Propositional Quantifiers
Propositional Quantifiers
Propositional Quantifiers
Propositional
Quantifiers
About the Series Series Editors
This Cambridge Elements series provides Bradley
an extensive overview of the many and Armour-Garb
varied connections between philosophy SUNY Albany
and logic. Distinguished authors provide
an up-to-date summary of the results of
current research in their fields and give
Frederick Kroon
The University of
Auckland
Peter Fritz
PROPOSITIONAL QUANTIFIERS
Peter Fritz
University of Oslo
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009177740 Published online by Cambridge University Press
Shaftesbury Road, Cambridge CB2 8EA, United Kingdom
One Liberty Plaza, 20th Floor, New York, NY 10006, USA
477 Williamstown Road, Port Melbourne, VIC 3207, Australia
314–321, 3rd Floor, Plot 3, Splendor Forum, Jasola District Centre,
New Delhi – 110025, India
103 Penang Road, #05–06/07, Visioncrest Commercial, Singapore 238467
www.cambridge.org
Information on this title: www.cambridge.org/9781009532747
DOI: 10.1017/9781009177740
© Peter Fritz 2024
This publication is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception and to the provisions
of relevant collective licensing agreements, no reproduction of any part may take
place without the written permission of Cambridge University Press & Assessment.
When citing this work, please include a reference to the DOI 10.1017/9781009177740
First published 2024
A catalogue record for this publication is available from the British Library.
ISBN 978-1-009-53274-7 Hardback
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009177740 Published online by Cambridge University Press
DOI: 10.1017/9781009177740
First published online: May 2024
Peter Fritz
University of Oslo
1 Propositional Quantifiers 1
2 Relational Frames 22
4 Conclusion 88
List of Abbreviations 93
References 94
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009177740 Published online by Cambridge University Press
Propositional Quantifiers 1
1 Propositional Quantifiers
1.1 Introduction
The simplest languages of formal logic are propositional. These languages
provide sentential letters and connectives with which we can represent, for
example, the conditional structure of a sentence like the following:
Letting s stand for you inventing the smiley, p for me being the pope, and using
→ to represent the conditional in (1), this can be formalized as follows:
(2) s → p
Necessity and belief are not truth-functional: some but not all truths are nec-
essary, and some but not all truths (and falsehoods) may be believed by a
given agent. Nevertheless, it is straightforward to extend the language of prop-
ositional logic to capture these statements as well. For the first, it suffices to
introduce a sentential operator □ for necessity, and for the second, a sentential
operator Bk for being believed by Kushim:
(5) □r
(6) Bk g ∧ g
In (5) and (6), r stands for Jupiter being a planet, and g for barley being a grain.
The study of logical systems with sentential operators which are not truth-
functional is known as modal logic; see, for example, Hughes and Cresswell
(1996) and Blackburn et al. (2001).
All three of the examples just mentioned are particular, as opposed to general.
For example, (4) attributes to Kushim a particular (correct) belief. But in many
2 Philosophy and Logic
As a final illustration, note that when I say in (1) (“If you invented the smiley,
then I am the pope”) that I am the pope, I am simply saying something which is
patently false. I could equally have said that I am the king or queen of England,
or made any other absurd claim. More generally, I might say that any absurdity
is the case, or simply – and absurdly – that everything is the case:
familiar case of the quantifiers of first-order logic which bind individual vari-
ables. With such quantifiers, (7), (8), and (9) are straightforwardly formalized
as follows:
(10) ∀p(Bk p → p)
(11) ∃p□p
(12) s → ∀q q
Logic is not just about formalizing statements, but also about capturing log-
ical properties of, and relationships among, such statements. For example,
(3) (“Necessarily, Jupiter is a planet”) is an instance of the existential claim
(8) (“Something is necessary”), and so the latter follows intuitively from the
former. Thus, we would expect ∃p□p to be counted as a logical consequence of
□r. Using instances of classical propositional reasoning, this follows straight-
forwardly by a schematic principle of existential introduction, in particular the
following instance:
Propositional Quantifiers 3
(13) □r → ∃p□p
(14) ∀q q → p
logics. A final Section 1.6 of the present section gives a brief overview of the
historical development of propositional quantifiers in formal logic.
This Element presents a continuous narrative, but it is also possible to read
the various sections selectively and out of order. Figure 1 presents a depend-
ency diagram indicating which sections depend on which other sections. The
label “PML” indicates that starting with Section 2, familiarity with the basics
of propositional modal logic will be assumed. The central logical theory of
propositionally quantified modal logics is developed in the section numbers
highlighted in bold.
formal system. Can’t we just use first-order logic to formalize the preceding
examples?
In first-order logic, an atomic formula consists of an application of a pred-
icate F to a finite number of arguments t1, . . . , tn , forming the statement
Ft1 . . . tn . In the simplest case, the arguments are individual variables x1, . . . , xn ,
which can be bound by first-order quantifiers ∀ and ∃. Thus, the claim that every
echidna is happy can be formalized as follows, with the obvious interpretations
of the predicate letters:
How might we use such first-order quantifiers to formalize, for example, (8)
(“Something is necessary”)? We cannot just replace a propositional variable by
a first-order variable: □ is a sentential operator, and so □ can only be applied
to formulas, and not to individual variables; thus the string ∃x□x is ill-formed.
There are two natural options to overcome this difficulty. First, we might use a
necessity predicate N instead of a necessity operator □. With N, we might use
the following formula of first-order logic:
(16) ∃xNx
(17) ∃x□Tx
Propositional Quantifiers 5
(18) N [Fj]
the notion of being believed by Kushim. With this, we can state that Kushim
believes something using the formula ∃xKx. But it is not possible to formalize
(7) along the lines of ∀p(Bk p → p); in particular, the string ∀x(Kx → x) is
ill-formed, since x cannot take the position of a formula. The simplest way to
address this deficiency is to introduce a truth predicate T. We can then propose
to use the following formula:
to consider the inferential relationships between the various claims on this sec-
ond approach. To capture that (8) (“Something is necessary”) follows from (3)
(“Necessarily, Jupiter is a planet”), we now would want ∃x□Tx to follow from
□r. Again, this means going from a sentential expression r to an individual var-
iable x, which is naturally effected using the propositional abstraction device
[. . .]. For example, one might appeal to the following schematic principle
governing truth, where φ may be any formula:
(20) φ ↔ T [φ]
We have seen that there are ways of formalizing the quantificational exam-
ples of Section 1.1 in first-order logic. However, I hope to have illustrated
that they come with certain complexities. In contrast, formalizations using
propositional quantifiers are extremely simple. The complexities of first-order
approaches may earn their keep by allowing for the formulation of theories
which do better on other dimensions of theoretical virtue. This is not the place
to try to settle these issues. For defenses of different versions of the first-order
approach, see Halbach and Welch (2009) and Bealer (1998); for exchanges on
the relative merits of the first-order and propositional approaches, see Anderson
(1987) and Bealer (1994), as well as Menzel (2024) and Williamson (2024).
One straightforward reason for investigating propositional quantifiers is
therefore their simplicity. Another has to do with the ontological commitments
of different forms of quantification. When we regiment claims like (8) (“Some-
thing is necessary”) using first-order quantifiers, it is natural to take these
quantifiers to range over propositions. Existential claims like ∃xNx and ∃x□Tx
therefore commit us to an ontology of propositions, namely to the existence
Propositional Quantifiers 7
1.3 Redundancy
I have argued that propositional quantifiers are natural and useful logical con-
cepts, which cannot straightforwardly be replaced by more familiar forms
of quantification in formal logic. Yet, propositional quantifiers are relatively
underexplored. In this section, we observe one important reason for this: in
many contexts, propositional quantifiers are redundant in at least one of two
senses of redundancy.
To illustrate the first sense of redundancy, consider classical propositional
logic. Assume that the formulation of this logic under consideration includes
two logical sentential constants, ⊤ and ⊥, with ⊤ and ¬⊥ being provable.
8 Philosophy and Logic
⊢∗ ∀pφ → φ[ψ/p],
⊢∗ φ → ψ only if ⊢∗ φ → ∀pψ.
It follows from these assumptions that the formulas provable in ⊢∗ are closed
under uniform substitution, in the sense that φ[ψ/p] is provable whenever φ
is provable and ψ is free for p in φ; the argument is analogous to the proof of
Proposition 2.2.2.
The elimination of propositional quantifiers can be stated more rigorously by
defining a mapping ·∗ from L∗ to the sublanguage of L∗ in which no universal
propositional quantifiers occur. This mapping is defined recursively, with only
one nontrivial clause:
(∀pφ)∗ := φ∗ [⊤/p] ∧ φ∗ [⊥/p]
To say that the mapping is recursive and all other cases are trivial is just to say
that ⊤∗ := ⊤, (¬φ)∗ := ¬(φ∗ ), and so on.
We can now prove that this elimination succeeds by showing that it maps any
formula to a provably equivalent formula which does not contain any universal
propositional quantifiers:
⊢∗ φ[+/p] → φ∗ [+/p].
For the right-to-left direction, note first the following two instances of
extensionality:
⊢∗ ( p ↔ ⊤) → (φ∗ ↔ φ∗ [⊤/p])
⊢∗ ( p ↔ ⊥) → (φ∗ ↔ φ∗ [⊥/p])
⊢∗ φ∗ [⊤/p] ∧ φ∗ [⊥/p] → φ∗
⊢∗ φ∗ [⊤/p] ∧ φ∗ [⊥/p] → φ
Since p is not free in the antecedent of this conditional, we can apply UG:
related fields, see Shukla et al. (2019). There are also applications of proposi-
tional quantifiers to the axiomatics of classical propositional logic; we discuss
them in Section 1.6.
In second-order logic, propositional quantifiers can also be seen to be redun-
dant in a second sense: Second-order logic adds to first-order logic variables
taking the position of predicates, and quantifiers binding these variables. For
example, in second-order logic, we can state ∀X(Xc). For a detailed intro-
duction to second-order logic, see Shapiro (1991). Just as predicate constants
can have any arity, so can second-order variables. Depending on the formula-
tion of second-order logic, this may not just include the cases of polyadic and
monadic variables, but also the limiting case of zero-adic, or nullary, variables.
A nullary predicate takes no arguments to form an atomic predication, so we
can understand it as a propositional constant. Analogously, a nullary second-
order variable can be understood as a propositional variable. Propositional
quantifiers can therefore be understood as nullary second-order quantifiers.
In the context of a suitable formulation of second-order logic, propositional
quantifiers are therefore also redundant in a second sense: they are already
included.
The second sense of redundancy extends to higher-order extensions of
second-order logic. This is important since third- and higher-order logics do not
(without further assumptions) satisfy the extensionality requirement of the first
redundancy argument. This is easy to see: In third-order logic, a standard pred-
icate F can not only be applied to individual terms to form an atomic formula,
but also serve itself as the argument of a (higher-order) predicate Y. Here, Y may
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009177740 Published online by Cambridge University Press
( p ↔ q) → (Xp ↔ Xq)
Although p and q might have the same truth-value, the two variables need
not stand for the same proposition. Thus one of them might have a property
X which the other lacks. This is an informal semantic argument, but it can
easily be turned into a rigorous model-theoretic proof to show that in third-
and higher-order logic (without any extensionality assumptions), this instance
of the extensionality schema cannot be derived. In this sense, the step from
second- to third- and higher-order logic takes us outside the realm of extension-
ality. In third- and higher-order logic, propositional quantifiers are therefore
not redundant in the first sense, but they are redundant in the second sense:
12 Philosophy and Logic
while they are not eliminable, they are already included as nullary second-order
quantifiers.
easy to see what this difference should amount to, especially as modal logics
are used in a variety of different applications, on different interpretations of the
modal operators.)
If the languages of propositional modal logic are fragments of the language
of third-order logic, then so are their extensions by propositional quantifiers:
they can be understood as obtained by adding to the relevant quantifier-free
fragment the special case of nullary second-order quantifiers. In such a con-
text, propositional quantifiers need not be redundant in either of the two
senses discussed earlier: the first redundancy argument does not apply, since
propositional modal logics are typically not extensional, and the second redun-
dancy argument does not apply since they do not already include propositional
quantifiers (or any other form of quantification).
One might wonder: Why bother with all these fragments? Why not just work
in third-, or better, higher-order logic? In some cases, this may well be the best
option, but it will not be the best option in all cases. Third- and higher-order log-
ics are complex systems, which may well introduce significant complications.
Propositional Quantifiers 13
If the full flexibility of these systems is not required, it may well be a signifi-
cant advantage to make do with a more restrictive fragment. For example, many
second- and higher-order logics are essentially incomplete: the valid formulas,
on a suitable notion of validity, cannot be exactly captured by any proof system.
In technical terms, the validities are not recursively enumerable, essentially due
to the incompleteness results of Gödel (1931). By restricting the language to the
formulas of a propositional modal logic, this issue is very often avoided, as very
many propositional modal logics are computationally much more tractable.
In systematically investigating the principles of a logic of, for example,
belief, there are therefore good reasons not to always work in full higher-order
logic, but sometimes also in more restrictive fragments, like propositional logic
with an extra unary sentential operator. In some cases, however, the restrictions
of this particular fragment may prove to be too limiting. Our initial examples,
such as (7) (“Everything Kushim believes is true”), illustrate this, showing that
in many applications, it is natural to quantify over the arguments of modalities.
Such quantification does not require the full power of third-order logic: we
can expand propositional modal logic more carefully using just the required
propositional (i.e., nullary second-order) quantifiers. As we will see later in
this Element, in some but not all cases, such quantifiers preserve the tracta-
bility of propositional modal logics. Just like propositional modal logics, their
extensions by propositional quantifiers provide a trade-off between strength
and tractability. Which systems are most suitable will depend on the particular
application.
Propositional modal logics are the main setting in which propositional quan-
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009177740 Published online by Cambridge University Press
tifiers have been studied, and they will also be the focus of this Element. But
there are other settings in which they play an important role. In particular,
there are other proper fragments of third- and higher-order logics which include
propositional quantifiers, and in which they are not eliminable. For example,
propositional quantifiers can be added to first-order modal logic. Such a lan-
guage has proven useful in investigating the interpolation property in first-order
modal logics; see the discussion of Fine (1979) by Kripke (1983), as well as
Fitting (2002). Another example is the extension of modal logics by proposi-
tional quantifiers and third-order quantifiers binding variables in the position of
sentential operators. A philosophical application of such a system can be found
in Fritz (2023c).
In the following, I will call a propositional modal logic with propositional
quantifiers a “propositionally quantified modal logic”. In the literature, this
label is used interchangeably with “quantified propositional modal logic”.
The reason for adopting the former rather than the latter is that the former
makes clear that only propositional quantifiers added. Logics with further
14 Philosophy and Logic
quantifiers are therefore explicitly excluded, such as the one just mentioned
which incorporates certain third-order quantifiers.
1.5 Outlook
For the reasons discussed in the previous subsection, the two subsequent sec-
tions of this Element will focus on propositional quantifiers in the context of
propositional modal logic. It makes little sense to consider such extensions
without having already studied propositional modal logics on their own. Con-
sequently, from Section 2 on, I will assume familiarity with basic definitions
and results in propositional modal logic.
The material to be discussed in the remaining two sections is organized
according to different model-theoretic approaches. The main reason for this
is a matter of expository convenience: different model-theoretic approaches
require rather different mathematical tools. The sections aim to introduce the
relevant model-theoretic concepts, to consider the logics to which the relevant
models give rise from a deductive perspective, and to illustrate the usefulness
of these ideas in applications. For reasons of space, it will only be possible to
state many of the most important results; in these cases, proofs can be found
in the references provided. This Element therefore aims to be an introduction
and a survey rather than a comprehensive textbook on propositional quan-
tifiers. Although many interesting results have been obtained on propositionally
quantified modal logics, many natural questions have not been considered. A
number of basic results on such questions will be established here; in these
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009177740 Published online by Cambridge University Press
cases, proofs are either routine or are provided in detail. Many further ques-
tions remain open, and many specific results await a more systematic treatment.
Each section therefore also states some important open questions concerning
the relevant model-theoretic approach.
Section 2 discusses the most well-known models for propositional modal
logic, based on sets of possible worlds and relations of accessibility between
them; such structures are known as relational frames or Kripke frames. On
such frames, propositional quantifiers can be interpreted straightforwardly as
ranging over sets of worlds. Section 2.1 begins by laying out the syntax of
propositionally quantified modal logics. Section 2.2 sets up proof systems
in a general manner, and formulates the axioms and rules of classical logic
for propositional quantifiers. Section 2.3 introduces relational frames and the
resulting notion of normality for modal logics. To illustrate the usefulness
of propositional quantifiers in applications, this section also briefly discusses
the knowability paradox, and shows how its conclusion can be derived for-
mally using the proof systems defined here. Section 2.4 considers two further
Propositional Quantifiers 15
principles which are valid on relational frames, namely a version of the Barcan
formula and a principle of atomicity which is unique to the case of propositional
quantifiers. Section 2.5 discusses the well-known modal logic S5, in which
propositional quantifiers behave especially well, and lead to an axiomatizable
logic. As a second illustration of an application of propositional quantifiers,
this section also discusses arguments to the effect that possible worlds can be
understood as special propositions, and shows how these arguments might be
formalized using propositional quantifiers. Section 2.6 turns to the more techni-
cal question of (recursive) axiomatizability of propositionally quantified modal
logics on classes of relational frames, and notes that propositional quantifiers
often lead to unaxiomatizability. Only in relatively few cases is it possible to
give complete axiomatizations; these cases and the corresponding complete-
ness questions are discussed in Section 2.7. The final Section 2.8 discusses
some model-theoretic beginnings, focusing in particular on transformations of
relational frames and their interactions with propositional quantifiers.
Section 3 turns to interpretations of propositionally quantified modal lan-
guages beyond relational frames. Section 3.1 begins by generalizing relational
frames to neighborhood frames, which are still based on possible worlds. Sec-
tion 3.2 goes further and generalizes neighborhood frames to models based
on complete Boolean algebras. Section 3.3 discusses a generalization which
can be applied to any frames based on possible worlds or models based on
complete Boolean algebras, which is to distinguish either one of the worlds,
or a filter of the algebra. Section 3.4 discusses a second way of generalizing
models based on complete Boolean algebras, namely by weakening the require-
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009177740 Published online by Cambridge University Press
ment for the algebra to be complete. Section 3.5 considers the corresponding
generalization of relational and neighborhood frames, which involves limiting
which sets of possible worlds are counted as propositions. All of the generaliza-
tions of these five sections are well-known in the case of propositional modal
logics, but many of them have been little explored in the presence of prop-
ositional quantifiers. Section 3.6 considers possible worlds models in which
the domain of propositional quantification varies from world to world, adapt-
ing well-known model-theoretic ideas for modal predicate logic. Section 3.7
notes that propositional quantifiers need not be interpreted as ranging over any
domain of propositions at all, as there are formally coherent ways of inter-
preting propositional quantifiers as substitutional, and so as ranging – in some
sense – over sentences. The final Section 4 notes that even if propositional quan-
tifiers are interpreted as ranging over a domain of propositions supplied by a
model, and the model is to validate the principles of classical logic, the domain
of quantification does not have to constitute a Boolean algebra. It concludes
by using propositional quantifiers to discuss certain paradoxes of propositional
16 Philosophy and Logic
(1979, pp. 251–252), but neither of them uses any symbolism in these notes,
and therefore also no propositional quantifiers.
A few years after Ramsey’s discussion, propositional quantifiers play a sig-
nificant role in the first edition of Lewis and Langford (1959 [1932], see ch. VI,
sect. 6). Lewis and Langford develop proof systems for propositional modal
logic, and note that they intend not to include the principle which may be
rendered in modern notation as follows:
(21) □( p → q) ∨ □( p → ¬q)
Active Years (1955–1975) Starting in the late 1950s and continuing through
the 1960s, great advances are made in the study of modal logic. As we have seen
earlier, in such modal contexts, propositional quantifiers play a more substantial
role, and it is therefore not surprising to see a renewed interest in proposi-
tional quantifiers in this period. Essentially, these investigations return to the
applications of propositional quantifiers pioneered by Ramsey, and Lewis and
Langford, some three decades earlier. This is not to say that no studies of prop-
ositional quantifiers in intensional systems are considered in this intervening
period – see, for example, Łoś (1948), an English review of which was pub-
lished by Suszko (1949) – but only that they did not seem to have elicited much
excitement.
Arguably the most influential advocate of propositional quantifiers in the
period of their resurgence is Arthur Prior. Prior (1955, pp. 190–192) already
briefly discusses questions arising from the combination of propositional quan-
tifiers and modal operators, addressing an argument of Łukasiewicz (1951).
Two years later, Prior (1957) considers a range of interpretations of modal
operators, including temporal, alethic, epistemic, and deontic ones. Prior (1957,
pp. 130–131) briefly mentions an example involving propositional quantifica-
tion into an epistemic context, which prompts Cohen (1957, p. 231, fn. 6) to
challenge Prior to explain how his system avoids a form of the liar paradox.
Drawing on observations in a review of Koyré (1946) by Church (1946), Prior
(1958b) develops a more explicit deductive account of a propositionally quan-
tified modal logic, and uses it to discuss the paradox. Prior (1961) continues
this discussion; we return to it in the final Section 4.
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009177740 Published online by Cambridge University Press
Carnap (1942), who in turn cites Ramsey (1923). It is also worth noting that Sel-
lars is likely to have been familiar with propositional quantification in modal
logic, since, as noted by deVries (2020), he studied modal logic with Lang-
ford around the time of publication of the first edition of Lewis and Langford
(1959 [1932]).) Combined with a defense of propositional quantifiers by Grover
(1970, 1972), this leads to a version of the deflationary theory of truth called
the prosentential theory of truth by Grover et al. (1975). For further examples
of uses of propositional quantifiers in this period, see Fitch (1963).
In a few short years, from 1967 to 1970, an immense amount of progress is
made on propositionally quantified modal logic. Many of the most fundamental
results in the area are established in this period, which will be covered in detail
later, with references to the original publications. The outstanding achievement
in this period is an article of Fine (1970), which focuses on propositionally
quantified modal logic interpreted over possible worlds models. It is hard to
convey a sense of just how many important contributions are contained in the
eleven short pages of this article, including axiomatizations, model construc-
tions, and results on completeness, decidability, and the failure of recursive
axiomatizability. The multitude of references to it in this Element will give
something of an impression of its importance. However, as a consequence of
the wealth of results in this short article, proofs are often only sketched in the
barest outlines.
quantifiers at this point: First, Arthur Prior, the chief proponent of proposi-
tional quantifiers in the 1960s, dies in 1969. Second, Quine (1986 [1970])
argues influentially against both modal and higher-order logic (where proposi-
tional quantifiers count as an instance of the latter). From a Quinean standpoint,
modal logic with propositional quantifiers manages to combine two conceptual
confusions in one very simple package.
Whatever the reasons for the lack of interest in propositional quantifiers in
modal logic, little work is done in the field for roughly the next twenty years.
This changes from the mid 1990s, as illustrated by publications of Ghilardi
and Zawadowski (1995), Kaminski and Tiomkin (1996), Kremer (1997c),
Antonelli and Thomason (2002) and ten Cate (2006). Especially in the last
decade, one finds a marked resurgence of higher-order modal logic in philos-
ophy, in no small part due to the influence of Williamson (2013). A number
of interesting philosophical arguments require propositional quantifiers but no
other higher-order quantifiers, and can therefore naturally be formulated in
Propositional Quantifiers 21
propositionally quantified modal logic. For examples in this Element, see the
discussion of the knowability paradox in Section 2.3, the reduction of pos-
sible worlds to propositions in Section 2.5, the contingency of propositional
existence in Section 3.6, and the paradox of Epimenides in Section 4.
Over the last 60 years, many important results on propositionally quantified
modal logics are obtained, and many interesting applications are discussed.
Some examples of applications will be discussed in what follows, involving
epistemic and alethic modalities. Propositional quantifiers are also used in the
context of applications involving other modalities, such as deontic (see Prior
(1958a), Lokhorst (2006) and Rönnedal (2020)) and temporal (see Kesten and
Pnueli (2002) and French and Reynolds (2003)).
In these respects, propositionally quantified modal logic resembles standard
propositional modal logic. However, due to periods of neglect, the proposi-
tionally quantified case is comparatively understudied, and especially lacking
in general and systematic results. This is illustrated by the fact that a complete-
ness theorem for the most straightforward algebraic model theory of the most
straightforward propositionally quantified modal logic is only established very
recently, by Holliday (2019). The field is rife with similar longstanding open
questions, which are open not because of intrinsic mathematical difficulty, but
because of a lack of interest. In order to encourage research on these questions,
I will highlight some of them in the following sections.
2 Relational Frames
2.1 Propositionally Quantified Modal Languages
We start with a formal definition of a language of propositionally quantified
modal logic. There are a number of choice of points in setting up this definition.
First, it is clear that the language will have to be based on a choice of atomic
proposition letters. Such letters could be divided into nonlogical constants and
variables, but we won’t need such a division: in all the applications discussed
in this section, the role of nonlogical constants can be played by free variables.
So we start from a countably infinite set of variables Φ. For elements of Φ, we
use lowercase Roman letters, in particular p, q, and r, and the results of adding
various indices to these letters.
Second, different choices of Boolean connectives may be included. Propo-
sitional modal logics are often defined using some small functionally complete
set of connectives, that is, a set of connectives such that every polyadic func-
tion on truth-values is expressed by some complex formula. This is because the
modal logics of interest typically do not distinguish between formulas which
are equivalent by the principles of classical propositional logic. For example,
if a modal logic does not distinguish between formulas of the form ¬φ and
φ → ⊥ in any context, then there is no reason to include ¬ as a connective of
the language in addition to → and ⊥; instead, we can simply introduce “¬φ”
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009177740 Published online by Cambridge University Press
as a way of abbreviating “φ → ⊥”. The main reason for limiting the number
of Boolean connectives is that it simplifies many definitions and proofs, and
we follow this common practice here, using just → and ⊥ as Boolean connec-
tives. For concreteness, we use other Boolean connectives as abbreviations, as
follows:
¬φ := φ → ⊥
φ ∨ ψ := ¬φ → ψ
φ ∧ ψ := ¬(φ → ¬ψ)
φ ↔ ψ := (φ → ψ) ∧ (ψ → φ)
⊤ := ¬⊥
The choice of → and ⊥ may seem a strange one, since ⊥ is not an especially
natural connective; in particular, there is no obvious way of rendering it in
English. From the perspective of translating the formal language into English,
it would be more natural to start with, for example, ¬ and ∧, which are very
Propositional Quantifiers 23
naturally read as “not” and “and”. But → and ⊥ have two formal advantages:
→ is the most important connective for stating standard axiomatic principles,
so including it allows us to avoid using defined connectives in the statement
of these principles. And various arguments are simplified by ensuring that ⊤
and ⊥ contain no free variables (or quantifiers), which motivates including ⊥ as
primitive. It is worth noting that in the general context of classical modal logics
as introduced in the next section, the choice of primitive Boolean connectives
can make a substantial difference; see Makinson (1973) and Segerberg (1982)
for discussion.
Quantifiers present a choice-point similar to that of Boolean connectives. In
many logics, the existential and universal quantifiers are treated as each other’s
duals, so that, for example, formulas of the form ∃pφ and ¬∀p¬φ are not dis-
tinguished in any context. We take the universal quantifier ∀ as primitive, and
introduce the existential quantifier as the following abbreviation:
∃pφ := ¬∀p¬φ
It is worth noting that the definition of ⊥ as ∀pp discussed in Section 1.6 would
be available to us for much of the following. However, we still include ⊥ as a
primitive connective, for two reasons: First, as noted, it can be helpful for ⊤ and
⊥ to contain neither free variables nor quantifiers. Second, in discussing stand-
ard (i.e., quantifier-free) propositional modal logics, we still need to ensure that
the set of Boolean connectives is functionally complete.
Finally, our languages will contain modal operators. Most discussions of
modal logics only consider including a single unary operator □. But from the
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009177740 Published online by Cambridge University Press
Definition 2.1.1 A modal signature is a pair σ = ⟨O, ρ⟩, where O is a set, and
ρ : O → N.
24 Philosophy and Logic
(i) If p ∈ Φ, then p ∈ Lσ .
(ii) ⊥ ∈ Lσ .
(iii) If φ, ψ ∈ Lσ , then (φ → ψ) ∈ Lσ .
(iv) If o ∈ O and φ1, . . . , φρ(o) ∈ Lσ , then oφ1 . . . φρ(o) ∈ Lσ .
(v) If p ∈ Φ and φ ∈ Lσ , then ∀pφ ∈ Lσ .
σ is the set of quantifier-free formulas of Lσ , that is, the smallest set
Lqf
σ instead of Lσ .
satisfying conditions (i)–(iv) for Lqf
they are pairwise distinct – just as it does not matter exactly what the elements
of Φ are – we will leave this unspecified.
Third, according to clause (iv), a formula obtained using an application of
a binary modal operator o has the form oφψ. However, some modal opera-
tors, such as , are more commonly used infix rather than prefix: it is more
common to write (φ ψ) rather than φψ. We therefore allow the former
notation as an abbreviation for the latter formula. When not required to resolve
any structural ambiguities, we drop the parentheses, as we do for →. Among
binary operators, we assume that ∧ and ∨ bind stronger than any other. So, to
illustrate, we write p → q ∧ r to abbreviate ( p → (q ∧ r)).
Finally, the notion of a free occurrence of a variable is defined as usual:
an occurrence of p is bound if it is in the scope of a quantifier ∀p, and free
otherwise. A variable p is free in φ if there is a free occurrence of p in φ. A
formula ψ is free for p in φ if no free occurrence of a variable in ψ becomes
bound when every free occurrence of p in φ is replaced by ψ. If ψ is free for
p in φ, we write φ[ψ/p] for the result of this replacement. We generalize this
Propositional Quantifiers 25
last notation to finite sequences, writing φ[ψ1 /p1, . . . , ψn /pn ] for the result of
simultaneously replacing every free occurrence of pi in φ by ψi , assuming ψi is
free for pi in φ (for 1 ≤ i ≤ n, with p1, . . . , pn being pairwise distinct).
ponens. With this rule, we could modify the first condition, and require only a
finite set of axioms to be included from which all tautologies are derivable using
modus ponens. This choice points won’t matter in the following, so we simply
include all tautologies; note that the definition of being a tautology using truth-
tables constitutes a decision procedure. Turning to quantifiers, we require the
inclusion of every instance of universal instantiation. This condition encap-
sulates the idea that if a given condition holds for every proposition, then it
holds as well for the proposition expressed by any given formula ψ. Finally,
we require closure under universal generalization: If a conditional φ → ψ
is contained in the set and p is not free in φ, then φ → ∀pψ must be con-
tained as well. This condition encapsulates the idea that propositional variables
stand for arbitrary propositions, and the thought that if a condition ψ is guar-
anteed to hold for an arbitrary p (on the assumption of φ), then it must hold
for every p (assuming φ). These four conditions suffice to ensure that the basic
principles of classical logic are included. We therefore call the relevant logics
classical:
26 Philosophy and Logic
Definition 2.2.1 Given any modal signature σ, define the following conditions
on a set Λ ⊆ Lσ :
Proof We consider the first three items; the rest can be deduced from these by
standard arguments.
(1): Assume φ is a tautology. Then so is ⊤ → φ, which is therefore a member
of Λ, by Taut. So with UG, ⊤ → ∀pφ ∈ Λ. As ⊤ ∈ Λ by Taut, ∀pφ ∈ Λ
Propositional Quantifiers 27
As a special case of (3), we obtain the observation that relabeling free vari-
ables does not affect membership in a classical propositionally quantified modal
logic Λ: if Λ contains φ, then Λ also contains φ[q/p], as long as q is free for p
in φ. Further, from (7) we can see the equivalence of a universally quantified
statements with the result of relabeling the bound variable of the outermost
quantifier. By a straightforward induction, this can be extended to relabeling
the bound variables of any quantifiers which are not in the scope of any modal
operators. But we cannot remove the restriction on modal operators, since we
are not assuming that formulas which are equivalent by the lights of Λ are
interchangeable within modal operators. This is intentional: At this point, we
don’t want to impose any limitations on the distinctions which can be drawn
by modal operators. For example, we will consider a binary operator of iden-
tity = in Section 4. We don’t want to assume at this point that, for example,
(∀pp) = (∀qq), even if it is plausible. Consequently, we cannot assume that
bound variables can always be relabeled. It is therefore important that such
a relabeling is not built into the definition of φ[ψ/p], as it sometimes is, for
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009177740 Published online by Cambridge University Press
Definition 2.2.3 Given any modal signature σ, a classical modal logic is a set
σ which satisfies Taut, MP, and the following condition:
Λ ⊆ Lqf
28 Philosophy and Logic
σ , then φ[ψ/p] ∈ Λ.
(US) If φ ∈ Λ, p ∈ Φ, and ψ ∈ Lqf
The terminology used here comes apart somewhat from established termi-
nology, which uses the label “modal logic” for what we are calling a “classical
modal logic”; see, for example, Segerberg (1971, p. 8). Segerberg also uses
the label “classical modal logic” for a different notion, which we call “con-
gruential modal logic” in Section 3.1, following Makinson (1973, p. 196). The
reason for our use of “classical” for the notion just defined is that it corresponds
to the previous notion of classicality in the propositionally quantified case. As
noted, there are modal logics based on non-classical propositional logics, and
in Section 3.5, we will see logics which weaken the principles associated with
the quantifiers. Because of these reasons, we require the qualifier “classical”.
So far, we have taken an abstract approach to modal logics as sets of formu-
las satisfying certain closure conditions. One might wonder why we haven’t
considered any proof systems. In fact, each closure condition considered here
corresponds to a schematic axiom or rule, and a constraint like classicality can
be turned into a proof-theoretic concept. I will illustrate the point using the
notion of a classical propositionally quantified modal logic, but it is easy to see
that it applies as well to classical modal logics and similar concepts defined
below.
First, we note that for every set of formulas Γ ⊆ Lσ , there is a unique small-
est classical propositionally quantified modal logic including Γ, namely the
intersection of all classical propositionally quantified modal logics including Γ.
This intersection is guaranteed to be well-defined, since Lσ trivially includes Γ
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009177740 Published online by Cambridge University Press
and satisfies the four closure conditions. The smallest classical propositionally
quantified modal logic including Γ can alternatively be characterized as the set
of theorems of the proof system which contains as axioms the tautologies and
instances of the schema of universal instantiation (as in Taut and UI), as well
as the elements of Γ, and as rules modus ponens and universal generalization
(as in MP and UG). We therefore define:
Definition 2.2.4 For any set Γ ⊆ Lqf σ , the classical modal logic axiomatized
σ
by Γ, written C Γ, is the smallest classical modal logic including Γ. For any
set Γ ⊆ Lσ , the classical propositionally quantified modal logic axiomatized
by Γ, written CσΠ Γ, is the smallest classical propositionally quantified modal
logic including Γ.
σ γ . . . γ instead of Cσ Γ.
If Γ is a finite set {γ1, . . . , γn }, we also write C(Π) 1 n (Π)
σ
In particular, C(Π) is the smallest classical (propositionally quantified) modal
logic. For brevity, we usually omit mention of the modal signature σ in Cσ ,
Propositional Quantifiers 29
unless it is not clear from context. All of these conventions will be applied to
analogs of this definition for normal and congruential modal logics as well.
A set of formulas is a classical propositionally quantified modal logic if and
only if it is the classical propositionally quantified modal logic axiomatized by
Γ, for some set Γ. This observation gives us a deductive formulation of classi-
cal propositionally quantified modal logics. It also follows that every classical
propositionally quantified modal logic Λ is axiomatized by some set, in par-
ticular by Λ itself, so in this sense, every such logic is axiomatizable. In this
sense, being axiomatizable is an uninteresting notion. In later discussions of
axiomatizability, we will therefore consider a more demanding notion. If we
think of a logic (set of formulas) Λ as given axiomatically, we say that φ is a
theorem of, or derivable in, Λ if φ ∈ Λ.
^φ := ¬□¬φ
R[x] is the set of elements v such that Rwv for some w ∈ x. We can now define
relational frames formally as follows:
F, w, a ⊩ p if and only if w ∈ a( p)
F, w, a ⊮ ⊥
F, w, a ⊩ φ → ψ if and only if F, w, a ⊩ φ only if F, w, a ⊩ ψ
F, w, a ⊩ ∀pφ if and only if F, w, a[x/p] ⊩ φ for all x ⊆ W
F, w, a ⊩ □φ if and only if F, v, a ⊩ φ for all v ∈ R□ (w)
From this, two notions of validity are derived, letting C be a class of relational
frames:
Propositional Quantifiers 31
Relational frames provide a very flexible model theory for modal languages:
Every class of relational frames C determines a logic, namely the set of formu-
las valid on every frame in C. For example, in order to ensure the validity of
the principle □p → p, we may focus on relational frames in which R□ is reflex-
ive, and to ensure the validity of the principle ∃p(□p ∧ ¬p), we may focus on
relational frames in which R□ is irreflexive. This is a general feature of model
theories for modal languages, so we define generally:
We call Lσ (C) the propositionally quantified modal logic of C, and Lqf σ (C)
the modal logic of C. We can show that the (propositionally quantified) modal
logic of any class of relational frames is a classical (propositionally quantified)
modal logic. In fact, the logics of classes of relational frames are guaranteed
to satisfy two additional conditions, which lead to the following notion of
normality:
Proof It is routine to show that LO (C) satisfies each of the six conditions. □
Kripke (1963a, p. 67), and Lemmon (1977 [1966], p. 30). It is only in sys-
tematic explorations of relational frame semantics, such as Makinson (1966,
p. 379) and Segerberg (1971, p. 12), that the now-common notion of normal-
ity emerged (initially called “semi-normality” by Makinson). In the literature
on propositionally quantified modal logics, a definition of normality for the
unimodal case can be found in Ding (2018, 2021a) and Holliday (2019).
Analogous to the case of classicality, normality gives rise to a notion of
normal logics axiomatized by a given set of axioms:
We write R for the class of all relational frames (for a given modal signature),
and say that R(Γ) is the class of relational frames defined by Γ. Since every NML
defines a class of relational frames, and every class of relational frames gives
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009177740 Published online by Cambridge University Press
I don’t follow this notation here is the following: Given an NML Λ, there are sev-
eral ways of adding propositional quantifiers. For example, we might consider
the smallest classical propositionally quantified modal logic including Λ, or the
smallest NPQML including Λ. Adding Π as a subscript to K makes clear that the
normal extension is intended. The downside of this notation is that it makes
it awkward to specify normal propositionally quantified extensions when the
relevant NML is not given in the form KΓ. The most prominent cases are the
Lewis systems S4 and S5. This awkwardness can be mitigated by introducing
the convention of writing SΠ 4 and SΠ 5 instead of KΠ S4 and KΠ S5, respec-
tively, and analogously for their extensions. Similarly, some NMLs have names
of the form KX, without X being an axiom or list of axioms; an example is K3,
which we discuss in Section 2.6. In these cases, we also write KΠ X for KΠ KX.
Classes of relational frames, normal modal logics, and the relation of valid-
ity give rise to many questions which have been central to the study of modal
logic. Such questions are often phrased in terms of soundness and complete-
ness: A normal modal logic Λ is said to be sound with respect to a class of
relational frames C if every member of Λ is valid on C, and complete if every
formula valid on C is a member of Λ. Establishing these properties is especially
interesting if Λ is specified as KΓ, for a finite set of axioms Γ.
For every class of relational frames C, there is a unique normal modal logic
which is sound and complete with respect to it, namely LO qf
(C); this is the logic
determined by C. But conversely, it is not obvious that every normal modal logic
KΓ is sound and complete with respect to some class of frames. If it is, then it is
sound and complete in particular with respect to R(Γ), and so KΓ = LO qf
(R(Γ)).
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009177740 Published online by Cambridge University Press
KΓ is always sound with respect to R(Γ), but it is not obvious that KΓ should
always be complete with respect to R(Γ). That is, it may be that some formula
φ is valid on every relational frame in the class defined by Γ, even though
φ cannot be derived from Γ, in the sense that φ < KΓ. In fact, Thomason
(1974) and Fine (1974) showed that there are normal modal logics which are
not determined by any class of relational frames. Such logics are often called
Kripke-incomplete.
Although not every normal modal logic is Kripke-complete, very many nat-
ural normal modal logics are so. This includes every normal unimodal logic
axiomatized by a subset of the following common modal axioms:
D □p → ^p
T □p → p
B p → □^p
4 □p → □□p
5 ^p → □^p
34 Philosophy and Logic
For example, KT is sound and complete with respect to the class of relational
frames on which T is valid, which contains just those relational frames with
a reflexive accessibility relation, and K is sound and complete with respect to
the class of all relational frames.
Much of the remainder of this section will be concerned with these kinds of
questions in the propositionally quantified modal case. As it turns out, in the
presence of propositional quantifiers, the situation changes drastically: KΠ Γ is
incomplete with respect to R(Γ) for very many natural choices of axioms Γ.
This incompleteness can have a number of different sources, which we explore
in the following.
Before turning to these model-theoretic questions in subsequent sections, it
is worth noting a purely deductive question which appears not to have been
considered in the literature. Say that a propositionally quantified modal logic
Π is a conservative extension of a modal logic Λ if the quantifier-free theorems
of Π are just the theorems of Λ; that is, if Π ∩ LO qf
= Λ. One would not expect
that adding propositional quantifiers governed by UI and UG to a given propo-
sitional modal logic would allow the derivation of any additional purely modal
(i.e., quantifier-free) principles. And indeed, it is not very difficult to show the
following, as I do in Fritz (unpublished):
This is the analogous question for normal logics, namely the question whether
KΠ Γ is always a conservative extension of KΓ. Note that this is not settled
by the previous result: if we let ∆ be KΓ, then C∆ is KΓ, and so CΠ KΓ is a
conservative extension of KΓ. But it doesn’t obviously follow that KΠ Γ is a
conservative extension of KΓ: KΠ Γ does, but CΠ KΓ does not obviously allow
quantified axioms to be necessitated. It is easy to see that if KΓ is the logic of
a class of relational frames, this class will also validate KΠ Γ, whence KΠ Γ is
a conservative extension of KΓ. But, as I show in Fritz (unpublished), there
are cases of Kripke-incomplete NMLs KΓ in which the incompleteness can be
demonstrated deductively with the addition of quantifiers:
known the knowability paradox. Informally, this is an argument for the sur-
prising conclusion that if every truth is knowable, then every truth is known. It
was first published by Fitch (1963), but it is due to Church (2009 [1945]) who
formulated it in a referee report for an earlier version of Fitch’s article. Many
detailed discussions of the argument can be found in an edited volume on the
argument, Salerno (2009). Informally, the argument goes as follows:
modal operators: a unary operator K for “it is known that” and a unary operator
□ for “it is necessary that”. Then the conclusion of the knowability paradox can
straightforwardly be stated as follows:
The second kind of principle arises from the fact that for every world w of a
relational frame, the domain of propositions P(W ) contains the singleton {w}.
From an algebraic perspective, such propositions can be seen as atomic ele-
ments; we return to this perspective in Section 3.2. We therefore call singletons
of worlds atomic propositions. Such propositions have special properties which
can be expressed in a propositionally quantified language. This leads to a clus-
ter of related principles which are valid on relational frames but which are not
in general derivable in NPQMLs.
For the first such principle, note that for every world w, the atomic propo-
sition {w} is true in w and no other (accessible) world. Thus, at w, every true
proposition q is strictly implied by {w}, in the sense that necessarily, if {w}
then q. Relational frames therefore validate the following schematic principle,
which says that there is a proposition p with this feature (for any □ ∈ O):
For another example, assume that v is accessible from w, and consider the
atomic proposition {v}. From the perspective of w, {v} is possible, and for
every proposition p, {v} either strictly implies p or strictly implies the negation
(complement) of p. {v} therefore satisfies a condition which we can formulate
in the object language as follows, for any proposition expressed by a formula φ:
Open Question 1 In the context of which NPQMLs does At entail At′ (and vice
versa), in the sense that the logic contains the former only if it contains the
latter?
Similar questions arise for further natural principles of atomicity. These prin-
ciples include a number of variants of At and At′ in which □ is strengthened
to a more demanding condition. By way of illustration, consider At. First, in
a bimodal setting with modalities □1 and □2 , we may not only consider an
instance of At for each modality, but also the following combined principle:
It is easy to see that this is derivable in any NPQML containing the relevant two
instances of At: if p1 and p2 are witnesses of At for □1 and □2 , respectively,
then p1 ∧ p2 is a witness of the combined principle. While this variant is easily
seen to be derivable, the matter is different with a second variant, which iterates
the modality as follows:
It is far from clear that an NPQML which contains At must also contain this
iterated principle (unless, of course, it contains an iteration principle like 4).
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009177740 Published online by Cambridge University Press
notion of necessity as being maximally broad; see Kripke (1980 [1972], p. 99)
and Williamson (2013).
Unusually, the results on S5 can be extended to propositional quantifiers.
First, the propositionally quantified modal logics of E and U are also the same,
as we will show in Section 2.8 using the standard technique of generated sub-
frames. Second, the resulting propositionally quantified modal logic also has
very natural axiomatizations. Since S5 contains B, any NPQML which includes
S5 already contains Bc. In Section 3.2, we will show that such an NPQML
need not include the atomicity principles discussed in the last section. But the
axiomatization of S5π+, that is, L□ (R(S5)), can be completed by adding At:
Theorem 2.5.1 SΠ 5At is sound and complete with respect to U, the class of
relational frames with a universal accessibility relation.
This result was shown by Kaplan (1970b) and Fine (1970). Soundness is
straightforward to establish using Proposition 2.3.4. Fine notes two ways of
establishing completeness: one is by a canonical model construction, and the
other by a quantifier-elimination argument using certain additional logical con-
stants. Kaplan employs the second method. Kaplan and Fine don’t provide
many details of these proofs, although related discussion can be found in
Kaplan (1970a) and Fine (1969, 1972).
As indicated in Section 1.6, an important motivation for the investigation
of S5π+ can be found in the works of Prior (1967, 1968). One of Prior’s con-
cerns was the task of giving an account of possible worlds in philosophical
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009177740 Published online by Cambridge University Press
the intended notion of necessity in the sense that all of its theorems are true
under any interpretation of the free propositional variables. (As discussed by
Williamson (2013, section 3.3), this is the notion of logical truth of Tarski (2002
[1936]).) Prior’s idea can then be understood as proposing that talk of possi-
ble worlds can be understood as talk of propositions corresponding to possible
worlds. To correspond to a possible world, a proposition has to describe a pos-
sible and complete way for things to be, that is, to be possible and to settle the
truth of every proposition. In this modal context, a proposition p can be under-
stood to settle a proposition q as being true if it strictly implies it, namely, if
□( p → q), and to settle q as being false of it strictly implies its negation, that
is, if □( p → ¬q). That is, a proposition p corresponds to a possible world just
in case it satisfies condition Q defined in the previous section. If p is a such
world-proposition, we understand a proposition q to be true in p just in case p
settles q as being true, that is, just in case □( p → q).
We can now use SΠ 5At to show that this way of regimenting talk of possible
worlds vindicates central assumptions about the relationship between possible
worlds and propositions. Most importantly, we can prove what Menzel and
Zalta (2014) call the fundamental principle of world theory: the claim that a
proposition is possible just in case it is true in some possible world. On Prior’s
proposal, this can be regimented as the following sentence of L□ :
to play the role of worlds. This applies to Prior’s proposal as well: the claim
that a proposition is possible just in case it is true in some world(-proposition)
depends essentially on the inclusion of the atomicity principle At. Using the
models of Section 3.2, we can show that this equivalence cannot be derived in
SΠ 5. This poses the question: Why think that At is (necessarily) true?
It turns out that the matter can easily be settled if a way of quantifying
plurally over propositions is added to L□ . The relevant plural propositional
quantifiers are analogous to the plural (first-order) quantifiers of Boolos (1984).
By a variant of arguments of Gallin (1975), Fine (1980), and Menzel and Zalta
(2014), it can be shown that At becomes derivable in the presence of such plu-
ral propositional quantifiers. I discuss this derivation in more detail in Fritz
(2023c). This result illustrates that just as in the case of standard proposi-
tional modal languages, the restrictiveness of propositionally quantified modal
languages is both a boon and a burden: it makes results like Theorem 2.5.1
possible, but also bars certain interesting arguments from being formulated.
Another instance of this important lesson will be mentioned in Section 4.
Finally, it is worth noting that a reduction of possible worlds to propositions
can also be carried out in the context of modal logics weaker than S5. However,
further complexities arise in these settings, in particular since we may no longer
be able to rely on a completeness result corresponding to Theorem 2.5.1, as
we will see in the next section. For recent discussion of such more general
reductions of possible worlds to propositions in higher-order languages, see
Dorr et al. (2021, section 1.6) and Bacon (2024, section 7.5).
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009177740 Published online by Cambridge University Press
2.6 Axiomatizability
Earlier, we noted that every NPQML is axiomatizable in the sense of being the
NPQML axiomatized by itself. This sense of axiomatizability is therefore uninter-
esting. A more interesting notion of axiomatizability is that of being recursively
enumerable, which requires being relatively well-behaved from a computa-
tional perspective: a set of formulas Λ is recursively enumerable if there is a
computer program which produces only theorems of Λ, and, for every theorem
Λ, produces it after some finite number of computational steps. For example, if
Γ is a finite set of axioms, then KΠ Γ is recursively enumerable. So, since S5π+
can be axiomatized as SΠ 5At (i.e., KΠ T5At), it is recursively enumerable. In
fact, S5π+ is computationally even better behaved, as it is decidable, which
means that there is a computer program which takes any formula φ ∈ L□ as
input, and outputs after a finite number of computational steps the answer to
the question whether φ ∈ S5π+:
42 Philosophy and Logic
This result was also established by Kaplan (1970b) and Fine (1970). Fine
notes that it follows from the quantifier-elimination argument used to prove
completeness. As shown by Ding (2021a), this argument can be extended to
show that KD45π+ is decidable as well. Fine observes that there is a sec-
ond way of proving Theorem 2.6.1, which is also used by Kaplan. It proceeds
by extending the standard translation of propositional modal logic to propo-
sitional quantifiers. The standard translation shows that propositional modal
languages can be thought of as fragments of first-order languages: worlds
become individuals, propositional variables become predicates, and modal
operators become first-order quantifiers restricted to accessible worlds. This
extends straightforwardly to propositional quantifiers, which become monadic
second-order quantifiers. The translation can therefore be defined as follows,
given a first-order variable x which serves as the world of evaluation of the rele-
vant formula, and assuming that Xp is a distinct monadic second-order variable,
for every propositional variable p:
px := Xp x
⊥x := ⊥
(φ → ψ)x := φx → ψ x
(□φ)x := ∀y(R□ xy → φy )
(∀pφ)x := ∀Xp (φx )
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009177740 Published online by Cambridge University Press
Various decidability results can be derived from this. For example, with the
fact that every normal extension of K5 is finitely axiomatizable, as shown
by Nagle and Thomason (1985), it follows that Λπ+ is decidable for every
unimodal NML Λ containing the axiom 5. The general formulation of this obser-
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009177740 Published online by Cambridge University Press
M □^p → ^□p
G1 ^□p → □^p
J1 □(□( p → □p) → p) → p
W □(□p → p) → □p
It is worth noting that K4.2W proves 4 and J1. J1 is also known as Grz; W
is also known as GL, after Gödel and Löb, as it plays an important role in
provability logic; see Boolos (1985).
There is one important group of NMLs which the results mentioned so far do
not cover, namely those (apart from S5) containing the following axiom:
This axiom enforces a weak form of linearity on relational frames. Fine (1970)
noted that the propositionally quantified unimodal logic of the singleton class
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009177740 Published online by Cambridge University Press
containing the relational frame consisting of the natural numbers under their
natural order (weak or strict) is decidable. This follows by the standard trans-
lation using the corresponding result about monadic second-order logic, which
had been shown by Büchi (1962). In Fritz (forthcoming), this observation is
extended to show the following result:
Büchi’s result was strengthened by Rabin (1969), and Fine (1970) asserts
that this can be used to establish the decidability of S4.3π+ (with S4.3 being
KT4Lem0 ). But according to Kaminski and Tiomkin (1996), this is incorrect,
as it follows from results of Shelah (1975) and Gurevich and Shelah (1983)
that S4.3π+ is in fact not recursively enumerable. In Fritz (forthcoming), this
observation is extended to show the following result, where K3 is KT4Lem0 M:
Proposition 2.6.5 For any normal unimodal logic Λ included in K3, Λπ+ is
not recursively enumerable.
Open Question 2 Are there finite sets Γ ⊆ ∆ ⊆ L□qf such that KΓπ+ is
recursively axiomatizable while K∆π+ is not?
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009177740 Published online by Cambridge University Press
This was shown by Antonelli and Thomason (2002); proofs can also be found
in Kuhn (2004) and Belardinelli et al. (2018). The result is strengthened in Fritz
46 Philosophy and Logic
(2020) to the logic of so-called products of two frames with a universal acces-
sibility relation. In contrast, it is shown in Fritz (forthcoming) that if S5 ⊗ S5 is
strengthened by the addition of the principle □p → ⊠p, the result of which is
there called a linear fusion, the resulting NML defines a class of frames whose
propositionally quantified modal logic is again decidable. In the case of episte-
mic logic, axiomatizability results have also been obtained for propositionally
quantified multimodal logics involving operators of public announcement or
common knowledge; see Belardinelli et al. (2016) and Belardinelli et al. (2018),
respectively.
Many problems concerning the axiomatizability of propositionally quan-
tified modal logics of classes of relational frames remain open. A number of
them are noted in Fritz (forthcoming, section 7), including the following (which
is only very partially addressed by the results just mentioned):
Open Question 3 Among NMLS Λ such that Λπ+ is decidable, which fusions
define classes of frames whose propositionally quantified modal logic is decid-
able?
classification:
a universal accessibility relation. This shows that SΠ 5At is S5π+; see The-
orem 2.5.1. Recall that one proof of this result proceeds by a quantifier-
elimination argument. This technique can be developed further to apply to
extensions of S5π+, to prove the following result. It follows from a more
general result of Ding (2018), using algebraic models which we consider in
Section 3.2.
Proposition 2.7.1 Every NPQML which includes S5π+ is complete with respect
to the class of relational frames it defines.
It is worth noting that some of these normal extensions of S5π+ are not of
the form Λπ+, for any normal modal logic Λ. For example, we can consistently
extend S5π+ using the claim that there is a contingent truth: ∃p( p ∧ ¬□p).
This claim is not provable in Λπ+, for any consistent NML Λ: by Makinson
(1971), every consistent NML is valid on a one-element relational frame, in
which every truth is necessary. The characterization of the extensions of S5 by
Scroggs (1951) and Gärdenfors (1973) therefore requires further elaboration to
be adapted to the propositionally quantified case. For such an elaboration, see
Ding (2018).
Using algebraic methods, Ding (2021a) has also extended the completeness
result via quantifier elimination in the other direction, of weaker NMLs, and
shown the following result:
tional frames it defines, namely, the class of relational frames with a serial,
transitive and Euclidean accessibility relation.
Proof We note that ^∀p( p → □p) is valid on R(S4M): Call a world of a rela-
tional frame with a reflexive accessibility relation final if it can only access
itself. Consider any relational frame on which S4M is valid. By standard argu-
ments, it can be shown that the accessibility relation of such a frame is reflexive,
transitive, and relates every world to some final world; for details, see Cha-
grov and Zakharyaschev (1997, p. 82). From the last condition, the validity of
^∀p( p → □p) is immediate.
K3.1 is an extension of S4M, so it follows that K3.1π+ contains ^∀p( p →
□p) as well. In Section 3.5, we will be able to show that we cannot derive
this formula in KΠ 3.1BcAt; see Proposition 3.5.8. So KΠ 3.1BcAt is incom-
plete with respect to R(K3.1) (the class of relational frames it defines). And
since K3.1 is a normal extension of S4.3.1, it follows by Proposition 2.6.4 that
K3.1π+ is decidable. □
In light of this result, it is interesting to ask how one might provide perspic-
uous axiomatizations of recursively enumerable logics of the form Λπ+ for
NMLs Λ. As noted by Ding (2021a, p. 1196) the syntactic reductions involved
in quantifier-elimination arguments require very strong modal logics, and it
is not to be expected that this technique is applicable to all decidable logics.
Fortunately, another approach is available, which is the construction of canon-
ical models, used by Fine (1970) to establish the completeness of SΠ 5At with
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009177740 Published online by Cambridge University Press
respect to U. In unpublished work, Yipu Li and Yifeng Ding (pc) use this tech-
nique to provide a complete axiomatization of the propositionally quantified
modal logic of any class of relational frames which has finite diversity and
which is defined by a set of Sahlqvist formulas Γ, in terms of Γ, Bc, At, and
one further axiom.
There is an important observation to be drawn from the discussion in this
section and the previous one: for many NMLs Λ, it is highly ambiguous to
speak of “propositionally quantified Λ”. Taking the case of S4, namely, KT4,
as an example, we must distinguish between the weaker SΠ 4 and the stronger
S4π+. Since the former is recursively enumerable and the latter is not, there
are infinitely many NPQMLs linearly ordered in strength between these two log-
ics. All of these logics will be conservative extensions of S4, and could in this
sense be counted as “propositionally quantified S4”. In fact, there is even a
decidable NPQML extending S4π+ which is a conservative extension of S4. This
follows via the standard translation from the completeness of S4 with respect
to a single countable reflexive and transitive tree – see Blackburn et al. (2001,
Propositional Quantifiers 49
Definition 2.8.1 For any relational frame F = ⟨W, R□ ⟩□∈O and world w ∈ W,
the point-generated subframe Fw is ⟨W′, R□′ ⟩□∈O , where
F, w, a ⊩ φ iff Fw, w, a′ ⊩ φ,
whose accessibility relations are universal, with F containing two worlds and
F ′ containing one world. There is just one function mapping the worlds of F to
the world of F ′, and it is a surjective bounded morphism. Consequently, every
propositional modal formula valid on F is valid on F ′. It is easy to see that this
does not hold for formulas with propositional quantifiers: ∃p( p ∧ ¬□p) is valid
on F but not valid on F ′.
The case of bounded morphisms illustrates that propositional modal lan-
guages become more expressive when propositional quantifiers are added. This
idea can be made more precise by considering the notion of a modally definable
class of frames: a class of relational frames C is definable in a given language L
if there is a set of formulas Γ of L which defines C. A well-known case of a class
of relational frames which is not definable in L□qf is the class of frames in which
the accessibility relation is irreflexive. This is easy to define with propositional
quantifiers, using the formula ∃p(□p ∧ ¬p). Yet, even with propositional quan-
tifiers, not every class of frames is definable. This follows already by cardinality
Propositional Quantifiers 51
This puts various constraints on the set of propositions which fall under the
modality □ at any given world. For example, for every world w, the set of
propositions which include R□ (w) is closed under conjunction (i.e., intersec-
tion). The resulting constraints ensure that the logic of any class of relational
frames is normal.
However, in various applications, normality is undesired. For example, you
might endorse an epistemic theory on which knowledge is not closed under
conjunction, so that an agent might know p and know q, without knowing p∧q.
This is an instance of a much-debated principle of closure in epistemology; see
Hawthorne (2004) for in-depth discussion. Similarly, a deontic theory might
deny that an obligation to bring p about entails an obligation to bring p ∨ q
about, which is another entailment licensed by normal modal logics. A well-
known example for this is due to Ross (1941), who notes that it does not seem
to follow from an agent being obliged to post a letter that the agent is obliged
to post it or burn it.
To obtain models which don’t underwrite these inferences of normal modal
logics, we should allow for the set of propositions which are determined to fall
under □ not to obey the relevant closure conditions. The simplest way to intro-
duce this flexibility is to specify directly as part of the model which propositions
fall under □ at a given world. So, instead of an accessibility relation R□ , we may
simply use a function N□ which maps every world w to the set of propositions
which fall under □ at w. For historical reasons to do with connections to topol-
ogy, to which we return shortly, such a function N□ is known as a neighborhood
function, from which the terminology of neighborhood frames is derived.
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009177740 Published online by Cambridge University Press
based on possible worlds, such as those of Stalnaker (1968) and Lewis (1973).
For discussions of propositional quantifiers in such a context, see Lewis (1973,
pp. 45–47) and Besnard et al. (1997).
Having motivated neighborhood frames conceptually, we define them as
follows:
We write N for the class of all neighborhood frames (for a given modal
signature).
Although neighborhood frames do not enforce the principles of normality,
they do impose constraints which go beyond those captured by classicality
as defined in Section 2.2. It turns out that the principal constraint imposed
on the logic of any class of neighborhood frames is that if it is valid on the
class that two formulas are materially equivalent, then these formulas can be
replaced in any context without changing the validity of the surrounding for-
mula. Adapting terminology from algebra, we call this feature congruentiality.
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009177740 Published online by Cambridge University Press
(Recall from Section 2.2 that “classical” is sometimes used instead of “congru-
ential”, a usage which we don’t follow since we require the label “classical” for
a weaker condition.) Formally, this constraint can be formulated as follows:
Definition 3.1.4 For any set Γ ⊆ Lqf σ , the CML axiomatized by Γ, written Eσ Γ,
is the smallest CML including Γ. For any set Γ ⊆ Lσ , the CPQML axiomatized
by Γ, written EσΠ Γ, is the smallest CPQML including Γ.
Neighborhood frames relate to CMLs in very much the same way in which
relational frames relate to NMLs. We have already seen Proposition 3.1.3, which
corresponds to Proposition 2.3.4. E is also complete with respect to N, just as
K is complete with respect to R. Furthermore, Gerson (1975b) showed that
there are CMLs which are not sound and complete with respect to any class of
neighborhood frames, just as there are NMLs which are not sound and complete
with respect to any class of relational frames.
Turning to propositionally quantified modal logics, the corresponding com-
pleteness question with respect to arbitrary neighborhood frames appears not to
have been considered. Some basic observations are easily made. We start with
the two schematic principles discussed in Section 2.4. First, even though the
domain of propositional quantification is still independent of the world of eval-
uation, the Barcan formula Bc can be falsified on neighborhood frames. In fact,
the same applies to instances of the converse Barcan formula, which are deriv-
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009177740 Published online by Cambridge University Press
Proof Let W = {0, 1}. For each formula, we construct a neighborhood frame
on W on which it can be falsified. For (i), interpret □ as negation, that is, let
N□ (w) = {x ⊆ W : w < x} for all w ∈ W; then (i) is false in every world. For
(ii), let N□ (0) = {∅, W} and N□ (1) = {{0}, {1}}; then (ii) is false in 1. For (iii),
let N□ (w) = ∅ for all w ∈ W; then (iii) is false in every world. □
Propositional Quantifiers 55
With none of the formulas of Section 2.4 being valid on all neighborhood
frames, it is natural to wonder whether EΠ is complete with respect to N. But
this can easily be shown not to be the case. First, □⊤ → At is valid on N for
every unary modality □: if □⊤ is true in a world w, then {w} again witnesses the
truth of At. Second, we will see in the next sections that there are extensions
of EΠ which are normal, and therefore contain □⊤, but which do not contain
At. Any formula of the form □⊤ → At is therefore an example of the incom-
pleteness of EΠ with respect to N. In fact, L□ (N) is not recursively enumerable.
We return to this observation at the end of this section, when we will be able
to derive it from a corresponding result, due to Kremer (1997c), for a more
restricted class of frames which we will encounter shortly.
So far, we have considered two ways in which neighborhood frames offer
greater flexibility than relational frames: First, they weaken the logical con-
straints, allowing us to extend our scope from normal to congruential modal
logics. Second, they very naturally extend to polyadic modal operators. There
is a third way in which neighborhood frames offer greater flexibility than
relational frames: there are normal unimodal logics which are not sound and
complete with respect to any class of relational frames, but sound and complete
with respect to classes of neighborhood frames. This was shown by Gerson
(1975a, 1976). Nevertheless, there are also normal unimodal logics which are
not sound and complete with respect to any classes of neighborhood frames,
which was also shown by Gerson (1975b).
Neighborhood frames whose logic is normal are easily characterized using
the standard order-theoretic notion of a filter on a powerset. A set F ⊆ P(W )
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009177740 Published online by Cambridge University Press
For any unary modal signature O, let a neighborhood frame F = ⟨W, N□ ⟩□∈O
be a filter neighborhood frame just in case for every □ ∈ O and w ∈ W, N□ (w)
is a filter. Let F be the class of filter neighborhood frames.
Proposition 3.1.6 A neighborhood frame F = ⟨W, N□ ⟩□∈O for a unary modal
signature O is a filter neighborhood frame if and only if the LO
qf
-formulas valid
on F form an NML (in which case the LO -formulas valid on F form an NPQML).
Proof The left-to-right direction follows from the fact that if F is filter neigh-
borhood frame, then W ∈ N□ (w), and (W \x) ∪ y, x ∈ N□ (w) only if y ∈ N□ (w),
for all w ∈ W and x, y ⊆ W. The right-to-left direction follows from the fact
that every NML contains □⊤, (□p ∧ □q) → □( p ∧ q), and □p → □( p ∨ q). □
56 Philosophy and Logic
Proof Let F be the neighborhood frame ⟨N, N□ ⟩, where for each n ∈ N, N□ (n)
is the set of cofinite subsets of N, that is, the set of x ⊆ N such that N\x is finite.
Since the cofinite sets form a filter, F is a filter neighborhood frame.
J□p → pKF,a is cofinite, whether a( p) is cofinite or not. So F ⊩ ∀p□(□p →
p). However, if a( p) = N\{n}, then F, n, a ⊮ □p → p. So, F ⊩ ¬∀p(□p → p),
whence F ⊩ ¬□∀p(□p → p). Thus F ⊮ ∀p□(□p → p) → □∀p(□p → p). □
(i) W ∈ T and ∅ ∈ T.
∩
(ii) If X is a finite subset of T, then X ∈ T.
∪
(iii) If X is a subset of T, then X ∈ T.
Propositional Quantifiers 57
(In topological terms, and adopting the algebraic perspective which we will
consider in the next section, this means that □ is interpreted as the interior
operation of the topological space.) Let T be the class of neighborhood frames
determined by topological spaces. All such frames are filter neighborhood
frames; moreover, the modal logic of T turns out to be exactly S4.
Kremer (1997c) introduces the label S4πt for L□ (T). His results entail the
following proper inclusions:
This is the result we can use to establish that L(N) is not recursively axioma-
tizable, since L(T) is reducible to L(N), in the sense that there is a computable
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009177740 Published online by Cambridge University Press
function f : L → L such that φ ∈ L(T) if and only if f (φ) ∈ L(N). In fact, L(T)
is reducible to the logic of any class of neighborhood frames which includes
all (neighborhood frames determined by) topological spaces. The class of filter
neighborhood frames F is another example of such a class we have encountered.
The reduction itself is easy to define. First, we introduce a formula which
encodes that the axiomatic principles of S4 hold on any interpretation of the
proposition letters:
(□φ)∗ := □(ρS4 → φ∗ )
58 Philosophy and Logic
W′ = JρS4 KF
N′(w) = {x ∩ W′ : x ∈ N(w)}
The central claims needed to establish the reduction are collected in the
following lemma:
Given our observations here, a positive answer will settle the matter as well
for L(N) and L(F). If the answer is negative, separate analogous questions arise
for these logics.
tain agent), then the relevant function ∗□ can be understood as mapping every
proposition x to the proposition that x is known.
A neighborhood frame can therefore equivalently be presented as a structure
⟨W, ∗◦ ⟩◦∈O , where W is a set and ∗◦ is a function from P(W )ρ(◦) to P(W ), for
all ◦ ∈ O. On this presentation, the evaluation clause for modal operators turns
into the following condition:
JpKF,a = a( p)
J⊥KF,a = ∅
Jφ → ψKF,a = (W \JφKF,a ) ∪ JψKF,a
We focus just on the quantifier-free setting for the moment, and get back to
quantifiers shortly.
We have arrived at an algebraic perspective on neighborhood frames. (For
more on algebraic approaches to logic, see Halmos and Givant (1998), Dunn
and Hardegree (2001), and Rasiowa and Sikorski (1963).) Let a powerset alge-
bra be a structure A = ⟨A, 0, ⊐⟩, where A = P(W ) for some set W, 0 = ∅, and
x ⊐ y = (W \x) ∪ y for all x, y ⊆ W. (Here, “0” need not stand for the number
zero; context will always disambiguate between the algebraic and numerical
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009177740 Published online by Cambridge University Press
For a proof, and rigorous definition of the relevant algebraic concepts, see
a textbook treating Boolean algebras, such as Davey and Priestley (2002) and
Givant and Halmos (2009). Here, we will have to limit ourselves to a brief dis-
cussion of these concepts. First, we can think of a Boolean algebra as an algebra
Propositional Quantifiers 61
JpKA,a = a( p)
J⊥KA,a = 0
Jφ → ψKA,a = JφKA,a ⊐ JψKA,a
J◦φ1 . . . φn KA,a = ∗◦ (⟨Jφ1 KA,a, . . . , Jφn KA,a ⟩)
The label of “Boolean algebra expansion” is taken from Ding and Holliday
(2020). We abbreviate it using “BAE” in the following. As in the case of neigh-
borhood frames, the logic of every class of BAEs is a CML. However, unlike the
case of neighborhood frames, the converse holds for BAEs: every CML is the
logic of some class of BAEs. This is straightforward to show, using the standard
construction of a Lindenbaum–Tarski algebra. In the terminology of Chagrov
and Zakharyaschev (1997), BAEs therefore provide an “adequate” model theory
of CMLs.
We are finally ready to return to languages involving propositional quan-
tifiers. First, note that the evaluation clause of propositional quantifiers in
neighborhood frames can equivalently be formulated by stating that the propo-
sition expressed by a universal propositional quantification is the conjunction
(intersection) of its instances:
∩
J∀pφKF,a = x∈P (W ) JφKF,a[x/p]
In a powerset P(W ), the intersection of any set X ⊆ P(W ) is its greatest lower
bound (under the entailment order ≤). This fits well with the common idea that
universal quantifications are conjunctions of their instances, and the fact that
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009177740 Published online by Cambridge University Press
the binary conjunction operation ⊓ in Boolean algebras maps any two elements
to their greatest lower bound. This suggests that algebraically, propositional
quantifiers can be interpreted using greatest lower bounds as well. In the fol-
∧
lowing, we notate greatest lower bounds using . We must, of course, ensure
that the relevant greatest lower bounds always exist. The simplest way to do
so is to assume that the algebra is complete, in the sense defined earlier. (We
consider a weaker, but more complicated, requirement in Section 3.4.) With
this, Definition 3.2.2 is straightforwardly extended to propositional quantifiers,
at least for complete BAEs, which we call CBAEs. (We extend properties of Bool-
ean algebras to BAEs in the obvious way; for example, a BAE is complete just in
case its underlying Boolean algebra is complete.)
Proof The argument is routine except for the case of UG. For this case, we
∧
appeal to the following law of complete Boolean algebras: y∈Y x ⊐ y = x ⊐
∧
Y. This follows from the infinite distributivity laws of complete Boolean
algebras; see (the dual of) Givant and Halmos (2009, p. 47, lemma 3). □
CBAEs can be shown using two results of Ding (2021a,b). First, Ding (2021b,
p. 53, theorem 3.2.16) shows that there are instances of the following schema
which are not derivable in KΠ D45:
(We return to the kinds of models used in this proof in Section 3.6.) Second,
Ding (2021a, p. 1162, theorem 3.1) shows that all instances of 4∀ are valid on
the class of CBAEs defined by KΠ D45. (Moreover, Ding (2021a) shows that
KΠ D4∀ 5 is sound and complete with respect to this class.) Therefore:
Most of the existing work on CBAEs is concerned with normal logics, despite
the fact that CBAEs constitute a natural model theory for the wider class
of congruential logics. As in the case of neighborhood frames, BAEs whose
64 Philosophy and Logic
(Normality) ∗□ 1 = 1
(Additivity) For all elements x and y, ∗□ (x ⊓ y) = (∗□ x ⊓ ∗□ y).
Proof The left-to-right direction follows from the fact that if A satisfies nor-
mality and additivity, then its validities contain □⊤ (and so the LO
qf
-formulas
valid on A are closed under necessitation), and the axiom K□ . The right-to-left
direction follows from the fact that every NML contains □⊤ and □( p ∧ q) ↔
(□p ∧ □q). □
In the context of CBAEs, it is natural to consider a generalization of additivity
to arbitrary greatest lower bounds:
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009177740 Published online by Cambridge University Press
∧ ∧
(Complete Additivity) For every set of elements X, ∗□ X= {∗□ x : x ∈ X}.
In certain cases, this stronger condition leads to additional validities. This can
be illustrated using results by Ding (2021a), who shows that KΠ D4∀ 5 – which
is complete with respect the class of CBAEs it defines – is incomplete if this
class is restricted to CBAEs whose modal operation is completely additive. This
is witnessed by certain instances of the Barcan formula. With Bc, 4 ∀ becomes
derivable; in fact, Ding shows:
Ding also considers At, and shows that At becomes valid if, in addition to
complete additivity, we restrict ourselves to atomic CBAEs. Such CBAEs are sim-
ply relational frames, algebraically presented. Consequently, Proposition 2.7.2
shows the soundness and completeness of KΠ D45BcAt with respect to the
Propositional Quantifiers 65
Definition 3.2.8 A Henle algebra is a BAE ⟨A, 0, ⊐, ∗□ ⟩ such that for all x ∈ A:
1
if x = 1
∗□ (x) =
0 otherwise
Complete and atomic Henle algebras are simply relational frames with a uni-
versal accessibility relation, algebraically presented. We therefore know from
Theorem 2.5.1 that At is valid on such Henle algebras. In fact, we know that the
logic of such Henle algebras is exactly SΠ 5At. But what happens in nonatomic
complete Henle algebras? Bull (1969, p. 260) observed that At is not valid on
any complete Henle algebra which is not atomic. However, it is easy to see
that the axioms T and 5 are valid on all complete Henle algebras, from which
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009177740 Published online by Cambridge University Press
This result, together with the completeness of SΠ 5At with respect to com-
plete atomic Henle algebras, suggests two very natural conjectures: first, that
completeness is preserved when At is removed and nonatomic algebras are
admitted, and second, that completeness is preserved when At is replaced by
its negation ¬At, and only atomless algebras are considered. These very natural
conjectures were only recently confirmed by Holliday (2019), who established
the following companions to Theorem 2.5.1:
The results of Ding and Holliday concern two very strong NMLs, namely
KD45 and S5. This is no accident, since the proof methods used by both authors
heavily depend on the quantifier elimination technique of Kaplan (1970b) and
Fine (1970). Fine had already extended these methods to SΠ 5, which he used to
establish the decidability of this logic. These methods also allow Ding (2021a)
to establish decidability for all of the particular extensions of KΠ D45 discussed
by him. However, it is far from clear that these quantifier elimination results
can be extended to weaker NMLs. Consequently, many open questions remain,
many of which will likely require very different techniques. A basic example
is the following:
Depending on the answer to the this question, many variants and further
questions arise. For example, if the answer to this question is positive, is EΠ
complete with respect to the class of all CBAEs? Is the answer the same if we
consider unary modal signatures, and CBAEs whose modal functions satisfy nor-
mality and (complete) additivity? Can the logic of such restricted classes of
CBAEs be completely axiomatized using KΠ ? Are the answers to any of these
questions dependent on the modal signature? For further discussion of open
questions, see Holliday (2019) and Ding (2021a).
Before moving on to another topic, it is worth noting an alternative approach
to CBAEs. Recall how neighborhood frames can be considered as the special case
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009177740 Published online by Cambridge University Press
whose modal functions satisfy normality and additivity. (Along with neigh-
borhood frames, these models therefore exemplify the earlier claim that the
model-theoretic ideas of possible worlds and accessibility relations are entirely
separable.) Such a possibility semantics for propositional modal languages
was proposed by Humberstone (1981); the general theory and connection to
algebraic models is developed in detail by Holliday (forthcoming). These mod-
els can be extended to provide an elegant model theory for propositionally
quantified modal logic; see Holliday (2021, section 5.1) for an illustration.
Pointed frames are often not considered since many of the formal results
on relational and neighborhood frames transfer straightforwardly to pointed
frames. But there are many applications of modal logics in which the addi-
tional flexibility of pointed frames is important. An example from philosophy
is the logic of indexical operators, such as “now” and “actually”, investigated
by Kaplan (1989 [1977]) and Crossley and Humberstone (1977). An example
from mathematics is the QNML GLS, which Solovay (1976) showed to capture
the notion of provability from the axioms of Peano arithmetic according to true
arithmetic, on the provability interpretation of modal logic; this is discussed in
more detail in Boolos (1985). In the context of neighborhood frames, pointed
frames also allow the construction of model theories of some lesser known
Lewis systems, including S2 and S3, since the models of Kripke (1965) for
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009177740 Published online by Cambridge University Press
From this definition, it is easy to see that the notion of a BAE can be
understood as the special case of a BAE-matrix with the singleton filter {1}.
Propositional Quantifiers 71
Lσ (C) is a QCPQML.
Proof The crucial case of UG is as in the proof of Proposition 3.2.4, using the
fact that principal filters are closed under arbitrary greatest lower bounds. □
Along the lines of Proposition 3.2.6, it is easy to conclude from this that if
the modal functions of a class of CBAE-matrices with principal filters satisfy
normality and additivity, the logic of the class is a QNPQML.
of elements JφKa[x/p] , for arbitrary elements x, has a greatest lower bound. This
motivates the following definition:
1 if JφKA,a[x/p] = 1 for all x ∈ A
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009177740 Published online by Cambridge University Press
J[∀p]φKA,a =
0 otherwise
With Proposition 3.2.6, we get as an immediate corollary the same claim for
NPQMLs and QBAEs satisfying normality and additivity:
Corollary 3.4.4 Any NPQML is Lσ (C) for some class C of QBAEs satisfying
normality and additivity.
tation of J·K · given by Definitions 2.3.1 and 3.1.1. Validity is defined by letting
F ⊩ φ if F, w, a ⊩ φ for all w ∈ W and a : Φ → A.
Along the lines discussed in Section 3.2, this means that the evaluation clause
for propositional quantifiers is the following:
Propositional Quantifiers 75
∩
J∀pφKF,a = x∈A JφKF,a[x/p]
But note that the evaluation clause on the algebraic side interprets proposi-
tional quantifiers using greatest lower bounds. Transferring this condition to
the setting of general frames, we obtain the following condition:
∧
J∀pφKF,a = x∈A JφKF,a[x/p]
The same is not possible for quantifiers: The interpretation of a quantified for-
mula depends on the domain of quantification, namely, the very field of sets
we are trying to construct. Consequently, we cannot construct a quantifiable
general frame simply by starting from any set and closing it to include all
the “required” propositions: which propositions are required depends on the
algebra of propositions, which is just being determined.
How do QGNFs relate to QBAEs? It is easy to see that if a general neighborhood
frame is quantifiable, then the BAE to which it corresponds is quantifiable as
∩
well. This follows from the fact that for any field of sets A and X ⊆ A, if X ∈
∩
A, then X is the greatest lower bound of X in A. This is a useful observation
since it allows us to construct further examples of BAEs which are quantifiable
without being complete: Recall that the examples of such BAEs arising from
Proposition 3.4.3 are all atomless. In contrast, many useful examples of general
relational and neighborhood frames are based on incomplete atomic fields of
sets, and some of them are easily shown to be quantifiable. The QGRF S defined
in the following discussion is an example.
Every QGNF corresponds to a QBAE, but the converse is not the case. Indeed,
there is a CBAE which does not correspond to any QGNF. Let A be a BAE for
the unary unimodal signature based on a complete atomless field of sets A ⊆
P(W ), with a function ∗□ defined as in the proof of Proposition 3.3.5, where
U = {x ∈ A : a ∈ x} for some a ∈ W. (Since A is atomless, U is a nonprincipal
ultrafilter.) Let F be the general neighborhood frame corresponding to A, based
∩
on W and A. Then {J□pKF,a[x/p] : x ∈ A} is {a}. Since A is atomless, {a} < A.
Thus, F is not quantifiable: the intersection needed to interpret ∀p□p is not an
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009177740 Published online by Cambridge University Press
Proposition 3.5.3 For any class C of QGRF/ QGNF, Lσ (C) is an NPQML/ CPQML.
Proof Routine except for the case of UI, which follows using the fact that
JφKF,a is guaranteed to be a member of A. □
General frames have mostly been considered in the form of general relational
frames. It is easy to see that all instances of the Barcan formula Bc are valid on
QGRFs. In contrast, At is not valid on all QGRFs. This follows from the following
completeness results of Bull (1969) (the last two) and Fine (1970), together with
Proposition 3.2.9 on the underivability of At:
Theorem 3.5.4 KΠ Bc, KΠ TBc, SΠ 4Bc and SΠ 5 are complete with respect to
the classes of QGRFs they define.
Propositional Quantifiers 77
We can now establish our first claim, that requiring the underlying frame to
validate certain principles can be more demanding than requiring the general
frame itself to validate these principles, and that this can be reflected in the
validities on the relevant class of structures:
Proof A routine argument shows that in every relational frame validating S4M,
every world w can access a world v such that R□ (v) = {v}; this ensures the
validity of ^∀p( p → □p). However, S, which we have just shown to validate
S4M, does not validate ^∀p( p → □p), since it contains no world at which all
propositions are settled. □
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009177740 Published online by Cambridge University Press
Next, we can show that the second reading of Fine’s claim concerning
canonical NMLs is incorrect:
We can also use S to prove an assertion used in the proof of Proposition 2.7.3:
Propositional Quantifiers 79
Proof Given the preceding results, it suffices to show that KΠ 3.1BcAt is valid
on S. The only interesting case is J1, that is, the formula □(□( p → □p) →
p) → p. Arguing contrapositively, consider any world n in which p is false, on
a given variable assignment a. There are two options: either p is settled as false
at some m ≥ n, or p settles as true at m + 1 for some m ≥ n at which p is false.
(For brevity, we conflate p and a( p) in laying out the argument.) In both cases,
it is easy to see that □( p → □p) → p is false in m, whence □(□( p → □p) → p)
is false in n. Therefore J1 is valid on S. □
in which case he would plausibly not have existed, in the sense that there would
not have been anything identical to him. In this sense, then, there is something
which might have failed to exist.
Some philosophers have not only endorsed contingentism, but also argued
that propositions are existentially dependent on the individuals they are about;
see, for example, Prior (1967), Fine (1977), Adams (1981), and Stalnaker
(2012). For example, they would argue that the proposition that Ludwig Witt-
genstein is a philosopher existentially depends on Ludwig Wittgenstein: had
there not been Ludwig Wittgenstein, there would also not have been the
proposition that Ludwig Wittgenstein is a philosopher. Similarly, had Lud-
wig Wittgenstein been the father of a daughter, the proposition that she is
his daughter would have existed, but since she does not actually exist, nei-
ther does the proposition that she is his daughter. Adapting Williamson’s
terminology, Fritz (2016) calls the view that propositional existence is con-
tingent propositional contingentism, and the opposing view propositional
necessitism. Contingentism has therefore been argued to lead to proposi-
tional contingentism. This argument was already made by Prior, and Prior
accommodated this propositional contingentism in his propositionally quan-
tified modal logic; this led to his System Q in Prior (1957, chapter 5).
Prior assumed that nonexistent propositions are neither true nor false, which
led to a complicated and, from a modern perspective, unusual system. In
the following, we will consider some less intrusive modifications to the
models considered so far which nevertheless make room for propositional
contingentism.
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009177740 Published online by Cambridge University Press
Proof Routine. For the validity of UI, we use the fact that JφKF,a ∈ D(w) for
every formula φ ∈ Lσ , w ∈ W, and a : Φ → D(w). □
With this concrete way of constructing variable domain frames, we can easily
show that both the Barcan formula Bc and its converse have instances which
are not valid on VDRFs. This is expected, as these formulas are hallmarks of
(propositional) necessitism; see Williamson (2013, chapter 2) for discussion.
To state these observations, note that on frames with a universal accessibility
relation, the following definition allows us to state in the object language that
the proposition expressed by any given formula φ exists, in the sense of being
in the domain of the world of evaluation:
Propositional Quantifiers 83
Eφ := ∃q□(q ↔ φ),
Proposition 3.6.5 The following instances of Bc and its converse are not valid
on VDRFs:
such a predicate E can be defined in the context of VDRFs with a single univer-
sal accessibility relation. The restricted version of UI can then be formulated
as follows:
The matter is more difficult in the context of VDRFs generally, or even VDNFs,
where the definition of Eφ is not guaranteed to express existence of the relevant
proposition. In these contexts, one might instead adopt the approach of Kripke
(1963b), and use an axiom schema consisting of certain closed instances of UI:
On this approach, it is a substantial claim that there are any models at all. For
a given relational frame, we cannot simply assume that there is any relation ⊩
of truth satisfying the desired truth conditions. In certain cases, it can be shown
that there is such a relation; for example, Kripke (1976, p. 332) notes that a
suitable relation ⊩ can always be found if all operators are truth-functional.
This can be shown using the eliminability of propositional quantifiers in such a
setting, discussed in Section 1.3. In the context of his models based on neigh-
borhood frames, Gabbay (1971) establishes completeness results, which entail,
for every formula φ which is not derivable in the relevant proof system, the
existence of a model in which φ is falsified. It is important to note, however, that
without an independent proof of the consistency of the relevant proof system,
such a completeness result does not entail the existence of any model.
Propositional Quantifiers 87
v(⊥) = 0
v(φ → ψ) = 1 if and only if v(φ) = 1 only if v(ψ) = 1
v(□φ) = 1 if and only if v(φ[ψ1 /p1, . . . , ψn /pn ]) = 1 for all ψ1, . . . , ψn ∈ L□
free for p1, . . . , pn , respectively, in φ
v(∀pφ) = 1 if and only if v(φ[ψ/p]) = 1 for all ψ ∈ L□ free for p in φ
More generally, one might ask whether every mapping from p ∈ Φ to {0, 1} has
a unique extension to a substitutional valuation of L□qf . In the propositionally
quantified case, all of these questions remain open:
Bacon and Fine (forthcoming) consider a version of this question, and con-
jecture that there is a substitutional valuation of L□ . It is worth noting that
Bacon and Fine’s definition of a substitutional valuation is slightly different,
since their language contains both propositional variables and nonlogical con-
stants, and their conditions for the modal operator and quantifier refer to closed
substitution instances only. Moreover, while their constraints on quantified
statements match the definition given here insofar as it considers substitutions
of the bound propositional variable, their constraints on modal statements of
the form □φ vary not the interpretation of free variables in φ but of the propo-
sitional constants in φ. This leads to substantial differences, even within the
shared fragment of the language not involving any propositional constants.
For example, in Bacon and Fine’s setting, a substitutional valuation must map
( p → □p) ∧ (¬p → □¬p) to 1 (taking p to be a variable, as before), whereas
on the definition presented here, it must map this formula to 0. It is also worth
noting that it is not immediately obvious whether substitutional valuations as
defined earlier verify all classical principles, that is, all theorems of CΠ . In
contrast, in the quantifier-free case, it follows from results of McKinsey (1945)
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009177740 Published online by Cambridge University Press
that any substitutional valuation verifies every theorem of S4M. If the answer
to the first part of Question 8 is positive, there are therefore natural follow-up
questions concerning which logical principles are guaranteed to be verified by
substitutional valuations, and whether there are substitutional valuations which
verify, for example, every theorem of SΠ 4M.
4 Conclusion
We have seen that propositional quantifiers constitute a natural extension of
a number of logical systems, in particular propositional modal logics. The
resulting propositionally quantified modal logics can be interpreted over many
well-known classes of models for propositional modal logics. Many of the
standard questions concerning propositional modal logics arise as well for
propositionally quantified modal logics. Some results extend from the stand-
ard quantifier-free setting to the setting with propositional quantifiers, but often
they do not do so, or do not do so without nontrivial adjustments. Over many
Propositional Quantifiers 89
(γ) Eδ → ¬δ
We assumed Eδ, so ¬δ follows, but this contradicts the assumption. So, ¬δ. But
then there is some p such that Ep and p. What is this p? It cannot be δ, since
¬δ. But we have only assumed that Epimenides says δ. We seem to be forced,
paradoxically, to the conclusion that there is something else which Epimenides
says, even if he only utters “∀p(Ep → ¬p)”:
(β) ¬∀q(Eq ↔ q = δ)
As the present sketch suggests, this argument can be carried out in a relatively
weak propositionally quantified modal logic, using plausible deductive princi-
ples for = and no particular assumptions about E. This was well known to the
founders of symbolic logic, and a derivation along these lines can be found, for
example, in Hilbert and Ackermann (1938, pp. 114–121). The paradox, in its
formalization using propositional quantifiers, was also discussed at length by
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009177740 Published online by Cambridge University Press
model theory. The issue has recently received renewed attention; see Bacon
et al. (2016), Holliday and Litak (2018), Bacon and Uzquiano (2018), Ding
and Holliday (2020), and Uzquiano (2021).
Returning to non-Boolean models, such models are especially interesting for
exploring views on which propositions are very finely individuated. However,
we need to be cautious in doing so, for two reasons: First, once we reject the
identities of Boolean algebras, we must reconsider the interdefinability of the
operators ⊤, ⊥, ¬, ∧, ∨, → and ↔. For example, on a fine-grained conception
of propositions, the formulas ( p → ⊥) → q and (q → ⊥) → p may not always
express the same proposition (on a given interpretation of p and q). In such a
situation, it is not clear that we can use (φ → ⊥) → ψ to abbreviate φ ∨ ψ: the
former may simply fail to express disjunction. In fact, in such a setting, it is not
clear that we can make any such abbreviations. We may then have to take all
of the operators as primitive.
Second, the restrictiveness of languages like Lσ involving only propositional
quantifiers may make fine-grained theories of propositions more plausible than
they are. This is because prima facie plausible principles of fine individuation
of propositions can be shown to be inconsistent using higher-order quantifiers,
by an argument due to Russell (1903, appendix B) and Myhill (1958). In a
higher-order language, using X and Y as variables which take the position of
unary sentential operators, a natural version of the idea that propositions are
structured leads to the following principle:
∀X ∀Y ∀p(Xp = Yp → X = Y )
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009177740 Published online by Cambridge University Press
(RI) p = p
(LL) p = q → (φ → φ[q/p]), whenever q is free for p in φ
For any modal signature σ = ⟨O, ρ⟩ which includes the binary identity con-
nective =, let Iσ be CΠ
σ RILL, the classical propositionally quantified modal
Blackburn, Patrick. Maarten de Rijke, and Yde Venema. Modal Logic, vol-
ume 53 of Cambridge Tracts in Theoretical Computer Science. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2001.
Blackburn, Patrick. Torben Braüner, and Julie Lundbak Kofod. Remarks on
hybrid modal logic with propositional quantifiers. In Peter Hasle, David
Jakobsen, and Peter Øhrstrøm, editors, The Metaphysics of Time: Themes
from Prior, pages 401–426. Aalborg: Aalborg Universitetsforlag, 2020.
Boolos, George. To be is to be a value of a variable (or to be some values of
some variables). The Journal of Philosophy, 81:430–449, 1984.
Boolos, George. The Logic of Provability. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1985.
Bradfield, Julian. and Colin Stirling. Modal µ-calculi. In Patrick Blackburn,
Johan van Benthem, and Frank Wolter, editors, Handbook of Modal Logic,
pages 721–756. Amsterdam: Elsevier, 2007.
Brentano, Franz. The True and the Evident. London: Routledge and Kegan
Paul, 1966.
Büchi, J. Richard. On a decision method in restricted second order arithmetic.
In Ernest Nagel, Patrick Suppes, and Alfred Tarski, editors, Logic, Meth-
odology and Philosophy of Science: Proceedings of the 1960 International
Congress, pages 1–11. Redwood City, CA: Stanford University Press, 1962.
Bull, R. A. On possible worlds in propositional calculi. Theoria, 3:171–182,
1968.
Bull, R. A. On modal logics with propositional quantifiers. The Journal of
Symbolic Logic, 34:257–263, 1969.
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009177740 Published online by Cambridge University Press
Fine, Kit. For some proposition and so many possible worlds. PhD thesis,
University of Warwick, 1969.
Fine, Kit. Propositional quantifiers in modal logic. Theoria, 36:336–346,
1970.
Fine, Kit. In so many possible worlds. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic,
13:516–520, 1972.
Fine, Kit. An incomplete logic containing S4. Theoria, 40:23–29, 1974.
Fine, Kit. Properties, propositions and sets. Journal of Philosophical Logic,
6:135–191, 1977.
Fine, Kit. Failures of the interpolation lemma in quantified modal logic. The
Journal of Symbolic Logic, 44:201–206, 1979.
Fine, Kit. First-order modal theories II – Propositions. Studia Logica, 39:159–
202, 1980.
Fine, Kit. The permutation principle in quantificational logic. Journal of
Philosophical Logic, 12:33–37, 1983.
Fitch, Frederic B. A logical analysis of some value concepts. The Journal of
Symbolic Logic, 28:135–142, 1963. Reprinted in Salerno (2009).
Fitting, Melvin. Interpolation for first-order S5. The Journal of Symbolic Logic,
67:621–634, 2002.
Frege, Gottlob. Begriffsschrift, eine der arithmetischen nachgebildete Formel-
sprache des reinen Denkens. Halle a. S.: Louis Nebert, 1879.
Frege, Gottlob. Über Begriff und Gegenstand. Vierteljahresschrift für wis-
senschaftliche Philosophie, 16:192–205, 1892.
Frege, Gottlob. Posthumous Writings. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1979. Edited
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009177740 Published online by Cambridge University Press
Grover, Dorothy L., Joseph L. Camp, Jr., and Nuel D. Belnap, Jr. A prosen-
tential theory of truth. Philosophical Studies, 27:73–125, 1975. Reprinted in
Grover (1992).
Gurevich, Yuri, and Saharon Shelah. Monadic theory of order and topology in
ZFC. Annals of Mathematical Logic, 23:179–198, 1983.
Gärdenfors, Peter. On the extensions of S5. Notre Dame Journal of Formal
Logic, 414:277–280, 1973.
Gödel, Kurt. Über formal unentscheidbare Sätze der Principia Mathematica
und verwandter Systeme I. Monatshefte für Mathematik und Physik, 38:173–
198, 1931.
Halbach, Volker, and Philip Welch. Necessities and necessary truths: A pro-
legomenon to the use of modal logic in the analysis of intensional notions.
Mind, 118:71–100, 2009.
Halmos, Paul, and Steven Givant. Logic as Algebra. The Mathematical Asso-
ciation of America, 1998.
References 101
Holliday, Wesley H., and Tadeusz Litak. One modal logic to rule them all? In
Guram Bezhanishvili, Giovanna D’Agostino, George Metcalfe, and Thomas
Studer, editors, Advances in Modal Logic, volume 12, pages 367–386.
College Publications, 2018.
Hughes, G. E., and M. J. Cresswell. A New Introduction to Modal Logic.
London: Routledge, 1996.
Humberstone, Lloyd. From worlds to possibilities. Journal of Philosophical
Logic, 10:313–339, 1981.
Jónnson, Bjarni, and Alfred Tarski. Boolean algebras with operators, part I.
American Journal of Mathematics, 73:891–939, 1951.
Jónnson, Bjarni, and Alfred Tarski. Boolean algebras with operators, part II.
American Journal of Mathematics, 74:127–162, 1952.
Kaminski, Michael, and Michael Tiomkin. The expressive power of second-
order propositional modal logic. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic,
37:35–43, 1996.
102 References
Myhill, John. On the interpretation of the sign ‘⊃’. The Journal of Symbolic
Logic, 18:60–62, 1953.
Myhill, John. Review of Formal Logic by A. N. Prior. The Philosophical
Review, 66:117–120, 1957.
Myhill, John. Problems arising in the formalization of intensional logic.
Logique et Analyse, 1:78–83, 1958.
Nagle, Michael C., and S. K. Thomason. The extensions of the modal logic K5.
The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 50:102–109, 1985.
Pacuit, Eric. Neighborhood Semantics for Modal Logic. Short Textbooks in
Logic. Cham: Springer, 2017.
Parry, W. T. Zum Lewisschen Aussagenkalkül. Ergebnisse eines Mathematis-
chen Kolloquiums, 4:15–16, 1933.
Pascucci, Matteo. Propositional quantifiers in labelled natural deduction for
normal modal logic. Logic Journal of the IGPL, 27:865–894, 2019.
Pitts, Andrew M. On an interpretation of second order quantification in first
order intuitionistic propositional logic. The Journal of Symbolic Logic,
57:33–52, 1992.
Plantinga, Alvin. The Nature of Necessity. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1974.
Połacik, Tomasz. Operators defined by propositional quantification and their
interpretation over Cantor space. Reports on Mathematical Logic, 27:67–79,
1993.
Połacik, Tomasz. Pitts’ quantifiers are not topological quantification. Notre
Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 39:531–545, 1998a.
Połacik, Tomasz. Propositional quantification in the monadic fragment of
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009177740 Published online by Cambridge University Press
van Benthem, Johan. Modal Logic and Classical Logic. Naples: Bibliopolis,
1983.
van Benthem, Johan, and Guram Bezhanishvili. Modal logics of space. In
Marco Aiello, Ian Pratt-Hartmann, and Johan van Benthem, editors, Hand-
book of Spatial Logics, pages 217–298. Dordrecht: Springer, 2007.
van Ditmarsch, Hans. To be announced. Information and Computation, 292:1–
42, 2023.
van Inwagen, Peter. Generalizations of homophonic truth-sentences. In Richard
Schantz, editor, What Is Truth?, volume 1 of Current Issues in Theoretical
Philosophy, pages 205–222. Berlin: De Gruyter, 2002.
Whitehead, Alfred North, and Bertrand Russell. Principia Mathematica, Vol-
umes 1–3. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1910–1913.
Williamson, Timothy. Modal Logic as Metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 2013.
Williamson, Timothy. Menzel on pure logic and higher-order metaphysics.
In Peter Fritz and Nicholas K. Jones, editors, Higher-Order Metaphysics.
Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2024.
Wittgenstein, Ludwig. Logisch-philosophische Abhandlung. In Wilhelm
Oswald, editor, Annalen der Naturphilosophie, volume 14, pages 185–262.
Leipzig: Unesma, 1921.
Zach, Richard. Decidability of quantified propositional intuitionistic logic and
S4 on trees of height and arity ≤ ω. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 33:155–
164, 2004.
Zdanowski, Konrad. On second order intuitionistic propositional logic without
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009177740 Published online by Cambridge University Press
Bradley Armour-Garb
SUNY Albany
Bradley Armour-Garb is chair and Professor of Philosophy at SUNY Albany. His books
include The Law of Non-Contradiction (co-edited with Graham Priest and J. C. Beall,
2004), Deflationary Truth and Deflationism and Paradox (both co-edited with J. C. Beall,
2005), Pretense and Pathology (with James Woodbridge, Cambridge University Press,
2015), Reflections on the Liar (2017), and Fictionalism in Philosophy (co-edited with Fred
Kroon, 2020).
Frederick Kroon
The University of Auckland
Frederick Kroon is Emeritus Professor of Philosophy at the University of Auckland. He has
authored numerous papers in formal and philosophical logic, ethics, philosophy of
language, and metaphysics, and is the author of A Critical Introduction to Fictionalism
(with Stuart Brock and Jonathan McKeown-Green, 2018).