Lec Nyamweya Lesson 4, 5 and 6 Notes PHIL 104
Lec Nyamweya Lesson 4, 5 and 6 Notes PHIL 104
Lec Nyamweya Lesson 4, 5 and 6 Notes PHIL 104
Idealism
➢ Idealism is now usually understood in philosophy as the view that
mind is the most basic reality and that the physical world exists only
as an appearance to or expression of mind, or as somehow mental
in its inner essence.
➢ However, a philosophy which makes the physical world dependent
upon mind is usually also called idealist even if it postulates some
further hidden, more basic reality behind the mental and physical
scenes (for example, Kant’s things-in-themselves).
➢ There is also a certain tendency to restrict the term ‘idealism’ to
systems for which what is basic is mind of a somewhat lofty nature,
so that ‘spiritual values’ are the ultimate shapers of reality. (An
older and broader use counts as idealist any view for which the
physical world is somehow unreal compared with some more
ultimate, not necessarily mental, reality conceived as the source of
value, for example Platonic forms.)
➢ The founding fathers of idealism in Western thought are Berkeley
(theistic idealism), Kant (transcendental idealism) and Hegel
(absolute idealism). Although the precise sense in which Hegel was
an idealist is problematic, his influence on subsequent absolute or
monistic idealism was enormous. In the US and the UK idealism,
especially of the absolute kind, was the dominating philosophy of
the late nineteenth and early twentieth century, receiving its most
forceful expression with F.H. Bradley. It declined, without dying,
under the influence of G.E. Moore and Bertrand Russell, and later
of the logical positivists. Not a few philosophers believe, however,
that it has a future.
Empiricism
➢ Empiricism means dependence upon direct experience for
information. Only information experienced by someone is valued,
not ideas created purely in one's mind.
➢ Empiricism is the belief that knowledge is based on experience.
Empiricists believe this experience can mainly be gained through
the use of the senses.
➢ The concept of empiricism is the idea in philosophy that knowledge
is gained through sensory experience. This means that information
is not innate in humans but is instead learned through experiences
even as a newborn.
➢ Some examples of empiricism are that stone is hard, ice is cold, and
glue is sticky. Until one has experienced these with the senses, this
information will be meaningless. Empiricists would assert there is
no way to understand that stone is hard unless someone
experiences it because otherwise, they would not know what hard
even meant.
➢ Most medieval philosophers after St. Augustine (354–430) took an
empiricist position, at least about concepts, even if they recognized
much substantial but nonempirical knowledge. The standard
formulation of this age was: “There is nothing in the intellect that
was not previously in the senses.”
➢ St. Thomas Aquinas (1225–74) rejected innate ideas altogether.
Both soul and body participate in perception, and all ideas
are abstracted by the intellect from what is given to the senses.
Human ideas of unseen things, such as angels and demons and even
God, are derived by analogy from the seen.
➢ The empiricism of the 14th-century Franciscan nominalist William
of Ockham was more systematic. All knowledge of what exists in
nature, he held, comes from the senses, though there is, to be sure,
“abstractive knowledge” of necessary truths; but this is
merely hypothetical and does not imply the existence of anything.
His more extreme followers extended his line of reasoning toward
a radical empiricism, in which causation is not a rationally
intelligible connection between events but merely an observed
regularity in their occurrence.
➢ During the 1600s, scientific advancements and discoveries had
changed the way people thought of the world and their place in it.
The Catholic Church had accepted the idea that the sun was at the
center of the solar system, and scientists were developing an early
form of the scientific method.
➢ For thousands of years, scientific claims could be justified through
thought experiments. For example, many principles the Greek
philosopher Aristotle created were based on internal reasoning.
However, by the 1600s, the early scientific method came into use.
In order to support a claim, one had to provide evidence based on
observations made with the senses or scientific instruments.
➢ In response to the developments of the scientific method and
Descartes's rationalism, philosophers in the 1600s and 1700s began
to argue that the world can only be understood via the senses. This
school of thought is known as empiricism and followers believe
that people possess no prior knowledge when they are born.
Instead of having innate understanding of certain concepts,
empiricists believe that a newborn is a tabula rasa, which means
blank slate in Latin. The most famous of these philosophers was
John Locke, who argued that lived experiences are what turn the
blank slate of a person into who they are and sensory experiences
provide people with all the knowledge they ever gain. He opposed
Descartes's idea that knowledge is possessed upon birth and
thought the senses were the main way to empirically understand
what was true in the world.
➢ The most important defender of empiricism was Francis Bacon,
who, though he did not deny the existence of a priori knowledge,
claimed that, in effect, the only knowledge that is worth having (as
contributing to the relief of the human condition) is empirically
based knowledge of the natural world, which should be pursued by
the systematic—indeed almost mechanical—arrangement of the
findings of observation and is best undertaken in the cooperative
and impersonal style of modern scientific research. Bacon was, in
fact, the first to formulate the principles of scientific induction.
Rationalism
➢ Rationalism, in Western philosophy, the view that
regards reason as the chief source and test of knowledge. Holding
that reality itself has an inherently logical structure, the
rationalist asserts that a class of truths exists that the intellect can
grasp directly.
➢ There are, according to the rationalists, certain rational
principles—especially in logic and mathematics, and even
in ethics and metaphysics—that are so fundamental that to deny
them is to fall into contradiction. The rationalists’ confidence in
reason and proof tends, therefore, to detract from their respect for
other ways of knowing.
➢ Rationalism has long been the rival of empiricism, the doctrine that
all knowledge comes from, and must be tested by, sense
experience. As against this doctrine, rationalism holds reason to be
a faculty that can lay hold of truths beyond the reach of
sense perception, both in certainty and generality.
➢ In stressing the existence of a “natural light,” rationalism has also
been the rival of systems claiming esoteric knowledge, whether
from mystical experience, revelation, or intuition, and has been
opposed to various irrationalisms that tend to stress the biological,
the emotional or volitional, the unconscious, or the existential at
the expense of the rational.
➢ The first Western philosopher to stress rationalist insight
was Pythagoras, a shadowy figure of the 6th century BCE. Noticing
that, for a right triangle, a square built on its hypotenuse equals the
sum of those on its sides and that the pitches of notes sounded on a
lute bear a mathematical relation to the lengths of the strings,
Pythagoras held that these harmonies reflected the ultimate nature
of reality. He summed up the implied metaphysical rationalism in
the words “All is number.”
➢ Plato so greatly admired the rigorous reasoning of geometry that
he is alleged to have inscribed over the door of his Academy the
phrase “Let no one unacquainted with geometry enter here.” His
famous forms are accessible only to reason, not to sense.
➢ Plato’s successor Aristotle (384–322 BCE) conceived of the work
of reason in much the same way, though he did not view the forms
as independent. His chief contribution to rationalism lay in
his syllogistic logic, regarded as the chief instrument of
rational explanation. Humans explain particular facts by bringing
them under general principles. Why does one think Socrates will
die? Because he is human, and humans are mortal. Why should one
accept the general principle itself that all humans are mortal?
➢ In experience such principles have so far held without exception.
But the mind cannot finally rest in this sort of explanation. Humans
never wholly understand a fact or event until they can bring it
under a principle that is self-evident and necessary; they then have
the clearest explanation possible. On this central thesis of
rationalism, the three great Greeks were in accord.
➢ The first modern rationalist was Descartes, an original
mathematician whose ambition was to introduce
into philosophy the rigour and clearness that delighted him
in mathematics.
➢ In his Meditations on First Philosophy (1641), he set out
to doubt everything in the hope of arriving in the end at
something indubitable. This he reached in his famous dictum cogito
ergo sum, “I think, therefore I am” (expressed in the Meditations as
cogito sum, “I think, I am”); for to doubt one’s own doubting
would be absurd.
➢ Here then was a fact of absolute certainty, rendered such by the
clearness and distinctness with which it presented itself to
his reason. His task was to build on this as a foundation, to deduce
from it a series of other propositions, each following with the same
self-evidence. He hoped thus to produce a philosophical system on
which people could agree as completely as they do on
the geometry of Euclid. The main cause of error, he held, lay in the
impulsive desire to believe before the mind is clear. The clearness
and distinctness upon which he insisted was not that
of perception but of conception, the clearness with which the
intellect grasps an abstract idea, such as the number three or its
being greater than two.
➢ How, then, does reason operate and how is it possible to have
knowledge that goes beyond experience? A new answer was given
by Kant in his Critique of Pure Reason (1781; 1787), which, as he
said, involved a Copernican revolution in philosophy.
➢ The reason that logic and mathematics will remain valid for all
experience is simply that their framework lies within the human
mind; they are forms of arrangement imposed from within upon
the raw materials of sensation.
➢ Humans will always find things arranged in certain patterns because
it is they who have unwittingly so arranged them. Kant held,
however, that these certainties were bought at a heavy price. Just
because a priori insights are a reflection of the mind, they cannot
be trusted as a reflection of the world outside the mind. Whether
the rational order in which sensation is arranged—the order, for
example, of time, space, and causality—represents an order
holding among things-in-themselves (German Dinge-an-sich)
cannot be known. Kant’s rationalism was thus the counterpart of a
profound skepticism.