometimes contrasted
with the act of committing things to paper, which might retard the ability to
internalize, and was thus a species of forgetting, which is one further reason
why it is not helpful to look only to chronicles to understand medieval engage
ments with the past.82
While Hugh was not greatly successful in stimulating historical study in
general, his Chronicon, or Liber de tribus maximis circumstantiis gestorum, id
est personis, locis, temporibus (Book of the three main circumstances of history,
namely persons, places, times) had manifold significance. It fed into Helinand
of Froidmont’s (c.1160–c.1237) and Vincent of Beauvais’s (c.1190–1264) later
chronicles of known world history from Adam onwards. For Hugh’s own students,
this detailed set of lists, plus his ‘glosses’ to the historical books of the Old
Testament, became a cardinal aid in establishing the literal meanings of scripture.
Hugh’s and Andrew’s commentaries, along with Walafrid Strabo’s Glossa Ordinaria
and Josephus’s Antiquities, underpinned Peter Comnestor’s (died 1179) Historia
Scholastica, a comprehensive running literal commentary on the historical
books of the Bible which, in its establishment as a standard text for the teaching
of sacred scripture in the schools, furthered Hugh’s goal of entrenching biblical
History as the ground for biblical reading. This achievement aroused the ire of
affiliates of the ecclesiastical reform movement, who emphasized the practical
pastoral and orthodox theological instruction of clerics over Hugh’s goal of devel
oping the contemplative mind. Thus Peter the Chanter (died 1197) decried a ten
dency that sounds to have something in common with the more prosaic of today’s
Histories of material culture as it supposedly encouraged the examination of
superfluities, such as the exact location of places, the number of years and
periods, genealogies, the mechanical dispositions in building, such as the dis
position of the tabernacle, the temple, even the imaginary temple [i.e. the temple
vision of Ezekiel]. Holy Scripture is not given to us to search for idle and super
fluous things in it, but to search for faith and moral lessons . . .83
82 On Hugh, Frans van Liere, An Introduction to the Medieval Bible (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2014), 159; Franklin T. Harkins, ‘Fundamentum omnis doctrinae: The Memorization
of History in the Pedagogy of Hugh of St. Victor’, Pecia. Le livre et l’écrit 14: Texte, liturgie et mémoire
dans l’Église du Moyen Âge (2012), 267–93. On the principles of memorialization, Given-Wilson,
Chronicles, 58.
83 Southern, History and Historians, 41–2; cf. van Liere, An Introduction to the Medieval Bible,
158–63, which provides most of the material on Hugh and his influence—see also p .142 on
Chrysostom and Origen as different sorts of hermeneut. On Origen and Josephus, and the extent of
Comnestor’s debt to Josephus and other Jewish sources, plus the significance of Comnestor’s work:
Louis H. Feldman, Studies in Hellenistic Judaism (Leiden: Brill, 1996), 302, 317–26, 343–4. On
Hugh, Andrew, and Josephus, Mark Somos, Secularisation and the Leiden Circle (Leiden: Brill,
2011), 345–6.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
For Andrew of St Victor, sometimes called ‘the second Jerome’, literal reading
had meant an increasing focus on grammar, on recovering original wording,
and on the surface meaning of words, even to the point at which he produced a
non-Christological reading of books of the ‘Old Testament’.84 The author’s
inferred intention should also determine what counts as a figurative meaning,
which is where Andrew’s and Hugh’s debt to Rashi is perhaps most obvious. For
Rashi, the literal sense meant recapturing what the authors of scripture had
intended to communicate to their primary, contemporary audiences. This quest
required historical contextualization, as with his endorsement of peshat (literal,
contextual reading) over homiletic midrash traditions.85 Ironically, it may be that
Hugh had turned to Jewish scholarship in the first place to further his own literal
ist interests precisely because of the enduring Christian stereotype, attributable to
Paul and Augustine, that literal reading without deeper symbolic understanding
was all that the benighted Jews were capable of.86
While, as Coleman observes, the sensus historicus of medieval hermeneutic
was often identical with the sensus grammaticus, with the historical truth of what
was written being accepted as literal truth once the grammatical meaning of it
had been established,87 ascertaining authorial intention demanded contextual
understanding that looked beyond individual texts in a non-figurative sense: it
could be History in today’s sense of the word, as the medievalist biblical scholar
Frans van Liere observes.88 Checking text against text, setting one authority
against another, was also a form of source criticism, as Abelard showed in a con
troversy over the biography of the first-century convert to Christianity, Dionysius
the Areopagite.89 Comparison of the original Hebrew of the Old Testament could
reveal inaccuracies in later translations. By extension, such inaccuracies could affect
the figural relations established between episodes in Old and New Testaments.90
Further, as Abelard and Peter Lombard demonstrated via their dialectic methods,
[When] the apostles did on that occasion require Christians to abstain from the
blood of animals, and not to eat of things strangled, they seem to me to have
consulted the time in choosing an easy observance that could not be burden
some to any one, and which Gentiles might have in common with the Israelites,
for the sake of the Cornerstone [i.e. Christ], who makes both one in himself [. . .]
But since the close of that period during which the two walls of the circumcision
and the uncircumcision, although united in the Cornerstone, still retained some
distinctive peculiarities, and now that the Church has become so entirely Gentile
that none who are outwardly Israelites are to be found in it, no Christian feels
91 Paul Tillich, A History of Christian Thought, ed. Carl E. Braaten (New York: Touchstone,
1968), 169–70.
92 On elements of Augustine’s theory of accommodation, Levitin, ‘From Sacred History to the
History of Religion’, 1131; Betty Jo Teeter Dobbs, The Janus Faces of Genius: The Role of Alchemy in
Newton’s Thought (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), 59–60. However, for the point
about eighth- and ninth-century thought, and indeed for my entire discussion of Augustine here,
references to Augustine’s work and all, I am indebted completely to Rick Sowerby.
93 Augustine, Contra Faustum, 32.14, repr in Augustine, The Works of Aurelius Augustine: A New
Translation, ed. Marcus Dods, vol. 5 (Edinburgh: Clark, 1872), 541.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
bound to abstain from thrushes or small birds because their blood has not been
poured out, or from hares because they are killed by a stroke on the neck with
out shedding their blood. Any who still are afraid to touch these things are
laughed at by the rest.94
Returning to the topic of the central middle ages, the legal scholar Gabriel
Le Bras noted that the early canonists marked ‘off from principles of eternal
validity the variable elements of the law, which had been suggested by particular
circumstances, whether of time, place, or persons’, and he concluded on ‘the
relativity of rules’. More strongly, Donald R. Kelley detects ‘geographical and
historical relativism’ in their thought, amid a ‘process of “historicization” ’ in the
interpretation of canon law, and a third scholarly authority, R. L. Benson, sees
‘historical relativism’ in the thought of Gratian and his immediate successors,
the decretists.95 It is difficult to detect relativism in this train of thought: all the
medieval thinkers in question insist on distinguishing unchangeable elements
of the law from variable parts. Gratian, for instance, was prepared to countenance
the revision of ancient law, but only in order that it align more closely with
divine law, which no human law might contradict. Ultimately his goal was dis
pensing with customs that did not correspond to reason and conscience.
Focusing on the variable elements of law, Benson alludes to Gratian’s dictum
that ‘if among the several things which were done by our predecessors and
ancestors there are some things which were able to be [done] without guilt, and
afterward turned into error and superstition, then without hesitation and with
great authority, they ought to be destroyed by those who come later’.96 As much
as anything this passage illustrates the balancing act between recognition of past
and present papal legislative legitimacy. Such diplomatic phrasing does not
mean that ‘what once was good can turn bad as a result of the changing of the
times’.97 Saying that something might have been done without guilt is not
the same as saying it was good, only that the doer was not culpable. The limited
circumstance in which two contradictory rules could be true, according to
Gratian’s prologue to the Concordance of Discordant Canons, was when they
related to a law which was variable and the contradiction stemmed from a
94 Augustine, Contra Faustum, 32.13, repr in Augustine, The Works of Aurelius Augustine: A New
Translation, vol. 5, 540–1.
95 Gabriel Le Bras, ‘Canon Law’, in C. G. Crump and E. F. Jacob (eds.), The Legacy of the Middle
Ages (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1943), 321–61, here 326; Kelley, Foundations of Modern Historical
Scholarship, 154. Benson cited in Achim Funder, Reichsidee und Kirchenrecht: Dietrich von Nieheim als
Beispiel spätmittelalterlicher Rechtsauffassung (Freiburg: Herder, 1993), nn. to pp. 292, 334. Note that
Kelley also claims strains of cultural relativism in the work of the twelfth-century bishop and philosopher
of History Otto of Freising: Kelley, Faces of History, 129. I cannot see relativism in Otto but obviously
that does not mean it is not there.
96 Stanley Chodorow, Christian Political Theory and Church Politics in the Mid-Twelfth Century
(Berkeley: University of California Press, 1972), reproduces this passage and contextualizes it on p. 140.
97 Funder, Reichsidee, 292: ‘was einmal gut gewesen ist, kann sich durch die Veränderung der
Zeiten zum schlechten wenden’.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
dispensation allowed in a special case.98 Relativism this was not, but Gratian
does evince that sense of anachronism, i.e. the sense of not applying standards
and perspectives to past people who did not have them, that is so often held to
be a post-medieval attitude.
Another contextualizing exercise by Maimonides has led some scholars to talk
of historicism and historicization in relation to his work, especially passages in
his Guide for the Perplexed (c.1190 in Judeo-Arabic, translated into Hebrew
in 1204).99 Those scholars do not equate historicism or historicization with a
relativistic view, but since historicism is sometimes given those connotations, and
in light of the previous paragraph, a brief digression on relativism is merited.
Relativism is a philosophical outlook predicated upon recognition of multiple,
perhaps infinite accounts of the good and right (moral relativism), and/or the
beautiful (aesthetic relativism), and/or the true (epistemic relativism). In its sim
plest ‘descriptive’ form relativism just acknowledges the fact of the diversity of
systems of value or belief. It is doubtful that ‘descriptive relativism’, as it is called,
really qualifies as relativism, because one could easily contend that some or all
or all-but-one of these manifold systems of belief is faulty. More properly relativ
ist is the argument that there is no standpoint or yardstick external to all cultures
that provides an ultimate vindication for different belief/value systems or renders
their differing terms mutually commensurable (see p. 326). Accordingly, any
claim to universal standards of judgement is a form of self-deceit, a spurious uni
versalization of one culture’s standards. The only standards of, say, good and bad
are those that develop within cultures, in the plural. Maimonides clearly does not
hold such a position.
Like Aquinas, Maimonides was concerned with reconciling Aristotle with
scripture, or at least with creating some insulation where conflict was likely. He
also tried to interpret some of the apparently more arcane biblical injunctions,
without allegorization, for a contemporary Jewish readership. Thus he accounted
for initial divine approval of sacrifice as a concession to ‘the custom which was in
those days general among all men, and the general mode of worship in which
the Israelites were brought up’. It was a concession to reality, much as in Islamic
jurisprudence—which may have been one of the many Islamic influences on
Maimonides—the Koran’s acceptance of polygamy was seen as a concession to
pre-Islamic practices. And just as more recent Muslim exegesis has argued that
Koranic limits on the scale of polygamy suggest a tendency towards the reduction
98 Harold J. Berman, Law and Revolution, the Formation of the Western Legal Tradition (Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press, 1983), 145–6 on this point and on Gratian weeding out problematic
custom.
99 Levitin, ‘From Sacred History to the History of Religion’, 1131, including extensive notes to rele
vant scholarship. Note that Maimonides’ historical thinking plays an important role in Funkenstein’s
thought about the origins of modern historicist thinking—see Moyn, ‘Amos Funkenstein’. It should be
clear that I would argue that Maimonides’ contribution to a sense of acculturated human difference
across time is only one among many such contributions in and around his period.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
and eventual elimination of the practice, so for Maimonides the concession was a
transitional measure. Manifestly there is here a sense of acculturated difference
and cultural change across time. Maimonides’ idiom is at once of an anthropo
logical psychology in which it is in ‘the nature of man, who generally cleaves to
that to which he is used’, but also of tutelage from infancy to adulthood, as
Maimonides talks of young mammals being weaned from milk to solids.100
So such tolerance as exists of the earlier practice may be sympathetic, but it is also
paternalistic and provisional, as one might indulge a child. It is this psychological
contextualization that distinguishes Maimonides’ account from Augustine’s
theory of accommodation with its more circumstantial focus. (See pp. 122–3 for
elaboration.)
The focus on literalism and historical contextualism as opposed to allegorical
meaning in reading practices was accompanied by an increased attention to liter
ary quality as a constituent of the written account and as an index of interest in
the human author. The concept of the auctor shifted its meaning somewhat
between the eleventh and thirteenth centuries. Sharing a root with auctoritas,
meaning approximately authentic truth, it implied authority that commanded
respect, and was the sort of thing that historians and others strived to achieve.
Conventionally, God was seen as the author of the sacred texts, and the scribe
merely as conduit, but as—especially under the influence of the Victorines—
questions turned to matters of how, where, when, and from what materials the
scribe had compiled his account, they also considered why. The ‘why’ concerned
the personal ends of the flesh-and-blood writer, which had to be considered as an
additional causal factor alongside the ultimate divine ‘causes’ of the work.
The concept of ‘four causes’ which systematically elucidated different types of
influence was, by the way, a major part of the thirteenth century’s Aristotelian
inheritance.101 His Physica and Metaphysica entered university curricula at that
time, having mostly been translated into Latin by around 1200, while the Latin
occupation of Constantinople (1204–61) facilitated a further engagement with its
treasures. Aristotle’s concepts had been only partially retrieved before then. Now
they proved valuable not just for hermeneutics but for hermeneuts, who could
become auctors themselves, as Walter Map had obviously aspired to be in the
realm of secular History (p. 83), rather as latter-day literary theorists have been
able to market their criticism as literature. The idea of a writer as an ‘author’ can
be contrasted with the label compilator or compiler that medieval chroniclers
often applied to themselves. For the interpreting reader, the idea of multiple
causal influences also meant that it was possible to be more explicitly critical
towards canonical texts, since one was not criticizing the word of God so much
100 Moses Maimonides, The Guide for the Perplexed, trans. M. Friedländer (New York: Dover,
1956), ch. XXXII at 322–7, all quotes from 322–3.
101 On Aristotelian categories and causation, William J. Connell, ‘The Eternity of the World and
Renaissance Historical Thought’, California Italian Studies 2:1 (2011), 1–23.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
as a human-influenced amalgam.102 Scholars who study the sixteenth and seven
teenth centuries should be careful in arrogating to their period the innovation of
debates on how to reconcile the biblical authority, ‘which was divine, with its his
tory, which was more and more evidently human’.103 When Grafton writes of
‘humanists’ reading their texts ‘as clouded windows which proper treatment
could restore to transparency, revealing the individuals who had written them’, he
makes a vital point about the recognition that texts reveal as much about their
own authors and origins as about their explicit subject-matter.104 But however
much humanists may have developed this critical principle any sharp contrast
with prior scholasticism does not quite work, for reasons already provided.
If Aquinas was merely one hugely influential part of a longer movement in the
direction of prioritizing literalism, a further step in the subjective reading not just
of actual texts but of the world as a text was provided by William of Ockham
(c.1287–1347). He was not the earliest but he was the most famous medieval
‘nominalist’. The debate between nominalists (formerly ‘vocalists’) and ‘realists’
corresponded to some instantiations of the debate between moderni and antiqui,
and had begun in the twelfth century, especially in the crucible of Abelard’s
thought. While Aquinas was not of the moderni, he was clearly influenced by
them. As ever beneath the headline bifurcation, the lines of distinction between
travellers on the via antiqua and via moderna vary very much from person to
person. Perhaps the most important crack that Aquinas created in Catholic
orthodoxy, the crack that nominalism forced much wider and deeper, was his
contention that while God was of course immediately certain for himself, he was
not immediately certain to humans.105 The nominalist challenge brought epis
temological and metaphysical questions together.
Let us open the discussion of nominalism with the dispute concerning God’s
role in allocating salvation. In an answer to the question, which had distinct
echoes of Plato’s asking whether the gods will what is just/reasonable or is the
just/reasonable what the gods happen to will, the antiqui banked on the regulata
ble certainties of the former. Nominalism effectively reversed the order of priority.
Only if God’s will was supreme could ‘his’ power be truly unlimited, truly free.106
This conclusion also militated against any notion emerging from the study of
102 Michel Zimmermann (ed.), Auctor et auctoritas. Invention et conformisme dans l’écriture médiévale
(Paris: École des Chartes, 2001); A. J. Minnis, Medieval Theory of Authorship: Scholastic Literary Attitudes
in the Later Middle Ages (London: Scolar, 1984), ch. 1 but also pp. 190–210 on how ‘compilation’ became
a literary form of its own; Sara S. Poor, Mechthild of Magdeburg and her Book: Gender and the Making of
Textual Authority (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 2004), 2–4.
103 Noel Malcolm, ‘Hobbes, Ezra, and the Bible: The History of a Subversive Idea’, in Malcolm,
Aspects of Hobbes (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2002), 383–431, here 420, cited and endorsed by Levitin,
‘From Sacred History to the History of Religion’, 1126–7.
104 Grafton, Defenders of the Text, 8–9. 105 Tillich, Protestant Era, 71.
106 Lauri Haikola, Gesetz und Evangelium bei Matthias Flacius Illyricus: eine Untersuchung zur
Lutherischen Theologie vor der Konkordienformel (Lund: Gleerup, 1952), 32 ff.; Jörg Dierken,
Selbstbewusstsein individueller Freiheit: religionstheoretische Erkundungen in protestantischer
Perspektive (Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck, 2005), 135–6, 203–4.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
Greek naturalism that God might have to be reconciled with the laws of nature.
As against a metaphysically ‘realist’ position that one could know the universe in
itself as the manifestation of a divine, hierarchical order, nominalists believed that
the human mind was left with articulating its own systems on the fragmentary
evidence of experience and reason. For the same reasons nominalists conducted a
cull of those atemporal, abstract entities that metaphysical/ontological realists
like Plato had called eternal ‘forms’—the sorts of entities that for prior theolo
gians had divinely vouchsafed the interlinked order of the natural world. Words
were increasingly seen as arbitrary signs allocated to contingent entities and
linked to each other by grammatical convention—and as the tool of human auc-
tores rather than anything else. They were not indicators of spiritual realities or
divine natural order. Religious hierarchs were in no better position to determine
the higher meaning behind the literal word than any other literate person profi
cient in the use of reason. Logic of thought and grammatical logic of written and
spoken language were the only reliable tools of analysis at human disposal, but
they were uncoupled from metaphysics. Everything else was at God’s unknowable
disposition, leaving the individual human with faith alone, and a terrifying free
dom to choose his or her way in the world during those times when God did
not intervene. Concrete, mundane individuals existed on their own, albeit in
virtue of God’s omnipotence and in some way in ‘his’ image, certain only of their
own inner states.107
The development of nominalism as a theological position prior to and
through William’s early fourteenth-century work was accompanied socially by a
thirteenth-century evangelical explosion in which men and a growing number of
women took on the roles of auctores, seeking to embody and disseminate the
principles that Christ had exemplified in his life, disavowing worldly goods and
preaching in the vernacular.108 Intellectually, a particular sort of subjectivism was
enhanced, with the emphasis on the human mind rather than the accumulated
authority of institutions and the all-encompassing order of the divine which intel
lectual systems were supposed to map. For related reasons, nominalism was an
essential precursor of the Reformation since the Protestant belief that salvation
comes from faith and God’s grace alone (the meeting of the two comprising the
kairos), not from the good works of man, stems from the rejection of inferable
divine reason. For the nominalists as for Luther, one side of the interpretative
coin was a recognition of how much could be inferred, unassisted, by the applica
tion of human reason to texts, and the other side of the coin was a claim about
how much must remain obscure without the aid of revelation and grace.109
107 Coleman, Ancient and Medieval Memories, 530–6 and passim; Gordon Leff, William of Ockham:
The Metamorphosis of Scholastic Discourse (Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1975), 54–5.
108 Poor, Mechthild, 4.
109 Robert B. Pippin, Modernism as a Philosophical Problem: On the Dissatisfactions of European
High Culture (Malden, MA: Blackwell, 1999), 19.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
110 On some interesting conceptual linkages between theological debates and economics, see
Siegfried Van Duffel, ‘From Objective Right to Subjective Rights: The Franciscans and the Interest and
Will Conceptions of Rights’, in Virpi Mäkinen (ed.), The Nature of Rights (Helsinki: Societas
Philosophica Fennica, 2010), 63–91.
111 A distinction identified by Moishe Postone, Louis Galambos, and Jane Eliot Sewell, Time, Labor,
and Social Domination: A Reinterpretation of Marx’s Critical Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2003), 211.
112 Dipesh Chakrabarty, ‘The Death of History? Historical Consciousness and the Culture of Late
Capitalism’, Public Culture 4:2 (1992), 47–65, here 56.
113 Postone et al., Time, Labor, 209–11.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
Manifold were the background factors against which such ostensibly technical
developments might be ascribed significance, but among those factors were the
increasing scepticism of the ‘moderns’ about divine time-schemas devised by
‘ancients’, and the nominalist relegation of time to the realms of the unpredictable
dispensations of the divine. Mundane time was freed up along with much of
the natural world as a resource for individuals and their managers, at around the
same point as Christendom’s sense of space was being expanded by encounters
at its margins, with both developments being conducive to commerce.114 Neither
of these changes coheres with Michel Foucault’s claim that it was only in the
seventeenth and eighteenth century that a ‘new mechanism of power’ was invented
‘which permits time and labor, rather than wealth and commodities, to be
extracted from bodies’.115 Neither coheres with anthropologist Johannes Fabian’s
claim that ‘Enlightenment thought’ (for there is apparently only one such kind,
like the ‘medieval’ equivalent) breaks with ‘a conception of time/space in terms of
a history of salvation to one that ultimately resulted in the secularization of Time
as natural history’.116 Both are obscured by studies of high medieval historiog
raphy that focus on the new eschatological speculative philosophies written in the
high middle ages by Otto of Freising and Orderic Vitalis amongst others. As ever,
these speculative philosophies are not categorically different in all respects to
other more ‘secular’ Histories of the period, but their different emphases and
purposes mean that they cannot be considered representative of the mass of
historically oriented scholarship in the period, far less of the historical thought
investigated in the previous section.117
The label ‘renaissance’ was applied to the twelfth-century crucible of nominal
ism and so much else, by twentieth-century medievalists keen to undo some of
the damage done to the name of the middle ages by the propagandists of the
better-known Renaissance. The ‘monastic reformation’ of the twelfth century also
anticipates ‘the’ fifteenth- and sixteenth-century Reformation. Such labels may
serve merely to antedate the origins of ‘the modern’ to the twelfth century, but
that would be insufficient. Instead, as Le Goff and others have posited, the lan
guage of culmination may be more appropriate in highlighting the development
of ‘medieval’ Christian civilization by its own lights. After all, it was only at the
outset of the twelfth century that ‘Christendom’ arrogated that name to itself,
after Gregorian reform and at a time of centralization and state-building. This
sort of thinking prompts a reassessment of the nature of distinctions between
118 R. I. Moore, The Formation of a Persecuting Society: Authority and Deviance in Western Europe,
950–1250 (Oxford: Blackwell, 2007).
119 Le Goff, ‘What Did the Twelfth-Century Renaissance Mean?’; Peter von Moos, ‘Das. 12.
Jahrhundert—eine “Renaissance” oder ein “Aufklarungszeitalter”?’, Mittellateinisches Jahrbuch, 23
(1988), 1–10. See also the locus classicus, Haskins, The Renaissance of the Twelfth Century.
120 Bloch, Feudal Society, 99–107; Damian-Grint, New Historians, 189.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
sense that kinship was determined by relative distance from the living person
(man or woman, both of whom had inheritance rights), with salient distances
measured in degrees from that person. The patrilineal system was ‘ancestor-
focused’; it posited an absolute anchorage in the past and a line of ever-growing if
now purely male extension into the present and beyond. Connection to the past
was announced by the adoption of the agnatic family name, alongside coats of
arms, and mottoes, with the systematic use of heraldry emerging in the mid-
twelfth century. The new emphasis on patrilineage was attributable on one hand
to the partial success of the church’s push from the Gregorian reform period to
enforce monogamy and a new marriage ethic on the nobility, and on the other
hand to the matter of land resources. In an increasingly delineated Europe, nei
ther the fruits of pillage nor new land were easy to come by, and in the interests of
maintaining extant landholdings, rights of inheritance were limited, with females
being most adversely affected.121 A reciprocal relationship developed between
nobles organizing themselves patrilineally and the literary genre of genealogy
that expressed the lineage’s self-consciousness. This new ordering principle
shaped the narrativization of the past by fusing the chronography of the chronicle
with the vita or biography. While legitimating hereditary rule by projecting it as
an unbroken chain into the distant past (a continuity principle), in a way similar
to the origin myths of Christianity in which Eve sprang from Adam and Christ
from the Father (a religious principle), genealogical narrative also established the
most important periodization (a discontinuity principle) with reference to human
generational change (a secularity principle). Altogether, this produced a fusion of
religious-literary tradition with the demands of new social realities. In place
of the chronicler’s time or a divine scheme inferable by figural thought, dynastic
or political time now became more pronounced as an organizing principle for the
histories of kingdoms, fiefdoms, and abbeys, along with the requisite acts of
procreation, marriage, and heroism. Spiegel explains that
121 David Herlihy, Women, Family and Society in Medieval Europe (Oxford: Berghahn, 1995), 143–7;
on heraldry, but also on the plurality of agnatic and cognatic lineages into the twelfth century and
beyond, see David Crouch, ‘The Historian, Lineage and Heraldry 1050–1250’, in Peter Coss and
Maurice Keen (eds.), Heraldry, Pageantry and Social Display in Medieval England (Woodbridge:
Boydell, 2002), 17–37.
122 Spiegel, The Past as Text, 104–110, quotation from 108–9; Given-Wilson, Chronicles, 87, 157.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
Clearly gestes were supposed to provide eternally valid exempla, but the sense of
time measured by human life and experience, and of that life in turn being illu
minated by purposive action, provides further evidence against assertions like
that by Benedict Anderson of a medieval ‘conception of temporality in which
cosmology and history were indistinguishable’.123
Moments of secular rupture like the Norman Conquest stimulated greater inter
est in secular cultural changes within Christendom and effected fundamental
shifts in the periodization of English and British Histories. More broadly, a curs
ory glance at the History of Europe in the eleventh and twelfth centuries reveals
great developments in state formation, centralization, and colonization in which
emperors and popes fought over whether primacy was to be accorded to the
priestly sword or the royal one. Shared legal systems were a key source of indi
viduating collective identity against other collectives, too. The growing pan-state
influence of Roman law, the ius commune, while competing in some ways,
favoured secular authority as against ecclesiastical law.124 That was but one of the
ways in which the secular past was increasingly imbricated in the mundane regu
lative structures of life: while canon law was predicated upon the ancient texts,
secular law depended upon secular precedent, if also on Roman law texts, hence
the importance of jurists in the early development of European historiography,
and the continued influence of historians of laws and constitutions even into the
modern period. All of this was in place from hundreds of years before Anderson
allows the development of any patriotism distinct from a non-territorialized
Christendom.125 In fact some of these politico-legal developments, which had
roots in the post-Roman sixth and seventh centuries, pre-dated the very concept
of Christendom, and were not eradicated by that concept during its relatively
brief and never unchallenged dominance.
The very concept of the body politic that would be so central to early modern
theories of state was a twelfth-century invention even if it was disguised as being
classical in origin. John of Salisbury (1120–80), a product not of the Empire but
of a Chartres education and the ‘modern’ Anglo-Norman kingdom, propagated a
positivist science of the state whose administration was based on functions and
elements of meritocracy rather than feudal oaths. He helped pave the way for the
126 Briggs, The Body Broken, 93–7; Chenu, Nature, 196–7; S. H. Rigby, Wisdom and Chivalry: Chaucer’s
Knight’s Tale and Medieval Political Theory (Leiden: Brill, 2009), 13–14 on the pseudo-Aristotelian
Secretum Secretorum. For references as to how Aristotle’s works were known at second hand before the
thirteenth century, see pp. 15, 85–6.
127 Susan Reynolds, ‘Medieval Origines Gentium and the Community of the Realm’, History, 68:224
(1983), 375–90; on origines ordinum, Jotischky, The Carmelites and Antiquity, 305–11.
128 Given-Wilson, Chronicles, 179–85.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
131 Robert Bartlett, The Natural and the Supernatural in the Middle Ages (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2008), ch. 3.
132 Damian-Grint, New Historians, 4.
133 Baswell, Virgil, 28–9; on the broader context, Chenu, Nature, ch. 5. On Herodotus, Baron,
Timaeus, 237 f.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
a people that has not yet departed from the primitive habits of pastoral life. In
the common course of things, mankind progresses from the forest to the field,
from the field to the town, and to the social condition of citizens; but this nation,
holding agricultural labour in contempt, and little coveting the wealth of towns,
as well as being exceedingly averse to civil institutions, lead the same life their
fathers did in the woods and open pastures, neither willing to abandon their old
habits or learn anything new.138
Note ‘learn’, for, alongside a description of ‘progression’ that would not have been
out of place among eighteenth-century stadial theories of human socio-economic
134 On the significances of Gerald, including the ethnographic ones, see Robert Bartlett, Gerald of
Wales, 1146–1223 (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1982). On the imperial context, see John Gillingham,
‘The Beginning of English Imperialism’, Journal of Historical Sociology 5 (1992), 392–409.
135 Gerald of Wales, Giraldus Cambrensis The Topography of Ireland, trans. Thomas Forester, rev.
and ed. Thomas Wright (Cambridge, ON: In Parentheses, 2000), Distinction III, ch. XLVII.
136 Ibid., Distinction I, ch. XIII. 137 Ibid., introduction to Distinction II.
138 Ibid., Distinction III, ch. X.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 07/04/20, SPi
development (Chapter 5), Gerald had the rudiments of an explanation for that
progression. He wrote that ‘habits are formed by mutual intercourse’. The sup
posed problem for the Irish was that they ‘inhabit a country so remote from the
rest of the world, and lying at its furthest extremity, forming, as it were, another
world, and are thus secluded from civilized nations, they learn nothing, and prac
tise nothing but the barbarism in which they are born and bred, and which sticks
to them like a second nature’.139
For Gerald, to look west was to look back in time. The same attitude has been
identified in other actors, and the anthropologist Fabian called it the ‘denial of
coevalness’, the ‘tendency to place the referent(s) of anthropology in a Time other
than the present of the producer of anthropological discourse’.140 Yet this attitude
has been associated with much later developments, developments perhaps begin
ning with Europe’s embarkation on transatlantic colonialism and encounter with
the ‘new world’ three centuries after the Topography of Ireland, and crystallizing
in the Enlightenment.141
There is an irony in Fabian’s work, and it relates to his aforementioned claim
that ‘Enlightenment thought’ breaks with ‘a conception of time/space in terms of
a history of salvation to one that ultimately resulted in the secularization of Time
as natural history’.142 Fabian’s Time and the Other is a fine study of the role of
‘modern’ concepts of time as they have influenced anthropological thinking and
shaped constructions of ‘others’ as backward. Yet in order to establish these con
cepts as distinguishing marks of modern thought, Fabian performs that now
familiar construction of a contrasting, monolithic medieval mindset by his char
acterization of ‘the’ medieval comprehension of time; to highlight the supposedly
distinct quality of Enlightenment thinking, he conflates the medieval and the
Christian and reduces both to a single and exclusive temporal sense related to ‘a
history of salvation’. By Fabian’s account it would have been impossible for Gerald
of Wales to have written what he wrote.
139 Ibid. 140 Fabian, Time and the Other, 31—in the original this sentence is italicized.
141 Ibid. 146–7. 142 Ibid. 26.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
4
Renaissances and Reformations
Introduction
This chapter concerns the time from around 1400 to around 1700. If the title gives
a clue as to some of the major intellectual influences on historical thinking during
the period, we ought not ignore additional cultural shifts and political and tech
nical developments.
On the political side, conquest and sovereignty change remained as important
as ever in stimulating new thinking, but the designs of monarchs with increas
ingly absolutist tendencies added a further element. Overtly political factors
chimed with different regional strains of humanism and the religious movements
of Reformation and Counter-Reformation insofar as all three clusters of thought
pertained to History as Identity, in the sense of a profound concern with origins
and legitimation.
Technically, the invention and diffusion of printing stands above all else. The
growth of literacy which it presupposed was greatest in the Italian city-states
where mercantile wealth brought education well beyond ecclesiastics and the
nobility. With an expansion of readers came an expansion of writers, resulting in
a significantly greater widening of perspectives than had come in, say, late medi
eval Britain, as secular clergy broke the previous monastic monopoly on histor
ianship. Even though churchmen continued to play a major role over the next few
centuries, there was now something of a return to the classical convention
whereby men of political experience asserted their authority on what mattered in
the study of the present and of the past. All these developments help explain a
greater scholarly focus on the study of human achievement in the mundane
sphere, the studia humanitatis, from which we get umanisti, humanists, and, at
one further remove, the ‘humanities’ as a group of disciplines. As the printing
press supplied the reading market it also supplied scholars with copies of texts
ancient, medieval, and contemporary, that thitherto only existed as scarce manu
scripts in limited circulation. A proliferation of scholarly materials facilitated the
acquisition of erudition and the comparison of sources.
Publications also catered to existing preferences, however, and it would be mis
leading to think that what was held to be interesting or politically important
changed abruptly or completely. In 1476–7, the Grandes Chroniques de France
became the first French-language work to be printed in Paris, and other annalistic
accounts recent and more venerable, including the work of Gregory of Tours,
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
were reproduced and read for at least a century thereafter. In the Germanic lands,
the same went for the Fredegar chronicle and its ilk.1 Social stratification mat
tered here, whether in terms of purchasing power or assumptions of propriety.
Putting aside that of which we know least, that which Markus Völkel calls ‘wild
historical knowledge’ produced from below rather than above, there were major
differences in the sort of historical product to which people might be exposed. In
the Germanic context from the Reformation to the Enlightenment, Völkel indi
cates the prominence of ‘the broadsheet, the pseudohistorical romance, or the
even more unconsolidated form of the “yearly reports” drawn from the periodical
press’.2
On the cultural level, the fifteenth and sixteenth centuries saw widespread
encounter with more ‘new’ worlds, whether via more expansive commercial
engagement, further Iberian exploration of Africa, or the invasion of the Americas
with their particular human cultures and strange animal and vegetable species.
Jean Bodin (1530–96), that embodiment of the French Renaissance, mused
‘Who can doubt that the Christian religion is the true religion or rather the only
one? . . . Almost all the World.’3 The transatlantic venture in particular altered the
mental map characterized by the mappae mundi by showing that Jerusalem was
not the centre of the world and that the landmass of Asia, Africa, and Europe
was not the only one. At the same time, though, if French literature is any indica
tion, in the sixteenth century more was produced and consumed about European
encounters with the ‘Near’ and ‘Far East’ than with the Americas, and the discrep
ancy only increased over time.4
In the interplay of spatial and temporal thought, the informative encounter
with foreign worlds in the present was matched by learning from prior worlds,
including via the ancient geographical descriptions of Ptolemy. Encounters with
the past were perforce historical in the broad sense, and they demanded particu
lar interpretative skills. In specialist historiographic terms, the literary forms and
style of classical works of History were at least as influential as their content:
hence the term ‘renaissance of letters’. Other innovations with knock-on effects in
historiography came in the fine arts, literature and poetry, political philosophy,
and through re-engagement with a wider range of Platonic texts than had been
1 On Florentine literacy and other elements of the Italian context, William J. Connell, ‘Italian
Renaissance Historical Narrative’, in José Rabasa, Masayuki Sato, Edoardo Tortarolo, and Daniel
Woolf (eds.), The Oxford History of Historical Writing 1400–1800 (Oxford: Oxford University Press,
2015), 347–63, here 348–9; on French publishing, Chantal Grell, ‘History and Historians in France,
from the Great Italian Wars to the Death of Louis XIV’, in the same volume, 384–405, here 384–5. On
the Fredegar Chronicle’s printing, Wallace-Hadrill, ‘Fredegar’, 528–9.
2 Markus Völkel, ‘German Historical Writing from the Reformation to the Enlightenment’, in
Rabasa et al. (eds.), The Oxford History of Historical Writing 1400–1800, 324–46, here 327.
3 Jean Bodin, Colloquium of the Seven about Secrets of the Sublime (Princeton: Princeton University
Press, 1975), 163. See also Auerbach, Mimesis, 282.
4 Denys Hay, Europe: The Emergence of an Idea (New York: Harper, 1966), 99.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
available earlier to the bearers of the Neoplatonist flame at Chartres and the
Dominican School of Cologne.
Running in a different direction to Platonism and Neoplatonism, radical ‘pyr
rhonian scepticism’ was also resurrected along with the works of Sextus Empiricus
(160–210 ce). Pyrrhonian scepticism affected humanist more than scientific
thought in the sixteenth century, and its influence was supplemented in the fol
lowing century by René Descartes’s assessment of History: amongst other things
Descartes wrote of exemplar historians that the omissions they make in the inter
ests of relevance ensure that ‘the remainder does not appear as it really was’—
le reste ne paroît pas tel qu’il est—and those who model their behaviour on such
exempla ‘are prone to succumb to the extravagances that ail the Paladins of our
romances, and to conceive designs which exceed their powers’.5 Ironically, the
humanist Francesco Robortello (1516–67) may have helped promote Sextus by
trying to dismiss him when, in his De historica facultate disputatio (1548),
Robortello penned a not entirely coherent defence of History against his yet rela
tively obscure opponent. Latin translations of two of Sextus’s major works in the
1560s brought him squarely into public view.6 Bodin’s influential Methodus ad
facilem historiarum cogitionem (Method for the easy comprehension of History)
of 1565/6 addressed scepticism about History’s reliability by providing readers
with criteria for discernment and writers with a manifesto on content.7
The main body of this chapter begins with general reflections on History’s
place within the wider intellectual developments of Renaissance Italy. Then it
shows how the historiographies of various states, as well as their political doc
trines, were to one degree or another influenced by particularistic tendencies in
Italian humanism, as well as by the impact of the Reformation. France is accorded
particular attention, and then more briefly England and parts of the Holy Roman
Empire. Then the chapter addresses the central historiographical battles that cor
responded to the religious conflicts of the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries.
These were battles of ecclesiastical History, centring on ancient sources. The
polemical nature of some of the disagreements and the accompanying instru
mentalization of the documentary record reinforced existing scepticism as to
History’s ‘epistemic’ status, which means that they buttressed doubts about the
reliability of historical knowledge claims. Yet an increasingly bipartisan critical
methodology developed, based on a combination of humanist philology and new
Re-Encounters
8 Schiffman, The Birth of the Past, 152; Christopher Celenza, ‘Humanism’, in Anthony Grafton,
Glenn W. Most, and Salvatore Settis (eds.), The Classical Tradition (Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press, 2010), 462–7, here 463.
9 Michael D. Reeve, ‘Classical Scholarship’, in Jill Kraye (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to
Renaissance Humanism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), 20–46, here 32, emphasis
added.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
but this was a matter of seizing an opportunity. The opportunity came from
another instance of cross-cultural encounter, as more classical texts washed up on
‘Europe’s’ shores, along with the experts in their interpretation, in the face of the
Ottoman annexation of Greece and the threat, and then, in 1453, the actuality, of
the conquest of Constantinople.
In 1390 the classical scholar Manuel Chrysoloras led a Byzantine delegation to
Venice to beg the assistance of Christian powers against the Ottomans, where
upon he impressed the Italian cognoscenti enough for Salutati later to invite him
to Florence to teach Greek literature and grammar. Chrysoloras’s grammar of
ancient Greek, later to be published courtesy of Gutenberg’s press, became a basic
text of the proliferating humanist scholars of that language, while his sometime
student Bruni translated a number of Plato’s Dialogues and letters. His archaeo
logical insights into ruins, as in his Comparison of Old and New Rome (1411) are
said to have marked ‘a significant step beyond Petrarch’, one ‘fundamental to the
Renaissance recovery of classical culture’ in the sense of reading ‘the remnant as
signifying an ideal whole’. Reliefs on statues, columns, and tombs revealed, in
Chrysoloras’s words ‘how things were in past times and what the differences were
between peoples’, offering ‘eyewitness knowledge [autopsía] of everything that has
happened’.10 Another influence was Georgius Gemistos ‘Plethon’ who arrived as
part of the Greek delegation at the councils of Florence–Ferrara in 1438–9, which
took abortive steps towards the reconciliation of Eastern and Western churches
in the context of the Ottoman rise and the Hussite wars. When not in session
Plethon gave a number of lectures contrasting Aristotelian and Platonic philoso
phy, which stimulated the Florentine Platonist intellectual movement.
Shortly before the Florence–Ferrara gatherings, Nicholas of Cusa (1401–64),
or Cusanus, met Plethon in a formative visit to Constantinople. Cusanus had
been exposed to humanist ideas during his education in Padua and had also been
educated at the Neoplatonist stronghold of Cologne. He shared Plethon’s desire
for a harmonious unitas ecclesiae, but we should not see this as yet another
Romano-Christian wish for the development of unity out of initial diversity, as
earlier seen in Eusebius’s chronography and Bede’s vision of the unifying of pagan
Britons under Christianity. Rather, Cusanus’s thought had connotations, within
limits, of unity-in-diversity, diversity as a descent from an initial unity in ‘the one’.11
10 Patricia Fortini Brown, Venice and Antiquity: The Venetian Sense of the Past (New Haven: Yale
University Press, 1996), 76–7. Brown also tells us that the idea of ancient artifacts and images offering
‘unmediated testimony—“autopsía” . . . would become one of the fundamental tenets of modern
archaeology’.
11 Jasper Hopkins, A Concise Introduction to the Philosophy of Nicholas of Cusa (Minneapolis:
University of Minnesota Press, 1978), 4, and passim; Marica Costigliolo, ‘Organic Metaphors in
“De concordantia catholica” of Nicholas of Cusa’, Viator 44:2 (2013), 311–21, here 312, 314. See also
(for some suggestive oppositions between Cusanus and the humanists on one hand and nominalism
on the other) parts 10–11 of the ‘Sequence on Political Ontology’ of John Milbank, Beyond Secular
Order: The Representation of Being and the Representation of the People (Hoboken, NJ: Wiley, 2013).
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
His On the Peace of Faith (1453), written at the time of the fall of Constantinople,
was an imagined dialogue between different Christian confessions, representa
tives of Islam, Judaism, and even of religions that would have been conceived
as ‘pagan’. While clearly prejudiced in favour of Christianity, and sometimes
dismissive of the beliefs of Jews, it sought to remove grounds for antagonism by
casting religious disagreements as misconceived on the basis that behind their
different ‘rites’ each religion tacitly shared the same assumptions and thus paved
the way to the higher truth. Within constraints, ‘diversity’ is accepted and even
welcomed.12 Such ideas influenced Marsilio Ficino (1433–99), who published the
Complete Works of Plato in translation in 1484.
Ficino, who was the first significant philosopher to win fame during his life
time as a result of the printing press, subsequently produced translations of major
Neoplatonists including Plotinus, whose rethinking of Plato was central to the
Neoplatonic revival. Ficino also translated the work of one ‘Hermes Trismegistus’,
supposedly an Egyptian priest who some accounts dated to around Abraham’s
time. We now know that the major texts of hermeticism were written at some
point in the first to third century ce, but the relevance is that ‘hermeticism’ may
well have helped draw humanists to Plato and Neoplatonism, linking Plato to the
ancient Hebrews, substantiating the idea that Platonic doctrine prefigured the
revelation of Christianity, and portraying Hermes as the medium of God’s revela
tion to Jews and pagans. Obversely, Florentine hermeticism was of a distinctly
Platonic tinge. Ficino gave the name prisca theologia to the single true theology
that is supposedly to be found within every religion. Hermeticism was also bound
to Neoplatonism in the work of Ficino’s student Gianfrancesco Pico della Mirandola,
author of the famous Oration on the Dignity of Man (1486). Neoplatonists of
following generations included Giordano Bruno and the Augustinian biblical
scholar Agostino Steuco (On the Perennial Philosophy, 1540) who wrote that Jews,
Egyptians, and Chaldaeans had bequeathed to the ancient Greeks doctrines
chiming with Christianity, like the creation of the world and the immortality of
the soul. The space for this sort of thought would be radically reduced over the
sixteenth century with the advent of Reformation and Counter-Reformation
demands on orthodoxy, but it survived nonetheless, and had an important role to
play in later historiography (see Chapters 5–6).13
12 Translated text of De Pace Fidei, in Jasper Hopkins, Nicholas of Cusa’s De Pace Fidei and Cribratio
Alkorani: Translation and Analysis (Minneapolis: The Arthur J. Banning Press, 1994), 633–70: see
especially Part XVIII, §66 and Part XIX, §§67–8 of De Pace Fidei at pp. 68–70. On Cusanus’s ‘plural
ism’, see Markus Riedenauer, Pluralität und Rationalität: Die Herausforderung der Vernunft durch
religiöse und kulturelle Vielfalt nach Nikolaus Cusanus (Stuttgart: Kohlhammer, 2007).
13 On hermeticism, see Florian Ebeling, The Secret History of Hermes Trismegistus (Ithaca: Cornell
University Press, 2007), esp. ch. 3. For other material see Frederick Purnell Jr, ‘Concord, Philosophical’,
in Anthony Grafton, Glenn W. Most, and Salvatore Settis (eds.), The Classical Tradition (Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press, 2010), 233–4, and ch. 4 of Richard H. Popkin (ed.), The Pimlico History
of Western Philosophy (London: Pimlico, 1999). On the Greek influence in particular, see Marios
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
through the mouth of their greatest authors that from the Greeks they received
all aspects of knowledge: the verdict of our own Cicero confirms that we Romans
either made wiser innovations than theirs by ourselves or improved on what we
took from them, but of course, as he himself says elsewhere with reference to his
own day: ‘Italy is invincible in war, Greece in culture’.14
In virtue of their language and knowledge, the ‘Byzantines’ were being cast as
Greeks by their world-historical successors, even though the Byzantines generally
regarded themselves as eastern Romans. They claimed heritage of an unbroken
imperial-cultural tradition from classical antiquity—and of a powerful strand of
Christianity.
An intriguing adjunct to the story is Plethon’s influence, via one of his students,
in the self-redefinition of Byzantines as Greeks rather than Romans. The classi
cizing Histories (1450s) of Laonikos Chalkokondyles (c.1430–c.1465) imitated
Thucydides in language and Herodotus in content, depicting the triumph of
oriental forces—now Ottoman Muslims rather than Persians—over occidental
ones. Chalkokondyles wrote in a secular vein, with no polemical hostility towards
Islam or ‘Turks’, and propounded a cultural–linguistic more than religious or
institution-based sense of Hellenism, which was appropriate at a time when the
‘Byzantine’ political structure had come crashing down. This sort of thinking
would be useful for members of the Greek émigré community in Italy, although
Chalkokondyles himself did not emigrate, as they tried to retain their cultural
distinctiveness and resist Italian condescension, while hoping that ‘westerners’
might some day retrieve Anatolia from the Ottoman grasp.15
Philippides and Walter K. Hanak, The Siege and the Fall of Constantinople in 1453: Historiography,
Topography and Military Studies (Farnham: Ashgate, 2011), 194–5.
when Florence was founded the city of Rome flourished greatly in power, liberty,
genius, and especially with great citizens. Now; after the Republic had been
16 Marin Sanudo, ‘Praise of the City of Venice, 1493’, in David Chambers, Brian Pullan, and
Jennifer Fletcher (eds.), Venice: A Documentary History, 1450–1630 (Oxford: Blackwell, 1992), 4–21,
with reference to shepherds at 4 and primacy at 5 and 16–17. Thanks to David Laven for this
reference.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
17 All quotes from the translation of Bruni’s Laudatio Florentinae Urbis or Panegyric to the City of
Florence (c.1403–4), online at https://www.york.ac.uk/teaching/history/pjpg/bruni.pdf
18 Mikael Hörnqvist, ‘The Two Myths of Civic Humanism’, in James Hankins (ed.), Renaissance Civic
Humanism: Reappraisals and Reflections (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000), 105–42, here
121–9.
19 Hans Baron, ‘Das Erwachen des historischen Denkens im Humanismus des Quattrocento’,
Historische Zeitschrift 147 (1932–3), 5–20, here 11–16.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
Bruni’s also unhelpfully being dubbed the first modern historian.20 Bruni’s third
historical phase began in the year 1250, which remains a popular point of departure
for Histories of the ‘late medieval’ or ‘early humanist’ periods. It was the year of the
death of Emperor Frederick II, which brought to an end the struggles between
the Hohenstaufen dynasty and northern Italian cities, permitting the consolidation
of the latter’s independence.
Bruni’s periodization suggests that for all the novel elements in his work it has
that familiar quality whereby concepts of temporal and cultural difference are
interwoven. While Salutati mixed respect for ‘Greeks’ with his condescension
towards them, both Petrarch and Bruni, so aware of the role of the historian in
fostering a cultural consciousness, ended up constructing and ‘othering’ a his
torical period by their scorn for the foreign cultures with which they associated
it. Indeed, this cultural stigmatization drove the periodization. Thus, whereas
Orosius had the Visigothic King Ataulf opting to develop Romania instead of
replacing it with Gothia, for Bruni this was just sophistry: if anything of the old
Rome endured, it was the name alone.21 In Petrarch’s Africa, the epic that made
this scion of Tuscany into Rome’s poet laureate, Petrarch has Scipio Africanus
the elder prophesying the downfall of Rome, whereupon ‘strangers of Spanish
and African extraction will steal the sceptre and the glory of the Empire founded
by us with great effort. Who can endure the thought of the seizure of supreme
control by these dregs of the people, these contemptible remnants, passed over by
our sword?’22 The ‘African’ and Spaniard he had in mind were probably the
emperors Septimus Severus and Theodosius. Spaniards and Africans were, how
ever, not the major targets of Petrarch or Bruni; ‘Goths’ were. By the sixteenth
century at the latest, the pejorative ‘Gothic’ was attached to high medieval archi
tecture (‘irrational’) and art, but it was used in the fifteenth century in relation
to architectural ornaments and ‘barbarous’ handwriting. ‘Goth’ was a catch-all
category for ‘Germanic’, or, still more broadly, ‘northerner’, which in turn denoted
anyone from the Visigoths through the Ostrogoths, the Lombards, the Franks,
and the inhabitants of much of the Holy Roman Empire latterly.23 Successive
emperors were not really Roman at all, and thus arguably not even legitimate
emperors: in a letter of 1333 Petrarch wrote of Charlemagne as ‘King Charles
who, by the cognomen of “the Great”, barbarous peoples dare to raise to the level
of Pompey and Alexander’.24
20 On the origins and endurance of this label, Gary Ianziti, ‘Leonardo Bruni: First Modern
Historian?’, Parergon 14:2 (1997), 85–99.
21 Baron, ‘Das Erwachen’, 14.
22 Theodor E. Mommsen, ‘Petrarch’s Conception of the “Dark Ages”’, Speculum 17 (1942), 226–42,
here 234–5.
23 On usages and referents, see variously Nick Groom, The Gothic (Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 2012), ch. 2; E. P. Goldschmidt, The Printed Book of the Renaissance (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1950), 2.
24 Mommsen, ‘Petrarch’s Conception’, 235.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
things of the sort Z could not have happened/been said/been thought at time Y
because of different cultural or socio-economic contexts, differing linguistic
idioms, and so on. It is the alleged failure of medieval thought in this second
respect that Valla is supposed to have overcome. Now on one hand we have
already seen that medieval scriptural exegetes had earlier developed something of
that which is attributed to Valla. On the other hand, it seems that whilst Valla
clearly possessed a sense of linguistic-cultural difference in his juxtaposition of
linguistic ‘barbarisms’ and classical purity, this awareness was associated less with
matters of temporality, asynchronicity, and anachronism than with cultural issues
that still pertained in the present, however much they also obtained in the past.
Germanic ‘barbarians’ still exist and write barbarically as they did before. The
major juxtaposition is not Constantine’s fourth-century-ness and the forger’s
likely eighth-century-ness. Parenthetically, partly because some of his assump
tions about classical purity were just assumptions, Valla ended up deploying the
critical standard of probability and likelihood which was familiar to medieval
chroniclers as much as to Herodotus.28
One major historian with a great historical interest in language but less of a
concern for rhetorical self-presentation was Flavio Biondo (1392–1463), to whom
Valla may well owe some of his critical insight.29 Biondo authored the massive
Decades historiarum ab inclinatione Romanorum imperii (Decades of History from
the Deterioration of the Roman Empire). Its title and span, from the sack of Rome
in 410 up to his present in 1440, indicate Petrarchian preoccupations. Given his
suspicion of partisan eyewitness testimony, a central concern of Biondo’s was
comparing and contrasting earlier narratives and other sources, to the point
where much of his writing was more of a disquisition on evidence and the work
of other historians than a continuous narrative. (This exercise in ‘showing one’s
working’ in the final written product rather than the seminar debate would peri
odically resurface in popularity, most recently from the late twentieth century.)
Tacitus, Sallust, and Orosius all fell grist to his critical mill. Among his critical-
linguistic concerns was the impossibility of channelling the vogue for classical
Latin into an accurate account of post-classical history. Thus, whilst ‘imperator’
had once signified a supreme military commander, now, in Biondo’s day, it meant
the Holy Roman Emperor. Gary Ianziti sees this sort of attention to language as a
new historiographical feature.30 It does not delegitimate all of Ianziti’s arguments
to point in qualification to Procopius’s excursus on the different sorts of combatant
indicated across time by the common term bowmen (pp. 79–80).
The critical use of a wide range of often conflicting sources was a signal feature
of Bruni’s work as much as Biondo’s, though in this respect we should only measure
the distance of either from previous historiography in relatively fine degrees not
28 Ibid. 20–4 (quotation from 23–4. 29 Ianziti, ‘Humanism’s New Science’, 61–2.
30 Ibid. 64–9, 82–4.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
nature.31 In Bruni’s case his critical endeavours were not purely the expression of
commitment to rigour in principle so much as a matter of casting the net widely
to substantiate new historical interpretations which had their own political con
notations. As with the twelfth- and thirteenth-century barons who shaped new
genealogical Histories, novelty was born of necessity. But a blow had still been
struck against the partly observed norm of accepting the verdicts of previous
generations of historians—this blow was the historiographical equivalent of the
earlier changes in the concept of auctoritas in scriptural exegesis. The earlier ‘con
vention’ had permitted many students of contemporary history to assume a solid
foundation upon which to construct their own edifices, which would in turn be
accepted as given. The revisionist attitude had the potential to keep everything
permanently open, as regards the past at least: the ever-moving present was a dif
ferent matter. Implicit in Bruni’s work, and more clearly in that of his follower
Matteo Palmieri and of Biondo, is the sense that the contemporary cannot be
written of in the same register as the past. Partly this is to do, as Valla noted in the
context of inscribing the deeds of his patron King Ferdinand, with the extra pres
sures involved in writing about the living and the still-influential. (Nothing new
there: see Polybius, Cassiodorus, and Henry of Huntingdon plus a long tradition
of criticism by allegory.32) But just as much, this problem arose from the fluidity
of the present and the sense that one does not have the same perspective on it as
one has on the past. For Biondo this sense was supposedly enhanced by rapid
change in the public and private spheres as well as technologies of warmaking.33
Here again, Procopius’s ‘bowmen’ are relevant to the historiographical debate.
One development in History’s purposes from the fifteenth and sixteenth centuries
onwards was the deployment of historically oriented exemplarity in the service of
a more fully fledged theory of autonomous political ethics. Bruni’s vitam et mores
et res gestas of Cicero preceded Machiavelli in separating questions of personal
31 As to ‘innovations’ in source criticism, bear in mind that the likes of Abelard had already
done some source-comparison work—p. 88. Additionally on medieval source criticism, Haskins,
Renaissance, 236; Charles C. Rozier, ‘Repairing the Loss of the Past: The Use of Written, Oral and
Physical Evidence in the Ecclesiastical History of Orderic Vitalis (c.1113−42)’, Historical Research,
92:257 (2019), 461–78.
32 Henry of Huntingdon devoted close attention to Henry I (r. 1100–35) much of it while Henry
was still on the throne. Around five years after the king’s death (c.1140), the historian wrote: ‘As usu
ally happens when a man dies, the frank opinions of the people came out.’ In his frank opinion he was
critical of the erstwhile monarch’s greed and cruelty. That opinion was radically revised later in a
substituted passage when it became apparent that the present king, Stephen, would be succeeded by
Henry’s grandson (Henry II). See Henry of Huntingdon, The History of the English People, 65, 134.
33 For all the themes of this paragraph, Ianziti, ‘Humanism’s New Science’, especially 64–5, 68–9,
74–80.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
morality from the political morality of the man of power: thus was History as
Lesson adapted to what the sociologist Max Weber would call the ethics of
responsibility of office. Like Machiavelli later, and Polybius long before, Bruni was
aware of the potentially advantageous or disadvantageous elements of his own
political context and the advancement his work might bring: Books VII–XII of
his History of the Florentine People accordingly served to vindicate the Medici oli
garchy which had come to power by the time of their writing or publishing. This
context might help explain his attitude to the exercise of political power. Previous
mirrors of princes had prioritized secular authority, but the extent of moral lee
way here (as judged against Christian teaching) was new. Unlike Plutarch, Bruni
did not see Cicero as failing because of personal shortcomings like excessive
ambition, and unlike Petrarch he did not see Cicero as innately flawed by his
ignorance of Christ. Rather, he saw that political struggles have their own rules,
the moral parameters of which are governed by matters like state survival.34 This
vision need not entail atheism. For Bruni, who influenced Machiavelli more than
did the theorist Valla, God provided an ultimate parameter, but that parameter
was a long way in the background. The ends of politics had not necessarily
changed, but in Bruni’s theory the means had.
By Machiavelli’s time, the political context had changed again, and it was above
all this context, in particular the ‘Italian wars’, also called the ‘Habsburg–Valois
wars’, that gave his work its urgency and edge. These wars lasted on and off from
1494 to 1559 and involved most of the Italian states in changing alliances with the
others and with one or other of the great powers, France, Spain, and the Holy
Roman Empire, that invaded parts of the peninsula at various points. At a time of
gross violence and destruction in Italy, it seems rather perverse that one of the
early consequences of the French invasion was an enhanced French Italophilia,
even if this could take the form of grand theft from Italian libraries. Another
expression of Italophilia was the royal patronization of an Italian, Paolo Emilio, to
write a celebratory History of France (De rebus gestis Francorum, 1516–19) in the
best humanist style.35 While interventions and attempted interventions in Italian
internal affairs by France and the Empire were by no means unprecedented, the
‘Italian wars’ shattered the relative peace northern Italy had enjoyed for a few
decades, and threatened Bruni’s vision of Florentine ascent.
34 Gary Ianziti, ‘A Life in Politics: Leonardo Bruni’s Cicero’, Journal of the History of Ideas, 61:1
(2000) 39–58, here 50–1, 56–8. Ianziti, Writing History in Renaissance Italy: Leonardo Bruni and the
Uses of the Past (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2012), Part II on the Florentine Histories.
On classical and medieval views of the connection between elite ethical conduct and the wellbeing of
the state, see Briggs, The Body Broken, 94.
35 On Italomania and plunder, Grell, ‘History and Historians in France’, 386–7, 394; on the
phenomenon of Italian humanists writing national histories for foreign monarchs, Markus Völkel,
‘Rhetoren und Pioniere. Italienische Humanisten als Geschichtsschreiber der europäischen Nationen.
Eine Skizze’, in Peter Burschel, Mark Häberlein, and Volker Reinhardt (eds.), Historische Anstöße
(Berlin: Akademie, 2002), 339–62.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
Political and military affairs could not be anywhere but at the centre of a
scholarly attempt to get to grips with the Italian situation, and while Machiavelli
wrote an orthodox historical work, the vernacular Florentine Histories, he is best
known today for crossing the line that divides exemplar History from political
theory grounded in historical thought. Machiavelli’s attitude to religion is a
matter of controversy. In separating political from Christian morality, or at least
Christian morality as interpreted by the church, he at once felt himself to be
describing elements of how ‘princes’ had actually behaved and encouraging
clearer thought about how they should behave. As constituted, Christian other
worldliness was unsuitable as a basis for civic virtù or political theory in a brutal
world.36 While the de facto situation had changed in the middle ages with the
growth of secular papal power, the de jure status of Christian morality remained,
creating a problematic tension. Machiavelli was actually true to a longstanding
tradition of trying to separate church and politics.37 In that sense he was also not
far from his contemporary Luther: both fancied themselves realists about worldly
politics, and, in their desire to end illusions about how government was run and
how it ought to be run—i.e. free from supervening ecclesiastical influence—both
gave secular governance the honour due to it.38 All this in turn reminds us of the
strength of the arguments that draw parallels between Machiavelli’s thought and
thought influenced by nominalism: theologically realist ‘ideas’ and conceptions of
divinely bequeathed order were replaced with rediscovered, capricious fortuna;
God-given moral rules gave way to flexible, prudential, and strategically immoral
leadership. One had to fall back on the mental synthesis of sensual experience
backed up by and systematized in historical enquiry—enquiry, that is, into the
way other humans had handled the world.39
In one sense Machiavelli’s work had the project of historical contextualization
at its core. It was predicated on the idea that the highest good, order, stemmed not
from fiat of higher authority but from the efforts of rulers in particular situations
36 Christian veneration of ‘humility, abnegation and contempt for mundane things’ were to be
contrasted with the ‘magnanimity, bodily strength’ and boldness encouraged in pre-Christian Rome.
Niccolò Machiavelli, The Discourses of Niccolò Machiavelli, vol. 1, ed. Leslie Walker (London: Routledge,
2013), II.2.6–8 (at p. 364).
37 Paul-Erik Korvela, ‘Machiavelli’s Critique of Christianity’, in Kari Palonen (ed.), Redescriptions:
Yearbook of Political Thought and Conceptual History, vol. 9 (Münster: LIT, 2005), 183–213, which also
invokes the work of Victoria Kahn on rhetoric. On new political means and old ends, Quentin Skinner
The Foundations of Modern Political Thought, vol. 1 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1978),
134–5.
38 R. H. Murray, The Individual and the State (London: Hutchinson, 1946), ch. 4; Quentin Skinner,
The Foundations of Modern Political Thought, vol. 2 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1978), 143.
39 Brian Harding, Not Even a God can Save Us Now: Reading Machiavelli after Heidegger (Montreal:
McGill-Queen’s University Press, 2017), ch. 3; for the nominalist connection, Michael Allan Gillespie,
The Theological Origins of Modernity (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2008), 134–8; at the nexus
of nominalist influence and historiography, Janet Coleman, ‘Machiavelli’s Via Moderna: Medieval
and Renaissance Attitudes to History’, in Martin Coyle (ed.), Niccolò Machiavelli’s The Prince: New
Interdisciplinary Essays (Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1995), 40–65.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
40 On Machiavelli see M. C. Lemon, Philosophy of History (London: Routledge, 2003), 96; Ernst
Cassirer, The Myth of the State (Hamburg: Meiner Verlag, 2007), 126–8; Robert Kocis, Machiavelli
Redeemed: Retrieving his Humanist Perspectives on Equality, Power and Glory (New Jersey: Associated
University Presses, 1998); Eugene Garver, ‘After Virtù: Rhetoric, Prudence and Moral Pluralism in
Machiavelli’, in Robert Hariman (ed.), Prudence: Classical Virtue, Postmodern Practice (University
Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University Press, 2003), 67–97, here 89; Grafton, What was History?, 214;
Coleman, Ancient and Medieval Memories, 585. For the parenthetical quote about The Prince, which is
originally from J. G. A. Pocock, see Olmstead, Rhetoric, 55.
41 Olmstead, Rhetoric, 54–5.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
Writers and practitioners of the ars historica claimed that they knew how to
walk the tightrope that stretched between practical application and pure his
toricism. In fact, however, they could not explain even to themselves how the
42 From Guicciardini, Storia d’Italia (1537–40), cited in Mark Phillips, Francesco Guicciardini: The
Historian’s Craft (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1977), 27. More generally on Guicciardiani,
Nicolai Rubinstein, ‘The “Storie fiorentine” and the “Memorie di famiglia” by Francesco Guicciardini’,
Renascimento 4 (1953), 171–225.
43 Woolf ‘From Hystories to the Historical’, 43–4; Ianziti, ‘Humanism’s New Science’, 67; Connell,
‘Italian Renaissance Historical Narrative’, 360.
44 For the phrasing of the latter dilemma, see the editor’s introduction to Frederick Beiser (ed.),
The Cambridge Companion to Hegel and Nineteenth Century Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2008), 7.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
modern reader was supposed to go about both setting his texts back into their
own times, with all the skill of a philologist, and making them relevant to his
own day, with the bravura of a rhetorician.45
We should perhaps take ‘historicism’ here in the limited sense of being historically
contextualized and thus non-transferable, rather than as having the connotations of
relativism that some latter-day historicisms do. But the distinction is not always an
easy one to make, as further reflection on the concept of ‘contextualization’ shows.
An oddity of a profession whose practitioners so regularly invoke the practice
of contextualization is how rarely that practice is subject to conceptual scrutiny.46
Consider two main sorts of contextualization: functional and cultural. The prop
osition underlying functional contextualizations is ‘If I were in their situation
I would act as they do’, as for instance when one considers the extremity of human
behaviour in wartime or other situations of duress. This approach posits a basically
shared human rationality and value system. If functional contextualization con
cerns ‘people like us’ albeit in particular situations, cultural contextualization
concerns people who are ‘just different to us’ in their rationality and/or value
system. Cultural contextualization is involved when historians talk about ‘under
standing people in the context of their own time’ and it is implicit in the
description of the past as a ‘foreign country’. Thinking back to the previous chapter,
Maimonides’ theory of accommodation has more of the element of ‘cultural’
contextualization whereas Augustine’s theory is based more on a ‘functional’
contextualization in terms of its focus on political conditions (p. 89–92). But the
distinction between these two forms of contextualization is not always clear-cut
and what at first glance looks like a cultural argument may in fact be a functional
argument. Thus if one observes that different societies can have very different
birthrates one might automatically lean to a cultural interpretation, only to factor
in more functional thought when the correlation is revealed between birthrate
and poverty. Conversely, if one is exposed to new (functional) circumstances for
long enough, one becomes acculturated/socialized into/by those circumstances.
Since a certain amount of confusion still reigns about the nature of contextualiza
tion and since the above sorts are only entirely distinct in their ideal types, one
who searches for perfect clarity in contextualization now or previously is on a
fool’s errand. The matter is yet further complicated when one factors in contrast
ing historical interests that produce focuses on different aspects of the past.
One especially salient contrast concerns focuses on the ‘external’ element of
action in the world as against focuses on the internal element of thought and
spirit. To explore this contrast, let us juxtapose Roman annals and medieval
chronicles with scriptural hermeneutics. The relevant distinction concerns the
emphasis on elucidating gestae (deeds), with its associations with genealogical
and exemplar History, versus the emphasis on interpreting meaning, with its
associations with History as Communion. Again, the distinction is of an ideal
nature, since the elucidation of events and the interpretation of meaning can
go together, in the sense of understanding the motive that led to a deed or the
significance that the historical actor attributed to the deed, just as one can
devote intensive hermeneutic endeavour to divining the meaning of some event
described in the scriptures. Nonetheless there can be a significant difference of
emphasis between the more ‘exterior’ and more ‘interior’ approaches and it has
ramifications for what ‘contextualization’ is taken to mean. For instance, a focus
on the visible externalities of events might serve to immortalize actors and monu
mental deeds in a way that renders irrelevant the passage of time, whereas a focus
on the internal ‘Gestalt’ of some ancient mind or church synod requires some
distancing historicization in the first place even if just as a prelude to locating
what is really relevant today after the historicization has been conducted.
Ultimately, we have four poles at the respective ends of two axes—interior
versus exterior interest, functional versus cultural contextualizations—and can
produce various permutations. Since these axes have any number of points
between the poles the number of potential permutations when we move away
from ideal forms is limitless. Any given permutation could produce a History that
was novel, but that is very often the case with combinations, and novelty in this
sense is not necessarily profound. What we may safely say is that all four ‘poles’
were present in historiographical thought for centuries before Guicciardini and
his successors, and, accordingly, the potential for all manner of different permuta
tions had also existed even if not all those permutations had been realized.
To turn the same point around, if the potential for conflict between different
interests and contextualizations pre-dated the Italian Renaissance, then the
ability to reconcile or at least ameliorate such conflict was also present, and
continued to be so. In the period covered by this chapter, whether or not the
choice between emphasizing contextualization or exemplarity was really a choice
between assumed opposites, exemplarity did remain one of the major rationales
for historical scholarship.47 And as we shall now see, Polybius’s cyclical doctrine
47 For the opposition, Grafton, What was History?, 228 and Ianziti, ‘Humanism’s New Science’, 60,
though there Ianziti also stresses the general reaffirmation at the time, contra Guicciardini, of the
‘paradigmatic nature of past experience’ and thus the idea that historia magistra vitae. On the latter,
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
of History, anacyclosis (p. 36), and its close relation, the stoic concept of similitudo
temporum, which was associated with Tacitus, provided one way among others to
square exemplarity with at least some sorts of contextualism.
Without naming Polybius, more and more of whose work had become available
in translation since its rediscovery at the start of the fifteenth century, Machiavelli’s
work reveals the influence of the anacyclosis concept, while Book I, chapter 2 of
the Discourses on Livy draws extensively on Polybius’s sixth book. Machiavelli was
less interested in tracing historical cycles than in apprehending Polybius’s lesson
in how human actors might intervene to influence the cycle—as in Polybius’s
example of the creation of the mixed Roman constitution.48 Similitudo temporum
was explored by Bodin, the Flemish jurist and historian François Baudouin
(1520–73), and other influential contemporaries in the sixteenth century. The
concept helped move the focus away from individuals, whether in the classical
and medieval garb of res gestae or the late medieval and early humanist clothing
of biography and ‘life-writing’, and towards other times as a whole, especially cri
sis moments.49 With the rebirth of similitudo temporum, as it were, one could
acknowledge historical periodization and past–present contextual difference in
principle while, in practice, also availing oneself of those select bits of the past
that were deemed relevant to the present. Alternatively, as with the later Lutheran
theologian Georg Calixtus (1586–1656), one could use the birth of Christ as a
mirror point, with each numbered century working back from him finding some
reflection in the events of the corresponding century working forward.50 By the
lights of similitudo temporum Tacitus could be appropriated as an effective con
temporary, as in a number of seventeenth-century images that depict him as an
early modern scholar.51 It was indeed Tacitus, whose Annals and Histories were
brought to Florence in the 1390s and became increasingly widely known from the
1420s, who became the greatest classical beneficiary of the classical theory,
though uses of him were often intertwined with uses of Polybius.
Rüdiger Landfester, Historia magistra vitae: Untersuchungen zur humanistischen Geschichtstheorie des
14. bis. 16. Jahrhunderts (Geneva: Droz, 1972).
Montaigne was taken with Tacitus’s psychological approach, dubbing his work
‘a seminary of moral, and a magazine of politique discourses for the provision
and ornament of those that possess some place in the managing of the world’,
whilst Francis Bacon borrowed from his style as well as his History.52 Tacitus fell
into that select category of historians whom Montaigne felt had ‘a right to assume
the authority for moulding our beliefs on theirs’, who could infer the motives of
princes from their ‘characters and humours’, and who ‘put appropriate words into
their mouths’. (In Montaigne’s view those lesser historians who were aware of
their own limitations stuck to the compilation of facts, while the commonest sort
of historian made judgements but with insufficient wisdom to justify their pre
sumption to judge.)53 The catastrophic conflict scarring the mostly Protestant
Netherlands—the Dutch Revolt from 1568 to 1648 against Spain under the
Habsburg Philip II—provided the classicist Justus Lipsius with the justification of
historical analogy to publish a major edition of Tacitus’s work in 1574. The doc
trine of similitudo temporum led Lipsius to compare the prevailing political
context to that of imperial Rome, hence his view of Tacitus as velut theatrum
hodiernae vitae, ‘in sum, a theatrical representation of life today’.54 Polybius pro
vided substantive advice to go with the historical analogy. Book 6 of his Histories
was not just applicable to Machiavelli’s preoccupations with governance, but
owing to its detail on the Roman military, prompted Lipsius to write the Five
Books on the Roman Army. A Commentary on Polybius (1595) that shaped the
military reforms of William of Nassau who went on to end Spanish hegemony in
the Netherlands.55 Christopher Watson’s English translation of Polybius in 1568
picked out the Greek historian’s ‘holsome counsels and wonderful devices against
the inconstances of fickle Fortune’.56
As with any instance of History by analogy, all manner of opportunities pre
sented themselves to the skilled rhetorician, and if the truth be known, Lipsius
sometimes forewent the principle of careful comparison between periods in the
interests of self-serving example-grabbing.57 His Tacitus was dedicated to the
Holy Roman Emperor Maximilian II and he had taught Maurice, Prince of
Orange, whereas two centuries later Orangists were denouncing the use of
52 Montaigne cited in J. H. M. Salmon, ‘Stoicism and Roman Example: Seneca and Tacitus in
Jacobean England’, Journal of the History of Ideas, 50:2 (1989), 199–225, here 210; on Bacon, Francis
Bacon, Essays (London: JM Dent and Sons, 1972), pp. xvii–xviii.
53 Michel de Montaigne, Essays, ed. J. M. Cohen (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1976),169–70.
54 Daniel Simhon, ‘Similitudo Temporum: Agrippine et Medea, Marie et Médéé’, in
Richard G. Hodgson (ed.), La Femme au XVIIe siècle (Tübingen: Gunter Narr, 2002), 97–114, here 114
for the quote and 97 and passim for Lipsius’s general significance.
55 McGing, Polybius’ Histories, 215. 56 Polybius, The Rise, introduction, 19.
57 On this variation, see Harro Höpfl, ‘History and Exemplarity in the Work of Lipsius’, in Erik De
Bom, Marijke Janssens, Toon Van Houdt and Jan Papy (eds.), (Un)masking the Realities of Power:
Justus Lipsius and the Dynamics of Political Writing in Early Modern Europe (Leiden: Brill, 2010),
43–73, here 70–1; Bermejo, Translating Tacitus, 92 ff.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
58 On the eighteenth century Dutch debates, Wyger R. E. Velema, Republicans: Essays on Eighteenth
Century Dutch Political Thought (Leiden: Brill, 2007), 69–70; Bermejo, Translating Tacitus, 92 ff.
59 Tutino, Shadows of Doubt, 62; Ronald Mellor, Tacitus (New York: Routledge, 1994), 145;
Momigliano, Classical Foundations, 117.
60 Zoe Lowery, Historiography (New York: Britannica Educational Publishing, 2016), 34–5.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
Roman law was, like so much else, completely ahistorical, with no awareness of
the many differences between Roman and medieval society’.61 In correcting such
views one first needs to recall the historical endeavour that had already gone into
harmonizing legal-moral thought in the twelfth century (p. 90), prior to the pro
duction in the early thirteenth century of the collection of legal interpretations
( glossae) known as the Glossa ordinaria. But much more needs to be said by way
of nuance and partial rebuttal.
An important context is that Roman law of any sort was only thought to
endure with force of law in parts of Italy and southern France; beyond those
areas it could only ever exercise influence on the legal systems that were in place
prior to the rediscovery of the Digest, and thus always existed in tension with
other precepts, whatever the desire for jurisprudential harmony. This tension
helps explain the evolution of the ‘post-glossators’, pre-eminently Bartolus de
Sassoferrato (1313–57), who certainly did not treat ‘Roman law as an internally
consistent body of universal law, to be freely interpreted for application to the
modern world’. (Note that the label mos italicus applies to both the glossators and
the post-glossators in whose ranks Bartolus figured.) Bartolus opened the door
to compromises with customary legal systems in a way that actually made some
version of ‘applied’—as opposed to ‘pure’—Roman law quite attractive to codifiers
of customary law, ensuring that it retained wide influence for a long time to
come, even in Britain which had no ‘continental’ civil law tradition. Roman law
would also influence the Code Napoleon of 1804, which standardized the legal
system in France and is not generally thought of as an instance of medieval
anachronism.62
Furthermore, to contrast the post-glossators or their predecessors with a point
edly named ‘historical school’ of jurisprudence63 obscures the fact that some
of the thinkers generally placed in the historical school by no means jettisoned
all Bartolist precepts. The man sometimes identified as the pioneer of the anti-
Bartolist historical study of the law in France, Guillaume Budé (1468–1540),
seems on closer inspection not to fit that picture either.64
61 Stephen Davies, Empiricism and History (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2003), 15.
62 The ‘universal law’ quote from Schiffman, On the Threshold, 19, as contrasted with
Daniel R. Coquillette, The Civilian Writers of Doctors’ Commons, London (Berlin: Duncker and
Humblot, 1988), 42–3; Walter Ullmann, The Medieval Idea of Law as Represented by Lucas de Penna
(Routledge, 2010), ch. 1 and the introduction by H. D. Hazeltine; Michèle Ducos, ‘Legal Science in
France in the 16–17th Centuries’, in Gerald N. Sandy (ed.), The Classical Heritage in France (Leiden:
Brill, 2002), 297–314, here 312.
63 As for instance Schiffman, On the Threshold, 18; Davies, Empiricism and History, 16.
64 See generally the discussion in Ducos, ‘Legal Science in France’; Ullmann, The Medieval Idea of
Law, pp. xxvii–xxix; J. G. A. Pocock, The Ancient Constitution and the Feudal Law (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1987), 23–5, on Jean Bodin and ‘neo-Bartolism’. On Budé,
Douglas J. Osler, ‘Budaeus and Roman Law’, Ius commune: Veröffentlichungen des Max-Planck-Instituts
für Europäische Rechtsgeschichte, vol. XIII, ed. Dieter Simon and Walter Wilhelm (Frankfurt am Main:
Klostermann, 1985), 195–212.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
Finally, some of those who did set their faces against Bartolus were effectively
just claiming to do the same thing better. Take Andrea Alciato (1492–1550), an
Italian lawyer who spent much of his career teaching in France and helped intro
duce the new humanist-critical style that came to characterize the mos gallicus.
For Alciato, the purpose of the philological exercise was to clear away latter-day
accretions from the Roman law in order to access the purified original, rather
than engaging extensively with glosses that merely confused the issue further. He
was just as presentist as the scholastic hermeneuts in the quest for relevance,
merely disagreeing about what it was that needed to be rendered relevant.65
The most extensive historicization of law—here meaning the contextualization
of legal doctrines according to the different historical junctures at which they
were established—was triggered almost by accident, and its fullest ramifications
were not widely accepted. The critical skills wielded by Budé and Alciato, who
were themselves indebted to Valla’s and Poliziano’s philology, were passed down
to the next generation, including Bodin and Baudouin, but for such scholars the
intellectual implications of the analysis were negative as much as positive, for
reasons that ought now to be familiar: if the Digest was a product of its times,
which were far removed, what interest did it have for anyone other than the anti
quarian? Some legal theorists like Jacques Cujas (1522–90) may have been pre
pared to accept the basic irrelevance of Roman law, but that was not the prevailing
view, and since some Roman law continued to hold influence in parts of France
the matter could not be ignored. There was a more general principle at stake
about the relationship between past and present. Ostensibly the most fervent his
toricizer of Cujas’s and Baudouin’s generation of mos gallicus students, François
Hotman (1524–90), wrote at length in his Anti-Tribonian (1567)66 about the
unreliability of the Justinian Code as a guide even to anything ancient, as well as
denying its transferability to the present. Yet he concluded the work commending
something like Plato’s project in his third book of the Laws (p. 33) in much the
same way as Bodin had done very recently in the Methodus: putting aside specific
regulations, Hotman felt one ought to study Roman and other law codes in the
search for general underlying principles ‘founded on a natural justice, reason, and
equity’.67 Here, ‘contextualization’ meant contextualizing in order to arrive at a
point beyond contextualization.
Baudouin’s Institutio historiae universae (On the Institution of Universal History
and its Conjunction with Jurisprudence, 1561) also sought to understand the past
on its own terms and as fully as possible in order to establish what principles from
the past still obtained in the present, and what was historically variable. Baudouin
viewed the marriage of history and jurisprudence as the way to provide lessons
for the running of a state. He therefore endorsed the ‘classical’ notion of ‘pragmatic’
history as ‘the form of history that exerts itself to explain and wisely and usefully
demonstrates what it narrates, so that it describes not only events, but their
causes, and gives events with their counsels’.68 His work was more a guide to the
researching of History than the writing of it as he weighed and distinguished
between primary and secondary sources, examining eyewitness evidence and
other historical scholarship. The conjunction of his opus and Bodin’s Methodus
only five years later underlines the continuing advances in the ars historica.
Bodin advocated a vastly ambitious study of human affairs, including geo
graphical, climatic, and even cosmological influences, down to social and govern
mental arrangements, and how they changed over time. In his quest for causes
and deep principles and patterns, which suggests the influence of Polybius’s
theory of cycles, he was influential, though not original, in rejecting the ‘four
monarchies’ theory of translatio imperii (p. 53). His prescriptions for the content
of historical enquiry presupposed the capacity critically to appraise the historian
ship upon which one was reliant in all of these wide-ranging investigations.
He emphasized some critical historiographical principles, including the process
of comparing and contrasting existing works of History, and reflecting on the
subject-position of authors.
Universalistic and particularistic elements both appeared in Bodin’s work as
much as they did in Italian humanism, and while they sometimes jostled they
could also complement each other. The element of cultural nationalism in the
Methodus marks Bodin as a ‘man of his times’, times which included not just the
wars of religion of 1562–98 but also the spread of Lutheranism and Calvinism
into France from 1520 that supplied much of the tinder—the ‘French Reformation’
is said to have begun in 1534. A more specific context was the atmosphere after
France’s decisive defeat by the Habsburgs in the Italian Wars at Pavia in 1525.
Hispanophobia waxed; Italophilia waned. Rabelais might still try to distance him
self from ‘the Goths, who had dealt all literature a death blow’, but the equally
humanist Etienne Pasquier (1529–1615) was stung by Italian scorn for the ‘bar
barian’ French into trying to raise the cultural level of French vernacular letters.69
Legislation about the official use of French evinced a determination to replace
Latin as a language of culture, and the distancing of Roman law paved the way for
68 Grafton, What Was History?, 70–2; Jacques Bos, ‘Nineteenth-Century Historicism and its
Predecessors: Historical Experience, Historical Ontology and Historical Method’, in R. Bod, J. Maat,
and T. Weststeijn (eds.), The Making of the Humanities, vol. 2 (Amsterdam: Amsterdam University
Press, 2012), 131–47, here 136.
69 On Rabelais see Schabert, ‘Modernity and History I’, 10. On Pasquier, Schiffman, On the
Threshold, 39.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
a stress on the relevance of French customary law, which fed into a growing
interest in the particularity of French customs and culture tout court.70
A new myth of national origins replaced that one associated with classicism. Its
first point of reference was ancient Gaul, with Julius Caesar’s Commentaries on the
Gallic Wars being a prime source of both History and inspiration. Gallic culture,
portrayed as enduring under Roman rule, providing a supposedly unbroken if
sometimes subterranean line to the French present.71 The link is explicit in the
title of Hotman’s 1574 book Franco-Gallia. Pasquier’s Recherches de la France
(1560) began not, as per medieval convention, with mythic diasporic Trojans, but
with Gauls.72 There are elements of prefiguration in the story, as in so many
genealogical accounts where links are made across large tracts of time, but the
story was ethno-national rather than religious in content, which may explain
why moderate Huguenots like Hotman and self-styled independent minds like
Pasquier were prominent in propounding it.73 Where confession divided, custom
might unite. The characteristics of custom, as in customary law, also made it more
relevant to historians shaped by the precepts of the mos gallicus, who might
otherwise historicize the deeper past into oblivion. Indeed while the mos gallicus
denoted a particular French school of thinking about law, we can associate it with
a wider set of customary concerns that included but were not limited to law.
Custom, as studied in Pasquier’s pathbreaking collection of essays in the his
torical ethnography of his own country, complicates any sharp ‘othering’ of the
past. The logic went that, unlike written law, which can be pinned to specific
meanings of time and place, customary law develops with the society bearing the
custom. As almost a living, evolving force in Hotman’s depiction, custom creates
a conduit from past and present, discarding what is no longer needed, preserving
that which is necessary: what exists, what remains, has proved its worth.74 In the
narrower terms of the development of historiography, a concern with custom was
married to a concern with causation. It was no longer enough just to establish a
lineage from deep past to present. Now one had also to explain how state of affairs
A developed into state of affairs B and so on down to the present.
This building-block method of linking past to present, with a focus on culture
and institutional structures rather than ‘accidental’ events, is well exemplified in
70 Ducos, ‘Legal Science in France’; Peter Stein, Roman Law in European History (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2012), 77–9; Schiffman, On the Threshold, 19, 39.
71 Claude-Gilbert Dubois, Celtes et Gaulois au XVIe siècle: Le développement littéraire d’un mythe
nationaliste (Paris: Vrin, 1972).
72 Étienne Pasquier, Les Recherches de la France d’Estienne Pasquier (Paris: Pierre Menard 1643),
3 ff. On the Trojan question, 37.
73 On some of the contrivances of Pasquier’s image, Catherine Magnien-Simonin, ‘Étienne
Pasquier (1529–1615) ou la dissidence discrète’, Les Dossiers du Grihl (online) (January 2013): http://
journals.openedition.org/dossiersgrihl/5748
74 Pocock, The Ancient Constitution, 15.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
75 See Schiffman’s On the Threshold, 31–3 and passim, for most of the analysis in this paragraph.
76 La Popelinière, L’Histoire des histories: L’Idée de l’histoire accomplie, cited in Costas Gaganakis,
‘Thinking About History in the European Sixteenth Century: La Popelinière and his Quest for “Perfect
History” ’, Historein, 10 (2010), 20–7, here 23.
77 On La Boderie and the hermetic and Neoplatonic connection, including the popularity of such
thinking in particular French intellectual circles, Frances A. Yates, Ideas and Ideals in the North
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
The association of Gomer with Noah shows a link to the monotheisms that is also
posited by the Egyptian ‘Hermes’’ alleged contemporaneity with Abraham and
by Plato’s supposed knowledge of Jewish scripture.
Bodin’s Methodus combines French boosterism and respect for Jewish
antiquity. Bodin was also taken with druidic wisdom, but where La Boderie saw a
divine light being passed from discrete civilization to discrete civilization, and
where La Popelinière advocated a culture-by-culture accounting, Bodin, like
Gerald of Wales before him, stressed the interaction of civilizations as they learn
from and mingle with each other. Jewish primacy comes from Bodin’s conviction
that only Jews ‘can boast about the antiquity of their origin and the great age
of their race’.78 Elements of advance through interaction/exchange and of prisca
theologia-type belief in the inner truth of different (but still broadly occidental)
traditions are both present in Bodin’s Colloquium of the Seven About Secrets of the
Sublime, manuscripts of which were circulated after its completion in 1588. In the
vein of Cusanus’s On the Peace of Faith in the previous century, Bodin’s convers
ing seven are: a Catholic, a Lutheran, a Calvinist, a Jew, a Muslim, a sceptic, and a
philosophical naturalist.79
Modern Contextualization?
European Renaissance (London: Routledge, 1999), 117–18, quote on ‘cult of ancient wisdoms’ from
117. See also Henry Hornik, ‘Guy Lefèvre de La Boderie’s La Galliade and Renaissance Syncretism’,
Modern Language Notes, 76:8 (1961), 735–42.
which, to interpret the actions, words and thoughts of the men who lived at that
time’; ‘postulating that there existed, in the past of their own civilization, tracts of
time in which the thoughts and actions of men had been so remote in character
from those of the present as to be intelligible only if the entire world in which
they had occurred were resurrected, described in detail and used to interpret
them’.81 Certainly, the degree to which the contexualizing approach was then
practised does appear to be different to anything previous. But however extensive
contextualizing History was in the sixteenth century, or is now, it could not meet
Pocock’s exacting standard whereby an ‘entire world’ is reproduced in order to
shed light on meanings and deeds. Who is to decide if enough relevant settings
from the past have been described and whether they have been described in suf
ficient ‘detail’, especially since before this level of contextualization was applied
historians did not unreasonably think themselves capable of rendering certain
actions and deeds ‘intelligible’? A standard of proper History is being invoked by
Pocock, but in the absence of a total contextualization, which might be a descrip
tion that never stopped, there will always be arguments about which aspects of
which contexts ought to be emphasized. It is manifestly not the case that no pre-
sixteenth-century History took a concern to contextualize anything at all since
some act of contextualization is inextricable from the act of explanation and thus
an account of causation. In fact there is no difference between a context and a
cause; they are names we pragmatically give to different parts of an explanation.
Saying that Jill kissed Jane out of love is to say that love belongs to the causal
explanation of Jill’s kiss, but we might just as well call love a context for the kiss.
As soon as a historian offers any causal (part) explanation for anything she is
providing a (part) contextualization.
Schiffman’s concern to identify what is ‘modern’ is more philosophical than
methodological. He talks of a culturally relativistic outlook amongst the ‘new his
torians’ of the sixteenth century who were informed by the mos gallicus. More
precisely he sees them as having ‘the experience of relativism’ without going the
whole hog and embracing the ‘doctrine of relativism’. In fact he portrays a retreat
from the implications of relativism on the part of the historians concerned, with
out making clear whether this was a conscious or unconscious reaction. For all
the brilliance of his textual exegesis, he provides little evidence for the claim that
it was just too much for the sixteenth-century historians to follow through with
the relativistic implications of their findings. His reasoning is hamstrung from the
outset in that he never defines relativism in a precise fashion. It is difficult to see
what is meant by the ‘experience of relativism’ as separate from the ‘doctrine’ of it,
since relativism is nothing if not a doctrine. Schiffman describes the experience
of relativism as ‘an awareness of the human world as being filled with unique
historical entities, such as laws, institutions, and states’, but such an awareness has
no logical consequences for relativistic doctrine-building from which a retreat
had perforce to be beaten if the consequences were too much to bear. To think
otherwise is to elide ‘is’ and ‘ought’: awareness of uniqueness might provide the
grist for relativism but it might also provide the grist for scepticism about values
or a neutralist withholding of any value considerations or an attempt to prove one
set of unique institutions superior to another.82 Indeed it would require some
extensive argument to reconcile La Popelinière’s position with relativism. He has
a distinctly ‘progressivist’ view, stating that his present civilization ought to be
‘superior in all things’ to earlier versions partly because of its own historical
knowledge. Furthermore, one rationale for his studying the indigenous peoples of
the Americas is that they are on the same ‘primitive’ level as ancient civilizations.83
The wider importance of the point is that Schiffman sees a later, more complete
embrace of relativism as being the moment when historical thought became fully
modern. To borrow from the title of his first book, On the Threshold of Modernity,
the sixteenth-century historians refused to cross the threshold. The title of his
second book, The Birth of the Past, purports to show how scholars of the seven
teenth and eighteenth centuries took this decisive step. Now it is true that strands
of relativism—here meaning moral–cultural relativism—have been important in
shaping important historiographical norms in recent centuries, much more so than
the epistemological relativism that has been much discussed in recent decades.
Here Schiffman displays more self-awareness than many practising historians of
recent generations, who if they ever discuss the matter may distance themselves
from relativism even while tacitly endorsing it in the name of a certain interpretation
of ‘historicization’. But other influences have also shaped modern historiographical
norms, such as the pressure for neutrality or impartiality (see Chapter 6), and
these tendencies are not the same as relativism even if sometimes they appear to
promote a similar outlook. In his imprecision about the conditions and meaning
of relativism Schiffman actually epitomizes a disciplinary confusion that still
reigns about how we do, and should, orientate ourselves towards the pasts on
which we write (see Chapter 8).
Montaigne
‘Relativist’ is not the correct epithet for Michel de Montaigne (1533–92), who is
far better known than the new historians of the sixteenth century and just as con
cerned with human diversity. The major classical influence on his moral thought
was scepticism: Sextus Empiricus’s concerns were at least as much about ethical
convictions as knowledge. The doctrines of scepticism and relativism are actually
not good bedfellows, since relativism is one of those strong conclusions that the
sceptic is chary of endorsing, or at least endorsing strongly. It is scepticism that
underpinned Montaigne’s anti-dogmatism. While recognizing the strong attach
ment to belief that acculturation brings, he professed uncertainty about any
specific belief-system. To explain his stance, we might look to the context of
burgeoning religious strife and also his stint as Mayor of Bordeaux, holding the
city for Henri III, France’s most sexually controversial monarch, who could not
but have benefited from Montaigne’s elaboration of varying sexual mores from
around the world. Looking backwards in time, Montaigne approved of Ammianus
Marcellinus as a ‘pagan’, classicizing historian who was nonetheless fair to
Christians and critical of the religious policies of the emperor Julian. Looking out
to the wider world Montaigne’s argument for religious toleration went hand-in-
hand with reflections such as his essai ‘On Cannibals’.
On the whole, Montaigne seems to have viewed the differences between
peoples as being superficial rather than deep, and thus at some level reconcilable.
He also tacitly subscribed to some moral absolutes, and, alongside proposing
arguments that appealed to ‘nature’, he believed in a superior rationality. His
admiration of the martial courage of indigenous south American peoples was less
an instance of taking them on their own terms than finding commonality with
the Greek culture that he so admired. He identified with the ‘cannibals’’ viewpoints
when that helped in rendering self-criticism of French and European society. At
the same time, in ‘On Cannibals’ the opposed categories of ‘barbarian’/‘savage’ are
revealed to be a matter of perspective rather than objective judgement. ‘Savages’’
mechanisms of leadership selection might compare favourably with allowing
children to accede on the basis of heredity alone, while European inequalities
exceeded anything that the old inhabitants of the ‘new world’ had to offer. It was
not obviously worse to eat other men than to eat one’s own god by way of com
munion; in any case, eating the bodies of the dead was better than torturing the
bodies of the living. Overall, self-reflection is Montaigne’s point—self-reflection
as an ethos, making an enemy of dogmatism and blind assumptions of superior
ity or rectitude in light of agonizing schisms in his own civilization. The reversal
of the gaze at the end of ‘On Cannibals’, where French society is seen through the
eyes of indigenous Americans, indicates the capacity to estrange one’s own ‘mores’,
to see them from the perspective of an outsider to them.84
84 Montaigne, Essays, 113, 114, 118–19, 184; Edwin M. Curley, ‘Skepticism and Toleration: The
Case of Montaigne’, Oxford Studies in Early Modern Philosophy, 2 (2005), 1–33; Ann Hartle,
‘Montaigne’s Accidental Moral Philosophy’, Philosophy and Literature 24:1 (2000), 138–53; Katherine
Crawford, The Sexual Culture of the French Renaissance (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
2010), pp. ix–xii. Finally, thanks to Felicity Green for her thoughts on these matters.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
85 Philippe Desan (ed.), Montaigne politique (Paris: Honoré Champion Éditeur, 2006), contains
essays exploring all sides of the issue, including the central question of the tension between
Montaigne’s public role and his role as a private intellectual.
86 This explanation for the decline of the ‘new history’ is broadly George Huppert’s in The Idea
of Perfect History: Historical Erudition and Historical Philosophy in Renaissance France (Urbana:
University of Illinois Press, 1970).
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
87 De Grazia, ‘Anachronism’, 24–5. Daniel Woolf, ‘Historical Writing in Britain from the Late
Middle Ages to the Eve of Enlightenment’, in Rabasa et al. (eds.), The Oxford History of Historical
Writing 1400–1800, 473–96, here 478–81.
88 Pocock, The Ancient Constitution. On William of Malmesbury, see R. M. Thompson, ‘William of
Malmesbury’s Diatribe against the Normans’, in Martin Brett and David A. Woodman (eds.), The Long
Twelfth-Century View of the Anglo-Saxon Past (Farnham: Ashgate, 2015), 113–22.
89 Woolf, ‘Historical Writing’, 482–3.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
At the same time as History was enjoying a mutually beneficial relationship with
philology, via jurisprudence, it continued to be shaped in tandem with an older
partner: religious hermeneutics. Baudouin features in both relationships, for
he was sometime collaborator of the man often viewed as the father of ‘modern’
or at least Protestant hermeneutics—Matthias Flacius Illyricus.91 Like Luther,
Flacius (1520–75) was a traveller on the via moderna first paved centuries earlier
by men such as Ockham, who, for Luther, was ‘magister meus’, ‘mein lieber
92 Matthias Kossler, Empirische Ethik und christlicher Moral (Würzburg: Königshausen und
Neumann, 1999), 312.
93 Dilthey, ‘The Development of Hermeneutics’, 252–3. 94 Kelber, ‘The Quest’, 80.
95 Ibid. 82. On continuities between Luther and trends from the high middle ages, Dierken,
Selbstbewusstsein, 203–4; Ward, Word and Supplement, 32–3; on Flacius and the via moderna, Haikola,
Gesetz und Evangelium, 32 ff.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
to commit history to memory, as the foundation of doctrine’, Flacius cut out the
middleman of ‘memory’, which was easier to do in the age of the printing press,
and essential when one was not just in the business of training other clerics:
historia est fundamentum doctrinae—‘History is the foundation of doctrine’:
I wish then, that a church history would be written in which would be shown in
definite order and according to chronology, how the true church and its religion
gradually fell from its original purity and unity in apostolic times into evil ways,
this partially from the negligence and ignorance of its teachers and also partly
through the wickedness of the godless. It should also be shown how the church
now and then has been reinstated by several truly pious men . . . until finally in
these our times, when the truth appeared almost completely wiped out, true
religion in its purity has once more been established through the immeasurable
goodness of God.
Here was a mission statement for the great collaborative research project Flacius
led, the thirteen-volume History of the church popularly known as the Magdeburg
Centuries (1560–5).96 The endeavour set in motion a historiographical battle
against which the tremors caused by chapters 15 and 16 of Gibbon’s Decline and
Fall two centuries later paled in comparison.
The major Catholic riposte to the Lutheran challenge came courtesy of the
cardinal and ecclesiastical historian Cesare Baronio, in the form of the twelve-
volume Annales ecclesiastici a Christo nato ad annum 1198 (The Ecclesial and
Secular Annals from the Birth of Christ until the Year 1198, 1588–1607). As well as
their impact, with sales constituting 13 per cent of the Plantin Press’s income in
1590–5, the Annales further buttressed historical literalism with the antiquarian’s
concern for minutiae and precision in the interests of grander projects of persua
sion.97 Ecclesiastical History was utterly bound to original principles, which is
why ‘the sources’ might connote not just ‘the evidence’ but ‘the origins’. (Centuries
later the philosopher Jacques Derrida made play of the relationship between ‘the
archive’ and the arche, or origin.) The analogy of ‘cause’ and ‘origin’ was strong for
humanist historians from Bruni to La Popelinière. Since the Universal Church—
which all parties to the Reformation and Counter-Reformation believed in,
differing only on what its essential principles were—had historical beginnings,
96 Magdeburger Zenturien (Jena, 1560–5): for the intellectual origins and thematic-cum-rhetorical
shaping of the project, which is by no means only organized by centuries and shows Baudouin’s
input, see Heinz Scheible, Die Entstehung der Magdeburger Zenturien. Ein Beitrag zur Geschichte der
historiographischen Methode (Gütersloh: Gerd Mohn, 1966). The lengthy quotation from Flacius in
the main text is in Wilhelm Preger, Matthias Flacius Illyricus und seine Zeit (Erlangen, 1859), vol. 2,
416–17, cited, contextualized, and translated in Earle Hilgert, ‘Protestantism—Revolt or Reform?’,
Ministry Magazine (July 1953), online at https://www.ministrymagazine.org/archive/1953/07/research
97 On sales statistics, Levitin, ‘From Sacred History to the History of Religion’, 1118. Levitin’s article
more generally considers the historiographical significance of the ecclesiastical History debates.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
98 Momigliano, Classical Foundations, ch. 6; Tutino, Shadows of Doubt, 67–70; Ginsburg, Threads,
20–3; Levitin, ‘From Sacred History to the History of Religion’. For Derrida’s contribution on ‘the
archive’, see Jacques Derrida, Archive Fever: A Freudian Impression (Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 1996).
99 Thomas Carlyle, Heroes and Hero Worship, repr. in Carlyle, Sartor Resartus, Heroes and
Hero-Worship, Past and Present, ed. G. T. Bettany (London: Ward, Lock and Co., 1892), 93;
cf. Kelber, ‘The Quest’, 80; Jean Grondin, Sources of Hermeutics (New York: SUNY Press, 1995),
19–21.
100 For examples of attempted usages of the scriptures in a political-critical spirit by the
Reformation writers Anne Askew, Anne Lock, and Anne Dowriche, see Elaine V. Beilin, ‘ “The World
reproov’d”: Writing Faith and History in England’, in Margaret Mikesell and Adele Seeff (eds.), Culture
and Change: Attending to Early Modern Women (Newark: University of Delaware Press, 2003),
266–80.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
political conduct was concerned. Luther was notorious for relegating problematic
biblical passages to secondary status within the canon, and for writing prejudicial
commentaries and introductions to the scriptures—as well as for disavowing
Thomas Müntzer’s militant ‘peasants’ who mistakenly thought that the reformers’
message might have some relevance for their existence outside their souls and
before their deaths.
Nevertheless, critical historical scholarship did gain its own momentum
during this period within small but important communities of scholars of a range
of confessions. This is very far from a stereotype whereby ‘Protestants wrote
histories of the church’s corruption by the papacy, Roman Catholics of its
unchanging adherence to papal tradition, and both of the ancient Jews as God’s
unique chosen people’, and whereby ‘real’ non-dogmatic, critical History only
appeared under the influence of seventeenth-century deism or of eighteenth-
century Enlightenment as represented by works such as David Hume’s 1757
Natural History of Religion.101 (How alike in condescension is the Enlightenment
caricature of rigid orthodoxy in prior ‘early modern’ History to the Renaissance
depictions of medieval scholasticism!) Sixteenth and seventeenth-century reli
gious scholarship incorporated the study of ancient Judaism, and paganism,
including pre-Islamic Arabic History, and was facilitated by the circulation of
many documents and manuscripts that had been torn from cathedrals and mon
asteries during the Wars of Religion. It was fired by the likes of the revolutionizer
of ancient and biblical chronology, Joseph Justus Scaliger (1540–1609) and his
fellow Huguenot, the Hebraist Isaac Casaubon, whose ‘spiritual quest’, in the
words of Joanna Weinberg and Anthony Grafton, ‘knew no denominational
boundaries’. The philosophical point at stake is that these scholars were not just
involved in the politics of the period but were also engaged in a search for what
they conceived as literal truth. In the aforementioned scholarly communities, his
torians of all confessions were recognized only as historians by other members
of the communities if they subscribed to critical precepts. And if ideology could
influence historical enquiry, some of the scholarly developments of the period
showed that the reverse could also be true as clerics drew on the interpretative
skills of humanists of the respublica litteraria. All this is what historiographical
disputes typically tend to produce, and this was one of the most important such
disputes in occidental history, and the most sophisticated thitherto. The result
was what the intellectual historian Dimitri Levitin calls ‘a sociology of knowledge
that transcended both politics and confessions’. Indeed some of the eighteenth-
century philosophes realized their scholarly debt to those who had disdainfully
been dubbed mere érudites, but were too embarrassed to declare it in light of the
101 Levitin, ‘From Sacred History to the History of Religion’, 1119–20, who rightly criticizes this
vision.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
belief that French neo-classicism was intellectually superior to and different from
all that had gone before.102
Catholic and Protestant scholars differed amongst themselves as much as with
each other: Jesuits, for instance, might be set against Jansenists. Most embraced
historical literalism, as well as some Jewish exegetical assistance, as long as they
could keep hold of some typological/figural thought. Thus the Jesuit ‘Bollandists’
embraced the spirit of criticism in defence of the Catholic Church, and in so
doing, via the Acta Sanctorum (Deeds of the Saints) project initiated in 1607,
acknowledged as a starting point the fictitious nature of almost all saints’ lives
produced thereto. The quest as they saw it—and still see it, since Bollandism con
tinues to this day in Brussels—was to establish such historical reality as could be
gleaned from beneath the embellishments of hagiography.103
A relatively late entrant to the scene was one of the most influential players.
The Benedictine monk Jean Mabillon (1632–1707) worked in the traditions of the
‘Maurist’ school which was active from 1618–c.1730. He was at least as concerned
to combat pyrrhonian scepticism and criticize Bollandist works as he was to
engage in the battle against Protestantism for which his school had actually been
set up. In a trio of works, the most famous of which is De re diplomatica (1681), in
which the word ‘diplomatic’ pertained to ‘diplomas’, meaning official documents,
he all but founded the modern discipline of palaeography. Where philology is
concerned with the internal, linguistic features of texts, which may have con
notations for ageing and verification related to authorship, palaeography is the
study of scripts, which includes their materiality as well as their textual content.
Mabillon’s external criteria of criticism demanded expertise in parchments, ink,
and paper. Of the text itself, alongside language and internal coherence, he stressed
coherence with other texts, a.k.a. evidence.
The intellectual courage of some of the aforementioned figures may be inferred
from the disapprobation with which their work was received by the churches whose
ends they nominally served. In 1695 the fourteen volumes of the Bollandists’ Acta
Sanctorum published to that point were condemned by the Inquisition. The
Histoire critique du Vieux Testament (Critical History of the Old Testament) of the
Oratorian Richard Simon (1638–1712) antagonized his fellow French Catholics
as well as Protestants: he was expelled from his order. It did not help Simon’s case
that he was associated with the thought of the excommunicate Jewish philosopher,
Baruch—Benedictus—de Spinoza (1634–77). Spinoza had declared that much of
what appeared to be prophetically divined morality was not actually written by
102 Ibid. 1160; on Casaubon, Grafton and Weinberg with Alastair Hamilton, ‘I have always loved
the Holy Tongue’: Isaac Casaubon, the Jews, and a Forgotten Chapter in Renaissance Scholarship
(Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press, 2011), 43. See also Grafton, Joseph Scaliger: A Study in the History of
Classical Scholarship, 2 vols. (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983, 1993).
103 On the Bollandists, Raymond E. Wanner, Claude Fleury (1640–1723) as an Educational
Historiographer and Thinker (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1975), 79.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
the prophets and was more in the way of a social code for a specific society, the
ancient Hebrews, than a general code for all peoples. Spinoza mirrored Hobbes,
Grotius, and yet others in arguing that the Pentateuch had not been written by
Moses, though some doubts about Mosaic authorship had been raised as early as
the tenth century by the Jewish Neoplatonist Isaac ben Suleiman. One of Spinoza’s
major hermeneutic tools was the awareness of anachronism, a word that unbe
knownst to him probably entered the English language during his lifetime, amid
the ruptures across the channel from the Netherlands. The principle was applied
in a way that had many precedents in legal-historical thought. In order to detach
the necessary from the contingent, the transcendent from the transient, one had
first to historicize in order to establish the immediate contexts of enunciation that
needed to be stripped away.104
Shortly after Spinoza, another member of a minority whose beliefs had caused
him trouble with authorities published his Dictionnaire Historique et Critique
(1697). Pierre Bayle was a Huguenot, who had fled France for the Netherlands,
and like his sixteenth-century predecessors thus had personal cause to promote
irenic thought. His dictionary deployed detailed historical study alongside strict
reasoning and a highly sceptical spirit in order to argue against inherited theo
logical tenets and thus religious dogma, and in favour of religious toleration. Both
Bayle and Spinoza influenced the eighteenth-century Scottish philosopher Hume;
Spinoza has been described as writing a ‘natural history of religion’ (i.e. not a
supernatural or dogmatic one), and one Hume expert opines that without him
Hume would not have been able to write his influential treatise of that name.105
Now we know that the picture is more complicated, and the intellectual debts yet
wider and deeper. Spinoza’s commendation that the Bible be read like any other
text had secularizing overtones but these need to be distinguished from irreligious
overtones, not least because he obviously perceived a god of sorts and had a long
Jewish hermeneutic tradition on which to draw—in this connection we might
note the publication and popularity of Maimonides in the seventeenth-century
Dutch Republic.106 Furthermore, some of Spinoza’s conclusions had been antici
pated in detail by the likes of yet another Huguenot, Isaac La Peyrère (c.1596–1676),
and the Quaker Samuel Fisher (1605–65).107 Spinoza’s premise that Adam was
104 J. Samuel Preus, Spinoza and the Irrelevance of Biblical Authority (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2001), 37, 182–3; on ‘anachronism’, Christopher Hill, Reformation to Industrial
Revolution, vol. 2, 1530–1870 (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1976), 198. On Isaac ben Sulieman and Ibn
Ezra: John H. Hayes, ‘The History of the Study of Israelite and Judaean History from the Renaissance
to the Present’, in V. Philips Long (ed.), Israel’s Past in Present Research (Winona Lake, IN: Eisenbrauns,
1999), 7–42, here 19.
105 Steven Nadler, Spinoza: A Life (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001), 271;
Richard H. Popkin, ‘Hume and Spinoza’, Hume Studies, 5:2 (1979), 65–93, here 70.
106 Aaron Katchen, Christian Hebraists and Dutch Rabbis (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press, 1984).
107 Travis L. Frampton, Spinoza and the Rise of Historical Criticism of the Bible (New York: T&T
Clark, 2006), 15–16, 41–2.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
not the first man was actually the founding assumption of La Peyrère’s ‘polygenetic’
theory of multiple human origins, as expressed in his Praeadamitae (1655): the
Jewish people might be ‘Adamite’ but since the Bible was only the History of
the Jewish people, no one else was.108 Recent scholarship has suggested we can
go significantly further back than these for similar critical comment on the Old
Testament,109 though it is still reluctant to accredit the relevant high medieval
thinkers. In other words, we should see Spinoza as pouring oil on living flame
rather than putting spark to tinder. The strength of the reaction against him is
explained less by the novelty of his historical and scriptural interpretations
than by how much of a premium was put on the literal truth of the scriptures at
the time of his views gaining notice, and perhaps above all by the fact that his
general religious views were so radically heterodox, when hitherto more critical
historical methods had been developed and adopted largely independently of
heterodox belief.
Since one object of this book is relating historical thought to other intellectual-
cultural trends, and since the seventeenth century is associated with the Scientific
Revolution more than any historiographical turn, it is interesting to recall the role
of some medieval thought in this apparently least medieval of developments.
Nominalist hermeneutics, and elements of nominalism’s aftermath in Reformation
thought, provide a cultural bridge between the Renaissance humanist focus on
the human sciences and the later sixteenth- and seventeenth-century develop
ments in natural science. Nominalism moves towards non-symbolic readings of
the natural world. Protestantism, while stridently insisting on the marriage of the
spirit and the letter in interpretation, nonetheless created a sharper dualism
between the cities of man and of god. Accordingly it paved the way for a contrac
tion of ‘the sphere of the sacred, forcibly stripping objects, natural and artificial,
of the roles they had once played as bearers of meaning’, and opening the way for
what are in hindsight more recognizably scientific, mechanistic explanations
and models of relationships. Purged of immanent spiritual meaning, nature was
rendered more fully as the servant of human material needs.110 All of this con
stitutes a significant series of steps down the road to what its most influential
theorists would later depict as quintessential characteristics of ‘modernity’—
namely a ‘mathematical-scientific desire to understand and relate to what there is
111 Espen Hammer, Philosophy and Temporality from Kant to Critical Theory (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2011), 71.
112 Descartes, Discourse on Method, editor’s introduction 1–32, quote on ‘lords’ at 10.
113 On changing views of the world Philip J. Kain, Nietzsche and the Horror of Existence (Lanham,
MD: Lexington, 2009), 10.
114 Richard W. Hadden, On the Shoulders of Merchants: Exchange and the Mathematical Conception
of Nature in Early Modern Europe (Albany: State University of New York, 1994).
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
touch the areas of identity reached by genealogical and figural History. Even at
the level of specialist political and legal argumentation the evidence is more
nuanced, beyond cases like that of Locke, whose political theory evinced a lack
of interest in History, even as his Essay on Human Understanding set out some
arguments about differing levels of certainty that would have aided historians in
their fight against pyrrhonian scepticism.120 For Spinoza, say, ‘reason’ alone could
reveal knowledge of a god and should promote the golden rule of loving it and
one’s neighbour as oneself, but we have seen that he deployed complementary
historical-hermeneutic enquiry.121 Similarly, if the Dutch humanist lawyer Hugo
Grotius (1583–1645) was one of the major seventeenth-century legal-political
theorists, he too, like the later jurist-philosopher Samuel Pufendorf (1632–94),
wrote works of History alongside his better-known theoretical tracts. In support
of his theoretical contentions, he followed the well-trodden path of working
through the historical and geographically variable ‘positive’ laws of human groups
in order to identify a universalist core in ‘natural law’. He has been accused of
historical cherry-picking to this end, though that scarcely distinguishes him from
Lipsius or Machiavelli, and if anything it reminds us of the ongoing significance
of some version of historical exemplarity.122 Consider for instance the use of
Thucydides, whose pedigree in influencing the classically educated is as well
established as that of Tacitus, and who has been deployed with equally varied
results. Among students of the Peloponnesian War we can count the English phil
osopher Hobbes and the American statesman John Adams. Hobbes translated
Thucydides in 1629 and there are notable similarities between Hobbes’s descrip
tion of the ‘state of nature’ and Thucydides’ account of the Corcyraean revolution
(427 bce) whose bloodshed Hobbes used to illustrate anarchy and to substantiate
his argument for a Leviathan-absolutism. Later, Adams (1735–1826) used the
same events to illustrate the atavism of ‘human nature’ in order to substantiate his
argument for a republican regime in which warring influences would hold each
other in check by the separation of powers.123 Finally, let us dwell for a moment
on the ‘Glorious Revolution’ of 1688 and the 1689 Bill of Rights, of which Locke is
seen as effectively the official philosopher. The events do seem to have reduced
‘Whig’ reliance on deep historical accounts of English liberties, but while they can
be interpreted as an interpellation of reason divorced from tradition, the turn
from deep History could just as well be explained by an interpretation of 1688
as a new foundational moment, a sort of year zero, in the lexicon of later
120 For the nuance and Locke’s exceptionality, see Pocock, The Ancient Constitution, 235–42.
On Locke and degrees of certainty, Burke, ‘History, Myth, and Fiction’, 274–5.
121 Preus, Spinoza and the Irrelevance of Biblical Authority, 37, 182–3.
122 Grafton, What was History?, 222.
123 Marshall Sahlins, The Western Illusion of Human Nature (Chicago: Prickly Paradigm Press:
2008), 8–11.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
124 Pocock, The Ancient Constitution, 235–42, contains much of the evidence on which I make
these assertions, though Pocock bears no responsibility for any errors in my rendering.
125 Grafton, What was History?, 231.
126 Bernard Williams, Truth and Truthfulness: An Essay in Genealogy (Princeton: Princeton
University Press, 2002).
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
miseries on themselves and hence how they might avoid them’.127 Little under the
sun being entirely new, there were antecedents to Rousseau’s agenda of what
Marxists would call ‘de-reification’, the denaturalization by examination of their
aetiology of arrangements assumed to be natural. In 1453 Nicholas of Cusa wrote
that ‘the earthly human condition has this characteristic: viz., that longstanding
custom, which is regarded as having passed over into nature, is defended as the
truth’.128 But in any case in Rousseau’s letter we have the fundaments of the justifi
cation for studying the past that this book dubs History as Emancipation.
Since science and religion did not necessarily stand in tension, religious
views of History were not necessarily threatened by science any more than
non-religious views of History were threatened by philosophy. Sometimes reli
gious views were even reinforced. Puritans, with their apocalyptic philosophies of
History, contributed disproportionately to the scientific endeavour. For some
puritans, ‘Progress in the arts and sciences [was] held to be at once a sign of the
imminence of the golden age of the spirit on earth and a cause of this imminence’,
thus fusing the Greek concept of advancement through the arts and sciences
with theological millenarianism.129 History also performed an exemplar function
in the basic Reformer conviction that scripture provides reconstructable historical
models for forging the commonwealth in the here and now. Even when that design
was thwarted in Europe it might still be pursued across the Atlantic.130
Elsewhere, views of the course of history long endorsed by Rome were repro
duced or renovated. While medievals had more than just the great theologies of
history available to them to understand the past, many inhabitants of the ‘early
modern’ world were still exposed by book and tutelage to those selfsame theolo
gies of history that we think of as quintessentially pre-modern. In Italy, where the
forces of Catholic orthodoxy were especially strong for much of the sixteenth and
seventeenth centuries, secular historiography having retreated somewhat since
Machiavelli and Guicciardini, the Jesuit Antonio Foresti reproduced the tenets
of sacred History, divine interventions and all, in his Mappamondo istorico
(Historical Map of the World, 1690–4). The work was translated into German, and
reproduced by a Venetian printer as the opening part of a more global History
featuring volumes on the Islamic world and China as well as Europe.131 Most of
It is the progress of these two particulars, I mean that of religion, and that of
empires, that you ought to imprint upon your memory; and as religion and
political government are the two hinges, whereon all human things turn, to see
whatever concerns those particulars summed up in an epitome, and by this
means to discover the whole order and progression of them, is to comprise in
thought all that is great among men, and to hold, so to say, the thread of all the
affairs of the world.132
Bossuet’s was the last great explicitly religious philosophy of history, with elem
ents of Augustine and his concept of the ‘two cities’, but the Discours was notable
for its incorporation of humanist sentiments and aspects of civic morals, and its
general attempts at fairness to a range of parties, so it was not entirely antithetical
either to Baudouin’s earlier work or to the ‘modernizing’ religiosity of the pur
itans.133 It was admired by some ‘Enlighteners’ for its range and its account of
causation. While it was concerned with God’s relationship to humanity, Bossuet’s
concept of ‘secondary causes’ meant that God’s direct influence did not always
need to be established, which kept the linkage between sacred and profane his
tory whilst simultaneously opening the way for a more secular analysis of change
for those not interested in or sceptical of the divine side of things.
If Bossuet’s passion was winning Protestants back to Catholicism, one of his
correspondents, Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (1646–1716), sought to end religious
antagonism with a philosophy of tolerance and he produced a novel metaphysics
to match. In Bossuet’s 1688 tome Histoire des variations des Églises protestantes
(History of the Variations of the Protestant Church), with the evidence of different
Protestantisms already before his eyes, he had argued that once a dissident church
132 Quotation from the English translation of the 13th edition of Bossuet’s original: An Universal
History from the Beginning of the World to the Empire of Charlemagne (New York: Robert Moore,
1821), 13; on Daniel e.g. 77 f.; 174–87.
133 Nisbet, Progress, 141–2.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
had rejected the idea of a worldly sovereign interpreter of scripture, that church
was apt to continue fragmenting in exegetical dispute. Leibniz effectively welcomed
diversity and gave it a philosophical justification in his Theodicy (1710) and
Monadology, which was published in 1714 but conceived in the 1670s–1680s,
when religious warfare was fresh in the memory and Louis XIV was breaking the
international peace and ending religious toleration at home, via the Revocation
of the Edict of Nantes (1685). Leibniz had tried to effect reconciliation between
Protestants and Catholics before concentrating on intra-Protestant relations. In
these works, like Cusanus, Ficino, and Bodin before him, he sought to identify
the unity that could be traced through diversity.134
Leibniz was influenced by the Neoplatonic theory of emanationism, in which
all things issue and descend—with decreasing perfection and increased concrete
ness—from one perfect/divine source. Of particular importance for subsequent
conceptualization of the diversity of religions, nations, and individuals is his
reworking of the ancient concept of the monad as part of a new metaphysics of
existence. For Leibniz, God was ‘the primitive unity’ (Monadology135 §§47–8),
and each of the monads he created had the quality of a sort of soul, or ‘entelechy’.
There was no direct conversation between the monads; they ‘have no windows’ (§7).
Each had its own integrity as part of a whole that was nonetheless in some way
connected: as ‘the same city viewed from different directions appears entirely
different’ there are ‘as many different universes, which are, nevertheless, only per
spectives on a single one’ (§57). Or, as Leibniz put it in another work, each monad
represents the universe from ‘its point of view’.136 While each monad itself com
prised smaller monads (§§65, 67), some types of monad had a higher conceptual
character than others—if ‘each living body has a dominant entelechy’ (§70), some
elect ‘souls are elevated to the rank of reason and to the prerogative of minds’
(§82). Unlike ordinary entelechies/souls, ‘minds’ are ‘images of the divinity itself,
capable of knowing the system of the universe, and imitating something of it
through their schematic representations of it, each mind being like a little divinity
in its own realm’ (§83). The idea of reasoning monads of the same level coexisting
side by side legitimated varying conceptions of god—varying confessions—but
could easily be adapted to pertain to varying social orders aligned with different
confessions and ways of viewing the world, and to different cultures more gener
ally. Such an elaboration need not entail relativism, since in the Leibnizian scheme
diversity was reconciled in the ultimate unity of God, but given that the God’s-eye
134 On some of the context, Nicholas Rescher, G. W. Leibniz’s Monadology: An Edition for Students
(Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press, 1991), 5, 8, and C. A. van Peursen, Leibniz (London: Faber
and Faber, 1969), 9. On Protestant and Catholic relations and theology see Irena Backus, Leibniz:
Protestant Theologian (New York: Oxford University Press, 2016).
135 Leibniz, ‘Monadology’, in Steven M. Cahn (ed.), Classics of Western Philosophy (Indianapolis:
Hackett, 1990), 604–13.
136 Leibniz, ‘Principes de la nature et de la grâce fondé en raison’, in Leibniz, Oeuvres de Leibniz, ed.
M. A. Jacques (Paris: Charpentier, 1846), 479–87, here 480. Emphasis added.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
perspective was not available to any person, or any people, the doctrine was one
further step down the road to relativism in the sense of human unfitness to
judge other ways of living and believing. As we shall see in Chapter 6, in the
German idealist tradition towards which Leibniz’s thought contributed, a trad
ition which reached its heights in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries and
found its historiographical expression in German historicism, discrete peoples,
ultimately nation-states, were accorded the attributes of higher-level monads in
their supposedly self-sufficient wholeness and their moral integrity as reflections
of the divine.
As far as the next chapter is concerned, just as important as Leibniz’s views on
synchronic diversity was his account of diachronic change. In recognition of
change over time, but in fidelity to his idea that monads were windowless, Leibniz
claimed that each monad must be moved by an ‘internal principle’. Monads must
have some internal plurality of properties even in their unity: ‘since all natural
change is produced by degrees, something changes and something remains’ at
any one time. Given ‘every present state of a simple substance is a natural conse
quence of its preceding state’, he claimed, in words that would ring down the
centuries, ‘the present is pregnant with the future’ (Monadology §§10–13, 22).
Leibniz’s theory of change was not a fully fledged philosophy of history, but it had
dialectical overtones.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
5
Society, Nature, Emancipation
Introduction
the thinkers under consideration had a view of history as progress. On one hand,
as already implied, this sort of thinking was not necessarily teleological—one
could imagine a never-ending process of civilizational improvement without
some culmination—and indeed it need imply no causal determinism either—it
could just reflect optimism, or a sense of what would happen were human poten-
tialities fulfilled. Yet on the other hand it could tend towards the self-congratulatory
and was easily bowdlerized for popular consumption into some partisan claim on
destiny, as a species of History as Identity.
On the whole the scholarship under examination evinced a liberal and peace-
able spirit as regards confessional and national differences, though it was fre-
quently marked by a partiality to occidental civilization, and traces of national
bias may often be detected. The dynastic and religious wars of the sixteenth and
seventeenth centuries had induced suspicion about dogmatism and scepticism as
to the motivation of great men. This helps explain a shift away from the study of
religious and political institutions and towards—or back towards, insofar as there
was some crossover with the French ‘new History’ of the sixteenth century—civic
morals, culture, and the structural conditions of social life. History expanded fur-
ther from being an instruction in statecraft for public men to proffering more
rounded edification in the form of vicarious experience of different spheres of life,
which had the effect of producing more female historians and readers.1
At the same time, the injection of new ideologies into politics from the six-
teenth and seventeenth centuries meant that it was possible to recast wars between
states as conflicts between political systems rather than peoples. Whereas certain
medieval chronicles and the French ‘new historians’ had focused on deep ethnic
origins as an index of national difference and particularity, at least one strand of
British historiography in the eighteenth century reflected on the common ‘gothic’
roots of different European peoples, such that ‘the craven, despotic and Roman
Catholic “other” of the Continent was not wholly alien, but a deformed and cor-
rupted version of the hardy libertarian Goth’. While the likes of the ‘Whiggish’
historian Catharine Macaulay evinced an ethno-cultural chauvinism to go with
her radical politics, for others the problem was not ethnic so much as political in
the broadest sense, and accordingly could be solved by political changes.2
The interpretative battles in which Macaulay and her interlocutors engaged
reminds us that there is no clear line separating (for shorthand) Enlightenment
historiography from its predecessors and that equally fruitful lines of enquiry
persisted and developed alongside the ‘archetypal’ Enlightenment sort. The
1 On the last sentence, Karen O’Brien, ‘English Enlightenment Histories, 1750–c.1815’, in Rabasa
et al. (eds.), The Oxford History of Historical Writing 1400–1800, 518–35, here 521–2, 531–2.
2 Colin Kidd, British Identities Before Nationalism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999),
ch. 9, quote from p. 211. This may simply reflect the fact that the British historiographical tradition
was less deeply rooted in ethnic thought than its French or German equivalents, for aforementioned
reasons of focus on dynastic rather than ethnic matters up to the seventeenth century.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
3 Guido Abbattista, ‘The Historical Thought of the French Philosophes’, Rabasa et al. (eds.), The
Oxford History of Historical Writing 1400–1800, 406–27, here 413–14, 424–5.
4 O’Brien, ‘English Enlightenment Histories’, 531–2.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
The Tory politician and political philosopher Henry St John, Viscount Bolingbroke
(1678–1751) set some of the terms of the intellectual debate with which this
chapter is concerned. He married a generalized classical view of History as
‘teacher of life’ (magistra vitae) with a particular conviction, perhaps shaped by
his own fraught endeavours to promote Anglo-French peace in the last years of
Queen Anne (d. 1714) and Louis XIV (d. 1715), that History could help extin-
guish ‘those national partialities and prejudices that we are apt to contract in our
education’.5 A preacher of confessional tolerance, in the tradition of Montaigne he
also used the wider world to challenge prevailing assumptions of superiority, as
when he suggested that ‘the Mexican with his cap and coat of feathers, sacrificing
a human victim to his god, will not appear more savage to our eyes, than the
Spaniard with a hat on his head, and a gonilla around his neck, sacrificing whole
nations to his ambition, his avarice, and even the wantonness of his cruelty’.6 His
historical scepticism—perhaps with a nod to Descartes he once suggested that
much History was just ‘authorized romance’—was reflected in the fact that his
best-known contribution to the discipline is a series of letters and thoughts rather
than a historical narrative. We may also detect some of the influence of the new
English political settlement of 1688–9 in his belief that remote areas of History
were not only difficult to know but also useless to learn about because of their
irrelevance to the problems of his present day. ‘An application to any study, that
tends neither directly nor indirectly to make us better men and better citizens, is
at best but a specious and ingenious sort of idleness . . . and the knowledge we
acquire by it is a creditable kind of ignorance, nothing more.’7 If this was a rather
unforgiving standard it once more pressed the question of the utility of historical
enquiry given contextual differences across time and given the challenges of
philosophy which worked from principles rather than precedents. Secular
philosophy of History was one answer to that question.8
The road from theology to secular philosophy of History passes through the
work of a pious Catholic, Vico (1688–1744). While not much acknowledged at
the time, Vico’s work anticipated the themes of many of the other scholars we are
to encounter, while sharing some elements with Leibniz’s thought. It was written
in conversation with Descartes, whose thought dominated Latinate philosophical
circles in the seventeenth century and whose politely dismissive opinions on
History we have already encountered: Descartes was also suspicious of rhetoric as
something that obscured the ‘clear and distinct’ ideas that formed the founda-
tions of reliable systems of belief, or, worse, provided false promise as to same.9
Vico was additionally engaged with social contract theories.
Against Hobbes and Locke and in line with David Hume, Vico observed that
humans were more likely to be joined in sociability by shared emotional ties,
pasts, and associated myths, than by rational agreement. Enculturated similarity
was a precondition of the capacity for rational agreement, which meant that
what was considered rational would vary from culture to culture. As opposed to
the rationalist students of the natural world, he claimed that humans could not
bracket this sensual quality in their consciousness. Working from the claim that
certain knowledge could be achieved only in mathematics, he observed that this
was because principles, postulates, geometrical forms, and so on, were of human
creation, and so were more like human social and cultural institutions than
was the natural world—note the difference with Platonic thought in which ideal,
universal forms like perfect circles had higher (metaphysical) reality than mere
‘concrete’ reality. Only that which ‘man’ had created could he know, in a way
beyond utilitarian acquaintance such as he had with the natural world. The philo-
sophical thrust was that there was no clear Cartesian distinction between investi-
gating subject and object in the human sciences; self-understanding and historical
understanding illuminated each other given the appropriate ‘historical conscious-
ness’. Historical enquiry could not be modelled on the paradigm of the natural
sciences and could not rely on a concept of explanation modelled on scientific
principles of causation. In such ‘scientific’ thinking, ancient myths were dismissed
as simple misunderstandings of the way the world worked, or ‘at best’ seen as
allegorical ways of expressing accurate knowledge of the world. For Vico, this was
the high road to an anachronistic misunderstanding of the cultural worldviews
that these myths had created. It also resulted in a mistaken view of the way in
which the present had developed out of the past in question, which was for the
8 I owe to Pocock, The Ancient Constitution, 246–8, this link from Bolingbroke to Vico and other
philosophers of history.
9 Giambattista Vico, On Humanistic Education (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 2003), 25–6; Isaiah
Berlin, Vico and Herder: Two Studies in the History of Ideas (London: Chatto and Windus, 1980).
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
10 Joseph Mali, The Rehabilitation of Myth: Vico’s New Science (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1992); Robert C. Miner, Vico: Genealogist of Modernity (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame
Press, 2002).
11 Ibid.; on the Heidegger comparison Ernesto Grassi, Vico and Humanism: Essays on Vico,
Heidegger, and Rhetoric (New York: Peter Lang, 1991).
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
12 Giambattisa Vico, New Science, §31 in Giambattisa Vico, The New Science of Giambattista Vico:
Unabridged Translation of the Third Edition (1744), trans. Thomas Goddard Bergin and Max Harold
Fisch (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1984), 20.
13 Ibid.
14 Giuseppe Mazzotta, The New Map of the World: The Poetic Philosophy of Giambattista Vico
(Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1999), 115–19.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
religions alone can bring the peoples to do virtuous works by appeal to their
feelings, which alone move men to perform them; and the reasoned maxims of
the philosophers concerning virtue are of use only when employed by a good
eloquence for kindling the feelings to do the duties of virtue. There is, however,
an essential difference between our Christian religion, which is true, and all the
others, which are false. In our religion, divine grace causes virtuous action for
the sake of an eternal and infinite good. This good cannot fall under the senses,
and it is consequently the mind that, for its sake, moves the senses to virtuous
actions. The false religions, on the contrary, have proposed to themselves finite
and transitory goods, in this life as in the other (where they expect a beatitude of
sensual pleasures), and hence the senses must drive the mind to do virtuous
works.16
17 Louis Althusser and Étienne Balibar, Reading Capital (London: New Left Books, 1970), 94–7,
186–9; Althusser, For Marx (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1969), 103.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
humain’. At the same time, certain formal similarities between his and Bossuet’s
work are undeniable:
parallel to the providential presence of the Holy Spirit was the intramundane
esprit humain; parallel to the apocalyptic transfiguration of the end of days
was the ecumenic spread of politesse; the historical extinction, rebirth, and pro-
gress of the human spirit were the secular equivalent to the Christian drama of
the fall of humanity in the story of Adam, the redemption of humanity in the
story of Christ, and the transfiguration of humanity in the evocation of the Last
Judgment.19
19 Barry Cooper, Eric Voegelin and the Foundations of Modern Political Science (Columbia:
University of Missouri Press, 1999), 218–19.
20 Quotes from David Allan, ‘Scottish Historical Writing of the Enlightenment’, in Rabasa et al.
(eds.), The Oxford History of Historical Writing 1400–1800, 497–517, here 514.
21 Edward Gibbon, The History of the Decline and Fall of the Roman Empire, ed. David P. Womersley,
vol. 3 (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1995), 1068.
22 Michael Bentley, ‘Introduction: Approaches to Modernity’, in Bentley (ed.), Companion to
Historiography, 395–506, here 403–5.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
The significance of the earlier Hume (1711–76) in these connections was not
his faith—he had none—in grand interpretative historical schemes or linear
developmentalism, but his reflection on psychology within the ‘science of man’.
Psychology was a central element in any systematic thinking about causation in
human affairs and linkages between people across time and place. For Hume, as
for Vico, the science of man was a foundation for considering the other scientific
investigations on which ‘man’ embarked, but Hume perceived a more thorough
going constancy in human nature. It was this, perhaps, that allowed him to sub-
scribe to most of the Greek rationales for writing History simultaneously. At one
point he averred that ‘the advantages found in history seem to be of three kinds,
as it amuses the fancy, as it improves the understanding, and as it strengthens
virtue’,27 and at another time that ‘History, the great mistress of wisdom, furnishes
examples of all kinds; and every prudential, as well as moral precept, may be
authorized by those events, which her enlarged mirror is able to present to us’.28
He also suggested that whoever wanted to know ‘the sentiments, inclinations, and
course of life of the Greeks and Romans’ should study ‘the temper and actions of
the French and English’.
Mankind are so much the same, in all times and places, that history informs us
of nothing new or strange in this particular. Its chief use is only to discover the
constant and universal principles of human varieties of circumstances and situ
ations, and furnishing us with materials from which we may form our observa-
tions and become acquainted with the regular springs of human action and
behaviour. These records of wars, intrigues, factions, and revolutions are so
many collections of experiments, by which the politician or moral philosopher
fixes the principles of his science, in the same manner as the physician or natural
philosopher becomes acquainted with the nature of plants, minerals, and other
external objects, by the experiments which he forms concerning them.29
To use the terms deployed earlier (p. 122) this is a more functional ‘men of their
place’ argument than a culturally-oriented ‘men of their times’ stance, but Hume
was aware that other cultures and times held divergent values, and insisted that
people should only be judged by the standards prevailing locally, even if one
disapproves of those standards. Because he believed that relatively superficial
27 S. K. Wertz, ‘Moral Judgments in History: Hume’s Position’, Hume Studies, XXII:2 (1996), 339–68,
here 342.
28 David Hume, The History of England, from the Invasion of Julius Caesar to the Revolution in 1688,
vol. VII (London: T. Cadell, 1778), 150.
29 David Hume, On Human Nature and the Understanding, ed. Antony Flew (New York: Macmillan,
1962), 94–5.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
30 Frank Edward Manuel, The Eighteenth Century Confronts the Gods (Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press, 1959); Peter Melville Logan, Victorian Fetishism: Intellectuals and Primitives (Albany:
State University of New York, 2009), ch. 1.
31 Allan, ‘Scottish Historical Writing’, 504–6.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
34 Immanuel Kant, Idee zu einer allgemeinen Geschichte in weltbürgerlicher Absicht, trans. in Kant:
Political Writings, ed. Hans Reiss (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), 41–53. For wider
contextualization, Thomas Sturm, Kant und die Wissenschaften vom Menschen (Paderborn: Mentis,
2009) chs. VI–VII. On Kant’s particular understanding of ‘pragmatic’, and its place in his scheme, see
John H. Zammito, Kant, Herder and the Birth of Anthropology (Chicago: University of Chicago Press,
2002), 348–9.
35 For changes over time and inconsistencies and consistencies, including the difference between
Kant’s personal prejudices and the implications of his theories: Sturm, Kant und die Wissenschaften
vom Menschen; Robert B. Loud, Kant’s Impure Ethics: From Rational Beings to Human Beings
(New York: Oxford University Press, 2000), 99, 195, 209; Pauline Kleingeld, ‘Kant’s Second Thoughts
on Race’, The Philosophical Quarterly, 57:229 (2007), 573–92; and Amélie Oksenberg Rorty and
James Schmidt (eds.), Kant’s ‘Idea for a Universal History With a Cosmopolitan Aim’: A Critical Guide
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2011), 184. On ‘race-mixing’, Mark Larrimore, ‘Antinomies
of Race: Diversity and Destiny in Kant’, Patterns of Prejudice, 42:4/5 (2008), 341–63. For anti-colonial-
ism and the entry of the world’s peoples ‘in varying degrees into a universal community’ in the light of
connectivity in Towards Perpetual Peace, see the reproduction of the essay in Kant: Political Writings,
ed. Reiss, 93–130, here 106–7, and, for the Montaigne-like quotation on ‘savages’, 103: ‘the main differ-
ence between the savage nations of Europe and those of America is that while some American tribes
have been entirely eaten up by their enemies, the Europeans know how to make better use of those
they have defeated than merely by making a meal of them. They would rather use them to increase the
number of their own subjects, thereby augmenting their stock of instruments for conducting even
more extensive wars.’
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
capacities for reason, Kant nevertheless suggested in Towards Perpetual Peace that
how explicit those categories are in the mind, and thus how they are actualized,
varies according to time and place.36
Just as important as Kant’s reflections on history and diversity were his
thoughts—and, as we shall shortly see, the reaction to those thoughts—about
how people conceived themselves in time and in regard of reason and the world
beyond the mind. Against the pure rationalism of Descartes (in one of his modes),
Baconian and Newtonian empiricism soon showed how experimental observa-
tion of the world could confound deductive theory, but likewise it was apparent
that the mind was not a blank slate on which the truths of empiricism were
inscribed—instead the mind had a synthesizing quality. The very act of ‘making
sense’ undermined the concept of mental perceptions as uncomplicatedly mirror-
ing the world as it was, being then elucidated by transparent language. But rather
than concluding that strong scepticism was therefore vindicated, Kant rejected it
along with rationalism and empiricism in his ‘transcendental idealism’. Kant’s
‘Copernican revolution’ required seeing the subject as actively constituting its
experience by means of a synthetic activity that it undertakes. Such a synthetic
activity, according to Kant, operates by means of the ‘forms of intuition’, i.e. space
and time, which give experience a temporal and spatial order, and by means of
apriori conceptual categories like quantity, quality, and relation that allow that
experience to be subsumed under judgements. It is only through the judging
activity of the subject that it comes to have any experience of objects in the first
place. Human thought was no longer to be assessed for its capacity as a more or
less leaky vessel for knowledge whose origin lay beyond the subject (in God, in
the world, or whatever). Rather, the mind itself was the origin of knowledge.
Human subjectivity, in that sense, was the grounding of objectivity, but this is
subjectivity in the sense of a general human capacity, not a unique possession of
one individual. Note that what Kant called the transcendental (not transcendent)
ego is to be distinguished from what he called the empirical ego. The empirical ego
was the expression of unique, individual character. The transcendental ego was
a characteristic of every subject, but as the very basis of subjective thought, it
could only be approached by philosophical reflection not empirical enquiry.
Moral philosophy too relied on the capacity to create and access a generalizable
structure of reason.
Kant combined the sovereign quality of the self as legislating to itself with a
rationally constituted social glue whose generally recognized legitimacy would
replace that provided by revealed religion. In Kant’s view, all agents of sufficient
rationality could come to articulate the moral law for themselves, by virtue of
reasoning that they themselves were prepared only to live with norms that they
36 Michael N. Forster, Hegel’s Idea of a Phenomenology of Spirit (Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 1998), 363.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
would themselves be prepared to legislate for all rational beings. This position
he termed the ‘categorical imperative’. In principle, all inherited and otherwise
external sources of moral or interpretative authority were supplanted by human
reflection on the finite world of experience and appearance, and the capacity for
reason. While the apriori categories were the structuring condition of thought
and understanding, the exercise of the latter faculties was an achievement in
human spontaneity, giving both freedom and responsibility to the subject. This
was at once uplifting—transient mortal existence need no longer be contrasted
with the uncorrupted and superior version—and salutary—for the soul’s
immortality had conventionally alleviated the burden of physical finitude, and
furthermore responsibility for identifying the moral life for the sake of that life
itself now lay absolutely with the human. Another nail was driven into the coffin
of human orientations towards the ancestral-traditional past or the eternal.
Though Kant himself was still committed to a ‘rational theology’, in subsequent
thought humans were now oriented towards an open-ended future in which their
projects needed no sanction from inherited meanings and, as long as the pro-
jects respected other rational beings, could be pursued with the deployment of
fungible natural resources exploited for their instrumental value against clock
time as that determined everyday secular activity.37 A perfect philosophy, then,
for a bourgeois-capitalistic modernity in which community dissolves into self-
directed individualism, bonds into contracts of exchange, technological control
obviates natural rhythms, and accelerated change demands prediction and con-
trol of the future?38 If Kant would not have endorsed these conclusions, and if
they are in many ways an absurd reduction of his magnificent achievement,
for travellers on the via antiqua they would have seemed but a logical extension
of the process by which the productive mystery of the Bible had been obliterated
in construction of the via moderna.39
Consonant with a world of predictable rhythm, one of whose historiographical
expressions was the increased circulation of History in Britain identified by
Woolf (p. 147), eighteenth-century Germany witnessed a gradual and uncertain
shift in the concept of ‘pragmatic history’, though Polybius, the historian who
had coined that term, had anticipated most of the variations on the theme. While
in a manifesto of 1714 Johann David Köhler associated pragmatic History with
orientation in civic life, especially political affairs, Johann Christoph Gatterer
(1727–99), of Göttingen’s influential Royal Institute for Historical Sciences,
understood it as developing ‘the whole system of causes and effects, of means and
37 On this aftermath, Martin Shuster, Autonomy after Auschwitz: Adorno, German Idealism, and
Modernity (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2014), ch. 2; Hammer, Philosophy and Temporality,
71–5.
38 Ibid. 41–53, chs. 3 and 4. For the relation to historical consciousness, see Koselleck, Futures Past,
passim.
39 Kelber, ‘The Quest’, 81.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
40 On ‘Nexus rerum universalis’: Wolfgang Proß, ‘Die Begründung der Geschichte aus der Natur—
Herders Konzept von “Gesetzen” in der Geschichte’, in Hans Erich Bödeker, Peter Hanns Reill, and
Jürgen Schlumbohm (eds.), Wissenschaft als kulturelle Praxis, 1750–1900 (Göttingen: Vandenhoeck
und Ruprecht, 1999), 187–225, here 194; other quotes and analysis from Peter Hanns Reill, The
German Enlightenment and the Rise of Historicism (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1975),
42–3 and Sturm, Kant und die Wissenschaften, 309–32, esp. 313–15. On the ‘science of man’, see
Zammito, Kant, Herder, 336 ff.
41 On which see Cecil P. Courtney and Jenny Mander (eds.), Raynal’s ‘Histoire des deux Indes’
(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2015); Abbattista, ‘French Philosophes’, 420–4.
42 Walter Schmitthenner, ‘Rome and India: Aspects of Universal History during the Principate’, The
Journal of Roman Studies, 69 (1979), 90–106, here 90.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
43 The contrast between Meiners’s and Herder’s approach to History on one hand and Gatterer’s
approach on the other from Proß, ‘Die Begründung der Geschichte aus der Natur’. For Herder’s
attitude to diasporic groups, Karol Sauerland, ‘ “Die fremden Völker in Europa”: Herder’s unpolitische
Metaphern und Bilder zu den höchst politischen Begriffen Volk und Nation’, in Gesa von Essen and
Horst Turk (eds.), Unerledigte Geschichten: Der literarische Umgang mit Nationalität und Internationalität
(Göttingen: Wallstein, 2000), 57–71.
44 Johann Gottfried von Herder, Philosophical Writings, ed. Michael N. Forster (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2002), 297 and 299 (emphases in original).
45 Michael Bentley, ‘Introduction: Approaches to Modernity’, 406.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
best mirror of the human mind, and that a precise analysis of the significations
of words would tell us more than anything else about the operations of the
understanding.’50 Hamann had linked events in the Garden of Eden and in
‘Babel’ rather as they are linked in the book of Genesis. In Genesis, Adam’s and
Eve’s rebellion, then the attempt to build a tower as a monument apart from god,
each resulted in dispersal and alienation, first of people from god, then of peoples
from each other.51 For his part, Herder saw the linguistic-cultural diversity that
supposedly resulted from the Babel episode as something to be celebrated, with
any future conceptualization of human unity having first to take account of
diversity.52 The religious references were more by the way of adornments than
architecture in the work of this erstwhile clergyman, however.
Herder replaced Hamann’s historical-theological admixture with an account
of historical-social evolution in which environmental factors and human reflec-
tion on sense-data also played a role, and differing religions were the products
of those different circumstances.53 He also deployed the classical concept of
humanitas/Humanität to express a basic human commonality to set alongside his
awareness of rich and very deep human cultural-linguistic differences. All groups
must, he felt, have possessed some concept of humanity as a ground for social
obligation: ‘The human heart has always remained the same in inclinations, just
as the mind has in abilities.’54 He sought ‘to gather historical examples of how far
the diversity of human beings can extend, to bring it into categories, and then to
try to explain it’, for the history of diverse creatures is ‘the history of our nature’.55
There was no way to short-circuit the process of historical and ethnographic
enquiry by some process of rational deduction, and presentism went hand-in-
hand with ethnocentrism as an obstacle to thought on the human condition.
‘People who, ignorant about history, know only their own age believe that the
current taste is the only one and so necessary that nothing but it can be imagined.’
‘Time has changed everything so much that one often needs a magic mirror in
order to recognise the same creature beneath such diverse forms.’56
Herder’s conception of the relation of culture to nature is expressed by his
comment: ‘How different is the world in which the Arab and the Greenlander, the
soft Indian and the rock-hard Eskimo, live! How different their civilization, food,
50 Leibniz quote from John Leavitt, Linguistic Relativities: Language Diversity and Modern Thought
(Cambridge University Press, 2011), 51–2.
51 James Austin, The Tower of Babel in Genesis (Bloomington: Westbow, 2012).
52 Michael Morton, Herder and the Poetics of Thought (University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State
University Press, 1989), 34–6, 62, 65–6.
53 Ibid. 34–6; John R. Betz, After Enlightenment: The Post-Secular Vision of J. G. Hamann
(Chichester: Blackwell, 2012), ch. 6; Proß, ‘Die Begründung der Geschichte aus der Natur’.
54 Herder, Philosophical Writings, ed. Forster, 268. See also 213–14: ‘Humanity is the noble measure
according to which we cognize and act’. On Humanität more generally: Hans Adler and Wulf Koepke
(eds.), A Companion to the Works of Johann Gottfried Herder (Rochester, NY: Camden House, 2009),
104 ff.
55 Herder, Philosophical Writings, ed. Forster, 249. 56 Ibid. 255.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
education, the first impressions that they receive, their inner structure of sensa-
tion! And on this structure rests the structure of their thoughts, and the offprint
of both, their language.’57 Mental reflection (Besonnenheit) on the sensual, reflec-
tion which is coextensive with language, permits abstraction within the limits of
given conditions. Historical and sensual conditions account for the heteronomy
of human value-systems.58
Herder’s views on morality sometimes reached the level of proper, thorough
going relativism of the sort sometimes described today as meta-ethical moral
relativism (see p. 326). There was no common denominator or yardstick outside
the very general parameters set by the yet-to-be established ‘nature’ by which to
assess differing moral outlooks. Of ‘moral virtue and human beings’ happiness’, he
wrote that
For both of these we not only still lack a correct criterion, but it could even per-
haps be that human nature had such a flexibility and mutability as to be able to
form out for itself in the most diverse situations of its efficacy also the most
diverse ideals of its actions into what is called virtue and the most diverse ideals
of its sensations into what is called happiness, and to be able to maintain itself
therein until circumstances change and further formation occurs.59
External evaluation not only seemed to make no sense, it also missed the point
about something akin to what Althusser called ‘expressivism’ in relationship to
Montesquieu’s thought. Laws and norms could not be transferred piecemeal from
one society to another because those societies were tightly interconnected wholes
that had developed organically together and set their own, incommensurable
criteria of right and wrong. ‘Shortcoming and virtue always dwell together in one
human hut’, Herder wrote, and ‘good and evil are only relational terms’.60 The
one depends on the other, and they both stem from the same Volksgeist or folk-
national-spirit. What we see here is the transposition of a certain burgeoning
Enlightenment conception of individual people as self-contained, consistent sub-
jects to the conceptualization of human collectives. The result, for Herder, was a
cultural essentialism that sits easily with his cultural relativism: essences-of-peoples
were not unchanging, but at any one time they are there, which also explains
Herder’s difficulty with diasporic minorities that sat amongst otherwise supposedly
discrete peoples.
61 A heritage made explicit for instance in Ernst Troeltsch, Der Historismus und seine Probleme:
Erstes Buch, ed. Friedrich Wilhelm Graf and Matthias Schlossberger (Berlin: de Gruyter, 2008 [orig.
1922]). 402–3, 987–9. On the links between Herder and Leibniz’s monadological thought: Ulrich
Eisel, ‘Individualität als Einheit in der konkreten Natur: Das Kulturkonzept der Geographie’, in
Parto Teherani-Krönner (ed.), Humanökologie und Kulturökologie (Opladen: Westdeutscher Verlag,
1992), 107–52, here 118 ff.; Samuel Fleischacker, Integrity and Moral Relativism (Leiden: Brill,
1992), 217.
62 Herder, Philosophical Writings, ed. Forster, 221.
63 Paul Bertagnolli, Prometheus in Music: Representations of Myth in the Romantic Era (London:
Routledge, 2007), 146.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
Hegel
Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel (1770–1831) may for present purposes be seen as
fusing Kant’s thought with the holism of Herder, Montesquieu’s interest in institu-
tions, and elements of Aristotelian teleology. The concept of esprit was central to
his philosophy but it did not have the same connotations as Voltaire’s. Hegel saw
‘spirit’, or Geist in his German, not as something that had to be liberated from
institutions and the hold of history, but as something that developed across time
in tandem with ‘circonstance’ and institutions. Hegel’s importance to this volume
is partly indirect, in the reactions which his work provoked in thinkers as differ-
ent as Marx and Leopold von Ranke, but it is also direct, in that Hegel was not
only deeply interested in the History of philosophy but tried to do philosophy in a
way that related it to historical change. He was a significant early contributor to
and product of a general historical infusion of many non-historical disciplines,
though most historians would come to regard him as not being historical enough,
given the teleological element in his philosophy. He was wary of History as Lesson
and scorned Hume’s comparisons of ancient Greeks with modern Frenchmen:
‘No difference could be greater than that between the nature of those ancient
peoples and our own time.’65 One purpose of his work was nonetheless to link
ancient Greeks and occidental moderns through an analysis of the entire
‘historical process’ that drew on inductive-empirical historical scholarship but
was underpinned by a speculative philosophy whose subject was Geist.
64 Editor’s introduction to Herder, Philosophical Writings, ed. Forster, pp. xiv–xxi.
65 G. W. F. Hegel, Introduction to the Philosophy of History with an Appendix from The Philosophy of
Right, trans. Leo Rauch (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 1988), 8–9.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
66 G. W. F. Hegel, The Philosophy of Right, trans T. M. Knox (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1952),
quotation from 89–90.
67 See John Edward Toews, Hegelianism: The Path toward Dialectical Humanism, 1805–1841
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985), chs. 1–2, quote from 34. On ‘The Kantian Paradox’,
Terry Pinkard, German Philosophy 1760–1860: The Legacy of Idealism (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2002), 59–60, 227.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
own nature, Hegel thought, but—and here the omnipresent dialectical element of
his doctrine—it had come at the cost of Geist’s alienation. The alienation from the
world beyond the mind was expressed through objectifying that world.68
Since Hegel claimed that philosophy ‘has no other object but God and so is
essentially rational theology’ it is not surprising that Geist can be interpreted as
either a spiritual or a rational, almost social-scientific, concept, but in either case
it is supra-personal.69 Let us explore the social-scientific valence first, which is
also the reading that has been most influential recently. Recall Adam Smith’s idea
of an invisible hand that makes sense of an infinite number of often competing
and dissonant human actions and interactions: in the social scientific reading
of Hegel, Geist pertains to the subject of humankind in the same way. To be
sure, Hegel did identify ‘world-historical’ characters—invariably occidental—like
Socrates, Jesus, Caesar, or Napoleon whose exceptional thoughts and deeds
embodied the shift from one epochal order to the next rung of Geist’s ascent, but
the actors were not necessarily aware of the deep meaning of their own actions:
they were simply especially prominent vessels of Geist. Thus, just as Smith’s self-
interested trader unwittingly consolidates the capitalist order even though he has
no comprehension of economic theory so the historical function of individual
actions is to embody and consolidate some particular stage of Geist. Accordingly,
such ‘progress’ as humans make can only be assessed at the level of humankind,
not of individual people. Throughout history, Geist has been embodied in the
dominant political, legal, social, religious, and cultural institutions of social
orders. Thinking along Aristotelian lines, these institutions provided the forms
for the social content of human interaction. They were objectifications of Geist,
familiar representations of the social order to its inhabitants, and they could be
‘read’ by later generations with the help of the hermeneutic method that provided
empirical complement to speculative reflection. At any given time, particularly
insightful thinkers—especially philosophers like Hegel himself—could give indi-
vidual expression to the nature of Geist at that phase of its existence, becoming its
spokespersons as it were, but even they were generally incapable of exceeding
its general structural parameters, and so were better at divining what had already
become manifest than predicting the future as one order ended and another
began as the result of some world-historical act or change in interactive patterns.
(This is the meaning of Hegel’s famous claim that ‘the owl of Minerva spreads its
wings with the coming of the dusk’.) Thus, for Hegel, whatever constitutes the
structure of reason, and so of society, at any one time is a social, historical
construction, not an individual one or a metaphysical one.70
Periods of relative or apparent stasis exist betwixt epochal advances, all the
while building up forces that are ready to be unleashed at the next ‘phase transi-
tion’, or revolution. Individuals may suffer in this process, because it is not an
even upward march, but, in dialectical fashion, may feature ostensible setbacks.
At one point Hegel categorically states, in contradiction of one of Kant’s iterations
of the categorical imperative, that flesh-and-blood individuals ‘come under the
category of means’ rather than ends-in-themselves. History is ‘the slaughter-
bench, upon which the happiness of nations, the wisdom of states, and the virtues
of individuals were sacrificed’. By one contested reading of Hegel this suffering is
not just necessary for the final outcome, it is redeemed by that outcome, ‘the
ul
tim ate goal for which these sacrifices were made’.71 Before attending to
the end-state, talk of redemption prompts us to see how that state might be
approached in accordance with the more religious reading of Hegel.
When exploring the developmental elements of Hegel’s thought the link
between reason and religion is provided by Neoplatonism, though Hegel also
evinces broader pantheistic influences. Hegel’s Geist has much in common with
Plotinus’s nous, as something that may be translated as ‘spirit’ but also connotes
reason, which is why some also translate Geist as ‘mind’. Contrary to the domin
ant Christian metaphysics, for Hegel the universe was not voluntarily created by
God in a one-off act. God cannot exist separately from the universe, which is an
emanation of himself—while impersonal, ‘he’ exists in all aspects of his creation
and must reveal himself in it. Dialectically, that creation is necessary for God to
become aware of, and so to perfect, himself. Hegel differed from Augustine, who
also saw struggle as movement, because for Augustine divine redemption was not
the direct consequence of historical development. For Hegel, enlightenment was
the point at which humankind realized that it had the answer to humankind’s
questions—at this point it was a creation reaching its own state of self-aware
perfectibility. This was the moment of Geist’s self-conscious reach for reason, as
opposed to previous orders under which people had looked to external divine
forces for guidance, or invoked quasi-divine entities like the extra-mental Kantian
‘noumenal’ world that still somehow conditioned human reason even if it could
never be apprehended by the mind. In Hegel’s vision reason triumphed at the
point of nothing more and nothing less than the free exchange of reasoned argu-
ments, untrammelled by mistaken metaphysical considerations. At the same time
the ‘right’ metaphysical thought is that the ultimate unity of subject and object are
revealed by human subjects contemplating themselves as elements in a holistic
world, parts of a unifying Geist. Scientific categories and law may not be inherent
71 Hegel, Introduction to the Philosophy of History, 23–4, 32–8, 70, 101; Marcuse, Reason and
Revolution, 227–34. For contestation see Shuster, Autonomy after Auschwitz, ch. 4 and Terry Pinkard,
Does History Make Sense? Hegel on the Historical Shapes of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press, 2017).
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
in the object but creating those categories and laws furthered the self-knowledge
of Geist. This is Hegel’s update of the old idealist idea that knowledge of laws is
knowledge of the thought of God: one knows God because one knows oneself.
The advance of reason was thus intrinsically bound up with knowledge of the
state of human freedom, for only under those circumstances was it possible
to have the equal, intersubjective discussion whereby one could reach agreed
norms via reasoned exchange. Where in the apocryphal oriental despotisms from
which the Greeks had advanced the state of Geist was such that only the despot
was known to be free, and where in Greco-Roman antiquity only the citizens were
known to be free, after the Reformation with its doctrine of spiritual freedom, all
were known to be free. What was then needed were the social institutions in
which this freedom could be expressed, which brings us back to the more secular
and sociological Hegel.72
In Hegel’s thought the state should be understood as an organic entity housing
the modern-day ecclesia, rather than a string of bureaucratic institutions for
which Hegel had some fetish. The state actualizes the freedom of the people.73
Some states—most obviously German ones in his time—had a role as world-
leaders, Hegel thought. What he called ‘world-historical national spirits’ took
the lead among the community of national spirits, in promoting freedom and
awareness thereof. A reading of the Reformation as spiritual liberation and the
progression of equality and freedoms enshrined in law were essential for the
claim to German primacy, for by the early 1820s post-Napoleonic reforming
Prussia had come for Hegel to symbolize the substantial, though certainly not
complete, reconciliation of rational rule and communal sensibility, form and sub-
stance, particular and universal. But the deeper point about modern states as such
is that they supposedly provide sites for something like the institutionalization or
materialization of self-aware Geist. In his examination of the balance of and inter-
relation between personal rights, property rights, and state rights, and between
different social structures from the family to the social ‘estates’ to the world of
contractual exchange, we see Hegel at his most sociologically acute. Giving sys-
tematic form to social life, these arrangements prompt individuals to identify
their own freedom with the substantial order of which they were part—again,
reconciling subject and object.74
72 Hegel, Introduction to the Philosophy of History, 17–18, 20–1, 99–103. John Laughland, Schelling
versus Hegel: From German Idealism to Christian Metaphysics (Aldershot: Ashgate, 2007), 142–3;
Thomas Albert Howard, Religion and the Rise of Historicism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
2000), 84–5; Adorno, History and Freedom, 147–9. On nous, Bertrand Russell, History of Western
Philosophy (London: George Allen and Unwin, 1947), 312–13. Also Anthony Kenny, The Rise of
Modern Philosophy (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2006), 113–16, 163–4, and, on intersubjective agreement
and reason-giving, Pinkard, German Philosophy, 359–62.
73 See Alan Patten, Hegel’s Idea of Freedom (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999).
74 Hegel, Introduction to the Philosophy of History, 26, 40–56; Toews, Hegelianism, ch. 3; Marcuse,
Reason and Revolution, 236–9.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
Despite caricatures of his thought, Hegel did not see his contemporary world
as constituting history’s culmination, even if he did regard it as having reached
the highest point so far. Whatever the teleological element in his philosophy of
history he was decidedly pessimistic about the possibility of attaining true har-
mony between individual and whole. He was also aware of how tenuous the
Prussian political synthesis was and perceived threats to it from populist
nationalism and unreflective political reaction, while his intellectual world was
under constant threat of impingement by committee intervention and censor-
ship. Consciousness of freedom, and the thought that went with such con-
sciousness, would have always to be active, and so might well come into conflict
with the very state whose existence facilitated that freedom in the first place.
With an eye to continuities across the millennia, he squarely replicated a sense
of the westward movement of History, from ‘the Orient’ through Greece, and
Rome. The Mediterranean comprised the ‘centre of world history’, but the ‘land
of the future’ was not Germany: it was the westernmost outpost of the occident,
America.75
So much, then, for the conservative Hegel, or the statist patriot, or the
Olympian justifier of all suffering in the name of progress. There were other
visions of him at the time, as is appropriate for one whose name is synonymous
with dialectic thought. If, as he famously said ‘the real is rational’, then rulers
might fear that only what is rational is actually real in the philosophical sense,
and that the self-conscious mind might adjudge contemporary realities as
irrational and therefore ephemeral—there was more than enough autonomous
reason in Hegel’s system for that outcome. If individual events from terrible suf-
fering to heroic triumph were vectors of deeper processes, then what seemed con-
crete and given at any one time might turn out to be merely fleeting. In the more
sociological reading of Hegel, the ‘negative’ element in his thought pertains to the
ways in which various configurations—forms of life, shapes of spirit—break down
under their own weight and contradictions. In the more metaphysical reading the
‘negative’ element in his thought existed precisely to question what actually
existed at any given moment, in line with the basic ontological problem of why
some things existed but not others. Here, indeed, we witness echoes of Leibniz’s
so-called esoteric philosophy, which is by no means as favourable to the status
quo as his conventionally understood position which Voltaire mocked as
‘Panglossian’. Certain entities, Leibniz wrote, are not ‘compossible’—they cannot
coexist, so it is a matter of either-or, which is to be decided metaphorically speak-
ing in a sort of competition between possibles after god has made the choice to
create something. Similarly, for Hegel, the establishment of that which is, is also
an alienating repression or repulsion of that which is not (but might have been
75 On Hegel’s misgivings, Toews, Hegelianism, ch. 3; on contingency, Pinkard, German Philosophy,
361; on matters geographical, Hegel, Introduction to the Philosophy of History, 83–91.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
and might yet be). In Hegelian terms, that which is purports to constitute an
organic whole but is in fact mutilated, incomplete. Negative thought is not nega-
tive in the sense of unconstructive, but in the sense of subversive, in the way that
the literature and poetry of the avant-garde sought to establish a new language
uncontaminated by the ‘facticity’ of a certain brand of realism, and modernist art
rejected mimesis and classical concepts of representation, as well as Christian
concepts of incarnation. Not for nothing did Friedrich Wilhelm IV of Prussia
condemn Hegel as sower of the ‘dragon seed’ of revolution.76
One response to Hegelian negative philosophy, as to French revolutionary
rationalism and scepticism, was positive philosophy—‘positivism’. For Comte in
restoration France, see the legal theorist F. J. Stahl in Germany. The ‘universalism’
of Comte and the nationalist-particularism of Stahl are different: the former
espoused a tripartite stadial theory of ‘social evolution’ that supposedly applied to
every people, at the final, highest, ‘scientific’ stage of which (his present) social
thought would be governed by analogy to physiology; the latter was embedded in
the specificity and historical prerogatives of the state, had debts to idealism, and
set itself against universalistic concepts like natural law. But both opposed the
‘insubstantial’, speculative element of Hegelian dialectical thought.77
Marx
Whatever else he was, Karl Marx (1818–83) was a child of the Enlightenment,
bringing together German, Scottish, and French influences. He ultimately dis
agreed that the historical process evinced any intrinsic rationality or meaning in
Hegel’s sense, but at all times he felt it could be rationally understood, which was
essential to intervening in it. His very claim to scientific status entailed rejecting
moral judgement as an obstacle to analysis, prediction, and emendation, even as
moral outrage coloured so many of his deliberations. In his mode as speculative
philosopher of the historical process Marx’s was the obviously apocalyptic coun-
terpart to Hegel’s ostensibly prophetic view of history, and he rejected the redemp-
tive aspects of Hegel’s theory as obscenely complacent in the face of what they
were held to redeem. He replicated Hegel’s conception of successive historical
stages but replaced the idealist conception of Geist’s self-actualization with aspects
of Adam Smith’s materialist stadialism. The product of all this, at least as indicated
in his early Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts (1844), was a historical
subject that only attained its fullness at the last historical stage. What Marx
called alienation denoted the perversion and frustration of many potentialities.
76 Marcuse, Reason and Revolution, pp. vii–xi, 231, 325–6; Norman Levine, Marx’s Discourse with
Hegel (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2012), 9. The Leibniz connection is my own.
77 Marcuse, Reason and Revolution, 323–74.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
78 Karl Marx with Friedrich Engels, The German Ideology, including Theses on Feuerbach and
Introduction to the Critique of Political Economy (Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books, 1998), 34.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
alienation has its broadest existential meanings. The other two aspects of Marx’s
thought Fleischer calls ‘pragmatological’ and ‘nomological’. The essence of the
pragmatological type is encapsulated in the famous claim of Marx’s most famous
historical essay, The 18th Brumaire of Louis Napoleon (1852), that ‘Men make
their own history, but they do not make it just as they please. They do not make it
under circumstances chosen by themselves but under circumstances directly
encountered, given and transmitted from the past.’79 The pragmatological
approach is context-sensitive and allows for divergent paths, albeit that—and here
few historians of any stripe would disagree—the range of possible paths is con-
strained by paths already taken. Marx and Engels had arrived at this approach by
the time of The German Ideology, where they criticized Hegelian philosophy of
history for its determinism and mocked his dialectics. It was later, from the late
1850s, that they sometimes deployed what came to be called (by others) a dialect
ical materialist philosophy of history of the sort Fleischer calls nomological. As its
name suggests, the nomological (i.e. law-making) form does present an overarch-
ing, unilinear theory of history.80 Whatever the weaknesses of the nomological
interpretation, many left-wing workers and intellectuals took inspiration from its
optimistic sense of inevitability, just as many Protestants took inspiration from
the idea that God was on their side. But scientific and pseudo-scientific develop-
ments related to the theory of evolution also seemed to push in the same direction,
as with the Lamarckianism evinced in the thought of Karl Kautsky and Georgi
Plekhanov in the Second International of 1889–1914. Plekhanov was the man
who introduced the term ‘dialectical materialism’ to Marxist theory, and that
was taken up and ‘refined’ by Joseph Stalin, though Leon Trotsky claimed to be a
dialectical materialist too.81
While it is impossible to reconcile the nomological and pragmatological
strands in their purest forms and in their entirety, it is possible to reconcile elem
ents of each, and after all we must recall that each is only a tendency in Marx’s
thought rather than the all-controlling element at any given stage. Here is one
attempt at partial reconciliation.82 In the case of capitalism, Marx did see
inevitability in the development of crisis, thus in Leibnizian terms the present
was pregnant with the future, but not necessarily in the direction of resolution of
79 Karl Marx, The Eighteenth Brumaire of Louis Bonaparte (New York: International Publishing,
1969 [orig. 1852]), 15; Helmut Fleischer, Marxism and History (New York: Harper, 1973);
Alvin W. Gouldner, The Two Marxisms: Contradictions and Anomalies in the Development of Theory
(Basingstoke: Macmillan, 1993).
80 S. H. Rigby, Engels and the Formation of Marxism (Manchester: Manchester University Press,
1992), 81–3, 97, 187–98.
81 On naturalism and the Second International, see Alex Callinicos, ‘Marxism and the Status of
Critique’, in Brian Leiter and Michael Rosen (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Continental Philosophy
(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007), 210–39, here 212. For Stalin’s 1938 ‘Dialectical and Historical
Materialism’, see J. V. Stalin, Problems of Leninism (Peking: Foreign Languages Press, 1976), 835–73,
online at https://www.marxists.org/reference/archive/stalin/works/1938/09.htm
82 I draw heavily here on Marcuse, Reason and Revolution, 310–19.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
crisis. Dialectical thought, with its emphasis on rise and fall, stresses and strains
in a Leibnizian interconnected whole, was predicated upon the emergence of
internal contradictions, or the self-negation of capitalism. The contradiction
springs from ever-increasing capital accumulation and concentration to the point
where monopoly displaces competition. Paralleling that development is ever
more intensive, competitive labour exploitation. At the same time technological
advance means the value of human labour depreciates. Reduced popular purchas-
ing power, but especially the rising ‘organic composition of capital’,83 reduced the
rate of profit of the surviving industries which, trapped in the logic of constant
accumulation through utilization of capital, overproduce, and the search for new
resources and markets prompts international warfare and expansion. Meanwhile,
domestically, political repression is needed to complement workplace ‘discipline’
as discontent arises. Thus far, the emphasis is all on the ‘objective’ factors rather
than on human agency and consciousness. The introduction of ‘subjective’ factors
is key for the transition to a socialist order—here again the Hegelian synthesis of
subjective and objective, which we might also call the conjunction of agency and
structure—in the form of the working class’s awareness of its own predicament
and opportunity and of self-conscious proletarian organization in the political
sphere. But the advent of that subjective factor is not inevitable, as stressed by
Marx at points and by that notable applied theorist Lenin.
Different Marxist thinkers are free to pick-and-mix between different Marxes,
but we can make some rough generalizations as to affinities. Historian Steve
Rigby observes that the split between pragmatological and nomological Marxisms
tends to be linked to whether, within the general Marxist emphasis on the eco-
nomic base, they emphasize the role of productive forces as the key determinant of
historical change or the relations of production. The productive forces are the
technological and other skills and equipment available at any one time, say the
hand-mill before it is replaced by the water-mill and that in turn by the steam-
mill. The ‘relations of production’ means the way in which primary, technical, and
human ‘resources’ are arranged, and thus includes class structure. Emphasis on
relations of production corresponds more with pragmatological consideration of
the divergence of paths and the role of class-oriented political action at specific
‘under-determined’ historical conjunctions. Emphasis on the causal primacy of
society’s growing productive forces tends to be associated with a nomological
account of history as an inevitable process.84
Moving from the constituents of the economic base to that of what Marxists
call the political and ideological superstructure, Marxism has often been seen as a
83 S. H. Rigby, Marxism and History (Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1998), 49–50.
84 Ibid., chs. 3–6 on the first tendency and chs. 7–8 on the second. See also on divergence Robert
Brenner, ‘Agrarian Class Structure and Economic Development in Pre-Industrial Europe’, Past and
Present 70 (1976), 30–74, and on underdetermined conjunctions, Althusser, For Marx, 228–9.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
claim that there is a one-way determination of the former by the latter (‘vulgar
Marxism’), even though Engels went out of his way to correct this conception and
even though Marx’s own historical writings, most notably the 18th Brumaire, dis-
play an awareness of the active historical role played by politics and ideas.85 Many
of Marx’s balder statements about the historical primacy of base-material factors
should be seen in the polemical context of his struggle with the powerful German
idealist tradition. Certainly, important later Marxists have distanced themselves
from vulgar Marxism, as when Antonio Gramsci (1891–1937) invoked the con-
cept of ‘hegemony’ as part of his argument that proletarian (‘subaltern’) submis-
sion was the product not just (sometimes not even) of coercion but was also
achieved at the cultural level, through which workers came to acquiesce in the
moral authority of those above them. Base and superstructure might also inter-
penetrate, as for instance with laws affecting economic activity, meaning that
they are not really separable in the first place for one to determine the other.
As the Marxists Maurice Godelier and Ellen Meiksins Wood have argued, feudal
law, which ‘vulgar Marxism’ might see as a part of the superstructure, is actually
central to the definition of feudal classes by which the base is constituted.86
If one wanted to identify continuities in Marx alongside the changes, one could
look to the focus on unmasking, which is also central to the project of undermin-
ing cultural dominance/hegemony shared later by Gramsci and his contemporary
György Lukács (1885–1971). Unmasking, which also fits some definitions of
‘de-reification’, is what the introduction to this chapter alluded to when associat-
ing Marxist historiography with the agenda of History as Emancipation. It is a
matter of removing illusions of naturalness or ordained-ness. In his 1843 essay
‘Contribution to the Critique of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right’, Marx wrote that ‘The
abolition of religion as the illusory happiness of men, is a demand for their real
happiness . . . The criticism of religion disillusions man so that he will think, act
and fashion his reality as a man who has lost his illusions and regained his reason.’
In the German Ideology of 1845–6 he wrote that communism ‘overturns the basis
of all earlier relations of production and intercourse, and for the first time con-
sciously treats all natural premises as the creatures of hitherto existing men,
strip[ping] them of their natural character’.87 Denaturalization was one of the
major themes of Marx’s Introduction to A Contribution to the Critique of Political
Economy (1859) while the Preface to that work contained Marx’s most famous
criticism of any Kantian idea of a self-authoring sovereign subject: ‘The mode of
production of material life conditions the social, political and intellectual life
process in general. It is not the consciousness of men that determines their being,
but on the contrary, their social being that determines their consciousness.’88
And again, in Capital (1867): ‘the advance of capitalist production develops a
working class, which by education, tradition, habit, looks upon the conditions of
that production as self-evident laws of Nature’.89 The raising of consciousness
about the artificiality of the whole set-up was a precondition for the reversal of
‘self-estrangement’.
At the same time Marx’s views did develop as to precisely what it was that
would be un-self-estranged or unalienated. In the more ‘anthropogenetic’ 1844
Manuscripts he talked of humans being estranged from their creative species-
essence by the mechanisms of capitalism, whereas later he dropped such meta-
physical talk about what humans ‘really are’, used ‘alienation’ in a more limited
sense, and reflected on the variable cultural construction of ways of being. When
‘man’ first takes up tools, he changes the world and thus himself.90 So while in
some ways Marx becomes less historically contingent (less ‘pragmatological’)
and more law-oriented (more ‘nomological’) over time as regards the analysis of
social-economic change, he becomes more ‘historical’ over time in his under-
standing of the relationship of human conditions in the plural to changing socio-
economic orders and the environment.
In principle there is nothing new in Marx’s agenda of denaturalization. It is
implicit in anthropological ventures from Hippocrates onwards, and explicit in
the words of Rousseau and of the historian of ancient Rome Barthold Georg
Niebuhr (1776–1831). Niebuhr wrote that History revealed what ‘even the
greatest and highest spirits of our human race’ do not understand, namely ‘how
their eyes only acquired by chance the way in which they see’.91 Marx’s older
contemporary John Stuart Mill (1806–73), a positivist liberal-utilitarian, asked
rhetorically: ‘was there ever any domination which did not appear natural to
those who possessed it?’ Alongside the examples of racial and sexual repression,
past and present, with which he illustrated the point, Mill wrote that ‘acquaintance
with human life in the middle ages, shows how supremely natural the dominion
of the feudal nobility over men of low condition appeared to the nobility them-
selves’ and ‘hardly . . . less so to the class held in subjection’.92 The novelty of
Marx’s intervention is not critical historicization in general, but the radical
nature of the agenda to which he attached it. The particular focus of his critique
88 Introduction repr. in Marx with Engels, The German Ideology, 1–23; Preface repr. in Karl Marx
and Friedrich Engels, Collected Works, vol. 29: Marx 1857–61 (London: Lawrence and Wishart, 2010),
261–5, with quote at 263.
89 Karl Marx, Capital: A New Abridgement, ed. David McLellan (Oxford: Oxford University Press,
1999), 372.
90 Graeme Campbell Duncan, Marx and Mill: Two Views of Social Conflict and Social Harmony
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1977), 55.
91 Niebuhr, Lebensnachrichten über Barthold Georg Niebuhr, vol. 2 (Hamburg: Perthes, 1838), 480.
92 John Stuart Mill, J. S. Mill: ‘On Liberty’ and Other Writings, ed. Stefan Collini (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2003), 129–30.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
was the current economic order and its sustaining philosophies, which brings
us briefly back to Adam Smith.
To take Ockham’s razor to Smith’s account, ‘commercial society’ is a product of
the ‘natural’ inclinations to ‘truck, barter, and exchange’, after a certain point and
under certain conditions. Given all the necessary ‘positive’ developments pro-
duced by demographic pressures and sufficient ‘primitive accumulation’, what
is needed are negative measures, the removal of restrictions that inhibit and
distort the ‘natural’ inclinations. Smith had in mind as restrictions patterns of
landholding and land use associated with certain classical and medieval orders
plus the mercantilism of the age of absolutism. Their removal would produce a
‘spontaneous order’ much more economically effective and respectful of freedoms
than any that could be manufactured: realized, indeed, is the principle of the ‘sys-
tem of natural liberty’. For Marx, clearly enough, the capitalist order is anything
but the outcome of natural tendencies unleashed in the right circumstances—it is
a distinctly historical achievement, a cultural development in the broadest sense
of culture. Marx also saw that capitalism had more far-reaching connotations
than Smith allowed. It does not leave intact the sort of ‘natural’ ties of sympathy
that Smith saw as the restraining moral context for the exercise of self-interest:
Smith’s Wealth of Nations should always be read against the backdrop of his
earlier Theory of Moral Sentiments. For Marx, conversely, capitalism creates a con-
cept of the human by its own particular ‘laws’ of motion, principles of competitive
production, reinvestment, and profit maximization. The social serves the eco-
nomic not vice versa. ‘Primitive accumulation’ may be necessary for this cultural
shift but is by no means sufficient.93
Marx’s conception of false consciousness and exploitative relations of produc-
tion posed a full-frontal challenge to the romantic-idealist conception of society,
replacing it with one of competing class interests and identities. This set him at
odds with most other sociology of the nineteenth century, as well as with the
dominant German historical school of his time, which rejected Hegel’s overarch-
ing philosophy of History but kept the element of Herderian social holism.
93 Ellen Meiksins Wood, The Origin of Capitalism: A Longer View (London: Verso, 2002), 21–5,
34–7; on ‘spontaneous order’, Smith, Adam Smith’s Political Philosophy, with ‘system of natural liberty’
at 90.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
6
Nationalism, Historicism, Crisis
Introduction
There is no European nation which, within the course of half a century or little
more, has undergone so complete a change as this kingdom of Scotland. The
effects of the insurrection of 1745,—the destruction of the patriarchal power of
the Highland chiefs,—the abolition of the heritable jurisdictions of the Lowland
nobility and barons,—the total eradication of the Jacobite party, which, averse to
intermingle with the English, or adopt their customs, long continued to pride
themselves upon maintaining ancient Scottish manners and customs,—com-
menced this innovation. The gradual influx of wealth and extension of com-
merce have since united to render the present people of Scotland a class of
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
beings as different from their grandfathers as the existing English are from those
of Queen Elizabeth’s time.1
1 Walter Scott, Waverley, or ’Tis Sixty Years Since (Edinburgh: Adam and Charles Black, 1854), 316.
2 Alongside Friedrich Christoph Schlosser’s famous biographies, note his Weltgeschichte in zusam-
menhängender Erzählung, 4 vols. (Frankfurt am Main: Varrentrapp 1815–41); Weltgeschichte für das
deutsche Volk, 19 vols. (Frankfurt am Main: Varrentrapp 1844–57).
3 Monika Badr, ‘East-Central European Historical Writing’, in Stuart Macintyre, Juan Maiguashca,
and Attila Pók (eds.), The Oxford History of Historical Writing 1800–1945 (Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 2015), 326–48, here 335–6.
4 Pim den Boer, ‘Historical Writing in France’, in Macintyre, Maiguashca, and Pók (eds.), The
Oxford History of Historical Writing 1800–1945, 184–203, here 190–1, 201.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
largely ignored. In Germany the story was of a certain ‘historicist’ thought affect-
ing other disciplines like economics much more than those disciplines affected
the work of historians. There the method conflict was decisively won by the
political-institutional tendency of historiography over competing tendencies
associated today particularly with Karl Lamprecht (1856–1915). The victory owed
less to intellectual vindication than weight of numbers and institutional position
and to the broader political and cultural climate in Germany.
The first section of this chapter addresses the general political context of so
much historical thought across the Continent, with the French Revolution and its
aftershocks especially prominent in the explanation. It seeks to draw connections
between different sorts of national situation and different sorts of national
Identity History, paying particular attention to British and French historiograph
ical trends.
The second section narrows the focus as it examines the dominant trends of
German historiography in the nineteenth century. Why Germany? Because
German thought was especially significant in fostering ‘national consciousness’ in
central, eastern and south-eastern Europe. As well as Herder, the geographical
breadth of the Göttingen historian August Ludwig von Schlözer’s (1735–1809)
interests was an important source of inspiration in eastern Europe and indeed
beyond the Continent, while it is worth noting, for instance, the intellectual debt
accrued in Berlin to Leopold von Ranke by the historian, ideologue of the 1848
Moldavian Revolution, and later Prime Minister of Romania, Mihail Kogălniceanu
(1817–91).5 Moreover, German historianship was the first to professionalize in
Europe and indeed the world, and what happened in the German academy
shaped institutional development elsewhere. At the same time, we have already
hinted at challenges to the prevailing German model of historiography. Key
challenges in the 1860s from Switzerland and France are examined in the third
section.
Given the grand fluctuations in German political fortunes in the nineteenth
and early twentieth centuries, and the accompanying turmoil in historical phil
osophy, Germany also features quite heavily in most of the remaining sections of
the chapter. Here we examine how the particularizing, relativizing, tendency of a
brand of historical thought turned in upon itself from around 1870, as some of
the ontological certainties of the nation-through-history were undermined by the
effects of modernization and world conflict, and the social function of the
5 Gyula Szvák, ‘The Golden Age of Russian Historical Writing: The Nineteenth Century,’ in
Macintyre, Maiguashca, and Pók (eds.), The Oxford History of Historical Writing 1800–1945, 303–25,
here 305–6, 308; Badr, ‘East-Central European Historical Writing’, 330, 336, 340–1 (though note
exceptions to the generalizations about Geist as regards Poland, with its more monarchical-based
nationalism), 345. As mentioned, among the imitators of the Monumenta Germaniae Historica were
the Monumenta Hungariae historica (Magyar történelmi emlékek) and the Monumentae Historiae
Bohemica. On the circumstances of the founding of the Monumenta Germaniae Historica see Ian
Wood, The Modern Origins of the Early Middle Ages (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013), 156–7.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
historian became the subject of renewed debate. One upshot was a series of mani-
festos for scholarly neutrality, and a proceduralist emphasis on History as
Methodology alone.
As the influential German model of national History was weakened in the first
half of the twentieth century, more space was created for competing methodolo-
gies within Germany too, especially those associated with the social sciences. The
final section of this chapter considers some of the alternative German models as
they developed in relationship to their forebears.
6 Marius Turda, ‘History Writing in the Balkans’, in Macintyre, Maiguashca, and Pók (eds.), The
Oxford History of Historical Writing 1800–1945, 349–66, here 349–50, 361.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
museums. Historian Stefan Berger reminds us that grand national narratives were
produced beyond the precincts of universities and the circles of trained histor
ians. ‘In many parts of Europe, it was civil servants, members of the clergy and
the aristocracy, middle-class writers, and intellectuals as well as politicians who
were the authors of key historical national narratives. These “amateur” historians
formed historical associations and museums and edited journals as well as major
source editions.’7 Document editions included the Monumenta Germaniae
Historica.8 This publication series of primary sources pertaining to all places of
Germanic influence from the end of the Roman Empire through the medieval
period was established in 1819. The motto of the series, which encouraged Czech
and Hungarian imitations, was Sanctus amor patriae dat animum, ‘holy love of
the fatherland gives spirit’. The first volume of what are now more than 300 was
printed in 1826. The Russian interior minister from 1809, N. P. Rumiantsev, initi-
ated the publication of official documentation, and one of his recruits, Pavel
Mikhailovich Stroiev, copied and catalogued a vast corpus of non-state sources to
complement the central archives. The first series of the Complete Collection of
Russian Annals were published under the auspices of the Ministry of Education in
the 1830s and publication has continued to the present day.9 In the same decade,
that in which, under the July Monarchy, historical instruction was formalized in
French schools and teacher-training instituted, the Committee for Historic and
Scientific Works was formed and began publishing the Collection of Unpublished
Documents on the History of France.10
For all that, it is consistent with earlier warnings about sharp distinctions
between ‘modernity’ and the pre-modern to advise caution about attributing too
much of the ‘invention of national traditions’ to the nineteenth century. Invention
there surely was, but not a little of it had happened much earlier. From a millen-
nium and more before the nineteenth century, remember, origines gentium tales
had served the purposes of political legitimation by genealogical pedigree. Even
when they furthered elite interests they were often ethno-cultural, even quasi-
racial, in reference, whether in the widespread invocation of Trojan roots or the
construction of the Angelcynn or the Franks as chosen people. There was more to
the political ideology of nationalism—the claim of a ‘nation’ of people to exclusive
ownership of a territorial state, i.e. a nation-state—than this, but these older elem
ents were nonetheless congruent with many modern nationalisms and they con-
stituted the raw materials on which those nationalisms depended. Much the same
went for the association of particular ethnic groups with particular confessions,
and, within broad confessions, particular churches; the nineteenth century saw a
multiplication of the ‘national churches’ whose origins can be traced not just to
the Reformation but the earlier establishment of increasingly distinct English and
French Catholic churches.
The French Revolution interacted in different ways with existing philosophies
of differentiation between peoples owing to its own combination of universalism
and particularism. A movement that invoked a general will rather than a dynasty
accentuated the tendency, inherent in pre-existing contract and natural law the
ories and in Anglo-Saxon constitutional developments, to move the locus of sov-
ereignty from the crown. ‘We the people’ was the formula for reconfiguring the
basis of legitimate authority, however the ‘we’ was defined. The revolutionaries
and then Napoleon threatened to generalize this conceptual model through con-
quest and the stimulation of insurgence against existing rulers elsewhere in
Europe—however tyrannical revolutionary and Napoleonic rule was in practice.
Constitutions were exported alongside other ‘modernizing’ and ‘rationalizing’
reforms abroad, such as Napoleonic educational policy in the short-lived French
protectorate of Illyria which ignited national-historical interests amongst Croat
and Slovene scholars. Constitutions unleashed tendencies that could not just be
forced back into the genie’s bottle by the 1815 settlement. Nor did post-Napoleonic
rulers desire to force them all back in—including French rulers, especially from
the overthrow of the restoration regime in 1830. Rather, the rulers wished to
exploit these new tendencies while controlling them, with memories fresh as to
the potency of a revolutionary ‘nation in arms’. The logic and the result could be
much the same whether one embraced the inspiration of French reforms or
reformed oneself in order that one was strong enough to resist conquest by the
likes of France (both apply in some way to Prussia) or (as in the case of Russia or
in its own way Britain) where one’s ‘national consciousness’ had been ‘enhanced’
by resisting France. The key was to project, via some balance of rhetoric and
policy, the idea that the interests of elites and broader swathes of the population
were roughly the same. The project became especially important as the century
progressed, and with it the upheavals and potential for class conflict attendant
upon industrialization. Of particular symbolic use was the emphasis on shared
history, culture, and language which we associate with romanticism.
Whatever else it was linked with, the revolutionary era was linked with French
intrusion into other peoples’ affairs. The fact that intrusion came in the name of
universalism and issued forth from France prompted a rejection of universalism
along with French dominance in favour of philosophical and ethno-national par-
ticularism. Disruption in the lives of Europe’s states and peoples (including in
France) then and during industrialization brought forth an emphasis on the con-
tinuous and the historical. This helps explain nineteenth-century medievalism,
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
which was very different in character from the disdain for the middle ages evident
in some French and British Enlightenment historiography. The medieval world
was seen as the incubator of modern peoplehood, and the depth of bonds thereby
intimated stood in contrast to the supposed shallowness of Enlightenment ration-
alism. There was functional and patriotic value to such an outlook, given the
invocation of universal, natural law by the French revolutionaries. The failure of
Prussian arms at Jena and Auerstadt need have no metaphysical significance if set
against a theory positing the difference but not inferiority of Germanic traditions
against French. What was needed to put things right, in the commendation of the
philosopher Johann Gottlieb Fichte (1762–1814), was the consolidation of
Germany’s own folk-consciousness, the awakening of the German nation, whose
political iteration was the drive for a solely German state. Indeed it was the
Prussian reformer vom Stein who, fresh from disappointment that the 1815
Congress of Vienna did not promote German unification, set up with his own
funds the society that produced the Monumenta Germaniae Historica in order to
instruct Germans about their past. He was also instrumental in establishing
Berlin University, as if acting under Herder’s injunction to ‘promote the unity of
the territories of Germany through writings . . . and institutions’ (p. 177). In prin-
ciple an anti-universalist outlook was at least pluralistic, and possibly relativistic.
This may appear ironic when one considers how German traditions were later
promoted to the status of inherently superior after success against France in
Bismarck’s final war of unification. Yet Fichte himself had intimated that
Germany’s inherently cosmopolitan and spiritual outlook gave it a privileged
place in leading the European peoples forward now that the French had forfeited
their right to leadership.11
Emphasizing civilizational depth might entail focusing on longstanding insti-
tutions or on ethnic commonality. Sometimes these foci complemented each
other, as in England, where there was extensive and enduring overlap between the
territorial state and its institutions and the ethnos in question. The concept of
‘Anglo-Saxon liberties’ connoted the ethnic and the institutional at once, and such
a concept underlay some of the most famous statements of ‘whig’ history, as did
an ethos of Anglicanism. When one talks of the ‘whig’ tendency in English his
toriography the immediate associations are of constitutional History, bringing
together the political and the legal across large tracts of time in an optimistic
story of progressive change whereby underlying continuities are given their due
and the wrong sort of change is repelled. Neither explicitly cultural nor explicitly
social in approach, whig History nonetheless clearly felt itself to be bringing out
something of the national ‘character’, and it was nationalist in its sense of English
exceptionalism. The joinder of this exceptionalism with universalism is also no
12 P. B. M. Blaas, Continuity and Anachronism (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1978), 111, 117.
13 Freeman cited in Bentley, ‘Introduction: Approaches to Modernity’, 437.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
14 William Stubbs, The Constitutional History of England in its Origins and Development, vol. 1
(Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1874), 247.
15 Den Boer, ‘Historical Writing in France’.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
16 Ceri Crossley, French Historians and Romanticism: Thierry, Guizot, the Saint-Simonians, Quinet,
Michelet (London: Routledge, 1993), 193–204; Tom Conner, ‘Writing History: Michelet’s History of the
French Revolution’, in Gail M. Schwab and John R. Jeanneny (eds.), The French Revolution of 1789 and
its Impact (Westport, CT: Greenwood Press, 1995), 13–22.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
Course in Positive Philosophy had appeared between 1830 and 1842, and the final
two volumes concerned the prospect of a social science that would remove the
‘theologico-metaphysical philosophy’ with which he felt the theorizing of even
the finest minds of his day was still suffused. In Comte’s own tripartite stadial
analysis, a social science would properly be based on the empirical principles of
positive science.17 The experimental method gained in prestige subsequently via
the achievements of Marcellin Berthelot in chemistry and Claude Bernard in
medicine. In France, romanticism’s literary and philosophical pretensions were
cast as suspect in a shift much more accentuated than the rejection of Macaulay’s
romanticism by later English whig historians.18 The application of more scientific
methods to History as the century progressed promised—spuriously—to obviate
or transcend divisive politics.
Unlike France and England, in most ‘national’ cases early in the nineteenth
century there was no even approximate coincidence of ethnos on one hand and
territory or institutions on the other hand. Ultimately the wish to reconstitute
borders and institutions to correspond to supposedly discrete ethnic groups tri-
umphed in the period 1866–1923, though all manner of political and military
contingencies paved the way. Beyond the twisted paths to Italian and German
‘unification’, especially significant was the First World War that shattered the
multinational Romanov, Habsburg, and Ottoman empires.19 Certainly the major
nationalist thinkers of the early nineteenth century did not think in quite such
apocalyptic terms. We know that political nationalism was initially conceived in
relation to liberalism and Enlightenment ideas of equality, partly based on the
analogy of collective to individual self-determination, partly because of the
connection between broadened political representation and recognition of ‘the
people’ as a source of authority. Following Herder, the vision could be of self-
authorizing collectives living in harmony with each other. Elements of the flower-
ing of vernacular literature and serried cultural renaissances of the nineteenth
century did indeed evince that spirit. But since that self-same ‘flowering’ indi-
cated vigorous efforts to create the nation as much as to express it, we ought to
remember that creation involved definition as well as a great deal of archaeological
excavation in the name of ‘recovering what had been lost’, be that through
17 Comte, The Positive Philosophy of Auguste Comte, vol. 2, ed. Harriet Martineau (London:
Trübner, 1875), 1.
18 On these challenges see Ceri Crossley, ‘Historiography: France’, in Christopher John Murray
(ed.), Encyclopedia of the Romantic Era, 1760–1850 (London: Fitzroy Dearborn, 2004), 505–7;
den Boer, ‘Historical Writing in France’, 195–6.
19 On the matter of contingency, it is also important to stress that nationalism was not always the
dominant discursive framework of discontent in the multinational empires. In the Habsburg case, for
instance, many of the challenges to Vienna’s authority that used History were not national, but local in
character. Equally, the Habsburgs were perfectly capable of annexing the Histories of their subject
peoples to the History of the multinational empire. The statue of Jan Hus in Prague was erected under
the Habsburgs; the Titian memorial in the Frari church in Venice was used to stress the harmony of
Venetian, Italian, and Austrian interests. Thanks to David Laven for these thoughts.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
One should not just focus on the multinational empires in this connection,
however, for no state was without grievances or divisions that titular elites feared
might thwart the project of national unification. The nation-state was, and
remains, an ideal rather than a reality. The ‘differences’ that had to be transcended
or eradicated in the nation-building process were not just ethnic or ethnoreli-
gious ones, though these tended to be the ones over which most blood was to be
shed outside of the USSR. Differences of regional dialect and local loyalties could
be just as problematic, and extant peasant culture was as much of an obstacle as
any nascent ‘class consciousness’ in the creation of unity and more integrated
and ‘rationalized’ national economies, as the project of ‘making peasants into
Frenchmen’ in late nineteenth-century France revealed. Even after ‘unification’ in
nineteenth-century Italy or Germany, and ‘liberation’ in Bulgaria (1878) or
Poland (1919), states had to try to foster the national consciousness, loyalty, and
togetherness that unification was supposed to express. In one sense this indicates a
contradiction, but in another sense it reinforced the sense of continuity-in-process
over time, as when American politicians invoke the ongoing effort to create the
‘more perfect union’ of which the Constitution speaks.
For better or for worse, Leopold von Ranke (1795–1886) has become synonym
ous with the mainstream tradition of nineteenth-century German historiography,
the tradition known as historicism—Historismus in German. Ranke’s prefaces,
like those of Tacitus or Thucydides, contain some of the most quoted manifestos
of the discipline, although, as with his classical forebears, if one relies on the pref-
aces to characterize the historian, one is apt to miss a great deal. Ranke’s vast
scholarly output includes volumes-worth of source discussions to underpin some
of the historical narratives that precede them, while an appendix to his first
monograph, Histories of the Latin and Germanic Peoples [Völker], 1494–1535
(1824), is his best known methodological contribution. Ranke taught many stu-
dents and pioneered the Berlin seminar with its focus on archival documents and
source criticism, which was used inter alia as the model for the first US History
PhD programme at Johns Hopkins University.
While Ranke conducted extensive research, often in hitherto closed archives,
not everything he wrote was in accordance with his own strictures; more import
antly, given that few of us are innocent of hypocrisy on that score, many of these
strictures were not new. What Ranke supposedly did for the study of modern
sources, Barthold Georg Niebuhr had already done for Roman sources. Putting
aside the contributions to critical historical scholarship of scholars in other coun-
tries and before the eighteenth century, and focusing only on the immediate
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
Ranke’s name is often associated with the idea of History as a science, but this
is apt to induce confusion if it is not appreciated that the German Wissenschaft
has broader connotations than the natural sciences and applies to any body of
systematic enquiry. The term does not merit the specific interpretation given to it
by many scholars outside Germany. Not for the last time, ideas originating on the
European continent found less critical application when applied in the Anglo-
Saxon world.29 The translator of the 1887 English edition of the Histories of the
Latin and Germanic Peoples not only singularized Histories to History, thus
removing Ranke’s gesture to modesty, he only saw fit to reproduce the following
sentence from Ranke’s original—1824—preface, nourishing the idea of Ranke as a
naïve fact-fetishist: ‘A strict representation of facts [Thatsache in the original], be
it ever so narrow [bedingt; better translated as conditional or contingent, as
opposed to the philosophically ‘necessary’] and unpoetical [unschön], is, beyond
doubt, the first law.’30 But in Germany too lesser minds reduced the thoughts of
their heroes to what they themselves found most palatable—or manageable—and
Ranke’s emphasis on source criticism and validation became for some the alpha
and omega of his message. Consider the following, written at the turn of the
1880s by George Prothero, not yet professor at Edinburgh University, of erstwhile
hosts in Bonn who evinced a ‘tendency to stop at a collection of facts, to let the
facts speak for themselves, or rather remain dumb . . . They don’t seek enough to
get at the great laws of history, development of nations, differences of national
character . . . One wants a people with more imagination . . . to extract the essence
from the material they collect . . .31 This is actually one version of Ranke criticizing
another. While encapsulating aspects of his method, the scholars whom Prothero
depicted had failed to address Ranke’s more philosophical concerns.
Establishing a ‘regulative ideal’ rather than praising his own Olympian view-
point may well have been Ranke’s own meaning when he wrote that historians
should try to efface themselves from what they wrote, and that his work on the
Latin and Germanic peoples ‘will bloss sagen wie es eigentlich gewesen’. This line,
written in the proximate context of Ranke’s use of Venetian archives, means that
Ranke ‘wants/seeks merely to tell how it [i.e. the past] actually/essentially was’,32
though invariably the phrase is repeated or modified without the initial modal
‘wants/seeks’ or the adverb ‘merely’. Certainly the interpretation to modesty is
Geschichte. Historisch-kritische Ausgabe, ed. Theodor Schieder and Helmut Berding (Munich:
Oldenbourg, 1971), 53 ff.
29 See for instance the reception of ‘Rankean’ ideas in the USA: Peter Novick, That Noble Dream:
The ‘Objectivity Question’ and the American Historical Profession (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1999).
30 Leopold von Ranke, History of the Latin and Teutonic Nations from 1494–1514, trans.
P. A. Ashworth (London: George Bell and Sons, 1887), p. vi.
31 Cited in Michael Bentley, Modernizing England’s Past: English Historiography in the Age of
Modernism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005), 99. Emphasis added.
32 Ranke, Geschichten der romanischen und germanischen Völker, p. vi.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
supported by Ranke’s stated aspiration elsewhere ‘to see with unbiased eyes the
progress of universal history and in this spirit to produce beautiful and noble
works[:] Imagine what happiness it would be for me if I could realize this ideal,
even in a small degree.’33 What exactly is denoted by ‘eigentlich’ remains a matter
of some debate, as indicated. The differing interpretations ‘actually’ and ‘essen-
tially’, in the sense of ‘in essence’, can both be justified if one holds to the view that
Ranke leaned on the 1821 paper of the philosopher and educational theorist
Wilhelm von Humboldt, ‘On the task of the historian’ (Geschichtsschreiber), for
that address implies each meaning at different points.34 This volume’s contention,
given how rationalists had fostered an inferiority complex among so many histor
ians, is to place Ranke and probably Humboldt too in relation to that passage in
The Discourse on Method in which Descartes writes of exemplar historians that
the omissions they make in the interests of relevance ensure that ‘the remainder
does not appear as it really was’ and who thus mislead by their partial exempla.
Ranke might well have agreed with Descartes’s criticism but wanted to render it
redundant by his own approach to History.
As relevant as the content of Ranke’s aspiration to tell the past ‘wie es eigentlich
gewesen’ was that with which he juxtaposed the aspiration. He prefaced the
famous words by a resignation from other tasks that had been conferred on
History over the previous centuries, including the ‘office of judging the past, of
instructing the present for the benefit of future ages’. Humboldt was just as scep
tical of the exemplary rationale.35 In fact Ranke was not entirely consistent on the
matter of exemplarity—elsewhere he also wrote of the guidance that might be
provided by discrete ‘examples of ancient and modern times’—and, as we shall
see, he did think History could instruct in some way.36 But there were reasons
pragmatic as well as philosophical for disavowing History as Lesson, so we should
by no means think of Ranke as purely an advocate of the procedural rationale of
History as Method, whatever his insistence on scholarly rigour. Like Humboldt
he had his own substantivist rationales related to his own ontology or concept of
fundamental reality.
When he avowed an interest in ‘der Sinn jede Epoche an und für sich selbst’, i.e.
in the meaning/significance of every epoch on its own terms, and wrote that all
33 Final sentence cited in Leopold von Ranke, The Secret of World History: Selected Writings on the
Art and Science of History, ed. Roger Wines (New York: Fordham University Press, 1981), 259.
34 Wilhelm von Humboldt, ‘On the Historian’s Task’, History and Theory, 6:1 (1967), 57–71, espe-
cially the opening pages. For the influence of the Humboldt essay see Georg G. Iggers, ‘The Intellectual
Foundations of Nineteenth-Century “Scientific” History: The German Model’, in Macintyre,
Maiguashca, and Pók (eds.), The Oxford History of Historical Writing 1800–1945, 41–58, here 43–4.
35 For contextualization see Ulrich Muhlack, ‘Leopold von Ranke und die Begründung der
quellenkritischen Geschichtsforschung’, in Jürgen Elvert and Susanne Krauß (eds.), Historische
Debatten und Kontroversen im 19. und 20. Jahrhundert (Stuttgart: Steiner, 2003), 23–33, here 27–8.
On Humboldt’s views, Humboldt, ‘On the Historian’s Task’, 60–1.
36 Leopold von Ranke, The Theory and Practice of History, ed. Georg G. Iggers (London: Routledge,
2011), 82.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
ages were equidistant from eternity, or ‘umittelbar zu Gott’, immediate unto God,
Ranke was opposing the idea, associated with Hegel, that epochs or peoples were
merely vectors of some progressing general spirit.37 In his lectures to Ludwig II of
Bavaria in the 1850s he anticipated Nietzsche in criticizing the ‘Hegelian’ idea that
‘each generation surpasses the preceding one, so that the latest is always the most
favoured and the preceding generations are only the bearers of those that follow.’38
Contrary to historian Charles Bambach’s claims, Ranke did not generally think in
terms of a ‘Hegelian pageant of world history’, and while he professed thoughts
tantamount to the idea that ‘universal history was organized according to provi-
dential design’ he did not claim to decipher the design. He did not conceive of a
‘unitary narrative’ or ‘a historical continuum with equally measured intervals
where one can . . . “see with unbiased eyes the progress of universal history” ’ (how
misleading these partial quotations can be), and he did not envisage time ‘as pure
temporal succession’ in a way that supposedly ‘undergirds . . . the modernist logic
of overcoming’ and ‘opens the path for . . . the “end of history” ’.39 While Ranke did
talk of progress in a rather unclear way, and while in his very long career and
intellectual development he sometimes invoked spiritual tendencies as under
lying motors of visible change, most of Bambach’s assertions are explicitly dis
avowed in Ranke’s lectures on World History of 1854 and his notes on History
and Philosophy in his World History of 1881–8.40 To be sure, his uncompleted,
multi-volume work on world History was Eurocentric, not least because it was
interested in the impact of powerful Europe on the rest of the world, but this was
a study of connections and influences between states and peoples, not a tale of
rational global advance to destiny. Whatever Ranke’s reservations about the
approach of the earlier Göttingen historians, the philosophy of his world History
owed more to Gatterer, even Bodin, than Hegel’s concept of historical development,
even if he and the great philosopher are bound together by some idealist precepts.41
37 Quotes from Daniel Fulda, Wissenschaft aus Kunst: Die Entstehung der modernen deutschen
Geschichtsschreibung, 1760–1860 (Berlin: de Gruyter, 1996) 183–4.
38 Cited in Lionel Grossman, Basel in the Age of Burckhardt: A Study in Unseasonable Ideas
(Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2000), 216.
39 All quotes from Charles R. Bambach, Heidegger, Dilthey, and the Crisis of Historicism (Ithaca:
Cornell University Press, 1995), 8–9.
40 From the 1854 lectures, in Ranke, The Secret of World History, 160–1: ‘We can assume in the
areas of material interest an absolute progress, a highly decisive ascent which would require an enor-
mous upset to bring about a decline. But we cannot find a similar progress in moral affairs. . . . From
the viewpoint of the divine idea, I can think of the matter only this way: humanity contains within
itself an endless variety of developments which come to view from time to time, according to laws
which are unknown to us, more mysterious, and greater than we can conceive.’
41 For the philosophy of his world History see Leopold von Ranke, Weltgeschichte, ed. Alfred Dove
and Georg Winter, vol. IX, part II (Leipzig: Duncker and Humblot, 1888), pp. vii ff. Generally on
Ranke’s world history, François Hartog, ‘Von der Universalgeschichte zur Globalgeschichte?
Zeiterfahrungen’, Le Débat, 154 (2009), 53–66, here point 14; Ulrich Muhlack, ‘Das Problem der
Weltgeschichte bei Leopold Ranke’, in Wolfgang Hardtwig and Philipp Müller (eds.), Die
Vergangenheit der Weltgeschichte: Universalhistorisches Denken in Berlin 1800–1933 (Göttingen:
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 2010), 143–72. On reservations about the Göttingen approach by Ranke
and Herder, see Fulda, Wissenschaft aus Kunst, 183 ff.
42 Cited in Robert A. Pois, ‘Two Poles Within Historicism: Croce and Meinecke’, Journal of the
History of Ideas, 31:2 (1970), 253–72, here 253.
43 Geoffrey Elton, The Practice of History (Sydney: Sydney University Press, 1967), 16.
44 Ibid. 13.
45 On Spinoza, Russell, History of Western Philosophy, 597. On Ranke’s panentheism, Carl Hinrichs,
Ranke und die Geschichtstheologie der Goethezeit (Gottingen: Musterschmidt, 1954)—thanks to
Reinbert A. Krol for the reference. On Meinecke’s panentheism, Krol, ‘Friedrich Meinecke:
Panentheism and the Crisis of Historicism’, Journal of the Philosophy of History, 4 (2010), 195–209,
here 206 ff.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
of the fleeting conglomerations that the [social] contract theories invoke like
cloud formations, I perceive spiritual essences, original creations of the human
spirit—one might say thoughts of God’.46
From this perspective we can also understand why historicists developed a
particular focus on the state and a particular attitude towards its power. The
focus, by no means all-consuming—after all, Ranke wrote not only histories of
multiple major European states at key periods of their development and the
papacy as a political as well as religious force, but also on Italian poetry47—was
partly a matter of the availability of sources, partly of elitist concerns. It was also a
reflection of the times themselves, in which successive European revolutions and
processes of state formation seemed to indicate the overwhelming importance of
politics and warfare.
The idealist legacy is apparent in Ranke’s idea of public institutions as the locus
of something like ‘objective spirit’. The state had a will and character of sorts, and
both were shaped not just by the people comprising the body politic at any one
point, but by the traditions that had developed over time. The state guaranteed
the liberty and expressed the individuality of nations on the stage of world his-
tory. As such, not only was it owed loyalty, it was itself a moral entity, as Samuel
Pufendorf and Hegel also maintained. This is not to say that Ranke felt that the
state could do no wrong: in keeping perhaps with the Neoplatonic elements of his
thought, the purest entities were the highest up the chain of being, the least
coloured by the mundane and the physical. But precisely because states and their
leaders had to act in an imperfect world it would be wrong either to expect per-
fection of them or to denigrate them for their imperfection. It would, he wrote,
‘be infinitely wrong to seek only the effects of brutal forces in the struggles of his
torical powers . . . no state has ever existed without a spiritual basis and a spiritual
content. A spiritual essence appears in power itself, an original genius with its
own particular life.’48
Since the state was a moral entity, its prerogatives were not easily limited by
recourse to the concept of external wills and moralities; its duty was at once to
protect the people and express its ‘moral energy’. This was the thrust of Bismarck’s
emphasis on the primacy of foreign policy, the arena in which the state preserved
its existence—hence the nineteenth-century resurgence in popularity of the
Renaissance high priest of raison d’état.49 Equally, the true statesman should
imbibe History in order to acquaint himself with the appropriate way to act
46 ‘Statt jener flüchtigen Konglomerate, die sich dir aus der Lehre vom Vertrag erheben wie
Wolkengebilde, sehe ich geistige Wesenheiten, originale Schöpfungen des Menschengeists,—man darf
sagen, Gedanken Gottes’: Ranke, ‘Politisches Gespräch’, Historisch-politische Zeitschrift, ed. Leopold
Ranke, vol. 2 (1833–6), 775–807, here 794.
47 Leopold von Ranke, ‘Zur Geschichte der italienischen Poesie’, Abhandlungen der Königlichen
Preußischen Akademie der Wissenschaften zu Berlin (Berlin: Duncker und Humblot, 1835), 401–85.
48 Ranke, Weltgeschichte, vol. IX, part II, p. xi. 49 Cassirer, The Myth of the State, 125.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
within national traditions and the potentialities of the age. This was one way in
which the statesman, like anyone else, might benefit from the enhanced sense of
his own historicity, his own nature as a being-in-time and as a product of his
torical forces, that he might also act with such forces. In this sense historicist
thought was political through-and-through, even though its proponents saw
themselves as above mere party politics. Historians working in this tradition of
History as political-cultural rather than religious Communion might lay claim to
divining the normative order of their state, establishing its ‘common-sense’,
and nowhere is such a tendency clearer than in the inaugural issue of the journal
the Historische Zeitschrift, which was first published in 1859 and spawned imita-
tors internationally in the following decades.50 The editor, Heinrich von Sybel
(1817–95) claimed to:
Ranke and his successors saw themselves battling for interpretative supremacy
in the human sciences as a whole. History could take its place as the cardinal
humanistic discipline by making a virtue of the diverse particularities that con-
ventional philosophy was not equipped to consider, while the spiritual-idealistic
side of historicism ensured that a concern with empirics did not degenerate into a
preoccupation with detail for its own sake. To this day, individual historians may
spend so much time on ‘the facts’ because some are theory-shy, but History the
discipline as such remains especially concerned with the particular, either alone
or, as with Ranke, as a component and reflection of the universal. (In this line of
thought the primary importance of fact is its expression of particularity, albeit
that many latter-day arguments about the nature of History have focused upon
50 Margaret F. Stieg, The Historische Zeitschrift: The Origin and Development of Scholarly Historical
Periodicals (Tuscaloosa: University of Alabama Press, 1986).
51 Editorial trans. and repr. in Stern (ed.), The Varieties of History, 171–2.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
52 Nathan Rotenstreich, ‘From Facts to Thoughts: Collingwood’s Views on the Nature of History’,
Philosophy, 35:133 (1960), 122–37, here 129. My point may or may not be an adaption. For an inter-
rogation of the narrow conception of truth as correctness, Robert Piercey, The Uses of the Past from
Heidegger to Rorty (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2011), 53–7.
53 Cited in Peter Koslowski (ed.), The Discovery of Historicity in German Idealism and Historicism
(Berlin: Springer, 2005), 42.
54 Beiser, The German Historicist Tradition, 278–9.
55 Claasen, ‘Res Gestae, Universal History, Apocalypse’, 401.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
56 Gunter Scholtz, ‘Historismus’ als spekulative Geschichtsphilosophie: Christlieb Julius Braniss
(Frankfurt: V. Klostermann, 1973). Braniss was a convert from Judaism, but we should note that the
German-centred Jewish Enlightenment (Haskalah) itself evinced elements of idealism similar to
Ranke’s, while the developmental element of Hegelian and then historicist thought gave a new twist to
the historical character that had never been absent from Jewish theology. Thus Immanuel Wolf in his
1822 ‘On the Concept of a Science of Judaism’ (which reflected the thought of the Society for the
Culture and Science of Judaism established by Hegel’s student Eduard Gans (1797–1839)): ‘man needs
time in order to raise himself from the world of the physical and the many to that of the universal
unity, the all-embracing and all existing Monas’ (Monas stemming from the Greek monos, from which
we also get ‘monad’); ‘peace and permanence are alien to the realm of the spirit, which is truly living.
It is in the nature of the spiritual world to be in constant motion, and never to cease development’; ‘It
is manifest everywhere that the fundamental principle of Judaism is again in a state of ferment, striv-
ing to assume a shape in harmony with the spirit of the times.’ See also Nahman Krochmal (1785–
1840): ‘just as the king of a nation binds it together and unifies it with regard to readily visible
externals, so too the manifestation of the divine which it contains unifies and binds it together intern
ally with regard to place and time, from generation to generation’. Wolf and Krochmal contextualized
and excerpted in Davis Biale (ed.), Judaism (New York: Norton, 2015), 514–23, quotes from 518, 519, 521.
57 D. Villemaire, E. A. Burtt: Historian and Philosopher (Dordrecht: Springer, 1992), 19.
58 Randall, Nature and Historical Experience, 15; 72 ff.
59 Georg Gottfried Gervinus, Geschichte der poetischen National-Literatur der Deutschen, 5 vols.
(Leipzig: Engelmann, 1835–42).
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
As we approach the end of this section, reflection on quite what objectivity might
mean brings us to Gustav Droysen (1808–84), who also disapproved of Gervinus’s
approach. One of Droysen’s significances it that he contributed to a shift in
emphasis away from the idea of History as high art or literature to that of it as a
form of scientific labour with a unique and rigorous methodology; any given
individual specialist was but one contributor to a wider progressive process of
understanding.61 His concept of Historik, or ‘historics’, as in the title of his meth-
odological work Grundriß der Historik (Outline of the Principles of History,
1857/8), had been deployed, inter alia, in an earlier work of Gervinus’s where it
stood in relation to History much as Aristotle’s Poetics (c.335 bce), in German
Poetik, stood to literature.62 The contrast, from Droysen’s perspective, of Historik
and Poetik is as significant in its own way as is Droysen’s criticism from a hermen
eutic perspective of Thomas Buckle’s positivist historianship.63 Yet for all of his
emphasis on empirical research as opposed to Hegelian speculation, Droysen was
much influenced by Hegelian concepts of deep historical forces, and both his
philosophical reflections on History and his historical works evince teleology:
while contributing to methodical debates, Droysen also sought to systematize and
encourage a specific, disciplined historical way of thinking to enable historians to
place their present in relationship to the past and to the future with reference to
the deeper unfolding forces.64
Droysen is as deserving as Ranke of the epithet ‘great man’ historian, though
there is a clear Hegelian sense of some of his great men as bearers of world-
historical Volk-spirits (pp. 180–2). His precocious breakthrough work was his
History of Alexander the Great (1833), shortly followed by his History of Hellenism.
The link between the achievements of Alexander’s father and Philip II in
‘unifying’ Greece under the Macedonian kingdom, then Alexander in expanding
60 Gordon A. Craig, The Politics of the Unpolitical: German Writers and the Problem of Power,
1770–1871 (Munich: Beck, 1993), 146, 154.
61 Wolfgang Hardtwig, ‘Geschichtsreligion—Wissenschaft als Arbeit—Objektivität. Der Historismus
in neuer Sicht’, Historische Zeitschrift, 252:1 (1991), 1–32, here 19 ff.
62 Christiane Hackel, Aristoteles-Rezeption in der Geschichtstheorie Johann Gustav Droysens (Berlin:
de Gruyter, 2019), 147.
63 On Buckle see Johann Gustav Droysen, ‘Erhebung der Geschichte zum Rang einer Wissenschaft’,
Historische Zeitschrift, 9 (1863), 1–22, which was reproduced in the 1882 edition of Grundriß der
Historik (Leipzig: Veit, 1882), 47 ff.
64 Arthur Alfaix Assis, What Is History For? Johann Gustav Droysen and the Functions of
Historiography (New York: Berghahn, 2016), ch. 2; Beiser, German Historicist Tradition, ch. 8.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
65 Droysen, Geschichte Alexanders des Grossen (Hamburg: Perthes, 1833); Geschichte des
Hellenismus, 2 vols. (Hamburg: Perthes, 1836–43).
66 Droysen, Geschichte der preussischen Politik, 14 vols. (Leipzig: Veit, 1855–86). For Ranke’s view,
Wilfried Nippel, Johann Gustav Droysen: ein Leben zwischen Wissenschaft und Politik (Munich: Beck,
2008), 287.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
God’s-eye view.67 But Droysen went further still, actively embracing this perspec-
tivalism: ‘Insofar as I consider the past from my standpoint, from the thoughts of
my nation and state, from my religion and past, I stand high above my individual
ego. I think, as it were, from a higher ego, in which the slag of my little person has
been melted away.’ Thus we encounter not Ranke’s famed (and caricatured) aspir
ation to self-effacement before the past, but self-effacement before the cultural
traditions through which the particular historian investigates the past, the indi-
vidual only ever being a less complete whole than the greater and higher whole of
the collective.68
If we can abstract a little, moving away from Droysen’s particular preoocupa-
tions, and focusing on the logic of such pronouncements, we see that they raise as
many questions as they answer. Hippolyte Taine implied the superfluity of the
Romantic artists’ injunction il faut être de son temps, ‘one ought to be of one’s
times’, since one was ‘of one’s times’ whether one liked it or not.69 The same pre-
sumably went for one’s own nation, state, religion. Furthermore, in the event that
one tried consciously to embrace the relevant context(s), by that very effort one
would actually be adding something over-and-above general acculturation and
thus would have done the opposite of melting away the slag of one’s own personal
idiosyncrasies. One might add that there is no way a reader could establish
whether any given historical interpretation was an authentic expression of the
accultured author or of something else altogether, irrespective of what the author
claimed, not least because no culture or ‘time’ produces a monolithic expression
of itself. Droysen’s prescription was either unactualizable, meaningless, a recipe
for creating uncertainty in the reading audience as to whether they had been mis-
led about the historian’s agenda, or a pseudo-philosophical justification of his
nationalist position.
This debate also shows how historicism could progress from an ontological
claim about the relationship between particulars and universals to an epistemo-
logical claim, a claim about the nature of knowledge. The argument would go like
this: if peoples are different from each other in some fundamental way with their
outlooks being set by their national ‘essence’ or at least their national ‘experience’,
then they are not capable of taking a perspective from above the fray, and indeed
members of one people are not really capable of grasping the perspective of
67 For varying contextualizations and interpretations of Droysen on ‘eunuch-like objectivity’ and
related matters, see Beiser, German Historicist Tradition, 305–7; Assis, What Is History For?, 66–71;
White, The Content of the Form, ch. 4.
68 Droysen quote from Beiser, German Historicist Tradition, 307; further from Droysen: ‘Der ein-
zelne wird nur relative Totalität; verstehend und verstanden ist er nur wie ein Beispiel und Ausdruck
der Gemeinsamkeiten, deren Glied er ist und an deren Wesen und Werden er teilhat . . .’. Cited in
Christian-Georg Schuppe, Der andere Droysen: neue Aspekte seiner Theorie der Geschichtswissenschaft
(Stuttgart: Steiner, 1998), 25. All the works cited in this and the previous note are also relevant to the
exegesis of these quotes, and thus also to my discussion in the following paragraphs.
69 Linda Nochlin, Realism (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1971), 104–5.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
members of another people. Even in the event that competing group perspectives
are believed to be perspectives on a higher truth, which is rather less popular as
an idea today, there is no way of accessing that truth, so all we have is perspectives
that are irreconcilable by human beings (and by extension potential ethical prob-
lems in writing about other groups than one’s own for those who are not inter-
ested in celebrating their own perspective). This reasoning is one of the tributary
streams to the ‘crisis of historicism’ that we will turn to shortly.70
The tension between what we might call the ‘longitudinal’ and ‘latitudinal’ elem
ents of historicism contributed to the ‘crisis’ too, which brings us to the Swiss
Jacob Burckhardt (1818–97). Like his teacher, Ranke, Burckhardt had once been a
theology student. He felt that a growing emphasis on laborious research as the
basis of understanding threatened the aesthetic qualities of historical understand-
ing and the poetic status of History, reducing it to a specialist guild science rather
than an element of a rounded cultural education.71 With Ranke he repudiated
‘theorists’ who used History to advocate or accuse, and was as vociferous in his
rejection of any mechanistic ‘laws’ of the historical process. But where Ranke’s
dissertation had concerned Thucydides, Burckhardt’s interest was in Herodotus,
and this showed in his masterpiece, The Civilization (or Culture: Cultur in the first
edition, Kultur in subsequent editions) of the Renaissance in Italy (1860). The
high cultural elements of his interests, married to his social elitism, were some
distance from the ‘cultural turn’ of late twentieth-century historians, but much
less alien was his Herodotean and Vico-like interest in the importance of myths to
the understanding of society, and his concerns with festival, popular religion, and
mores.72
Burckhardt’s was a departure in emphasis from the political focus of so much
German historicism, though one does not wish to exaggerate the point since his
initial chapter established political and structural developments as a condition of
possibility for what he characterized as the Renaissance. Perhaps more important
on the political front was his implication that the state might be a potentially sup-
pressive/repressive element in aspects of socio-cultural life, as well as an expres-
sion and protector of cultural tendencies. Further, within Burckhardt’s interest in
70 On connections between Droysen and the ‘crisis of historicism’ see Beiser, German Historicist
Tradition, 320–1.
71 John R. Hinde, Jacob Burckhardt and the Crisis of Modernity (Montreal: McGill-Queen’s
University Press, 2000), 212. On the significance of Burckhardt’s theological training, Howard,
Religion, 110 ff.
72 On ‘theorists’, Jacob Burckhardt, The Civilization of the Renaissance in Italy (London: Penguin,
2004), 271. On Thucydides and Herodotus and myths, Richard Franklin Sigurdson, Jacob Burckhardt’s
Social and Political Thought (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 2004), 78 ff.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
These were grounds for his conclusion that ‘the people of Europe can maltreat,
but happily not judge one another’, which intimates the clash of irreconcilable
national perspectives discussed just now, and illustrates how a relativistic outlook
on values is itself no obstacle to conflict with those bearing other perspectives.75
Almost simultaneously to Burckhardt, Fustel de Coulanges was working on
The Ancient City (1864), which in a more overtly sociological fashion explored
another Zeitgeist, in the form of the relationship between political institutions
and religion in those ‘foreign countries’, the Greek and Roman city states. With
his focus on the regularities of institutions rather than on variable actions or
‘events’, and in his analysis of the socio-political function of religion, Fustel was to
be one of the major influences on his student, the great sociologist Émile
Durkheim.76 Fustel defined the ‘true object’ of history idealistically as ‘the human
mind: it should aspire to know what this mind has believed, thought and felt in
the different ages of the human race’.77 Other scholars in the nineteenth-century
French historiography of society and culture went further than Burckhardt or
Fustel in their attempts to codify the relationship between longitudinal and latitu-
dinal factors, crosshatching changes over time with differences in national and
73 Daniel Fulda, ‘Historicism as a Cultural Pattern: Practising a Mode of Thought’, Journal of the
Philosophy of History, 4 (2010), 138–53.
74 Burckhardt, Civilization, 271.
75 Ibid.
76 Steven Lukes, Emile Durkheim, his Life and Work: A Historical and Critical Study (Stanford:
Stanford University Press, 1985), 60–4.
77 Fustel, The Ancient City, 76.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
other characteristics. In this project they could draw on romantic and positivistic
influences.
The intellectual hinterland included Germaine de Staël’s On Literature
Considered in its Relations to Social Institutions (1800), which had set itself the
task of examining ‘the influence of religion, morals and laws on literature’,
and conversely ‘the influence of literature on religion, morals and laws’.78
Charting changes in this relationship in what from today’s perspective is a fairly
orthodox series of periodizations from Homer through Christianization and the
Renaissance to her present, she also divided literature in what she called the mod-
ern period—with its particular characteristics including the specific nature of its
consideration of women—according to different national-cultural and regional
tendencies in Europe, and furthermore she factored in political ideologies. Her
imprint, as well as that of Comte, can be detected on Hippolyte Taine’s work on
the psychology of art and the History of English literature in the 1860s. In the
latter Taine ascribed the qualities of literature at any one moment not to the ori
ginality of the individual mind but to the nexus of three different contexts—‘la
race, le milieu et le moment’—whose weights of influence could be calculated.79
Painting with too broad a brush, Taine claimed that Enlightenment thinkers
believed ‘men of every race and century were all but identical: the Greek, the bar-
barian, the Hindoo, the man of the Renaissance, and the man of the eighteenth
century’. ‘They did not know that the moral constitution of a people or an age is as
particular or as distinct as the physical structure of a family of plants or an order
of animals.’80
In German historiography, as in historically influenced German economics,
there was less space for social-scientific or comparative approaches and the polit
ically oriented historicist tradition remained supreme through the later nine-
teenth and early twentieth century. In the generations after Ranke’s period of
pre-eminence, the philosophy of historicism was embodied in Droysen, whose
influential reaction against positivism indicated its growing strength beyond
Germany, in Ranke’s student von Sybel, and Sybel’s editorial successor at the
Historische Zeitschrift, Heinrich von Treitschke (1834–96). Parenthetically, all
three taught Meinecke at points and so it was no surprise when he received the
baton of the journal in the 1890s.
Sybel introduced the Rankean seminar to the University of Munich on his
arrival in 1856, before his anti-Catholicism and pro-Prussianism prompted a
departure from Bavaria, to Bonn. His major works of modern History addressed
78 Germaine de Staël, De la littérature considérée dans ses rapports avec les institutions sociales,
vol. 1, 2nd edition (Paris: de Crapelet, n.d.), 27.
79 Hippolyte Taine, Histoire de la littérature anglaise, 5 vols. (Paris: Hachette, 1863–4), vol. 1, preface,
part V; cf. Taine, The Philosophy of Art (New York: Holt and Williams, 1873), 180–5.
80 Cited in Kenan Malik, The Meaning of Race: Race, History and Culture in Western Society
(New York: New York University Press, 1996), 142–3.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
the French Revolution and The Founding of the German Empire under Wilhelm I
(1889–94), while he bound together his medieval and modern interests with the
short 1862 work The German Nation and the Empire [Kaiserreich], which explored
the relationship between the universalist elements of the Holy Roman Empire,
the polynational character of the Habsburg polity, and the particular story of the
German people.81
Treitschke had been taught by the historian and politician Friedrich Christoph
Dahlmann (1785–1860), agitator of the ‘Schleswig Holstein question’ and author
of Histories of the English and French Revolutions, which had given him a privil
eged position to proselytize for constitutional monarchy as well as Prussian-led
German unification.82 Treitschke’s own major historical work was the History of
Germany in the Nineteenth Century,83 but his philosophy of History may be
inferred from his essays on contemporary politics. He rather personifies the ter-
minal point of the shift in German nationalism (and other nationalisms too) from
early and mid-nineteenth-century liberalism to later nineteenth-century chau-
vinism; from the nationalism of self-determination to the nationalism of imperi-
alist self-assertion; from cosmopolitan nationalism to intolerant ethnocentrism,
meaning in Treitschke’s case anti-Semitism, anti-Catholicism, and anti-Polonism.
The Rankean sense of the state as a moral power remained, but it was coloured by
‘social Darwinism’.
Reactions to Historicism
81 Heinrich von Sybel, Die Begründung des deutschen Reiches durch Wilhelm I, 7 vols. (Munich:
Oldenbourg, 1889–94); von Sybel, Die deutsche Nation und das Kaiserreich (Düsseldorf: Buddeus,
1862).
82 Friedrich Christoph Dahlmann, Geschichte der englischen Revolution (Leipzig: Weidmann,
1844); Dahlmann, Geschichte der französischen Revolution bis auf die Stiftung der Republik (Leipzig:
Weidmann, 1845).
83 Heinrich von Treitschke, Deutsche Geschichte im Neunzehnten Jahrhundert, 5 vols. (Leipzig:
Hirzel, 1878–94).
84 John Emerich Edward Dalberg-Acton, Historical Essays and Studies (London: Macmillan, 1908),
491. See also 352–6, 427 for praise and criticism of Ranke.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
85 Ibid. 362. 86 Ibid. 437. See also 354–5. 87 Ibid. 437.
88 I can take no credit for the counting: see Carlo Ginzburg, The Judge and the Historian (London:
Verso, 1999), 123 n. 10.
89 Acton, Historical Essays and Studies, 436–7, 504–6. Lord Acton, Lectures on Modern History
(London: Fontana, 1960), 38: ‘I exhort you never to debase the moral currency or lower the standard
of rectitude, but to try others by the final maxim that governs your own lives, and to suffer no man
and no cause to escape the undying penalty which history has the power to inflict on wrong.’
90 Tacitus, Annals, 4.33. 91 Ibid. 3.65.
92 Lord Acton, Lectures on the French Revolution (London: Macmillan, 1920), 92. See also Acton,
Lectures on Modern History, 30: ‘It is by solidity of criticism more than by the plenitude of erudition,
that the study of history strengthens, and straightens, and extends the mind.’
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
without their discernment, that society might fall into the error of worshipping
false idols who were successful at the cost of moral rectitude.93
The author of Thus Spake Zarathustra, Friedrich Nietzsche (1844–1900), makes
a curious bedfellow for Acton, but this is so only up to a point. After all, the ascent
of Hegelian immanent reason was one target of both and Christian teleology
another. Acton’s point about holding power to account was also close to
Nietzsche’s belief that Rankean anti-Hegelianism, while it could lead to respect
for all forms of life rather than just the final one, might also lead to automatic self-
validation of any present, a sort of self-immunization against the criticism of pos-
terity. Both men advocated taking the responsibility implied in judgement, and
both were aware of the hold of the past on the present, and thus of the historian’s
social influence. Nietzsche’s penchant for talking about History may obscure the
fact that his is more a tale of the impact of historical thought on philosophy than
vice versa.
Nietzsche’s interest in what historical thinking could fruitfully instil, and when
it was a burden from which humans needed to be liberated in order to flourish,
led him to describe different forms of History and prescribe particular combin
ations of these. The emergence of the state of Germany stimulated one of his
‘untimely meditations’, entitled ‘On the Uses and Disadvantages of History for
Life’ (1874), which is his most cited pronouncement on History.94 It was shaped
in the particular context of his reaction against the public (ab)uses of History in
the immediate, triumphalist aftermath of war-driven unification. Those reserva-
tions were shared by Gervinus, and in fact when representing Nietzsche’s attitudes
to History, it is important to appreciate how much his thinking at the time of this
piece was characterized by an animus to a general sub-Hegelian, propaganda-
fuelled sense of riding history’s wave from glory unto glory. Nietzsche also feared
an overly historical disposition among moderns whose consciousness could no
longer integrate past and present in a beneficial way, who wished to live in the
present alone but could not find the wherewithal to forget or otherwise discard
the past: in short, he feared, in Goethe’s words, that ‘even the best history always
has something corpse-like, the smell of a tomb’.95 He argued for a delimitation of
History’s purview, and at the same time stipulated the directions it might take.
The past could be used for inspiration, focusing specifically on ‘monumental’
History that dwelled on moments of past significance as a way of making use of
may shape ‘his’ own character in his present, though that cannot be achieved by
mere fiat. To enable the relative freedom of choice by which humans, or at least
the best among them, could fulfil their creative potential, the critical work of
liberation was necessary vis-à-vis inherited frameworks of thought and meaning,
especially morality. Nietzsche concerned himself with ‘the question of what origin
our terms good and evil actually have’, with ‘the descent of our moral
prejudices’.99
In rudimentary terms some of the argument of the Genealogy of Morality can
be compared to what is today known as the ‘just world fallacy’. The just world
belief, that the world is basically fair—i.e. good—in its allocation of outcomes is
popular in the same measure that arbitrariness is unpalatable. It promises to ren-
der the world potentially controllable given the ‘right’ behaviour, and thus appeals
to a desire for cognitive mastery. One consequence of the idea of personal con-
trollability is to rationalize inequalities, without questioning the way the world is
and how it might be altered, by proposing that the less well situated (rather than,
say, structured inequalities) are to blame for their situation. That belief is not just
entertained by the powerful or well-to-do, since even for the victims of misfor-
tune, there is a certain reassurance of orderliness in the idea that remediable
behaviour brought about their situation. It has also been the province of a range
of religions to inculcate a sense of sin or imperfection twinned with the promise
of next-life improvement consequent on a certain mode of behaviour in this
world, thus implying ultimate controllability beyond death, alongside quietism in
this life. Indeed Nietzsche ties the development of a particular concept of moral-
ity as meek, ascetic self-denial to the Judeo-Christian tradition, especially in light
of the historical weakness of Jews and early Christianity. The Judeo-Christian
values which occidental civilization claims as its own were, he believes, defined
against the self-assertive strength and nobility of Rome, and as such were shaped
by that repressed envy and hatred which internalizes itself under the name ‘con-
science’. Nietzsche’s is a story of group psychology as a particular human culture
cooks up something that it calls morality, then persuades itself that this is the only
true morality, while forgetting its contingent origins and development and tra-
ducing alternative value systems. Occidentals forgot the violence involved in
establishing rules of law, the violence involved in domesticating human beings to
observe a set of precepts, and the fact that punishment only gradually came to
mean something more ‘profound’ than vengeance. They forgot that guilt was
invented where once the concept of debt (Schuld) alone had existed, even as they
conceived themselves beholden—indebted—to god. All this was concealed
beneath a glorious origin story, but was nonetheless carried forward within the
structure of the whole system of belief and value. Now despite the book’s subtitle,
it was not just a polemic: Nietzsche believed that the Judeo-Christian ‘slave revolt’
in morality made humans more interesting since it somehow fostered their sub-
jectivity and it was in some ways to be respected since it gave otherwise weak
creatures power over physically stronger creatures. As at once a measure of
humans and a limit on them, however, Nietzsche found this morality unsatisfac-
tory, and he was especially concerned to ask what humans would do in an age in
which religious faith, which was fundamental to the whole moral framework, was
in question.
While Nietzsche used a species of historicization as a tool of existential liber
ation he also tried to work through the possible problems of such historicization.
He feared its capacity, if followed through to one of its possible relativistic conclu-
sions, to replace faith in the transcendent, or in a given historical ‘character’, with
faith in nothingness, i.e. with nihilism, which was just as problematic. Moreover,
whatever his thoroughly immodest claim that there are no eternal facts or abso-
lute truths, there was still enough of a conventional, dare one say it Enlightenment,
philosopher in Nietzsche for him to resist all of the implications of contextualist
historicization—indeed this was implicit in his agenda of emancipation from
established precepts, moral and otherwise, and embracing new values. In 1888 he
wrote that the philosopher’s duty was to try to ‘overcome his age in himself, to
become timeless’, by way of trying to establish some capacity to assess one’s times
as if from beyond them.100 Earlier, in ‘On the Uses and Disadvantages of History
for Life’ he talked of the suprahistorical (überhistorisch) powers of art (and inter-
estingly of religion), with the implication that some residue remained in great art
once one had exhaustively historicized all that could be historicized in it. ‘I call
“suprahistorical” the powers which lead the eye away from becoming towards
that which bestows on existence the character of the eternal and stable.’101 Some
of his historical heroes and their deeds have a timeless quality too, while he
appears to have seen a generally desirable disposition in the Homeric Greeks. He
had a certain philosophy of history of his own—not a stadial or teleological one,
but one in which civilizational tendencies that were already present in ancient
Greece circulated across time in different combinations and with different expres-
sions.102 All this is Nietzsche’s structural alternative to matters like the ‘universal’
or the highest ‘one’ that Neoplatonism and Rankean historicism had invoked.
For a more systematic attempt to work through the implications of variety, his-
toricity, and flux for thought about ‘the human condition’, we need to turn to the
100 Daniel Conway, Nietzsche and the Political (London: Routledge, 1997), 63–4. The quotation is
from Nietzsche’s Der Fall Wagner (1888).
101 Nietzsche, ‘Uses and Disadvantages’, 120.
102 Otto Gerhard Oexle, Geschichtswissenschaft im Zeichen des Historismus (Göttingen:
Vandenhoeck und Ruprecht, 1996), ch. 3; F. R. Ankersmit, ‘The Ethics of History: From the Double
Binds of (Moral) Meaning to Experience’, History and Theory, 43:4 (2004), 84–102, here 102; Katrin
Meyer, Ästhetik der Historie: Friedrich Nietzsches ‘Vom Nutzen und Nachteil der Historie für das Leben’
(Würzburg: Königshausen und Neumann, 1998), 131–3.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
thought of yet another erstwhile theology student, and son of a Lutheran pastor,
Wilhelm Dilthey (1833–1911). For Dilthey, when one was trying to understand
oneself, Cartesian introspection or Kantian regressive analysis towards the apriori
categories concealed the historical conditions of one’s existence. All being was
being in time (Zeitlichkeit), which also meant being-in-relation-to a range of
external influences present and past. At the same time, he did not accept that
these influences were determinant. They shaped the pre-conscious hypotheses
that are necessary for any initial encroachment on an infinitely complex reality,
but could be reduced in significance by the products of induction from empirical
study. In other words, an investigator is culturally and temporally situated, but is
not inevitably constrained to reproduce her own cultural thoughtworld or, when
acting as an historian, to project that thoughtworld onto the historical-cultural
others that she studied.103
Dilthey owed some conceptual debts to Droysen’s emphasis on understanding
one’s own historicity and his elaboration of the way in which hermeneutic tech-
niques could be expanded from the reading of texts to the contemplation of wider
human worlds, including the relationship of the historian to his or her own con-
texts. For Dilthey, however, the major flaws of historicism à la Droysen were its
overly subjective elements and its abiding emphasis on uniqueness that prohib-
ited systematic comparative study, and thereby cut historicists off from pasts that
were not the pasts of ‘their own’, their monad. One key way of thinking outwards
and comparatively was through contemplating some of the shared ways in which
life was expressed and structured. Just as in everyday life the individual gains a
sense of self from interaction with others around her, so, at a higher level of reflec-
tion, the historical thinker learns to appreciate the particular character of her own
niche in space-time by communing with other times. Past mental worlds could be
inferred from the hermeneutic interpretation of the material products or ‘objecti-
fications’—art, architecture, but especially literary products—created by minds
from those ages. Where Hegel focused on institutions as reason-bearers, Dilthey
was concerned with all creative manifestations of human interaction with the
natural world as expressive of human value. Moreover, he was as concerned with
103 My account of Dilthey in this and the following two paragraphs is distilled, doubtless to the
dissatisfaction of any given one of them, from the insights of: Rudolf A. Makkreel, ‘The Productive
Force of History and Dilthey’s Formation of the Historical World’, Revue internationale de philosophie,
226 (2003/4), 495–508 and more generally Rudolf A. Makkreel, Dilthey: Philosopher of the Human
Sciences (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1992); Eric S. Nelson, ‘Empiricism, Facticity, and the
Immanence of Life in Dilthey’, Pli: Warwick Journal of Philosophy, 18 (2007), 108–28; Hajo Holborn,
‘Wilhelm Dilthey and the Critique of Historical Reason’, Journal of the History of Ideas, 11:1 (1950),
93–118; Thomas Teo, ‘Karl Marx and Wilhelm Dilthey on the Socio-Historical Conceptualization of
the Mind’, in C. Green, M. Shore, and T. Teo (eds.). The Transformation of Psychology: Influences of
19th-Century Philosophy, Technology and Natural Science (Washington, DC: APA, 2001), 195–218;
Jacob Owensby, Dilthey and the Narrative of History (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1994); Reinhold
Niebuhr, Faith and History: A Comparison of Christian and Modern Views of History (New York:
Charles Scribner’s Sons, 1949), 18–20.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
the literally individual mind as with what Hegel would have called the objective,
or social-institutional mind. Dilthey’s individuals were constituted at the meeting
points of various social, cultural, economic, and political institutions and influ-
ences. So while agreeing with Marx that the division of labour differentiated
people in one way, Dilthey believed many other inputs also needed to be considered.
Just as importantly, individuals did not give the entirety of themselves to their
various societal roles, so those roles in turn did not exhaust the content of their
individuality. It might be impossible for the historian to penetrate to that excess
of absolute individuality once relational, contextual thought had been exhausted,
but from working ‘inwards’ from general cultural patterns that were evident even
in the most original thinkers, down through the mid-range institutional influ-
ences, one was nonetheless establishing a logic of individuation. Hermeneutic
understanding was realized when one recognized something of the self in the
historical or cultural ‘other’. This was History as Communion, not in a religious or
nationalist sense, but in the broadest humanist sense.
One could use the hermeneutic understanding of the intersection of different
contexts to think in a way that was both historical and existential. The enquiring
subject, aware of her own structured existence in time, transcends some of the
given-ness of the present by recalling the choices and changes that had led to the
present. Some of these choices were hers, which illustrate her capacity to influ-
ence the future in new ways; some were not hers, which illustrates the influence of
larger conceptual and situational structures. At the same time the enquirer
expanded her own horizons, as she conceived of herself within ever-larger and
more inclusive historical contexts up to the point of a universal, shared
humanity.
Dilthey’s thought seemed at the time to fall between a number of stools. The
philosopher Martin Heidegger (1889–1976), whose concept of historicity, of
being in time-and-culture—his most famous work was Sein und Zeit, Being and
Time (1927)—shows clear commonality of interest with Dilthey, nonetheless
criticized him for being too close to the Cartesian–Kantian aspiration to ascend
to some point outside history.104 Dilthey scarcely satisfied those Kantians who
still thought in terms of the transcendental, self-authoring subject. And he was
considered methodologically problematic and too relativistic by Ernst Troeltsch
(1865–1923), who wrote of the ‘crisis of historicism’ and was itself one of its prod-
ucts as he struggled to reconcile his historian’s belief in the historical develop-
ment of competing religions and sects with his theologian’s reluctance to accept
the relativity of Christian truth.105
Whether the crisis of historicism is a good name for one of the many ‘crises’ in
this period depends on what we take the subject of the crisis of historicism to be.
The crisis was one in which historicism suffered, if by historicism one means the
hegemony of the German critical historical school, and the agendas of some of its
key members, wherein the past was a source of meaning and an assurance of a
certain existential coherence. Abetted by growing intra-societal tensions, the
sense of mutability across time and place became increasingly detached from
speculative philosophies of the historical process, or at least progressive ones, and
any sense of the ontological security that some had found in the Volksgeist and
others in religion. But in the broader sense of the abidingly influential particular-
istic historical outlook that this book calls neo-historicism, the crisis—dating
approximately from the 1870s through the interwar period—was one to which
historical thought contributed, even though historians were not prominent in
working through its philosophical ramifications. The crisis gained its purchase
from the late nineteenth century because of the wider ‘crisis of liberalism’ and
theology with which it intersected, plus associated material and political
change.106 The primary protagonists of the crisis were increasingly philosophers,
Jewish and Christian theologians (like Troeltsch), and some nationalists, because
these were the people primarily concerned with the justification of absolute,
metaphysical, originary, or essentialist positions.107 This is not to say that nation-
alism itself dwindled during this period—quite the opposite, it reached an aggres-
sive crescendo in which there was an obsession with internal loyalty and unity in
the face of outside forces.
Classical historicism of the Rankean sort was threatened by fractures within
the Volk, or national community, and/or the state. In the later nineteenth century,
fears of degeneration and the destruction of traditional values multiplied amid
population growth, industrialization and urbanization, the rise of the organized
left, and demands for new forms of representative politics. The 1870s, with its
stock market shock, the beginnings of repeated rural depression, and the ‘second
industrial revolution’, instituted what the Marxist historian Giovanni Arrighi later
dubbed the long twentieth century, which superseded the era of British world
106 On the importance of the collapse of liberal Protestant thought in stimulating new reflection at
this time, see A. James Reimer, Paul Tillich: Theologian of Nature, Culture and Politics (Münster: LIT,
2004), 162. On the many tributaries and differing manifestations of the ‘crisis of historicism’, see
Herman Paul, ‘Religion and the Crisis of Historicism: Protestant and Catholic Perspectives’, Journal of
the Philosophy of History, 4 (2010) 172–94. On the ‘crisis of historicism’ and the success of professional
historianship: Beiser, German Historicist Tradition, 24–6.
107 Paul, ‘Religion and the Crisis of Historicism’; David N. Myers, Resisting History: Historicism and
its Discontents in German-Jewish Thought (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2003); Troeltsch,
Der Historismus. Herman Paul, ‘A Collapse of Trust: Reconceptualizing the Crisis of Historicism’,
Journal of the Philosophy of History, 2 (2008), 63–82, notes the important distinction between doubts
about universal or objective value and doubts about being able to justify such value in the light of the
collapse of historical certainties in this period. He is surely right that the latter tendency was more
prevalent.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
108 Arnold Toynbee, A Study of History, abridgement of vols. I–VI by Robert Somervell (Oxford:
Oxford University Press 1946), 39.
109 Coleman, Ancient and Medieval Memories, 593.
110 Paul, ‘A Collapse of Trust’, 79–80. The most relevant of Lamprecht’s works in this connection is
his Deutsche Geschichte, 12 vols. (Berlin: Gaertner, 1891–1909), but see also his earlier Deutsches
Wirtschaftsleben im Mittelalter, 4 vols. (Leipzig: Dürr, 1885–6).
111 Patrick Wormald, Legal Culture in the Early Medieval West (London: Hambledon, 1999), 58–60.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
the First World War, Lord Bryce recorded the expansion in the recent scope of
enquiry in historical studies, as broadly conceived.
We have now come to regard history as a record of every form of human effort
and achievement, concerned not any more definitely with political events and
institutions than with all the other factors that have moulded man and all the
other expressions his creative activity has found . . . [T]he historian, who in the
days of Thucydides needed to look no further than to Susa on the east and
Carthage on the west, must now extend his vision to take in the whole earth.112
In much of Europe, and to an extent even in Germany itself, the 1880s saw an
anti-historical ‘synchronic turn’ in the study of linguistics and languages, though
historicism veritably flourished in the area of German cultural studies. Historically
influenced philosophy in Germany was somewhat moderated by the temporary
114 Edward Sidelsky, Ernst Cassirer (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2008), 167–8; Peter
Uwe Hohendahl, ‘The Crisis of Neo-Kantianism and the Reassessment of Kant after World War
I’, Philosophical Forum, 41:1–2 (2010), 17–39; Wotaru Koyama, ‘The Rise of Pragmatics: A
Historiographic Overview’, in Wolfram Bublitz and Neal R. Norrick (eds.), Foundations of Pragmatics
(Berlin: de Gruyter, 2011), 139–66, here 149 ff. On cultural studies, Otto Gerhard Oexle (ed.), Krise
des Historismus— Krise der Wirklichkeit (Gottingen: Max-Planck-Instituts für Geschichte, 2007).
115 Max Weber, ‘Science as a Vocation’, in Max Weber: Essays in Sociology, ed. H. H. Gerth and
C. Wright Mills (New York: Oxford University Press, 1946), 129–56, here 52.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
between the roles of the human scientist on one hand and the politician or citizen
on the other hand.
Weber was influenced by Nietzsche on the end of religious certainty as a guar-
antor of values,116 and was himself a theorist of modernization, with its implica-
tions of fracture and flux. He saw that meanings and values were made rather
than located in the historical record or the objective patterns of the natural world:
‘The fate of a cultural epoch that has eaten of the tree of knowledge is that it must
know that we cannot learn the meaning of the world from the results of its ana
lysis, however perfect that analysis may be, but must instead be in a position to
create this meaning for itself.’ Such a recognition entailed acknowledgement of
different, potentially competing worldviews and prescriptions, with no higher
criteria for deciding between them based on claims about the nature of reality.117
In the present, human scientists could advise on the implications of this or that
social policy, just as the teacher could advise the student, but it was still for the
political leader to decide the policy.118 It followed that insofar as social scientists
advised on the implementation of policy, they should act in neutral terms towards
that policy, irrespective of who the winners were and who the losers—while in
full awareness that there would be winners and losers, in the sense of people
whose interests and values were better or worse served by this or that
dispensation.
Value-judgements might well be involved in one’s choice of an object of study
but the investigator’s professional ethic of responsibility—as opposed to the poli-
tician’s ethic of conviction as to the choice of governing values—was expressed
through refraining from evaluation of this subject matter once it had been
chosen.119 Investigators were to remain descriptive of value-significance, not pre-
scriptive of how that significant value should itself be evaluated. Whether per-
taining to study of the present or the past, Weber observed the logical distinction
between the investigator’s subjective evaluation of social or historical facts and
the scholarly task of relating those facts to values. As one of his contemporaries
put it, ‘Valuations must always involve praise or blame. To refer to values is to do
neither.’120 For Weber, ‘the investigator and teacher should hold as uncondition-
ally separate the establishment of empirical facts (including what he establishes
as the “value-oriented” conduct of the empirical individuals whom he is
116 On the influence of Nietzsche, Horst Baier, ‘Die Gesellschaft—ein langer Schatten des toten
Gottes’, Nietzsche-Studien: Internationales Jahrbuch für die Nietzsche Forschung, 10–11 (1981–2), 6–33.
117 Max Weber, ‘Die “Objektivität” sozialwissenschaftlicher und sozialpolitischer Erkenntnis’,
Archiv für Sozialwissenschaft und Sozialpolitik, 19:1 (1904), 22–87, here 30. Emphasis added.
118 Weber‚ ‘Science as a Vocation’, 151–2.
119 On the ethic of responsibility versus the ethic of conviction (Gesinnungsethik), Weber, ‘Science
as a Vocation’ should be read against Max Weber, ‘Politics as a Vocation’, in Max Weber: Essays in
Sociology, ed. and trans. Gerth and Mills, 77–128.
120 The contemporary was the neo-Kantian Heinrich Rickert, cited in Makkreel, Dilthey:
Philosopher of the Human Sciences, 41.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
121 Max Weber, ‘Der Sinn der “Wertfreiheit” der soziologischen und ökonomischen Wissenschaften’,
in Max Weber: Gesammelte Aufsätze zur Wissenschaftslehre. Hrsg. von Johannes Winckelmann. 6.,
erneut durchgesehene Auflage, (Tübingen: Mohr /Siebeck, 1985), 489–540, here 499.
122 Two journal essays—both in the Archiv fur Sozialwissenschaft und Sozialpolitik, 20:1 (1904),
1–54 and 21:1 (1905), 1–110—were grouped together under the problematizing title in Max Weber,
Gesammelte Aufsätze zur Religionssoziologie, vol. 1 (Tübingen: Mohr, 1920), 17–206.
123 Beiser, German Historicist Tradition, ch. 13.
124 Hardtwig, ‘Geschichtsreligion’, 17–20, 32.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
125 On social science, neutrality, objectivity, and value judgements, see John Lewis, Max Weber and
Value-Free Sociology (London: Lawrence and Wishart, 1975); Colin Loader, The Intellectual
Development of Karl Mannheim (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985), 98–100; Jay A. Ciaffa,
Max Weber and the Problems of Value-Free Social Science (Cranbury, NJ: Associated University
Presses, 1998), 63 ff.
126 The social sciences figure in the full titles of Weber, ‘Die “Objektivität” ’ and Weber, ‘Der Sinn
der “Wertfreiheit” ’; note also that Weber began ‘Science as a Vocation’ (p. 129) by referring to himself
as a ‘political economist’. For dissent from Weber’s arguments about value neutrality in History, see
Donald Bloxham, History and Morality (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2020).
127 The concluding pages of the present book address the difficulties historians face in removing all
intimations of value judgement, and they question the desirability of such a divestment (pp. 353–7).
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
contents. Thus Thierry, Carlyle, and Michelet were read long after their death,
despite having been interpretatively superseded. Conversely, the public would
read on the natural sciences whatever the author’s style, since there the content
was what mattered.128 This does not mean that Langlois and Seignobos were
(social) scientific positivists in the search for social laws: they were not, and
indeed the political paradigm for historiography that they adopted was one of
the objects of critique and modification in the establishment of the journal
Revue de synthèse historique (1900) and in the work of Lamprecht’s friend Henri
Pirenne (1862–1935). What Langlois and Seignobos had in mind was a particular,
ascetic approach to research which eschewed speculation and focused on the
empirically verifiable.
Well before this point romantic style and literary quality had been associated
with rhetoric in the sense of illegitimate persuasion, as we know, but there were
now additional political reasons for distancing oneself from the work of a Thierry.
Whatever the specifics of his own role as cheerleader of the July Monarchy,
Thierry’s anti-clerical, pro-revolutionary stance, first established in print in the
teeth of the Restoration regime, drew the intellectual focus towards class conflict.
With the downfall of the Second Empire in 1870, then further defeats at Prussian
hands, and the advent and crushing of the Paris Commune in early 1871, the
social and ideological divisions that had never disappeared in French society
gained the significance that, beyond constituting an argument about France’s path
internally, they were a source of weakness in its external relations. French frag-
mentation contrasted with Prussian, now German, unity, and catalysed the sort of
reappraisal of French institutions that Napoleonic conquest had prompted in
other states at the beginning of the century.
The educational system in general, and universities in particular, were
reformed, and within the universities historical research and teaching was profes-
sionalized decades after similar developments in various German states. German
historiography was seen as one of the keys to German unity of historical sense
and present purpose, even as Germanophobia was entrenched in so much French
political discourse.129 In La Monarchie franque (1888) Fustel reflected on the
motto of the Monumenta Germaniae Historica, i.e. ‘the love of the fatherland gives
spirit’. ‘The motto is beautiful’, he wrote, ‘but it is perhaps not appropriate for sci-
ence’, before going on to observe how in German historical scholarship of the
previous fifty years historical theory and patriotism had been in striking
128 Charles-Victor Langlois and Charles Seignobos, Introduction aux études historiques, ed. Pierre
Palpant (electronic edition, 2005 [orig 1898]), 167–8: http://classiques.uqac.ca/classiques/langlois_
charles_victor/intro_etudes_historiques/seignobos_etudhisto.pdf See also Weber, ‘Science as a
Vocation’, 137–8.
129 Isabel DiVanna, Reconstructing the Middle Ages: Gaston Paris and the Development of
Nineteenth-Century Medievalism (Newcastle: Cambridge Scholars Press, 2008).
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
130 N. D. Fustel de Coulanges, Histoire des institutions politiques de l’ancienne France, vol. III:
La Monarchie Franque (Paris: Hachette, 1905 [orig. 1888]), 31.
131 N. D. Fustel de Coulanges, ‘L’Organisation de la Justice dans l’antiquité et les temps modernes’,
Revue des Deux Mondes, 94 (July 1871), 536–56, here 538.
132 N. D. Fustel de Coulanges, Histoire des institutions politiques de l’ancienne France, 6 vols. (Paris:
Hachette, 1874–92); Augustin Thierry, Récits des temps mérovingiens précédés de Considérations sur
l’histoire de France, 2 vols. (Paris: Tessier, 1840).
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
by revealing her historical traditions and, at the same time, the transformations
these traditions have undergone’.133
In Britain politics was somewhat less pressured but some of the foregoing
themes are recognizable. In his 1903 inaugural as Regius Professor of History at
Cambridge, J. B. Bury reinforced the notion that History was not a branch of lit-
erature and should also disavow ‘her old associates, moral philosophy and
rhetoric’.134 The prefatory note to the first issue of the English Historical Review in
1886 laid out the journal’s philosophy in order to ‘avoid the suspicion of partisan-
ship in such political or ecclesiastical questions as are still burning’. It is a bit of a
hodge-podge:
Some topics it will be safer to eschew altogether. In others fairness may be shown
by allowing both sides an equal hearing. But our main reliance will be on the
scientific spirit which we shall expect from contributors likely to address us. An
article on the character and career of Sir Robert Peel will be welcome, so long as
it does not advocate or deprecate the policy of protective tariffs; and President
Andrew Jackson may properly be praised or blamed if the writer’s purpose be
neither to assail nor to recommend, with President Cleveland in his eye, the sys-
tem of party appointments to office. Recognizing the value of the light which
history may shed on practical problems, we shall not hesitate to let that light be
reflected from our pages, whenever we can be sure that it is dry light, free from
any tinge of partisanship.135
133 Text of preface trans. and repr. in Stern (ed.), The Varieties of History, 172–4, with quotes from
173–4. Stern’s introductory remarks on the journal at p. 171.
134 Doris S. Goldstein, ‘J. B. Bury’s Philosophy of History: A Reappraisal’, The American Historical
Review, 82:4 (1977), 896–919, here 897.
135 Preface repr. in Stern (ed.), The Varieties of History, 176.
136 Novick, That Noble Dream, chs. 2–4.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
137 Dumas quoted in René Vallery-Radot, The Life of Pasteur (London: Constable, 1928), 251.
138 Acton quoted in Breisach, Historiography, 284.
139 Herbert Butterfield, Christianity, Diplomacy and War (London: Epworth, 1953), 4. On foot-
notes, Niall Ferguson, The Pity of War (New York: Basic Books, 1999), 233.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
‘Progressive’ History
In the interwar years the American historian Charles Beard (1874–1948) drew
out some of the self-deceptions of the neutralists, including those among his
compatriots. He noted that historians were apt to be ‘disturbed, like their fellow
citizens, by crises and revolutions occurring in the world about them’, and drew
explicitly on the work of the Italian philosopher historian Benedetto Croce, the
sociologist Karl Mannheim, and the theologian and author of The Crisis of
Historicism (1932), Karl Heussi, in observing that ‘so-called neutral or scientific
history reached a crisis in its thought before the twentieth century had advanced
far on the way’. These crises affected different countries in different ways, largely
dictated by their relationship to the course of the First World War and the inter-
war order. At the time of speaking, the outset of the New Deal period in 1933,
Beard was optimistic enough to foresee history’s ‘forward’ movement to a ‘collect
ivist democracy’.140
Beard was one of the foremost members of the ‘Progressive’ American his
torical movement, alongside Robinson, Carl Becker, and Mary Beard. Becker was
waxing Weberian when he averred that the historian’s own concept determines
the choice of facts, not vice versa, and observed the difficulty of distinguishing
‘facts’ from ‘theories’.141 Beard: ‘no historian can describe the past as it actually
was’ (a dig at a vision of Ranke) and ‘every historian’s work—that is, his selection
of facts, his emphasis, his omissions, his organization, and his methods of presen-
tation—bears a relation to his own personality and to the age and circumstances
in which he lives’. Despite the notoriety of his remarks about the historian’s situat-
edness, the reformist-socialist Beard stressed that he was only repeating the
received wisdom of ‘a century or more that each historian who writes history is a
product of his age, and that his work reflects the spirit of the times, of a nation,
race, group, class, or section’. It is just that such opinions had not tended to receive
much of an airing in previous presidential addresses to the American Historical
Association, many of whose members were still in thrall to the ‘scientific’ Ranke.
As it happens, Beard approved of the ‘scientific method’, seeing in it, in the fateful
year of Hitler’s ascent but from a safe distance, ‘the chief safeguard against the
tyranny of authority, bureaucracy, and brute power’—but he felt in rather
Nietzschean fashion that ‘science’, while a good servant, was a poor master.142
Some of his own historical investigations look more like orthodox leftist critiques
based on an orthodox process of inference from evidence, so we could take his
views on perspectivalism as descriptive rather than necessarily prescriptive of a
140 Charles A. Beard, ‘Written History as an Act of Faith’, American Historical Review, 39:2 (1934),
219–31, here 221, 228. See also Karl Heussi, Die Krisis des Historismus (Tübingen: Mohr, 1932).
141 Carl Lotus Becker, Detachment and the Writing of History (Ithaca: Cornell University Press,
1958), 24, 10–11.
142 Beard, ‘Written History’, 227.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
143 Charles A. Beard, An Economic Interpretation of the Constitution of the United States (New York:
The Free Press, 1965 [orig. 1913]), 15–16.
144 Villemaire, E. A. Burtt, 15–19.
145 Van Wyck Brooks, ‘On Creating a Usable Past’, The Dial, 64:7 (11 April 1918), 337–41, here
338–9.
146 Van Wyck Brooks, The Wine of the Puritans (London: Sisley’s, 1908), 138.
147 Villemaire, E. A. Burtt, 15–19. 148 Ibid. 18–19, quoting Harvey Wish.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
The interwar atmosphere was altogether more extreme in Germany, the country
whose intellectuals had helped set the American ‘new historians’’ thoughts in
train and whose cultural crisis was aggravated by the economic crises of the era.
Shortly after Brooks’s essay appeared, and only a year after Weber had written
along similar lines about the creation rather than the location of meaning, the
German-Jewish pacifist Theodor Lessing published his once-censored Geschichte
als Sinngebung des Sinnlosen. The title translates as ‘History as the conferral of
meaning on the meaningless’ and is a characterization of the discipline that
became one of Hayden White’s clarion calls about half a century later.149 Lessing’s
work dissected self-serving dealings with the past, especially teleological
readings.
It was overshadowed within a year by the best-selling work of philosophy of
History in the twentieth century: Oswald Spengler’s two-volume Der Untergang
des Abendlandes, The Decline of the Occident, which fused the portentous tone of
the medieval theologians of history with the assumptions of epistemic and cul-
tural relativism. Like Toynbee’s later twelve-volume A Study of History (1934–61),
Spengler’s work become something of a case study in the sort of cherry-picking
historians ought not to engage in. This should not obscure its immense popular-
ity at the time. While it had been substantially completed before the war, giving it
a prophetic character, it appeared between 1918 and 1923, thus chronologically
bracketing Troeltsch’s Der Historismus und seine Probleme (1922). Many among
Spengler’s German audience read Untergang as ‘downfall’ or collapse, and inferred
from the book a pessimism that Spengler himself purported not to share. Yet the
work had broader implications than for German nationalists and anti-democrats.
It was a species of monadology modified for a godless moment, decentring the
occidental experience and removing any fixed point of reference beyond the lives
of peoples. Spengler regarded a unilinear ancient–medieval–modern develop-
mental conception of History as analogous to the discredited Ptolemaic, earth-
centred view of the physical universe. He compared himself to Copernicus as a
revolutionizer of thought and perspective, again illustrating the cultural signifi-
cance of revolutionary scientific thinking in that era.
149 Theodor Lessing, Geschichte als Sinngebung des Sinnlosen (Munich: Beck, 1919).
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
For Spengler, cultures were not linked in some developmental chain; they
enjoyed their own isolated and apparently predetermined patterns of birth, life,
and death. Where Toynbee contrived to reduce the ‘major civilizations’ of the past
and present world to 21–23 in number, and attributed monadic qualities to them,
he, like Troeltsch, denied that such entities were windowless monads, or
Ganzheiten, self-enclosed wholes.150 Spengler, whose ‘high’ or ‘mature’ world-
historical cultures numbered precisely eight, leaned more towards Leibniz in that
insofar as his Ganzeiten came into contact with each other, they only left superfi-
cial impressions, one never influencing the other’s essence. Spengler sought to
illustrate the contention of radical difference with an example from the most
logical of disciplines: for the ancient Greeks, mathematics was about magnitude;
for modern Europeans living with the insights of Euclidean geometry, mathemat-
ics was a matter of function. Thus, while a modern German might be able to learn
the ancient Greek word for ‘mathematics’, she would not understand the same
thing by it as the ancient Greeks did—the concepts were incommensurable, and the
idea of incommensurability hangs over Spengler’s book in tandem with that of
relativism, though he only occasionally used the term itself.151 Common to most
of ‘incommensurability’s’ definitions is the absence of a common denominator or
external standard of measurement, which associates the concept with relativism.
There is no set of higher co-ordinates on which, say, different ethical values or
mathematical precepts can be plotted, probably because their functions within
their respective systems are just different. For Spengler, a culture’s essence lay in
its relationship with its environment, and, in the absence of any aperspectival
notification of the relationship, discerning this relationship was a matter of the
historian’s subjective judgement. The historian should not be a moralist and, in
her striving for understanding at the level of essence, she should not forget that
she was an aesthete more than a scientist. Spengler’s work was admired by some
of Dilthey’s followers and the first volume of Untergang was awarded a prize by
the Nietzsche archive.152
If the collapse of the ‘Third Reich’ sounded the death-knell for classical his
toricism as a national German approach to History, the statist and high political
focus had been influentially challenged in the interwar period from further to the
right. The catastrophe of the First World War fed competing waves of German
nihilism and cultural despair, dialectical materialism, and aggressive organicist
nationalism that broke in the intellectual ferment of the Weimar Republic.
150 Toynbee’s position in Michael Palencia-Roth, ‘On Giants’ Shoulders: The 1961 Salzburg Meeting
of the ISCSC’, Comparative Civilizations Review (Spring 2010), 142–58. Troeltsch, Der Historismus, 987.
151 Spengler, Der Untergang des Abendlandes (Munich: Beck, 1998), 87 ff. on Euclid and the
‘inkommensurable’.
152 Eugene F. Miller, ‘Positivism, Historicism, and Political Inquiry’, American Political Science
Review, 66:3 (1972), 796–817, here 799 n. 9. William Dray, Perspectives on History (London: Routledge
and Kegan Paul, 1980), part 3, has influenced my discussion here.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
A range of philosophies took concepts like Volksgeist and rebirth and, like Martin
Heidegger, applied them in highly political ways ‘appropriate’ to Germany’s situ
ation during and after the conflict.153 Germany’s territorial diminution in the
Versailles peace treaty, and this so soon after the vast eastward expansionist
agenda set forth in the March 1918 treaty of Brest-Litovsk, highlighted the misfit
between the boundaries of the state and of the Germanic people, or Volk. As had
been the case in the historiography of other peoples before they had gained state-
hood, or in Chalkokondyles’ case after the state had been lost, the historical focus
shifted directly to the ethnos, as opposed to the political entity that housed it. This
emphasis on the Volk was also thoroughly characteristic of Nazism, so practi
tioners of the new Volksgeschichte, like Werner Conze (1910–86) and Theodor
Schieder (1908–84), and of the related Landesgeschichte, like Otto Brunner
(1898–1982), found an especially conducive political environment after 1933. If
not necessarily outright Nazis, such historians were generally of the hard con-
servative right, whose agenda of territorial revisionism, ethno-nationalism, and
anti-socialism dovetailed with Nazism in many respects. The Ostforschung of the
Volks-historians, including work on ‘lost territories’, ethnic Germans in eastern
Europe, and the legitimacy of German empire over ‘inferior’ peoples, provided
intellectual sustenance for Hitler’s imperialism, and indeed some of these scholars
acted as direct advisers to the Nazis.154
As to historicists in the older vein, Germany’s experience in both world wars
and under Nazism even caused Meinecke to recant his faith in the moral primacy
of the nation-state. He now criticized the idealization of power that had drawn
German away from the ideals of Goethe to those—allegedly—of Machiavelli. He
defected from Ranke to Burckhardt. Meinecke was followed in his disenchant-
ment with statist moral-legal positivism by a number of colleagues, especially
after Nazi Germany’s decisive defeat at Stalingrad at the turn of 1942–3. To be
sure, Meinecke did not desist from seeking solace in his historical interpretations.
Having earlier reflected in rather Weberian form that the principal concerns of
the historian were values and causation, and that these two were intrinsically
linked, by the time of The German Catastrophe (1946) causation, in terms of the
rise of Nazism, had become for Meinecke a matter of sheer (mis)fortune.
153 Forman, ‘Weimar Culture, Causality, and Quantum Theory’; Sidelsky, Ernst Cassirer, 167–8;
Hohendahl, ‘The Crisis of Neo-Kantianism’.
154 For distinctions and relations between Volksgeschichte and Landesgeschichte: Willi Oberkrome,
Volksgeschichte: Methodische Innovation und völkische Ideologisierung in der deutschen
Geschichtswissenschaft, 1918–1945 (Göttingen: Vandenhoeck und Ruprecht, 2011), including 22 ff. on
the anti-Versailles agenda and 56 ff. and 211 ff. on ‘Ostforschung’. Extensively on Conze: Thomas
Etzemüller, Sozialgeschichte als politische Geschichte: Werner Conze und die Neuorientierung der
westdeutschen Geschichtswissenschaft nach 1945 (Munich: Oldenbourg, 2001), including 70–89 on
Otto Brunner.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
Germany’s crimes beyond Germany were marginalized; the ‘catastrophe’ was one
that Nazism may have produced but Germany experienced.155
The trope of Nazism as an aberrant interlude was a popular one, especially for
nationalist conservatives. Included in that number was Meinecke’s student Hans
Rothfels (1891–1976). A Jewish convert to Lutheranism, Rothfels, like his own
student Conze, had opposed the Weimar republic and endorsed German imperi-
alism in eastern Europe. He reluctantly fled Germany in 1938 under pressure of
racist persecution. His 1948 work The German Opposition to Hitler embodied his
view that the conspirators involved in the July 1944 plot on Hitler’s life repre-
sented the essence of German conservative and militaristic traditions, whereas
Nazism was an interloping force. The non-Nazi conservative nationalist historian
Gerhard Ritter (1888–1967), who had actually been incarcerated for his member-
ship of the circle involved in the 1944 plot, had a similar vision of the true
Germany, one he had developed before the war. He conceived a fundamental
break in 1918, which introduced an unwelcome era of ‘mass democracy’ that
included the Weimar and the Nazi periods, and could be traced back to the for-
eign influence of the French Revolution. Nonetheless Ritter sensed enough of a
problem in the longerstanding traditions of German historianship that in 1949 he
urged the convention of the German Historical Association to stop taking reality
for granted. He seems to have meant this in the sense of not giving normative
status to the powers that be simply because they be, which is one implication of
Ranke’s claim that each epoch is immediate to god—he equally rejected the
Rankean view of war as a ‘struggle of moral energies’. Instead historians should be
prepared to apply political and moral judgement to discern between more and
less appealing options in any given historical context.156
In light of the decline of classical historicism, it is one of History’s and history’s
little ironies that the post-war decade was the incubation period for a vital late
development in the hermeneutics that had bound philosophy to historicism.
Where some hermeneuts had prided themselves that they might know the
authors of historical texts better than those authors knew themselves, and
Humboldt suggested that one’s understanding of the objects of one’s investiga-
tions would always be deficient, Hans-Georg Gadamer, erstwhile student of
Heidegger, came to a third conclusion. He wrote that ‘there is no understanding
or interpretation in which the totality of this existential structure [the structure
shaping the consciousness of the investigator] does not function, even if the
155 Meinecke, Burckhardt und Ranke (Berlin: Deutsche Akademie der Wissenschaft, 1948);
Meinecke, Die Deutsche Katastrophe (Wiesbaden: Brockhaus, 1947), passim, but see especially
comments on p. 125; Hardtwig, ‘Wissenschaft als Arbeit’, 10.
156 On Rothfels’s pre-war scholarship and thought, Oberkrome, Volksgeschichte, 132 ff.; Etzemüller,
Sozialgeschichte, 24–5. On Ritter: Klaus Schwabe, ‘Change and Continuity in German Historiography
from 1933 into the Early 1950s: Gerhard Ritter (1888–1967)’, in Hartmut Lehmann and James Van
Horn Melton (eds.), Paths of Continuity: Central European Historiography from the 1930s to the 1950s
(Washington, DC: German Historical Institute, 2003), 83–108, esp. 104 ff.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
intention of the knower is simply to read “what is there” and to discover from his
sources “how it was”. ’157 This did not mean that the hermeneut merely read the
present into the past. Such meanings as historical texts evince will be the fusion of
the horizons of meaning of the contemporary interpreter with the meanings of a
text that was produced against a different horizon. That fusion, rather than the
comprehension of the ‘original meaning’, is not a misunderstanding; it is just what
‘understanding’ is. It is not clear from Gadamer that he thought the subject could
fuse horizons with the pasts, or, one assumes, the presents, of significantly differ-
ent human groups, and this may be another area in which he differs from Dilthey
as from Herder. Thinking within the boundaries of one’s ‘own’, however, a phil
osophy of fusion across time implied that even when revolution or defeat—in
1789, 1918–19, or 1945—appeared to have established a clear break with the past,
there were always points of inheritance, and thus continuity. For German liberals
and leftists, conversely, the inherited traditions of ‘life’ were precisely what needed
to be brought under critique.
Left-leaning German intellectuals, many sociologists among them, had been
decimated under Nazi rule, leaving little in the way of more radical opposition
voices. For a revolution in West German historianship generational change was
needed, and a related shift away from two decades of post-war political domin
ation by the conservative Christian Democratic Union. The propitious cultural
environment of the later 1960s coincided with the intellectual diversification
attendant upon the expansion of the German university system, with academics
and students more than quadrupling in numbers from 1960 to 1975.158 The year
1975 also saw the first edition of the journal Geschichte und Gesellschaft, whose
title, ‘History and Society’, indicates the sort of History in question. Whatever has
subsequently been said about it, though, this historiographical ‘revolution’
inhered more in the political philosophies of the new historians than in their
methods and focus; the latter were only new when contrasted with the Rankean
model that had already been brought into question.
Hans-Ulrich Wehler (1931–2014), arguably the pre-eminent social historian of
Germany’s later twentieth century, acknowledged his debt to the interwar eco-
nomic historianship of Hans Rosenberg (1904–88) and Eckhart Kehr (1902–33),
and their identity as marginalized émigrés from Nazi Germany bolstered the
‘critical’ credentials of his project, yet in terms of method and approach he owed
as much to Conze. In 1957, from a chair in Heidelberg, and along with another
former Volks-historian, Eric Maschke, Conze established an Institute for
Economic and Social History and was a key player in the simultaneous creation
of the Working Group for Modern Social History. Conze’s anti-socialist
157 Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method (London: Sheed and Ward, 1979 [orig. 1960]), 232.
158 For the statistics and elements of the context, David Blackbourn, Populists and Patricians:
Essays in Modern German History (Abingdon: Routledge, 2014), 10.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
philosophy of social or, as he called it, ‘structural’ History prompted work on the
transformations of German society since the eighteenth century at the agrarian
and industrial levels. Many of the supposed innovations of post-war social History
can be traced to the interwar period; the Volks-historians’ multi-dimensional
concern with society necessitated engagement with folklorism, dem og
raphy,
geography, ethnology, and sociology.159 Conze had even reflected on an attenu-
ated sense of common historiographical revisionism with the French Annales
school, which is considered on its own terms in the next chapter.160
Where Wehler would presumably have displeased his doctoral supervisor
Schieder was in the political thrust of his work and that of the whole ‘Bielefeld
school’ of social History with which he became synonymous. Another leading
Bielefeld light, Jürgen Kocka (1941–), once mused that there might have been
more friction between Germany’s historical profession and Nazism had the for-
mer been more suffused with the cosmopolitan, comparative, indeed ‘Enlightened’
outlook of the likes of Gatterer, Vico, Voltaire, and Adam Ferguson, rather than
the heritage of nineteenth-century historicism with its emphasis on national
particularity.161 The historical project of Kocka, Wehler, and others means that
both they and their conservative protagonists were very obviously fighting battles
of their present by the discussion of its immediate Nazi, Weimar, and Wilhelmine
historical background. Rejecting not just the organicist thrust of historicism but
the hermeneutic approach that could serve merely to comprehend the dominant
forces of the nation-state-monad on its own terms, the more social-scientific
approaches of the new German social History were aligned to emancipation and
national self-critique as much as explanation, even as they focused more on
longer-term processes and structures than individual agents. Key goals included
exposing social structures that might still dominate suppressed social groups and
identifying continuities between Nazism and the Kaiserreich that problematized
the comforting view of Nazism as aberration. This was the ‘negative Sonderweg’
thesis, i.e. the counterpart to the complacent, self-regarding conservative view of
German History that had emphasized the superiority of German institutions and
spirituality.162
159 Peter Lambert, ‘Social History in Germany’, in Peter Lambert and Phillipp Schofield (eds.),
Making History (Abingdon: Routledge, 2004) 93–108, here 93–6; and Etzemüller, Sozialgeschichte.
160 For the nature and limits of these links, see Etzemüller, Sozialgeschichte, 1, 54–9; Traian
Stoianovich, French Historical Method: The Annales Paradigm (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1976),
45–6; Peter Schöttler, ‘Das “Annales-Paradigma” und die deutsche Historiographie (1929–1939)’, in
Lothar Jordan and Bernd Kortländer (eds.), Nationale Grenzen und internationaler Austausch
(Tübingen: Niemeyer, 1995), 200–20.
161 Jürgen Kocka, Geschichte und Aufklärung (Göttingen: Vandenhoeck und Ruprecht, 1989),
142–4.
162 Arguably the cardinal document of the negative Sonderweg theory was Wehler, Das Deutsche
Kaiserreich, 1871–1918 (Göttingen: Vandenhoeck und Ruprecht, 1973). For a succinct summary of
the positive and negative Sonderweg debates, see Blackbourn, Populists and Patricians, 1–12.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
7
Turns to the Present
Introduction
The work of Wehler and others in Germany was part of the broader north Atlantic
ascent of social History from the later 1950s to the peak of the 1970s and early
1980s. Social History took different forms in different countries depending on
their political constellations and the relative significance of related disciplines.
From the 1980s social History was gradually supplanted in prominence by a clus
ter of related historiographical developments concerned with language and cul
ture. In the last fifteen years or so newer fashions have waxed, and to those too
this chapter will attend, but in terms of major new lines of occidental historiog
raphy with consequences in justifications for History, social History and what for
shorthand we may call the linguistic and cultural turns remain of particular
importance.
In a broader historical perspective, the oscillation between social and linguistic-
cultural concerns looks like a reprise of the eighteenth-to-nineteenth-century
battles between ‘German’ culturalism and ‘French’ sociological thought. There is
truth to the comparison, but such dyads obscure as much as they reveal, since by
no means all social History was conducted with the social science method, and by
no means all cultural History focused on the more internalized understanding
and exploration of subjective meaning that we associate with hermeneutics.
Social History, especially History ‘from below’, as the French socialist politician
and historian Jean Jaurès (1859–1914) may have been first to call it,1 could be just
as interested in matters of ‘subjective’ individual and social ‘consciousness’ as
matters of ‘objective’ social ‘existence’, and it could focus on the interpenetration
of material and cultural elements rather than the determination of one level by
the other. Cultural History could be concerned with culture as a separate sphere
to ‘the social’ or ‘the economic’, but it could be just as all-encompassing in its
approach as social History had sometimes attempted to be. Under precepts influ
enced by the linguistic and cultural theory of structuralism and its descendants,
cultural History could be conducted according to ‘scientific’ (scientistic?) prin
ciples of explanation at least as much as hermeneutic principles of interpretative
understanding.
1 See Georges Lefebvre, The Coming of the French Revolution, ed. and introduced by Timothy
Tacket (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2005), p. xi.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
Claims for the utility of History varied according to practitioner but a few sub
stantivist rationales stand out. Social-scientific social historians were more apt to
assert History’s predictive value or at least its pragmatic contemporary import
ance at a time of industrialization beyond the north Atlantic—this was an update
of History as Practical Lesson. More methodologically ‘traditional’ qualitative
social historians were more likely to be found revising prevailing conceptions of
the past with a view to altering politics in the present—disturbing ‘whiggish’ nar
ratives, or inserting the marginalized into the historical record to fortify their
voices now. This was a species of History as Identity fused with History as
Emancipation. ‘New cultural historians’ specialized in a version of History as
Travel as they invoked exotic worlds past. They, like the many historians under
the influence of Michel Foucault, who addressed culture through the prism of
power, might adapt the Travel rationale, contrasting past ways of doing things
with present ways in order to underline/unmask the conventional, made and
remade, character of social relations and of human-being, and thus the possibility
of changing them. This was a Marxist agenda of History as Emancipation adapted
for a post-Marxist philosophy. Its proponents discarded Dilthey’s definition of
hermeneutic understanding as recognizing the self in the historically distant
Other, and focused more exclusively on the differences. The element of History as
Communion that had underlain so many hermeneutic approaches to the evi
dence of the past was abandoned in this philosophy.
Like History as Emancipation, the other relatively new rationale for History in
the period, ‘History as Therapy’, owes more to thought incubating in the nine
teenth century than to any of the self-conscious theoretical radicalism of the later
twentieth century. Since History as Therapy is less popular a rationale than
History as Emancipation or indeed any of the other rationales, further discussion
of it is postponed until the final chapter where all are revisited. The words of
the sociologist Pierre Bourdieu (1930–2002) nonetheless illustrate how closely
the therapeutic and emancipatory agendas can be associated as he broadened the
associations of the ‘unconscious’ from those in Schelling’s philosophy and psy
choanalysis. He used it in relation to his concept of the ‘habitus’, the set of norms,
skills, and, tastes that we each develop according to our socialization:
In practice, it is the habitus, history turned into nature, i.e. denied as such, which
accomplishes practically the relating of these two systems of relations [i.e. the
relations between objective structures, subjective practices, and the uncon
scious], in and through the production of practice. The ‘unconscious’ is never
anything other than the forgetting of history which history itself produces.2
Note that each of the three uses of ‘history’ has a different meaning. The ‘history’
that is forgotten is the way that the present emerged contingently from the past.
The ‘history’ that induces the forgetting of the past is a sort of official account, a
realization, perhaps of what the Marxist theorist György Lukács (1885–1971)
conceived as the aim of ‘bourgeois’ thought: ‘an apologia for the existing order of
things or at least the proof of their immutability’ as supposedly ‘eternal laws of
nature’. ‘As Marx points out,’ Lukács wrote, ‘people fail to realise “that . . . definite
social relations are just as much the products of men as linen, flax, etc.” ’3
Bourdieu’s solution to that second sort of ‘history’—i.e. his recommended device
for reversing the ‘denial’ of the contingency of historical developments and their
presentation as given ‘nature’—was a third form of history, which is my upper-
case History, that which in some instantiations has claim to be called critical
enquiry into the past. Thus, in Bourdieu’s words:
All sociology should be historical and all history sociological. In point of fact,
one of the functions of the theory of fields that I propose is to make the oppos
ition between reproduction and transformation, statics and dynamics, or struc
ture and history, vanish . . . [W]e cannot grasp the dynamics of a field without a
historical, that is, a genetic, analysis of its constitution and of the tensions that
exist between positions in it, as well as between this field and other fields.4
If this chapter is mainly concerned with what was added to History’s tapestry in
the north Atlantic centres of professional historiography, we must as ever
acknowledge that which was not new but which was retained from the past, i.e.
political History and related areas of elite interest like diplomatic History and
‘traditional’ international History. Especially from the 1960s the popularity of
political History dwindled signally among professional historians, though much
less so amongst general reading publics. Along with many other strands of his
toriography it has reinvented itself, as we shall see at the end of the chapter.
The First World War shook what was left of the stuffing from the British ‘Whig’
tradition that had developed out of the progressivist confidence of the eighteenth
century and peaked during Britain’s mid-nineteenth-century world dominance.
The power of the whig narrative had been waning for at least a generation by
3 Georg Lukács, History and Class Consciousness: Studies in Marxist Dialectics (Cambridge, MA:
MIT Press, 1971 [orig. 1922]), 48.
4 Pierre Bourdieu and Loïc Wacquant, An Invitation to Reflexive Sociology (Cambridge: Polity,
1992), 90.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
1914, consistent with ‘crisis-thinking’ across the Continent, and now it was criti
cized by a new breed of ‘modernist’ historians who rejected its ‘picturesqueness’
and rhetorical tendencies in the name of a forensic discipline.5 Some of their
barbs were not a world removed from the criticisms which the later nineteenth-
century whigs had directed at Macaulay before them. In 1929 the historian of
Anglo-Saxon England Frank M. Stenton (1880–1967) wrote sniffily of Stubbs’s
Constitutional History of England (1874–8; pp. 198–9) that ‘the details of medieval
finance [and] law are frequently interrupted by moral reflection in which a liter
ary purpose is powerfully present’.6
The epithet ‘modernist’ has been applied to the likes of Stenton by the historian
Michael Bentley and it helps to understand what Bentley means to read the label
as denoting contrast both to ‘whigs’ beforehand and ‘postmodernists’ afterwards.
Alongside a conviction that secure atomic facts could be established by archival
research and then used as firm bases on which to construct or test interpretations,
these modernists rejected speculation and suasive prose—and in the process they
rather rejected reflection on their own subject-positions and the literary and
otherwise creative (‘poetic’) nature of their own products. Bentley writes of a gen
eral sensibility, ‘the modernist feel for realizable truth and a consistent implica
tion that the past was out there as a visitable place’.7 Arguably these scholars did
come close to the barest historical literalism, the diminution of the already
reduced Lutheran hermeneutics to half of its purpose, but this literalism was not
the same as credulity. The ‘modernists’ were skilled in source criticism—as such
they were a world away from literalists as pejoratively understood—and while
they may have fancied themselves to be detached students of the past, there was
no general subscription to any simplistic liberal theory of context-free human
being as regards the people they studied. In that sense they were guilty of the
same sins of self-exemption or performative contradiction (where one’s practice
gainsays what one preaches) that marks a huge number of historians. Whilst
ditching some of the self-conscious narrative tendencies of historicism they
maintained and even enhanced its contextualism.
Most august of these modernists, Lewis Namier (1888–1960) was what the
social historian E. P. Thompson called an ‘inverted Marxist’: a man of the political
right who believed interests shape values. Namier also commended his friend
Freud’s insight into non-rational and unconscious motivations. Above all, he may
be said to have tied high politics to social History. His parliamentary History
assumed that the political behaviour of members could only be understood with
8 The ‘history of parliament’ project was the grandest expression of this philosophy. On
Thompson’s description, and Freud, Kevin Passmore, ‘History and Historiography since 1945’, in
Roger E. Backhouse and Philippe Fontaine (eds.), A Historiography of the Modern Social Sciences
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2014), 29–61, here 34.
9 Lewis Namier, The Structure of Politics at the Accession of George III (London: Macmillan, 1973),
pp. x–xi.
10 Lewis Namier, ‘History’ (1952), excerpted in Stern (ed.), The Varieties of History, 373. More
generally on anachronism see Blaas, Continuity and Anachronism.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
stadial History, Foucault did not present one stage as an advance on previous
ones. His famed project of creating a ‘historical ontology of ourselves’, i.e. a his
torical picture of successive human conceptions of what it was to be human, is a
sharpened elaboration of the nineteenth-century Francophone History in the
tradition of Taine, whose message was that ‘Each epoch of history . . . had its dis
tinctive institutions. Men were molded and remolded by these changing social
forms. Thus men could not be regarded as the same throughout history’; each
period had its ‘peculiar institutions and . . . corresponding psychology’.11 In the
first edition of Foucault’s Folie et déraison: Histoire de la folie à l’âge classique
(1961), the later English version of which was called Madness and Civilization, he
talked of producing ‘a structural study of an historical ensemble—notions, insti
tutions, juridical and police measures, scientific concepts’.12 Overall, there is a
Namier-esque quality both to the ‘static’ analysis of some of Foucault’s work and
the determination to show discontinuity across time in matters like scientific con
cepts. When objecting to ‘the philosophical myth of history’ as a ‘grand and
extensive continuity’, he repeatedly credited practising historians in general with
having destroyed this myth, and when he identified any particular historians, he
noted not just some of his own French predecessors but ‘the English historians’.
‘Modernist’ historians like Namier, with their preoccupation with anachronism
and suspicion of Whiggery, were, I propose, precisely the English historians he
had in mind. Others of the same stripe included Maitland (pp. 228–9), who in
turn bears the influence of the philosopher Henry Sidgwick, of whom it has been
said that he used the past ‘not to construct patterns of historical dynamics but to
discredit them’ along with ‘grand schemes of social evolution’.13
Namier’s title, like some of Foucault’s aforementioned vocabulary in Folie et
déraison, also hints at affinities with the structuralism that was fashionable in
interwar Continental linguistic theory and is most associated with the Swiss
Fernand de Saussure (1857–1913). Saussure rejected the conception of language
as relating the mind directly to the things of the external world. Thus far he was
consistent with romantic theories of language since Leibniz, and with nominal
ism. However he also opposed the conventional historical approach to language
that seemed irrelevant to the actual lived experience of the language community
and the psychological reality of the language user at any given moment. He made
11 Martha Wolfenstein, ‘The Social Background of Taine’s Philosophy of Art’, Journal of the History
of Ideas, 5 (1944), 332–58, here 337.
12 Translated and criticized in Jacques Derrida, Writing and Difference, ed. Alan Bass (London:
Routledge, 2005), 53.
13 Thomas R. Flynn, Sartre, Foucault and Historical Reason, vol. 1 (Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 1997), 246–7. For further remarks as to the role of artisanal historians in undermining the
myths of philosophical History, see Michel Foucault ‘Discourse on Language’ (1971) published as
appendix to Foucault, The Archaeology of Knowledge (New York: Pantheon, 1972), 215–37, here 230;
and the quotations in Flynn, Sartre, Foucault and Historical Reason, vol. 2, (Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 2005), 50–51, 115–16. On Maitland and Sidgwick, Wormald, Legal Culture, 60–1.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
the comparison between economic and linguistic systems that were not just
transactional but value-creating. Meanings are generated by language itself, by
syntax (word order), grammar, and relations of opposition (left versus right, etc.).
Given the highly contextual, web-like quality of meaning-production, one could
not actually dissociate the expression of an ostensibly simple ‘matter of fact’ or a
‘truth of reason’ from all of the other conventional understandings that structured
the intelligibility of the proposition.14
Why spend so much time on a linguistic theory? Because structuralist prin
ciples were later adopted in the human sciences well beyond the discipline of lin
guistics: indeed they were adopted there even as they were being challenged in
linguistics. Saussure himself had thought to develop a general theory of semiotics
on the principle that language was only the most obvious system of signs by
which humans made sense of the world and oriented their behaviour. A more
general semiotics (the study of sign-systems) sheds light on the unspoken but
omnipresent set of taboos, prompts, and community-specific forms of expres
sion, from facial markings to eating rituals to architectural forms, that make up
the thing we call a culture. The anthropologist Claude Lévi-Strauss asked this
question, to which his answer was positive: ‘Although they belong to another
order of reality, kinship phenomena are of the same type as linguistic phenomena.
Can the anthropologist, using a method analogous in form (if not in content) to
the method used in structural linguistics, achieve the same kind of progress in his
own science as that which has taken place in linguistics?’15 This marked the
advent of structuralist anthropology, as against Boas’s historicist anthropology.
Moreover, structuralism fed a general intellectual atmosphere that was already
receptive to broadly similar ideas. Structuralism has some similarities with, and
possibly roots in, the side of Kant’s thought that dealt with the transcendental ego,
with its focus on structures shaping the cognitive faculties that were brought to
bear on the phenomenal world. Forms of psychology bear comparison to struc
turalism too, in the idea of a subconscious influencing conscious behaviour.
Structuralism can also be seen as analogous to the Marxist concept of relations of
production defining social (class) arrangements, i.e. the economic base determin
ing the socio-cultural superstructure, but also in the mutually constituting nature
of oppositions/relations (left–right, bourgeoisie–proletariat). In each case some
subterranean force shapes surface enunciations, as when Herbert Butterfield criti
cized Namier for explanatory resort to a vague but determinant underlying ‘struc
ture of politics’.16
14 On truths of fact and truths of reason see Willard Van Orman Quine, ‘Two Dogmas of
Empiricism’, The Philosophical Review, 60 (1951), 20–43.
15 Claude Lévi-Strauss, Structural Anthropology (New York: Basic Books, 1963 [orig 1958]), 34.
Emphases in original.
16 Butterfield, George III and the Historians, cited in Paul Franco, Michael Oakeshott: An
Introduction (New Haven: Yale University Press, 2004), 138.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
However, such analogies only work so far. Kant’s transcendental ego has to go
by the board along with anything else resembling a universal structure of reason:
under structuralism, while there is a purely formal similarity of law-giving struc
tures across all cultures and language, substantively there is no way of comparing
language X or culture Y with an overarching supracultural standard. Structuralism
therefore has strong relativist connotations, and indeed from the mid-twentieth
century structuralist relativism reinforced the relativist connotations of classical
historicism even as classical historicism was discredited by the world wars. Lévi-
Strauss wrote of the role of myths, in creating a sense of cultural discontinuity ‘by
the radical elimination of certain fractions of the continuum’; ‘a discrete [cultural]
system is produced by the destruction of certain elements or their removal from
the original whole’.17 The same idea applied diachronically too, judging by Lévi-
Strauss’s criticism of certain sorts of History as giving a false sense of continuity
across time.18 Sharper differentiation across time as well as place is the essence of
neo-historicism, as this book calls it.
Something is also lost in the analogy of psychological theory and structural
ism. In order to render mental material malleable enough to accord with struc
turalism without remainder, Lévi-Strauss had to evacuate on one hand any
element of recalcitrant individual uniqueness à la Jung, and on the other hand
any of the innate, universal drives that Freud conceived.19 Similarly, the strength
of the analogy with Marxism varies according to the type of Marxism chosen.
Those who think less in terms of the determination of the superstructure by the
base, and more in terms of the interpenetration or reciprocal influence of the two
elements, will find the analogy less satisfactory. Where Marxism of any sort (and
psychoanalysis) differs from structuralism is that it purports not just to describe
but to diagnose and where possible amend. Nonetheless, the spirit—less often the
letter—of structuralist, psychological, and Marxist thought is in evidence in so
much of what was novel in twentieth-century occidental historianship.
Marxist-inspired History made significant inroads from the margins after the
Bolshevik revolution. Marx’s historian followers have increasingly discarded
Marx the dialectical philosopher of History but regard Marx the historian, econo
mist, and sociologist as having created important analytical tools. In the USA the
early influence of Marxism showed itself in the diluted form of the ‘progressive’
New History. In the UK, the development of social History was shaped in the
interwar period by a group of interdisciplinary left-wing historians, social scien
tists, and policymakers at the London School of Economics, that product of
17 Claude Lévi-Strauss, The Raw and the Cooked (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1986), 52–3: my
attention was drawn to this passage by Gillian Gillison, ‘From Cannibalism to Genocide: The Work of
Denial’, The Journal of Interdisciplinary History, 37:3 (2007), 395–414, here 412.
18 Claude Lévi-Strauss, The Savage Mind (London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson, 1966), 256–64.
19 Gillison, ‘From Cannibalism to Genocide’, 411–13.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
20 Maxine Berg, A Woman in History: Eileen Power 1889–1940 (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1996), 162 ff.
21 e.g. Lucien Febvre, Philippe II et la Franche-Comté (Paris, Champion, 1912), esp. ch. 1 for the
geographical context; Febvre, La Terre et l’évolution humaine: Introduction géographique à l’histoire
(Paris: La Renaissance du Livre, 1922).
22 Charles Seignobos, La Méthode historique appliquée aux science sociales (Paris: Alcan, 1901); cf.
Paul Lacombe L’Histoire considérée comme science (Paris: Hachette, 1894) and François Simiand,
‘Méthode historique et science sociale’, Revue de Synthèse historique, 6 (1903) 1–22, 129–57.
23 François Dosse, New History in France: The Triumph of the Annales (Chicago: University of
Illinois Press, 1994) 13 ff.; Hartog, ‘Von der Universalgeschichte’, point 11.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
of unique particularities it was already a social science. For all of their adoption of
social scientific methods and suspicion of high political History it is not clear that
the Annalistes were moving from the particular to the general in the way
Durkheim commended. One might just as well say that they had larger-scale par
ticulars in mind, since geography, geology, and deep structures of belief were not
the same everywhere, and the historians in question did not seek to abstract away
from those particularities so as to create a general, lawmaking science of human
kind, or even of humankind at particular stages of development. Bloch himself
was an early advocate of comparative History, though comparison may be con
cerned as much with differences as similarities. Works like his Les Caractères orig-
inaux de l’histoire rurale française,24 however bold in scope, still had a high level
of specificity as to the (three) types of agrarian community in France, and the
influence of these patterns over centuries into the French present, with the impli
cation that France was different in that respect to, say, the British present. Finally,
however long the spans of time with which Annalistes concerned themselves, they
still took the temporal, processual element seriously, and did not deal in the time
less models characteristic of structural linguistics or econometrics.
The Annalistes rejected as subjective and unsystematic any concept of History
as the study of individual meaningful actions and events embedded in contingent
causal sequences, phenomena whose character was only ascertainable through
the lens of a potentially infinite number of actor-perceptions as to their ‘meaning’.
With their focus ranging from the early development of the capitalist system to
topography through the full range of subjects studied by the human sciences in
their broadest definitions, the Annalistes were above all concerned with the over
arching, or perhaps underpinning, environmental, economic, psychological,
technical, and social frameworks within which different peoples lived. All this
helps explain Bloch’s opposition to moral evaluation of individuals who partook
of broader ‘mentalités’, which were a creation of forces beyond their comprehen
sion and which comprised the condition of their consciousness rather than being
its creation. The contrast is sharp with the prevailing orthodoxies of the historical
discipline at the outset of the twentieth century, when political History accounted
for more than half of all French History theses and biographical studies for more
than 30 per cent.25 In other countries political History was yet more dominant.
The concept mentalité, nearer in determinative strength to ‘episteme’ than
‘Zeitgeist’, and partly defined against intellectual ‘ideas’, is the product of Febvre’s
call for ‘historical psychology’, and perhaps also of Bloch’s experience of collective
behaviour during the First World War. As in Georges Lefebvre’s The Great Fear of
1789 (1932),26 on popular unrest in the build-up to the French Revolution, the
27 André Burguière, L’École des Annales. Une histoire intellectuelle (Paris: Odile Jacob, 2006), 42–3.
28 Strasbourg: Istra, 1924.
29 Lucien Febvre, Le Problème de l’incroyance au XVIe siècle (Paris: Albin Michel, 1942).
30 Lévi-Strauss, Structural Anthropology, 23–4. 31 Ibid.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
Historical Studies had had an economic section for some time. The influence of
German nineteenth-century historical economics was noted, alongside the work
of Pirenne, French studies of the impact of the French Revolution on local eco
nomic life, and, in Britain, the work of Arnold Toynbee senior (1852–83).32
It may be that economic History benefited in popularity from the same ten
dencies that boosted intellectual History between the wars (though not in the
work of the early Annalistes), as the study of high politics and diplomacy came
under the same sort of critique as the high politicians who had led the continent
into destruction.33 But the stock market crash of 1929 guaranteed greater atten
tion to impersonal economic forces, and by coincidence the Annales journal was
first published in that year. In a famous 1933 book, Ernst Labrousse deployed
quantitative methodology to gauge the movement of prices and revenue in
eighteenth-century France,34 and capitalized on the immediate interest in the
present conjuncture and the enduring interest in the causes of the French
Revolution. His was only the best known of a number of investigations into the
history of economic fluctuations at the time from the very first issue of Annales
onwards, and in the work of Simiand.35
32 William Ashley, ‘The Place of Economic History in University Studies’, The Economic History
Review, 1:1 (1927), 1–11.
33 D. R. Woolf, ‘The Writing of Early Modern European Intellectual History, 1945–1995’, in Bentley
(ed.), Companion to Historiography, 307–35, here 309.
34 Ernst Labrousse, Esquisse du mouvement des prix et des revenues en France au XVIIIe siècle
(Paris: Dalloz, 1933).
35 François Simiand, Les Fluctuations économiques à longue période et la crise mondiale (Paris:
Alcan 1932); Simiand, Recherches anciennes et nouvelles sur le mouvement général des prix du VXIe au
XIXe siècle (Paris: Domat-Montchrestien, 1932). For the Annales journal, merely consult the contents
pages.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
36 Fernand Braudel, The Mediterranean and the Mediterranean World in the Age of Philip II, vol. 1
(London: Collins, 1972 [orig. 1949]), 21.
37 Ibid.
38 Pierre Nora, ‘Le Retour de l’événement’, in Jacques Le Goff and Pierre Nora (eds.), Faire de
l’histoire, 3 vols. (Paris, Gallimard, 1974), I, 285–308; Jacques Rancière, Les Mots de l’histoire. Essai de
poétique du savoir (Paris, Seuil, 1992).
39 François Dosse, History of Structuralism, vol. 2: The Sign Sets, 1967–Present (Minneapolis:
University of Minnesota Press, 1998), 116.
40 Fernand Braudel, On History (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1980), 10.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
If the relationship of events and structures needs clarification, confusion may also
arise over the relationship of structures to structuralism, though what is at issue is
merely a semantic similarity. Structuralism pertains to elements in an interrelated
system; those elements may be structures in the substantive sense, but simply
talking about structures is not to subscribe to structuralism, and as soon as one
attends to the specificities/contents of substantive structures one has already
shifted emphasis away from the precepts of structuralism with its emphasis on the
productive quality of relations between elements. It does, however, help to explain
the prominence of ‘the event’ in French philosophy in the second half of the
twentieth century if we see it as something conceived as in ontological contradic
tion to ‘the system’ or whatever is seen as the underlying determinant of the social
order—as if that order were not itself the product of event-ful processes, or as if
there were some difference in metaphysical kind between ‘the event’ and those
other events.
Whatever the difference between talk of structures and of structuralism, struc
turalism’s inability to account for change is related to its lack of interest in his
torical analysis, but also to the coherence that it implies for any given order as it
stands. On the whole, historical thought influenced by structuralism tends either
to ignore change, via static descriptions, or posits some revolution-like eruption
in a way that may be inspired by Marxist thought. Beyond adapting Weberian
41 See Braudel’s awareness of the contestableness of his definition of ‘event’: Fernand Braudel, The
Mediterranean and the Mediterranean World in the Age of Philip II, vol. 2 (Berkeley: University of
California Press, 1995), 1243.
42 Foucault, ‘The Discourse on Language’, 230.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
43 John O’Neill, ‘The Disciplinary Society: From Weber to Foucault’, British Journal of Sociology,
37:1 (1987), 42–60.
44 A. J. Rowse, The Use of History (Harmondsworth: Pelican, 1971), 85.
45 Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1961.
46 Braudel, The Mediterranean, vol. 1, p. 21. On moral judgement, Marc Bloch, The Historian’s Craft
(New York: Vintage Books, 1953 [French orig. 1949]), 139, 142.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
continuity that differed in certain respects from the classical historicist ‘German’
doctrine of the same.
Braudel realized that the broader the historical canvas upon which one wishes
to paint, the less significant individual or even collective agency will seem, up to
the point where the individual and even the war or revolution is erased entirely.
But it is just a matter of choice as to whether one focuses most of one’s energy on
addressing the longue durée or on shorter ones, on the impersonal or the per
sonal—neither approach reveals ‘the truth about history’ as a process. The answer
one gets is a function of the question one has set oneself, and there is no intrinsic
hierarchy of importance of such questions. Nor is there any inherent incompati
bility in studying different durées. Bloch’s study of feudalism certainly seems to
have little to do with the later microstoria or ‘microhistory’ of Carlo Ginzburg and
Natalie Zemon Davis, and indeed microhistory was a reaction to the vast sweep
of earlier Annales scholarship. But the microhistorians had an eye on the bigger
picture, however ostensibly small their focus, on the principle that a case study
well conducted can cast wider light whether its focus is on a civilization, a
sixteenth-century Friulian miller (Ginzburg, The Cheese and the Worms, 1976) or
an impostor in a Pyrénéan village of the same period (Davis, The Return of Martin
Guerre, 1983). Giovanni Levi, author of The Immaterial Inheritance: Career of an
Exorcist in Seventeenth-Century Piedmont (1985), wrote of his desire to ‘address a
more complex social structure without losing sight of the individual’s social space
and hence, of people and their situation in life’, noting that the ‘minutest detail/
action of say somebody buying a loaf of bread actually encompasses the far wider
system of the whole world’s grain market’.47 Writing in the 1990s, Hans Medick
claimed that his local history of the Swabian village of Laichingen from 1650
to1900 could be a ‘micro-historically grounded’ form of ‘general History’ (allge-
meine Geschichte).48 Braudel’s student Emmanuel le Roy Ladurie navigated
between the macro level, with his study of the peasants of the Languedoc from
the fifteenth to the eighteenth centuries, and the meso level, with his account of
a single village over thirty years.49 The concept of mentalité guided a number of
these scholars, though they would differ amongst themselves and with other
microhistorians as to the relationship between mentalité and the individual
capacity for reflection and agency. On the whole, the sharper the focus on
47 Giovanni Levi, ‘On Microhistory’, in Peter Burke (ed.), New Perspectives on Historical Writing
(University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press, 1992), 93–113, here 99, 104; Giovanni Levi,
L’Eredità Immaterial: Carriera di un Exorcista nel Piemonte del Seicento (Turin: Einaudi, 1985); Carlo
Ginzburg, The Cheese and the Worms: The Cosmos of a Sixteenth-Century Miller (London: Routledge,
1980 [Italian orig. 1976]); Natalie Zemon Davis, The Return of Martin Guerre, (Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press, 1983).
48 Hans Medick, Weben und Überleben in Laichingen, 1650–1900: Lokalgeschichte als Allgemeine
Geschichte (Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 1996), 13.
49 Emmanuel le Roy Ladurie, Les Paysans de Languedoc, 2 vols. (Paris: Mouton, 1966); Montaillou,
village occitan de 1294 à 1324 (Paris: Gallimard, 1975).
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
individual lives, the greater the impression of agency and of the capacity for
self-fashioning.
Allied victory in 1945 ensured the continued rise of the Annales as an institution,
though it was only in the 1970s with English language translations of the major
works that its influence thoroughly percolated the American academy. While the
editorial philosophies of the journal changed somewhat along with personnel,
maintaining a distance from the emotions of contemporary politics was a consist
ent feature of the Annales ethos from Bloch through Braudel and Ladurie. This
ethos chimed with ‘Weberian’ neutralism even while it had its own distinct
genealogy. Both stances met with a full-frontal challenge in the political circum
stances of the time. In France, as elsewhere, the Second World War and then the
advent of the Cold War ignited further History wars along the lines of political
identity.50
As around the 1914–18 conflict, the issue of moral righteousness came to the
fore for professional historians as well as politicians. In the USA in 1949 the presi
dent of the American Historical Association enjoined historians to enlist in ‘total
war’, supporting certain values as absolute, and censoring themselves by the rec
ognition that some historical matters were not ‘appropriate for broadcasting at
street corners’.51 Writing in 1952, the American historian of slavery Kenneth
Stampp noted the ongoing debate within his country’s historical profession
between ‘scientific’ and ‘subjectivist-relativist-presentist’ schools as to the validity
of moral judgement in works of History.52 In Britain in the decade from 1953,
Toynbee, Isaiah Berlin, Geoffrey Barraclough, C. V. Wedgwood, David Knowles,
and E. H. Carr pitched into the same argument. Herbert Butterfield held fairly
constantly to the nuanced anti-judgementalism that he had established before the
advent of Nazism.53 A chasm separates the agendas of Braudel’s Mediterranean or
Laudurie’s Paysans de Languedoc on one hand and on the other hand those of
Germany’s Hans Rothfels and his British counterpart Barraclough as they set
50 Pieter Lagrou, The Legacy of Nazi Occupation: Patriotic Memory and National Recovery in
Western Europe, 1945–1965 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000).
51 Conyers Read, ‘The Social Responsibilities of the Historian’, American Historical Review, 55
(1949–50), 275-85, here 283–4.
52 Novick, That Noble Dream, 351.
53 Arnold Toynbee, ‘The Writing of Contemporary History for Chatham House’, International
Affairs, 29:2 (April, 1953), 137–40; Isaiah Berlin, Historical Inevitability (London: Oxford University
Press, 1954), 30–53; Geoffrey Barraclough, History in a Changing World (Norman, OK: University of
Oklahoma Press, 1956), 1–7; Barraclough, ‘History, Morals, and Politics’, International Affairs, 34:1
(1958), 1–15; C. V. Wedgwood, Truth and Opinion: Historical Essays (London: Collins, 1960), 47–54;
E. H. Carr, What Is History? (New York: Knopf, 1962), 75–6; David Knowles, The Historian and
Character (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1963), 12–15.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
54 Ernest Lavisse (ed.), Histoire de France contemporaine, depuis la revolution jusqu’à la paix de
1919, 10 vols. (Paris: Hachette, 1920–2).
55 Geoffrey Barraclough, ‘The Historian in a Changing World’, in Hans Meyerhoff (ed.), The
Philosophy of History in Our Time (New York: Doubleday, 1959), 28–35, here 30–2; Barraclough,
Introduction to Contemporary History (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1967), 20.
56 Kristina Spohr Readman, ‘Contemporary History in Europe’, Journal of Contemporary History,
46:3 (2011), 506–30.
57 Stephen Toulmin, The Place of Reason in Ethics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1950),
171, 223.
58 Bédarida, ‘The Modern Historian’s Dilemma’, 339–40. H. S. Commager, The Search for a Usable
Past (New York: Knopf, 1967), 316.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
old left and right looked like the forces of repression to the ‘revolutionaries’ of
the 1960s.
The social upheavals of the Sixties made due impact on the mainstreams of
western professional historiography, though the themes of rights, repression, and
liberation were taken up in the first instance more at the margins of the academy.
As to the influence of social scientific theories, those that were most evident in
the mainstream historical work of the 1960s and 1970s were precisely the ones
that the conflicts of 1968 brought into question.
In the mid-1950s Richard Hofstadter wrote that ‘the most important function
which the social sciences can perform for the historian is that they provide
means . . . by which he can be brought into working relationship with certain
aspects of the modern intellectual climate’.59 By modern thought he meant the
sort of thing celebrated by his fellow historian Thomas C. Cochran around the
same time when Cochran said that ‘at the center of any comprehensive and mean
ingful synthesis, determining its topical and chronological divisions, should be
the material and psychological changes that have most affected, or threatened
most to affect, such human conditioning factors as family life, physical living con
ditions, choice of occupations, sources of prestige, and fundamental beliefs’.60
Hofstadter may have known that his criticism as to ‘means’ was not valid for
Annales historiography of the time, and from the 1970s that French influence
shaped the ‘intellectual climate’ of American historiography, as did American soci
ology. However, this was no radical hybridization since both Annales scholarship
and US sociology had Durkheimian lineages. Furthermore, French–American
intellectual cross-fertilization in the field had been encouraged in order to counter
French anti-Americanism by such means as the Ford Foundation’s grant for the
establishment of the Maison des sciences de l’homme in 1959.
Hofstadter and Cochran were speaking to an American audience of historians
who still overwhelmingly practised political History, though their points about
absences pertained equally to mainstream British and German historiography of
the time. Historicism had dealt in terms of monads rather than laws, of unique
individual entities and the grandest wholes, but even as it tried to hold the part
and the whole in balance, it maintained the dichotomy, leaving the middle ground
to the social scientists. The ‘comparatively constant’ was the purview of the sorts
59 Richard Hofstadter, ‘History and the Social Sciences’, in Stern (ed.), Varieties of History, 359–70,
here 363.
60 Thomas C. Cochran, ‘The Social Sciences and the Problem of Historical Synthesis’, in Stern (ed.),
Varieties of History, 348–59, here 357.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
of social scientists on whom historians could most fruitfully draw. This was the
realm of approximate similarities and recurrences, whether in forms of govern
ance or economy, or patterns of elite or mass behaviour. Scholars might also make
lawlike generalizations delimited by temporal or cultural boundaries, building
on the Weberian ideal type.61 The American economic historian Alexander
Gerschenkron, who had been trained in Austrian-school economics with its anti-
historicist doctrine, described historical research as ‘application to empirical
material of various sets of empirically derived hypothetical generalizations and in
testing the closeness of the resulting fit, in the hope that in this way certain
uniformities, certain typical situations, and certain typical relationships among
individual factors in those situations can be ascertained’. Cochran deployed a
Braudelian idiom of political events as ‘surface manifestations that are not of the
highest importance’ and so commended the study of threatened or realized deep
‘material and psychological changes’ in human patterns of life.62 Whereas the
French Revolution had once been a paradigm for political historiography and a
point of contrast for the Annalistes, and whereas May 1968 was to become a para
digm for philosophical thought about resistance to authority, the new social his
toriography had ‘modernization’ as its paradigm.
Sociology’s stock was already high in the USA as enhanced federal funding
promoted a discipline that had suggested its utility during the New Deal and
in wartime administration and would be needed for harmonious integration
and the analysis of post-war ills. Equally important was the ‘productivist’
Fordism of the American economy, and its concern with societal regulation
and predictability.63 Talcott Parsons, the dominant sociologist of mid-century
America, and another student of society persuaded by the utility of psychoanalysis,
put his focus on the preconditions for stability, seeing abrupt or disorderly
change as a sign of systemic dysfunction rather than the expression of emancipa
tory tendencies. In this intellectual environment, ‘modernity’ and ‘modernization’
were sociological buzzwords whereas unsurprisingly ‘capitalism’, dialectics, and
the class struggle were not so fashionable. In some quarters ‘class’ was used less to
denote position in the relations of production, and came to mean something
more akin to the Weberian concept of ‘status’ in the sense of ‘the relative position
of actors or social groups in a subjectively defined hierarchy of honour and
61 Helen P. Liebel, ‘Philosophical Idealism in the Historische Zeitschrift, 1859–1914’, History and
Theory, 3:3 (1964), 316–30, here 330.
62 Gerschenkron and Cochran quotes from Cochran, ‘The Social Sciences’, 348–9.
63 George Steinmetz, ‘American Sociology before and after World War Two’, in Craig Calhoun
(ed.), Sociology in American: A History (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2007), 314–66; Tony
Judt, ‘A Clown in Regal Purple: Social History and the Historians’, History Workshop Journal, 1 (1979),
66–94, here 81; for History’s interaction with social sciences in different countries, Passmore, ‘History
and Historiography since 1945’.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
64 Gareth Stedman Jones, ‘From Historical Sociology to Theoretical History’, The British Journal of
Sociology, 27:3 (1976), 295–305, here 302.
65 For Rostow’s historiographical significance, Passmore, ‘History and Historiography since 1945’,
35–40. On misreadings of Rostow, Guy Ortolano, ‘The Typicalities of the English? Walt Rostow, The
Stages of Economic Growth, and British History’, Modern Intellectual History, 12: 3 (2015), 657–84.
66 David Blackbourn and Geoff Eley, Mythen deutscher Geschichtsschreibung. Die gescheiterte
bürgerliche Revolution von 1848 (Frankfurt am Mein: Ullstein, 1980); The Peculiarities of German
History: Bourgeois Society and Politics in Nineteenth Century Germany (Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 1984).
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
67 Joan W. Scott and Louise A. Tilly, ‘Women’s Work and the Family in Nineteenth-Century
Europe’, Comparative Studies in Society and History, 17:1 (1975), 36–64, here 42, 50. On traditional
versus modern in modernization theory, Ortolano, ‘The Typicalities of the English?’, 658.
68 On the final points, Jones, ‘From Historical Sociology to Theoretical History’, 301–2.
69 These ‘tendencies’ are those of political historians. Take the case of political historians in Britain’s
historical profession, which had (has?) a reputation for theory-averseness. What was alleged as intel
lectual conservatism on the basis of focus of historical interest and method did not necessarily equate
to political Conservatism—compare A. J. P. Taylor to Lewis Namier—and political Conservatives dif
fered as much in their methods as Geoffrey Elton and Maurice Cowling. And note that in the German
case, while we have seen on one hand that it was eminently possible to have very rightwing social his
torians, equally on the other hand it was not just social historians who took up cudgels against nation
alist political historiography and the positive version of the Sonderweg thesis. Well before Wehler’s
contribution Fritz Fischer’s Griff nach der Weltmacht (Düsseldorf: Droste, 1961), English translation
Germany’s Aims in the First World War, was amongst other things a study of political decisions, pres
sure groups, and decision-making resting on official documentation.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
‘modernization’ defined much of the basic problematic, but how and with what
motivations one picked up on any of the range of related topics varied greatly.
One could be just as interested in explaining the social roots of rebellion as the
social process of adjustment to new norms and practices.
On the methodological side, any given historian could combine competence in
qualitative and quantitative skills, just as she or he might blend the approaches of
Erklären and Verstehen: for one or both of these combinations see for instance the
works of Ladurie, Scott and Tilly, Paul E. Johnson, William J. Sewell, Eric
Hobsbawm, and George Rudé. And while quantification seemed to promise an
objectivity lacking in hitherto dominant qualitative historical models, a prolifer
ation of empirically rich ‘small-N’ comparisons marked the take-off of detailed
comparative history after earlier prompts by Weber, Pirenne, and Bloch. A land
mark in this respect was the establishment of the journal Comparative Studies in
Society and History in 1958 by the social historian of the Middle Ages Sylvia
Thrupp, a former student of Eileen Power. Theda Skocpol explained what a ‘small-
N’ approach means, while exemplifying it in her discussion of the discontents of
modernization in States and Social Revolutions: A Comparative Analysis of France,
Russia and China (1979): ‘the comparative method is nothing but that mode of
multivariate analysis to which sociologists necessarily resort when experimental
manipulations are not possible and when there are “too many variables and not
enough cases” ’. In her version of comparison, the comparativist ‘looks for con
comitant variations, contrasting cases where the phenomena in which one is
interested are present with cases where they are absent, controlling in the process
for as many sources of variation as one can, by contrasting positive and negative
instances which otherwise are as similar as possible’. So the cases of Japan,
Germany, and pre-1905 Russia were studied as contrasting instances of ‘non-
social revolutionary modernization’. For all the social-scientific verbiage, Skocpol
recorded her determination to read extensively on the Histories of her chosen
countries prior to engaging the sociological models of revolution, of which she
was suspicious.70 Her comparative method was influential on important histor
ians, though we should not forget alternative comparative approaches.71 She
herself was a historical sociologist, and that breed was probably at its most influ
ential in the 1960s–1970s by virtue of her work and that of Barrington Moore,
70 Skocpol, Social Revolutions in the Modern World (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1994), 135; States and Social Revolutions: A Comparative Analysis of France, Russia, and China
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1979), preface.
71 On both Skocpol’s influence and alternative models, Mary Fulbrook, Piety and Politics: Religion
and the Rise of Absolutism in England, Württemberg and Prussia (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1983), 184–6. On the interface between the work of many historians and historical sociologists,
and the range of comparative models, Theda Skocpol, ‘Emerging Agendas and Current Strategies in
Historical Sociology’, in Skocpol (ed.), Vision and Method in Historical Sociology (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1994), 356–91.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
Much of this was acted out with mad-scientist bravado. One well-known quanti
fier said that anyone who did not know statistics at least through multiple
regression should not hold a job in a history department. My own advisor told
us that he wanted history to become ‘a predictive social science.’ I never went
that far. I was drawn to the new social history by its democratic inclusiveness as
much as by its system and precision. I wanted to write the history of ordinary
people—to historicize them, put them into the social structures and long-term
trends that shaped their lives, and at the same time resurrect what they said
and did. In the late 1960s, quantitative social history looked like the best way to
do that 76
Johnson’s aim was different to that of the French and Scottish Enlightenment
historians who addressed ‘manners and mores’ in the sense of general culture. It
was not, however, altogether new. Michelet had made a great point of writing
‘ordinary people’ into the historical record, seeking to retrieve the memory of the
‘too-forgotten dead’, those ‘miserabiles personae’ like widows and orphans, each of
whom ‘leaves but a small property, his memory, and asks that it be cared for. For
the one who has no friends, the magistrate must supply one. . . . This magistracy is
History.’77 French nineteenth-century historiography had preceded Marx in
examining social classes, with Marx dubbing Thierry the ‘father of the class strug
gle in French historiography’.78 In the interwar period Georges Lefebvre brought
Michelet’s and Thierry’s interests together from a Marxist perspective with his
study of the northern French peasantry during the Revolution.79 The US ‘progres
sive’ historians, like the British left-wing historians of Tawney’s generation, had
fused their economic interests with concerns for the lives of non-elites. In Eileen
Power’s case, the result was studies of the life of a Carolingian peasant, a fourteenth-
century Parisian housewife, and an Essex clothier during the reign of Henry
VII.80 Alice Clark, Annie Abram, and Ivy Pinchbeck, who all wrote their doctor
ates at the London School of Economics, produced Social England in the Fifteenth
Century, The Working Life of Women in the Seventeenth Century, and Women
Workers and the Industrial Revolution in 1909, 1919, and 1930 respectively; and
Lina Eckenstein published Women under Monasticism before any of them, in
1896.81 African American historiography had made significant strides early in the
twentieth century, as we shall see shortly. What was unprecedented from the late
1960s was the number of historians in different countries who were starting to
think in this way—and further unprecedented was the range of different groups
whose historical presence was to be considered.
76 Paul E. Johnson, ‘Reflections: Looking Back at Social History’, Reviews in American History, 39:2
(2011), 379–88, here 380.
77 Jules Michelet, Histoire du XIXe siècle, vol. II: Le Directoire, Preface, repr. in Roland Barthes,
Michelet (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1992), 101–2.
78 Quote in Ralph Raico, Classical Liberalism and the Austrian School (Auburn, AL: Ludwig von
Mises Institute, 2012), 187.
79 Georges Lefebvre, Les Paysans du Nord pendant la Révolution française (Lille, Camille Robbe,
1924).
80 Eileen Power, Medieval People (London: Methuen, 1924).
81 Ann Oakley, Women, Peace and Welfare: A Suppressed History of Social Reform, 1880–1920
(Bristol: Policy Press, 2019), 12.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
In the western bloc, Marxism played a greater role in British social History than
American, while for specific reasons it featured barely at all in the most influential
West German social History.82 British social History also evinced international
influences earlier and more markedly than US social History. Past and Present: A
Journal of Scientific History, established in 1952, immediately incorporated
Annaliste and eastern European scholarly approaches. The journal’s subtitle, later
to be changed as it became less Marxist, hinted at its embrace of social scientific
methodologies, which set it apart from the mainstream of British historiography
quite as much as did the political orientation of its founders. Only with the pro
liferation of British universities and the liberalization of British society from the
1960s would British social History encroach from the margins, and even then
some of its leading Marxist lights found difficulty gaining conventional academic
posts.
Geoff Eley gives us some of the flavour of his national context when he recalls
‘the pompous and sentimentalized nationalist history delivered by conservative
patriots during the first two postwar decades in Britain, for which the grandiose
multipart television documentary celebrating Churchill’s war leadership, The
Valiant Years, was the epitome’. In Eley’s dispiriting initiation to Oxford University
in 1967 ‘the first term brought only Gibbon and Macaulay, de Tocqueville,
Burckhardt, and—last but not least—the Venerable Bede’. There was no sense that
the syllabus had been established with a view to comparing some classic models
of yesteryear with more contemporary and novel approaches, since the latter went
unmentioned. The Swinging Sixties this was not. For approaches that better
matched his social concerns at Oxford, Eley had to look to the intellectual mar
gins of the History faculty, to historians at the new universities, and to other
disciplines.83
If the social science with which British social historians established the closest
working relationship was economics, we need to resist any assumption of a nar
row materialist doctrine. Marx was, after all, the presiding sociologist, and in
both his more and less determinist modes he insisted on the connectedness of
all facets of life, differing only on the causal relationships between them.
Furthermore, while the influential Cultural Studies Movement associated with
Stuart Hall did not include many historians, it grew out of the same post-war
Marxist milieu as the Communist Party Historians Group (1946–1956/7) and
shared many of the group’s broad intellectual concerns. When social History fell
out of fashion in the USA in the final two decades of the century it was replaced
82 On the German context, including the Berufsverbot, see Eley, Crooked Line, 73–4.
83 Ibid. 1–2 and passim. Additional information from personal correspondence with Geoff Eley.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
by the ‘new cultural History’ (pp. 281–8), but many of Britain’s most prominent
social historians had long since transcended that divide.
The Annaliste concept of mentalité influenced the famous school of British
Marxist historians but these scholars also had ‘western Marxist’ theory, from
György Lukács onwards, to prompt and feed their interest in culture and other
matters that Marxists had once consigned to a secondary, ‘superstructural’ status.
The question of proletarian consciousness came to occupy western Marxists in
light of the failure of enduring socialist revolution outside the USSR. Lukács had
demurred from the economic/materialist determinism of the likes of Stalin,
focusing on the importance of proletarian ‘consciousness’ as against bourgeois
‘ideology’, but the essays in his History and Class Consciousness (1922) had been
compiled in 1917–22, against a backdrop of revolutionary success in Russia and
his native Hungary, which may explain why, even while claiming that the emer
gence of a revolutionary consciousness was not an automatic development, he did
not provide a thorough analysis of how such a consciousness actually came into
being. Conversely Antonio Gramsci did his most important theorizing under fas
cist rule, in prison. His concept of hegemony sought to account for the strength of
obstacles to the establishment of revolutionary consciousness, which drew his
attention to the cultural sphere—the sphere of norms, traditions, legitimacy, and
the sense of the possible. Hegemony was a function of what Lukács called the
ruling classes’ ‘overwhelming resources of knowledge, culture and routine’.84
While E. P. Thompson’s monumental The Making of the English Working Class85
was criticized by later cultural historians for allowing too much influence to the
economic ‘base’, it was also criticized by more materialist Marxists for being too
concerned with the ‘superstructure’, culture and all. In a 1978 essay, Thompson
sought to counter ‘the notion that it is possible to describe a mode of production
in “economic” terms; leaving aside as secondary (less “real”) the norms, the cul
ture, the critical concepts around which this mode of production is organised’.86
Such concerns had already been ventilated through historical investigation in the
work of the literary theorist Raymond Williams in his Culture and Society,
1780–1950.87 All those historians who retained a focus on Marxist categories and
concepts, including Dorothy Thompson, Victor Kiernan, Hilton, Hill, Hobsbawm,
and Rudé, found the ‘pragmatological’, historically divergent Marx much more
useful than the ‘nomological’, determinist Marx (pp. 186–7).88 This was appropri
ate for a group of scholars who were concerned not just with social structures but
with bottom–up agency, whether in the English Peasants’ Revolt of 1381 or the
self-constitution of the English working class from the late eighteenth century.
Hilton’s work on medieval peasant movements, like Rudé’s work on the French
Revolution, exploded the stereotype of the mindless mob that was common to
anti-revolutionaries at the time of both sets of events and to some of the contem
porary ‘modernization’-oriented sociology.89
As well as straightforward historical analysis, the work of the British Marxists
often fulfilled the functions of monumental exemplarity regarding the possibil
ities of change in the present, as they reflected on past moments of actual or frus
trated change. Their work, married to a memorial commitment to the lowly and
the forgotten, is marked by an interest in revolutions, civil wars, rebels, and dis
senters. Thompson’s The Making combined the functions of History as Lesson,
Memorial, and Identity—in the sense of critical reflection on identity—as he
revealed the social struggles and ‘lost causes’ that lay beneath the surface of com
forting narratives of British institutional evolution.90
For Thompson, ‘class’, as in the self-manufacture of ‘the working class’, was a
popularly generated cultural response to changing material circumstances and
norms. We can see some of the same ideas at work in the Subaltern Studies
Collective on South Asian History, which took off from beginnings at the
University of Sussex in 1979–80. The title of the group and its anthologies indi
cated a debt to Gramsci.91 The work of its first leading light, Ranajit Guha, on
peasant society, ‘peasant consciousness’, and the associated character and under-
appreciated political significance of rural insurgency under imperialism, brought
together now familiar elements of Marxism inflected with a concern for non-elite
agency and the lives and worldviews of those so often left out of national political
narratives. Quite how far the early agenda of the journal Subaltern Studies, first
published in 1982, simply adopted the approaches and concerns of British Marxist
historians is debated, but the inheritance is significant.92 Both, in any case, inter
sected with the wider interest in ‘History from below’.
89 Rodney Hilton and Hyman Fagin, The English Rising of 1381 (London: Lawrence and Wishart,
1950); Rodney Hilton, Bond Men Made Free: Medieval Peasant Movements and the English Rising of
1381 (London: Routledge, 2003 [orig. 1973]). George Rudé, The Crowd in the French Revolution
(Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1959). See also Eric Hobsbawm and George Rudé, Captain Swing (London:
Lawrence and Wishart, 1969) and E. P. Thompson, ‘The Moral Economy of the English Crowd in the
Eighteenth Century’, Past & Present, 50 (1971), 76–136. For the historiographical contextualization,
Passmore, ‘History and Historiography since 1945’ and Eley, Crooked Line.
90 Thompson, The Making, 13.
91 See in particular Ranajit Guha, Elementary Aspects of Peasant Insurgency in Colonial India
(Delhi: Oxford University Press, 1983) and, for a further tribute to the significance of Gramsian cat
egories, Guha, Dominance without Hegemony: History and Power in Colonial India (Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press, 1998).
92 Dipesh Chakrabarty, ‘Subaltern Studies and Postcolonial Historiography’, Nepantla: Views from
South, 1:1 (2000), 9–32, who contests Arif Dirlik’s and Edward Said’s arguments about the extent of
the borrowing. Conversely, and for a position which this author sees as more persuasive, see e.g. Arif
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
History from below was not constrained, or certainly not necessarily, by con
cerns about ‘the working class’ as a class. The German version was Alltagsgeschichte,
the History of everyday life. It was pioneered by the likes of Alf Lüdtke, who fought
for a place for mundane experience and actor perspectives as against the structur
ally oriented and impersonal work—elite actors sometimes excepted—of major
powerbrokers like Wehler.93 In Britain, a pathbreaker was the History Workshop
Movement, with its openness to non-academics and associations with adult educa
tion. Methodological innovations included oral History. New work in women’s
History consolidated the progressive legacy of Power, Abram, and Clark at the LSE.
With its more radical character, more marginal status, and broader range of
interests tying ‘new’ and ‘old left’ together, British social History of the
1950s–1960s had a little more in common on the average than did sociological
American social History with the historiographical developments invigorated by
the US civil rights struggle. In the USA the civil rights struggle led the way as a
political model for new forms of mass association and political-intellectual vocal
ization. The struggle was by no means limited to the 1950s–1960s—it began much
earlier, albeit that those decades were important in the process of a very gradual
‘mainstreaming’ of African American History, which also meant that white US
historians started to make a substantial critical contribution after decades when
African American scholars largely worked alone, barring exceptions like the
Jewish Marxist historian Herbert Aptheker (1915–2003), whose American Negro
Slave Revolts appeared in 1943.94 Later nineteenth- and early twentieth-century
historiographical foundations had been laid by, amongst others, John Wesley
Cromwell (1846–1927), author of The Negro in American History (1914),
W. E. B. Du Bois (1868–1963), author of Black Reconstruction in America (1935),
and Carter G. Woodson (1875–1950). From the 1910s through the 1930s
Woodson wrote key Histories on aspects of African American social life and slav
ery in the antebellum period, and he also founded the Association for the Study
of Negro Life and History in 1915 and the Journal of Negro History in 1916, which
was renamed the Journal of African American History in 2002. In 1926 he estab
lished ‘Negro History Week’, the precursor of today’s Black History Month. A
conducive intellectual and political context in the 1920s was the Harlem
Renaissance, with its emphasis on African American culture, while in the 1930s
Dirlik, ‘The Postcolonial Aura: Third World Criticism in the Age of Global Capitalism’, Critical
Inquiry, 20:2 (1994), 328–56, here 340.
93 Alf Lüdtke (ed.), Alltagsgeschichte: zur Rekonstruktion historischer Erfahrungen und Lebensweisen
(Frankfurt am Main: Campus, 1989).
94 Herbert Aptheker, American Negro Slave Revolts (New York: Columbia University Press, 1943). I
stress ‘critical contribution’ as against apologetic accounts, e.g. Ulrich Bonnell Phillips American Negro
Slavery (New York: Appleton, 1918), which influenced ‘mainstream’ scholarship through the 1950s, as
testified to by David Brion Davis, ‘Reflections: Intellectual Trajectories: Why People Study What they
Do’, Reviews in American History, 37:1 (2009), 148–59, here 157.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
interest in the life of an oppressed minority dovetailed with some of the concerns
of Progressive US historiography, and was fed by the slave narratives collected
under the auspices of the New Deal Federal Writers’ Project. Pushing into the
1940s Benjamin Arthur Quarles (1904–96) published his doctoral dissertation on
the abolitionist Frederick Douglass in 1948 and went on to become one of the
major African American historians of the third quarter of the century. John Hope
Franklin’s (1915–2009) autobiographical Mirror to America (2005) appeared
more than sixty years after his 1943 volume The Free Negro in North Carolina,
1790–1860.95
Was the project of attending to the history of non-elites a matter of showing
what the relevant group had historically experienced, or what it had done? The
answer, predictably enough, is either and both. Accounts of slavery and discrim
ination perforce pointed to black experiences, but, especially in response to slav
ery Histories that caricatured slaves as passive victims, the portrayal of experience
fused with that of deeds of resistance in all senses of the term—spiritual, familial,
physical, political. Emphasis on deeds, whether in African American or feminist
scholarship, helped combat allegations of inferiority. Uniting the study of doing
and being was the political desideratum of registering historical presence. ‘If a
race has no history, if it has no worthwhile tradition’, wrote Woodson in the
inaugural Black History Week pamphlet, ‘it becomes a negligible factor in the
thought of the world and it stands in danger of being exterminated’. The Jamaican-
born political theorist Marcus Garvey (1887–1940) likewise felt that ‘a people
without the knowledge of their past history, origin and culture is like a tree with
out roots’.96 Towards the other end of the century, in Staying Power: The History of
Black People in Britain (1984), Peter Fryer observed that ‘traces of black life have
been removed from the British past to ensure that blacks are not part of the
British future’ so he sought to help in ‘setting the record straight’.97
In the date of its appearance, Hidden from History: 300 Years of Women’s
Oppression and the Fight Against It (1973), by the British feminist theorist
and historian Sheila Rowbotham, was in harmony with historiographical
95 Quarles’s early publications include Frederick Douglass (Washington, DC: Associated Publishers,
1948) and The Negro in the Civil War (Boston: Little, Brown and Co., 1953). John Hope Frankin, The
Free Negro in North Carolina, 1790–1860 (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1943);
Mirror to America (New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux, 2005). John Wesley Cromwell: The Negro in
American History (Washington, DC: American Negro Academy, 1914). W. E. B. Du Bois, Black
Reconstruction in America (New York: Harcourt, Brace, and Co., 1935). Woodson’s works include: The
Education of the Negro Prior to 1861 (New York: G. P. Putnam’s Sons, 1915), A Century of Negro
Migration (Washington, DC: Association of Negro Life and History, 1918), The Negro in Our History
(Washington, DC: Associated Publishers, 1922).
96 Woodson: Jeffrey Aaron Snyder, Making Black History: The Color Line, Culture, and Race in the
Age of Jim Crow (Athens: University of Georgia Press, 2018), 96–7. Garvey, and similar sentiments by
Malcolm X: Rufus Burrow, Jr, James H. Cone and Black Liberation Theology (Jefferson, NC: McFarland,
1994), 21.
97 Peter Fryer, Staying Power: The History of Black People in Britain (London: Pluto Press, 1984),
399. Thanks to Tony Kushner for pointing me to this quote.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
developments across the Atlantic. In the USA, Barbara Ehrenreich’s and Deirdre
English’s Witches, Midwives and Nurses appeared in the same year; Elizabeth
Gould Davies’s The First Sex two years earlier. The 1970s were as crucial for wom
en’s History as for second-wave feminism. Rowbotham wrote of her aspiration to
turn ‘up the top soil in the hope that others will dig deeper’, adding, ‘I know
already the woman’s movement has made many of us ask different questions of
the past’.98 There is, again, a heuristic distinction to be made between sorts of
History: on one hand writing women back into the past (‘women’s History’) and
on the other hand addressing the facts and mechanisms of patriarchy with a view
to liberation in the present (‘feminist History’). Clearly these agendas could be
fused in any given work, as Rowbotham’s title and subtitle indicate. Gerda Lerner,
who, like Rowbotham and Joan Kelly, enjoined the recovery of women’s pasts,
made her justification for History explicit with the observation that ‘patriarchy as
a system is historical: it has a beginning in history. If that is so, it can be ended by
historical process.’99
Since they were often aimed more at non-academic or only partly academic
audiences, newer Histories benefited from and contributed to the rise of ‘radical
publishers’. Neither in the mass-sales mainstream nor the university press trad
ition, these publishers routinely produce some of the most stimulating intellec
tual output in the areas of feminist, anti-racist, and socialist scholarship. Both
Rowbotham and Fryer were published by Britain’s Pluto Press, founded in the
1970s.100 Witches, Midwives and Nurses was published by the Feminist Press,
founded as a non-profit organization in 1970.
If some of the new Histories were politically forthright, or romanticizing, this
was not without good reason.101 Sometimes their authors felt more obligation to
those groups than to the national professions—not to mention states—that had
marginalized them. Much more importantly, while establishments might charge
these new Histories with politicization, such a response could elide distinctions
between History written for political reasons, History with political ramifications,
History in which uncomfortable or thesis-challenging evidence had been
excluded for political ends, and History whose content was manipulated by parts
of its audience for political reasons. As in all such discussions, we need to con
sider what this ‘politicized History’ was implicitly being contrasted with, and to
disavow any presumption of the sort evinced in the opening editorial of the
98 Sheila Rowbotham, Hidden from History (London: Pluto Press, 1973), p. x; Barbara Ehrenreich
and Deirdre English, Witches, Midwives and Nurses (New York: Feminist Press, 1973); Elizabeth
Gould Davies, The First Sex (New York: Penguin, 1971).
99 Gerda Lerner, The Creation of Patriarchy (New York: Oxford University Press, 1986), 6, cited in
Dorothy Ko, ‘Gender’, in Ulinka Rublack (ed.), A Concise Companion to History (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2011), 203–25, here 207–8.
100 Thanks again to Tony Kushner for this observation.
101 See Barbara Ehrenreich’s and Deirdre English’s reflective introduction to the second edition of
Witches, Midwives and Nurses (New York: Feminist Press, 2010).
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
Historische Zeitschrift (p. 210) that more established sorts of History were more
objective or apolitical. Nor was romanticization the sole preserve of any group or
historical school.
Nor, again, was ‘identity politics’ confined to any one identity group, which is
important to bear in mind as the aforementioned historical tendencies are cor
ralled under the heading History as Identity. History as Identity has been around
as long as History has existed, but the term identity politics was coined and
accepted into academic discourse in the 1960s–1970s. The basic idea of identity
politics is similar to the Marxist idea of class consciousness as self-awareness of
collective predicament, as opposed to the liberal bourgeois conception of politics
as negotiation of individual self-interest. Some of the manifestations of identity
politics can be described in the argot of ‘political emotion’, which is relevant in
virtue of a shift in the meaning of ‘empathy’ from its nineteenth-century meaning
as a form of cognition to the sort of affective/emotional valence that it often pos
sesses today, where it has taken on some of the meaning of ‘sympathy’. This shift
gave an added significance to the potentially essentialist claim, which can be
traced back at least as far as Gustav Droysen on the other side of the political
spectrum (pp. 214–16), that only members of group X could empathize with or
‘really understand’ the historical experience of group X—and thus that members
of other groups were actually not competent to write Histories of X.
Looking forward, a certain homogenization of within-group ‘experience’ and
‘identity’ presented problems for scholars working within the aforementioned
traditions as they sought to preserve the initial emancipatory drive of their
historical-theoretical project against contradictions emerging from within those
traditions. Alltagsgeschichte sounded problematic when one got to the Nazi period,
since German Jews were systematically excluded from the ‘everyday’ of non-Jews.
Joan Scott illustrated that Thompson’s The Making of the English Working Class was
a tale of English working men as the rational, political actors of their class, with
class given a correspondingly masculine character, and women, barring some
exceptions that proved the rule, largely in domestic or support roles.102 Equally,
social and gender History in the USA and beyond could be very shortsighted
on matters of ‘race’ as the critical social theorist bell hooks observed.103 The
postcolonial theorist Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak asked whether there really was
a homogeneous ‘peasant consciousness’ among Indian subalterns.104
There is certainly a real sense in which, as historian Priya Satia notes, inclusion
begets inclusion; once one goes down the path of amending omissions and
102 Joan Wallach Scott, Gender and the Politics of History, 30th Anniversary Edition (New York:
Columbia University Press, 2018), ch. 4.
103 bell hooks, Ain’t I a Woman? Black Women and Feminism (Boston, MA: South End Press, 1981).
104 Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak, ‘Subaltern Studies: Deconstructing Historiography’, in Ranajit
Guha and Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak (eds.), Selected Subaltern Studies (New York: Oxford University
Press, 1988), 3–32.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
digging down, one is more apt to be aware of hitherto unnoticed omissions and
hitherto unappreciated depths.105 But one cannot focus on everything at the same
time. As often as not the ‘classic’ triumvirate of social cleavages—race, class, and
‘gender’ (which really meant ‘sex’ for a long time)—joined later by sexuality, com
peted for representational space in History books, as they do up to the present.
The tensions have been ameliorated but not averted by intersectional analysis,
and it is unclear that they can be averted. If one is thinking in the emancipatory
vein, the prospect of a ‘rainbow alliance’ of the marginalized and repressed is an
attractive one, but once one has transcended binary divisions of society where the
lines of battle and solidarity are straightforward, one encounters criss-crossing
lines of power, privilege, and prejudice that can make potential allies in one
sphere into opponents in another.106
What we may say with safety is that the culture wars of the 1960s highlighted
the limitations of any purely or even primarily material analysis of society, and in
that sense dovetailed neatly with the cultural concerns of ‘western Marxism’. The
‘new left’ that emerged empowered from these conflicts was at least as concerned
with matters of identity as place in the relations of production. The fortunes of the
old left were additionally damaged by the (further) discrediting of the USSR in
Hungary and Czechoslovakia, the actions of communist parties like the PCF that
opposed the ’68ers just as much as did de Gaulle, by the end of Keynesianism in
the early 1970s, and by the rise of neo-liberalism.
Where sociology and economics had provided the main external disciplinary
inputs to north Atlantic historiography in the second and third quarters of the
twentieth century, the final quarter saw more extensive borrowings from linguis
tics, Continental philosophy, and anthropology. The ensuing historiographical
developments have sometimes been described under the headings of the ‘linguis
tic turn’ and the ‘cultural turn’. Rather than allowing the focus to be determined
by labels that mean slightly different things to different people, the intention of
this section is to probe relevant linkages and distinctions between linguistic and
cultural matters, especially with regard to different elements of the historian’s
activities. To begin with, though, let us consider another, largely non-taken ‘turn’,
this time of a literary-aesthetic sort. This discussion, while seeming further to
complicate matters, ultimately helps in clarification.
105 Priya Satia, ‘The Whitesplaining of History is Over’, The Chronicle of Higher Education,
28 March 2018, The Chronicle Review.
106 Rainbow alliance reference and problematization: Rosalind O’Hanlon and David Washbrook,
‘After Orientalism: Culture, Criticism and Politics in the Third World’, in Vinayak Chaturvedi (ed.),
Mapping Subaltern Studies and the Postcolonial (London: Verso, 2012), 191–219, here 200.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
107 Hayden White: Metahistory; The Content of the Form; and Tropics of Discourse (Baltimore: Johns
Hopkins University Press, 1978).
108 On Geertz and Darnton, Burke, What is Cultural History?, 37–8.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
109 Jonathan Hearn, Theorizing Power (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2012), 90–2.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
110 Lynn Hunt, ‘Introduction: History, Culture, and Text’, in Lynn Hunt (ed.), The New Cultural
History (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1989), 1–22, here 12.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
111 At other points Foucault’s historical agenda was comparable to that of a Cryer or a Thompson as
a more orthodox form of ‘History from below’ that wrote particular groups and actors back into the
past and generated a critical perspective on the present. Thus Foucault once wrote of the retrieval of
what he called ‘subjugated knowledges’. Retrieval involved taking seriously the perspectives—and by
extension, contra Joan Scott (see p. 290) the experience—of ‘the psychiatrized, the patient, the nurse,
the doctor . . . the knowledge of the delinquent’. This ‘retrieval’ was, obviously enough, historical schol
arship, leading to a ‘historical knowledge of struggles. . . . We have both a meticulous rediscovery of
struggles and the raw memory of fights. . . . If you like, we can give the name “genealogy” to this coup
ling together of scholarly erudition and local memories, which allows us to constitute a historical
knowledge of struggles and to make use of that knowledge in contemporary tactics.’ Foucault, Society
Must be Defended, 7–9.
112 See Jordan Goodman, ‘History and Anthropology’, in Bentley (ed.), Companion to Historiography,
783–804, here 792–4.
113 Burke, What is Cultural History?, 113 on the work of Alain Corbin.
114 All items in this list have been addressed inter alia by the Bloomsbury ‘Cultural Histories’ series.
The output of Reaktion Books covers some of the same areas and in addition addresses topics includ
ing the Earth and—in the ‘Objekt’ series—all manner of design objects.
115 Philippe Ariès, L’Enfant et la vie familiale sous l’ancien régime (Paris: Plon, 1960). Ariès’s work
has now been superseded, especially by ‘new childhood studies’ scholarship which has highlighted the
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
importance of recovering children’s perspectives and agency, rather than perpetuating their margin
alization or representation as objects of adult scrutiny. For recent work (with thanks to Louise
Jackson) see Harry Hendrick, Children, Childhood and English Society, 1880–1990 (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1997); Steven Mintz, Huck’s Raft: A History of American Childhood
(Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2004). Hendrick and Mintz have also proposed that ‘age’
be treated as a category of analysis analogous to ‘gender’.
the killing and the church’s purificatory rituals—the Huguenots were, after all,
seen as pollutants. This contextualization helped explain the use of fire and water
as methods of destruction and the desecration of corpses as a further ‘weakening’
of the spiritual threat.119 Darnton’s famous essay ‘Workers’ Revolt: The Great Cat
Massacre of the Rue Saint-Séverin’ (1984) showed why it made cultural as well as
sociological sense that a group of downtrodden Parisian apprentice printers in
the 1730s should find it amusing to slaughter the ‘privileged’ animals after a mock
trial of the same.120
History as Travel, or ‘capturing otherness’ as Darnton put it, was back on the
agenda. In a way that would have been familiar to the British historian Keith
Thomas, who also drew on anthropology to explore the bygone exotic, Darnton
wrote: ‘When we cannot get a proverb, or a joke, or a ritual, or a poem, we know
we are onto something. By picking at the document where it is most opaque, we
may be able to unravel an alien system of meaning. The thread might even lead
into a strange and wonderful world view.’ ‘And once we have puzzled through to
the native’s point of view, we should be able to roam about in his symbolic
world.’121 Getting students to ‘see the world through the eyes of others’, ‘through
the prism of another time and another place’ is an avowed aim of the cultural
historian of the Renaissance, Kenneth Bartlett.122 As a mind-broadening hermen
eutic pursuit this species of History as Travel had something in common with
History as Communion, though its benefits were less direct and the interlocutor
different. While most of the American social History of the 1960s–1970s focused
on the nineteenth and twentieth century, many more new cultural Historians
focused on medieval and early modern history, the better, presumably, for con
trast—and here there is a marked crossover with the focus, as well as the ethos, of
the microhistorians. In a 1988 work on Renaissance England the ‘new historicist’
literary theorist Stephen Greenblatt named his ‘desire to speak with the dead’.
Greenblatt coined the name ‘new historicism’, which constitutes a major point of
intersection between literary theory and new cultural History. In terms redolent
of Darnton, H. Aram Veeser described how new historicists alight ‘upon an event
or anecdote—colonist John Rolfe’s conversation with Pocahontas’ father, a note
found among Nietzsche’s papers to the effect that “I have lost my umbrella”—and
re-read it in such a way as to reveal through the analysis of tiny particulars the
119 Natalie Zemon Davis, ‘The Rites of Violence: Religious Riot in Sixteenth-Century France’, Past
and Present, 59 (1973), 51–91.
120 Robert Darnton, ‘Workers’ Revolt: The Great Cat Massacre of the Rue Saint-Séverin’ is chapter 2
of Robert Darnton, The Great Cat Massacre and Other Episodes in French Cultural History (New York:
Basic Books, 1999 [orig. 1984]).
121 Ibid. 5, 262. Keith Thomas, ‘Ways of Doing Cultural in History’, in Rik Sanders, Bas Mesters,
Reinier Kramer, and Margreet Windhorst (eds.), Balans en Perspectief van de Nederlandse
Cultuurgeschiedenis (Amsterdam: Rodopi, 1991), 65–82.
122 Kenneth R. Bartlett, ‘Cultural History Advice for Students from Professor Ken Bartlett’, online
at https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=Px1GwHyAYXs
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
behavioural codes, logics, and motive forces controlling a whole society’.123 This
literary-theoretical movement forms part of the broader neo-historicist trend,
and the term neo-historicism had to be coined in this book because ‘new his
toricism’ had already been taken.
The recognition of cultural difference across time—it cannot remotely be called
a discovery, but it can be called a re-emphasis on particular aspects of difference
and differentiation, characterized by a rebellion inter alia against a type of materi
alist thought that at its extreme dissolved questions of value or meaning into mat
ters of interest—fuelled another pre-existing justification for History: History as
Emancipation. Emancipatory History shared the premises about difference that
underpinned History as mind-broadening Travel, but it had less of an orientation
towards Communion with different people past and a more explicitly critical
agenda towards the present. The extent to which the advocates of History as
Emancipation were interested in exploring different ways of thinking ‘from the
inside’ varied: the constant was their interest in the mechanisms whereby ‘differ
ences’ are constructed and might be deconstructed. This is the school of thought
associated with Foucault, though it cannot be reduced to his thinking.
The issue is fruitfully approached through Joan Scott’s 1986 article ‘Gender as a
Category of Historical Analysis’. Gender History can be linked with new cultural
History just as women’s History from the 1960s onwards may be associated with
the social History that explored less well covered terrains of experience, contribu
tion, and identity. Gender History is concerned less with the study of women ‘in
and for themselves’ than with the way in which femininity and masculinity are
variably defined under different cultural dispensations. Natalie Davis first sug
gested to Scott that reminded us that ‘ “women” were always defined in some rela
tionship to men’, which has a structuralist ring to it. The idea of a power agenda
being involved in the construction of gendered difference also appealed to the
growing number of admirers of Foucault for whom power inhered impersonally
in relations, and it meant that concerns of power did not have to be discarded as
materialist and class analysis was downplayed. Scott wrote that ‘gender is a consti
tutive element of social relationships based on perceived differences between the
sexes’, and a ‘way’ of ‘signifying relationships of power’.124
Women’s History and gender History could both be written with emancipa
tionist goals, but that did not mean that women’s and gender historians necessar
ily approved of each others’ approaches and their implications. Consider the idea
123 Stephen Greenblatt, Shakespearean Negotiations (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1988)
1; H. Aram Veeser, introduction to H. Aram Veeser (ed.) The New Historicism (New York: Routledge,
1989), pp. ix–xvi, here p. xi.
124 Joan W. Scott, ‘Gender: A Useful Category of Historical Analysis’, The American Historical
Review, 91:5 (1986) 1053–75, here 1067. On Davis’s prompt, see Joan W. Scott, ‘Unanswered
Questions’, The American Historical Review, 113:5 (2008), 1422–30, here 1422. On changing historical
constructions of femininity, see also the work of Scott’s sometime collaborator, Denise Riley, Am I that
Name? Feminism and the Category of ‘Women’ in History (Basingstoke: Macmillan, 1988).
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
implication that patriarchy could ‘be ended by historical process’, she was build
ing on Engels’s Origins of the Family, Private Property and the State (1884).130
Semiotic analysis could affect the trappings of a social science just as much as
could Marxism or structuralism, as it attempted to say something general about
the way things are in the construction of human worlds. Some of the most prom
inent practitioners of this mode of analysis—Scott and William Sewell—were
intellectually socialized as sociologically oriented social Historians, and a residual
positivism can be identified in their work after they both took a semiotic turn. In
his Logics of History (2005), Sewell wrote of extending ‘radically the range and
ambition of cultural history’ to the point of ‘specifying the codes or paradigms
underlying meaningful practices that seem resistant to linguistic analysis and that
might conventionally be thought of precisely as the sort of “nondiscursive social
realities” that causally limit or shape discourses’.131 He claimed that ‘the social’
At points like this semiotic approaches moved from being additive to the rich
blend of existing approaches, or corrective of them in some important particu
lars, to claiming the status of a new master approach. At such points semiotic
approaches, cultural or linguistic, could be as reductive as economic or material
ist determinism.
If the basic claim of, say, new cultural History at its most imperialist is that
ways of thinking, seeing, valuing, etc. are culturally constructed, and thus that
everyone, past and present is always already constructed to think, etc., through a
particular, if changing, cultural matrix, we need to follow Peter Burke in asking
after the agents, materials, and constraints of that construction.133 If one defined
culture, or meaning, or language broadly enough then it would cover everything,
but the victory would be pyrrhic since nothing would then really be explained.
How, if at all, did factors that could not satisfactorily be accounted for under the
rubric of culture, as culture was understood by the new cultural historians,
130 Friedrich Engels, Origins of the Family, Private Property and the State (Chicago: Kerr, 1902
[German orig. 1884]); Ko, ‘Gender’, 207–8, identifies the influence of Engels on Lerner and other
feminists of her period.
131 Sewell, Logics of History, 338. 132 Ibid. 369.
133 e.g. Burke, What is Cultural History?, ch. 5.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
influence the culture? How far were people choicelessly following a cultural script
or interpreting in accordance with a governing power-discourse? One among
many definitions of the cultural historian’s aim is ‘discover[ing] the ways in
which past actors sought to give meaning to their lives through symbol, ritual
and narrative’,134 which suggests some active seeking by agents. As to language,
Hunt’s important claim that ‘Revolutionary language did not simply reflect the
realities of revolutionary changes and conflicts, but rather was itself transformed
into an instrument of political and social change’ raises as many questions as it
answers. The fact that that language was ‘itself transformed’ suggests some extra-
linguistic power doing the transforming, or some extra-linguistic change in the
world that caused the language to gain new purchase.
Theoretical enquiry here has not been aided by the lack of consistency with
which the case has been made by major proponents, though we must allow for
the hyperbole that accompanies innovation in any field of enquiry. Just two pages
before stressing the primacy of semiotics, and thus of semiotic code-breaking,
Sewell noted that physical substances such as the human body and the natural
and built environment are subject to ‘other determinations than the semiotic’, and
that semiotic and non-semiotic elements of social life are intertwined.135 Consider
also Gareth Stedman Jones, who was explicit in his debts to Saussurean linguistics
in his pathbreaking essays Languages of Class (1984). The insertions in italics
within the brackets in the body of Jones’s text serve to highlight the inconsisten
cies of the promised explanation.
In general, whether steeped in the older traditions of labour history or the newer
conventions of social history, historians have looked everywhere except at
changes in political discourse itself to explain changes in political behav
iour. . . . The implicit assumption is of civil society as a field of conflicting social
groups or classes whose opposing interests will find rational expression in the
political arena. Such interests, it is assumed, pre-exist their expression . . .
In order to rewrite the political history of the ‘working class’ or ‘working
classes’, we should start out from the other end of the chain. [A strong claim.]
Language disrupts any simple notion of the determination of consciousness by
social being because it is itself part of social being. [A weaker claim: language is
‘part of social being’, not determinant of it.] We cannot therefore decode political
language to reach a primal and material expression of interest since it is the dis
cursive structure of political language which conceives and defines interest in
the first place. [Back to a stronger claim, albeit with a narrower conception of
134 Dan Stone, ‘Introduction: The Holocaust and Historical Methodology’, in Dan Stone (ed.), The
Holocaust and Historical Methodology (New York: Berghahn, 2012), 1–19, here 13.
135 Sewell, Logics of History, 367.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
In a sympathetic and sensitive work on voices and the victims of the Inquisition
John Arnold deploys the Foucauldian concept of ‘discourse’ and tries to explain
change (or perhaps just the possibility of change) with reference only to the work
ings of discourse. In the process he replicates the ambiguities of Foucault’s own
thought on power and discourse. In the vein of History as Practical Lesson,
Arnold concludes that
Discourses construct and position us as subjects; but they also allow (or, as
I have argued, demand) an excess of speech and action. In confronting that
excess, change occurs. And where there is change, there is hope. We are not,
as some have suggested, merely prisoners of discourse, we are also its—and
our—guardians and servants. But if we have agency, there may be other roles we
can choose.137
Discourses demand something, or perhaps they just allow it, but then that some
thing can be used to act against the demands of discourses. We are prisoners,
servants, and guardians of the same thing, with the ability to rebel and choose not
136 Gareth Stedman Jones, Languages of Class (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1984)
21–2, and 20 on Saussure. The first nine lines of Jones’s p. 24 could be subjected to similar treatment.
137 John H. Arnold, Inquisition and Power (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 2001), 228.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
to fulfil any of those functions (if discourse allows it?). Inmates of supermax peni
tentiaries may or may not feel that the carceral metaphor is apt.
Similarly, Richard Biernacki has shown of Joan Scott’s analysis of discourses on
economic matters among Parisian garment makers in the 1840s that in practice,
whatever her claims about the primacy of language in constituting reality, Scott
ends up positing economic distress as the cause of the relevant linguistic framing.
Likewise he shows that in her discussion of Chartism she ends up ‘assuming the
fit’ between a discourse on propertylessness ‘and the social positions of property
less agents’, which problematizes any idea that the discourse drove the constitu
tion of the outlook of the propertyless.138 In works such as those examined by
Biernacki, Scott is clearly trying, albeit not entirely successfully, less to subvert
than to invert the determinant relationship proposed in elements of Marxist
thought between the ideological ‘superstructure’ (now labelled discourse, culture,
etc.) and the material ‘base’. Elsewhere, in a famous essay ‘The Evidence of
Experience’ Scott oscillates between stronger and weaker claims as to the causal
powers of the semiotic. She brings under critique the sort of ‘identity History’
associated with the civil rights movement and second wave feminism, with its
recounting of the experiences and agency of the groups in question. First we are
given the weaker, additive claim: ‘Treating the emergence of a new identity as a
discursive event is not to introduce a new form of linguistic determinism, nor to
deprive subjects of agency. It is to refuse a separation between “experience” and
language.’ Then we are confronted with the stronger, supplanting position, which
better reflects the tenor of her essay: ‘subjects are constituted discursively’, and
historians should ‘take as their project not the reproduction and transmission of
knowledge said to be arrived at through experience, but the analysis of the pro
duction of that knowledge itself ’. (Why historians may not do both is unclear).
Scott claims that the latter approach ‘does not undercut politics by denying
the existence of subjects, it instead interrogates the processes of their [i.e. the
subjects’] creation’. But this ‘clarification’ comprises a distinction without a
difference unless one allows that after the moment of their ‘creation’, subjects
can somehow act upon reflection, perhaps in the light of new experiences,
which would rather undermine the imperative to study the ‘creation’ rather
than what comes after it.139
138 Richard Biernacki, ‘Method and Metaphor after the New Cultural History’, in Victoria E. Bonnell
and Lynn Hunt (eds.), Beyond the Cultural Turn (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1999),
62–92, here 68 and 86 (n. 26). See also Biernacki, ‘Work and Culture in Class Ideologies’, in
John R. Hall (ed.), Reworking Class (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1997), 169–92, here 174.
139 Joan W. Scott, ‘The Evidence of Experience’, Critical Inquiry 17:4 (1991), 773–97, here, in order
of the quotations in my main text, 792–3, 793, 797.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
140 On the essays ‘we’ve all read . . . where Freud and Foucault, Baudrillard and Booth are each and
all cited as sources of analytic authority without concern for the incompatibilities among them’: Bill
Brown, cited in Stanley Fish, ‘Theory’s Hope’, Critical Inquiry, 30:2 (2004), 374–8, here 375. Note, too,
that when I use ‘theory’ here it is as a shorthand for the most self-conscious correctives of recent gen
erations; all History is theory-laden in some respects, and when ‘theory’ is used as loosely as it is in so
many of these debates, historians not persuaded by some of the new theories can claim to be deploy
ing their own theories all the time. So it is rarely a case of theoretically-informed thought versus non-
theoretically-informed thought.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
History and anthropology, Robert Mandrou on the notion of the baroque, Roland
Barthes on Jean Racine, and Lucien Goldmann on Chagall. The 1970 volume fea
tured work on Etruscan city planning, Indian gods, Sudanese gold, Bedouins,
fairy-tales, Freud, climate History, Peruvian cathedrals, brain physiology, and the
’68 student movement.141
The key twentieth-century French theorists drew on yet more august Germanic
predecessors. The Lebensphilosophie or ‘philosophy of life’ that culminated in
Heidegger and thinkers of a different political persuasion like Ortega y Gasset
had roots in the thought of Dilthey as well as Nietzsche, and of every hermeneut
who was dissatisfied with the abstractions and formalism of Kantians and the sci
entism of the sociological positivists and sought to preserve other ways of
knowing the human in all its cultural variety. Consider, for instance, Dilthey’s
conceptualization of the individual as constituted at the meeting points of various
social, cultural, economic, and political influences (pp. 225–6): this conceptual
ization is not so very far from Foucault’s vision in which the individual’s con
sciousness is constructed at the intersection of various discourses. Like
neohistoricism, the entire postmodern critique of the idealized ‘Enlightenment’
hermetic/punctal/self-sufficient ‘subject’ has debts to the contextualist theories of
Hamann, Herder, and Historismus. Hermeneutic and historical enquiry provided
one of the major routes away from traditional philosophy with its concern for
abstractions and universals. The rejection of questions of ‘first philosophy’
prompted one thinker to label much ‘continental’ thought of the last 150 years or
so as ‘antiphilosophy’.142 Above all else, the attention to particular contexts is one
of the major ways in which Continental philosophy distinguishes itself from fore
going philosophy and contemporary analytical philosophy. ‘Context’, and the
particularity that goes along with it, is something that historians are good with in
practice even if not necessarily in theory.
Historians can also combine an interest in situated/contextualized being with
an interest in becoming, as they address the relationships between context and
process, structure and agency, continuity and change. ‘Process philosophy’, from
Hegel through Nietzsche, indicates the impact of historical thought on philoso
phy.143 At the same time, while in his The Postmodern Condition (1979) Jean-
François Lyotard defined postmodernism is a matter of ‘incredulity towards
metanarratives’ of the Hegelian sort, i.e. philosophies of history, postmodernists
scarcely have claim to being the first to develop this scepticism.144 As Foucault
141 For all of which and more see George Huppert, ‘The Annales Experiment’, in Bentley (ed.),
Companion to Historiography, 873–88, here 880, 882.
142 Boris Groys, Introduction to Antiphilosophy (London: Verso, 2012).
143 See generally David D. Roberts, Nothing But History: Reconstruction and Extremity After
Metaphysics (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1995).
144 Jean-François Lyotard, The Postmodern Condition (Manchester: Manchester University Press,
1984 [French orig. 1979]), p. xxiv.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
attested, many artisanal historians had already rejected Hegel alongside all his
predecessor and successor schemes (p. 251).
The emphasis on change and temporality sets History apart from some of the
most influential forms of anthropology. The criticisms of structuralism by Jacques
Derrida echo the words of anthropologist Edward Evans-Pritchard before him,
namely that social anthropologists had been writing ‘cross-sections of history,
integrative descriptive accounts’ depicting worlds ‘at a moment of time’.145 While
agreeing with structuralism’s contention about the conventional nature of lan
guage Derrida dismissed it on other grounds. Following Louis Althusser’s and
Fernand Braudel’s ideas of different temporalities or durées coexisting, and criti
cizing the absence of a historical dimension in general from the static structural
ist analysis, Derrida underlined how structuralism imputed too great a coherence
to any social order and gave the observer an illusion of being able to read the
order from some sort of privileged point of access.146 Derridean poststructural
ism was partly established in rejection of structuralism’s scientistic pretensions.147
It is anti-predictive in its emphasis on the interplay of structure and event/contin
gency/temporality. If anything, it can only work on the basis of a last instance
appeal to heed specificity, incongruity, the particular that is never subsumed by
the general law or theory or structural account, which would scarcely surprise the
fairly conventional idiographic historian. Althusser dubbed his own theory of
change, with its different ‘temporalities’ and all, ‘matérialisme aléatoire’, ‘aleatory
materialism’:148 ‘aleatory’ means dependent upon chance rather than determin
ation, and whatever Althusser’s theoretical elaboration it brings to mind nothing
so much as Harold Macmillan on the disruptive power of ‘events, dear boy, events’.
Analogously, Derridean deconstruction demands that the reader be alive to
resistances in the text, precisely so it does not assume the reductive capacity of
any reading that is too keen to impose some theoretical grid on its subject
matter.
Deconstruction takes a different tack from, say, biblical hermeneutics, which
seeks to reconcile the particular and the general within a text, and to transcend
ostensible contradictions.149 Deconstruction is best known as a hermeneutics of
145 Evans-Pritchard cited in Aletta Biersack, Clio in Oceania: Toward a Historical Anthropology
(Washington, DC: Smithsonian Institution Press, 1991), 1.
146 On explicit and implicit criticisms of structuralism see Derrida, Writing and Difference, 52–3,
197 and 351 ff.; and Derrida, Margins of Philosophy, 307–30. For Derrida’s position on different tem
poralities in the Althusserian vein, Jacques Derrida, Positions (Chicago: University of Chicago Press,
1982), 57–9.
147 Michael Peters, ‘(Posts-) Modernism and Structuralism: Affinities and Theoretical Innovations’,
Sociological Research Online, 4:3 (1999) http://www.socresonline.org.uk/4/3/peters.html
148 Louis Althusser, Écrits philosophiques et politiques, vol. 1 (Paris: Éditions Stock, 1994), 21
and passim.
149 For an attempt to establish relationships between Derridean hermeneutics and its more
‘conventional’ predecessors, John D. Caputo, Radical Hermeneutics: Repetition, Deconstruction, and
the Hermeneutic Project (Bloomington: University of Indiana Press, 1987).
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
disruption, which can turn parts against the whole, and it is used in interrogating
the claims to authority in legal or philosophical texts. It is alive to the constructed,
conventional nature of binary oppositions, which is its debt to structuralist pre
cepts, and it owes to psychoanalysis its attention to minor textual ‘tics’ that may
be tantamount to Freudian slips. None of this means that deconstruction neces
sarily de-legitimates the argument of the text on which it operates, but it does
mean that space is opened up for alternative readings than that which the author
seems most obviously to be intending.150 However indiscriminately deconstruc
tion was applied as it reached the level of high intellectual fashion in literary the
ory—Derrida regretted the extent to which the interpretative ‘freeplay’ he had
spawned had been accorded too great a status, preferring the more limited ‘play’,
jeu—it engaged with many elements of a text and as such represents an advance
on, say, Hayden White’s reductive formalism, with its proximity to structuralism
and its programmer’s talk of codes.151
The issue of discriminate application obtains when it comes to deconstruction’s
relevance for works of History. Unlike philosophical or legal or theological tracts
about how things ‘just are’, or ‘must be’, or ‘ought to be’, works of History are gen
erally concerned with making claims on how things contingently were, or contin
gently came to be. Historians do not—or certainly ought not—claim for their
work the same sort of conceptual completeness or closure that are often claimed
for the other sorts of text. (Even in their primary task of explaining some devel
opment or illuminating some past world of experience historians should know
that their work is incomplete.) In other words, Histories have none of the sup
posed axiomatic coherence that some might contend deconstruction exists to
scrutinize.152 Indicatively, when Derrida reviewed Foucault’s Folie et déraison
there was nothing distinctively ‘deconstructive’ about his essay, nothing in
150 There is more to it than this of course. An excellent account is Simon Critchley, The Ethics of
Deconstruction: Derrida and Levinas (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 1999). Thanks to Guy
Halsall for discussion on these matters.
151 To other literary analysts White claimed that the greater ‘utility’ of his semiological method
over the utility of any content-based approach was ‘quantitative—it could ‘account for more of the
elements of any given text’. While enjoining historians to liberate their subjectivity from a conservative
historical idiom, he criticized other literary theorists for basing their analyses on ‘personal taste, incli
nation, or ideological commitment’. Instead, he prescribed a method that sought ‘to characterize the
types of messages emitted [by a text] in terms of the several codes in which they are cast and to map
the relationship among the codes thus identified both as a hierarchy of codes and a sequence of their
elaboration’. All White quotes from Russell Jacoby’s analysis of White in Jacoby, ‘A New Intellectual
History’, in Elizabeth Fox-Genovese and Elisabeth Lasch-Quinn (eds.), Reconstructing History
(London, Routledge, 1999), 94–118, here 100–1. For White’s disparaging of deconstruction and the
poststructuralist turn, see his chapter ‘The absurdist moment in contemporary literary theory’ in
White, Tropics of Discourse, ch. 12, pp. 261–82.
152 Critchley, Ethics of Deconstruction, 2, says that ‘the pattern of reading produced in the decon
struction of—mostly, but by no means exclusively—philosophical texts has an ethical structure’.
Though qualified, this statement implies that the nature of the text itself is relevant to the relevance of
deconstructing it. See also Umberto Eco, ‘Intentio lectoris: The State of the Art’, Differentia, 2 (1998),
147–68, here 166. Christopher Norris, Derrida (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1987),
20–7, 52–60, addresses the literature–philosophy nexus, as well as debunking the ‘freeplay’ element.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
structures change while old forms may express new functions or old functions
may find expression in new form’,156 which is not far from Nietzsche’s point that
‘the whole history of a “thing”, an organ, a tradition can . . . be a continuous chain
of signs, continually revealing new interpretations and adaptations’.157 To this
problematic the poststructuralist would add the uncertain stance of the inter
preter in the ever-changing, multi-contextual present. Derrida equated ‘there is
no outside-text’ (hors-texte), sometimes translated as ‘there is nothing outside the
text’, with there is no ‘outside-context’, sometimes translated as ‘there is nothing
outside context’. Everything is interpreted through conceptual schemes rather
than just apprehended, and these schemes, relating as they do to other interpret
ations, present, and past, are never transparent. There is no space that exists in a
state of separation from context.158 Far from negating any attempts to interpret,
Derrida’s point was that all that was left was interpretation, of the diverse and
often conflicting elements of one’s own lifeworld and of other lifeworlds.159 This
did not mean just any old interpretation, irrespective of intelligence, erudition, or
procedural ethos, so we may discard the ‘anything goes’ idea that was sometimes
associated with poststructuralism; as Derrida put it in a related connection, ‘it
should be possible to invoke rules of competence, criteria of discussion and of
consensus, good faith, lucidity, rigor, criticism, and pedagogy’.160 Again, contra
structuralism and other positivisms, he disavowed a final master interpretation
that claimed some objective grounding in semiotic codes or logics (a similar
objective grounding to that once claimed by quantitative methodologists) that
would situate the investigator outside the interpretative process. Derrida took it
as a Gadamerian given that the interpretative process would be a fusion of the
interpreter’s horizon(s) of meaning—a horizon that was contextually shaped in
the present—with the set of contextual meanings bound up with the object of the
interpretation. That fusion is one of the reasons why the deconstructionist rejects
the idea that any reading can finally establish the meaning of a text.161
Thinking to rationales for History and analogous interpretative acts, there is,
by Derrida’s thinking, always the possibility of something like an authentic
encounter with another world for the interpreter who is sufficiently open to the
possibility of embracing interpretation in its unknown potential. Such an event-
like encounter, or ‘interruption’, can expand or alter the interpreter’s own sym
bolic world. In the theoretical jargon, there is potential for the hermeneutic
156 E. P. Thompson, Persons and Polemics: Historical Essays (London: Merlin, 1994), 213.
157 Nietzsche, On the Genealogy of Morality, Second Essay, §12, at p. 51.
158 Jacques Derrida, Limited Inc. (Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 1988), 136. See also
9, 148, 152.
159 John D. Caputo, The Prayers and Tears of Jacques Derrida: Religion Without Religion
(Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1997), 276–7.
160 Derrida, Limited Inc., 146. See also 144.
161 On Derrida’s debts to Gadamer, see Michael N. Forster, ‘Hermeneutics’, 66–8.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
sublime.162 (The link here to the broader preoccupation of mid- and later
twentieth-century French philosophy with the structure-busting ‘event’ is not at
all coincidental—and note that Althusser also called his ‘aleatory materialism’ the
‘matérialisme de la rencontre’ or materialism of the encounter. If we wished to go
further back we could trace elements of such concern to religious notions of
epiphany and kairos.163) Following this reasoning as applied to History, studying
the past can be a species of Travel in a stronger sense than just collecting photos
for an album. If, as is now a commonplace, the practice of History tells us about
the present, then studying the past can also alter us in the present, just not by
handing us the decoding machine.
In recent generations, especially since the ‘new cultural History’ one supposes, it
has been more professionally advantageous to be a new something than an old
one. To be self-referential, I was labelled a practitioner of the ‘new transnational
trend’ in History for a work on the international origins and aftermaths of the
Armenian genocide.164 The label captured an important aspect of what I was up
to, though had I been asked at the time of writing the book I would have mum
bled something about combining diplomatic, political, and social History as a
contribution to ‘genocide studies’—the ‘studies’ bit of which, as in medieval stud
ies or queer studies, denotes an interdisciplinary approach to which History can
contribute.
Sometimes I have also described my work as ‘new international History’.
Where the ‘transnational’ label captured the important regional and cross-border
dynamics of my project as regards knock-on effects between developments in the
southern Balkans, Anatolia, and the Russian-ruled Caucasus, the ‘international’
moniker worked a little better for the elements of geo-strategy, foreign policy, and
diplomacy that came into play when further removed powers, including Britain,
France, and the USA, were involved. As it happens transnational History owes
162 Paul Patton, ‘Events, Becoming and History’, in Jeffrey A. Bell and Claire Colebrook (eds.),
Deleuze and History (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2009), 33–53, here 41–3; Derrida,
Writing and Difference, 74: on dialogue ‘between that which exceeds the totality and the closed totality’
and more generally Writing and Difference, 193–211. The concepts of openness and the hermeneutic
sublime, etc., show Derrida’s debts to the work of the philosopher Emmanuel Levinas (1906–95) on
the ethic of relationship to the ‘Other’, notably in regard of the appearance of the ‘face’ of the other. On
this relationship see Critchley, Ethics of Deconstruction.
163 This is true of Levinas (see previous note), for whom the ‘face’ of the other is akin to the face of
god. See also on the connections between philosophy and theology in some twentieth-century
Continental thought Ward Blanton and Hent de Vries (eds.), Paul and the Philosophers (New York:
Fordham University Press, 2013).
164 Jay Winter, review of Donald Bloxham, The Great Game of Genocide (Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 2005), in European History Quarterly, 38:1 (2008), 126–8, here 126.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
a significant debt to the ‘older’ area studies tradition, which suggests that some of
the ‘new’ Histories are really conceptually expanded versions of prior sorts,
evincing the influence of the major twentieth-century ‘turns’ in their additive
and corrective manifestations. The new political History is a case in point.165
Since roughly the end of the Cold War global and world History have devel
oped major significance. With the disappearance of the ‘second world’, non-
aligned status also became meaningless. Much of what had been problematically
called the ‘third world’ had already been incorporated into the economic struc
tures of international capitalism. After the downfall of the USSR most of the rest
of it was incorporated too, alongside Russia and the other formerly Soviet states.
‘One world’ was the result, albeit that some parts of it were ‘developed’ and some
still ‘developing’. ‘Globalization’ was the buzzword for the dynamic by which dif
ferent parts of the world were connected. Connectivity, embodied in the rise and
rise of multinational corporations, labour mobility, cheaper travel, and freer
finance flows, encouraged a re-focusing away from the nation-state and towards
the forces that transcended national boundaries. The History of international law
and international political institutions received a boost for much the same
reasons.
Historians were also encouraged to think backwards to earlier moments of glo
balization, such as the nineteenth-century heyday of the British empire. The old
economic theory of ‘hegemonic stability’—where stability referred to the oper
ations of the international economy rather than the lives of people affected by the
hegemon’s actions—meant that one need not jettison the study of empire in order
to partake of one of the new Histories. As to the new global hegemon, American-
led armed interventions, after the successful prosecution of the 1991 Gulf war
had ameliorated the ‘Vietnam syndrome’, and especially after the terrorist attacks
of 11 September 2001, were but another sign that national destinies were not
entirely in the hands of national leaders and domestic majorities, despite
decolonization.
It was not just modern or ‘modernizing’ empires that piqued the interest.
Decentring the nation-state prompted renewed attention to other sorts of polity, a
range of empires included, that might previously have been deemed irrelevant to
the post-1918 or post-1945 worlds in which nation-states proliferated. Conversely,
with the emphasis on continuity rather than contrast, for all of the political
imperative for postcolonial states to develop Histories of and for the nation-state,
the border-transcending forces of the present surely also prompted scholars to
165 Steven Fielding, ‘Political History’, and Patrick Finney, ‘International History’, online respect
ively at:http://www.history.ac.uk/makinghistory/resources/articles/political_history.html http://www.
history.ac.uk/makinghistory/resources/articles/international_history.html
See also Allan G. Bogue, ‘United States: The “New” Political History’, Journal of Contemporary
History, 3:1 (1968), 5–27.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
pierce the ‘periodization blinders that prevent scholars from finding commonal
ities between the colonial and national periods’.166
Precisely what defines global and world History respectively is to some extent
in the eye of the beholder, but some generalizations are possible. The journal
World History was only established in 1990, but world History has been practised
in a recognizable form since at least the Enlightenment. It treats the world as its
unit of analysis and is concerned with trends and tendencies that are observable
in or across the boundaries of many societies. There is some fusion between world
History and global History in works that treat the world as an interconnected
whole. The scholarship of William H. McNeill from the 1960s and 1970s exempli
fies, as it addressed the interactions of different cultures, as opposed to painting
a Spenglerian portrait of monads wending their own way through time without
really influencing one another.
Global History tends to be associated more with the processes of globalization
and its antecedents. We should note the paths broken by the neo-Marxist school
of ‘world systems theory’, which set itself against the precepts of ‘modernization
theory’, and drew in its turn on ‘dependency theory’ and ultimately on Lenin’s and
Rosa Luxemburg’s theories of imperialism. Perhaps it is no coincidence that a
Marxist anthropologist, Eric Wolf, should have been so prominent in illustrating
the relations between different peoples across the globe while countering a stereo
type of westerners and ‘the west’ as historical agents acting on more passive ‘oth
ers’. In global History the emphasis is on connections between parts of the whole
(the globe) and as such it is perfectly possible to write a global History of a village,
or indeed a person, as long as one embeds that object in relation to things spa
tially removed. One is apt to read quite a lot about cultural exchange, explorers,
commerce, and commodities from spices to opium to cotton, and, to use a term
from postcolonial theory, ‘hybridity’.167
If much global History and world History tends to be practised these days in a
way that decentres the European or occidental experience, thus providing an
important corrective to earlier Eurocentric accounts, this is a development more
at the level of historical content than historical method or concept. Put in the
terms of the postcolonial theorist Dipesh Chakrabarty, such ‘provincialization’ of
the west as has occurred in historiography within the global north-west has been
166 Jacob Blanc and Frederico Freitas, ‘Introduction’, in Jacob Blanc and Frederico Freitas (eds.), Big
Water: The Making of the Borderlands Between Brazil, Argentina, and Paraguay (Tuczon: University of
Arizona Press, 2018) 3–21, here 10.
167 For similar distinctions between the overlapping spheres of global and world History see Diego
Olstein, Thinking History Globally (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan 2013). William H. McNeill’s
works, some of which do have Eurocentric aspects, include in their number The Rise of the West: A
History of the Human Community (Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1963); A World History (New
York: Oxford University Press, 1967). As to Eric Wolf: Europe and the ‘People Without History’
(Berkeley: University of California Press, 1982).
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
more a matter of empirical focus than anything else.168 The great ‘turns’ of
twentieth-century historiography—social, cultural, linguistic—and what were in
their moment the avant-garde theories associated with these turns—Marxism,
structuralism, poststructuralism, serried literary and anthropological movements—
were embedded in western intellectual trends and often reflected western cultural
problems. This is not to suggest a hermetic seal separating western from non-
western trends; we are dealing in generalizations rather than categorical divides.
And it is certainly not to suggest that only ‘western’ minds could have conceived
of these theories. The point of dwelling on the conceptual self-referentiality of
much mainstream north-western historiography is as oft before, to highlight
regrettable inequality along the north-west/south-east cleavage. The matter is
important because of the still-great influence in the wider world of north-western
academies and their fashions.
Within north-western academies the tide of cultural History has ebbed but the
‘cultural History of X’ tradition (p. 282) remains influential, as in Histories of the
body, bodily experiences, or emotions. Indeed, given the thoroughly historicizing
thrust of the ‘affective turn’, it does no conceptual harm to see it as a subset of the
new cultural History.169 At the same time, it is eminently possible for the study of,
say, emotions, to be fused with the enduring study of History ‘from below’, as is
urged by the American Marxist historian and one-time student of E. P. Thompson,
James R. Barrett, in his recent essay collection History from the Bottom Up and the
Inside Out: Ethnicity, Race, and Identity in Working-Class History (2017).170
Within the broad ambit of semiotic analysis, the Foucauldian input is
variable, but has certainly shaped ‘subaltern’ historical studies since the earlier
Gramscian–Thompsonian days of that movement. Postcolonial theory, which
is obviously not coextensive with all the History produced in postcolonial
states, is deeply imbued with power theories alongside its critical concern for
linguistic–cultural binaries like civilized/uncivilized. Looking at the historio
graphical traditions of the author’s own country, imperial History, the ‘new
imperial History included’, could do with a stronger dose of postcolonial theory
to complement its traditional strengths in political and economic analysis and in
the relevant social History of the metropole.
Intellectual History has followed the trajectory of neo-historicism characteris
tic of so much twentieth-century historiography, and has enjoyed something of a
171 Quote from Stephan Collini, ‘The Identity of Intellectual History’, in Richard Whatmore and
Brian Young (eds.), A Companion to Intellectual History (London: Wiley, 2016), 7–18, here 10. On the
role of political thought and the History of science, see p. 9. See pp. 10–11 on the recent growth of
intellectual History, and the entirety of the essay for an assessment of the state of the field. Skinner’s
debts to Austin’s language theory, and Skinner’s broader hermeneutic philosophy are outlined early in
Skinner, ‘Hermeneutics and the Role of History’, New Literary History, 7:1 (1975), 209–32. As to ‘verti
cal’ versus ‘horizontal’ approaches, see Collini, ‘Intellectual History’ at: http://www.history.ac.uk/
makinghistory/resources/articles/intellectual_history.html
172 See, for instance, John Onians, Neuroarthistory: From Aristotle and Pliny to Baxandall and Zeki
(New Haven: Yale University Press, 2007); Daniel Lord Smail, On Deep History and the Brain
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
Some strands of scientifically oriented History have elicited claims that cultural
differentiation and associated neo-historicism have over-egged the pudding, and
that a Ciceronian view of History’s role as teacher of life should instead be reacti
vated.173 Relevant reasons were elaborated in 2010 by the literary theorist
Marshall Gregory. He based his advocacy of a new ethical turn in literary criti
cism partly on the ‘new empiricist’ work on common human ‘biocultural’ and
cognitive heritages. In a swift summary he begins with philosophers including
Mark Johnson and Richard Eldridge174 who argue that
instead of human beings being creatures of social construction ‘all the way
down’, human beings have a nature in which, not very far down at all, lies a vast
network of inclinations, dispositions, neural programming, and perceptual
protocols that come installed in every human being’s brain as a part of our evo
lutionary heritage. . . . In 1991 Mary Midgley published Can’t We Make Moral
Judgments?, and in 1992 Robert Louden published Morality and Moral Theory:
A Reappraisal and Reaffirmation, both of which argue that ethics comes neither
from transcendental sources nor entirely from culture, but from intrinsic human
needs that get mediated and tweaked by culture but that are not created by
culture. . . . In 1996 Steven Mithen published . . . The Prehistory of the Mind, giving
readers a sense of the vastness of time in which evolutionary pressures shaped
the human brain, and, thus, also shaped many features of human cognition,
emotion, perception, and interpersonal protocols, such as ethics.175
(Berkeley: University of California Press, 2008); Iain McGilchrist, The Master and his Emissary: The
Divided Brain and the Making of the Western World (New Haven: Yale University Press, 2009). See also
the list in Caroline W. Bynum, ‘Perspectives, Connections & Objects: What’s Happening in History
Now?’, Daedalus (Winter 2009), 71–86, here 77–8.
173 Wolf Schäfer, ‘Knowledge and Nature: History as the Teacher of Life Revisited’, Nature and
Culture, 2:1 (2007) 1–9.
174 Mark Johnson, The Body in the Mind: The Bodily Basis of Meaning, Imagination, and Reason
(Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1987); Richard Eldridge On Moral Personhood: Philosophy,
Literature, Criticism, and Self-Understanding (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1989).
175 Marshall Gregory, ‘Redefining Ethical Criticism: The Old vs. the New’, Journal of Literary
Theory, 4:2 (2010), online at: http://www.jltonline.de/index.php/articles/article/view/287/879
176 Clifford Geertz, ‘Anti Anti-Relativism’, American Anthropologist, New Series, 86:2 (1984),
263–78, here 268.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
For the same reasons one may also take issue with the historian of religion and
postmodernist Callum G. Brown, who claims that morality’s ‘absence of con
stancy is especially noticeable for those alive in the last 60 years as western society
has undergone the most dramatic shift in its sexual, racial and legal morality’.177
Far from closing the case, Brown begs the question about variables, comparators,
and the relative magnitude of the relevant differences. By way of making the con
trast with a certain representation of pre-modern historical consciousness,
Zachary Schiffman suggests that were we today ‘to ask ourselves whether we
would be different had we been born ten years earlier or later, most of us would
automatically answer in the affirmative—while dismissing the question as too
obvious’.178 ‘Different’, certainly, but how different?
The present work has proffered particular views on change and continuity, dif
ference and similarity, in a discipline of thought that counts the study of just those
duos among its major concerns. Specifically, the objects of concern have been
justifications for History, which means what the study of the past has been
thought to ‘do’ for historians and their audiences. There is no consensus as to jus
tification today and there never has been but interestingly enough the menu of
options over which historians still argue has not changed much in two and a half
thousand years. To conclude the book, let us assess the justifications head-on.
177 Callum G. Brown, Postmodernism for Historians (Harlow: Pearson, 2005), 145. Emphasis added.
178 Zachary Sayre Schiffman, ‘Historicizing History/Contextualizing Context’, New Literary
History, 42:3 (2011), 477–98, here 496.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
8
Justifying History Today
Introduction
This chapter tackles rationales for History on their own merits, in and for the
here-and-now. As well as considering the relatively young rationales of History as
Emancipation and History as Therapy, it returns to those that have existed for
millennia, namely History as: Entertainment; Memorialization; Speculative
Philosophy; Practical Lesson; Moral Lesson; Travel; Method; Communion; and
Identity. It considers which rationales still have any currency, concluding in
favour of all but Speculative Philosophy, Moral Lesson, and Communion in its
original sense. It then assesses the ones that do have currency for their coherence,
before making suggestions of its own.
Predictably enough, in most cases coherence depends upon how each rationale
is interpreted and what is promised on its behalf. For instance while History as
Travel can broaden the mind, as its proponents suggest, it cannot of itself foster
the virtue of tolerance. Your author is less sanguine than many about the pros-
pects for History as Emancipation, and more optimistic than many about forms
of History as Practical Lesson. History as Method has something going for it but
even on its own best ethical terms it needs to be bolstered by some substantivist
concerns, meaning concerns related to the content of the past rather than just to
procedures for researching and writing History. And when we come to the slightly
less exalted claims by which History as Method translates to the historian’s ‘trans-
ferable skills’, the vocations to which the skills are transferred often do not need or
even desire the more holistic critical ethos that is supposed to underpin their
deployment.
It would be better to say that coherence is addressed where necessary, as it is
not in the case of History as Entertainment. One simply is or is not entertained,
and it is debatable how fruitful the discussion is as to whether one ought or ought
not be. The fact that many people do seem to find History entertaining, as judged
by broadcasting and bookshops, might be thought rationale enough for it. In an
academic world where more and more emphasis is put upon measurable results
and monetary value the peculiar ‘utility’ of merely finding something interesting
or enjoyable ought perhaps to be celebrated. At the same time it does seem, meas-
ured again in terms of broadcasting and bookshops, that people are especially
entertained by particular sorts of History rather than just anything that happens
to be historical in focus, so the Entertainment rationale is generally alloyed with
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
other rationales. A theme running through the chapter and brought to the fore in
the section ‘Knowledge and Human Interests’ involves the tricky question, arising
from a rationale like Entertainment, of what it is for something to be intrinsically
interesting, or important, as opposed to being more instrumentally relevant.
Given crossovers between certain classes of rationale this chapter will not allot
equal or equally explicit attention to all. Thus the case of Memorialization is sub-
sumed within discussion of the Identity and Lesson genres. History as Identity
remains arguably the most important of all the substantivist rationales: it is cer-
tainly the most significant politically, which is why this chapter and thus the book
is crowned with a discussion of it. History as Identity is so often at issue even
when the identity question is addressed only indirectly via History as Travel,
since it is difficult to get away from the matter of how one defines oneself in rela-
tion to other, different ways of being and doing. Furthermore, those historians
who engage in Emancipatory History à la Foucault would be more effective if
they engaged more directly in Identity History, replacing their ‘crypto-normative’
critiques (the expression is explained below, p. 339) and engaging normativity
straightforwardly. Extending the discussion of normativity, the very final pages of
the book turn to the matter of moral evaluation by the historian, suggesting that
evaluation is not a category error or an anachronistic residue of the days when
History as Moral Lesson was explicitly endorsed by many historians.
In the historical profession, Speculative Philosophy is at its lowest ebb for many
centuries, perhaps for the entire history of History. Hayden White claimed to the
contrary, but this was more by assertion than illustration. A major influence on
White, the literary theorist Northrop Frye, reflected on Aristotle’s distinction
between poetry and History, according to which the latter only dealt with the par-
ticular whereas the former dealt with the universal. Frye claimed ‘that when a
historian’s scheme gets to a certain point of comprehensiveness it becomes myth
ical in shape and so approaches the poetic in its structure’.1 White radicalized the
claim, holding at the end of his opus Metahistory: The Historical Imagination in
the Nineteenth Century (1973) that ‘proper history and speculative philosophy are
distinguishable only in emphasis’. In White’s view the former sort of History, the
sort of History that most historians think they are engaged in, was just more sur-
reptitious or implicit in propagating some philosophy of History beyond its
explanation of some specific historical issue.2
1 Northrop Frye, Fables of Identity: Studies in Poetic Mythology (New York: Harcourt, Brace, and
World, 1963), 53–4.
2 Hayden White, Metahistory, 427.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
3 Ibid., p. ix.
4 Alex Callinicos, Theories and Narratives: Reflections on the Philosophy of History (Durham, NC:
Duke University Press, 1995).
5 Peter Munz, ‘The Historical Narrative’, in Bentley (ed.), Companion to Historiography, 851–72,
esp. 860–1. Similar points about generalizations in Alan Bulloch, ‘The Historian’s Purpose: History
and Metaphysics’, in Meyerhoff (ed.), The Philosophy of History in Our Time, 292–9, here 295–7.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
History as Method
At my university’s open days for potential students, far from proclaiming the his-
torian as oracle we employees are apt to be found extolling the ‘transferable skills’
developed in the practice of History. This is a benefit of History as Method. The
idea of transferability appeals to historians’ self-image as critical thinkers while
sounding worthwhile to potential employers of History students. It promises to
blend holistic and instrumental criteria—the argument goes that critical minds
are good things for people and society to have in general, whilst being useful in a
narrower productive sense.
Employment patterns suggest that historical training is valued in many work-
places, either directly or when refracted through conversion courses. That may be
enough for those looking to ‘sell’ the discipline, but it only tells us necessarily
about the technical side of the historian’s training and its instrumental potential.
It does not necessarily say anything about the whole critical-reflective disposition
that a historical training is also said to foster. So let us distinguish between the
thought of a rather stereotyped functionary and ‘critical’ thought. The distinction
is between those who apply their thinking in pursuit of the already established
ends of some extant set-up, and those who might apply their thinking critically
towards the founding assumptions of the set-up. The values that one reflects on as
a citizen might sit uncomfortably with the interests that one furthers in one’s job
by one’s particular skillset—of course they also might not clash, but the point is
that skills in the narrow sense are neutral as to the purposes they serve, whereas
the critical faculty in the broader sense is not. She who lends her skills profes-
sionally to the pursuit of maximizing profit may or may not as citizen approve of
the set-up that incentivizes such behaviour. She who has developed her critical
faculties might appreciate that the very idea that one’s work be hived off from
one’s life as a citizen stems from a particular worldview that is itself eligible for
criticism.
A second heuristic distinction cuts across the distinction between critical
thinkers and functionaries. It is a distinction based on the varying roles of truth-
fulness in relation to the conduct of one’s activities. On one side are intellectual
disciplines like History for which truthfulness is (or ought to be) a governing
value. On the other side are undertakings for which truthfulness is not necessar-
ily a governing value. The significance of this distinction is best elucidated by
considering some of the specific claims made on behalf of History and other
scholarly undertakings.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
The historiographer John Tosh lists among the virtues that have been proclaimed
for History the provision of ‘a training in the rational evaluation of evidence and
argument, on which democratic discourse depends’, adding that this classically
liberal justification ‘is probably the only perspective on which all historians agree’,
but also that ‘it amounts to no more than claiming for history a special distinction
in attitudes which are found in other disciplines too’.6 The study of literature,
poetry, and pragmatist philosophy has indeed enjoyed similar endorsement from
some of its advocates,7 and we ought also to note the connection that Karl Popper
drew between scientific method, openness to new conclusions, and the ‘open
society’.8 In Human, All Too Human Nietzsche provided his own justification for
systematic enquiry:
On the whole, scientific methods are at least as important as any other result of
research: for it is upon the insight into method that the scientific spirit
depends . . . Clever people may learn as much as they wish of the results of sci-
ence . . . [but] lack the scientific spirit . . . They are content to find any hypothesis
at all concerning some matter; then they are all fire and flame for it and think
that is enough. . . . If something is unexplained, they grow hot over the first
notion that comes into their heads and looks like an explanation—which results
progressively in the worst consequences, especially in the sphere of politics. For
that reason everyone should now study at least one science from the bottom up:
then he will know what method means and how important is the utmost
circumspection.9
sectional interest under pretence of open enquiry or pursuit of the common good.
Such people we might call propagandists. If ‘propagandist’ sounds too prejudicial,
take the adversarial stance of the lawyer in the common law system. The lawyer
tries to win an argument by any means that can be gotten away with within the
rules of the courtroom, rules which are by no means the same as the rules of
scholarly enquiry invoked by Nietzsche et al. The lawyer honours her profes-
sion—and fulfils an important social role—by acting as a zealous advocate for a
party to a dispute. When contrasting historians on one hand and lawyers and
certain politicians on the other, the claim is not that historians do not succumb to
advocacy or propagandistic forms of argument. Today, at least as much as before,
there is a professional tendency and a commercial imperative to make one’s mark
by a ‘strong argument’, where ‘strong’ does not mean ‘well-substantiated’ so much
as ‘provocative’—‘better to be strong and wrong’, I have heard said. Alan Bennett’s
play The History Boys (2005) reported rather than invented a vision of the discip
line wherein the capacity to persuade that orange is green is a virtue to be
applauded. Nevertheless, there is a different balance of governing ideals in an
intellectual discipline of supposedly open enquiry, as opposed to the balance per-
taining in sundry official, representative, and adversary roles, however appropri-
ate and even admirable the differing balances might be in their respective spheres.
As we move the discussion on, please note that the assertion that truthfulness
ought to be a governing ideal for those in the intellectual disciplines is made in
full awareness that, insofar as it has been an ideal for historians over time, the
understanding of what ‘truthfulness’ means has varied along with concepts of
truth. In this book we have encountered concepts of truth as plausibility or as
capturing the way things generally are assumed to be irrespective of particulars.
We have heard of historians bolstering their truth-telling authority by catering to
popular belief in omens and miracles. But we have also encountered the concept
of audience expectations of Histories, the greater credence audiences gave to
some parts of a work than others, audience awareness of authorial tropes, and so
forth. In short, we have grounds to believe that there was very often an implicit
contract of trust between writer and audience as to the nature of the written prod-
uct, however much the product and the expectation differed over time. We have
also tracked a diminution of the types of ‘truthfulness’, with increasing prioritiza-
tion of a certain literal, particular sort, as opposed, say, to figural truth. This
diminution over time correlates roughly with the rise of specialism, then profes-
sionalism, if also with a decline in certain hermeneutic traditions. Today, on the
whole, central to the contract of trust that the historian has with her audience is a
stipulation as to the historian’s truthfulness in this narrower sense. The contract is
underwritten by a belief, right or wrong, that by their training historians are best
placed to honour that particular ideal of truthfulness in the (method-ical) way in
which they draw inferences from evidence, but there must be a presumed com-
mitment to truthfulness in the first place. Indeed, irrespective of how things were
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
in the past in the practice of historians, there are good Kantian reasons for high-
lighting the significance of the contract of trust, because to abuse trust—to
deceive—is to treat audience members as means for the agenda of the deceitful
historian, not as ends in themselves. To deceive might also involve co-opting the
denizens of the past. In the absence of a tacit commitment to fulfilling the con-
tract of trust with the audience, the historian will step into the shoes of the zeal-
ous advocate with her different and, in the context of the discipline as it is at
present, inappropriate ethic of vocational responsibility.10
That august body, Britain’s Incorporated Association of Assistant Masters in
Secondary Schools, was heading roughly in the direction of venerating truthful-
ness when, alongside advocating the marketability of the historian’s skillset, its
The Teaching of History (1957) noted:
A clarification: the focus in this section is on truthfulness rather than the ‘truth’
invoked by the Assistant Masters. Under discussion is not the ability to ascertain
historical truth,12 which, even in the event that we all accepted a common defin
ition, will always be the subject of argument in an inferential undertaking. The
idea of truthfulness as a disposition or regulative ideal rather than truth-finding
as a capacity is the sort of thing the historian and political scientist Mark Bevir is
getting at when designating objectivity a normative standard to which to aspire,
rather than an epistemic claim about one’s standpoint or achievement.
Truthfulness as a parameter or ideal is implicitly honoured by the likes of the
historian and historiographer G. J. Reiner who noted in 1950 that ‘the morality of
history-writing is exclusively methodological’.13 It is explicit when intellectual
historian John Zammito lists ‘truth-telling’ as chief among what he calls the ‘cog-
nitive virtues’ of the scholar.14 The medievalist Eric John made the same point.15
One historian said of the British cohort that Bentley calls modernists (p. 249)
that those ‘new academic professionals’ regarded accepting the principles of
10 By ‘the audience’ I mean a general audience, not a particular one that might wish to have its
prejudices confirmed against another part of the potential audience.
11 Cited in D. M. Sturley, The Study of History (London: Longmans, 1969), 7.
12 Williams, Truth and Truthfulness.
13 Mark Bevir, ‘Objectivity in History’, History and Theory 33:3 (1994), 328-344, here 335;
G. J. Reiner, History: Its Purpose and Method (London: Allen and Unwin, 1950), 255.
14 John H. Zammito, review of David Carr, Thomas R. Flynn, and Rudolf Makkreel (eds.), The
Ethics of History (Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 2004) at http://ndpr.nd.edu/
news/24599-the-ethics-of-history
15 Eric John, ‘Some Questions on the Materialist Conception of History,’ History, 38 (1953), 1–10.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
16 John Kenyon, The History Men (Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press, 1984), 283.
17 Jean Stengers, ‘Quelques réflexions sur le jugement moral en histoire’, Bulletin de la Classe des
Lettres et des Sciences morales et politiques de l’Académie Royale de Belgique, 5th ser., 58:5 (1972),
189–205.
18 Nancy Streuver, ‘Philosophical Problems and Historical Solutions’, in Bernard P. Dauenhauer
(ed.), At the Nexus of Philosophy and History (Athens: University of Georgia Press, 2010), 73–93,
here 85.
19 Megill cited in Zammito review of Carr et al. (eds.), The Ethics of History.
20 Ermarth, ‘Ethics and Method’, History and Theory, 43:4 (2004), 61–83, here 63.
21 Zammito review of Carr et al. (eds.), The Ethics of History.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
22 Quentin Skinner, ‘Sir Geoffrey Elton and the Practice of History’, Transactions of the Royal
Historical Society, 6th ser., VII (1997), 301–16.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
23 Streuver, ‘Philosophical Problems and Historical Solutions’, writes that ‘The history of the use of
casuistry is interesting, the history of employed moralisms is not’ (p. 88). However, she goes on to
relate to the substance of the past not just in the form, say, of past argumentative strategies but as
regards the moral weight of that substance. It becomes not just a matter of History of the use of casu-
istry, but History of the impact of issues about which casuistic arguments are used. In insisting on
‘history as constituting a shared memory of our confections of moral identity’, she sees the constraint
‘to positive as well as negative considerations of past manifestations of moral competence’ (p. 89),
which implies nothing less than moral assessment of things past. If ‘even negative thoughts about the
past are ethically viable’, paving the way for the ‘uses of a bad past’ (p. 90) then judgement is presup-
posed. This is little distance from exemplary History.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
Reaching even a loose consensus as to the substantive value of studying the past is
not made easy by the fact that some academic historians often trade on a general
sense of History’s relevance while rather belittling the sorts of reasons that non-
academics might espouse. There are also different ways of honouring oneself. For
every popularizer who rides to celebrity on the back of the hard-won findings of
archival scholars, there are several cosmopolitan-but-protectionist historians,
self-appointed gatekeepers of esoteric knowledge: ‘it’s more complicated than
24 Jürgen Habermas, Knowledge and Human Interests (Cambridge: Polity Press, 1987), 309–10.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
that, as you would know if you had read the sources in four languages and twenty
archives’.
The tension between ‘relevance’ and ‘specificity’ has grown with academic spe-
cialism and with the ever finer differentiations characteristic of neo-historicism.
It has been highlighted in Britain by successive governments’ demands that
academics in all fields show the social, political, or economic ‘impact’ of their
research. (‘Impact’ is a separate category of measurement to quality, so in the
overall reckoning one can offset a jamboree of impact against a deficit of ‘excel-
lence’.) Since there are funding and ranking connotations that set institution
against institution by way of marketizing the sector, some historians are increas-
ingly concerned to show some quantifiable relevance of History even while others
fight an anti-utilitarian rearguard under the banner of ‘knowledge for knowledge’s
sake’ or ‘holistic critical faculty’. Putting to one side inane and/or pernicious
British higher education policies, the underlying intellectual issues have con-
cerned serious thinkers since at least the time of Aristotle.
How, given the focus on knowing more and more about less and less during
one’s training, is one to answer the PhD examiner’s ‘so what’ question? The very
asking of the question renders ineligible a ‘knowledge for knowledge’s sake’
defence. The implication is that some knowledge is more valuable/relevant/
significant than others. Over-interpretation can be one way of responding to the
question, with hard-earned empirical precision accompanied by conceptual over-
stretch, as if one’s chosen topic were a microcosm of a larger homogeneous whole,
or a case study of one among a standardized class of entities. In order to justify
their study, particular signs and texts must embody wider systemic logics or
discourses, or, the reverse, be the signs of deep conflict within the historical
meaning-system from which they sprang.25 If one cannot claim wider empirical
or heuristic relevance for one’s subject matter one may hope alternatively to hone
an investigative method of more general utility. The frenzy to coin terms that one
hopes will catch on, with appropriate footnotes to their progenitor, is the most
obvious instance of this tendency; the kingdom is yours if your name ends up
being associated with a ‘turn’.
The risks of over-interpretation are the price often paid for conceptual and
methodological innovation, so one should not be too harsh on over-interpreters.
But it does need to be noted how much the generalizing tendencies of over-
interpretation can militate against the neo-historicist logic with which the gate-
keepers of esoteric knowledge try to police their empirical bailiwick. Student and
examiner alike also need to recognize that measurements of significance are rela-
tive to scale and interest. The work of the examiner who asks ‘so what?’ may fall
foul of allegations of irrelevance when the focus is moved up an order of
25 Raphel Samuel, ‘Reading the Signs II: Fact Grubbers and Mind-Readers’, History Workshop
Journal, 33 (1992), 220–51, here 243–4.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
magnitude, and there is likely a difference between what the examiner—a par-
ticular specialist professional—will find significant and what other historians, not
to speak of members of the general public, will find significant. So while the ‘so
what’ question derives from a substantive rationale for History stronger than
own-sake-ism, it rarely carries a stipulation as to who the substance of the past is
supposed to be important for.
The History-reading public has been moved rather less profoundly than the
academic profession by the ‘turns’ of the last four decades. This is partly because
of the rise of an alienating jargon, a tendency which at once stems from and rein-
forces a wider tendency: most historians write primarily for other historians.
A minority of popularizers attend to the tastes and needs of the reading public,
which is itself relatively diverse owing to the spread of literacy. Unlike in classical
antiquity and beyond, only a few historians of any stripe today see elite decision-
makers as the major target audience, which is also an outcome of the turf-war
over the centuries between History and other disciplines, notably political phil
osophy and then the social sciences. History has ceded ground in some areas
while having more fall-back positions than these other disciplines have. So while
History as Travel, Entertainment, Memorialization, and Identity remain influen-
tial, History as Practical Lesson in the classical form of elite instruction is rarer
than it used to be.
As with other rationales, History as Practical Lesson has metamorphosed
rather than disappearing. It has softer and harder types. Lessons can come in
more and less literal form, and, in the shape of History as Emancipation, in ‘nega-
tive’ form. Some relatively hard lessons are inferred by readers even when not
necessarily propounded by historians. The story of war-waging politicians fight-
ing present wars through the lenses of the memory of previous wars is among the
most unfortunate and important of such cases—a blend of imagined exemplarity
and the similitudo temporum that has for centuries acted to reduce the historical
distance between relevant pasts and present, in a way that runs against the dis-
tancing tendency of ‘modern historical consciousness’.26 Not that there is any
shortage of historians trying to cash in on anniversaries with stronger arguments
as to the relevance of the memorialized event than the fact that past and present
moments are linked by calendrical digits.
Tosh has a ‘soft’ practical rationale in mind when he suggests that ‘historical
re-creation’ offers ‘vicarious experience to writer and reader alike’.27 Vicarious
experience was identified as a benefit of History by Carl Becker and, slightly more
26 On exemplarity in policymaking, Ernest May, ‘Lessons’ of the Past: The Use and Misuse of History
in American Foreign Policy (New York: Oxford University Press, 1975); Yuen Foong Khong, Analogies
at War: Korea, Munich, Dien Bien Phu, and the Vietnam Decisions of 1965 (Princeton: Princeton
University Press, 1992).
27 John Tosh, The Pursuit of History, 2nd edition (Harlow: Longman, 1993), 29.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
recently, the historian of late antiquity Henri Marrou.28 The historian of science
Thomas Söderqvist rejects the connotations of the sociologically oriented social
constructionist approach to the History of science, which he sees as downplaying
the creative agency and individuality of particular scientists. He commends writ-
ing detailed biographies that empower readers to make their own existential
choices by showing how historical figures made theirs. This is a form of practical
inspiration without any accompanying template for action.29 Foucault implied a
rather harder lesson when he wrote of retrieving ‘subjugated knowledges’ buried
beneath dominant thought systems (pp. 280–81), and at points in his work on
ancient Greece he subscribed to something not so very distant from exemplarity.
Foucault’s views shifted as to the balance of similarity and difference across
time, which reflected amongst other things the difference between his sediment-
ing horizontal-structural ‘archaeological’ approach and the diachronic biopsy of
his ‘genealogical’ approach. When trying to establish his position on the relation-
ship between past and present, and thus the use of History for life, there is also a
tension between his detailed, monographic ‘analytical’ historical work about
regimes of power-knowledge and his ‘diagnostic’ and prescriptive thinking about
resisting power in the present, which was to be found in the form of short essays
and interviews. It is said by one of Foucault’s enthusiasts of his late career lectures
at the Collège de France that ‘nowhere more clearly than [here] do we see the
balancing, the alternation, and the overlapping of these two poles’. Carefully
chosen words; ‘reconciliation’ is not among them.30 In what turned out to be his
final years, Foucault had not achieved a consistent view on History’s utility, but it
is clear that on occasions he was far less ruthlessly (neo-)historicizing than many
of the historians influenced by his early and mid-career work. When asked in
1983 whether ancient Greek ethics offered a plausible alternative in the present
his answer was emphatically negative. ‘I am not looking for an alternative; you
can’t find the solution of a problem in the solution of another problem raised at
another moment by other people. You see, what I want to do is not the history of
solutions—and that’s the reason why I don’t accept the word alternative. I would
like to do the genealogy of problems, of problématiques.’31 Now it takes little
reasoning to establish that there must be some relationship between the History
of problems and that of solutions, and a little later in the same interview Foucault
confirmed as much. ‘Among the cultural inventions of mankind there is a treas-
ury of devices, techniques, ideas, procedures, and so on, that cannot exactly be
28 Henri Marrou, The Meaning of History (Dublin: Helicon, 1966), 260; Becker, Detachment, 61.
29 Thomas Söderqvist, ‘Scientific Biography as a Hermeneutics of Edification’, International History
of Science Newsletter, no. 3 (April 1995), 4–6. For additional references and a critique: Paolo Palladino,
‘Icarus’ Flight: On the Dialogue between the Historian and the Historical Actor’, Rethinking History,
4:1 (2000), 21–36.
30 Foucault, Society must be Defended, editor’s introduction, pp. xvi–xvii.
31 Michel Foucault, Ethics: Subjectivity and Truth, ed. Paul Rabinow (New York: New Press, 1997),
256.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
historico-critical investigations are quite specific in the sense that they always
bear upon a material, an epoch, a body of determined practices and discourses.
And yet, at least at the level of the Western societies from which we derive, they
have their generality, in the sense that they have continued to recur up to our
time: for example, the problem of the relationship between sanity and insanity,
or sickness and health, or crime and the law; the problem of the role of sexual
relations; and so on.34
Current welfare systems are coming under significant critique, not least for ‘cru-
elty’ to service users[;] Abuse and cruelty in previous welfare systems have been
at significant cost to individuals and nations[;] Historical welfare policies pro-
vide useful evidence of how systems designed to care can become cruel[;] Abuse
by caring institutions is not just a problem of ‘isolated perpetrators’, but is
enabled by the ideologies around, investments in, and management of welfare
systems.36
While Barclay’s piece works by comparison/analogy, for example from the moral-
istic attitude to work and the deliberate harshness of welfare regimes in late eight-
eenth- and early nineteenth-century Ireland to the present in Britain, the work of
the social historian Louise Jackson in the same online venue highlights a different
relationship of relevance between past and present—the relationship of genealogy.
Her piece on ‘Child sexual abuse in England and Wales: prosecution and preva-
lence 1918–1970’ points to problems with the law’s response to abuse, showing
amongst other things that ‘Legislation developed in the nineteenth century, which
reflected Victorian moral values, was adapted inadequately to deal with offences
against children’ which led to legal loopholes. ‘It also made it impossible for poli-
ticians, policy-makers and campaigners to monitor increases in sexual offences
against children using criminal justice statistics.’37
35 On the theoretical self-constitution of theory, Kwame Anthony Appiah, In My Father’s House:
Africa in the Philosophy of Culture (New York: Oxford University Press, 1992), 142.
36 http://www.historyandpolicy.org/policy-papers/papers/creating-cruel-welfare-systems-a-his
torical-perspective published 1 March 2018.
37 http://www.historyandpolicy.org/policy-papers/papers/child-sexual-abuse-in-england-and-
wales-prosecution-and-prevalence-1918–197 published 18 June 2015.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
38 Carol Anderson, White Rage: The Unspoken Truth of Our Racial Divide (New York: Bloomsbury,
2016).
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
The stock of History as Moral Lesson has depreciated for many of the same
reasons that have affected the fortunes of History as Practical Lesson.
Contextualism, historicism, anachronism, relativism, neutralism: sometimes his
torians appeal to one of these concepts as against evaluative thought when they
mean another. They can be placeholders that interchangeably vouchsafe the non-
judgemental disposition one feels one ought to adopt towards the foreign country
past, where they do things differently.
It is, nonetheless, not unheard of for historians today to justify their work with
reference to moral edification. Michael Dintenfass recommends that History
become ‘a project of the should and the ought as well as the did and the was’,
though he would have done well to register that this was a function of History for
most of its existence.39 John Arnold thinks that examining ‘what human beings
have done in the past—the bad and the good—provides us with examples through
which we might contemplate our future actions’.40 This sounds old-fashioned, but
who decreed that historians had to adopt a modern enthusiasm for the new? The
historical theorist Jörn Rüsen once pointed out how little we really know about
the way readers assimilate History, and in an attempt to help rectify the situation
through an empirical study at the University of Bochum he found that students
embraced exemplarity as a way of learning.41 We have seen that the point of
topical thinking, which is a few millennia old, is that it is not a form of rote-
learning but an example-based exercise in honing one’s thinking such that it can
be deployed in new situations. One ‘thinks with’ real-life or hypothetical scen
arios, which is why novels, with their dense, highly contextualized evocations of
complex, fraught situations, can be so stimulating to the critical faculty.42 This
does not mean one expects to find a situation which mirrors one’s favourite read
in all particulars. No less a moral rationalist than Kant recognized that examples
are the ‘go-kart’ of moral thought—that which gives impetus to the whole
39 Michael Dintenfass, ‘Truth’s Other: Ethics, the History of the Holocaust, and Historiographical
Theory After the Linguistic Turn’, History and Theory, 39 (2000), 1–20, here 20.
40 John Arnold, History: A Very Short Introduction (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000), 118.
41 See George Kitson Clark on morality: The Critical Historian (London: History Book Club, 1968),
207. Jörn Rüsen, ‘The Didactics of History in West Germany: Towards a New Self-Awareness of
Historical Studies’, History and Theory, 26:3 (1987), 275–86, here 282–3.
42 This is one of the core tenets of the thought of those sometimes called literary Aristotelians. See
for instance Marshall Gregory, Shaped by Stories: The Ethical Power of Narratives (Notre Dame:
University of Indiana Press, 2009).
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
43 Hannah Arendt, Responsibility and Judgement (New York: Shocken, 2003), 143–4.
44 R. G. Collingwood, The Idea of History, revised edition (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005),
403–4.
45 Ibid. 18.
46 Lionel Rubinoff, Collingwood and the Reform of Metaphysics: A Study in the Philosophy of
Mind (University of Toronto Press, 1970), 229; William M. Johnston, The Formative Years of
R. G. Collingwood (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1968), 60; Alan Donagan, The Later Philosophy
of R. G. Collingwood (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1962), 246, and the review of Collingwood by Hayden
White in History and Theory, 4:2 (1965), 244–52.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
was the other way around).55 We are on firmer ground with Bolingbroke: ‘An
early and proper application to the study of history will contribute extremely to
keep our minds free from a ridiculous partiality in favour of our own country,
and a vicious prejudice against others.’56 Like Montaigne, Bolingbroke differs only
in tone from Descartes’s ever-so-slightly-dismissive conception of History as
travel to broaden the mind: ‘It is’, wrote Descartes, ‘good to know something
about the manners and customs of other nations so that we may judge more
sanely of our own, and may not think that whatever is contrary to our own mode
of life is both ridiculous and unreasonable, as is usually the case with those who
have seen nothing’, although he also said that ‘a man who has spent too much
time in travelling becomes in the end a stranger in his own country; and a man
who has too much curiosity about what happened in past centuries usually
shows a great ignorance of what is happening in this one’.57 Early in 2018 a
group of senior British m edievalists justified their activities in the face of assault
by a government that included no small number of History graduates, conclud-
ing that studying History makes one a ‘richer, better, more tolerant, better
informed person’.58 One of those had earlier written of the benefit of exploring
an ‘alternative world’ because ‘visiting the past is something like visiting a for-
eign country’.59
In the accounts of these scholars the idea of History as Travel is a non-
instrumental justification for the discipline, akin to Habermas’s vision of History
as a form of communication (p. 314). There are some grounds for accepting the
view: the basic interest in other ways of life, and how other humans experience
things, clearly can exist apart from any utilitarian justification. But this is not the
only reason for ‘travel’: what of that great British institution, the booze-cruise?
Even the sort of tourism with a little more in common with ‘the grand tour’ may
be more angled at gratification or relaxation than edification. (With the
Presocratic Gorgias ringing in the ears (p. 30), one needs to reject the fallacy
whereby something cannot be edifying if it is also entertaining: the question is of
the nature of this entertainment.) When we come to matters like sex-tourism
then self-gratification is also instrumentalization of others. In the scholarly
and political realm, one only needs to reflect upon the role that historical and
anthropological enquiry into the ways of ‘others’ has sometimes played in justify-
ing imperialism: here Foucauldian critiques about the relationship of knowledge
55 Rainer C. Schwinges, ‘Kreuzzugsideologie und Toleranz im Denken Wilhelms von Tyrus’,
Saeculum, 25 (1974), 367–85; Ulrich Berner, ‘Die Bibel in der mittelalterlicher Diskussion um Ketzer
und Muslime’, in Joachim Kügler and Werner H. Ritter (eds.), Auf Leben und Tod oder völlig egal:
Kritisches und Nachdenkliches zur Bedeutung der Bibel (Munster: LIT, 2005) 11–24, here 22 ff.
56 Bolingbroke, Letters, 27. 57 Descartes, Discourse, 40.
58 James Tapper, ‘Is Medieval History Bunk? Not if you’re a cabinet minister’, The Observer, 28
January 2018.
59 Arnold, History, 119–20.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
to power cohere with Edward Said’s critique of ‘orientalism’ and with some of the
central concerns of postcolonial scholarship.60
The association of History as Travel with tolerance is also wrong if it comes
with any presupposition of ditching the evaluative thought associated with
History as Moral Lesson. The problem is identical to the liberal problem of
whether to tolerate the intolerant or the intolerable. Tolerance is a principle which
will have at points to compete with other principles. When, having explicitly dis
avowed moral evaluation, Collingwood et al. claim that History will encourage
the embrace of human variety, each is prejudicing the issue. The attitude that is
supposed to be inculcated by studying the past is imposed, or already possessed,
prior to any particular encounter with the past, otherwise there is no guarantee of
the right outcome. Here we find much the same confusion—or circularity—that
we identified in the late nineteenth century when Fustel, Monod, and Fagniez
decreed that History, ‘properly’ understood, would promote national unity and
strength (pp. 235–6).
One cannot say in advance of encountering a specific practice that one will be
tolerant of it. That would be to forego the possession of any other principle than
tolerance, to render oneself so completely mutable as to have no identity as a
value-bearing individual qualified to be tolerant. Some of us might find that
studying the past makes us tolerant, others that it drives us to fury at the injustice
of it all. Others might take inspiration from the evidence of so many people prof-
iting from theft or slavery and getting away with it. Then again, surveying other
forms of life past or present might produce admiration and a desire for emula-
tion. As it happens such positively evaluative reactions are ruled out by the anti-
evaluative ‘tolerance’ prescription in the same way that negative responses are.
Unusually for a thinker of his calibre, Collingwood ended up in something of a
conceptual muddle over the tolerance question, When warning historians against
thinking as if ‘the massacre of Corcyra was now being enacted in the next room
and we ought to break open the door and stop it’ he was implying, in the same
way as the philosopher Michael Oakeshott later, that such present-centric
responses were category errors.61 Why, then, is tolerance exempt from the
charge of being a category error? It is, after all, a present-centric response that is
(supposedly) produced in relation to some historical substance, i.e. some foreign
way of thinking, being, doing. In the search for conceptual consistency ought we
also to disapprove of tolerance as an upshot of History? Or ought we to rethink
these prescriptions in light of the fact that people, historians included, will con-
tinue to have varying emotional, political, and evaluative responses to stories of
the past? Indeed the inferred substance of the past that feeds these responses is
significant in drawing people to History.
60 Edward Said, Orientalism: Western Conceptions of the Orient (London: Routledge and Kegan
Paul, 1978).
61 Collingwood, The Idea of History, 404–6.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
62 Good surveys of moral relativisms, including accounts of ‘meta-ethical moral relativism’ are:
Maria Baghramian, Relativism (Abingdon: Routledge, 2004), ch. 9; Chris Gowans, ‘Moral Relativism’,
in Edward N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2019 Edition), online:
https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2019/entries/moral-relativism/
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
History as Therapy
The newer rationales for History are based less on the Travel and Methodology
conviction that History will be liberalizing and more on the hope that it will be
liberating. History as Therapy and History as Emancipation are present-centric,
but since all rationales for History are present-centric in some way, that tells us
nothing in itself about their proponents’ commitments. Elements of both ration-
ales are captured in Goethe’s aphorism ‘Geschichte schreiben ist eine Art sich das
Vergangene vom Halse zu schaffen’: writing History is a way of shedding the
burden of the past. Like Nietzsche, who might have written the same words,
Goethe regarded historians’ primary responsibilities as being to themselves and
their readers rather than to the past itself.63
Any discussion of History as Therapy must accord pride of place to the intel-
lectual historian Dominick LaCapra. He argues that the historian is a ‘secondary
witness’ to historical events and when those events are traumatic, the historians
should, in the summary of the literary theorist Eric Kligerman, ‘generate the lost
anxiety of trauma in tolerable doses in order to circumvent repetition and filter
the shock of history’s traumas for the generations after the trauma’.64 The alterna-
tive, by which I understand LaCapra to mean the result of standard historical
practice in recounting traumatic events, is that the past might repeat itself: a trau-
matized individual re-enacts past traumas, as the historian forecloses on events
like genocide by encapsulating them in descriptions whose claim to cognitive
authority denies the capacity of the events to elude comprehension. The literary
theorist Eric L. Santner suggested that conventional narrative accounts of trau-
matic events might constitute ‘narrative fetishism’.65 By fetishism, he means the
historian’s alleged desire to gain mastery of the event not through a sort of
authentic psychoanalytic working-through of the trauma, or a mourning process,
but by repressing the traumatic aspects and then presenting the event to readers
as safe, as actually not traumatic in the first place. In the best scenario for LaCapra,
‘Working through trauma brings the possibility of counteracting compulsive “act-
ing out” through [an] explicit, critically controlled process of repetition that
63 See aphorisms 193 and 191 in Johann Wolfgang von Goethe, Goethe Werke—Hamburger
Ausgabe Band 12, ed. Erich Trunz (Munich: Beck, 2008), 390–1.
64 Eric Kligerman, Sites of the Uncanny: Paul Celan, Specularity and the Visual Arts (Berlin: de
Gruyter, 2007), 52–3.
65 Eric L. Santner, ‘History Beyond the Pleasure Principle: Some Thoughts on the Representation of
Trauma’, in Saul Friedländer (ed.), Probing the Limits of Representation (Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press, 1992), 143–54, here 144.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
significantly changes a life by making possible the selective retrieval and modified
enactment of unactualized past possibilities’.66
In bringing such thinking under critique here I note that in other works I have
found utility in LaCapra’s thinking on counter-transference;67 nevertheless, the
basic analogy between History and psychoanalysis is too loose. More precisely,
there are two analogies in play. The first is an analogy of the individual and group
psyche and situation—which LaCapra actually suggests is more than merely an
analogy.68 The second analogy is that between the way the individual therapist
relates to the individual patient and the way historians relates to their readerships,
which is assumed to correspond to the traumatized collective. This is at least one
analogy too far.
Even if one accepted the analogy between individual analysand and collective
analysand, and thus the applicability of similar psychoanalytic concepts to each,
then absent in the relationship between historian and collective analysand is the
sort of interaction that is achieved in the relationship between therapist and
patient. In the relationship between therapist and individual patient, the produc-
tion of representations of the past stands constantly in conversation with the way
in which such representations are consumed—sometimes producer and con-
sumer are the same person. In the relationship between historian and collective
‘patient’, the production stands alone, with the nature and outcome of consump-
tion untested and uncontestable, with no representative of the collective psyche
who can be assessed or can speak to the efficacy of the cure. Besides, in LaCapra’s
vision it rather seems that there is just one anointed historian-therapist providing
one therapeutic (or problematic) representation of the traumatic event. Perhaps
all historians are supposed to confer in order to coordinate their accounts (and
those of various museums, television documentaries, and so forth) in order not to
confuse the analysand.
Yet there is no reason to accept the individual:collective analogy either. It is one
thing to say, as LaCapra does, that there is a collective context for any therapy
since it is always therapy of the socialized individual, and quite another to say that
the collective has the same sort of consciousness and reflexes as the individual.69
True, there is a shared idiom of suffering: governments and leaders can easily
deploy the language of traumatization and catharsis, but this does not mean that
this language refers to the same phenomena. For instance, while one can talk of
both individual trauma and collective trauma, societies do not experience flash-
backs and involuntary reactions.
66 Dominick LaCapra, Representing the Holocaust: History, Theory, Trauma (Ithaca: Cornell
University Press, 1996 [orig. 1994]), 173–4.
67 Bloxham, History and Morality.
68 LaCapra, Representing the Holocaust, 173–4; LaCapra, History in Transit: Experience, Identity,
Critical Theory (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 2004), 73–4.
69 LaCapra, Representing the Holocaust, 173–4.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
We need not concur with Lewis Namier, who made an early comparison of
History with psychoanalysis and concluded that both were better at diagnosing
than curing: while the jury is out on History, psychoanalysis has achieved some
success. Namier was surely correct, however, that such benefits as analysis confers
are not attained by reading the results of someone else’s engagement with the pro-
cess, but rather by participating in the process—participating intersubjectively,
not one-sidedly. A somewhat better analogy would be to the writing of History as
therapy for the historian, not its reading as therapy for someone else for whose
particular existential dilemma the History was not composed.70
This is not to say that the reading of History can deliver no psychological bene
fit. We know from various therapies that explanations which make symptoms
comprehensible may help the analysand even while not alleviating the symptoms
themselves. They enable some sort of cognitive control. Shedding light on the
present by explaining problems stemming from the past may help the analysand
to feel less powerless, less at the mercy of incomprehensibly induced emotions.71
With the structural substitution of socio-economic circumstances for emotions
we may concur with the feminist medieval historian Judith Bennett when she
argued that a historically derived understanding of reproduced structures of
inequality can counteract the tendency to self-blame for ‘failure’ according to the
inequitable rules of the game.72 Bourdieu made the same point in regard of his
sociology, even once claiming for it a quasi-psychoanalytic, or ‘socioanalytic’,
function: sociology can help people stop looking in vain for biographical solu-
tions to structural problems.73
A difference between Bennett’s argument and LaCapra’s is that the analogy
emerging from Bennett’s case is not of historical conditioning and trauma.
Furthermore, while Bennett’s’ ‘therapy’ might provide a stimulus for structure-
changing action in pursuit of fuller social emancipation, in itself it ‘only’ entails
subjective ‘mental’ emancipation vis-à-vis social structures. This is perhaps the
most we can expect of any historical course of treatment, and it is no small thing
though it may appear to be when set against some of the grander emancipatory
promises made for History.
70 John Brooke, ‘Namier and Namierism’, History and Theory, 3 (1964), 331–47, here 345.
71 Anthony Storr, ‘The Concept of Cure’, in Charles Rycroft (ed.), Psychoanalysis Observed (London:
Constable, 1961), 51–84, here 73.
72 Judith M. Bennett, History Matters: Patriarchy and the Challenge of Feminism (Philadelphia:
University of Pennsylvania Press, 2006), 152.
73 Michael Grenfell, Pierre Bourdieu: Agent Provocateur (London: Continuum, 2004), 180.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
purports to help by changing attitudes to the past and reducing the hold of the
past on the individual’s present. History as Emancipation in its Marxist form
purports to demystify the way the world is set up, as a prelude to changing that
world in accordance with a specific alternative. History as Emancipation in its
most popular non-Marxist form purports to disavow any claim to revealing
truths about the way the world really is and really ought to be; it is concerned
with paving the way to individual self-determination in the present by challenging
given claims on the way things really are and ought to be—Marxist claims
included.
The intellectual historian Quentin Skinner has at points talked about the utility
in the present of contemplating early modern republican thought, which touches
on the terrain of History as Practical Lesson.74 More purely characteristic of
History as Emancipation is his belief that ‘to demand from the history of thought
a solution to our own immediate problems is . . . to commit not merely a meth
odological fallacy, but something like a moral error. But to learn from the past—
and we cannot otherwise learn it at all—the distinction between what is necessary
and what is the product merely of our own contingent arrangements, is the key to
self-awareness itself.’ Insofar as Marxism had highlighted the constraints placed
by society ‘upon our imaginations . . . the historical study of the ideas of other
societies should be undertaken as the indispensable and the irreplaceable means
of placing limits on these constraints’.75 Skinner was effectively reiterating the
point made in 1946 by A. L. Rowse that ‘freedom for a human being consists
in knowing the extent to which he is conditioned, and choosing his course
accordingly’.76 Similar sentiments were expressed at the outset of the third millen-
nium ce by the American historian of the Cold War, John Lewis Gaddis,77 but
they could have come straight from the pens of Nietzsche, Adorno, Marrou, a
range of postcolonial theorists and in his own way even Lord Acton!78 Foucault’s
thought is also relevant here.
It has been said of Foucault that he ‘does not seek the unchangeable amid the
changing, but rather to identify that which can be changed in that which is pre-
sumed static’,79 which suggests a different angle to that of Skinner when Skinner
talked of some necessity that might be detected behind contingent arrangements.
74 Quentin Skinner,‘The Idea of Negative Liberty: Philosophical and Historical Perspectives’, in
Richard Rorty, J. B. Schneewind, and Quentin Skinner (eds.), Philosophy in History: Essays on the
Historiography of Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998), 193–221. See also
Skinner, Liberty before Liberalism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998).
75 Quentin Skinner, ‘Meaning and Understanding in the History of Ideas’, History and Theory, 8:1
(1969), 3–53, here 53.
76 Rowse, The Use of History, 91.
77 John Lewis Gaddis, The Landscape of History (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004), conclu-
sion, especially 148–51.
78 Marrou, The Meaning of History, 283.
79 Kevin O’Brien, ‘Michel Foucault’s Genealogy of the Subject’ (PhD Thesis: Katholieke Universiteit
Leuven, 1988), 326.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
I. The items X are social/cultural constructions. They were different in the past
and we can change them in the present if we wish. (Note that the claim is not
unique to this school of thought. What might vary between salient schools
of thought is the size of set X.)
II. We need to change things because they are undesirable.
III. In order to change things, we need to understand their origins.
The three claims will now be assessed in reverse order. My deflationary assess-
ments are strictly related to the conceptual coherence of History as Emancipation
in those areas where it can be distinguished from History as Practical Lesson,
which, as argued above (pp. 314–21), can be useful in shaping thought in the
present. The point of the coming argument is not to deny that evidence as to
83 Michel Foucault, Discipline and Punish (London: Penguin, 1991), 31, 308. See also S. Fuggle,
Y. Lanci, and M. Tazzioli (eds.), Foucault and the History of our Present (Basingstoke: Palgrave
Macmillan, 2015).
84 Pierre Bourdieu, ‘Rethinking the State: Genesis and Structure of the Bureaucratic Field’, in
George Steinmetz (ed.), State/Culture: State Formation after the Cultural Turn (Ithaca: Cornell
University Press, 1999), 52–75, here 57.
85 Jürgen Habermas, On the Logic of the Social Sciences (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1988 [orig.
1967]) 168.
86 Steve Fuller, Thomas Kuhn: A Philosophical History for our Times (Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 2001), p. xvi.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
(p. 290). John Arnold enjoins studying how we came about in order ‘to be made
aware of the possibility of doing things differently’.87
In order to assess the emancipatory prospects of origin-quests we first need to
distinguish between chronological and conceptual senses of ‘origin’. One has to
guess which meaning of origin Max Horkheimer had in mind when he wrote that
‘for the little man who is turned down when he asks for a job because objective
conditions make it impossible, it is most important that their origin be brought to
the light of day so that they do not continue being unfavorable to him’.88 One of
Horkheimer’s successors in the Frankfurt School, the Hegelian Marxist Herbert
Marcuse, did not elaborate the difference between the chronological and concep-
tual senses of origins either, but both are present in his work. He argued that
‘social theory is historical theory’, and asked, ‘among the various possible and
actual modes of organizing and utilizing the available resources [of any given,
actual society], which ones offer the greatest chance of an optimal development?’89
Leaning towards conceptual origins in one passage, Marcuse stated that reifica-
tion ‘sets forth the actual social relations among men as a totality of objective
relations, thereby concealing their origin, their mechanisms of perpetuation, and
the possibility of their transformation. Above all, it conceals their human core
and content.’90 In another passage, Marcuse focused more on chronological
origins:
The way in which a society organizes the life of its members involves an initial
choice between historical alternatives which are determined by the inherited
level of the material and intellectual culture. The choice itself results from the
play of the dominant interests. It anticipates specific modes of transforming and
utilizing man and nature and rejects other modes. It is one ‘project’ of realiza-
tion among others. But once the project has become operative in the basic insti-
tutions and relations, it tends to become exclusive, and to determine the
development of the society as a whole.91
Marcuse used the term ‘project’ because it accentuates ‘most clearly the specific
character of historical practice’. That practice ‘results from a determinate choice,
seizure of one among other ways of comprehending, organizing, and transform-
ing society’. Marcuse sought to ‘emphasis[e] the element of freedom and responsi-
bility in historical determination’, to link ‘autonomy and contingency’.92
they had located the actual chronological origins of the problem, whereas that is a
primary concern for those who emphasize historical aetiology, moments of deci-
sion, transformation, etc.
The challenge of knowing exactly where chronological origins are to be found
is a challenge amongst other things to practitioners of a Foucauldian ‘History of
the present’. The problem of where to begin one’s critical account of ‘the present’ is
obviously a function of establishing where the salient present began. This will
seem comparatively easy for those who, like Foucault at one stage, believe that the
past can be split into blocks defined by particular epistemes, discursive structures,
and so forth, since one just has to look for the dividing moments like ‘epistemic
ruptures’ or great political revolutions. Much encouragement for this sort of view
has been provided by the popularity of the classical sociological concept of
‘modernity’ as a particular state or stage of human existence, as opposed, for
instance, to the Marxist emphasis on capitalism as a force that keeps pressing and
changing things, and has done either side of the supposed caesura between pre-
modern and modern.
In the caesural view, one period of the past is effectively the present extended
backward through time, while previous periods of time are properly, qualitatively
past. Given a non-caesural view, in which some continuity and change coexist at
all points in some shifting balance—a view substantiated by those critiques of
Foucault’s empirical work that show that certain medical practices do not corre
spond with the supposed lifespans of his epistemes96—then one has to be a little
more circumspect. When Hayden White wrote that ‘the understanding of any of
[a society’s] processes must always be directed at the search for origins, its rela-
tions to its time and space and socially specific contexts, and the emplotment of
its transformations over time’, he was, in preaching so many ‘musts’, just spreading
his bets.97 When engaging in historical explanation one needs to recognize the
inherently pragmatic nature of all of one’s starting points, the inherent contest
ability of the way that, by some act of initial ‘contextualization’, one cauterizes the
open vessels of history that pass beyond the point at which one has chosen to
start the story. Recognizing the possibility of a still-changing balance of change
and continuity after one’s chosen beginning is consonant with the version of post-
structuralism in which meanings and contexts are seen as constantly interacting
and modifying each other, as opposed to that stop–start view of history encour-
aged by the ‘opposition’ between ‘structure’ and ‘event’. Evolutionary changes may
be less obvious than, but as significant when accumulated over time as, the
96 José Guilherme Merquior, Michel Foucault (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1985), 29
(see also 27): ‘Foucault’s epochal monoliths crumble before the contradictory wealth of the historical
evidence’. Also: Ian Maclean, ‘Foucault’s Renaissance Episteme Reassessed: An Aristotelian
Counterblast’, Journal of the History of Ideas, 59:1 (1998), 149–66.
97 Hayden White, ‘Afterword’, in Victoria E. Bonnell and Lynn Hunt (eds.), Beyond the Cultural
Turn (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1999), 315–24, here 318.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
History as Emancipation II
98 Nietzsche, On the Genealogy of Morality, Second Essay, §12, at pp. 50–1. Emphasis added to the
first quote.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
his distaste for modern power-knowledge regimes and going on in later scholarship
to contemplate ways of escaping them.103 This tension is a problem in p rinciple
for the best-known Foucauldian analyses: since they claim that subjectivity, and
any and all ideas of ‘the human’, are merely products of contingent socio-historical
set-ups, thus that there is no ‘first nature’ to be liberated from the ‘second nature’
that the set-up creates, one might reasonably ask what normative grounds they
have for criticizing the set-up.
Perhaps for the Foucauldian in historical mode critiques emerge from contem-
plation of the past. One can imagine instances in which the historian comes
across something troubling or joyous in the past and it makes her re-evaluate
something in the present. But we have evidence that this is not always how cri-
tiques develop in the Foucauldian’s mind. Take Foucault’s Discipline and Punish:
The Birth of the Prison. By his admission in the book the project was stimulated
by contemplating the nature of contemporary prison regimes and the discontent
of the inmates.104 This means that we have to question his later assertion that ‘it
really was the appearance of historical contents’ ‘that made an effective critique of
the asylum or the prison possible’.105 We have grounds to believe that before the
historical enquiry into the birth of the prison (Naissance de la prison in the sub
title of the French original) came a normative critique stimulated by present
arrangements. Mutatis mutandis, one can readily imagine feminists who were
feminists before they became critical theorists and engaged those intellectual tra-
ditions precisely because of the promise of sharper critical tools to enhance the
feminist critique which is at base a normative one. The felt necessity of feminist
critique was there prior to its application to—in this case—some historical inter-
est. One result of these reflections is that clearly discourses of power-knowledge,
propriety, and normative correctness are not as strong in the present as suggested
by Foucauldians and sometimes by Foucault himself: just as Foucault was pre-
ceded by a long line of liberal prison-reformers unpossessed of the magic of post-
modern ‘critique’, ‘ordinary people’, not least rebellious prisoners, are frequently
capable of reflecting critically on their own experience and the experiences of
others. (Whether they have the power to act effectively on that reflection is a dif-
ferent matter.) But the main point is that in cases when normative critique has
inspired the historical examination rather than the other way around, History is
just one weapon in a battle that has already been joined. It is a tool of emancipation
in a different sense of emancipation to that of History as Emancipation I. History
serves here not to alert people to the contingency of their ways in order to liberate
their capacity for choice but rather makes the case for emancipation from a
103 On crypto-normativity and related criticisms, Nancy Fraser, ‘Foucault on Modern Power:
Empirical Insights and Normative Confusions’, Praxis International, 1:3 (1981), 272–87; Jürgen
Habermas, The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1990), 238–93.
104 Foucault, Discipline and Punish, 30. 105 Foucault, Society Must be Defended, 7.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
History as Emancipation I
The idea underlying History as Emancipation I was defined above in these terms:
‘The items X are social/cultural constructions. They were different in the past and,
and we can change them in the present if we wish.’ History as Emancipation I is
subject to the same qualifications and elaborations of utility as earlier applied
to History as Travel, since the two justifications are in principle identical. Unlike
History as Emancipation II, which involves some normative evaluation of the
present, History as Emancipation I is purely descriptive of difference between
now and then. If it is not original to the fashions of the later twentieth century,
History as Emancipation I may nonetheless differ today in reach from earlier
iterations. More tends to be seen as socially/culturally constructed nowadays than
in Rousseau’s or Adam Ferguson’s time, or Montaigne’s day before that. Any given
claim about construction must be assessed on its own merits, but that is not as
straightforward as it sounds given the confusing jumble of epistemological, onto-
logical, moral, and political considerations often at issue.
The epistemological matter is a particular case of the general problem of distin-
guishing between our concepts or perceptions of a thing and that thing to which
our concepts or perceptions pertain. One form of social constructionism, the sort
most relevant for the coming discussion, would deny that there is any ‘way things
are’ apart from the way societies discuss or conceive of them. This is a species of
idealism. When testing the propositions of social constructionism one always
needs to ask philosopher Ian Hacking’s question The Social Construction of
What?106 The game of tennis is manifestly a purely social creation, likewise a par-
liament, but those sorts of things are not the sort of things that arguments tend to
get heated about, and granting the claims of social constructionism in certain
areas is by no means to mandate social constructionism as a general claim on the
nature of things, i.e. a general ontological claim. Some things Hacking would call
ontologically subjective, like tennis or customs or relations of production or par-
liaments. (Note that when a tennis match or a parliamentary session is in process,
it is still a matter of what Hacking calls epistemic objectivity whether player A won
a set or legislation B was passed.) Other things are ontologically objective, like
106 Ian Hacking, The Social Construction of What? (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press,
1999).
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
that mountain over there. The mountain is my example, though Hacking would
probably accept it as an example of something ontologically objective. Others
might or might not accept the example, and there are a host of matters in addition
that some might think to be ontologically objective and others think to be onto-
logically subjective. Some social constructionists argue, for instance, about ‘the
social construction of nature’, which can mean different things in different
mouths.107
Arguments about sex and differences or similarities of sex show how politically
loaded consideration of the relations between the historico-cultural and the
natural can be. It is absolutely appropriate that claims about what is taken to be
natural have come in for profound scrutiny in this areas since, as in the idea of
‘woman’s nature’, such claims have often been the spurious basis for assigning
social roles. So much hinges, however, on where and how and with what signifi-
cance the natural is held to fit into the debate in the first place, since particular
claims about the natural need have none of the social significance attached to
phrases like ‘women’s nature’—phrases that have a metaphysical air as much as
anything else. That, indeed, is the thesis that needs to be borne in mind over the
following few paragraphs, prior to my argument’s culmination. Over matters of
sex and much else besides, more may depend on the associations culturally (reli-
giously, philosophically, etc.) attributed to the natural than to the belief or the
warranted assertion that this or that thing is partly or wholly natural. Assuming
this argument holds, then if History can play an emancipatory role in the relevant
debates it may be a different role to that which it currently plays.
Using debates around sex as a point of departure, let us consider Thomas
Laqueur’s 1990 volume Making Sex: Body and Gender from the Greeks to Freud. It
was prominent in pressing on the distinction between sex and gender, a distinc-
tion whereby sex is seen as a biological matter and gender a matter of identity
shaped at some nexus of cultural ‘common-sense’ and subjective orientation.
Laqueur’s historical enquiry showed how scientific understandings of sex differ-
ence and similarity had changed over time. In Laqueur’s view ‘sex, as much as
gender, is made’, a somewhat opaque statement qualified by his disavowal of any
‘interest in denying the reality of sex or of sexual dimorphism as an evolutionary
process’. He noted the distinction in his book ‘between language on the one hand
and extralinguistic reality on the other; between nature and culture’. He sought to
navigate a separate path to ‘those who would eliminate gender by arguing that
so-called cultural differences are really natural’ and to those who ‘empty sex of its
content by arguing, conversely, that natural differences are really cultural’.108
107 David Demeritt, ‘What is the “social construction of nature”? A Typology and Sympathetic
Critique’, Progress in Human Geography, 26:6 (2002), 767–90.
108 Thomas W. Laqueur, Making Sex: Body and Gender from the Greeks to Freud (Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press, 1990), pp. ix, 11–12.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
Eighteen years later the historian Joan Scott placed herself in the second of these
camps as she addressed the same question of the relationship between gender and
sex, and put sex on entirely the same cultural footing as gender. Thus: ‘differences
of sex [are] not set by nature but [are] established through language’; ‘sex, like
gender, [has] to be understood as a system of attributed meaning. Neither [is]
about nature; both [are] products of culture.’109 As it happens, Scott also wrote of
‘the admittedly different bodies of women’ and approvingly quoted another schol-
ar’s unproblematized reference to ‘female physiology’,110 but did not reconcile her
belief in physiological differences with her belief in the thoroughgoing cultural
construction of sex. We will stay with her claim about cultural construction,
because, as with the stronger of two claims about linguistic idealism in ‘Evidence
of Experience’ (p. 290), that is the one that gives Scott’s argument its point of con-
troversy and celebrity. Scott’s stronger claim is of the form ‘not nature but instead
culture’. It is not the same as one of Laqueur’s points, the important one that ‘dif-
ference and sameness, more or less recondite, are everywhere; but which ones
count and for what ends is determined outside the bounds of empirical
investigation’.111 Scott’s claim rules out the possibility, suggested by Meryl Altman
and Keith Nightenhelser in response to parts of Laqueur’s book, that it is ‘not that
“sex” is socially constructed too, but simply that we need to move the boundary a
bit—that we’ve been calling some things “sex” that are really, after all, gender’.112
Scott also implicitly rules out the idea that the cultural and the natural could
be co-constitutive of an outcome, or that the cultural and the natural could inter-
penetrate. Either of these possibilities break down the sharp nature–culture
dichotomy that Scott deploys.113
In the same categorical not-nature-but-instead-culture vein, within a generally
fascinating volume that exemplifies the power of cultural History, Common
Bodies: Women, Touch and Power in Seventeenth Century England, Laura Gowing
writes that ‘the most apparently natural of bodily events and processes—like
desire, labour or motherhood—are the product of culture’.114 Putting aside
Gowing’s three stated examples, which need further elaboration anyway, and
focusing on the general principle that ‘the most apparently natural of bodily
events and processes . . . are the product of culture’, does she really wish to claim
this for all of the most apparently natural bodily events and processes? As regards
another statement emerging from the new cultural History, it may well be that
‘smell is cultural’ since ‘odours are invested with cultural values’ and that ‘smell is
historical, because its associations change over time’, but that is a distance from
saying that smell is only cultural or historical—indeed the contrasts across time
and culture can only be made against an assumed parameter of a common cap
acity to smell.115 Exemplifying the ‘culture-is-all historicism’ stance that Geertz
believed ‘no one of any seriousness holds’,116 the former president of the Modern
Language Association Robert Scholes wrote in 2006 that ‘we were natural for
eons before we were cultural—before we were human, even—but so what? We are
cultural now.’ And, he added ‘culture is the domain of the humanities’; science
was apparently irrelevant to considering humans today.117 In the vein of injunc-
tions to historicize everything, the literary theorist Jonathan Culler wrote that ‘the
main thrust of recent theory’ is ‘the critique of whatever is taken as natural, the
demonstration that what has been thought or declared natural is in fact a his
torical, cultural product’.118
One wonders about the prospects for thesis-challenging evidence in the face of
Culler’s determination to conclude on culture instead of nature. A note on
method is in order to check such potentially illegitimate conclusions as might be
reached by cultural History and related cultural theory. One certainly cannot base
claims about the culturally constructed—ontologically subjective—nature of, say,
sex or sex difference/similarity on consideration of historically variable discourses
on sex and sex-difference/similarity, since that approach begs the question. It pre-
supposes the culturally or linguistically determined conclusions that are sup
posedly reached by its deployment. In such matters it is not just ontological
objectivists that might have further questions to ask, but common-or-garden
sceptics too. Note that critical scepticism, with its ‘negative’ aspects, is not at all
the same as the strong positive claims about the—thoroughly constructed—way
of the world made by our constructionists. Both the objectivists and the sceptics
are entitled to ask the subjectivists/constructionists to answer the ‘how do you
115 The first two quotations are reproduced in Burke, What is Cultural History?, 113; the third, on
the same page, comprises Burke’s own words. I do not accuse him of refusing to acknowledge the
common capacity—he just does not discuss it. Note, though, that (p. 115) he records that his ‘own
inclination would be to reserve the term “cultural” for the history of phenomena that seem “natural”,
such as dreams, memory and time’. The same considerations would apply to dreams and memory as I
have applied to smell.
116 Geertz, ‘Anti Anti-Relativism’, 268.
117 Robert Scholes, ‘Reply’, Proceedings of the Modern Language Association, 121:1 (2006), 297–8.
118 Jonathan Culler, Literary Theory: A Very Short Introduction (Oxford: Oxford University Press,
1997), 14. Emphases added.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
know?’ question as thoroughly as the objectivists should answer it, and that may
well involve engaging with the full range of competent scientific and philosoph
ical opinion, rather than just cherrypicking conducive thinkers. With an eye to
warding off circularity, sceptics or objectivists about some aspect of sex or sex-
difference/similarity might advert to the genetic fallacy. They might contend that
all cultures past just got their understanding of the relevant issue wrong, and/or
that even if present understandings are as questionable as earlier ones that does
not mean there is not something extra-cultural about some aspect of sex or sex-
difference/similarity to be (mis-)understood in the first place.
For the overall argument here, it is important to establish the identity of the
claimants on the natural to which the constructionists are effectively responding.
Some claimants might be political authorities, perhaps backed by philosophers or
theologians, who are interested in instituting or sustaining particular social
orders. Others might be scientists. Perhaps the scientists and the political author
ities are the same people, but that is not always the case, and scientists have as
often been a threat to authorities as a buttress. Sometimes scientists have pro-
vided ‘justification’ for, say, claims about ‘racial’ inequality but they have also
challenged such claims.119 In other words, ‘science’ does not speak with a single
transhistorical voice. Would the most thoroughgoing not-nature-but-culture con-
structionists present the well-corroborated scientific conclusions about the
absence of innate ‘racial’ inferiority/superiority as really just the expression of
another culturally contingent way of thinking about the so-called natural, an out-
look needing immediate historicization? In practice, probably not, since on the
whole constructionists see their constructionism as politically progressive, and
the scientific conclusions as to innate equality are apt to be embraced in progres-
sive politics. Yet it is not clear that the strongest constructionists could say no in
principle, which illustrates that there is nothing intrinsically progressive about
thoroughgoing social constructionism and its conceptual tool, historicization.
Equally there is nothing intrinsically conservative, or controlling, or whatever,
about claims that such-and-such a thing is partly or wholly natural. So much
depends on the context in which the claims are made. Consider the debate about
homosexuality and the hypothalamus triggered by Simon LeVay in the 1990s: the
claim that homosexuality had an involuntary organic foundation is only ‘progres-
sive’ in a culture that otherwise claims that homosexuals could and ought to
change their sexual orientation, and equally in one that would not draw the
119 For instance Angela Saini’s works Superior (Boston, MA: Beacon Press, 2019) and Inferior
(London: Harper Collins, 2018) illustrate the role of scientists’ prejudices in producing racist and sex-
ist conclusions. Her criticism of the relevant science as deficient of course appeals to a standard of
relatively good science; the epistemically better science is also the less racist or sexist science. Laqueur,
Making Sex, 9–10, also makes an appeal to the better science when he writes that ‘what evidence there
does exist for biological difference with a gendered behavioral result is either highly suspect for a
variety of methodological reasons, or ambiguous, or proof of Dorothy Sayers’ notion that men and
women are very close neighbors indeed if it is proof of anything at all.’
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
120 Thanks to Jane Caplan for this point and for the references: Simon LeVay, The Sexual Brain
(Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1993) and Queer Science: The Use and Abuse of Research into Sexuality
(Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1996).
121 On creation as the book of God: Rigby, Wisdom and Chivalry, 236 ff.
122 Agence France-Presse, ‘Vatican launches guide to tackle “educational crisis” on gender’,
Guardian, 11 June 2019.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
123 On related scenarios and associated anxieties, see Wahrman, ‘Change and the Corporeal’,
597–8.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
124 All quotes from Sharon Block, Rape and Sexual Power in Early America (Chapel Hill: University
of North Carolina Press, 2006), 7, 241. Again, thanks to Wahrman, ‘Change and the Corporeal’, 598–9,
for adverting me to the text and its relevant elements. Wahrman also provides a justly appreciative
account of Block’s work.
125 Note the influence on this discussion of Robert B. Pippin, ‘Natural and Normative’, Daedalus
(Summer 2009), 35–43.
126 Ania Spyra, ‘Is Cosmopolitanism Not For Women? Migration in Qurratulain Hyder’s Sita
Betrayed and Amitav Ghosh’s The Shadow Lines’, Frontiers: A Journal of Women Studies, 27:2 (2006),
1–26, here 1. See also Sonya O. Rose, What is Gender History? (Cambridge: Polity, 2010), 103 on ‘dis-
embodied white men’ as a particular case of the issue.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
Such an argument is supposedly rebutted if what looks like the natural (in this
example, the body) is actually claimed to be a cultural construct. This keeps the
study of the body as the preserve of students of the cultural, and just renders it
part of the broader cultural fabric, its discourses, language, etc., that are held to
constitute subjecthood. So the terms of mind:world (including mind:body) dual-
ism are replaced with ‘mind:culture’ as a prelude to immediately breaking down
any such dualism and replacing it, in the strongest version of the new argument,
with a relationship of culture→mind determinism. This looks like a weak form of
subjecthood if one is still thinking in individualistic terms, since the individual is
really just a function of the cultural. But cultures are humanmade, even if not by
individual persons. Accordingly, the anti-Cartesian theory is still anthropocentric
and stronger in relevant respects than the Cartesian/Baconian vision, since in the
latter the (individual) mind is only put in a position to perceive and alter the nat
ural world whereas in the former, with the power of the culture substituted for the
power of the mind, the culture is capable of creating what has hitherto been mis-
takenly identified as the natural world. Where the individual mind returns to the
picture is in the persona of our Foucauldians and semiotic code-crackers. By the
magic of their ‘critique’ they have managed to break out of the discursive prison,
stray from the ordained script, and so forth. The power of the liberating thought
of these critics correlates positively with the supposed constituting strength of the
discourses from which they free themselves and purport to free others with neo-
historicist reference to things like historical-cultural contingency. The idealist
insight that that which is thought about the world is part of the world gets
expanded to the point that thought (or in the Foucauldian case discourse)
becomes the determinant of the world ‘in itself ’.
If you are unpersuaded of the efficacy of this sort of thinking, but nonetheless
object to the role that claims on the natural play in the politics of your world, you
need to be clear who your interlocutors are in any given case. This will affect the
sorts of arguments you need to make against them and will provide you with
strategies for playing them off against each other in the event that they form con-
tingent alliances. We have already identified two potential interlocutors: natural
scientists or some subset thereof, and socio-political authorities leaning on cer-
tain metaphysical (whether religious or philosophical) claims. When talking of
politics and legitimation, these two groups must in turn be conceptually separ
ated—whatever the overlaps that may exist in practice—from a third group, those
whom we might call conservatives.
When talking of conservatives one must distinguish the classical theory of
conservatism, as represented in the recent past by the likes of Michael Oakeshott,
from certain usages in the contemporary British and American environments
where ‘conservative’ is applied to the avant-garde of a revolutionary neo-liberal
capitalism. Conservatives in the classical sense differ from the scientists because
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
the natural and the metaphysical need play no part in their discourse (though it
often has), even as the normative must. In archetype, the differences between the
groups are as follows:
• Scientists make claims on the natural with no necessary relevance for the
normative;
• Metaphysicians (the relevant ones) use the natural to substantiate claims on
the normative based on metaphysical presuppositions about the natural;
• Conservatives make claims on the normative based on the cultural, or put
differently, the culturally given has a normative status for them.
Conservatives are the ones whose claims on how things should be are apt most
frequently to involve evaluative attitudes to the past, given the relationship between
culture and history. This brings us finally to the terrain of History as Identity,
which is the ground on which many exponents of History as Emancipation are
actually operating anyway, whatever they might think.
History as Identity
History as Identity means that subset of historical enquiry that shapes readers’,
listeners’, and observers’ thoughts and feelings about their heritage. Some forms
of History as Identity are coextensive with a secularized form of History as
Communion. Identity History is widely consumed and readily recognizable, apt
as it is to address particular wars, revolutions, national stories, triumphs, losses,
and whatnot. It frequently forms an alliance of commercial convenience with
History as Entertainment.127 It can dovetail with History as Memorialization
when the memorialized deeds are specifically the deeds of one’s own claimed
forebears. A touch of similitudo temporum (pp. 124–6) might close the historical
‘gap’ between the memorialized past and the present for which the past is touch-
stone. At that point one cannot insert a cigarette paper between inspirational,
‘monumental’ History (in Nietzsche’s term—p. 221) and History as Lesson.
No criticism is intended by the label History as Identity. Different historians
operating in the tradition operate with different political agendas and differing
levels of proceduralist commitment. Different readers approach it with different
expectations and minds of varying degrees of openness. Some read just to find
out more about where they have ‘come from’, as the saying goes, based on the
127 I stress ‘convenience’. The commercial potential of History as Identity favours this union, but by
no means all commercially successful historians are Identity historians or Entertainment historians of
the more gratuitous sort; by the same token, the great mass of practising historians who have no com-
mercial success contain within their number Identity historians. Note also that the Entertainment and
Travel rationales have found just as rich a synergy.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
widespread feeling that this will tell them something about who they are. Others
want affirmation of a collective identity. Yet others seek substantiation for the dis-
sent they already espouse.
The potentially significant political ramifications of History in its Identity
mode mean that it has many more exponents than just academic historians, and
fewer professed than actual exponents amongst the ranks of academic historians.
Its practitioners could be museum curators, documentary makers, school
teachers, architects, city planners, politicians, newspaper editors, tour guides,
historical novelists, film directors, elders, parents . . . The list indicates how far all
of us are always-already under the influence of explicit historical interpretations
and meaning-laden historical imagery before we begin any enquiries of our own.
In identity History the potential for tension between ‘ “modern” historical con-
sciousness’ and ‘historicity’ is greatest. By historicity I mean the subjective way in
which one sees oneself as the product of particular historical patterns and institu-
tions, but also the objective ways in which one’s outlook, privileges, and disadvan-
tages are influenced by such institutions whether one realizes it or not. It will not
necessarily do, therefore, just to proclaim one’s emancipation from the past
because one does not feel connected to it. Recall the words of Fustel, notwith-
standing his injunction to study the past as if it were a ‘foreign nation’: ‘the past
never completely dies for man. Man may forget it, but he always preserves it
within him. For, take him at any epoch, and he is the product, the epitome, of all
the earlier epochs. Let him look into his own soul, and he can find and distin-
guish these different epochs by what each has left within him’. As well as his soul,
we might add, let ‘him’ look into his circumstances.
For those who embrace the idea, ‘ “modern” historical consciousness’ is a sub-
jective awareness of an objective reality, i.e. an awareness of actual differences of
present from past. Things are not so simple. What is taken for ‘awareness’ here is
not the correspondence of perception to external reality but the product of vari
able judgements about the significance and extent of various differences across
time. And what if something is adjudged to be significantly different under the
rubric of historical consciousness, yet still relevant under the rubric of historicity?
Establishing that something is a foreign country does not mean one has nothing
to do with it except the occasional holiday. Cross-border wars, alliances, and
commerce are not rarities in human history. They need not bespeak similarity
between the relevant parties but they undoubtedly indicate influence from one
party to another, and what goes synchronically, across place, can go diachronic
ally, across time.
In clarifying the issues at stake in identity-arguments, it is important to recog-
nize how many claims about the nature of the relationship of past to present and
future are imbued with judgements as to the desirability of that relationship, as
was the case in sundry debates across the centuries between antiqui and moderni
(pp. 79–85). Why, for instance, in and beyond the nineteenth century, was
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
128 There was also a close relationship between socialists and dialectics, but I shall ignore that
nexus in the interests of relative clarity in dense conceptual terrain.
129 Michael Oakeshott, Rationalism in Politics and Other Essays (New York: Basic Books, 1962).
130 Hans Blumenberg, The Legitimacy of the Modern Age (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1999) is the
source of the distinction between self-foundation and self-assertion. See also the helpful discussion in
Chantal Mouffe, The Return of the Political (London: Verso, 2005), 10–11, 41–2.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
131 Richard Rorty, Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity (Cambridge University Press, 1989).
132 Arlie Hochschild, Strangers in their Own Land: Anger and Mourning on the American Right
(New York: The New Press, 2016).
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
At the same time, substantial numbers of people reject particular deep stories,
or want to revise them, or wish to articulate their own deep story as against
another that has occluded it. Any of these endeavours is apt to be incendiary
given that they strike at the identity, with all of its more and less inchoate, reflex,
or reflective assumptions of the comforting, the orienting, the good. Just think of
the touchiness about empire or slavery in Britain and the USA: the knee-jerk jus-
tifications, the avoidance, awkward deflection, or some reference to the ‘values of
the time’ whose logic of distancing—it sounds like an appeal to the truths of the
‘modern historical consciousness’—is contradicted by the fact that it is obviously
uttered in defence of something that the defender’s historicity renders relevant in
the now. Sometimes the claim will be that one story is downright false, sometimes
that it contains important omissions and is skewed to serve one part of a com-
munity more than others. Sometimes the arrangements that have proved good for
one group might be shown to have been deleterious for others, which reminds us
that groups rarely develop in isolation from others, and so cannot always insist on
the right to be left alone to their positive feelings about their historical identity. If
the deep story concerns home, what happens when it is revealed that the home
was built on stolen land, by slave labour?
Debates about reparations for historical wrongs are only the tip of the concep-
tual iceberg, but they highlight something important about the objective element
of historicity. They remind that some groups are beneficiaries of historical inter-
actions, and whether or not any given members of such a group subjectively iden-
tify with their victor-forebears, they may still owe relatively advantageous
life-circumstances to those forebears. The question then, as with affirmative
action—based as it is on the principle of levelling a historically tilted playing
field—is what they are going to do about it.
Deep story battles are fronts in the conflict that we ascribe to identity politics.
We need, though, to remember that identity politics and identity History are not
just the preserve of minorities and the weak, but of majorities and the strong too.
It is an error to assume that the currently prevailing story, or the one that used to
prevail prior to recent contestation, is the only non-political one. This is the error
that the historian and diplomat Gerard Libaridian pinpoints when he writes that
‘Historians often function not only with the benefit of hindsight but also through
the recognition of [contemporary] political realities of which they are a part. In
their zeal to remain “non-political” they tacitly accept the assumption underlying
that same system.’ Their questions are influenced by the imperative to ‘interpret
the past in a way that it does not challenge the rationale of the present. This
mutual reinforcement between particular perceptions of the past and the present,
seen as objective since it implies no critique of the present, emanates from a spe-
cific ideological perspective.’133
133 Gerard J. Libaridian, ‘Objectivity and the Historiography of the Armenian Genocide’, The
Armenian Review, 31:1 (1978), 79–87, here 83.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
With identity History in mind, perhaps the most important question is not:
how do vocational historians rationalize what they do? Perhaps it is: given that
the past matters in questions of identity, what are we who spend our lives investi-
gating the past going to do about it? We are not obliged to engage in identity
History: interests vary immensely, and long may that be so. But what about when
our interests do coincide with identity topics?
Theoretical trepidation about engaging on this terrain is relatively recent, being
a product of that confluence of tributary streams named neutralism, pacifism,
relativism, and so forth. The trepidation ought not be overstated, because some
historiographical theorists, and many historical practitioners, would say that
identity-relevant History can be conducted according to the tenets of one or more
of those tributary streams in the way that any other sort of History can be. As it
happens, there are reasons to disagree both with the people who worry about the
potential for partisanship in the area of identity History alone and with some of
those who think that it can be conducted ‘unproblematically’ like other sorts of
History. So much depends on what the ‘normal’ way of conducting History is
meant to involve. Having already problematized appeals to relativism and the
tolerance-building capacities of History, let us now problematize ‘neutrality’. By
its special contemporary sensitivity, History in the Identity vein shines a bright
light on unavoidable normative questions, and while these questions are just as
unavoidable in some other areas of historical enquiry, there are obvious contem
porary political consequences of Identity History in the way in which these evalu-
ative questions are answered, whereas that may not be the case in others areas.
The whole issue is clouded in confusion, not least because for so long evaluative
thought was seen as coterminous with exemplarity—History as Lesson—and as
the latter receded as a justification for History, the former was either assumed
likewise to have receded or was regarded as an anachronistic vestige that proper
application of proceduralist precepts would eliminate.
Remember, first, that there is no necessary contradiction between faithfulness
to procedure and political engagement (pp. 311–12). A criticism of some narra-
tive of the ‘rise of X’ or ‘the benevolence of Y’ could at once be politically
motivated and more plausible—better substantiated—than the narrative under
criticism. As the literature scholar Brook Thomas once wrote, ‘so long as we
believe that we are empowered by knowledge of our situation in the world and so
long as we believe that that situation has in part been determined by the past, the
most empowering study of the past will be the one that comes as close as possible
to telling how it really was’.134
134 Brook Thomas, ‘The New Historicism and other Old-Fashioned Topics’, in Veeser (ed.), The
New Historicism, 182–203, here 201. Thomas’s final—Rankean—words should not distract from his
point: the concept of telling it how it was can easily be substituted for some more epistemologically
respectable construction about warranted inference from evidence.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
135 Leland Hamilton Jenks, The Migration of British Capital to 1875 (New York: A. A. Knopf,
1927), 225.
136 Colin Richmond, ‘Mickey Mouse in Disneyland: How Did the Fifteenth Century Get that
Way?’, in Linda Clark (ed.), The Fifteenth Century: V: Of Mice and Men: Image, Belief and Regulation in
Late Medieval England (Woodbridge: The Boydell Press, 2005), 157–70, here 166.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
Even in the event that it seems power was legitimately wielded by the lights of
the wielder, this is no guarantee that the object of the power felt the same way.
Differences of opinion as to legitimacy may constitute one of the major cleavages
in identity History, and the absence of just one set of standards ‘back then’
reminds us why it is often insufficient to adopt a crypto-relativistic argument to
‘the standards of the time’. Such crypto-relativist arguments may or may not affect
our judgements towards individual slaveowners, imperialists, and so on, as his
torically situated agents acting with particular cultural assumptions, but those
arguments cannot affect our normative attitudes to the institutions and practices
of slavery, empire, and so on.
Remember, in the foregoing discussion of relativism, the significance for the
evaluative process of historical practices themselves: the human consequences of
these practices in happiness or suffering (pp. 326–8). The historian is in charge of
the portrayal of such practices and/or their human consequences, and even if she
refrains from explicit judgement, the way that such matters are discussed, consti-
tutive silences and all (p. 295) has the potential to evoke some response by the
reader. With this in mind, how should the historian proceed? If the answer is that
her description and explanation ought to be as ‘balanced’ as possible, then, again,
we are already in the normative universe. If the answer is that she should write in
such a way that she is likely to produce no response whatsoever from the reader,
might we not think that slightly strange? It is unclear that the demand for the
historian’s ‘neutrality’ must mean that the historian has to try to ‘neutralize’, since
that term itself suggests some agenda of manipulation: ‘neutralization’ is not
‘neutral’.
It is difficult to reconcile neutralization with the procedural requirement of
truthfulness, for trying to ‘get it right’, since ‘getting it right’ might involve show-
ing that as far as one can infer from the evidence, historical character or interest
group X was responsible for whipping up hatred against group Y. If we take the
act of trying to ‘be fair’ to relevant historical actors to be synonymous with trying
to be accurate about them based on the evidence, then obviously enough ‘being
fair’ to them is not the same thing as ‘being nice’ to them or treating them neu-
trally. It may mean treating them impartially but, according to definition, that can
be a very different thing. Under one definition, impartiality is a position that one
adopts as the way to reach the best conclusion, and so actually implies the judge-
ment that ‘neutrality’ rejects. One might also think of a definition of ‘impartiality’
appropriate to the historian’s particular ethic of responsibility. Where civil ser
vants ought ‘impartially’ to implement the policies of the government of the day
on recognition that that government is legitimate, historians ought ‘impartially’
to report their interpretations of the past with no consideration for how much
they might irritate the government of the day. Historians might thus be playing a
political role, even a democratic one, but it is a role whose integrity is guaranteed
precisely by their not betraying their procedural ethic in the service of any con-
stituency or regime.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
It is fair to point out that historians are generally not trained in the sort of
evaluative reasoning that might make any of their judgements reliable, but what is
the thrust of that observation supposed to be? If it is to prompt historians to
acquaint themselves better with the tenets of evaluative reasoning, that is one
thing, and a rather good idea, though it ought not be thought that such training
will lead to unanimity in judgement, any more than the other elements of train-
ing lead to unanimity in conclusion in any other area of historical enquiry. If,
however, the point about training underpins an argument against historians mak-
ing evaluations then that is also an argument against historians doing the sorts of
History in which evaluations or evocative or neutralizing descriptions are
unavoidable. We can argue about precisely how many categories of History that
would exclude but it would likely rule out several areas of History as Identity,
Travel, Lesson, Memorialization, and Emancipation, which together account for a
great deal of all the History written and even more of the History that is read by
the general public. To be clear: the only way historians in the relevant areas could
escape normative engagement, as opposed to continuing to use evocative lan-
guage and make evaluative analyses without admitting it, is not to write or speak
on those areas. This would be a pity because it would remove empirically
informed voices when they are most needed.
If the idea of making or consciously prompting judgements sounds presump-
tuous, it is really nothing more than an expression of the responsibility that his
torians take on when engaging in the first place with historical matters of moral
significance. This responsibility is the quantum of the power historians can wield
in a world where opinions about the past still have fundamental importance.
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
History
History and Theory
History Workshop Journal
Histos
Hume Studies
I Tatti Studies in the Italian Renaissance
Indian Historical Review
International Affairs
International History of Science Newsletter
Ius commune
Journal of Contemporary History
Journal of Historical Sociology
Journal of the History of IdeasJournal of Interdisciplinary History
Journal of Literary Theory
Journal of Medieval and Early Modern Studies
Journal of the Philosophy of History
Journal of Roman Studies
Klio
Le Débat
London Review of Books
Modern Intellectual History
Midland History
Ministry Magazine
Mittellateinisches Jahrbuch
Modern Language Notes
Museum and Society
Nature and Culture
Nepantla: Views from South
New Literary History
Nietzsche-Studien
Observer
Oxford Studies in Early Modern Philosophy
Parergon
Past and Present
Patterns of Prejudice
Pecia. Le livre et l’écrit
Philosophical Forum
Philosophical Quarterly
Philosophical Review
Philosophy
Philosophy and Literature
Polity
Postmodern Culture
Praxis International
Principia
Proceedings of the Modern Language Association
Progress in Human Geography
Public Culture
Renascimento
Rethinking History
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
Online materials
Kenneth Bartlett interview: https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=Px1GwHyAYXs
Leonardo Bruni, Laudatio Florentinae Urbis or Panegyric to the City of Florence (c.1403–4),
online at https://www.york.ac.uk/teaching/history/pjpg/bruni.pdf
Collection des documents inédits sur l’histoire de France: https://cths.fr/ed/liste.php?
monocrit=c&collection=18
Stephan Collini, ‘Intellectual History’ online at: http://www.history.ac.uk/makinghistory/
resources/articles/intellectual_history.html
Matthew Crow, ‘Context as Environment: A “Workmanlike” Approach’, online at http://
historyofthepresent.org/forum/M_Crow_Context_as_Environ.pdf
The Encyclopedia of Ancient History, Wiley online library 2012: https://onlinelibrary.wiley.
com/
Steven Fielding, ‘Political History’, online at: http://www.history.ac.uk/makinghistory/
resources/articles/political_history.html
Patrick Finney, ‘International History’, online at: http://www.history.ac.uk/makinghistory/
resources/articles/international_history.html
Lloyd Gerson, ‘Plotinus’, in Edward N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of (Summer
2014 edn.): https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2014/entries/plotinus/
Chris Gowans, ‘Moral Relativism’, in Edward N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of
Philosophy (Summer 2019 edn.): https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2019/entries/
moral-relativism/
History and Policy: http://www.historyandpolicy.org/policy-papers/
Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy: http://www.iep.utm.edu/origen-of-alexandria/#SH5b
Jewish virtual library: http://www.jewishvirtuallibrary.org/jsource/judaica/ejud_0002_
0008_0_08624.html
Monumenta Germaniae Historica: https://www.dmgh.de/
Books
Abelard, Peter, Letters IX–XIV, ed. Edmé Renno Smits (Groningen: Bouma, 1983).
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
Bambach, Charles R., Heidegger, Dilthey, and the Crisis of Historicism (Ithaca: Cornell
University Press, 1995).
Baragwanath, Emily, and Mathieu de Bakker (eds.), Myth, Truth and Narrative in
Herodotus (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012).
Barnes, Timothy D., Ammianus Marcellinus and the Representation of Historical Reality
(Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1998).
Baron, Christopher A., Timaeus of Tauromenium and Hellenistic Historiography (New
York: Cambridge University Press, 2013).
Barraclough, Geoffrey, History in a Changing World (Norman, OK: University of Oklahoma
Press, 1956).
Barraclough, Geoffrey, Introduction to Contemporary History (Harmondsworth: Penguin,
1967).
Barrett, James R., History from the Bottom Up and the Inside Out: Ethnicity, Race, and
Identity in Working-Class History (Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 2017).
Barthes, Roland, Michelet (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1992).
Bartlett, Kenneth R. (ed.), The Civilization of the Italian Renaissance: A Sourcebook
(Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 2011).
Bartlett, Robert, Gerald of Wales, 1146–1223 (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1982).
Bartlett, Robert, The Natural and the Supernatural in the Middle Ages (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2008).
Baswell, Christopher, Virgil in Medieval England (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1995).
Baum, Gregory, The Social Imperative (New York: Paulist Press, 1979).
Baynes, K., J. Bonman, and T. McCarthy (eds), After Philosophy, End or Transformation?
(Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1987).
Beard, Charles A., An Economic Interpretation of the Constitution of the United States
(New York: The Free Press, 1965).
Beck, Hans, and Uwe Walter, Die frühen römischen Historiker, 2 vols. (Darmstadt:
Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, 2001, 2004).
Becker, Carl Lotus, Detachment and the Writing of History (Ithaca: Cornell University
Press, 1958).
Bede, Ecclesiastical History of the English People, ed. Leo Sherley-Price and D. H. Farmer
(London: Penguin, 1990), and ed. Judith McClure and Roger Collins (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1999).
Beer, Jeanette, Villehardouin: Epic Historian (Geneva: Droz, 1968).
Beiser, Frederick(ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Hegel and Nineteenth Century
Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2008).
Bell, Jeffrey A., and Claire Colebrook (eds.), Deleuze and History (Edinburgh: Edinburgh
University Press, 2009).
Bennett, Judith M., History Matters: Patriarchy and the Challenge of Feminism
(Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 2006).
Benson, Robert L., and Giles Constable (eds.), Renaissance and Renewal in the Twelfth
Century (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1985).
Bentley, Michael, Modernizing England’s Past: English Historiography in the Age of
Modernism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005).
Bentley, Michael(ed.), Companion to Historiography (Abingdon: Routledge, 2007).
Berg, Maxine, A Woman in History: Eileen Power 1889–1940 (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1996).
Berger, Alan L., and David Patterson, Jewish–Christian Dialogue: Drawing Honey from the
Rock (St Paul, MN: Paragon House, 2008).
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
Bod, Rens, Jaap Maat, and Thijs Weststeijn (eds.), The Making of the Humanities, 2 vols
(Amsterdam: Amsterdam University Press, 2010 and 2012).
Bolingbroke, Henry St John, Lord Viscount, Letters on the Study and Use of History
(London: T. Cadell, 1779).
Bonnell, Victoria E., and Lynn Hunt (eds.), Beyond the Cultural Turn (Berkeley: University
of California Press, 1999).
Bossuet, Jacques-Bénigne, An Universal History from the Beginning of the World to the
Empire of Charlemagne (New York: Robert Moore, 1821).
Bourdieu, Pierre, Outline of a Theory of Practice (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
2003).
Bourdieu, Pierre, and Loïc Wacquant, An Invitation to Reflexive Sociology (Cambridge:
Polity, 1992).
Braudel, Fernand, The Mediterranean and the Mediterranean World in the Age of Philip II,
vol. 1 (London: Collins, 1972), vol. 2 (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1995).
Braudel, Fernand, On History (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1980).
Brazeau, Brian, Writing a New France, 1604–1632: Empire and Early Modern French
Identity (London: Routledge, 2016).
Breisach, Ernst, Historiography: Ancient, Medieval and Modern (Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 2007).
Brett, Martin, and David A. Woodman (eds.), The Long Twelfth-Century View of the Anglo-
Saxon Past (Farnham: Ashgate, 2015).
Briggs, Charles F., The Body Broken: Medieval Europe, 1300–1520 (London: Routledge
2011).
Brooks, Van Wyck, The Wine of the Puritans (London: Sisley’s, 1908).
Brown, Callum G., Postmodernism for Historians (Harlow: Pearson, 2005).
Brown, Patricia Fortini, Venice and Antiquity: The Venetian Sense of the Past (New Haven:
Yale University Press, 1996).
Buchanan, George Wesley, The Book of Daniel (Eugene, OR: Wipf and Stock, 1999).
Burckhardt, Jacob, The Civilization of the Renaissance in Italy (London: Penguin, 2004).
Burguière, André, L’École des Annales. Une histoire intellectuelle (Paris: Odile Jacob, 2006).
Burke, Peter, The Renaissance Sense of the Past (London: Arnold, 1969).
Burke, Peter (ed.), New Perspectives on Historical Writing (University Park: Pennslyvania
State University Press, 1992).
Burrow, John, A History of Histories (London: Allen Lane, 2007).
Burrow, Rufus, Jr, James H. Cone and Black Liberation Theology (Jefferson, NC: McFarland,
1994).
Burschel, Peter, Mark Häberlein, and Volker Reinhardt (eds.), Historische Anstöße (Berlin:
Akademie, 2002).
Butterfield, Herbert, Christianity, Diplomacy and War (London: Epworth, 1953).
Butterfield, Herbert, The Whig Interpretation of History (New York: Norton, 1965).
Cahn, Steven M. (ed.), Classics of Western Philosophy (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1990).
Calhoun, Craig (ed.) Sociology in American: A History (Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 2007).
Callinicos, Alex, Theories and Narratives: Reflections on the Philosophy of History (Durham,
NC: Duke University Press, 1995).
Cameron, Averil, Procopius and the Sixth Century (Berkeley: University of California Press,
1985).
Canning, Joseph, The Political Thought of Baldis de Ubaldis (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1987).
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
Caputo, John D., Radical Hermeneutics: Repetition, Deconstruction, and the Hermeneutic
Project (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1987).
Caputo, John D., The Prayers and Tears of Jacques Derrida: Religion Without Religion
(Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1997).
Carlyle, Thomas, Sartor Resartus, Heroes and Hero-Worship, Past and Present, ed.
G.T. Bettany (London: Ward, Lock and Co., 1892).
Carr, E. H., What Is History? (New York: Knopf, 1962).
Cassirer, Ernst, The Myth of the State (Hamburg: Meiner Verlag, 2007).
Chalkokondyles, Laonikos, The Histories, 2 vols., ed. Anthony Kaldellis (Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press, 2014).
Chakrabarty, Dipesh, Provincializing Europe: Postcolonial Thought and Historical Difference
(Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2000).
Chambers, David, Brian Pullan, and Jennifer Fletcher (eds.), Venice: A Documentary
History, 1450–1630 (Oxford: Blackwell, 1992).
Chaturvedi, Vinayak (ed.), Mapping Subaltern Studies and the Postcolonial (London: Verso,
2012).
Chenu, Marie-Dominique, Nature, Man, and Society in the Twelfth Century (Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 1968).
Chesnut, Glenn F., The First Christian Histories: Eusebius, Socrates, Sozomen, Theodoret,
and Evagrius (Macon, GA: Mercer University Press, 1986).
Chesterton, G. K., Tremendous Trifles (London: Methuen, 1909).
Chodorow, Stanley, Christian Political Theory and Church Politics in the Mid-Twelfth
Century (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1972).
Ciaffa, Jay A., Max Weber and the Problems of Value-Free Social Science (Cranbury, NJ:
Associated University Presses, 1998).
Cicero, Cicero: On the Orator, Books 1–2, trans. E. W. Sutton and H. Rackham (London:
Heinemann, 1967).
Clark, George Kitson, The Critical Historian (London: History Book Club, 1968).
Clark, Linda (ed.), The Fifteenth Century: V: Of Mice and Men: Image, Belief and Regulation
in Late Medieval England (Woodbridge: The Boydell Press, 2005).
Clemoes, Peter, and Kathleen Hughes (eds.), England before the Conquest (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1971).
Cochran, Terry, Twilight of the Literary: Figures of Thought in the Age of Print (Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press, 2001).
Coleman, Janet, Piers Plowman and the Moderni (Rome: Edizioni di Storia e Letteratura,
1981).
Coleman, Janet, Ancient and Medieval Memories: Studies in the Reconstruction of the Past
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005).
Colley, Linda, Britons: Forging the Nation, 1707–1837 (New Haven: Yale University Press,
2005).
Collingwood, R. G., The Idea of History, revised edition (Oxford: Oxford University Press,
2005).
Commager, H. S., The Search for a Usable Past (New York: Knopf, 1967).
Comte, Auguste, The Positive Philosophy of Auguste Comte, vol. 2, ed. Harriet Martineau
(London: Trübner, 1875).
Condorcet, Nicolas de, Tableau historique des progrès de l’esprit humain: projets, esquisse,
fragments et notes (1772–1794), ed. Jean-Pierre Schandeler and Pierre Crépel (Paris:
L’Institute National d’Études Démographique, 2004).
Constable, Giles, The Reformation of the Twelfth Century (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2002).
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
Dauenhauer, Bernard P. (ed.), At the Nexus of Philosophy and History (Athens, GA:
University of Georgia Press, 2010).
Davies, Elizabeth Gould, The First Sex (New York: Penguin, 1971).
Davies, Stephen, Empiricism and History (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2003).
Davis, Natalie Zemon, The Return of Martin Guerre (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press, 1983).
Dawson, David, Christian Figural Reading and the Fashioning of Identity (Berkeley:
University of California Press, 2001).
De Bom, Erik, Marijke Janssens, Toon Van Houdt, and Jan Papy (eds.), (Un)masking the
Realities of Power: Justus Lipsius and the Dynamics of Political Writing in Early Modern
Europe (Leiden: Brill, 2010).
Delanty, Gerard, Social Science: Philosophical and Methodological Foundations (Maidenhead:
Open University Press, 2005).
de Mul, Jos, The Tragedy of Finitude: Dilthey’s Hermeneutics of Life (New Haven: Yale
University Press, 2004).
Derrida, Jacques, Margins of Philosophy (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1982).
Derrida, Jacques, Positions (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1982).
Derrida, Jacques, Limited Inc. (Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 1988).
Derrida, Jacques, Archive Fever: A Freudian Impression (Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 1996).
Derrida, Jacques, Writing and Difference, ed. Alan Bass (London: Routledge, 2005).
Desan, Philippe (ed.), Montaigne politique (Paris: Honoré Champion Éditeur, 2006).
Descartes, René, Discourse on Method, trans. Andrew Wollaston (Harmondsworth:
Penguin, 1960).
Dickens, A. G., The Age of Humanism and Reformation (London: Prentice Hall, 1977).
Dickson, Gwen Griffith, Johann Georg Hamann’s Relational Metacriticism (Berlin: de
Gruyter, 1995).
Dierken, Jörg, Selbstbewusstsein individueller Freiheit: religionstheoretische Erkundungen in
protestantischer Perspektive (Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck, 2005).
Di Leo, Jeffrey R. (ed.), Federman’s Fictions (Albany, NY: SUNY, 2011).
Dilthey, Wilhelm, Dilthey: Selected Writings, ed. H. P. Rickman (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1976).
Dionysius of Halicarnassus, On Thucydides, ed. W. Kendrick Pritchett (Berkeley: University
of California Press, 1975).
DiVanna, Isabel, Reconstructing the Middle Ages: Gaston Paris and the Development of
Nineteenth-Century Medievalism (Newcastle: Cambridge Scholars Press, 2008).
Dobbs, Betty Jo Teeter, The Janus Faces of Genius: The Role of Alchemy in Newton’s Thought
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991).
Donagan, Alan, The Later Philosophy of R. G. Collingwood (Oxford: Clarendon Press,
1962).
Dosse, François, New History in France: The Triumph of the Annales (Chicago: University
of Illinois Press, 1994).
Dosse, François, History of Structuralism: vol. 2: The Sign Sets, 1967–Present (Minneapolis:
University of Minnesota Press, 1998).
Downing, F. Gerald, Cynics, Paul and the Pauline Church (London: Routledge, 1998).
Dray, William, Perspectives on History (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1980).
Droysen, Johann Gustav, Geschichte Alexanders des Grossen (Hamburg: Perthes, 1833).
Droysen, Johann Gustav, Geschichte des Hellenismus, 2 vols. (Hamburg: Perthes, 1836–43).
Droysen, Johann Gustav, Geschichte der preussischen Politik, 14 vols. (Leipzig: Veit,
1855–86).
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
Feldherr, Andrew, and Grant Hardy (eds.) The Oxford History of Historical Writing:
Beginnings to AD 600 (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011).
Feldman, Louis H., Studies in Hellenistic Judaism (Leiden: Brill, 1996).
Ferguson, Niall, The Pity of War (New York: Basic Books, 1999).
Ferguson, Wallace K., The Renaissance in Historical Thought (New York: Houghton Mifflin,
1948).
Fischer, Fritz, Griff nach der Weltmacht (Düsseldorf: Droste, 1961).
Fish, Stanley, The Trouble with Principle (Cambride, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999).
Fleischacker, Samuel, Integrity and Moral Relativism (Leiden: Brill, 1992).
Fleischer, Helmut, Marxism and History (New York: Harper, 1973).
Flierman, Robert, Saxon Identities, AD 150–900 (London: Bloomsbury, 2017).
Flynn, Thomas R., Sartre, Foucault and Historical Reason, 2 vols. (Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 1997 and 2005).
Fornara, Charles William, The Nature of History in Ancient Greece and Rome (Berkeley:
University of California Press, 1983).
Forster, Michael N., Hegel’s Idea of a Phenomenology of Spirit (Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 1998).
Foucault, Michel, The Archaeology of Knowledge (New York: Pantheon, 1972).
Foucault, Michel, Discipline and Punish (London: Penguin, 1991).
Foucault, Michel, Ethics: Subjectivity and Truth, ed. Paul Rabinow (New York: New Press,
1997).
Foucault, Michel, Society Must be Defended, ed. Mauro Bertani and Alessandro Fontana
(New York: Picador, 2003).
Fox, Christopher, Roy Porter, and Robert Wokler (eds.), Inventing Human Science:
Eighteenth-Century Domains (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1995).
Fox-Genovese, Elizabeth, and Elisabeth Lasch-Quinn (eds.), Reconstructing History
(London, Routledge, 1999).
Frampton, Travis L., Spinoza and the Rise of Historical Criticism of the Bible (New York:
Clark, 2006).
Franco, Paul, Michael Oakeshott: An Introduction (New Haven: Yale University Press,
2004).
Frank, Jill, A Democracy of Distinction: Aristotle and the Work Of Politics (London:
University of Chicago Press, 2005).
Franklin, John Hope, The Free Negro in North Carolina, 1790–1860 (Chapel Hill: University
of North Carolina Press, 1943).
Franklin, John Hope, Mirror to America (New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux, 2005).
Friedländer, Saul (ed.), Probing the Limits of Representation (Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press, 1992).
Froissart, Jean, Chronicles, ed. Geoffrey Brereton (London: Penguin, 1978).
Frye, Northrop, Fables of Identity: Studies in Poetic Mythology (New York: Harcourt, Brace,
and World, 1963).
Fuggle, S., Y. Lanci, and M. Tazzioli (eds.), Foucault and the History of our Present
(Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2015).
Fulda, Daniel, Wissenschaft aus Kunst: Die Entstehung der modernen deutschen
Geschichtsschreibung, 1760–1860 (Berlin: de Gruyter, 1996).
Fulbrook, Mary, Piety and Politics: Religion and the Rise of Absolutism in England,
Württemberg and Prussia (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1983).
Fuller, Steve, Thomas Kuhn: A Philosophical History for our Times (Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 2001).
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
Funder, Achim, Reichsidee und Kirchenrecht: Dietrich von Nieheim als Beispiel spätmitte-
lalterlicher Rechtsauffassung (Freiburg: Herder, 1993).
Funkenstein, Amos, Theology and the Scientific Imagination from the Middle Ages to the
Seventeenth Century (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1986).
Fustel de Coulanges, N. D., Histoire des institutions politiques de l’ancienne France, 6 vols.
(Paris: Hachette, 1874–1892).
Fustel de Coulanges, N. D., The Ancient City (Kitchener, ON: Batoche, 2001).
Gadamer, Hans-Georg, Truth and Method (London: Sheed and Ward, 1979).
Gaddis, John Lewis, The Landscape of History (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004).
Gandillac, Maurice de, and Edouard Jeauneau (eds.), Entretiens sur la renaissance du 12e
siècle (Paris: Mouton, 1968).
Garver, Valerie L., Women and Aristocratic Culture in the Carolingian World (New York:
Cornell, 2009).
Gay, Peter, The Enlightenment: An Interpretation (New York: Norton, 1966).
George, Karen, Gildas’s De Excidio Britonum and the Early British Church (Woodbridge:
Boydell, 2009).
Gerald of Wales, Giraldus Cambrensis The Topography of Ireland, trans. Thomas Forester,
rev. and ed. Thomas Wright (Cambridge, ON: In Parentheses, 2000).
Gersh, Stephen, and Bert Roest (eds.), Medieval and Renaissance Humanism: Rhetoric,
Representation and Reform (Leiden: Brill, 2003).
Gervinus, Georg Gottfried, Geschichte der poetischen National-Literatur der Deutschen,
5 vols. (Leipzig: Engelmann, 1835–42).
Ghosh, Peter, Max Weber and the Protestant Ethic (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014).
Ghosh, Shami, Writing the Barbarian Past: Studies in Early Medieval Historical Narrative
(Leiden: Brill, 2016).
Gibbon, Edward, The History of the Decline and Fall of the Roman Empire, ed.
David P. Womersley, vol. 3 (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1995).
Gildas, The Ruin of Britain, Fragments from Lost Letters, The Penitential, Together with the
Lorica of Gildas, ed. Hugh Williams (London: Bedford Press, 1899).
Gillespie, Michael Allan, The Theological Origins of Modernity, (Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 2008).
Ginzburg, Carlo, The Cheese and the Worms: The Cosmos of a Sixteenth-Century Miller
(London: Routledge, 1980).
Ginzburg, Carlo, The Judge and the Historian (London: Verso, 1999).
Ginzburg, Carlo, Threads and Traces: True False Fictive (Berkeley: University of California
Press, 2012).
Gipper, Helmut, and Peter Schmitter, Sprachwissenschaft und Sprachphilosophie im
Zeitalter der Romantik (Tübingen: Narr, 1979).
Given-Wilson, Chris, Chronicles: The Writing of History in Medieval England (London:
Hambledon, 2004).
Goethe, Johann Wolfgang von, Goethe Werke—Hamburger Ausgabe Band 12, ed. Erich
Trunz (Munich: Beck, 2008).
Goetz, Hans-Werner, Die Geschichtstheologie des Orosius (Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche
Buchgesellschaft, 1980).
Goetz, Hans-Werner, Geschichtsschreibung und Geschichtsbewußtsein im hohen Mittelalter
(Berlin: Orbis mediaevalis, 1999).
Goldschmidt, E. P., The Printed Book of the Renaissance (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1950).
Gooder, Paula, The Pentateuch: A Story of Beginnings (London: T&T Clark, 2000).
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
Habermas, Jürgen, The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press,
1990).
Haberski, Raymond Jr, and Andrew Hartman (eds.), American Labyrinth: Intellectual
History for Complicated Times (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 2018).
Habinek, Thomas, and Alessandro Schiesaro (eds.), The Roman Cultural Revolution
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997).
Hackel, Christiane, Aristoteles-Rezeption in der Geschichtstheorie Johann Gustav Droysens
(Berlin: de Gruyter, 2019).
Hacking, Ian, The Social Construction of What? (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press, 1999).
Hadden, Richard W., On the Shoulders of Merchants (Albany: State University of New York,
1994).
Haidu, Peter, The Subject of Violence: The Song of Roland and the Birth of the State
(Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1993).
Haikola, Lauri, Gesetz und Evangelium bei Matthias Flacius Illyricus: eine Untersuchung zur
Lutherischen Theologie vor der Konkordienformel (Lund: Gleerup, 1952).
Hall, John R. (ed.), Reworking Class (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1997).
Hammer, Espen, Philosophy and Temporality from Kant to Critical Theory (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2011).
Hankins, James (ed.), Renaissance Civic Humanism: Reappraisals and Reflections
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000).
Harding, Brian, Not even a God can Save Us Now: Reading Machiavelli after Heidegger
(Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University Press, 2017).
Hardtwig, Wolfgang, and Philipp Müller (eds.), Die Vergangenheit der Weltgeschichte:
Universalhistorisches Denken in Berlin 1800–1933 (Göttingen: Vandenhoeck &
Ruprecht, 2010).
Hariman, Robert (ed.), Prudence: Classical Virtue, Postmodern Practice (University Park,
PA: Pennsylvania State University Press, 2003).
Harris, Stephen, and Bryon L. Grigsby (eds.), Misconceptions about the Middle Ages
(New York: Routledge, 2008).
Harrison, Peter, The Bible, Protestantism, and the Rise of Natural Science (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1998).
Hartley, L. P., The Go-Between (New York: New York Review Books, 2002).
Harvey, David Allen, The French Enlightenment and its Others: The Mandarin, the Savage,
and the Invention of the Human Sciences (London: Palgrave Macmillan, 2012).
Haskins, Charles Homer, The Renaissance of the Twelfth Century (Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press, 1927).
Hay, Denys, Europe: The Emergence of an Idea (New York: Harper, 1966).
Haynes, Kenneth, Hamann: Writings on Philosophy and Language (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2007).
Hearn, Jonathan, Theorizing Power (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2012).
Hegel, G. W. F., The Philosophy of Right, trans T. M. Knox (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1952).
Hegel, G. W. F., Introduction to the Philosophy of History with an Appendix from The
Philosophy of Right, trans. Leo Rauch (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 1988).
Heinzelmann, Martin, Gregory of Tours: History and Society in the Sixth Century
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001).
Hendrick, Harry, Children, Childhood and English Society, 1880–1990 (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1997).
Henry of Huntingdon, The History of the English People 1000–1154, ed. and trans. Diana
Greenway (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002).
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
Jacoby, Felix, Atthis: The Local Chronicles of Ancient Athens (Oxford: Clarendon Press,
1949).
Jameson, Fredric, The Political Unconscious (London: Routledge, 1983).
Jenkin, Richard, Virgil’s Experience: Nature and History; Times, Names and Places (Oxford:
Clarendon Press, 1998).
Jenkins, Keith, Re-Thinking History (London: Routledge, 1991).
Jenks, Leland Hamilton, The Migration of British Capital to 1875 (New York: Knopf, 1927).
Johnson, Mark, The Body In the Mind: The Bodily Basis of Meaning, Imagination, and
Reason (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1987).
Johnson, Paul E., A Shopkeeper’s Millennium: Society and Revivals in Rochester, New York,
1815–1837 (New York: Hill and Wang, 1994 [orig. 1978]).
Johnston, William M., The Formative Years of R. G. Collingwood (The Hague: Martinus
Nijhoff, 1968).
Jones, Gareth Stedman, Languages of Class (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1984).
Jordan, Lothar, and Bernd Kortländer (eds.), Nationale Grenzen und internationaler
Austausch (Tübingen: Niemeyer, 1995).
Jotischky, Andrew, The Carmelites and Antiquity: Mendicants and their Pasts in the Middle
Ages (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002).
Kain, Philip J., Nietzsche and the Horror of Existence (Lanham, MD: Lexington, 2009).
Kaldellis, Anthony, Procopius of Caesarea (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press,
2004).
Kaldellis, Anthony, A New Herodotus: Laonikos Chalkokondyles on the Ottoman Empire,
the Fall of Byzantium, and the Emergence of the West (Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press, 2014).
Kant, Immanuel, Kant: Political Writings, ed. Hans Reiss (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1991).
Katchen, Aaron, Christian Hebraists and Dutch Rabbis (Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press, 1984).
Kelley, Donald R., Foundations of Modern Historical Scholarship: Language, Law, and
History in the French Renaissance (New York: Columbia University Press, 1970).
Kelley, Donald R., Faces of History: Historical Inquiry from Herodotus to Herder (New
Haven: Yale University Press, 1998).
Kelly, Gavin, Ammianus Marcellinus: The Allusive Historian (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2008).
Kenny, Anthony, The Rise of Modern Philosophy (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2006).
Kenyon, John, The History Men (Pittsburgh, PA: University of Pittsburgh Press, 1984).
Kewes, Paulina (ed.), The Uses of History in Early Modern England (San Marino, CA:
Huntington Library, 2006).
Khong, Yuen Foong, Analogies at War: Korea, Munich, Dien Bien Phu, and the Vietnam
Decisions of 1965 (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1992).
Kidd, Colin, British Identities Before Nationalism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1999).
Klaus, Johann Heinrich, Die Jesus-Deutung von Ernst Troeltsch im Kontext der liberalen
Theologie (Tübingen: Mohr, 1997).
Kleinberg, Ethan, Haunting History: For a Deconstructive Approach to the Past (Stanford:
Stanford University Press, 2017).
Kligerman, Eric, Sites of the Uncanny: Paul Celan, Specularity and the Visual Arts (Berlin:
de Gruyter, 2007).
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
Klosko, George (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of the History of Political Philosophy (Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 2011).
Knowles, David, The Historian and Character (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1963).
Kocis, Robert, Machiavelli Redeemed: Retrieving his Humanist Perspectives on Equality,
Power and Glory (New Jersey: Associated University Presses, 1998).
Kocka, Jürgen, Geschichte und Aufklärung (Göttingen: Vandenhoeck und Ruprecht, 1989).
Konstan, David, and Kurt A. Raaflaub (eds.), Epic and History (Chichester: Wiley-
Blackwell, 2010).
Koselleck, Reinhart, The Practice of Conceptual History: Timing History, Spacing Concepts
(Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2002).
Koselleck, Reinhart, Futures Past: On the Semantics of Historical Time (New York:
Columbia University Press, 2004).
Koslowski, Peter (ed.), The Discovery of Historicity in German Idealism and Historicism
(Berlin: Springer, 2005).
Kossler, Matthias, Empirische Ethik und christlicher Moral (Würzburg: Königshausen und
Neumann, 1999).
Kraye, Jill (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Renaissance Humanism (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1996).
Kügler, Joachim, and Werner H. Ritter (eds.), Auf Leben und Tod oder völlig egal: Kritisches
und Nachdenkliches zur Bedeutung der Bibel (Munster: LIT, 2005).
Kuhn, Thomas, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 1961).
Labrousse, Ernst, Esquisse du mouvement des prix et des revenues en France au XVIIIe siècle
(Paris: Dalloz, 1933).
LaCapra, Dominick, Representing the Holocaust: History, Theory, Trauma (Ithaca: Cornell
University Press, 1996).
LaCapra, Dominick, History in Transit: Experience, Identity, Critical Theory (Ithaca:
Cornell University Press, 2004).
Lacombe, Paul, L’Histoire considérée comme science (Paris: Hachette, 1894).
Ladurie, Emmanuel le Roy, Les Paysans de Languedoc, 2 vols. (Paris: Mouton, 1966).
Ladurie, Emmanuel le Roy, Montaillou, village occitan de 1294 à 1324 (Paris: Gallimard,
1975).
Lagrou, Pieter, The Legacy of Nazi Occupation: Patriotic Memory and National Recovery in
Western Europe, 1945–1965 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000).
Lake, Justin (ed.) Prologues to Ancient and Medieval History: A Reader (Toronto: University
of Toronto Press, 2013).
Lambert, Peter, and Phillipp Schofield (eds.), Making History (Abingdon: Routledge, 2004).
Lamers, Han, Greece Reinvented: Transformations of Byzantine Hellenism in Renaissance
Italy (Leiden: Brill, 2016).
Lamprecht, Karl, Deutsches Wirtschaftsleben im Mittelalter, 4 vols. (Leipzig: Dürr,
1885–6).
Lamprecht, Karl, Deutsche Geschichte, 12 vols. (Berlin: Gaertner, 1891–1909).
Landfester, Rüdiger, Historia magistra vitae: Untersuchungen zur humanistischen
Geschichtstheorie des 14. bis. 16. Jahrhunderts (Geneva: Droz, 1972).
Lange, Carsten Hjort, and Jesper Majbom Madsen (eds.), Cassius Dio: Greek Intellectual
and Roman Politician (Leiden: Brill, 2016).
Langlois, Charles-Victor, and Charles Seignobos, Introduction aux études historiques, ed.
Pierre Palpant (electronic edition, 2005).
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
Laqueur, Thomas W., Making Sex: Body and Gender from the Greeks to Freud (Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press, 1990).
Laslett, Peter, The World We Have Lost (London: Methuen, 1965).
Laughland, John, Schelling versus Hegel: From German Idealism to Christian Metaphysics
(Aldershot: Ashgate, 2007).
Lavisse, Ernest (ed.), Histoire de France contemporaine, depuis la revolution jusqu’à la paix
de 1919, 10 vols. (Paris: Hachette, 1920–2).
Le Goff, Jacques, Time, Work, and Culture in the Middle Ages (Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 1980).
Le Goff, Jacques, and Pierre Nora (eds.), Faire de l’histoire, 3 vols. (Paris, Gallimard, 1974).
Leavitt, John, Linguistic Relativities: Language Diversity and Modern Thought (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2011).
Lee, Kyong-Jin, The Authority and Authorization of Torah in the Persian Period (Leuven:
Peeters, 2011).
Lefebvre, Georges, Les Paysans du Nord pendant la Révolution française (Lille: Camille
Robbe, 1924).
Lefebvre, Georges, La Grande Peur de 1789 (Paris: Armand Colin, 1932).
Lefebvre, Georges, The Coming of the French Revolution, ed. and intr. Timothy Tacket
(Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2005).
Leff, Gordon, William of Ockham: The Metamorphosis of Scholastic Discourse (Manchester:
Manchester University Press, 1975).
Lehmann, Hartmut, and James Van Horn Melton (eds.), Paths of Continuity: Central
European Historiography from the 1930s to the 1950s (Washington, DC: German
Historical Institute, 2003).
Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm, Oeuvres de Leibniz, ed. M. A. Jacques (Paris: Charpentier,
1846).
Leiter, Brian, and Michael Rosen (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Continental Philosophy
(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007).
Lemon, M. C., Philosophy of History (London: Routledge, 2003).
Lerner, Gerda, The Creation of Patriarchy (New York: Oxford University Press, 1986).
Lessing, Theodor, Geschichte als Sinngebung des Sinnlosen (Munich: Beck, 1919).
LeVay, Simon, The Sexual Brain (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1993).
LeVay, Simon, Queer Science: The Use and Abuse of Research into Sexuality (Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press, 1996).
Levi, Giovanni, L’Eredità Immaterial: Carriera di un Exorcista nel Piemonte del Seicento
(Turin: Einaudi, 1985).
Lévi-Strauss, Claude, Structural Anthropology (New York: Basic Books, 1963).
Lévi-Strauss, Claude, The Savage Mind (London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson, 1966).
Lévi-Strauss, Claude, The Raw and the Cooked (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1986).
Levine, Norman, Marx’s Discourse with Hegel (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2012).
Lewis, John, Max Weber and Value-Free Sociology (London: Lawrence and Wishart, 1975).
Lianeri, Alexandra (ed.), The Western Time of Ancient History (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2011).
Liddel, Peter, and Andrew Fear (eds.), Historiae Mundi: Studies in Universal Historiography
(London: Duckworth, 2010).
Lillington-Martin, Christopher (ed.), Procopius of Caesarea: Literary and Historical
Interpretations (New York: Routledge, 2018).
Linehan, Peter, and Janet L. Nelson (eds), The Medieval World (Oxford: Routledge, 2001).
Lipton, Sara, Images of Intolerance: The Representation of Jews and Judaism in the Bible
moralisée (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1999).
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
Livy, The Early History of Rome, trans. Aubrey de Sélincourt (Harmondsworth: Penguin,
1960).
Loader, Colin, The Intellectual Development of Karl Mannheim (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1985).
Logan, Peter Melville, Victorian Fetishism: Intellectuals and Primitives (Albany: State
University of New York, 2009).
Long, V. Philips (ed.), Israel’s Past in Present Research (Winona Lake, IN: Eisenbrauns,
1999).
Loud, Robert B., Kant’s Impure Ethics: From Rational Beings to Human Beings (New York:
Oxford University Press, 2000).
Lowenthal, David, The Past is a Foreign Country (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1985).
Lowenthal, David, The Heritage Crusade and the Spoils of History (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1998).
Lowery, Zoe, Historiography (New York: Britannica Educational Publishing, 2016).
Luce, T. James, The Greek Historians (London: Routledge, 1997).
Lukács, Georg, History and Class Consciousness: Studies in Marxist Dialectics (Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press, 1971).
Lüdtke, Alf (ed.), Alltagsgeschichte: zur Rekonstruktion historischer Erfahrungen und
Lebensweisen (Frankfurt am Main: Campus, 1989).
Lukes, Steven, Emile Durkheim, His Life and Work: A Historical and Critical Study
(Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1985).
Luraghi, Nino (ed.), The Historian’s Craft in the Age of Herodotus (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2001).
Lynch, Joseph H., and Phillip C. Adamo, The Medieval Church (London: Routledge, 2014).
Lyotard, Jean-François, The Postmodern Condition (Manchester: Manchester University
Press, 1984).
McGilchrist, Iain, The Master and his Emissary: The Divided Brain and the Making of the
Western World (New Haven: Yale University Press, 2009).
McGing, Brian C., Polybius’ Histories (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010).
Machiavelli, Niccolò, The Discourses of Niccolò Machiavelli, vol.1, ed. Leslie Walker
(London: Routledge, 2013).
Macintyre, Stuart, Juan Maiguashca, and Attila Pók (eds.), The Oxford History of Historical
Writing 1800–1945 (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2015).
McKitterick, Rosamond, History and Memory in the Carolingian World (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2004).
McNeill, William H., The Rise of the West: A History of the Human Community (Chicago:
Chicago University Press, 1963).
McNeill, William H., A World History (New York: Oxford University Press, 1967).
Magnus, Bern, Heidegger’s Metahistory of Philosophy: Amor fati, Being and Truth (The
Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1970).
Mahon, Michael, Foucault’s Nietzschean Genealogy (Albany: SUNY Press, 1992).
Mahoney, James, and Dietrich Rueschemeyer, Comparative Historical Analysis in the Social
Sciences (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003).
Maimonides, Moses, The Guide for the Perplexed, trans, M. Friedländer (New York: Dover,
1956).
Mäkinen, Virpi (ed.), The Nature of Rights (Helsinki: Societas Philosophica Fennica, 2010).
Malcolm, Noel, Aspects of Hobbes (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2002).
Mali, Joseph, The Rehabilitation of Myth: Vico’s New Science (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1992).
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
Mill, John Stuart, J. S. Mill: ‘On Liberty’ and Other Writings, ed. Stefan Collini (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2003).
Miller, J. Hillis, The Ethics of Reading (New York: Columbia University Press, 1987).
Miner, Robert C., Vico: Genealogist of Modernity (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame
Press, 2002).
Minnis, A. J., Medieval Theory of Authorship: Scholastic Literary Attitudes in the Later
Middle Ages (London : Scolar, 1984).
Mintz, Steven, Huck’s Raft: A History of American Childhood (Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press, 2004).
Mistry, Zubin, Abortion in the Early Middle Ages, c.500–900 (York: York Medieval Press,
2015).
Molyneaux, George, The Formation of the English Kingdom in the Tenth Century (Oxford:
Oxford University 2015).
Momigliano, Arnaldo, Classical Foundations of Modern Historiography (Berkeley:
University of California Press, 1990).
Momigliano, Arnaldo, Essays in Ancient and Modern Historiography (Chicago: University
of Chicago Press, 2012).
Moore, R. I., The Formation of a Persecuting Society: Authority and Deviance in Western
Europe, 950–1250 (Oxford: Blackwell, 2007).
Mortley, Raoul, The Idea of Universal History from Hellenic Philosophy to Early Christian
Historiography (New York: Edwin Mellen, 1996).
Morton, Michael, Herder and the Poetics of Thought (University Park, PA: Pennsylvania
State University Press, 1989).
Mouffe, Chantal, The Return of the Political (London: Verso, 2005).
Moulakis, Athanasios (ed.), The Promise of History: Essays in Political Philosophy (Berlin:
de Gruyter, 1986).
Muhlack, Ulrich, Geschichtswissenschaft im Humanismus und in der Aufklärung: Der
Vorgeschichte des Historismus (Munich: Beck, 1991).
Muntz, Charles Edward, Diodorus Siculus and the World of the Late Roman Republic
(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2017).
Murray, Alexander, Conscience and Authority in the Medieval Church (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2015).
Murray, Christopher John (ed.) Encyclopedia of the Romantic Era, 1760–1850 (London:
Fitzroy Dearborn, 2004).
Murray, R. H., The Individual and the State (London: Hutchinson, 1946).
Myers, David N., Resisting History: Historicism and its Discontents in German-Jewish
Thought (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2003).
Nadler, Steven, Spinoza: A Life (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001).
Nagy, Gregory, Poetry as Performance: Homer and Beyond (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1996).
Namier, Lewis, The Structure of Politics at the Accession of George III (London: Macmillan,
1973).
Nelson, Janet L., The Frankish World, 750–900 (London: Hambledon Press, 1996).
Nelson, Janet (ed.), Annals of St-Bertin (Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1991).
Nielsen, Fleming A. J., The Tragedy in History: Herodotus and the Deuteronomistic History
(Sheffield: Sheffield Academic Press, 1997).
Neuhouser, Frederick, Rousseau’s Critique of Inequality (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 2014).
Niebuhr, B. G., Lebensnachrichten über Barthold Georg Niebuhr, vol. 2 (Hamburg: Perthes,
1838).
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
Phillips, Mark, Francesco Guicciardini: The Historian’s Craft (Toronto: University of Toronto
Press, 1977).
Phillips, Ulrich Bonnell, American Negro Slavery (New York: Appleton, 1918).
Pico della Mirandola, Giovanni, Pico della Mirandola: Oration on the Dignity of Man: A
New Translation and Commentary, ed. Francesco Borghesi, Michael Papio and Massimo
Riva (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2012).
Piercey, Robert, The Uses of the Past from Heidegger to Rorty (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2011).
Pinkard, Terry, German Philosophy 1760–1860: The Legacy of Idealism (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2002).
Pinkard, Terry, Does History Make Sense? Hegel on the Historical Shapes of Justice
(Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2017).
Pippin, Robert B., Modernism as a Philosophical Problem: On the Dissatisfactions of
European High Culture (Malden, MA: Blackwell, 1999).
Pocock, J. G. A., The Ancient Constitution and the Feudal Law (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1987).
Pohl, Walter, Clemens Gantner, Cinzia Grifoni, and Marianne Pollheimer-Mohaupt (eds.),
Transformations of Romanness: Early Medieval Regions and Identities (Berlin: de Gruyter,
2018).
Pollmann, Judith, Memory in Early Modern Europe, 1500–1800 (Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 2017).
Polybius, The Rise of the Roman Empire, trans. Ian Scott-Kilvert (London: Penguin, 1979).
Poor, Sara S., Mechthild of Magdeburg and her Book: Gender and the Making of Textual
Authority (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 2004).
Popkin, Jeremy D., From Herodotus to H-Net: The Story of Historiography (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2015).
Popkin, Richard H., Isaac La Peyrère (Leiden: Brill, 1987).
Popkin, Richard H. (ed.), The Pimlico History of Western Philosophy (London: Pimlico,
1999).
Postone, Moishe, Louis Galambos, and Jane Eliot Sewell, Time, Labor, and Social
Domination: A Reinterpretation of Marx’s Critical Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2003).
Power, Eileen, Medieval People (London: Methuen, 1924).
Pownall, Frances, Lessons from the Past: The Moral Uses of History in Fourth Century Prose
(Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 2007).
Preus, J. Samuel, Explaining Religion: Criticism and Theory from Bodin to Freud (Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 1996).
Preus, J. Samuel, Spinoza and the Irrelevance of Biblical Authority (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2001).
Procopius, History of the Wars, trans. H. B. Dewing (London: Heinemann, 1914).
Quarles, Benjamin Arthur, Frederick Douglass (Washington, DC: Associated Publishers,
1948).
Quarles, Benjamin Arthur, The Negro in the Civil War (Boston: Little, Brown and Co.,
1953).
Rabasa, José, Masayuki Sato, Edoardo Tortarolo, and Daniel Woolf (eds.), The Oxford
History of Historical Writing 1400–1800 (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2015).
Raico, Ralph, Classical Liberalism and the Austrian School (Auburn, AL: Ludwig von Mises
Institute, 2012).
Rancière, Jacques, Les Mots de l’histoire. Essai de poétique du savoir (Paris, Seuil, 1992).
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
Randall, John Hermann, Nature and Historical Experience (New York: Columbia University
Press, 1958).
Ranke, Leopold von, Geschichten der romanischen und germanischen Völker von 1494 bis
1535 (Leipzig: Reimer, 1824).
Ranke, Leopold von, Die Serbische Revolution. Aus Serbischen Papieren und Mittheilungen
(Hamburg: Perthes, 1829).
Ranke, Leopold von, History of the Latin and Teutonic Nations from 1494–1514, trans.
P. A. Ashworth (London: George Bell and Sons, 1887).
Ranke, Leopold von, Weltgeschichte, ed. Alfred Dove and Georg Winter, vol. IX (Leipzig:
Duncker and Humblot, 1888).
Ranke, Leopold von, Über die Epochen der neueren Geschichte. Historisch-kritische Ausgabe,
ed. Theodor Schieder and Helmut Berding (Munich: Oldenbourg, 1971).
Ranke, Leopold von, The Secret of World History: Selected Writings on the Art and Science of
History, ed. Roger Wines (New York: Fordham University Press, 1981).
Ranke, Leopold von, The Theory and Practice of History, ed. Georg G. Iggers (London:
Routledge, 2011).
Rapport, Nigel (ed.), Democracy, Science and the ‘Open Society’: A European Legacy?
(Münster: LIT, 2005).
Redding, Paul, Continental Idealism: Leibniz to Nietzsche (London: Routledge, 2009).
Reeves, Marjorie, The Influence of Prophecy in the Later Middle Ages: A Study of Joachimism
(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000).
Reimer, A. James, Paul Tillich: Theologian of Nature, Culture and Politics (Münster: LIT,
2004).
Reimitz, Helmut, History, Frankish Identity and the Framing of Western Ethnicity
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2015).
Reiner, G. J., History: Its Purpose and Method (London: Allen and Unwin, 1950).
Rennie, Nicholas, Speculating on the Moment: The Poetics of Time and Recurrence in
Goethe, Leopardi, and Nietzsche (Göttingen: Wallstein, 2005).
Rescher, Nicholas, G. W. Leibniz’s Monadology: An Edition for Students (Pittsburgh:
University of Pittsburgh Press, 1991).
Reuter, Timothy (ed.), The Annals of Fulda (Manchester: Manchester University Press,
1992).
Richter, Daniel S., and William A. Johnson (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of the Second
Sophistic (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2017).
Rickman, H. P., Meaning in History: W. Dilthey’s Thoughts on History and Society (London:
Allen and Unwin, 1961).
Riedenauer, Markus, Pluralität und Rationalität: Die Herausforderung der Vernunft durch
religiöse und kulturelle Vielfalt nach Nikolaus Cusanus (Stuttgart: Kohlhammer, 2007).
Rigby, S. H., Engels and the Formation of Marxism (Manchester: Manchester University
Press, 1992).
Rigby, S. H., Marxism and History (Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1998).
Rigby, S. H., Wisdom and Chivalry: Chaucer’s Knight’s Tale and Medieval Political Theory
(Leiden: Brill, 2009).
Riley, Denise, Am I that Name? Feminism and the Category of ‘Women’ in History
(Basingstoke: Macmillan, 1988).
Roberts, David D., Nothing But History: Reconstruction and Extremity After Metaphysics
(Berkeley: University of California Press, 1995).
Robinson, James Harvey, The New History: Essays Illustrating the Modern Historical
Outlook (New York: Macmillan, 1912).
Rohrbacher, David, The Historians of Late Antiquity (London: Routledge, 2002).
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
Rorty, Amélie Oksenberg, and James Schmidt (eds.), Kant’s ‘Idea for a Universal History
With a Cosmopolitan Aim’: A Critical Guide (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
2011).
Rorty, Richard, Contingency, Irony, Solidarity, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1999).
Rorty, Richard, J. B. Schneewind, and Quentin Skinner (eds.), Philosophy in History: Essays
on the Historiography of Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998).
Rose, Sonya O., What is Gender History? (Cambridge: Polity, 2010).
Rowbotham, Sheila, Hidden from History (London: Pluto Press, 1973).
Rowse, A. J., The Use of History (Harmondsworth: Pelican, 1971).
Rubinoff, Lionel, Collingwood and the Reform of Metaphysics: A Study in the Philosophy of
Mind (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1970).
Rublack, Ulinka (ed.), A Concise Companion to History (Oxford: Oxford University Press,
2011).
Rudé, George, The Crowd in the French Revolution (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1959).
Rudwick, Martin J. S., Worlds before Adam: The Reconstruction of Geohistory in the Age of
Reform (Chicago: Chicago University Press, 2008).
Rüger, Jan, The Great Naval Game: Britain and Germany in the Age of Empire (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2007).
Russell, Bertrand, History of Western Philosophy (London: George Allen and Unwin, 1947).
Sahlins, Marshall, The Western Illusion of Human Nature (Chicago: Prickly Paradigm
Press: 2008).
Said, Edward, Orientalism: Western Conceptions of the Orient (London: Routledge and
Kegan Paul, 1978).
Saini, Angela, Inferior (London: Harper Collins, 2018).
Saini, Angela, Superior (Boston, MA: Beacon Press, 2019).
Samuel, Raphael, Theatres of Memory (London: Verso, 1994).
Sanders, Rik, Bas Mesters, Reinier Kramer, and Margreet Windhorst (eds.), Balans en
Perspectief van de Nederlandse Cultuurgeschiedenis (Amsterdam: Rodopi, 1991).
Sandy, Gerald N. (ed.), The Classical Heritage in France (Leiden: Brill, 2002).
Scheible, Heinz, Die Entstehung der Magdeburger Zenturien. Ein Beitrag zur Geschichte der
historiographischen Methode (Gütersloh: Gerd Mohn, 1966).
Schiffman, Zachary Sayre, On the Threshold of Modernity: Relativism in the French
Renaissance (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1991).
Schiffman, Zachary Sayre, The Birth of the Past (Baltimore: John Hopkins University Press,
2011).
Schlosser, Friedrich Christoph, Weltgeschichte in zusammenhängender Erzählung, 4 vols.
(Frankfurt am Main: Varrentrapp 1815–41).
Schlosser, Friedrich Christoph, Weltgeschichte für das deutsche Volk, 19 vols. (Frankfurt am
Main: Varrentrapp 1844–57).
Schuppe, Christian-Georg, Der andere Droysen: neue Aspekte seiner Theorie der
Geschichtswissenschaft (Stuttgart: Steiner, 1998).
Schwab, Gail M., and John R. Jeanneny (eds.), The French Revolution of 1789 and its Impact
(Westport, CT: Greenwood Press, 1995).
Scott, Joan Wallach, Gender and the Politics of History, 30th Anniversary Edition (New
York: Columbia University Press, 2018).
Scott, Walter, Waverley, or ’Tis Sixty Years Since (Edinburgh: Adam and Charles Black,
1854).
Seidel, Bradley Nelson, ‘Giambattista Vico and the Emergence of Historical Consciousness’
(Marquette University: PhD thesis, 1996).
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
Seignobos, Charles, La Méthode historique appliquée aux science sociales (Paris: Alcan,
1901).
Sewell, William G., Logics of History: Social History and Social Transformation (Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 2005).
Shuster, Martin, Autonomy after Auschwitz: Adorno, German Idealism, and Modernity
(Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2014).
Sidelsky, Edward, Ernst Cassirer (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2008).
Sigurdson, Richard Franklin, Jacob Burckhardt’s Social and Political Thought (Toronto:
University of Toronto Press, 2004).
Simiand, François, Les Fluctuations économiques à longue période et la crise mondiale
(Paris: Alcan 1932).
Simiand, François, Recherches anciennes et nouvelles sur le mouvement général des prix du
VXIe au XIXe siècle (Paris: Domat-Montchrestien, 1932).
Ska, Jean Louis, Introduction to Reading the Pentateuch (Winona Lake, Indiana:
Eisenbrauns, 2006).
Skinner, Quentin, The Foundations of Modern Political Thought, 2 vols. (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1978).
Skinner, Quentin, Liberty before Liberalism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1998).
Skocpol, Theda, States and Social Revolutions: A Comparative Analysis of France, Russia,
and China (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1979).
Skocpol, Theda, Social Revolutions in the Modern World (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1994).
Skocpol, Theda (ed.), Vision and Method in Historical Sociology (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1994).
Smail, Daniel Lord, On Deep History and the Brain (Berkeley: University of California
Press, 2008).
Smith, Craig, Adam Smith’s Political Philosophy: The Invisible Hand and Spontaneous Order
(Abingdon: Routledge, 2006).
Snyder, Jeffrey Aaron, Making Black History: The Color Line, Culture, and Race in the Age of
Jim Crow (Athens: University of Georgia Press, 2018).
Somos, Mark, Secularisation and the Leiden Circle (Leiden: Brill, 2011).
Southern, R. W., History and Historians: Selected Papers of R. W. Southern, ed. R. J. Bartlett
(Oxford: Blackwell, 2004).
Sparling, Robert Alan, Johann Georg Hamann and the Enlightenment Project (Toronto:
University of Toronto Press, 2011).
Spengler, Oswald, Der Untergang des Abendlandes (Munich: Beck, 1998).
Spiegel, Gabrielle M., The Past as Text: The Theory and Practice of Medieval Historiography
(Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1997).
Staël, Germaine de, De la littérature considérée dans ses rapports avec les institutions
sociales, vol. 1, 2nd edition (Paris: de Crapelet, n.d.).
Stalin, J. V., Problems of Leninism (Peking: Foreign Languages Press, 1976).
Stein, Peter, Roman Law in European History (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
2012).
Steinmetz, George (ed.), State/Culture: State Formation after the Cultural Turn (Ithaca:
Cornell University Press, 1999).
Stern, Fritz (ed.), The Varieties of History (New York: Meridian, 1956).
Stieg, Margaret F., The Historische Zeitschrift: The Origin and Development of Scholarly
Historical Periodicals (Tuscaloosa: University of Alabama Press, 1986).
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
Stoianovich, Traian, French Historical Method: The Annales Paradigm (Ithaca: Cornell
University Press, 1976).
Stone, Dan (ed.), The Holocaust and Historical Methodology (New York: Berghahn, 2012).
Stronk, Jan P., Ctesias’ Persian History: Introduction, Text, and Translation (Düsseldorf:
Wellem, 2010).
Stubbs, William, The Constitutional History of England in its Origins and Development, vol. 1
(Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1874).
Sturley, D. M., The Study of History (London: Longmans, 1969).
Sturm, Thomas, Kant und die Wissenschaften vom Menschen (Paderborn: Mentis, 2009).
Sulpicius Severus, Sulpicius Severus’ Vita Martini, ed. Philip Burton (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2017).
Swain, Harriet (ed.), Big Questions in History (London: Jonathan Cape, 2005).
Swanson, R. N., The Twelfth-Century Renaissance (Manchester: Manchester University
Press, 1999).
Swanton, Michael (ed.), The Anglo-Saxon Chronicles, (London: Phoenix, 2000).
Sybel, Heinrich von, Die deutsche Nation und das Kaiserreich (Düsseldorf: Buddeus, 1862).
Sybel, Heinrich von, Die Begründung des deutschen Reiches durch Wilhelm I, 7 vols.
(Munich: Oldenbourg, 1889–1894).
Tacitus, Tacitus: The Annals and the Histories, ed. Hugh Lloyd-Jones (New York:
Washington Sqaure Press, 1964).
Taine, Hippolyte, Histoire de la littérature anglaise, 5 vols. (Paris: Hachette, 1863–4).
Taine, Hippolyte, The Philosophy of Art (New York: Holt and Williams, 1873).
Teggart, Frederick J., Theory and Processes of History (Berkeley: University of California
Press, 1962).
Teherani-Krönner, Parto (ed.), Humanökologie und Kulturökologie (Opladen:
Westdeutscher Verlag, 1992).
Tentler, Thomas N., Sin and Confession on the Eve of the Reformation (Princeton: Princeton
University Press, 1977).
Thierry, Augustin, Récits des temps mérovingiens précédés de Considérations sur l’histoire de
France, 2 vols. (Paris: Tessier, 1840).
Thompson, E. P., The Making of the English Working Class (Harmondsworth: Pelican,
1968).
Thompson, E. P., Persons and Polemics: Historical Essays (London: Merlin, 1994).
Thucydides, The Peloponnesian War: The Crawley Translation (New York: Random House,
1982).
Tileagă, Cristian, and Jovan Byford (eds.), Psychology and History: Interdisciplinary
Explorations (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2014).
Tilley, Arthur Augustus, The Dawn of the French Renaissance (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1968).
Tillich, Paul, The Protestant Era (London: Nisbet, 1955).
Tillich, Paul, A History of Christian Thought, ed. Carl E. Braaten (New York: Touchstone,
1968).
Toews, John Edward, Hegelianism: The Path toward Dialectical Humanism, 1805–1841
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985).
Tosh, John, The Pursuit of History (Harlow: Longman, 1993).
Tosh, John, Why History Matters (Basingstoke: Palgrave, 2008).
Toulmin, Stephen, The Place of Reason in Ethics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1950).
Toynbee, Arnold J., Greek Historical Thought (New York: Mentor Books, 1952).
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
Toynbee, Arnold J., A Study of History, abridgement of vols. I–VI ed. Robert Somervell
(Oxford: Oxford University Press 1946).
Toynbee, Arnold J., A Study of History, abridgement of vols. VII–X ed. Robert Somervell
(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1985).
Treadgold, Warren, The Early Byzantine Historians (Basingstoke: Macmillan, 2010).
Troeltsch, Ernst, Der Historismus und seine Probleme: Erstes Buch, ed. Friedrich Wilhelm
Graf and Matthias Schlossberger (Berlin: de Gruyter, 2008).
Tucker, Aviezer (ed.), A Companion to the Philosophy of History and Historiography
(London: Wiley, 2009).
Tull, Patricia K., and Claire Mathews McGinnis (eds.), ‘As Those Who Are Taught’: The
Interpretation of Isaiah from the LXX to the SBL (Atlanta, GA: SBL, 2006).
Tutino, Stefania, Shadows of Doubt: Language and Truth in Post-Reformation Catholic
Culture (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014).
Ullmann, Walter, The Medieval Idea of Law as Represented by Lucas de Penna (Routledge,
2010).
Valla, Lorenzo, On The Donation of Constantine, ed. G. W. Bowersock (Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press, 2007).
Vallery-Radot, René, The Life of Pasteur (London: Constable, 1928).
van Houts, Elisabeth, Memory and Gender in Medieval Europe, 900–1200 (London:
Palgrave, 1999).
van Houts, Elisabeth (ed.), Medieval Memories: Men, Women and the Past, 700–1300
(New York: Longman, 2001).
van Liere, Frans, An Introduction to the Medieval Bible (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 2014).
van Oort, Henk, The Inner Rainbow: An Illustrated History of Human Consciousness
(Sussex: Temple Lodge, 2014).
van Peursen, C. A., Leibniz (London: Faber and Faber, 1969).
Veeser, H. Aram (ed.) The New Historicism (New York: Routledge, 1989).
Velema, Wyger R. E., Republicans: Essays on Eighteenth Century Dutch Political Thought
(Leiden: Brill, 2007).
Vico, Giambattisa, The New Science of Giambattista Vico: Unabridged Translation of the
Third Edition (1744), trans. Thomas Goddard Bergin and Max Harold Fisch (Ithaca:
Cornell University Press, 1984).
Vico, Giambattisa, On Humanistic Education (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 2003).
Villemaire, D., E. A. Burtt: Historian and Philosopher (Dordrecht: Springer, 1992).
Voegelin, Eric, Published Essays, 1953–1965 (Columbia: University of Missouri Press,
2000).
Völkel, Markus, Geschichtsschreibung: eine Einführung in globaler Perspektive (Cologne:
Böhlau, 2006).
von Essen, Gesa, and Horst Turk (eds.), Unerledigte Geschichten: Der literarische Umgang
mit Nationalität und Internationalität (Göttingen: Wallstein, 2000).
Walbank, Frank W., Polybius, Rome and the Hellenistic World (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2015).
Wanner, Raymond E., Claude Fleury (1640–1723) as an Educational Historiographer and
Thinker (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1975).
Ward, Timothy, Word and Supplement (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002).
Warner, Rex, The Greek Philosophers (New York: New American Library, 1958).
Weber, Max, Gesammelte Aufsätze zur Religionssoziologie, vol 1 (Tübingen: Mohr, 1920).
Weber, Max, Max Weber: Essays in Sociology, ed. H. H. Gerth and C. Wright Mills (New
York: Oxford University Press, 1946).
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
Weber, Max, Max Weber: Gesammelte Aufsätze zur Wissenschaftslehre. Hrsg. von Johannes
Winckelmann. 6., erneut durchgesehene Auflage (Tübingen: Mohr/Siebeck, 1985).
Wedgwood, C. V., Truth and Opinion: Historical Essays (London: Collins, 1960).
Wehler, Hans-Ulrich, Das Deutsche Kaiserreich, 1871–1918 (Göttingen: Vandenhoeck und
Ruprecht, 1973).
Welter, Jean Thiébaut, L’Exemplum dans la littérature religieuse et didactique du moyen âge
(Paris: Occitania E. H. Guitard, 1927).
Westman, Robert S. and David Biale (eds.), Thinking Impossibilities: The Intellectual
Legacies of Amos Funkenstein (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 2008).
Whatmore, Richard, and Brian Young (eds.), A Companion to Intellectual History (London:
Wiley, 2016).
White, Hayden, Metahistory: The Historical Imagination in the Nineteenth Century
(Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1973).
White, Hayden, Tropics of Discourse (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1978).
White, Hayden, The Content of the Form (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press,
1987).
Whitmarsh, Tim, Beyond the Second Sophistic: Adventures in Greek Postclassicism
(Berkeley: University of California Press, 2013).
Williams, Bernard, Truth and Truthfulness: An Essay in Genealogy (Princeton: Princeton
University Press, 2002).
Williams, Bernard, Shame and Necessity (Berkeley: University of California Press, 2008).
Williams, Raymond, Culture and Society, 1780–1950 (London: Chatto and Windus, 1958).
Williams, Raymond, Problems in Materialism and Culture (London: Verso, 1980).
Wolf, Eric, Europe and the ‘People Without History’ (Berkeley: University of California
Press, 1982).
Wolfskeel, C. W., De Immortalitate Animae of Augustine: Text, Translation and Commentary
(Amsterdam: Grüner, 1977).
Wood, Ellen Meiksins, The Origin of Capitalism: A Longer View (London: Verso, 2002).
Wood, Ian, The Modern Origins of the Early Middle Ages (Oxford: Oxford University Press,
2013).
Woodman, A. J., Lost Histories: Selected Fragments of Roman Historians (Newcastle: Histos,
2015).
Woodson, Carter G., The Education of the Negro Prior to 1861 (New York: G. P. Putnam’s
Sons, 1915).
Woodson, Carter G., A Century of Negro Migration (Washington, DC: Association of
Negro Life and History, 1918).
Woodson, Carter G., The Negro in Our History (Washington, DC: Associated Publishers,
1922).
Wormald, Patrick, Legal Culture in the Early Medieval West (London: Hambledon, 1999).
Yates, Frances A., Ideas and Ideals in the North European Renaissance (London: Routledge,
1999).
Zacher, Samantha, Rewriting the Old Testament in Anglo-Saxon Verse: Becoming the Chosen
People (London: Bloomsbury, 2013).
Zammito, John H., Kant, Herder and the Birth of Anthropology (Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 2002).
Zimmermann, Albert, and Gudrun Vuillemin-Diemand (eds.), Antiqui und Moderni:
Traditionsbewußtsein und Fortschrittsbewußtsein im späten Mittelalter (Berlin: De
Gruyter, 1974).
Zimmermann, Michel (ed.), Auctor et auctoritas. Invention et conformisme dans l’écriture
médiévale (Paris: École des Chartes, 2001).
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
Index
For the benefit of digital users, indexed terms that span two pages (e.g., 52–53) may, on occasion,
appear on only one of those pages.
Abelard, Peter 86, 88–9 Atthidographers 19–20, 29, 32–3, 68–71, 80
Abram, Annie 270, 274 Atticism 43
Acton (Lord) 219–21, 233, 237, 312–13, 325, 331 Auerbach, Erich 49
Adams, John 147–9 Augustine of Hippo 47, 50, 52–3, 55–7, 81–2,
Adorno, Theodor 149–50, 159, 313–14, 88–92, 110, 122–3, 146–7, 151, 160–1,
318–19, 331 181–2, 211–12
African American history 270, 274–5 Augustus (Emperor) 40–2, 60–1, 76
Africanus, Julius 48–51, 53, 55–6, 68–9 Austin, J. L. 300–1
ahistoricism 347–8
Alain de Lille 82 Bachelard, Gaston 259–60
Alciato, Andrea 128 Bacon, Francis 84, 125, 145–6, 170, 348–9
Altdorfer, Albrecht 80–1 Bambach, Charles 206–7
Althusser, Louis 162, 176, 293, 296–7 Barclay, Katie 319
Altman, Meryl 342–3 Baron, Hans 113–14
Ambrose 47 Baronio, Cesare 140–2
Ammianus Marcellinus 27–8, 43–6, 134–5 Barraclough, Geoffrey 262–3
anacyclosis 36, 123–4 Barrett, James R. 300
Anderson, Benedict 99 Barthes, Roland 291–2
Anderson, Carol 320–1 Bartlett, Kenneth 284–5
Andrew of St Victor 86, 88 Bartolus de Sassoferrato 127
Anna Komnēnē 73–4 Baudouin, François 124, 128–9, 136, 138–9
Annales 256–7, 262, 267–8, 291–2 Bayle, Pierre 144–5, 161–2
Annalistes 244–5, 254–9, 261–2, 264–5, Beard, Charles 238–9
271–2, 291–2 Beard, Mary 238–9
Anselm of Havelburg 84, 86 Beck, Hans 38
antiqui 79, 93–4, 351–3 Becker, Carl 238–9, 316–17
see also via antiqua Bede 60–1, 67–72, 100–1, 109–10, 271
apocalyptic philosophy of history 5–7, 53–7, ben Meir, Samuel 86
150, 164–5, 184–5 Bendix, Reinhard 268–9
Appian of Alexandria 43 Bennett, Alan 308–9
Aptheker, Herbert 274–5 Bennett, Judith 330
Aquinas, Thomas 5–7, 86, 91–3, 320 Benoît de Sainte-Maure 100–1
Arendt, Hannah 84 Benson, R. L. 90–1
Ariès, Philippe 282–3 Bentley, Michael 249, 310–11
Aristotle 36–8, 75, 91–2, 99–100, 185, 208–9, Berger, Stefan 194–5
211–13, 305 Berlin University 196–7, 204
on poetry 36–8 Berlin, Isaiah 262–3, 351–3
Aristotelianism 45–6, 75–6, 78, 81, 84, 92–3, Bevir, Mark 310–11
99–100, 109, 119–21, 145–6, 178–80, Biernacki, Richard 290
211–12, 221–2, 259–60, 346–7 Biondo, Flavio 4–5, 116–17, 120–1
Arnold, John 289, 321–2, 333–4 Blackbourn, David 266
Aron, Raymond 323–4 Bloch, Marc 254–6, 260–2, 268–9, 291–2
Arrian of Nicomedia 25–6, 43, 83 Block, Sharon 347–8
Arrighi, Giovanni 227–8 Boas, Franz 177, 252
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
390 Index
Index 391
392 Index
Index 393
Khaldūn, Ibn 2–4 Lukács, György 188–9, 248, 272, 286–7, 335–6
Kiernan, Victor 272–3 Lupus of Ferrières 71–2
Kleinberg, Ethan 295 Luther, Martin 138–9, 173–4
Kligerman, Eric 328–9 Luxemburg, Rosa 299
Knowles, David 262–3 Lyotard, Jean-François 292–3, 351–3
Kocka, Jürgen 245
Kogălniceanu, Mihail 193–4 Mabillon, Jean 143, 150–1
Köhler, Johann David 171–2 Macaulay, Catharine 155–6
Königshofen, Jakob Twinger von 60–1 Macaulay, Thomas Babington 198, 200–1,
Koselleck, Reinhart 2–7, 80–1 248–9, 271
Kuhn, Thomas S. 259–60 Machiavelli, Niccolò 117–21, 124, 147–51
Maimonides, Moses 86, 91–2, 103, 122–3, 144–5
La Boderie, Guy Lefèvre de 131–2 Maitland, Frederic William 228–9, 250–1
La Peyrère, Isaac 144–5 Mandrou, Robert 291–2
La Popelinière, Lancelot Voisin 130–4, 140–1, Mann, Michael 154
149–50 Mannheim, Karl 238
Labrousse, Ernst 257–8 Map, Walter 82–3, 92–3
LaCapra, Dominick 328–31 Marcuse, Herbert 334–5, 346–7
Lacombe, Paul 254, 257–8 Marrou, Henri 316–17, 331
Ladurie, Emmanuel le Roy 261–3, 268–9 Marx, Karl 154, 156–7, 161, 178, 184–90 passim,
Lamprecht, Karl 192–3, 216–17, 227–30, 225–6, 253–4, 265–6, 270, 272–3, 286–7,
233–4, 255–6 301, 306–7
Langlois, Charles-Victor 233–4 Marxism 184–90 passim, 252–3, 277–8, 281–2,
Laqueur, Thomas 342–3 286–7, 299–300, 333–4
Laslett, Peter 269 and capitalism 185, 188–90, 336
Lavisse, Ernest 262–3 and denaturalization 149–50, 188–90, 286–7
Le Bon, Gustav 255–6 and materialism 232, 238–9
Le Bras, Gabriel 90–1 anthropogenetic Marxism 185–6, 189
Le Goff, Jacques 95–7, 291–2 nomological Marxism 183–7, 189, 272–3,
Lebensphilosophie 222–3, 292 306–7
Lefebvre, Georges 255–6, 270 pragmatological Marxism 185–7, 189, 272–3,
Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm 151–3, 158, 161–2, 306–7
174–5, 177, 183–4, 186–7, 208–9, vulgar Marxism 187–8
251–2, 279 Marxist history 12, 227–8, 248, 253–4, 259–60,
Leninism 186–7, 299 267, 271–4, 278, 281–2, 299–300,
Lerner, Gerda 275–6, 286–7 330–1, 334
Lessing, Theodor 240, 279 and American social history 253–4, 267,
LeVay, Simon 345–6 271, 300
Levi, Giovanni 261–2 and British social history 265–6, 271–3
Levinas, Emmanuel 351–3 history from below 273–4, 281–2, 300
Lévi-Strauss, Claude 252–3, 255–7, 291–2 neo-Marxism 299
Levitin, Dimitri 142–3 post-Marxist philosophy 247
Libaridian, Gerard 354 Mascardi, Agostino 26–7
Lipset, Seymour Martin 268–9 Maschke, Eric 244–5
Lipsius, Justus 125, 147–9 McNeill, William H. 299
Lipson, Ephraim 256–7 Medick, Hans 261–2
Livy 38–42, 54, 66, 119–20 Medievalism 7, 96–7, 196–7, 227–8
Locke, John 146–9, 158–9 Megill, Allan 310–11
Lombard, Peter 88–9 Meiksins Wood, Ellen 187–8
longue durée 257–9, 261–2, 267 Meinecke, Friedrich 208–9, 242–3
Lovejoy, Arthur O. 322–3 Meiners, Christoph 173
Lowenthal, David 14 Melanchthon, Philip 78–9
Lucretius 23, 38–9 Menger, Carl 229–30
Lüdtke, Alf 274 Michelet, Jules 77, 199–201, 233–4, 270
OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 08/04/20, SPi
394 Index
Index 395
396 Index
theoria 32–3, 37–8, 46–7, 145–6, 208–9, 232 Völkel, Markus 105–6
Thierry, Augustin 199–200, 233–5, 270 Volksgeist 156, 176, 192, 216–17, 227, 241–2, 326
Thomas, Brook 355 Voltaire 11–12, 86–7, 149–50, 163–4, 178, 245
Thomas, Keith 284–5
Thompson, Dorothy 272–3 Wace 100–1
Thompson, E. P. 249–50, 272–3, 295–6, 300, 353 Wallerstein, Immanuel 268–9
Thrupp, Sylvia 268–9 Walter of Châtillon 83
Thucydides 10, 14, 17, 21–32, 39–40, 59, 73, 80, Walter, Uwe 38
147–9, 203, 216 Watson, Christopher 125
Tiberius 41–2 Webb, Beatrice 253–4
Tillich, Paul 55–6 Webb, Sidney 253–4
Tilly, Charles 268–9 Weber, Max 117–18, 229–34, 240, 259–60,
Tilly, Louise 267–9 268–9, 279
Timaeus of Tauromenium 34–5 Weberian influence 242–3, 259–60, 262,
Tönnies, Ferdinand 227–8 264–6
topical thinking 75–6, 108, 119–21, 317–18, Wedgwood, C. V. 262–3
321–2 Wehler, Hans-Ulrich 244–6, 274
Tosh, John 308, 316–17, 323–4 Weinberg, Joanna 142–3
Toulmin, Stephen 263–4 White, Hayden 10–11, 68–9, 279–80, 293–4,
Toynbee, Arnold J. 1–2, 227–8, 240–1, 262–4 305–7, 336–7
translatio imperii 53–4, 103, 113–14, 129, 137–8, William of Malmesbury 4–5, 69–70, 137, 198–9
199–200 William of Nassau 125
transnational history 297–8 William of Ockham 93–4, 190
Treitschke, Heinrich von 218–20, 230–1, 258–9 William of Tyre 60–1, 323–4
Trevelyan, G. M. 323–4 Williams, Bernard 58–60, 149
Trevor-Roper, Hugh 323–4 Williams, Raymond 272–3
Troeltsch, Ernst 226, 232, 240–1 Winckelmann, J. J. 161–3
Wittgenstein, Ludwig 300–1
Valla, Lorenzo 4–5, 115–18, 128, 138–9 Wolf, Eric 299
van Liere, Frans 88–9 Wolff, Christian 172
Varro 38–9 women’s history 274–6, 285–6
Veeser, H. Aram 284–5 see also gender history, feminist history
Veldeke, Heinrich von 102 Woodson, Carter G. 274–5
Velleius Paterculus 42 Woolf, Daniel 147–9, 171–2
Verstehen 230–1, 268–9 world history 192, 206–9, 298–300
via antiqua 93, 170–1 World History 299
via moderna 93, 138–9, 170–1
Vico, Giambattista 2–4, 156, 158–62, 166, Xenophon 29–30, 33
174–5, 179–80, 199–200, 211–12, 216, 245,
313–14 Yerushalmi, Josef 54–5
Vierteljahrshefte für Zeitgeschichte 262–3
Vincent of Beauvais 87 Zammito, John H. 311
Virgil 23, 34–5, 38–40, 81 Zeitgeist 156, 216–18, 255–6